This is a modern-English version of The Rights of War and Peace, originally written by Grotius, Hugo.
It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling,
and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If
you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.
Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.
Transcriber's notes:
Transcription notes:

UNIVERSAL
CLASSICS
LIBRARY
EDITOR'S
AUTOGRAPH EDITION
UNIVERSAL
CLASSICS
LIBRARY
EDITOR'S
AUTOGRAPH EDITION
ATTEST:
Robert Arnot
Managing Editor
ATTEST:
Robert Arnot
Managing Editor

UNIVERSAL CLASSICS
LIBRARY
UNIVERSAL CLASSICS
LIBRARY
ILLUSTRATED
WITH PHOTOGRAVURES
ON JAPAN VELLUM
HAND PAINTED
REPRODUCTIONS
AND FULL PAGE
PORTRAITS
OF
AUTHORS
ILLUSTRATED
WITH PHOTOGRAVURES
ON JAPAN VELLUM
HAND PAINTED
REPRODUCTIONS
AND FULL PAGE
PORTRAITS
OF
AUTHORS
M. WALTER DUNNE
PUBLISHER
NEW YORK AND LONDON
M. WALTER DUNNE
PUBLISHER
NEW YORK AND LONDON
Copyright, 1901,
BY
M. WALTER DUNNE,
PUBLISHER
Copyright, 1901,
BY
M. WALTER DUNNE,
PUBLISHER
GENERAL PREFACE

Of the Library of Universal Classics and Rare Manuscripts, twenty volumes are devoted to the various branches of Government, Philosophy, Law, Ethics, English and French Belles Lettres, Hebraic, Ottoman, and Arabian Literature, and one to a collection of 150 reproductions, bound in English vellum, of the autographs, papers and letters of Rulers, Statesmen, Poets, Artists and Celebrities ranging through three centuries, crowned by an illuminated facsimile of that historic Document, the Magna Carta.
Of the Library of Universal Classics and Rare Manuscripts, twenty volumes are dedicated to different branches of Government, Philosophy, Law, Ethics, English and French Literature, Hebraic, Ottoman, and Arabian Literature. Additionally, one volume contains a collection of 150 reproductions, bound in English vellum, of the autographs, papers, and letters of Rulers, Statesmen, Poets, Artists, and Celebrities spanning three centuries, highlighted by an illuminated facsimile of the historic document, the Magna Carta.
The series in itself is an epitome of the best in History, Philosophy and Literature. The great writers of past ages are accessible to readers in general solely through translations. It was, therefore, necessary that translations of such rare Classics as are embodied in this series should be of the best, and should possess exactitude in text and supreme faithfulness in rendering the author's thought. Under the vigilant scholarship of the Editorial Council this has been accomplished with unvarying excellence. The classification, selection and editing of the various volumes have been the subjectii of much earnest thought and consultation on the part of more than twenty of the best known scholars of the day.
The series is a perfect example of the best in History, Philosophy, and Literature. Great writers from the past are available to readers today only through translations. It was essential for the translations of these rare classics included in this series to be of the highest quality, with precise text and complete accuracy in conveying the author's ideas. Thanks to the careful scholarship of the Editorial Council, this has been achieved with consistent excellence. The organization, selection, and editing of the various volumes have involved a lot of serious thought and discussion among more than twenty of the most respected scholars of the time.
The Universities of Yale, Washington, Cornell, Chicago, Pennsylvania, Columbia, London, Toronto and Edinburgh are all represented among the contributors, the writers of special introductions, or upon the consulting staff, the latter including the Presidents of five of the Universities mentioned. Among others who contribute special essays upon given subjects may be mentioned the late Librarian of the British Museum, Dr. Richard Garnett, who furnishes the essay introducing "Evelyn's Diary." From the Librarian of the National Library of France, Léon Vallée, comes the fascinating introduction to the celebrated "Memoirs of the Duc de Saint-Simon." The scholarly minister to Switzerland (late First Assistant Secretary of State), Dr. David J. Hill, lent his wide reading to the brilliant and luminous essay that precedes the "Rights of War and Peace." The resources of the Congressional Library at Washington, as well as of foreign libraries, have all been drawn upon in the gigantic task of compressing into the somewhat narrow limits of twenty volumes all that was highest, best, most enduring and useful in the various ramifications of literature at large.
The universities of Yale, Washington, Cornell, Chicago, Pennsylvania, Columbia, London, Toronto, and Edinburgh are all represented among the contributors, the writers of special introductions, or on the consulting staff, which includes the presidents of five of the mentioned universities. Among others who contribute special essays on specific topics is the late librarian of the British Museum, Dr. Richard Garnett, who provides the essay introducing "Evelyn's Diary." The librarian of the National Library of France, Léon Vallée, offers the engaging introduction to the famous "Memoirs of the Duc de Saint-Simon." The scholarly minister to Switzerland (formerly First Assistant Secretary of State), Dr. David J. Hill, contributed his extensive reading to the brilliant and insightful essay that precedes "Rights of War and Peace." The resources of the Congressional Library in Washington, as well as foreign libraries, have all been utilized in the monumental task of condensing into the somewhat narrow limits of twenty volumes everything that is highest, best, most enduring, and useful in the various branches of literature.
The first section of the Library is devoted entirely to the manuscript reproductions of the autographs of celebrated men in all ranks and phases of life, covering a period of three centuries. They are, in fact, the American edition of the reproduction of rare and celebrated autographs drawn from the British Museum that was issued in England under the editorship of the Assistant Keeper of the Manuscripts. They afford an opportunity to the inquiring reader to study the characters of Rulers, Statesmen, Writers, and Artists through the medium of their chirography.
The first section of the Library is completely dedicated to reproductions of the original manuscripts from famous people across various backgrounds and times, spanning three centuries. They are, in fact, the American version of the reproduction of rare and famous autographs sourced from the British Museum, which was published in England under the direction of the Assistant Keeper of the Manuscripts. This collection provides curious readers with a chance to explore the personalities of rulers, statesmen, writers, and artists through their handwriting.
It has long been recognized that character is traceable through handwriting. So it is interesting to discerniii in the characters traced by Henry VIII the hardened, sensual and selfish character of that autocrat and polygamist; in the writing of Thomas Wolsey, those crafty traits combined with perseverance and mock humility which raised him wellnigh to supremacy in the realm and led him finally to a downfall more complete than any we read of in English history; and in that of Charles V, of Spain, the hard-headed continence of character and superb common sense which enabled him at the height of glory to retire to a monastery while yet there was "daylight in life," as he expressed it, "for the making of his soul." Apart from the historical interest of these Documents, this study of character as revealed in them will prove fascinating to thinking minds.
It has long been understood that character can be seen in handwriting. So, it's interesting to noticeiii in the signatures of Henry VIII the hardened, sensual, and selfish nature of that autocrat and polygamist; in the writing of Thomas Wolsey, those cunning traits mixed with perseverance and false humility that brought him close to power in the realm and ultimately led him to a downfall more complete than any we read about in English history; and in that of Charles V of Spain, the level-headed restraint and remarkable common sense that allowed him, at the peak of his glory, to withdraw to a monastery while there was still "daylight in life," as he put it, "for the making of his soul." Beyond the historical interest of these documents, this exploration of character as shown in them will be intriguing to thoughtful minds.
The Magna Carta, greatest of all historical charters wrung from the various kings of England from Henry I downward, was granted by King John at the pressing instance of the Barons and Commons of England toward the end of his ill-judged and unfortunate reign. Of this Document, celebrated and historic as it is, but little is known at large. Although Blackstone and other prominent lawyers have written upon it, information about it is hard to obtain. No reproduction of the original Document has ever been offered to American collectors. This facsimile is illuminated in colors with the shields of many of the Peers who compelled King John to accede to their demands for civil and religious liberty. The original charter was signed at a place called Runnymede (the Council Meadow) a spot between Windsor and Staines, on the 15th of June, 1215, about a year before the death of John. It practically guaranteed to the Commons of England all the civil and religious rights they enjoy to-day. It dealt with testamentary law as well, securing to widows all the legal rights which they to-day possess. It dealt with the rights of accused persons; with military service; with feudal tenure; with taxation, and it limited the heretofore autocratic power of the King to an extent unknown before in the history of the world.iv If we except the Declaration of Independence, it is the most interesting historical record of all time.
The Magna Carta, the most significant historical charter forced from various kings of England from Henry I onward, was granted by King John at the strong request of the Barons and Commons of England towards the end of his poorly judged and unfortunate reign. Despite its celebrated and historic status, not much is widely known about this document. Although Blackstone and other leading lawyers have written about it, information is hard to come by. No reproduction of the original document has ever been offered to American collectors. This facsimile is beautifully printed in colors featuring the shields of many of the Lords who pressured King John to agree to their demands for civil and religious liberties. The original charter was signed at a place called Runnymede (the Council Meadow), a location between Windsor and Staines, on June 15, 1215, about a year before John's death. It effectively guaranteed the Commons of England all the civil and religious rights they enjoy today. It also addressed testamentary law, ensuring widows all the legal rights they currently hold. It covered the rights of the accused, military service, feudal tenure, taxation, and it significantly limited the previously absolute power of the King in a way never seen before in world history.iv If we exclude the Declaration of Independence, it is the most fascinating historical record of all time.
The Second Section of the Library (ten volumes) is devoted to the presentation of Government, Philosophy, Law and Ethics. This section embraces such names as Grotius, Plato, Sir George Cornewall Lewis, Adam Smith, Hamilton, Madison, Jay, Walter Bagehot, Spinoza, Schopenhauer, Machiavelli, as well as those builders of Ideal Governments, More, Bacon, Campanella and Rousseau.
The Second Section of the Library (ten volumes) focuses on Government, Philosophy, Law, and Ethics. This section includes notable figures like Grotius, Plato, Sir George Cornewall Lewis, Adam Smith, Hamilton, Madison, Jay, Walter Bagehot, Spinoza, Schopenhauer, and Machiavelli, along with the visionaries of Ideal Governments, such as More, Bacon, Campanella, and Rousseau.
Of all benefactors in Literature of the human race, Grotius may perhaps rank as first among his equals. Centuries have borne witness to the justness of his premises and the wisdom of his conclusions. The principles of national law laid down by him are to-day accepted as the axioms of the Science. Among the nations, perhaps the United States is most deeply interested in the right administration of the principles affirmed by Grotius in his gigantic work on the "Rights of War and Peace," and it was therefore most fitting, when the recent peace conference at The Hague completed the great structure of international comity, the foundations of which were laid by Grotius in 1625, that a silver wreath was laid by the representative of the United States upon the grave of the man to whom the Conference owed its initial impulse, although at a distance in time of nearly three centuries.
Of all the contributors to literature in human history, Grotius might be considered the most significant among his peers. Centuries have shown the validity of his ideas and the soundness of his conclusions. The principles of international law he established are now accepted as the foundation of the field. Among nations, the United States likely has the most vested interest in properly applying the principles outlined by Grotius in his monumental work "On the Rights of War and Peace." So, it was fitting that at the recent peace conference in The Hague, which completed the important framework of international cooperation laid down by Grotius in 1625, a silver wreath was placed by the U.S. representative on the grave of the man whose ideas initially inspired the conference, despite the nearly three-century gap.
When the Publisher determined, under the advice of his Editorial Council, to publish Grotius, he found that only two volumes of the first edition were available in the Library of Congress. At much expense and trouble, he instituted a search in Europe and finally obtained the missing volume, which he presented to the Congressional Library, where it now is.
When the Publisher decided, based on the recommendations of his Editorial Council, to publish Grotius, he discovered that only two volumes of the first edition were available at the Library of Congress. After a lot of expense and effort, he initiated a search in Europe and eventually acquired the missing volume, which he donated to the Congressional Library, where it is now located.
Sir George Cornewall Lewis's "Government of Dependencies" is characterized by the accuracy of its information. It is a reliable text book for the guidance of any nation in the treatment of its dependencies and colonies. It is a Classic that will survive as long as colonization remains to be done, and it is remarkable that although itv was published for the first time sixty years ago, the illustrations afforded by the last two generations support the justice of its principles and the exactness of its deductions.
Sir George Cornewall Lewis's "Government of Dependencies" is known for its accurate information. It serves as a dependable textbook for any nation managing its dependencies and colonies. It's a classic that will endure as long as colonization continues, and it's noteworthy that even though it was first published sixty years ago, the examples from the last two generations reinforce the validity of its principles and the correctness of its conclusions.
Adam Smith's "Essay on Colonies" presents an introductory view of the principles governing colonial policy. It is a fitting work to go hand in hand with the greater one of Sir George Cornewall Lewis. It is of practical use to American Statesmen, since the United States seems at present to be entering upon a world-wide colonial policy. Its practical wisdom, which has made it a Classic for all times, finds a special applicability in the conditions of to-day, for Adam Smith was a theorist in the best sense of the word, that is to say, he was a man whose breadth of view, instead of unfitting him for practical details, enabled him to deduce from the lessons of history and experience the right solutions for the problems of Colonial policy.
Adam Smith's "Essay on Colonies" offers an introductory perspective on the principles that guide colonial policy. It pairs well with the more extensive work of Sir George Cornewall Lewis. This essay is practically valuable for American statesmen, as the United States currently appears to be embarking on a global colonial policy. Its practical insights, which have made it a timeless classic, are especially relevant today, since Adam Smith was a theorist in the best sense. His broad perspective allowed him, rather than hindering him in handling practical matters, to draw from history and experience to find the right solutions for the challenges of colonial policy.
Plato's "Republic" and "Statesman" must be regarded to-day not merely as historical records of a by-gone philosophy, but as living, teaching dissertations upon theories which cannot fail to awaken in studious minds the highest ideals of life and government. Modern problems stated in the light of Plato's philosophy, as it is expressed in these books, will find readier solutions when examined in the light of its principles. No student of sociology, of politics, national and municipal, or of government in all its many-sided aspects, can afford to be without a knowledge of these immortal discourses.
Plato's "Republic" and "Statesman" should be seen today not just as historical documents of an old philosophy, but as vibrant, instructive writings on ideas that are sure to inspire the highest ideals of life and government in thoughtful individuals. Modern issues viewed through the lens of Plato's philosophy, as presented in these texts, will more easily find solutions when analyzed according to its principles. No student of sociology, politics—whether national or local—or any aspects of government can afford to be without knowledge of these timeless discussions.
Goldwin Smith has declared that of all expositions of constitutional Government, "The Federalist" ranks the highest. When Hamilton, Madison, and Jay first conceived the idea of printing in the common tongue their ideas upon the principles of free government, they unwittingly laid the foundations of the best commentary on the principles of popular government ever written. Political science owes to them the most important contribution to its literature made since its birth. The Essays are equally admirablevi for sagacity, simplicity, and patriotism, and while The Federalist will never be read for pleasure, it contains a mine of wisdom for the student and the constitutional lawyer, and as a text book of political science is without a parallel.
Goldwin Smith has stated that of all explanations of constitutional government, "The Federalist" is the best. When Hamilton, Madison, and Jay first came up with the idea of expressing their thoughts on the principles of free government in plain language, they unknowingly created the foundation for the most insightful commentary on popular government ever written. Political science owes them its most significant contribution to its literature since it began. The Essays are admirablevi for their wisdom, clarity, and patriotism, and while The Federalist may not be read for enjoyment, it offers a wealth of knowledge for students and constitutional lawyers, and as a textbook of political science, it stands unmatched.
When Bagehot issued his work on the English Constitution, it was hailed by the critics as the most wonderful and philosophical dissertation on the subject in any language or from any pen. John Stuart Mill used to say that of all great subjects much remained to be written, and that especially was this true of the English Constitution. Bagehot's work, although affording the conclusion that monarchy in England exists as a logical necessity, is so unbiased in its premises, so logical and clear in its deductions, that this manifest fairness, although leading one to conclusions distasteful to a republican mind, must endear him to his readers. Dealing with a subject somewhat dry in its details, he invests inanimate objects with so much light that they become realities. In the highest sense he combines popularity and scholarship.
When Bagehot released his work on the English Constitution, critics praised it as the most amazing and philosophical analysis on the topic in any language or by any author. John Stuart Mill used to say that there was still a lot to be written about all major topics, and this was especially true for the English Constitution. Bagehot's work, while concluding that monarchy in England is a logical necessity, is so unbiased in its foundations and so logical and clear in its reasoning that this evident fairness, despite leading to conclusions unappealing to a republican mindset, must endear him to his readers. Although he tackles a topic that's somewhat dry in its details, he brings so much illumination to inanimate objects that they come alive. In the highest sense, he blends popularity and scholarship.
Spinoza's philosophy may be traced both to the influence of Bacon, his predecessor, and to Descartes, his contemporary. Its combination of positivism with the enthusiasm of piety characterizes his philosophy as unique in itself, for while treating man from a purely mechanical standpoint, it asserts that the mechanism itself is entirely divine. Spinoza was a voluntary martyr in the cause of Free Thought. He was at the same time both Pantheist and Monist, yet sincere in his devotion to nature and the God of nature. His religion naturally made him a Monist, while his philosophy led him to express the Pantheism that the lover of God in Nature cannot avoid. While he renounced his Judaism and entered the ranks of the Christian philosophers, he never received baptism. He may be ranked among the greatest of the German mystics, whose work had such profound influence upon the dogmatic Christianity of a later day. The epithetvii conferred on him, namely, "God-intoxicated," summarizes his whole attitude and the character of his philosophy better than any lengthy dissertation.
Spinoza's philosophy can be traced to both the influence of Bacon, his predecessor, and Descartes, his contemporary. Its mix of positivism and the zeal of piety makes his philosophy distinct, as it approaches humanity from a purely mechanical perspective while claiming that the mechanism itself is entirely divine. Spinoza willingly sacrificed himself for the cause of Free Thought. He was both a Pantheist and a Monist, yet genuine in his devotion to nature and the God of nature. His religious beliefs naturally made him a Monist, while his philosophical views led him to express the Pantheism that anyone who loves God in Nature cannot escape. Although he renounced Judaism and joined the ranks of Christian philosophers, he never went through baptism. He can be considered one of the greatest German mystics, whose work deeply influenced the dogmatic Christianity that followed. The labelvii given to him, "God-intoxicated," encapsulates his entire outlook and the essence of his philosophy better than any lengthy essay.
When Schopenhauer began to write, he declared himself a true disciple of Kant, but he modifies and adapts Kant's "Critique of Pure Reason" to such an extent that he reaches the attitude of opposition. This attitude he manifests throughout all his writings. He is truly an Apostle of Protest, but in spite of his positivist contradictions and his materialistic pantheism, he opens up a mine of suggestions to the literary and philosophical student. In spite of the apparent tragedy due to the conflict within him, we cannot help gathering from Schopenhauer an immensity of what is true, what is good and what is excellent. One thing especially noticeable about his writings is that while German philosophers are often ponderous and in fact nebulous, Schopenhauer is always clear, original, and readable.
When Schopenhauer started writing, he considered himself a true follower of Kant, but he modifies and adapts Kant's "Critique of Pure Reason" to such an extent that he takes a stance of opposition. He shows this attitude throughout all of his works. He is genuinely an Apostle of Protest, and despite his conflicting positivist views and his materialistic pantheism, he offers a wealth of ideas for literary and philosophical students. Despite the apparent tragedy stemming from the internal conflict within him, we can't help but find in Schopenhauer a vast amount of what is true, good, and excellent. One particularly striking aspect of his writing is that while German philosophers are often heavy and sometimes unclear, Schopenhauer is always clear, original, and engaging.
To Machiavelli belongs by acclaim the honor of having written the ideal biography of a State. His clear, straightforward, concise statement of conditions and characters as he saw then is a model for all writers of record. He was the first great Italian historian, and no man has ever been more ardent in his patriotism or a more earnest supporter of government for and by the people. The greatest tribute to his inflexible honesty of character is the fact that while no man had greater opportunities to enrich himself at the cost of the State, he died leaving his family in the greatest poverty. His varied political experience, and his assiduous study of classic writers, gave him the ability as well as the desire to write the history of his native State. Time has pronounced this History to be a classic worthy of preservation, and the perspective of time has also enabled us to form a juster and greater estimate of its author.
To Machiavelli goes the well-deserved recognition for writing the ideal biography of a State. His clear, straightforward, and concise portrayal of conditions and characters as he saw them serves as a model for all record writers. He was the first great Italian historian, and no one has ever been more passionate in his patriotism or a more dedicated advocate for government by and for the people. The greatest testament to his unwavering honesty is that, despite having many opportunities to enrich himself at the State's expense, he died leaving his family in great poverty. His diverse political experiences and thorough study of classic writers equipped him with the ability and desire to document the history of his homeland. Time has deemed this History a classic worthy of preservation, and the perspective gained over time has allowed us to form a more accurate and greater appreciation of its author.
The Ideal Republics and Empires that have been constructed from time to time by political dreamers haveviii all the attractiveness of works like Pilgrim's Progress or Gulliver's Travels, combined with a philosophy and political insight that give them a double claim to be considered Classics. Modern progress may be more deeply indebted than we can estimate to the fantasies and airy castles of men like Rousseau, More, and Campanella. The four Ideal Republics or Governments described in this volume are perhaps the most famous of all, since they rank not only as great creations of the imagination but as literature of the highest class; and their writers have a further claim upon posterity from the fact that they helped to make history.
The ideal republics and empires imagined by political dreamers over the years haveviii all the appeal of works like Pilgrim's Progress or Gulliver's Travels, along with a philosophy and political insight that give them a strong case to be considered classics. Modern progress may owe more to the visions and lofty ideas of thinkers like Rousseau, More, and Campanella than we can fully appreciate. The four ideal republics or governments described in this book are perhaps the most well-known of all, as they are not only incredible creations of the imagination but also high-quality literature; their authors have an additional claim to be remembered because they contributed to shaping history.
The Third and concluding Section of the Library deals with that tremendous range of world-wide literature which we call, for want of a better name, Belles Lettres. Goethe contributes his brilliant and sagacious observations on men and things as he communicated them to Eckerman. Landor, of whom Swinburne has said that Milton alone stands higher, both in prose and verse, furnishes us with his Classical Conversations. Montesquieu and Goldsmith are drawn on for their Persian and Chinese Letters. Lord Chesterfield gives us the irony and hard-headed criticism combined with worldly common sense contained in the Letters to His Son, and the various names best known in French and English Belles Lettres yield what is greatest in them. Ottoman Literature, comprising Arabian, Persian, and Hebraic Poems, affords the reader an insight into the romantic and dramatic character of the Oriental. The Dabistan, possibly the most extraordinary book ever written in the East, finds itself at home in this section, while the Literature of the Hebrews is ideally represented in that most wonderful of all monuments of human wisdom, and perhaps folly, the "Talmud," together with the basis of modern metaphysics, the "Kabbala."
The third and final section of the library covers the vast array of literature from around the world that we loosely refer to as Belles Lettres. Goethe shares his brilliant and insightful thoughts on people and the world as he conveyed them to Eckerman. Landor, whom Swinburne claims ranks only below Milton in both prose and poetry, offers his Classical Conversations. Montesquieu and Goldsmith provide their Persian and Chinese Letters. Lord Chesterfield delivers the blend of irony and sharp critique mixed with practical wisdom found in his Letters to His Son, while various well-known figures in French and English Belles Lettres contribute their finest works. Ottoman Literature, including Arabic, Persian, and Hebrew poems, gives readers a glimpse into the romantic and dramatic nature of the East. The Dabistan, perhaps the most remarkable book ever written in the East, fits well within this section, while the Literature of the Hebrews is beautifully represented in the incredible collection of human wisdom—and maybe folly—known as the "Talmud," along with the foundation of modern metaphysics, the "Kabbala."
The Sufistic Quatrains of Omar Khayyam are here for the first time presented complete in a collection of this order. The various editions of Fitzgerald are reprinted,ix collated, and to them is added the valuable Heron-Allen analysis of Fitzgerald's sources of inspiration. The very rare Whinfield version is found here complete; and for the first time in English appears M. Nicolas' French transcription of the Teheran Manuscript. It is safe to say that any lover of Omar wishing to add to his collection the versions here quoted would be compelled to disburse more than one hundred times the amount this book will cost him.
The Sufistic Quatrains of Omar Khayyam are presented here for the first time in a complete collection of this kind. The various editions of Fitzgerald have been reprinted,ix compiled, and include the valuable Heron-Allen analysis of Fitzgerald's sources of inspiration. The very rare Whinfield version is included here in full, and for the first time in English, M. Nicolas' French transcription of the Teheran Manuscript is featured. It's safe to say that any fan of Omar looking to add the versions included here to their collection would have to pay over one hundred times what this book costs.
While the Library of Universal Classics does not claim to be the final condensation of the treasure houses of human philosophy and lore, whether practical or ideal, it does most emphatically assert its right to be called the most useful, most attractive, and most representative selection, within the limits assigned to it, of those world-masterpieces of literature which men, for lack of a more luminous name, call Classics.
While the Library of Universal Classics doesn't claim to be the ultimate summary of the treasure troves of human thought and knowledge, whether practical or theoretical, it firmly asserts its right to be known as the most useful, most appealing, and most representative selection, within its limits, of those literary masterpieces that people, for lack of a better term, refer to as Classics.


HUGO GROTIUS
Hugo Grotius
From an Original Painting.
From an Original Artwork.

THE RIGHTS OF
WAR AND PEACE
INCLUDING THE
LAW OF NATURE
AND OF NATIONS
INCLUDING THE
Natural Law and International Law
TRANSLATED FROM THE ORIGINAL LATIN OF
GROTIUS
TRANSLATED FROM THE ORIGINAL LATIN OF
GROTIUS
WITH NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS FROM
POLITICAL AND LEGAL WRITERS
WITH NOTES AND ILLUSTRATIONS FROM
POLITICAL AND LEGAL WRITERS
BY
A. C. CAMPBELL, A. M.
BY
A. C. CAMPBELL, M.A.
WITH AN INTRODUCTION BY
DAVID J. Hill,
Assistant Secretary of State of the United States
WITH AN INTRODUCTION BY
DAVID J. Hill,
Assistant Secretary of State of the United States
M. WALTER DUNNE, PUBLISHER
NEW YORK & LONDON
M. WALTER DUNNE, PUBLISHER
NEW YORK & LONDON
Copyright, 1901,
BY
M. WALTER DUNNE,
PUBLISHER
Copyright, 1901,
BY
M. WALTER DUNNE,
PUBLISHER
ILLUSTRATIONS
Hugo Grotius | Frontispiece |
From an original painting. | |
Conflict | 109 |
By Gari Melchers, | |
From a panel painting in Library of Congress. | |
Peace | 213 |
By Gari Melchers, | |
From a panel painting in Library of Congress. | |
War and Peace | 307 |
Frontispiece to a rare edition of Grotius. |
CONTENTS
BOOK I. | ||
Chapter | Page | |
Introduction | 1 | |
I. | On War and Right | 17 |
II. | Inquiry into the Lawfulness of War | 31 |
III. | The Division of War into Public and Private, and the Nature of Sovereign Power | 55 |
BOOK II. | ||
I. | Defense of Person and Property | 73 |
II. | The General Rights of Things | 85 |
III. | On the Original Acquisition of Things, and the Right of Property in Seas and Rivers | 103 |
IV. | Title to Desert Lands by Occupancy, Possession, and Prescription | 109 |
IX. | In What Cases Jurisdiction and Property Cease | 117 |
X. | The Obligation Arising from Property | 123 |
XI. | On Promises | 131 |
XII. | On Contracts | 144 |
XIII. | On Oaths | 160 |
XV. | On Treaties and on Engagements Made by Delegates Exceeding Their Powers | 166 |
XVI. | The Interpretation of Treaties | 176 |
XVII. | On Damages Occasioned by Injury, and the Obligation to Repair Them | 195 |
XVIII. | On the Rights of Embassies | 202 |
XIX. | On the Right of Burial | 213 |
XX. | On Punishments | 220 |
XXI. | On the Communication of Punishment | 256 |
XXII. | On the Unjust Causes of War | 267 |
XXIII. | On Doubtful Causes | 274 |
XXIV. | Precautions against Rashly Engaging in War, Even upon Just Grounds | 280 |
BOOK III. | ||
I. | What Is Lawful in War | 290 |
II. | In What Manner the Law of Nations Renders the Property of Subjects Answerable for the Debts of Sovereigns. The Nature of Reprisals | 307 |
III. | On Just or Solemn War According to the Law of Nations on Declarations of War | 314 |
IV. | On the Right of Killing an Enemy in Lawful War and Committing Other Acts of Hostility | 323xiv |
V. | On the Right to Lay Waste an Enemy's Country and Carry Off His Effects | 332 |
VI. | On the Acquisition of Territory and Property by Right of Conquest | 334 |
VII. | On the Right over Prisoners of War | 345 |
VIII. | On Empire over the Conquered | 348 |
IX. | Of the Right of Postliminium | 351 |
XI. | The Right of Killing Enemies, in Just War, to be Tempered with Moderation and Humanity | 359 |
XII. | On Moderation in Despoiling an Enemy's Country | 365 |
XIII. | On Moderation in Making Captures in War | 369 |
XV. | On Moderation in Acquiring Dominion | 372 |
XVI. | On Moderation with Respect to Things Excluded from the Right of Postliminium by the Law of Nations | 375 |
XVII. | Respecting Those Who Are Neutral in War | 377 |
XIX. | On Good Faith between Enemies | 379 |
XX. | On the Public Faith by Which War Is Concluded; Comprising Treaties of Peace, and the Nature of Arbitration, Surrender, Hostages, Pledges | 385 |
XXI. | On Faith During the Continuance of War, on Truces, Safe-Conducts, and the Redemption of Prisoners | 403 |
XXII. | On the Faith of Those Invested with Subordinate Powers in War | 411 |
XXIV. | On Tacit Faith | 415 |
XXV. | Conclusion | 417 |
INDEX | 419 |
INTRODUCTION
The Work and Influence of Hugo Grotius.
The claims of the great work of Grotius, "De Jure Belli ac Pacis," to be included in a list of Universal Classics, do not rest upon the felicity of style usually expected in a classic composition. His work is marked by frequent rhetorical deformities, tedious and involved forms of reasoning, and perplexing obscurities of phraseology which prevent its acceptance as an example of elegant writing. Notwithstanding these external defects, it is, nevertheless, one of the few notable works of genius which, among the labors of centuries, stand forth as illustrations of human progress and constitute the precious heritage of the human race.
The claims of Grotius's major work, "De Jure Belli ac Pacis," to be included in a list of Universal Classics aren't based on the polished writing that's usually expected from a classic piece. His work has many rhetorical flaws, complicated reasoning, and confusing expressions that make it hard to accept as an example of elegant writing. Despite these surface issues, it remains one of the few significant works of genius that stand out among centuries of effort as examples of human progress and form an invaluable legacy for humanity.
If it is not literature in the technical sense, the masterpiece of Grotius is something higher and nobler,—a triumph of intelligence over irrational impulses and barbarous propensities. Its publication marks an era in the history of nations, for out of the chaos of lawless and unreasoning strife it created a system of illuminating principles to light the way of sovereigns and peoples in the paths of peace and general concord.
If it's not literature in the strict sense, Grotius' masterpiece is something greater and more refined—a victory of reason over emotional instincts and savage tendencies. Its release signifies a pivotal moment in the history of nations, as it brought clarity out of the chaos of lawless and thoughtless conflict, establishing a set of guiding principles to show leaders and citizens the way toward peace and mutual harmony.
I. The Age of War.
The idea of peaceful equity among nations, now accepted as a human ideal, though still far from realization, was for ages a difficult, if not an impossible, conception. All experience spoke against it, for war was the most familiar phenomenon of history.
The idea of peaceful equality among nations, now recognized as a human ideal, although still not fully achieved, has long been a challenging, if not impossible, concept. All experiences suggested otherwise, as war was the most common occurrence in history.
Among the Greek city-states, a few temporary leagues and federations were attempted, but so feeble were the bonds of peace, so explosive were the passions which led to war, that even among the highly civilized Hellenic peoples, community of race, language, and religion was powerless to create a Greek nation. It was reserved for2 the military genius of Alexander the Great, at last, by irresistible conquest, to bring the Greek Empire into being, to be destroyed in turn by superior force.
Among the Greek city-states, there were a few attempts at temporary alliances and federations, but the bonds of peace were weak and the passions that led to war were intense. Even among the highly advanced Hellenic peoples, shared race, language, and religion couldn’t create a unified Greek nation. It took the military genius of Alexander the Great, through unstoppable conquests, to establish the Greek Empire, which would eventually be destroyed by a stronger force.
The Roman Empire almost achieved the complete political unity of Europe, and bound parts of three continents under one rule, but the corruption of the military power which held it together led to its inevitable dismemberment.
The Roman Empire nearly achieved full political unity in Europe and unified parts of three continents under one rule, but the corruption of the military power that held it together resulted in its unavoidable breakup.
After the conflicts of the barbaric kingdoms which followed the dissolution of the Western Empire were ended by the predominance of the Frankish monarchy, the world believed that the Pax Romana was to be restored in Europe by the hand of Charles the Great; but the disruptive forces were destined to prevail once more, and the Holy Roman Empire never succeeded in reviving the power of ancient Rome. And thus the dream of a universal monarchy, of a central authority able to preside over kings and princes, adjusting their difficulties, and preserving the peace between them, was at last proved futile.
After the conflicts among the barbaric kingdoms that followed the fall of the Western Empire ended with the rise of the Frankish monarchy, people believed that the Pax Romana would be restored in Europe by Charles the Great. However, disruptive forces were destined to emerge again, and the Holy Roman Empire never managed to bring back the power of ancient Rome. Thus, the dream of a universal monarchy, a central authority that could oversee kings and princes, resolve their disputes, and maintain peace among them, ultimately proved to be futile.
In each of the great national monarchies that had already risen or were still rising on the ruins of imperial dominion, particularly in France, England, Holland, and the States of Germany, a continuous internal conflict over questions of religion complicated the bitterness and destructiveness of foreign wars until Europe was reorganized by the Peace of Westphalia, in 1648.
In each of the major national monarchies that had already emerged or were still developing from the remnants of imperial rule, especially in France, England, Holland, and the German states, an ongoing internal struggle over religious issues intensified the resentment and devastation of foreign wars until Europe was restructured by the Peace of Westphalia in 1648.
It was in the midst of these wars that Grotius was born. He saw his own country rising from a baptism of blood and all Europe rent and torn by the awful struggle of the Thirty Years' War, in the midst of which his great work was written and to whose conclusion it served as a guide and inspiration. The Empire, dismembered, had been reduced to almost complete impotence, the Church had been disrupted, and no international authority was anywhere visible. Amid the general wreck of institutions Grotius sought for light and guidance in great principles. Looking about him at the general havoc which war had made, the nations hostile, the faith of ages shattered, the passions of men destroying the commonwealths which nourished them, he saw that Europe possessed but one common bond, one vestige of its former unity,—the human mind. To this he made appeal and upon its deepest convictions he sought to plant the Law of Nations.
It was during these wars that Grotius was born. He witnessed his country emerging from a bloody baptism and all of Europe being torn apart by the brutal conflict of the Thirty Years' War, during which he wrote his great work that served as a guide and inspiration for its conclusion. The Empire, fragmented, had become nearly powerless, the Church had been thrown into chaos, and there was no sign of any international authority. Amid the widespread destruction of institutions, Grotius searched for clarity and direction in fundamental principles. Observing the overall devastation caused by war, the nations at odds, the beliefs of centuries shattered, and the passions of people destroying the societies that sustained them, he realized that Europe had only one common connection, one remnant of its former unity—the human mind. He appealed to this and sought to base the Law of Nations on its deepest convictions.
II. The Forerunners of Grotius.
It is historically accurate to say, that, until formulated by Grotius, Europe possessed no system of international law. Others had preceded him in touching upon certain aspects of the rights and duties of nations, but none had produced a system comparable to his.
It is historically accurate to say that, until Grotius formulated it, Europe did not have a system of international law. Others had addressed some aspects of the rights and duties of nations, but none had created a system comparable to his.
The earliest attempt to formulate recognized international customs was the formation of the early maritime codes, rendered necessary by the expansion of mediæval commerce from the end of the eleventh to the end of the sixteenth century, such as the "Jugemens d' Oléron," adopted by the merchants of France, England, and Spain, and reissued under other names for the merchants of The Netherlands and the Baltic. "The Consolato del Mare," a more elaborate compilation, was made, apparently at Barcelona, about the middle of the fourteenth century, and accepted generally by the traders of the chief maritime powers. It was in the cradle of commerce, therefore, that international law awoke to consciousness.
The earliest effort to establish recognized international customs was the creation of early maritime codes, which became necessary due to the growth of medieval trade from the late eleventh to the late sixteenth century. Examples include the "Jugemens d' Oléron," adopted by merchants from France, England, and Spain, and later reissued under different names for merchants in The Netherlands and the Baltic. "The Consolato del Mare," a more comprehensive compilation, was created, probably in Barcelona, around the middle of the fourteenth century, and was widely accepted by traders from the major maritime powers. Thus, it was in the early days of commerce that international law began to take shape.
As the Church was often intrusted with the task of pacification, it is but natural to look among her representatives for the earliest writers on the laws of international relations. It is, in fact, among the theological moralists that we find the first students of this subject. As early as 1564, a Spanish theologian, Vasquez, conceived of a group of free states with reciprocal rights regulated by jus naturale et gentium, without regard to a world-power, either imperial or ecclesiastical. In 1612, Saurez pointed out that a kind of customary law had arisen from the usages of nations, and distinctly described a society of interdependent states bound by fundamental principles of justice.
As the Church was often given the task of maintaining peace, it makes sense to look among its representatives for the earliest writers on the laws of international relations. In fact, it's among the theological moralists that we find the first students of this topic. As early as 1564, a Spanish theologian named Vasquez imagined a group of free states with mutual rights governed by jus naturale et gentium, independent of any world power, whether imperial or ecclesiastical. In 1612, Suárez noted that a form of customary law had developed from the practices of nations, and he clearly described a society of interdependent states linked by fundamental principles of justice.
At the close of the fifteenth and the beginning of the sixteenth centuries, a series of circumstances arose necessitating the extension of jurisprudence beyond its ancient boundaries, and thus tending to produce a group of international jurists. Among the juristic writers of this time are Balthazar Ayala, a Spanish jurisconsult, who died in 1584, having written in a historico-judicial spirit on the subject of war in his "De Jure et Officiis Belli"; Conrad Brunus, a German jurist, who wrote of the rights and duties of ambassadors in his "De Legationibus," published in 1548; and pre-eminent above all,4 Albericus Gentilis, an Italian professor of jurisprudence and lecturer at Oxford, a writer of force and originality, who published his "De Legationibus" in 1583 and his "De Jure Belli" in 1589.
At the end of the fifteenth century and the start of the sixteenth century, a number of factors came into play that required the expansion of law beyond its traditional limits, leading to a group of international legal scholars. Notable legal writers from this period include Balthazar Ayala, a Spanish legal expert who died in 1584 and wrote about the legal aspects of war in his "De Jure et Officiis Belli;” Conrad Brunus, a German legal scholar who discussed the rights and responsibilities of ambassadors in his "De Legationibus," published in 1548; and, notably, Albericus Gentilis, an Italian law professor and lecturer at Oxford, a powerful and original writer, who published his "De Legationibus" in 1583 and his "De Jure Belli" in 1589.
III. The Life and Personality of Grotius.
HUGO GROTIUS, to use the Latin form of his name by which he is best known, or Hugo de Groot as he is called in Holland, descended from a race of scholars and magistrates, was born at Delft, on April 10th, 1583. His family history has been related with much detail by De Burigny, in his "Vie de Grotius," published in French at Amsterdam in 1754; and by Vorsterman van Oyen, in his "Hugo de Groot en Zijn Gesclacht," a complete genealogy in Dutch, published at Amsterdam in 1883, which gives the descendants of Grotius down to the present generation. His origin is traced from a French gentleman, Jean Cornets, who took up his residence in The Netherlands in 1402. His descendant, Cornelius Cornets, married the daughter of a burgomaster of Delft on condition that the future children of this marriage should bear the name of their mother's family, in order to perpetuate the distinction which it had achieved. The maternal name imposed by Cornelius Cornets's Dutch father-in-law, Dirk van Kraayenburg de Groot, was de Groot, meaning the Great, and is said to have been bestowed for signal services rendered to his country by the first who had borne it four hundred years before. From this marriage sprung a Hugo de Groot, distinguished for his learning in Greek, Latin, and Hebrew and five times burgomaster of his native city. His eldest son, Cornelius, was a noted linguist and mathematician who studied law in France and received high office in his own country, afterward becoming a professor of law and many times rector of the University of Leyden. Another son, John de Groot, the father of Hugo Grotius, studied there under the famous Lipsius, who speaks of him with the highest commendation. Four times burgomaster of Delft, John de Groot became curator of the University of Leyden, a position which he filled with great dignity and honor.
HUGO GROTIUS, the Latin name he's best known by, or Hugo de Groot as he’s called in the Netherlands, came from a family of scholars and officials. He was born in Delft on April 10th, 1583. His family history is thoroughly detailed by De Burigny in his "Vie de Grotius," published in French in Amsterdam in 1754, and by Vorsterman van Oyen in his "Hugo de Groot en Zijn Gesclacht," a complete genealogy in Dutch published in Amsterdam in 1883, which tracks Grotius's descendants to the present day. His lineage goes back to a French gentleman, Jean Cornets, who settled in the Netherlands in 1402. His descendant, Cornelius Cornets, married the daughter of a mayor of Delft with the condition that their future children would carry the mother’s family name to preserve its distinction. The maternal name given by Cornelius Cornets's Dutch father-in-law, Dirk van Kraayenburg de Groot, was de Groot, which means the Great, and it’s said to have been awarded for significant services to the country by the first person who bore it four centuries earlier. From this marriage came Hugo de Groot, recognized for his expertise in Greek, Latin, and Hebrew, and who served as the mayor of his hometown five times. His eldest son, Cornelius, was a renowned linguist and mathematician who studied law in France and held high office back home, later becoming a law professor and often serving as rector of the University of Leyden. Another son, John de Groot, who was Hugo Grotius's father, studied under the famous Lipsius, who praised him highly. John de Groot, who served as mayor of Delft four times, became the curator of the University of Leyden, a role he fulfilled with great dignity and honor.
In his earliest years the young Hugo gave evidence of marked and varied ability. At eight he wrote Latin verses which betrayed poetic talent; at twelve he entered the University where he became a pupil of that prince5 of scholars, Joseph Scaliger, who directed his studies; and at fifteen he defended "with the greatest applause" Latin theses in philosophy and jurisprudence. His fame as a prodigy of diversified learning spread far and wide, and great scholars declared they had never seen his equal.
In his early years, the young Hugo showed notable and diverse talent. By the age of eight, he was writing Latin verses that displayed his poetic skill; at twelve, he entered the University and became a student of the esteemed scholar Joseph Scaliger, who guided his studies. By fifteen, he impressively defended Latin theses in philosophy and law "to great acclaim." His reputation as a prodigy with a wide range of knowledge grew, and renowned scholars claimed they had never seen anyone like him.
Grotius had won celebrity even in foreign lands when, in 1600, at the age of seventeen, he was admitted to the bar. The youthful prodigy had already accompanied the Grand Pensionary, John of Oldenbarneveld on a special embassy to France, where he was presented to Henry IV, who bestowed upon him his portrait together with a gold chain, and graciously called him "The Miracle of Holland." At Orleans he was made a Doctor of Laws.
Grotius had gained fame even in other countries when, in 1600, at the age of seventeen, he was admitted to the bar. The young prodigy had already joined the Grand Pensionary, John of Oldenbarnevelt, on a special mission to France, where he was introduced to Henry IV, who gave him a portrait along with a gold chain, and kindly referred to him as "The Miracle of Holland." In Orleans, he was awarded an honorary Doctor of Laws.
Married in 1609 to Marie van Reigersberg, whose devotion was worthy of his deep affection, and loaded with public honors, having been named the official historian of the United Provinces and the advocate-general of two provinces, Holland and Zeeland, Grotius set his hand to a work entitled "Mare Librum," in which he defended the freedom of the sea and the maritime rights of his country against the arrogant pretensions of the Portuguese in suppressing the commerce of other nations in Eastern waters,—a treatise destined to become still more celebrated in the history of international law by Selden's reply, "Mare Clausum," written in 1635. Next, turning his attention to the history of The Netherlands, he devoted himself for a time to his "Annals of the War of Independence."
Married in 1609 to Marie van Reigersberg, who was deeply devoted to him and received his profound love in return, and honored with several public titles, including the official historian of the United Provinces and the advocate-general of Holland and Zeeland, Grotius began a work called "Mare Librum." In it, he defended the freedom of the seas and his country's maritime rights against the overbearing claims of the Portuguese, who were trying to suppress the trade of other nations in Eastern waters. This treatise would later gain even more fame in the history of international law because of Selden's response, "Mare Clausum," written in 1635. After that, Grotius shifted his focus to the history of the Netherlands and dedicated some time to his "Annals of the War of Independence."
In 1613, Grotius added to his laurels as poet, jurist, and historian by entering the field of politics, and he was appointed Pensionary of Rotterdam upon the condition that he should continue in office during his own pleasure. It was during a visit to England upon a diplomatic mission in this same year that he met the great scholar Isaac Casaubon, who said in a letter to Daniel Heinsius: "I cannot say how happy I esteem myself in having seen so much of one so truly great as Grotius. A wonderful man! This I knew him to be before I had seen him; but the rare excellence of that divine genius no one can sufficiently feel who does not see his face and hear him speak. Probity is stamped on all his features."
In 1613, Grotius added to his achievements as a poet, lawyer, and historian by stepping into the world of politics, and he was appointed Pensionary of Rotterdam with the understanding that he would remain in the position as long as he wanted. During a trip to England for a diplomatic mission that same year, he met the renowned scholar Isaac Casaubon, who wrote in a letter to Daniel Heinsius: "I can’t express how fortunate I feel to have spent time with someone as truly remarkable as Grotius. What an incredible man! I already knew he was exceptional before meeting him; however, the extraordinary brilliance of his genius can't be truly appreciated unless you see his face and hear him speak. Integrity is evident in all his features."
Closely related by personal friendship as well as by his official duties to the Grand Pensionary, John of Oldenbarneveld, Grotius was destined to share with that unfortunate patriot the proscription and punishment which6 Maurice of Orange visited upon the two confederates in the defense of religious tolerance. Risking all as the apostles of peace, they were soon condemned to be its martyrs. Oldenbarneveld, having incurred the bitter hatred of the Stadtholder, was condemned to death by decapitation on May 12th, 1619. Grotius, less offensive to Maurice on account of his youth and his gracious personality, was sentenced six days later to perpetual imprisonment. On the 6th of June, 1619, he was incarcerated in the fortress of Loevestein.
Closely connected by personal friendship and his official duties to the Grand Pensionary, John of Oldenbarneveld, Grotius was fated to face the same exile and punishment that Maurice of Orange inflicted on the two allies in their fight for religious tolerance. Risking everything as advocates for peace, they soon became its martyrs. Oldenbarneveld, who had drawn the deep animosity of the Stadtholder, was sentenced to death by decapitation on May 12th, 1619. Grotius, being less of a target for Maurice due to his youth and likable character, was sentenced just six days later to life imprisonment. On June 6th, 1619, he was locked up in the fortress of Loevestein.
Rigorously treated at first, his docility and resignation soon won the respect and affection of his keepers. Writing materials and books were in time accorded him, and finally, on condition that she would continue to share his captivity, he was granted the presence of his wife. The studious prisoner and his devoted companion completely disarmed all suspicion of an intention to escape, and the ponderous chest in which books came and went continued to bring periodic consolation to the mind of the busy scholar. A treatise on the truth of the Christian religion, a catechism for the use of his children, a digest of Dutch law, and other compositions served to occupy and alleviate the weary months of confinement, until one day when the time seemed opportune Madame Grotius secretly inclosed her husband in the great chest and it was borne away by two soldiers. Descending the stone steps of the prison the bearers remarked that the trunk was heavy enough to contain an Arminian, but Madame Grotius's jest on the heaviness of Arminian books smoothed over the suspicion, if one was really entertained, and the great jurist was sent in the chest safe to Gorcum, attended by a faithful domestic, where in the house of a friend the prisoner emerged without injury and in the guise of a stone mason hastened to Antwerp. From Antwerp he took refuge in France, where he arrived in April, 1621, and was joined by his faithful wife at Paris in the following October.
At first treated harshly, his calmness and acceptance quickly earned the respect and affection of his guards. Eventually, he was given writing materials and books, and finally, on the condition that she would remain with him in captivity, he was allowed to have his wife by his side. The studious prisoner and his loyal companion completely eliminated any suspicion of an escape plan, and the heavy chest that carried books in and out continued to bring him regular comfort as he studied. A treatise on the truth of Christianity, a catechism for his children, a summary of Dutch law, and other writings helped pass the long months of confinement. Then, one day when the moment felt right, Madame Grotius secretly hid her husband in the large chest, and two soldiers carried it away. As they went down the stone steps of the prison, the soldiers joked that the trunk was heavy enough to contain an Arminian, but Madame Grotius's quip about the weight of Arminian books diffused any suspicion, if there was any, and the great jurist was safely sent in the chest to Gorcum, accompanied by a loyal servant. There, in a friend's house, the prisoner emerged unharmed and, disguised as a stone mason, quickly made his way to Antwerp. From Antwerp, he sought refuge in France, arriving in April 1621, and was reunited with his devoted wife in Paris the following October.
The bitterness of exile was now to be added to the miseries of imprisonment, for Grotius was not only excluded from The Netherlands, but in extreme poverty. His letters reveal his anguish of spirit at this period, but a generous Frenchman, Henri de Même, placed his country house at Balagni at his disposition, and there, supported by a small pension, which Louis XIII had graciously accorded him, though irregularly and tardily7 paid, Grotius commenced his great work, "De Jure Belli ac Pacis," in the summer of 1623.
The bitterness of exile was now added to the misery of imprisonment, as Grotius was not only barred from the Netherlands but also living in extreme poverty. His letters reveal his deep anguish during this time, but a kind Frenchman, Henri de Même, offered his country house in Balagni for Grotius to use. There, supported by a small pension that Louis XIII had generously granted him, albeit irregularly and slowly paid, Grotius began his great work, "De Jure Belli ac Pacis," in the summer of 1623.7
Much speculation has been indulged in regarding the causes which led to the composition of this masterpiece, but a recent discovery has rendered all this superfluous, as well as the ascription of special merit to the Counselor Peyresc for suggesting the idea of the work. It is, indeed, to the pacific genius of Grotius more than to all other causes that the world owes the origin of his great work; for it sprang from his dominant thought, ever brooding on the horrors of war and the ways of peace, during more than twenty years, and never wholly satisfied till its full expression was completed.
Much has been speculated about the reasons behind the creation of this masterpiece, but a recent discovery has made all that unnecessary, as well as giving special credit to Counselor Peyresc for suggesting the idea for the work. In fact, it is primarily thanks to the peaceful vision of Grotius that the world has this great work; it emerged from his persistent contemplation of the horrors of war and the paths to peace over more than twenty years, and he was never completely satisfied until he expressed it fully.
In the winter of 1604, there had sprung out of his legal practice the idea of a treatise entitled "De Jure Praedae," fully written out, but never printed by its author. The manuscript remained unknown by all his biographers until it was brought to light and printed under the auspices of Professor Fruin at The Hague in 1868. This interesting document proves that not only the general conception but the entire plan and even the arrangement of the "De Jure Belli ac Pacis" were in the mind of Grotius when he was only twenty-one years of age. The difference between the earlier work and the later is chiefly one of detail and amplification, the difference which twenty years of reading, experience, meditation and maturity of faculty would inevitably create.
In the winter of 1604, the idea for a treatise titled "De Jure Praedae" emerged from his legal practice. It was fully written out but never published by its author. The manuscript remained unknown to all his biographers until it was discovered and printed by Professor Fruin in The Hague in 1868. This fascinating document shows that not only the general concept but also the entire plan and arrangement of the "De Jure Belli ac Pacis" were in Grotius's mind when he was just twenty-one. The difference between the earlier and later work mainly lies in the details and expansions that twenty years of reading, experience, reflection, and personal growth would naturally bring.
The curious may find in his letters the almost daily chronicle of his progress with his book to the time of its publication after excessive labors lasting more than a year. In March, 1625, the printing of the first edition, which had occupied four months, was completed and copies were sent to the fair at Frankfort. His honorarium as author consisted of two hundred copies, many of which he presented to his friends. From the sale of the remainder at a crown each, he was not able to reimburse his outlay. In the following August he wrote to his father and brother that if he had their approbation and that of a few friends, he would have no cause for complaint but would be satisfied. Louis XIII, to whom the work was dedicated, accepted the homage of the author and a handsomely bound copy, but failed to exercise the grace customary with monarchs by according a gratification. At Rome, the treatise was proscribed in the index in 1627. Almost penniless and8 suffering from his protracted toil, Grotius seemed destined to neglect and oblivion, yet from his exile he wrote to his brother: "It is not necessary to ask anything for me. If my country can do without me, I can do without her. The world is large enough...."
The curious can find in his letters a nearly daily account of his progress on his book leading up to its publication after more than a year of hard work. In March 1625, the printing of the first edition, which took four months, was finished, and copies were sent to the fair in Frankfurt. His payment as the author was two hundred copies, many of which he gave to his friends. From selling the rest at a crown each, he couldn’t recover his costs. The following August, he wrote to his father and brother that if he had their approval and that of a few friends, he would have no reason to complain and would be content. Louis XIII, to whom the work was dedicated, accepted the author’s respect and a nicely bound copy but failed to give the customary reward that monarchs usually provide. In Rome, the treatise was banned in the index in 1627. Almost broke and suffering from his long struggle, Grotius seemed destined to fade into neglect and obscurity, yet from his exile he wrote to his brother: "It is not necessary to ask anything for me. If my country can do without me, I can do without her. The world is large enough...."
Invited to enter the service of France by Richelieu, Grotius would not accept the conditions which the Cardinal wished to impose,—such at least is the inevitable inference from his letters. His pension was not paid and his circumstances became so serious that one of his children had but a single coat. At length, pushed to the utmost extremity of want and instigated by his energetic wife, Grotius resolved to return to Holland. Driven from Rotterdam to Amsterdam, where he hoped to settle down as a lawyer, the States General twice ordered his arrest and named a price for his delivery to the authorities. The new Stadtholder, Frederick Henry, who, before succeeding his brother Maurice, had written kindly to Grotius after his escape from imprisonment, now approved his proscription. Abandoned by his prince as well as by his countrymen, Grotius once more turned his face toward exile and set out for Hamburg.
Invited to enter the service of France by Richelieu, Grotius refused to accept the conditions the Cardinal wanted to impose—at least, that’s the clear conclusion from his letters. His pension wasn't paid, and his situation became so dire that one of his children only had a single coat. Eventually, pushed to the brink of poverty and encouraged by his determined wife, Grotius decided to return to Holland. Forced to flee from Rotterdam to Amsterdam, where he hoped to establish a career as a lawyer, the States General ordered his arrest twice and set a bounty for his capture. The new Stadtholder, Frederick Henry, who had previously written kindly to Grotius after he escaped from prison, now supported his banishment. Abandoned by both his prince and his fellow citizens, Grotius turned once again towards exile and began his journey to Hamburg.
IV. The Work of Grotius.
It may be of interest at this point in the career of Grotius to describe briefly the character of the great work which was soon to win for him a new celebrity, and materially change his prospects in life.
It might be worth mentioning at this stage in Grotius's career to briefly outline the nature of the significant work that would soon bring him renewed fame and greatly alter his life’s prospects.
The inspiration of his "De Jure Belli ac Pacis" was the love of peace, yet he was far from being one of those visionaries who totally condemn the use of armed force and proscribe all war as wrong and unnecessary. On the contrary, he seeks to discover when, how, and by whom war may be justly conducted.
The inspiration for his "De Jure Belli ac Pacis" was a love of peace, but he was not one of those dreamers who completely reject the use of armed force and label all war as wrong and unnecessary. Instead, he aims to find out when, how, and by whom war can be justly conducted.
His plan of treatment is as follows:—
His treatment plan is as follows:—
In the First Book, he considers whether any war is just, which leads to the distinction between public and private war, and this in turn to a discussion of the nature and embodiment of sovereignty.
In the First Book, he looks into whether any war can be considered just, leading to a distinction between public and private wars, which in turn sparks a conversation about the nature and embodiment of sovereignty.
In the Second Book, the causes from which wars arise, the nature of property and personal rights which furnish their occasions, the obligations that pertain to ownership, the rule of royal succession, the rights secured by9 compacts, the force and interpretation of treaties, and kindred subjects are examined.
In the Second Book, he explores the reasons behind wars, the nature of property and personal rights that create the conditions for them, the responsibilities that come with ownership, the rules of royal succession, the rights guaranteed by 9 agreements, the power and interpretation of treaties, and related topics.
In the Third Book, the question is asked, "What is lawful war?" which prepares for the consideration of military conventions and the methods by which peace is to be secured.
In the Third Book, the question is raised, "What defines a lawful war?" which sets the foundation for discussing military agreements and methods to achieve peace.
From the authority of the Empire and the Church, no longer effectual as an international agency, Grotius appeals to Humanity as furnishing the true law of nations. Beginning with the idea that there is a kinship among men established by nature, he sees in this bond a community of rights. The society of nations, including as it does the whole human race, needs the recognition of rights as much as mere local communities. As nations are but larger aggregations of individuals, each with its own corporate coherence, the accidents of geographic boundary do not obliterate that human demand for justice which springs from the nature of man as a moral being. There is, therefore, as a fundamental bond of human societies a Natural Law, which, when properly apprehended, is perceived to be the expression and dictate of right reason. It is thus upon the nature of man as a rational intelligence that Grotius founds his system of universal law.
From the authority of the Empire and the Church, which are no longer effective as international agents, Grotius turns to Humanity as the source of the true law of nations. Starting with the idea that there's a natural kinship among people, he sees this connection as a community of rights. The society of nations, which includes all of humanity, requires the acknowledgment of rights just like smaller local communities do. Since nations are just larger groups of individuals, each with its own unity, the distinctions of geographical boundaries do not erase that inherent human demand for justice that comes from our nature as moral beings. Therefore, as a fundamental bond of human societies, there exists a Natural Law that, when fully understood, is recognized as the expression and command of sound reasoning. Grotius builds his system of universal law on the nature of man as a rational being.
As this law of human nature is universally binding wherever men exist, it cannot be set aside by the mere circumstances of time and place, whence it results that there is a law of war as well as a law of peace. As this law applies to the commencement of armed conflicts, war is never to be undertaken except to assert rights, and when undertaken is never to be carried on except within the limits of rights. It is true that in the conflict of arms laws must be silent, but only CIVIL laws, which govern in times of peace. Those laws which are PERPETUAL, which spring from the nature of man as man, and not from his particular civil relations, continue even during strife and constitute the laws of war. To deny these, or to disobey them, implies a repudiation of human nature itself and of the divine authority which has invested it with rights and obligations. To disavow the imperative character of these perpetual laws, is to revert to barbarism.
As this law of human nature applies to everyone, no matter where they are, it can't be disregarded just because of different times or places. This means there is a law of war as well as a law of peace. When it comes to starting armed conflicts, war should only be waged to assert rights, and once it begins, it should only be conducted within the limits of these rights. It's true that during armed conflict, laws must be quiet, but only CIVIL laws, which apply in times of peace. Those laws that are Eternal, based on human nature itself and not on specific civil relationships, continue even in times of conflict and form the laws of war. To deny or ignore these laws means rejecting human nature itself and the divine authority that has endowed it with rights and responsibilities. Rejecting the binding nature of these perpetual laws is a step back to barbarism.
It is necessary, however to distinguish between Natural Law, that principle of justice which springs from10 man's rational nature, and Conventional Law, which results from his agreements and compacts. Natural Law remains ever the same, but institutions change. While the study of abstract justice, apart from all that has its origin in the will or consent of men, would enable us to create a complete system of jurisprudence, there is another source which must not be neglected, since men have established the sanctity of certain rules of conduct by solemn convention.
It is important, however, to differentiate between Natural Law, the principle of justice that arises from10 human rationality, and Conventional Law, which comes from human agreements and treaties. Natural Law is always consistent, while institutions evolve. Although the exploration of abstract justice, independent of anything that stems from human will or consent, could allow us to develop a comprehensive legal system, we must also recognize the significance of another source: the fact that humans have created the sanctity of certain behavioral rules through formal agreements.
The Law of Nations does not consist, therefore, of a mere body of deductions derived from general principles of justice, for there is also a body of doctrine based upon CONSENT; and it is this system of voluntarily recognized obligations which distinguishes international jurisprudence from mere ethical speculation or moral theory. There are CUSTOMS of nations as well as a universally accepted law of nature, and it is in this growth of practically recognized rules of procedure that we trace the evolution of law international—jus inter gentes—as a body of positive jurisprudence.
The Law of Nations isn't just a set of conclusions drawn from general principles of justice; it also includes a framework built on Permission. This system of voluntarily accepted obligations separates international law from simple ethical discussion or moral theory. There are Cultural practices among nations, as well as a universally acknowledged law of nature. It is through the development of rules that are widely accepted and followed that we see the evolution of international law—jus inter gentes—as a form of positive law.
It is evident that the mind of Grotius is continually struggling to establish a science upon this positive basis, and it is this which gives a distinctive character to his effort. The great writers of all ages are cited with a superfluous lavishness, not so much to support his claims by an aggregation of individual opinions—still less to display his erudition, as his critics have sometimes complained—as to give a historic catholicity to his doctrine by showing that the laws he is endeavoring to formulate have, in fact, been accepted in all times and by all men. For this purpose also, he makes abundant use of the great authorities on Roman Law, whose doctrines and formulas were certain to carry conviction to the minds of those whom he desired to convince.
It’s clear that Grotius is constantly trying to build a science on this solid foundation, and this struggle gives his work a unique character. He references great writers from all eras with excessive abundance, not primarily to support his points through a collection of individual opinions—nor to show off his knowledge, as some of his critics have claimed—but to give a historical universality to his teachings by demonstrating that the laws he’s trying to define have been accepted throughout history and by all people. He also frequently relies on the major authorities of Roman Law, whose ideas and principles were sure to persuade the audiences he aimed to win over.
It is needless, perhaps, to point out that the work of Grotius is not and could not be a work of permanent authority as a digest of international law. His own wise appreciation of the positive and historical element—the authority derived from custom—should exempt him from the pretense of absolute finality. It is the Book of Genesis only that he has given us, but it is his indefeasible distinction to have recorded the creation of order out of chaos in the great sphere of international relationship, justly entitling him to the honor accorded to11 him by the spontaneous consent of future times as the Father of International Jurisprudence.
It’s probably unnecessary to point out that Grotius’ work is not, and cannot be, a definitive source of international law. His wise understanding of the positive and historical aspects—authority based on custom—should exempt him from claims of absolute finality. He has only given us the Book of Genesis, but his undeniable achievement is recording the establishment of order from chaos in the vast realm of international relations, rightly earning him the title given by the collective agreement of future generations as the Father of International Jurisprudence.
It is not difficult after more than three centuries of thought and experience to point out the defects in his doctrine. If he justifies slavery, it is not without ingenuity; for, he argues, if a man may sell his labor, why not his liberty? and if the conqueror may impose his will upon the property of the vanquished, why not also upon his person? If he identifies sovereignty with supreme power without any adequate conception of its ethical basis, he is at least as advanced in his thinking as the conceptions of his time, which had not yet grasped the idea of the state as a moral organism. If he has no adequate notion of neutrality, believing it to be the duty of a nation to enlist its energies for what it deems the right side, rather than to disavow all responsibility for actions foreign to its own interests, he is at least supported in this by the opinion of the multitude even at the present time; and even among jurists the modern conception of neutrality is hardly a century old. If the new schools of jurisprudence make light of Natural Law as a foundation of public and private rights, it is not certain that Grotius may not yet be vindicated as representing a doctrine at least as clear as any other which has been substituted for it. But, finally, to all these criticisms it may be answered, that no great thinker can be justly estimated except in relation to his predecessors and contemporaries. Measured by these, Grotius stands alone among the jurists of his century for originality of thought and power of exposition.
It’s not hard after more than three centuries of thought and experience to point out the flaws in his theory. If he justifies slavery, it’s with some clever reasoning; he argues that if a person can sell their labor, then why not their freedom? And if a conqueror can impose their will on the property of the defeated, why not also on their person? If he equates sovereignty with absolute power without any solid understanding of its ethical foundation, he’s at least as advanced in his thinking as the ideas of his time, which had yet to recognize the state as a moral entity. If he lacks a proper understanding of neutrality, believing it's the duty of a nation to channel its efforts toward what it considers the right side instead of dismissing any responsibility for actions outside its own interests, he is still backed by the majority's opinion even today; and even among legal experts, the modern idea of neutrality is barely a century old. If the new schools of law downplay Natural Law as a basis for public and private rights, it’s still possible that Grotius may be defended as representing a doctrine that’s at least as clear as any other that has replaced it. But ultimately, in response to all these criticisms, it can be said that no great thinker can be fairly judged without considering their predecessors and contemporaries. Compared to these, Grotius stands out among the jurists of his century for his original thought and ability to explain complex ideas.
V. The Impact of Grotius's Work.
It was during his sojourn in Hamburg in 1633, eight years after the publication of his "De Jure," and while he was still suffering from painful pecuniary embarrassment, that Europe suddenly awoke to a sense of his importance; and, almost at one time, Poland, Denmark, Spain, England, and Sweden all extended friendly invitations urging him to enter into their public service. His fame as a jurist had become international and, rudely repelled by his native Holland, he became the center of European interest. Gustavus Adolphus had placed the work of Grotius along side his Bible under his soldier's pillow, as he prosecuted his campaigns in the Thirty Years' War. The first edition of that work, written in Latin, the12 cosmopolitan language of learned Europe, had been quickly exhausted and widely scattered. Another had soon been called for at Paris, but the death of Buon, the publisher, created obstacles to its appearance. A second edition had appeared at Frankfort in 1626, another at Amsterdam in 1631, and still another with notes by the author in 1632. The book had aroused the thought of kings as well as of scholars, and in the circles of high influence everywhere in Europe the name of Grotius had become well known. His book had excited the most opposite sentiments and awakened the most contradictory judgments, but among lawyers and statesmen its reception was from the first generally marked by admiration. In spite of exile, poverty, and misfortune, Grotius had become a European celebrity and was about to enter into the reward of his labors. He had created a code for war and a programme of peace, and henceforth no statesman could afford to neglect him.
It was during his time in Hamburg in 1633, eight years after the publication of his "De Jure," and while he was still struggling with painful financial issues, that Europe suddenly recognized his significance. Almost simultaneously, Poland, Denmark, Spain, England, and Sweden all sent him friendly invitations, encouraging him to join their public service. His reputation as a legal expert had become international, and having been harshly rejected by his homeland of Holland, he became the center of European attention. Gustavus Adolphus kept Grotius's work next to his Bible under his soldier’s pillow as he carried out his campaigns in the Thirty Years' War. The first edition of that work, written in Latin, the12 cosmopolitan language of educated Europe, had been quickly sold out and widely distributed. A second edition was soon requested in Paris, but the death of Buon, the publisher, created hurdles for its release. A second edition had come out in Frankfort in 1626, another in Amsterdam in 1631, and yet another with notes by the author in 1632. The book had sparked interest among both kings and scholars, and in influential circles throughout Europe, the name Grotius had become well-known. His book provoked the most diverse opinions and elicited contradictory judgments, but among lawyers and politicians, it was generally received with admiration from the start. Despite his exile, poverty, and misfortunes, Grotius had become a European celebrity and was on the verge of reaping the rewards of his work. He had created a code for war and a framework for peace, and from then on, no statesman could afford to overlook him.
Gustavus Adolphus, the king of Sweden, before his death on the battlefield of Lützen, had commended Grotius to his great Chancellor, Oxenstiern. By the death of Gustavus the Chancellor had, in 1633, recently come into the regency of the kingdom at a critical moment when a retreat from the bitter contest with the Empire seemed to be foredoomed unless prevented by the support and friendship of France. Recalling the commendation of the late king, Oxenstiern sought and found in Grotius an ambassador of Sweden to negotiate a new Franco-Swedish alliance. Accepting this appointment in 1634, Grotius arrived at Paris on his diplomatic mission on March 2d, 1635.
Gustavus Adolphus, the king of Sweden, before he died on the battlefield of Lützen, had recommended Grotius to his great Chancellor, Oxenstiern. After Gustavus’s death in 1633, the Chancellor stepped into the regency of the kingdom at a crucial time when a retreat from the harsh struggle with the Empire seemed unavoidable unless France provided support and friendship. Remembering the late king's recommendation, Oxenstiern searched for and found Grotius as Sweden’s ambassador to negotiate a new Franco-Swedish alliance. Accepting this role in 1634, Grotius arrived in Paris for his diplomatic mission on March 2, 1635.
Richelieu, having failed to draw the great jurist into the orbit of his influence as a satellite, resented his appearance in a character so influential and honorable as that of ambassador of Sweden, and Grotius made little progress in his negotiation. Preoccupied with literature, he took more interest in the composition of a sacred tragedy on "The Flight into Egypt" than in reminding France of the existing treaty of Heilbronn or consolidating the new Franco-Swedish alliance. Where Grotius the theorist failed, Oxenstiern, the practical statesman, by a few dexterous strokes of diplomacy during a brief visit to Paris, easily succeeded; and the ambassador's mission was simplified to the rôle of a mere observer and reporter of occurrences.
Richelieu, unable to pull the renowned jurist into his sphere of influence, was irritated by his role as the highly respected ambassador of Sweden, and Grotius didn't make much headway in his negotiations. Focused on literature, he was more interested in writing a sacred tragedy about "The Flight into Egypt" than in reminding France of the existing treaty of Heilbronn or strengthening the new Franco-Swedish alliance. Where Grotius, the theorist, struggled, Oxenstiern, the practical statesman, succeeded easily with some clever diplomatic moves during a brief visit to Paris; the ambassador's role was reduced to that of just an observer and reporter of events.
13 By taste, nature, and training, Grotius was a jurist and not a diplomatist, and he soon realized that the two vocations, if not diametrically opposed, are at least separated from each other by a vast interval. His diplomatic correspondence betrays the keen observer and the conscientious moralist rather than the accomplished negotiator. Among the observations recorded in his dispatches, one may be quoted as an example of his penetration and his humor. Speaking of the Dauphin, the future Louis XIV, he says: "His frightful and precocious avidity is a bad omen for neighboring peoples; for he is at present on his ninth nurse, whom he is rending and murdering as he has the others!"
13 By instinct, background, and experience, Grotius was a legal expert and not a diplomat, and he quickly recognized that the two roles, while not entirely opposite, are at least separated by a significant gap. His diplomatic letters reveal him as a keen observer and a principled moralist rather than a skilled negotiator. One example of his insight and humor can be found in his reports, where he notes about the Dauphin, the future Louis XIV: "His terrifying and overly eager greed is a bad sign for neighboring countries; he is currently on his ninth nurse, whom he is draining and destroying like the others!"
It is painful to behold the great father of international jurisprudence descending in his dispatches to petty details of precedence and alienating from himself the sympathies of his colleagues by ridiculous ceremonial pretensions. He would no longer visit Mazarin, because the Cardinal insisted on calling him Eminence instead of Excellence; Grotius considering this distinction of terms a slight upon his rank as ambassador. So persistent was he in these follies and so rancorous were the feuds that the apostle of peace elicited that, in December, 1636, less than two years after his arrival at Paris, he advised Sweden to send to France a simple Chargé d'Affaires, instead of an ambassador, in order to restore diplomatic relations.
It’s painful to see the great father of international law getting caught up in petty details and pushing away the support of his colleagues with ridiculous formalities. He stopped visiting Mazarin because the Cardinal insisted on calling him Prominence instead of Excellence; Grotius thought this difference in titles was an insult to his position as ambassador. He was so stuck in these trivialities and so bitter were the conflicts he created that, in December 1636, less than two years after he arrived in Paris, he suggested to Sweden that they send a simple Chargé d'Affaires to France instead of an ambassador to mend diplomatic relations.
His quarrels concerning precedence, which rendered him an object of ridicule at the French Court, were not the only griefs of the ambassador of Sweden. Inadequately recompensed, he was obliged to wait two years for his salary and finally, being reduced to a condition in which he could no longer maintain existence otherwise, he was compelled to demand of the royal treasury of France a part of the subsidies promised to the army of his adopted country. Weary of his importunities, the French government repeatedly requested his recall. Disgusted with his mission, Grotius at last abandoned the duties of his office to the intriguing adventurer, Cerisante, who was sent to aid him, and buried himself in his books until his return to Sweden at his own request in 1645.
His arguments about precedence, which made him a laughingstock at the French Court, weren’t the only problems the Swedish ambassador faced. Underpaid, he had to wait two years for his salary and, reaching a point where he could barely survive, he was forced to ask the French royal treasury for a portion of the subsidies that were promised to the army of his adopted country. Tired of his persistent requests, the French government repeatedly asked for his recall. Frustrated with his mission, Grotius eventually left his duties to the scheming opportunist, Cerisante, who was sent to assist him, and buried himself in his books until he returned to Sweden at his own request in 1645.
Queen Christina of Sweden, a patroness of scholars, desirous of aiding Grotius and of retaining him in the service of her kingdom, made many offers and promises,14 but their execution being deferred, he became impatient of his lot, refused a position as counselor of state, and resolved to leave the country. His plan to abandon Stockholm secretly was prevented by a messenger of the queen who followed him to the port where he intended to embark and induced him to return for a farewell audience. With a handsome present of money and silver plate he took passage on a vessel placed at his disposition to convey him to Lübeck. Off the coast near Dantzic a violent tempest arose. On the 17th of August, 1645, the vessel was driven ashore and Grotius, overcome by his trying experiences, was taken ill at Rostock, where a few days later he passed away.
Queen Christina of Sweden, a supporter of scholars, wanting to help Grotius and keep him in her kingdom's service, made many offers and promises,14 but since they were delayed, he became frustrated with his situation, declined a position as state counselor, and decided to leave the country. His plan to leave Stockholm quietly was interrupted by a messenger from the queen who followed him to the port where he planned to board a ship and convinced him to return for a farewell meeting. With a generous gift of money and silver plate, he boarded a vessel provided for him to take him to Lübeck. A fierce storm hit off the coast near Danzig. On August 17, 1645, the ship was driven ashore, and Grotius, overwhelmed by his difficult experiences, fell ill in Rostock, where he passed away a few days later.
The later years of his life had been chiefly devoted to plans for the establishment of peace in the religious world, whose dissensions gave him great distress of mind.
The later years of his life were mostly spent on efforts to create peace in the religious world, as its conflicts caused him a lot of mental anguish.
The country of his birth, which had so long denied him citizenship, received him at last to the silent hospitality of the tomb. His body was taken to Delft, his native town, where his name is now held in grateful reverence.
The country where he was born, which had for so long refused to grant him citizenship, finally accepted him into the quiet embrace of the grave. His body was taken to Delft, his hometown, where his name is now remembered with gratitude.
At the time when Grotius left Stockholm, the last of the plenipotentiaries had arrived at Münster and Osnabrück to attend the great European congress convoked to terminate the hostilities of the Thirty Years' War. It is a tradition, but incapable of satisfactory proof, that it was with the purpose of being present at the councils of this congress that the author of "De Jure Belli ac Pacis" left Sweden for Germany. However this may be, it is certain that the mediation of the king of Denmark at Osnabrück and of the papal legate at Münster, though unsuccessful, was in accordance with the idea of Grotius expressed in the words: "It would be useful, and indeed it is almost necessary, that certain congresses of Christian powers should be held, in which controversies that have arisen among some of them may be decided by others who are not interested." The immediate establishment of an international tribunal, evidently contemplated in this suggestion, was not in harmony with the temper of those times; but it cannot be doubted that the Peace of Westphalia, whose treaties were to form a code of public law for Europe, was to a great degree an embodiment of the principles which Grotius was the first to enunciate.
At the time Grotius left Stockholm, the final delegates had arrived in Münster and Osnabrück for the major European congress called to end the Thirty Years' War. There’s a tradition, though it lacks solid proof, that Grotius intended to be present at the meetings of this congress when he left Sweden for Germany. Regardless of the reasons, it’s clear that the mediation efforts of the king of Denmark in Osnabrück and the papal legate in Münster, though unsuccessful, aligned with Grotius's idea expressed in the statement: "It would be useful, and indeed it is almost necessary, that certain congresses of Christian powers should be held, in which controversies that have arisen among some of them may be decided by others who are not interested." The immediate creation of an international tribunal, which this suggestion clearly anticipated, didn’t fit the mindset of that time; however, there’s no doubt that the Peace of Westphalia, whose treaties were to lay down a code of public law for Europe, largely reflected the principles Grotius was the first to articulate.
15 His "De Jure Belli ac Pacis" had already become a classic even before the author's death, and special professorships were soon founded in the universities to expound its principles. It would be tedious to name the numerous editions, translations, and commentaries which have given it an exceptional place in the literature of Europe. This task has been in part performed, however, by Dr. Rogge in his "Bibliotheca Grotiana," published at The Hague in 1883, and intended to be a full bibliography of Grotius's works. The whole number of titles included is 462, but they do not comprise the writings of the generations of jurists who have been inspired by the great master or of the critics and biographers who have discussed his life and work.
15 His "De Jure Belli ac Pacis" had already become a classic even before the author passed away, and soon after, universities established special professorships to teach its principles. It would be tedious to list all the numerous editions, translations, and commentaries that have granted it a distinguished place in European literature. However, Dr. Rogge has partially addressed this task in his "Bibliotheca Grotiana," published in The Hague in 1883, which aims to be a comprehensive bibliography of Grotius's works. The total number of titles listed is 462, but this does not include the writings of the many jurists inspired by the great master or the critics and biographers who have examined his life and work.
Tardily, but with full contrition for the bitter wrong done to one of her greatest and noblest sons, the memory of Grotius has received from his native land abundant recognition and commemoration. The appropriate tomb that marks his resting place in the Nieuwe Kerk at Delft, symbolical of his learning, genius, and renown, was erected in 1781. On the 17th of September, 1886, a noble statue of the great jurist was unveiled in the public square of his native town in front of the church which contains his tomb. Thus, more than a century after his death, and again still another century later, Holland has paid her tribute of respect to her illustrious citizen.
Slowly, but with deep remorse for the harsh injustice done to one of her greatest and most noble sons, Grotius's memory has finally received significant recognition and remembrance from his homeland. The fitting tomb that marks his resting place in the Nieuwe Kerk in Delft, representing his knowledge, talent, and fame, was built in 1781. On September 17, 1886, a magnificent statue of the great jurist was revealed in the public square of his hometown, in front of the church that holds his tomb. Thus, more than a century after his death, and again another century later, Holland has honored her illustrious citizen.
The later years have also brought new honors to Grotius's feet. At the recent Peace Conference at The Hague was completed the great structure of international comity whose corner stone was laid by him in 1625. It was most fitting that an international congress called in the interest of peace should blend with the negotiation of conventions for the pacific settlement of disputes between nations by a permanent tribunal, and for the amelioration of the laws of war, a celebration of the distinguished writer whose great thought had at last borne such precious fruits. In pursuance of instructions received from the Secretary of State, the United States Commission invited their colleagues in the congress, the heads of the Dutch universities, and the high civic authorities to join with them in observing the 4th of July by celebrating the memory of the great jurist. With appropriate exercises in the apse of the old church, near the monument of Grotius and mausoleum of William16 the Silent, the representatives of twenty-six nations gathered to do him honor. A beautiful commemorative wreath of silver was laid upon Grotius's tomb bearing the inscription:
The later years have also brought new honors to Grotius. At the recent Peace Conference in The Hague, the monumental framework of international cooperation, which he helped establish in 1625, was completed. It was very fitting that an international congress dedicated to peace should coincide with negotiations for treaties aimed at peacefully resolving disputes between nations through a permanent court and improving the laws of war, serving as a celebration of the influential writer whose significant ideas have finally produced such valuable results. Following instructions from the Secretary of State, the United States Commission invited their fellow delegates, heads of Dutch universities, and local leaders to join them in celebrating the 4th of July by honoring the memory of the great jurist. With appropriate ceremonies in the apse of the old church, near the monument of Grotius and the mausoleum of William16 the Silent, representatives from twenty-six nations gathered to pay their respects. A beautiful commemorative silver wreath was placed on Grotius's tomb, inscribed with the words:
TO
THE MEMORY OF HUGO GROTIUS
IN
Reverence and Gratitude
from the United States of America
ON THE
Occasion of the International Peace Conference
AT
The Hague July 4th, 1899.
TO
THE MEMORY OF HUGO GROTIUS
IN
Respect and Appreciation
from the United States
ON THE
Event of the International Peace Conference
AT
The Hague, July 4, 1899.
An eloquent oration by the Honorable Andrew D. White, Ambassador of the United States to Germany, and the head of the Commission, followed by other appropriate addresses, recalled the debt of mankind to the author of "De Jure Belli ac Pacis"; and thus the plenipotentiaries of the nineteenth century did homage to the exile of the sixteenth who had taught the world that even in the shock and storm of battle humanity cannot escape the dominion of its own essential laws, and that even independent states are answerable before the bar of human nature for obedience to principles imposed by a Power higher than the prerogatives of princes or the will of nations.
An eloquent speech by the Honorable Andrew D. White, the U.S. Ambassador to Germany and head of the Commission, along with other relevant addresses, highlighted humanity's debt to the author of "De Jure Belli ac Pacis"; and in this way, the representatives of the nineteenth century paid tribute to the exile of the sixteenth who taught the world that even in the chaos of battle, humanity cannot escape the rules that govern it, and that even independent states are accountable to human nature for abiding by principles set by a Power greater than the authority of kings or the desires of nations.

THE RIGHTS
OF
War and Peace,
INCLUDING
THE LAW OF NATURE AND OF NATIONS.
BOOK 1.
CHAPTER I.
Of War—Definition of War—Right, of Governors and of the governed, and of equals—Right as a Quality divided into Faculty and Fitness—Faculty denoting Power, Property, and Credit—Divided into Private and Superior—Right as a Rule, natural and voluntary—Law of Nature divided—Proofs of the Law of Nature—Division of Rights into human and divine—Human explained—Divine stated—Mosaic Law not binding upon Christians.
About War—Definition of War—Rights of Leaders and Followers, and of Equals—Rights divided into Ability and Suitability—Ability refers to Power, Property, and Credit—Divided into Private and Superior—Rights as a Principle, both natural and voluntary—Law of Nature explained—Evidence of the Law of Nature—Division of Rights into human and divine—Human defined—Divine explained—Mosaic Law not relevant to Christians.
I. The disputes arising among those who are held together by no common bond of civil laws to decide their dissensions, like the ancient Patriarchs, who formed no national community, or the numerous, unconnected communities, whether under the direction of individuals, or kings, or persons invested with Sovereign power, as the leading men in an aristocracy, and the body of the people in a republican government; the disputes, arising among any of these, all bear a relation to the circumstances of war or peace. But because war is undertaken for the sake of peace, and there is no dispute, which may not give rise to war, it will be proper to treat all such quarrels, as commonly happen, between nations, as an article in the rights of war: and then war itself will lead us to peace, as to its proper end.
I. Disputes that arise among people without any common civil laws to resolve their differences are similar to the ancient Patriarchs, who didn’t form a national community, or the many disconnected communities led by individuals, kings, or those in positions of Sovereign power, like the leaders in an aristocracy and the citizens in a republican government. The conflicts that arise among any of these groups are related to the conditions of war or peace. Since war is fought to achieve peace, and any dispute has the potential to lead to war, it’s important to regard these conflicts that commonly occur between nations as part of the rights of war. Ultimately, war itself is meant to guide us toward peace as its true objective.
II. In treating of the rights of war, the first point, that we have to consider, is, what is war, which is the18 subject of our inquiry, and what is the right, which we seek to establish. Cicero styled war a contention by force. But the practice has prevailed to indicate by that name, not an immediate action, but a state of affairs; so that war is the state of contending parties, considered as such. This definition, by its general extent, comprises those wars of every description, that will form the subject of the present treatise. Nor are single combats excluded from this definition. For, as they are in reality more ancient than public wars, and undoubtedly, of the same nature, they may therefore properly be comprehended under one and the same name. This agrees very well with the true derivation of the word. For the Latin word, Bellum, WAR, comes from the old word, Duellum, a DUEL, as Bonus from Duonus, and Bis from Duis. Now Duellum was derived from Duo; and thereby implied a difference between two persons, in the same sense as we term peace, Unity, from Unitas, for a contrary reason. So the Greek word, πολεμος {polemos} commonly used to signify war, expresses in its original, an idea of multitude. The ancient Greeks likewise called it λυη {lyê}, which imports a DISUNION of minds; just as by the term δυη {dyê}, they meant the DISSOLUTION of the parts of the body. Nor does the use of the word, War, contradict this larger acceptation of it. For though some times it is only applied to the quarrels of states, yet that is no objection, as it is evident that a general name is often applied to some particular object, entitled to peculiar distinction. Justice is not included in the definition of war, because the very point to be decided is, whether any war is just, and what war may be so called. Therefore we must make a distinction between war itself, and the justice of it.
II. When discussing the rights of war, the first thing we need to consider is what war is, which is the18 focus of our inquiry, and what right we aim to establish. Cicero described war as a conflict by force. However, the common usage has come to refer to it not as a specific action but rather as a state of being; thus, war is the condition of opposing sides, viewed as such. This definition broadly includes all types of wars that will be addressed in this discussion. Single combats are also included in this definition. Since they are actually older than public wars and are undoubtedly of the same nature, they can rightly be grouped under the same term. This aligns well with the true origin of the word. The Latin word, Bellum, WAR, comes from the older word, Duellum, a DUEL, just as Bonus comes from Duonus, and Bis from Duis. The word Duellum is derived from Duo; thus, it signifies a distinction between two people, in the same way we refer to peace as Unity, which comes from Unitas, for the opposite reason. Similarly, the Greek word, war {polemos}, commonly used to mean war, originally conveys an idea of multitude. The ancient Greeks also referred to it as λυη {lyê}, which denotes a DIVISION of minds; just as they used the term δυη {dyê} to indicate the Dissolution of the body’s parts. The term Conflict does not contradict this broader understanding of it. Although at times it is applied only to the conflicts between states, that doesn’t negate the fact that a general term can often refer to a specific object that deserves special recognition. Justice isn’t part of the definition of war because the core issue to be resolved is whether any war is just, and which wars can be classified as such. Therefore, we need to differentiate between war itself and its justice.
III. As the Rights of War is the title, by which this treatise is distinguished, the first inquiry, as it has been already observed, is whether any war be just, and, in the next place, what constitutes the justice of that war. For, in this place, right signifies nothing more than what is just, and that, more in a negative than a positive sense; so that RIGHT is that, which is not unjust. Now any thing is unjust, which is repugnant to the nature of society, established among rational creatures. Thus for instance, to deprive another of what belongs to him, merely for one's own advantage, is repugnant to the law of nature, as Cicero observes in the fifth Chapter of his third book of offices; and, by way of proof, he19 says that, if the practice were general, all society and intercourse among men must be overturned. Florentinus, the Lawyer, maintains that is impious for one man to form designs against another, as nature has established a degree of kindred amongst us. On this subject, Seneca remarks that, as all the members of the human body agree among themselves, because the preservation of each conduces to the welfare of the whole, so men should forbear from mutual injuries, as they were born for society, which cannot subsist unless all the parts of it are defended by mutual forbearance and good will. But as there is one kind of social tie founded upon an equality, for instance, among brothers, citizens, friends, allies, and another on pre-eminence as Aristotle styles it, subsisting between parents and children, masters and servants, sovereigns and subjects, God and men. So justice takes place either amongst equals, or between the governing and the governed parties, notwithstanding their difference of rank. The former of these, if I am not mistaken, may be called the right of equality, and the latter the right of superiority.
III. Since the title of this treatise is "The Rights of War," the first question, as has already been noted, is whether any war is just, and next, what makes that war just. In this context, "right" simply means what is just, and it refers more to the absence of injustice than to the presence of justice; therefore, RIGHT is that which is not unjust. Anything is unjust if it contradicts the nature of a society made up of rational beings. For example, taking something that belongs to someone else just for your own benefit contradicts the law of nature, as Cicero points out in Chapter 5 of his third book on duties. He argues that if this were a common practice, all social interactions among people would break down. Florentinus, the lawyer, states that it is wrong for one person to plot against another, as nature itself has established a bond of kinship among us. Seneca notes that just as all the parts of the human body work together because the survival of each part contributes to the health of the entire organism, people should avoid harming one another, as they were born to live in society, which can only exist if all its members practice tolerance and goodwill towards each other. Moreover, there are two types of social bonds: one based on equality, such as among siblings, citizens, friends, and allies, and another based on hierarchy, as Aristotle describes, which exists between parents and children, masters and servants, rulers and subjects, and God and humans. Thus, justice applies either among equals or between those who govern and those who are governed, despite their differences in status. The first type may be referred to as the right of equality, and the latter as the right of superiority.
IV. There is another signification of the word RIGHT, different from this, but yet arising from it, which relates directly to the person. In which sense, RIGHT is a moral quality annexed to the person, justly entitling him to possess some particular privilege, or to perform some particular act. This right is annexed to the person, although it sometimes follows the things, as the services of lands, which are called REAL RIGHTS, in opposition to those merely PERSONAL. Not because these rights are not annexed to persons, but the distinction is made, because they belong to the persons only who possess some particular things. This moral quality, when perfect is called a FACULTY; when imperfect, an APTITUDE. The former answers to the ACT, and the latter to the POWER, when we speak of natural things.
IV. There is another meaning of the word RIGHT, different from this one but still related, which pertains directly to the individual. In this sense, RIGHT is a moral quality associated with the person, justly entitling them to have a specific privilege or to take a certain action. This right is attached to the person, even though it sometimes pertains to things, like the rights associated with land, which are referred to as REAL RIGHTS, in contrast to those that are merely PRIVATE. Not because these rights aren't linked to individuals, but the distinction is made because they only belong to those who possess specific things. This moral quality, when fully developed, is called a FACULTY; when not fully developed, it's called an SKILL. The former relates to the ACT, and the latter to the POWER, when we discuss natural things.
V. Civilians call a faculty that Right, which every man has to his own; but we shall hereafter, taking it in its strict and proper sense, call it a right. This right comprehends the power, that we have over ourselves, which is called liberty, and the power, that we have over others, as that of a father over his children, and of a master over his slaves. It likewise comprehends property, which is either complete or imperfect; of the latter kind is the use or possession of any thing without the property, or20 power of alienating it, or pledges detained by the creditors till payment be made. There is a third signification, which implies the power of demanding what is due, to which the obligation upon the party indebted, to discharge what is owing, corresponds.
V. People refer to a right that everyone has over their own things as "faculty," but here, we'll refer to it more precisely as a right. This right includes the control we have over ourselves, known as liberty, and the control we have over others, like a father's authority over his children or a master's authority over his slaves. It also includes property, which can be either complete or incomplete; the latter refers to the use or possession of something without ownership, or the ability to sell it, as well as items kept by creditors until payment is made. There’s a third meaning, which involves the right to demand what is owed, corresponding to the obligation of the debtor to repay what they owe.
VI. Right, strictly taken, is again twofold, the one, PRIVATE, established for the advantage of each individual, the other, SUPERIOR, as involving the claims, which the state has upon individuals, and their property, for the public good. Thus the Regal authority is above that of a father and a master, and the Sovereign has a greater right over the property of his subjects, where the public good is concerned, than the owners themselves have. And when the exigencies of the state require a supply, every man is more obliged to contribute towards it, than to satisfy his creditors.
VI. Right, in its strict sense, is twofold: one is PRIVATE, established for the benefit of each individual, the other is BETTER, which relates to the claims that the state has on individuals and their property for the public good. Thus, the authority of the ruler is greater than that of a father or a master, and the Sovereign has a stronger claim over the property of their subjects when the public good is at stake than the owners themselves do. When the needs of the state arise, everyone is more obligated to contribute to it than to pay off their debts.
VII. Aristotle distinguishes aptitude or capacity, by the name of worth or merit, and Michael of Ephesus, gives the epithet of SUITABLE or BECOMING to the equality established by this rule of merit.
VII. Aristotle distinguishes ability or capacity, referring to it as worth or merit, and Michael of Ephesus uses the terms APPROPRIATE or BECOMING to describe the equality established by this rule of merit.
IX.1 There is also a third signification of the word Right, which has the same meaning as Law taken in its most extensive sense, to denote a rule of moral action, obliging us to do what is proper. We say OBLIGING us. For the best counsels or precepts, if they lay us under no obligation to obey them, cannot come under the denomination of law or right. Now as to permission,2 it is no act of the law, but only the silence of the law, it however prohibits any one from impeding another in doing what the law permits. But we have said, the law obliges us to do what is proper, not simply what is just; because, under this notion, right belongs to the substance not only of justice, as we have explained it, but of all other virtues. Yet from giving the name of a RIGHT to21 that, which is PROPER, a more general acceptation of the word justice has been derived. The best division of right, in this general meaning, is to be found in Aristotle, who, defining one kind to be natural, and the other voluntary, calls it a LAWFUL RIGHT in the strictest sense of the word law; and some times an instituted right. The same difference is found among the Hebrews, who, by way of distinction, in speaking, call that natural right, PRECEPTS, and the voluntary right, STATUTES: the former of which the Septuagint call δικαιώματα {dikaiômata}, and the latter ἐντολας {entolas}.
IX.1 There is also a third meaning of the word Right, which has the same definition as Law in its broadest sense, referring to a rule of moral behavior that requires us to do what is proper. We say REQUIRES us. Because the best advice or guidelines, if they don’t require us to follow them, cannot really be considered law or right. Now, regarding permission, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, it is not an act of the law, but merely the absence of law; however, it does prevent anyone from stopping another person from doing what the law allows. But we’ve stated that the law requires us to do what is proper, not just what is fair; because, under this idea, right pertains to the essence not only of justice, as we’ve described it, but of all other virtues. Yet by naming RIGHT to what is CORRECT, a broader meaning of the word justice has emerged. The best classification of right, in this broad sense, is found in Aristotle, who categorizes one type as natural and the other as voluntary, calling it a Legal Right in the strictest sense of the term law; and sometimes an instituted right. The same distinction exists among the Hebrews, who, for differentiation, refer to natural right as Principles and voluntary right as LAWS: the former of which the Septuagint calls rights {dikaiômata}, and the latter ἐντολας {entolas}.
X. Natural right is the dictate of right reason, shewing the moral turpitude, or moral necessity,3 of any act from its agreement or disagreement with a rational nature, and consequently that such an act is either forbidden or commanded by God, the author of nature. The actions, upon which such a dictate is given, are either binding or unlawful in themselves, and therefore necessarily understood to be commanded or forbidden by God. This mark distinguishes natural right, not only from human law, but from the law, which God himself has been pleased to reveal, called, by some, the voluntary divine right, which does not command or forbid things in themselves either binding or unlawful, but makes them unlawful by its prohibition, and binding by its command. But, to understand natural right, we must observe that some things are said to belong to that right, not properly, but, as the schoolmen say, by way of accommodation. These are not repugnant to natural right, as we have already observed that those things are called JUST, in which there is no injustice. Some times also, by a wrong use of the word, those things which reason shews to be proper, or better than things of an opposite kind, although not binding, are said to belong to natural right.
X. Natural right is the guidance of right reason, showing the moral wrongness or moral necessity of any action based on its alignment or misalignment with rational nature. Consequently, such an action is either forbidden or commanded by God, who is the author of nature. The actions that follow this guidance are either inherently binding or unlawful, and therefore are understood to be commanded or prohibited by God. This characteristic sets natural right apart not only from human law, but also from the law that God Himself has revealed, known by some as voluntary divine right, which does not inherently command or forbid actions that are binding or unlawful, but instead makes them unlawful through its prohibition and binding through its command. However, to grasp natural right, we must note that some things are said to belong to it not in a direct sense, but as the schoolmen put it, by way of accommodation. These are not contradictory to natural right; as we've noted, those things are called JUST in which there is no injustice. Sometimes, due to a misuse of the term, things that reason shows to be appropriate or preferable to things of an opposite nature, even though they are not binding, are also said to belong to natural right.
We must farther remark, that natural right relates not only to those things that exist independent of the human will, but to many things which necessarily follow the exercise of that will. Thus property, as now in use, was at first a creature of the human will. But, after it was established, one man was prohibited by the law of nature from seizing the property of another against his will. Wherefore, Paulus the Lawyer said, that theft is expressly forbidden by the law of nature. Ulpian condemns22 it as infamous in its own nature; to whose authority that of Euripides may be added, as may be seen in the verses of Helena:
We should also point out that natural rights not only involve things that exist independently of human choice but also many things that necessarily follow from the exercise of that choice. For example, property, as we understand it today, was originally created by human choice. However, once it was established, nature's law prohibits one person from taking another's property against their will. That’s why Paulus the Lawyer stated that theft is clearly forbidden by natural law. Ulpian considers it inherently disgraceful; we can also reference Euripides's authority, as seen in the verses of Helena:
"For God himself hates violence, and will not have us to grow rich by rapine, but by lawful gains. That abundance, which is the fruit of unrighteousness, is an abomination. The air is common to men, the earth also, where every man, in the ample enjoyment of his possession, must refrain from doing violence or injury to that of another."
"For God hates violence and doesn't want us to get rich through wrongdoing, but through honest means. The wealth that comes from injustice is detestable. The air is free for everyone, and so is the earth, where everyone, while enjoying their own possessions, must avoid harming or injuring others."
Now the Law of Nature is so unalterable, that it cannot be changed even by God himself. For although the power of God is infinite, yet there are some things, to which it does not extend. Because the things so expressed would have no true meaning, but imply a contradiction. Thus two and two must make four, nor is it possible to be otherwise; nor, again, can what is really evil not be evil. And this is Aristotle's meaning, when he says, that some things are no sooner named, than we discover their evil nature. For as the substance of things in their nature and existence depends upon nothing but themselves; so there are qualities inseparably connected with their being and essence. Of this kind is the evil of certain actions, compared with the nature of a reasonable being. Therefore God himself suffers his actions to be judged by this rule, as may be seen in the xviiith chap. of Gen. 25. Isa. v. 3. Ezek. xviii. 25. Jer. ii. 9. Mich. vi. 2. Rom. ii. 6., iii. 6. Yet it sometimes happens that, in those cases, which are decided by the law of nature, the undiscerning are imposed upon by an appearance of change. Whereas in reality there is no change in the unalterable law of nature, but only in the things appointed by it, and which are liable to variation. For example, if a creditor forgive me the debt, which I owe him, I am no longer bound to pay it, not because the law of nature has ceased to command the payment of a just debt, but because my debt, by a release, has ceased to be a debt. On this topic, Arrian in Epictetus argues rightly, that the borrowing of money is not the only requisite to make a debt, but there must be the additional circumstance of the loan remaining undischarged. Thus if God should command the life, or property of any one to be taken away, the act would not authorise murder or robbery, words which always include a crime. But that cannot be murder or robbery, which23 is done by the express command of Him, who is the sovereign Lord of our lives and of all things. There are also some things allowed by the law of nature, not absolutely, but according to a certain state of affairs. Thus, by the law of nature, before property was introduced, every one had a right to the use of whatever he found unoccupied; and, before laws were enacted, to avenge his personal injuries by force.
Now the Law of Nature is so unchangeable that it can't even be altered by God himself. Even though God's power is infinite, there are some things it doesn't cover because those things would lack true meaning and imply a contradiction. For instance, two plus two must equal four; it cannot be otherwise, nor can anything that is truly evil not be evil. This is what Aristotle meant when he said that some things, as soon as they are named, reveal their evil nature. The essence of things relies solely on themselves, meaning there are qualities that are inseparably linked to their being and essence. One of these qualities is the evil of certain actions, especially concerning the nature of a rational being. Therefore, God himself allows His actions to be judged by this standard, as seen in Genesis 18:25, Isaiah 5:3, Ezekiel 18:25, Jeremiah 2:9, Micah 6:2, Romans 2:6, and 3:6. However, it sometimes appears to those who don't see clearly that there is a change regarding cases decided by the law of nature. In reality, there is no change in the unchangeable law of nature, only in the things it governs, which can vary. For example, if a creditor forgives me the debt I owe him, I'm no longer obligated to pay it, not because the law of nature has stopped requiring the payment of a just debt, but because my debt has ceased to exist due to the forgiveness. Regarding this, Arrian in Epictetus argues correctly that borrowing money isn't the sole requirement to create a debt; there must also be the condition of the loan remaining unpaid. Thus, if God were to command that someone’s life or property be taken away, that action wouldn't justify murder or robbery, terms that inherently involve a crime. But what cannot be considered murder or robbery is what23 is carried out by the express command of Him, who is the sovereign Lord of our lives and of everything. There are also certain things allowed by the law of nature, not absolutely, but depending on specific circumstances. Before property rights were established, for example, everyone had the right to use whatever they found unoccupied; and before laws were made, individuals could seek vengeance for personal injuries by force.
XI. The distinction found in the books of the Roman Law, assigning one unchangeable right to brutes in common with man, which in a more limited sense they call the law of nature, and appropriating another to men, which they frequently call the Law of Nations, is scarcely of any real use. For no beings, except those that can form general maxims, are capable of possessing a right, which Hesiod has placed in a clear point of view, observing "that the supreme Being has appointed laws for men; but permitted wild beasts, fishes, and birds to devour each other for food." For they have nothing like justice, the best gift, bestowed upon men.
XI. The distinction made in the writings of Roman Law, which assigns one unchangeable right to animals alongside humans, referred to in a more limited sense as the law of nature, and another right to humans, often called the Law of Nations, is of little practical value. This is because only beings capable of forming general principles can possess rights. Hesiod clearly pointed this out, noting "that the supreme Being has established laws for humans; but allowed wild animals, fish, and birds to eat each other for food." They lack anything resembling justice, the greatest gift given to humans.
Cicero, in his first book of offices, says we do not talk of the justice of horses or lions. In conformity to which, Plutarch, in the life of Cato the elder, observes, that we are formed by nature to use law and justice towards men only. In addition to the above, Lactantius may be cited, who, in his fifth book, says that in all animals devoid of reason we see a natural bias of self-love. For they hurt others to benefit themselves; because they do not know the evil of doing wilful hurt. But it is not so with man, who, possessing the knowledge of good and evil, refrains, even with inconvenience to himself, from doing hurt. Polybius, relating the manner in which men first entered into society, concludes, that the injuries done to parents or benefactors inevitably provoke the indignation of mankind, giving an additional reason, that as understanding and reflection form the great difference between men and other animals, it is evident they cannot transgress the bounds of that difference like other animals, without exciting universal abhorrence of their conduct. But if ever justice is attributed to brutes, it is done improperly, from some shadow and trace of reason they may possess. But it is not material to the nature of right, whether the actions appointed by the law of nature, such as the care of our offspring, are common to us with other animals or not, or, like the worship of God, are peculiar to man.
Cicero, in his first book about duties, states that we don’t talk about the justice of horses or lions. Following this, Plutarch, in the life of Cato the Elder, points out that we are naturally inclined to use law and justice only towards other humans. Additionally, Lactantius can be referenced; in his fifth book, he says that all animals without reason show a natural tendency toward self-love. They harm others to benefit themselves because they don’t understand the harm of intentionally causing injury. However, this isn’t the case for humans, who, knowing the difference between good and evil, choose not to harm others even when it’s inconvenient for themselves. Polybius, discussing how humans first formed societies, concludes that injuries committed against parents or benefactors provoke the anger of people. He adds that since understanding and reflection create a significant difference between humans and other animals, it’s clear that people cannot overstep that difference like animals do without provoking widespread disgust for their actions. If justice is ever attributed to animals, it is done incorrectly, based on some semblance and trace of reason they might possess. However, it doesn’t matter to the nature of right whether the actions dictated by the law of nature, such as caring for our offspring, are shared with other animals or if, like the worship of God, they are unique to humans.
24 XII. The existence of the Law of Nature is proved by two kinds of argument, a priori, and a posteriori, the former a more abstruse, and the latter a more popular method of proof. We are said to reason a priori, when we show the agreement or disagreement of any thing with a reasonable and social nature; but a posteriori, when without absolute proof, but only upon probability, any thing is inferred to accord with the law of nature, because it is received as such among all, or at least the more civilized nations. For a general effect can only arise from a general cause. Now scarce any other cause can be assigned for so general an opinion, but the common sense, as it is called, of mankind. There is a sentence of Hesiod that has been much praised, that opinions which have prevailed amongst many nations, must have some foundation. Heraclitus, establishing common reason as the best criterion of truth, says, those things are certain which generally appear so. Among other authorities, we may quote Aristotle, who says it is a strong proof in our favour, when all appear to agree with what we say, and Cicero maintains that the consent of all nations in any case is to be admitted for the law of nature. Seneca is of the same opinion, any thing, says he, appearing the same to all men is a proof of its truth. Quintilian says, we hold those things to be true, in which all men agree. We have called them the more civilized nations, and not without reason. For, as Porphyry well observes, some nations are so strange that no fair judgment of human nature can be formed from them, for it would be erroneous. Andronicus, the Rhodian says, that with men of a right and sound understanding, natural justice is unchangeable. Nor does it alter the case, though men of disordered and perverted minds think otherwise. For he who should deny that honey is sweet, because it appears not so to men of a distempered taste, would be wrong. Plutarch too agrees entirely with what has been said, as appears from a passage in his life of Pompey, affirming that man neither was, nor is, by nature, a wild unsociable creature. But it is the corruption of his nature which makes him so: yet by acquiring new habits, by changing his place, and way of living, he may be reclaimed to his original gentleness. Aristotle, taking a description of man from his peculiar qualities, makes him an animal of a gentle nature, and in another part of his works, he observes,25 that in considering the nature of man, we are to take our likeness from nature in its pure, and not in its corrupt state.
24 XII. The existence of the Law of Nature is supported by two types of arguments: a priori and a posteriori. The first is a more abstract approach, while the second is more common and straightforward. We reason a priori when we show how something aligns or conflicts with a rational and social nature. On the other hand, we reason a posteriori when we assume something fits the law of nature based on probability rather than absolute proof, particularly because it is accepted as such by everyone or at least by the more civilized nations. A general effect can only come from a general cause. Rarely can we attribute such a widespread belief to anything other than the common sense, as it’s called, of humanity. There’s a well-regarded quote from Hesiod stating that beliefs held across many nations must have some basis. Heraclitus supports common reason as the best measure of truth, claiming that things which generally seem true are indeed certain. Additionally, we can reference Aristotle, who mentions it’s strong evidence in our favor when everyone seems to agree with our viewpoint, and Cicero argues that the consensus of all nations in any case should be recognized as the law of nature. Seneca shares this view, asserting that anything perceived the same way by all people is proof of its truth. Quintilian states that we consider as true those things that everyone agrees upon. We refer to them as the more civilized nations for good reason. As Porphyry notes, some nations are so unusual that we can't make a fair judgment about human nature based on them, as it would lead to errors. Andronicus the Rhodian says that for those with sound judgment, natural justice is unchangeable, regardless of what those with warped minds might think. For instance, claiming that honey is not sweet just because it seems different to people with a bad sense of taste would be incorrect. Plutarch aligns with these views in his biography of Pompey, stating that humans are not naturally wild or unsociable creatures. Instead, it’s the corruption of their nature that leads them to behave that way; however, they can return to their original gentleness through new habits, changes in environment, and lifestyles. Aristotle describes humans in terms of their unique qualities, identifying them as gentle creatures. In another part of his work, he notes that when examining human nature, we should look at it in its pure state rather than its corrupted form.25
XIII. It has been already remarked, that there is another kind of right, which is the voluntary right, deriving its origin from the will, and is either human or divine.
XIII. It has already been noted that there is another type of right, which is the voluntary right, originating from the will and can be either human or divine.
XIV. We will begin with the human as more generally known. Now this is either a civil right, or a right more or less extensive than the civil right. The civil right is that which is derived from the civil power. The civil power is the sovereign power of the state. A state is a perfect body of free men, united together in order to enjoy common rights and advantages. The less extensive right, and not derived from the civil power itself, although subject to it, is various, comprehending the authority of parents over children, masters over servants, and the like. But the law of nations is a more extensive right, deriving its authority from the consent of all, or at least of many nations.
XIV. We will start with what we generally know about humans. This is either a civil right or a right that is more or less broad than the civil right. A civil right comes from the civil authority. The civil authority is the ruling power of the state. A state is a complete group of free individuals who come together to enjoy shared rights and benefits. The less broad right, which does not come directly from the civil authority but is still subject to it, varies and includes the authority of parents over children, masters over servants, and similar relationships. However, international law represents a broader right, gaining its power from the agreement of all, or at least many nations.
It was proper to add MANY, because scarce any right can be found common to all nations, except the law of nature, which itself too is generally called the law of nations. Nay, frequently in one part of the world, that is held for the law of nations, which is not so in another. Now this law of nations is proved in the same manner as the unwritten civil law, and that is by the continual experience and testimony of the Sages of the Law. For this law, as Dio Chrysostom well observes, is the discoveries made by experience and time. And in this we derive great advantage from the writings of eminent historians.
It was appropriate to add MANY, because hardly any right can be found that is common to all nations, except for the law of nature, which is often referred to as the law of nations. In fact, what is considered the law of nations in one part of the world may not be recognized as such in another. This law of nations is proven in the same way as the unwritten civil law, through the ongoing experience and testimony of legal scholars. As Dio Chrysostom wisely points out, this law is based on discoveries made through experience and time. We gain significant insights from the writings of distinguished historians.
XV. The very meaning of the words divine voluntary right, shows that it springs from the divine will, by which it is distinguished from natural law, which, it has already been observed, is called divine also. This law admits of what Anaxarchus said, as Plutarch relates in the life of Alexander, though without sufficient accuracy, that God does not will a thing, because it is just, but that it is just, or binding, because God wills it. Now this law was given either to mankind in general, or to one particular people. We find three periods, at which it was given by God to the human race, the first of which was immediately after the creation of man, the second upon the restoration of mankind after the flood,26 and the third upon that more glorious restoration through Jesus Christ. These three laws undoubtedly bind all men, as soon as they come to a sufficient knowledge of them.
XV. The very meaning of the term "divine voluntary right" shows that it comes from God's will, which sets it apart from natural law, which, as noted before, is also considered divine. This law supports what Anaxarchus mentioned, as Plutarch recounts in Alexander's life, though not entirely accurately, that God does not will something because it is just, but rather, something is just or binding because God wills it. This law was given either to all of humanity or to a specific group of people. There are three key moments when God provided this law to humankind: first, immediately after the creation of man; second, when humanity was restored after the flood,26 and third, during the more glorious restoration through Jesus Christ. These three laws undoubtedly obligate everyone once they come to a sufficient understanding of them.
XVI. Of all nations there is but one, to which God particularly vouchsafed to give laws; and that was the people of Israel, whom Moses thus addresses in the fourth Chap. of Deuteronomy, ver. 7. "What nation is there so great who hath God so nigh unto them, as the Lord our God is in all things that we call upon him for? And what nation is there so great, who have statutes and judgments so righteous, as all this law, which I set before you this day!" And the Psalmist in the cxlvii. Psalm, "God shewed his word unto Jacob, his statutes and ordinances unto Israel. He hath not dealt so with any nation, and as for his judgments they have not known them." Nor can we doubt but that those Jews, with whom we may class Tryphon in his dispute with Justin, are mistaken, who suppose that even strangers, if they wish to be saved, must submit to the yoke of the Mosaic Law. For a law does not bind those, to whom it has not been given. But it speaks personally to those, who are immediately under it. Hear O Israel, and we read everywhere of the covenant made with them, by which they became the peculiar people of God. Maimonides acknowledges and proves the truth of this from the xxxiii. Chapter and fourth verse of Deuteronomy.
XVI. Among all nations, there is only one that God specifically chose to give laws to: the people of Israel. Moses speaks to them in the fourth chapter of Deuteronomy, verse 7: "What nation is so great that has God so close to them as the Lord our God is to us whenever we call on him? And what nation is so great that has laws and rules as righteous as all this law I present to you today?" The Psalmist in Psalm 147 states, "God revealed his word to Jacob, his laws and decrees to Israel. He hasn't done this for any other nation; they don't know his judgments." We should not doubt that the Jews, including Tryphon in his debate with Justin, are wrong in believing that even outsiders, if they want to be saved, must follow the Mosaic Law. Laws do not apply to those who have not been given them. Instead, they address those who are directly under them. "Hear, O Israel," and we often read about the covenant made with them, which made them God's chosen people. Maimonides acknowledges and proves this truth based on the 33rd chapter and 4th verse of Deuteronomy.
But among the Hebrews themselves there were always living some strangers, persons devout and fearing God, such was the Syrophoenician woman, mentioned in the Gospel of St. Matthew, xv. 22. Cornelius the Centurion. Acts. x. the devout Greeks, Acts xviii. 6. Sojourners, or strangers, also are mentioned. Levit. xxv. 47. These, as the Hebrew Rabbis themselves inform us, were obliged to observe the laws given to Adam and Noah, to abstain from idols and blood, and other things, that were prohibited; but not in the same manner to observe the laws peculiar to the people of Israel. Therefore though the Israelites were not allowed to eat the flesh of a beast, that had died a natural death; yet the strangers living among them were permitted. Deut. xiv. 21. Except in some particular laws, where it was expressly said, that strangers no less than the native inhabitants were obliged to observe them. Strangers also, who came from other countries, and were not subject to the Jewish laws, might27 worship God in the temple of Jerusalem, but standing in a place separate and distinct from the Israelites. I. Kings viii. 41. 2 Mac. iii. 35. John xii. 20. Acts viii. 27. Nor did Elisha ever signify to Naaman the Syrian, nor Jonas to the Ninevites, nor Daniel to Nebuchadnezzar, nor the other Prophets to the Tyrians, the Moabites, the Egyptians, to whom they wrote, that it was necessary for them to adopt the Mosaic Law.
But among the Hebrews, there were always some outsiders, people who were devout and feared God. An example is the Syrophoenician woman mentioned in the Gospel of St. Matthew, xv. 22. Cornelius the Centurion, as noted in Acts x. and the devout Greeks mentioned in Acts xviii. 6, also fit this description. Sojourners or strangers are mentioned in Leviticus xxv. 47. According to the Hebrew Rabbis, these individuals were required to follow the laws given to Adam and Noah, which meant they had to avoid idols and blood, along with other prohibitions. However, they were not required to adhere to the laws specific to the people of Israel. Therefore, while the Israelites were not allowed to eat the flesh of an animal that died naturally, the strangers living among them were permitted to do so, as noted in Deuteronomy xiv. 21. There were some specific laws where it was clearly stated that strangers, just like the native inhabitants, had to follow them. Strangers from other countries who were not subject to Jewish laws could worship God in the temple of Jerusalem, but they had to stand in a separate area from the Israelites, as detailed in I Kings viii. 41, 2 Maccabees iii. 35, John xii. 20, and Acts viii. 27. Neither Elisha indicated to Naaman the Syrian, nor Jonah to the Ninevites, nor Daniel to Nebuchadnezzar, nor other prophets to the Tyrians, Moabites, or Egyptians that they needed to adopt the Mosaic Law.
What has been said of the whole law of Moses applies to circumcision, which was a kind of introduction to the law. Yet with this difference that the Israelites alone were bound by the Mosaic Law, but the whole posterity of Abraham by the law of circumcision. From hence we are informed by Jewish and Greek Historians, that the Idumaeans, or Edomites were compelled by the Jews to be circumcised. Wherefore there is reason to believe that the numerous nations, who, besides the Israelites, practised circumcision, and who are mentioned by Herodotus, Strabo, Philo, Justin, Origen, Clemens, Alexandrinus, Epiphanius, and Jerom, were descended from Ishmael, Esau, or the posterity of Keturah. But what St. Paul says, Rom. ii. 14. holds good of all other nations; that the Gentiles, not having the law, yet doing by nature the things contained in the law, become a law to themselves. Here the word nature may be taken for the primitive source of moral obligation; or, referring it to the preceding parts of the Epistle, it may signify the knowledge, which the Gentiles acquired of themselves without instruction, in opposition to the knowledge derived to the Jews from the law, which was instilled into them from their cradle, and almost from their birth. "So the Gentiles show the work, or the moral precepts of the law, written in their hearts, their consciences also bearing witness, and their thoughts the mean while accusing or else excusing one another." And again in the 26th ver.; "If the uncircumcision keep the righteousness of the law, shall not his uncircumcision be counted for circumcision?" Therefore Ananias, the Jew, as we find in the history of Josephus, very properly taught Tzates, or as Tacitus calls him, Ezates, the Adiabenian, that even without circumcision, God might be rightly worshipped and rendered propitious. For though many strangers were circumcised, among the Jews, and by circumcision bound themselves to observe the law, as St. Paul explains it in Gal. v. 3.; they did28 it partly to obtain the freedom of the country; for proselytes called by the Hebrews, proselytes of righteousness, enjoyed equal privileges with the Israelites. Num. xv.: and partly to obtain a share in those promises, which were not common to mankind, but peculiar to the Jewish people, although it cannot be denied, that in later ages an erroneous opinion prevailed, that there was no salvation out of the Jewish pale. Hence we may infer, that we are bound by no part of the Levitical law, strictly and properly so called; because any obligation, beyond that arising from the law of nature, must proceed from the express will of the law-giver. Now it cannot be discovered by any proof, that God intended any other people, but the Israelites to be bound by that law. Therefore with respect to ourselves, we have no occasion to prove an abrogation of that law; for it could never be abrogated with respect to those, whom it never bound. But the Israelites were released from the ceremonial part, as soon as the law of the Gospel was proclaimed; a clear revelation of which was made to one of the Apostles, Acts x. 15. And the other parts of the Mosaic law lost their peculiar distinction, when the Jews ceased to be a people by the desolation and destruction of their city without any hopes of restoration. Indeed it was not a release from the law of Moses that we, who were strangers to the Commonwealth of Israel, obtained by the coming of Christ. But as before that time, our hopes in the goodness of God were obscure and uncertain, we gained the assurance of an express covenant, that we should be united in one Church with the seed of Israel, the children of the patriarchs, their law, that was the wall of separation between us, being broken down. Eph. ii. 14.
What has been said about the entire law of Moses also applies to circumcision, which served as an introduction to the law. However, the difference is that only the Israelites were obligated to follow the Mosaic Law, while all descendants of Abraham were subject to the law of circumcision. From this, we learn from both Jewish and Greek historians that the Idumaeans, or Edomites, were forced by the Jews to be circumcised. Thus, it’s reasonable to believe that the many nations, besides the Israelites, who practiced circumcision and are mentioned by Herodotus, Strabo, Philo, Justin, Origen, Clemens Alexandrinus, Epiphanius, and Jerome, were descended from Ishmael, Esau, or the descendants of Keturah. But what St. Paul says in Romans 2:14 applies to all other nations; that the Gentiles, who do not have the law, yet naturally do the things contained in the law, become a law to themselves. Here, the term "nature" can refer to the original source of moral obligation; or, relating to earlier parts of the letter, it may indicate the knowledge that Gentiles gained on their own without any teaching, in contrast to the knowledge given to the Jews through the law, which was instilled in them from childhood. "So the Gentiles show the work, or the moral principles of the law, written in their hearts, their consciences bearing witness, and their thoughts accusing or excusing one another." And again in verse 26: "If the uncircumcised keep the righteousness of the law, will not his uncircumcision be counted as circumcision?" Therefore, Ananias, the Jew, as noted in Josephus's history, rightly taught Tzates, or Ezates as Tacitus calls him, the Adiabenian, that even without circumcision, God could be properly worshipped and pleased. Although many non-Jews were circumcised among the Jews and bound themselves to observe the law, as St. Paul explains in Galatians 5:3, they did it partly to gain citizenship in the land; for proselytes, referred to by Hebrews as proselytes of righteousness, enjoyed the same rights as the Israelites (Numbers 15). They also did it partly to share in the promises that were not for all humanity but specific to the Jewish people, though it cannot be denied that over time, a mistaken belief grew that there was no salvation outside of Judaism. Thus, we can conclude that we are not bound by any portion of the Levitical law, strictly and accurately understood. Any obligation beyond that coming from the law of nature must come from the explicit will of the lawgiver. Now, there is no evidence that God intended anyone other than the Israelites to be subject to that law. Therefore, regarding us, there is no need to prove that the law was annulled because it could never have been annulled for those to whom it never applied. However, the Israelites were freed from the ceremonial aspects as soon as the law of the Gospel was declared; a clear revelation of which was made to one of the Apostles in Acts 10:15. The other aspects of the Mosaic law lost their unique status when the Jews stopped being a people due to the devastation and destruction of their city, with no hope for restoration. Indeed, it was not a release from the law of Moses that those of us who were outside the Commonwealth of Israel received with the coming of Christ. But before that time, our hopes in God's goodness were vague and uncertain; we gained the assurance of a clear covenant that we would be united in one Church with the descendants of Israel, the children of the patriarchs, their law, which was the barrier between us, being broken down (Ephesians 2:14).
XVII. Since then the law given by Moses imposes no direct obligation upon us, as it has been already shown, let us consider whether it has any other use both in this inquiry into the rights of war, and in other questions of the same kind. In the first place, the Mosaic law shows that what it enjoins is not contrary to the law of nature. For since the law of nature is perpetual and unchangeable, nothing contradictory to it could be commanded by God, who is never unjust. Besides the law of Moses is called in the xix. Psalm an undefiled and right law, and St. Paul, Rom. vii. 12, describes it to be holy, just, and good. Its precepts are here spoken of, for its permissions29 require a more distinct discussion. For the bare permission, signifying the removal of an impediment, or prohibition, has no relation to the present subject. A positive, legal permission is either full, granting us power to do some particular act without the least restriction, or less full, only allowing men impunity for certain actions, and a right to do them without molestation from others. From the permission of the former kind no less than from a positive precept, it follows that what the law allows, is not contrary to the law of nature.4 But with regard to the latter kind of permission, allowing impunity for certain acts, but not expressly authorizing them, we cannot so readily conclude those acts to be conformable to the law of nature.5 Because where the words of permission are ambiguous in their meaning, it is better for us to interpret according to the established law of nature, what kind of permission it is, than from our conception of its expediency to conclude it conformable to the laws of nature. Connected with this first observation there is another, expressive of the power that obtains among Christian Princes to enact laws of the same import with those given by Moses, except such as related entirely to the time of the expected Messiah, and the Gospel then unrevealed, or where Christ himself has in a general or particular manner established any thing to the contrary. For except in these three cases, no reason can be devised, why any thing established by the law of Moses should be now unlawful. In the third place it may be observed, that whatever the law of Moses enjoined relating to those virtues, which Christ required of his disciples, should be30 fulfilled by Christians now, in a greater degree, from their superior knowledge, and higher motives. Thus the virtues of humility, patience, and charity are required of Christians in a more perfect manner than of the Jews under the Mosaic dispensation, because the promises of heaven are more clearly laid before us in the Gospel. Hence the old law, when compared with the Gospel, is said to have been neither perfect nor faultless, and Christ is said to be the end of the law, and the law our schoolmaster to bring us to Christ. Thus the old law respecting the Sabbath, and the law respecting tithes, show that Christians are bound to devote not less than a seventh portion of their time to divine worship, nor less than a tenth of their fruits to maintain those who are employed in holy things, or to other pious uses.
XVII. Since the law given by Moses doesn’t impose any direct obligation on us anymore, as we've seen, let’s explore whether it serves any other purpose in this discussion about the rights of war and similar issues. First, the Mosaic law demonstrates that what it commands is not against the law of nature. Since the law of nature is permanent and unchanging, nothing contradictory to it could be commanded by God, who is always just. Furthermore, the law of Moses is referred to in Psalm 19 as a pure and right law, and St. Paul describes it in Romans 7:12 as holy, just, and good. This discussion focuses on its commands, as its permissions require a more detailed discussion. The simple act of permission, which indicates the removal of an impediment or prohibition, doesn’t relate to the current topic. A positive legal permission can be complete, allowing us to perform a specific act without any restrictions, or less complete, providing people with immunity for certain actions and a right to do them without interference from others. From permissions of the first type, just like from positive commands, we conclude that what the law allows isn’t against the law of nature.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__. However, concerning the second type of permission, which grants immunity for certain acts without explicitly allowing them, we can’t easily conclude that those acts align with the law of nature.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__. When the wording of permission is ambiguous, it’s better for us to interpret it according to the established law of nature and identify what type of permission it is, rather than relying on our judgment of its practicality to determine if it aligns with the laws of nature. Alongside this first observation, there’s another point about the authority that Christian rulers have to enact laws similar to those given by Moses, except for those that were specific to the time of the anticipated Messiah and the Gospel that hadn’t been revealed yet, or where Christ himself has established something to the contrary in a general or specific way. Aside from these three cases, there’s no reason to believe that anything established by the law of Moses should now be considered unlawful. Additionally, it should be noted that whatever the law of Moses required regarding the virtues that Christ demanded of his disciples should be fulfilled by Christians today to a greater extent, due to their superior understanding and greater motives. Therefore, the virtues of humility, patience, and charity are expected to be practiced by Christians in a more complete manner than they were by the Jews under the Mosaic law, as the promises of heaven are more clearly presented to us in the Gospel. Consequently, the old law, when compared to the Gospel, is considered neither perfect nor faultless, and Christ is regarded as the fulfillment of the law, while the law serves as our guide to lead us to Christ. Thus, the old law regarding the Sabbath and the law about tithes indicate that Christians are required to dedicate at least a seventh of their time to worship and at least a tenth of their produce to support those engaged in sacred work or for other charitable purposes.
CHAPTER II.
Investigation into the Legality of War.
Reasons proving the lawfulness of War—Proofs from History—Proofs from general consent—The Law of Nature proved not repugnant to War—War not condemned by the voluntary Divine Law preceding the Gospel—Objections answered—Review of the question whether War be contrary to the Law of the Gospel—Arguments from Scripture for the negative Opinions—Answer to the Arguments taken from Scripture for the affirmative—The opinions of the primitive Christians on the subject examined.
Reasons that demonstrate the legality of war—Historical evidence—General consensus—The Law of Nature is shown to not oppose war—War is not condemned by the voluntary Divine Law prior to the Gospel—Counterarguments addressed—Analysis of whether war contradicts the Law of the Gospel—Scriptural arguments supporting the negative view—Responses to the scriptural arguments supporting the affirmative—Examination of early Christian perspectives on the topic.
I. After examining the sources of right, the first and most general question that occurs, is whether any war is just, or if it is ever lawful to make war. But this question like many others that follow, must in the first place be compared with the rights of nature. Cicero in the third book of his Bounds of Good and Evil, and in other parts of his works, proves with great erudition from the writings of the Stoics, that there are certain first principles of nature, called by the Greeks the first natural impressions, which are succeeded by other principles of obligation superior even to the first impressions themselves. He calls the care, which every animal, from the moment of its birth, feels for itself and the preservation of its condition, its abhorrence of destruction, and of every thing that threatens death, a principle of nature. Hence, he says, it happens, that if left to his own choice, every man would prefer a sound and perfect to a mutilated and deformed body. So that preserving ourselves in a natural state, and holding to every thing conformable, and averting every thing repugnant to nature is the first duty.
I. After looking into the sources of right, the first and most general question that arises is whether any war can be considered just, or if it is ever acceptable to go to war. However, this question, like many that follow, must first be compared with the rights of nature. Cicero, in the third book of his "Bounds of Good and Evil," and in other parts of his works, thoroughly demonstrates through the writings of the Stoics that there are certain fundamental principles of nature, referred to by the Greeks as the first natural impressions, which are followed by other principles of obligation that take precedence even over the first impressions themselves. He describes the instinct every animal has, from the moment it's born, to look after itself and maintain its condition, along with its aversion to destruction and anything that threatens death, as a principle of nature. Therefore, he concludes that if left to his own devices, every individual would choose a healthy and whole body over a damaged and deformed one. Thus, preserving ourselves in a natural state and embracing everything that aligns with nature, while rejecting everything that contradicts it, is our primary duty.
But from the knowledge of these principles, a notion arises of their being agreeable to reason, that part of a man, which is superior to the body. Now that agreement with reason, which is the basis of propriety, should have more weight than the impulse of appetite; because the principles of nature recommend right reason as a rule that ought to be of higher value than bare instinct. As the truth of this is easily assented to by all men of sound judgment without any other demonstration, it32 follows that in inquiring into the laws of nature the first object of consideration is, what is agreeable to those principles of nature, and then we come to the rules, which, though arising only out of the former, are of higher dignity, and not only to be embraced, when offered, but pursued by all the means in our power.
But from understanding these principles, we get the idea that they align with reason, which is the part of a person that's greater than the body. This alignment with reason, which forms the basis of propriety, should carry more weight than the drive of desire; because the principles of nature advocate for right reason as a standard that should be valued more than mere instinct. Since this truth is easily accepted by everyone with sound judgment without needing further proof, it32 follows that when exploring the laws of nature, the first thing to consider is what aligns with those principles and then we look at the rules that, while stemming from the former, hold greater significance and should not only be embraced when presented, but actively pursued by all means available to us.
This last principle, which is called propriety, from its fitness, according to the various things on which it turns, sometimes is limited to a very narrow point, the least departure from which is a deviation into vice; sometimes it allows a wider scope, so that some actions, even laudable in themselves, may be omitted or varied without crime. In this case there is not an immediate distinction between right and wrong; the shades are gradual, and their termination unperceived; not like a direct contrast, where the opposition is immediately seen, and the first step is a transgression of the fixed bounds.
This last principle, called propriety, relates to how appropriate something is based on the various factors involved. Sometimes, it's very narrow, and even a slight deviation is considered a vice; other times, it allows for a broader interpretation, meaning that some actions, even if they are good in themselves, can be skipped or changed without being wrong. In this situation, there isn't a clear-cut distinction between right and wrong; the differences are subtle, and you might not even notice where it ends. It's not like a stark contrast, where the opposition is clear, and the first step you take is a clear violation of established limits.
The general object of divine and human laws is to give the authority of obligation to what was only laudable in itself. It has been said above that an investigation of the laws of nature implies an inquiry, whether any particular action may be done without injustice: now by an act of injustice is understood that, which necessarily has in it any thing repugnant to the nature of a reasonable and social being. So far from any thing in the principles of nature being repugnant to war, every part of them indeed rather favours it. For the preservation of our lives and persons, which is the end of war, and the possession or acquirement of things necessary and useful to life is most suitable to those principles of nature, and to use force, if necessary, for those occasions, is no way dissonant to the principles of nature, since all animals are endowed with natural strength, sufficient to assist and defend themselves.
The main goal of both divine and human laws is to turn what is simply commendable into something that people are obligated to follow. It has been stated before that exploring the laws of nature involves asking whether a specific action can be taken without being unjust. An act of injustice is understood as anything that conflicts with the nature of a rational and social being. Far from being against the principles of nature, they actually support war. The preservation of our lives and well-being, which is the purpose of war, along with obtaining what is necessary and useful for life, aligns with those principles. Using force when needed in these situations is completely in line with the principles of nature, as all animals are naturally equipped with the strength to protect and defend themselves.
Xenophon says, that every animal knows a certain method of fighting without any other instructor than nature. In a fragment of Ovid's, called the Art of Fishery, it is remarked, that all animals know their enemy and his means of defence, and the strength and measure of their own weapons. Horace has said, "the wolf attacks with its teeth, the bull with its horns, and whence is this knowledge derived but from instinct?" On this subject Lucretius enlarges, observing that "every creature knows its own powers. The calf butts with its forehead, before its horns appear, and strikes with all33 imaginable fury." On which Galen expresses himself in the following manner, "every animal appears to defend itself with that part of its body, in which it excels others. The calf butts with its head before its horns have grown, and the colt strikes with its heel before its hoofs are hard, as the young dog attempts to bite before his teeth are strong." The same writer in describing the use of different parts of the body, says, "that man is a creature formed for peace and war. His armour forms not an immediate part of his body; but he has hands fit for preparing and handling arms, and we see infants using them spontaneously, without being taught to do so." Aristotle in the 4th book, and tenth chapter of the history of animals, says, "that the hand serves man for a spear, a sword, or any arms whatever, because it can hold and wield them." Now right reason and the nature of society which claims the second, and indeed more important place in this inquiry, prohibit not all force, but only that which is repugnant to society, by depriving another of his right. For the end of society is to form a common and united aid to preserve to every one his own. Which may easily be understood to have obtained, before what is now called property was introduced. For the free use of life and limbs was so much the right of every one, that it could not be infringed or attacked without injustice. So the use of the common productions of nature was the right of the first occupier, and for any one to rob him of that was manifest injustice. This may be more easily understood, since law and custom have established property under its present form. Tully has expressed this in the third book of his Offices in the following words, "if every member could have separate feeling, and imagine it could derive vigour from engrossing the strength of a neighboring part of the body, the whole frame would languish and perish. In the same manner if every one of us, for his own advantage, might rob another of what he pleased, there would be a total overthrow of human society and intercourse. For though it is allowed by nature for every one to give the preference to himself before another in the enjoyment of life and necessaries, yet she does not permit us to increase our means and riches by the spoils of others." It is not therefore contrary to the nature of society to provide and consult for ourselves, if another's right is not injured; the force therefore, which inviolably abstains from touching34 the rights of others, is not unjust. For as the same Cicero observes some where in his Epistles, that as there are two modes of contending, the one by argument, and the other by force, and as the former is peculiar to man, and the latter common to him with the brute creation, we must have recourse to the latter, when it is impossible to use the former. And again, what can be opposed to force, but force? Ulpian observes that Cassius says, it is lawful to repel force by force, and it is a right apparently provided by nature to repel arms with arms, with whom Ovid agrees, observing that the laws permit us to take up arms against those that bear them.
Xenophon states that every animal knows a way to fight, guided solely by nature as their teacher. In a fragment from Ovid's "The Art of Fishery," it is noted that all animals recognize their enemies, their opponents' defenses, and the strengths and limitations of their own weapons. Horace has pointed out, "the wolf attacks with its teeth, the bull with its horns, and where does this knowledge come from if not from instinct?" Lucretius expands on this idea, mentioning that "every creature is aware of its own abilities. The calf pushes with its head before its horns have developed and strikes with all33 its might." Galen remarks that "every animal seems to defend itself with the part of its body where it excels. The calf butts with its head before its horns grow, and the colt kicks with its heels before its hooves harden, just as a young dog tries to bite before his teeth are strong." Similarly, Galen discusses how different parts of the body are used, saying, "man is a being equipped for both peace and war. His armor is not a direct extension of his body, but he has hands designed for preparing and wielding weapons, and we observe infants using them naturally, without any training." Aristotle, in the fourth book and tenth chapter of "History of Animals," claims that "the hand serves man as a spear, a sword, or any weapon because it can hold and use them." Reason and the nature of society, which plays an important role in this discussion, do not prohibit all forms of force, but only that which goes against societal norms by infringing on someone else's rights. The purpose of society is to create a collective effort to ensure that everyone retains what belongs to them. This was evident even before what we now consider property came into existence, as the unrestricted use of one's life and body was a right that couldn't be violated without wrongdoing. Similarly, the exploitation of nature's common resources belonged to the first person who occupied them, and any theft from that individual was clearly unjust. This is easier to grasp since law and tradition have established property as we know it today. Cicero articulated this in the third book of "Offices" with the following analogy: "if every body part could feel individually and believed it could gain strength by taking from a neighboring part, the entire body would weaken and die. In the same way, if each of us were allowed to take whatever we wanted from others for our own gain, it would lead to a complete collapse of human society and interaction. For while it is natural for every person to prioritize their own enjoyment of life and resources, nature does not allow us to enhance our own wealth at the expense of others." Therefore, it is not against the essence of society to provide for and look after ourselves as long as it doesn't harm someone else's rights; the force that steadfastly avoids infringing on others' rights is not unjust. As Cicero notes in one of his letters, there are two ways to contend: one through argument, the other through force. The former is unique to humans, while the latter is shared with the animal kingdom; we must resort to the latter when the former becomes impossible. And again, what can counter force but force? Ulpian notes that Cassius states it's permissible to resist force with force, and this seems to be a natural right to defend oneself with arms, which Ovid agrees with, emphasizing that the laws allow us to take up arms against those who bear them.
II. The observation that all war is not repugnant to the law of nature, may be more amply proved from sacred history. For when Abraham with his servants and confederates had gained a victory, by force of arms, over the four Kings, who had plundered Sodom, God approved of his act by the mouth of his priest Melchisedech, who said to him, "Blessed be the most high God, who hath delivered thine enemies into thine hand." Gen. xiv. 20. Now Abraham had taken up arms, as appears from the history, without any special command from God. But this man, no less eminent for sanctity than wisdom, felt himself authorized by the law of nature, as it is admitted by the evidence of Berosus, and Orpheus, who were strangers.
II. The idea that not all war goes against the law of nature can be better demonstrated through sacred history. When Abraham, along with his servants and allies, managed to defeat the four kings who had invaded Sodom, God supported his actions through his priest Melchizedek, who said to him, "Blessed be the Most High God, who has delivered your enemies into your hand." Gen. xiv. 20. Abraham took up arms without any specific command from God, as the history shows. Yet this man, who was just as distinguished for his piety as he was for his wisdom, believed he was justified by the law of nature, a viewpoint echoed by outsiders like Berosus and Orpheus.
There is no occasion to appeal to the history of the seven nations, whom God delivered up into the hands of the Israelites to be destroyed. For there was a special command to execute the judgment of God upon nations guilty of the greatest crimes. From whence these wars are literally styled in scripture, Battles of the Lord, as undertaken, not by human will, but by divine appointment. The xvii. chapter of Exodus supplies a passage more to the purpose, relating the overthrow which the Israelites, conducted by Moses and Joshua, made of the Amalekites. In this act, there was no express commission from God, but only an approval after it was done. But in the xix. chap. of Deut. ver. 10, 15. God has prescribed general and standing laws to his people on the manner of making war, by this circumstance shewing that a war may be just without any express commandment from him. Because in the same passage, a plain distinction is made between the case of the seven nations and that of others. And as there is35 no special edict prescribing the just causes for which war may be undertaken, the determination of them is left to the discovery of natural reason. Of this kind is the war of Jephthah against the Ammonites, in defence of their borders. Jud. xi. and the war of David against the same people for having violated the rights of his Ambassadors. 2 Sam. x. To the preceding observations may be added, what the inspired writer of the Epistle to the Hebrews says of Gideon, Barack, Sampson, Jephthah, David, Samuel, and others, who by faith made war upon kingdoms, prevailed in war and put whole armies of their enemies to flight. Heb. xi. 33, 34. The whole tenor of this passage shews, that the word faith implies a persuasion, that what they did was believed to be agreeable to the will of God. In the same manner, David is said, by a woman distinguished for her wisdom, 1 Sam. xxv. 28. to fight the battles of the Lord, that is to make lawful and just wars.
There’s no need to reference the history of the seven nations that God handed over to the Israelites for destruction. There was a specific command to carry out God’s judgment on nations guilty of serious crimes. That's why these wars are directly called in scripture, Battles of the Lord, because they were fought not by human will, but by divine directive. The 17th chapter of Exodus provides a relevant passage about the defeat that the Israelites, led by Moses and Joshua, achieved against the Amalekites. In this act, there wasn’t a direct command from God, only His approval afterward. However, in Deuteronomy 19:10, 15, God has laid down general and established laws for His people regarding how to conduct war, indicating that a war can be just without an explicit command from Him. In that same passage, a clear distinction is made between the cases of the seven nations and others. Since there isn't a specific decree outlining the just causes for which war can be waged, figuring those out is left to natural reasoning. An example of this is Jephthah’s war against the Ammonites, which was in defense of their borders (Judges 11), and David’s war against the same people for violating the rights of his ambassadors (2 Samuel 10). Additionally, it’s worth noting what the inspired author of the Epistle to the Hebrews says about Gideon, Barak, Samson, Jephthah, David, Samuel, and others, who, by faith, waged war against kingdoms, triumphed in battle, and put entire enemy armies to flight (Hebrews 11:33-34). The overall message of this passage shows that the term faith implies a belief that what they did was in accordance with God’s will. Similarly, David is described by a wise woman in 1 Samuel 25:28 as someone who fought the battles of the Lord, meaning he engaged in lawful and just wars.
III. Proofs of what has been advanced, may be drawn also from the consent of all, especially, of the wisest nations. There is a celebrated passage in Cicero's speech for Milo, in which, justifying recourse to force in defence of life, he bears ample testimony to the feelings of nature, who has given us this law, which is not written, but innate, which we have not received by instruction, hearing or reading, but the elements of it have been engraven in our hearts and minds with her own hand: a law which is not the effect of habit and acquirement, but forms a part in the original complexion of our frame: so that if our lives are threatened with assassination or open violence from the hands of robbers or enemies, ANY means of defence would be allowed and laudable. He proceeds, reason has taught this to the learned, necessity to the barbarians, custom to nations, and nature herself to wild beasts, to use every possible means of repelling force offered to their bodies, their limbs and their lives. Caius and Lawyer says, natural reason permits us to defend ourselves against dangers. And Florentinus, another legal authority, maintains, that whatever any one does in defence of his person ought to be esteemed right. Josephus observes, that the love of life is a law of nature strongly implanted in all creatures, and therefore we look upon those as enemies, who would openly deprive us of it.
III. Proofs of what has been mentioned can also come from the agreement of everyone, especially the smartest nations. There’s a famous part in Cicero's speech for Milo where he justifies using force to defend one’s life. He strongly acknowledges the feelings of nature, which has given us this law that isn’t written down but is innate. We didn’t learn it through teaching, listening, or reading; its elements are engraved in our hearts and minds by nature itself. This law isn’t formed by habits or learning but is part of our original nature. So, if our lives are threatened by assassination or open violence from robbers or enemies, ANY means of defense would be accepted and praised. He adds that reason has taught this to the educated, necessity to the uncivilized, tradition to nations, and nature itself to wild animals, urging them to use every possible means to repel any force against their bodies, limbs, and lives. Caius and Lawyer state that natural reason allows us to defend ourselves against dangers. Florentinus, another legal authority, argues that anything someone does to defend themselves should be considered right. Josephus notes that the love of life is a law of nature firmly established in all creatures, which is why we view those who try to take it away from us as enemies.
This principle is founded on reasons of equity, so evident, that even in the brute creation, who have no idea of right, we make a distinction between attack and defence.36 For when Ulpian had said, that an animal without knowledge, that is without the use of reason, could not possibly do wrong, he immediately adds, that when two animals fight, if one kills the other, the distinction of Quintius Mutius must be admitted, that if the aggressor were killed no damages could be recovered; but if the other, which was attacked, an action might be maintained. There is a passage in Pliny, which will serve for an explanation of this, he says that the fiercest lions do not fight with each other, nor do serpents bite serpents. But if any violence is done to the tamest of them, they are roused, and upon receiving any hurt, will defend themselves with the greatest alacrity and vigour.
This principle is based on obvious equity, so clear that even in the animal kingdom, where there's no understanding of right and wrong, we draw a line between attack and defense.36 When Ulpian stated that an animal lacking knowledge, meaning one that cannot reason, could never truly do wrong, he quickly added that when two animals fight, if one kills the other, we have to accept Quintius Mutius's distinction: if the aggressor is killed, no damages can be claimed; however, if the other animal, which was attacked, is harmed, a legal action can be taken. Pliny mentions that the fiercest lions don’t fight amongst themselves, nor do snakes bite each other. But if any harm is done to the tamest of them, they become aggressive, and when hurt, they will defend themselves with great energy and strength.
IV. From the law of nature then which may also be called the law of nations, it is evident that all kinds of war are not to be condemned. In the same manner, all history and the laws of manners of every people sufficiently inform us, that war is not condemned by the voluntary law of nations. Indeed Hermogenianus has said, that wars were introduced by the law of nations, a passage which ought to be explained somewhat differently from the general interpretation given to it. The meaning of it is, that certain formalities, attending war, were introduced by the law of nations, which formalities were necessary to secure the peculiar privileges arising out of the law. From hence a distinction, which there will be occasion to use hereafter, between a war with the usual formalities of the law of nations, which is called just or perfect, and an informal war, which does not for that reason cease to be just, or agreeable to right. For some wars, when made upon just grounds, though not exactly conformable, yet are not repugnant to the law, as will be explained more fully hereafter. By the law of the nations, says Livy, provision is made to repel force by arms; and Florentinus declares, that the law of nations allows us to repel violence and injury, in order to protect our persons.
IV. From the law of nature, which can also be referred to as the law of nations, it's clear that not all types of war should be condemned. Similarly, all history and the customs of every society show us that the voluntary law of nations does not condemn war. In fact, Hermogenianus has stated that wars were established by the law of nations, a statement that should be interpreted differently than the common understanding. What it actually means is that certain formalities associated with war were introduced by the law of nations, which were necessary to secure the specific privileges that come from this law. This leads to a distinction, which we will refer to later, between a war conducted with the usual formalities of the law of nations, known as just or perfect war, and an informal war, which, despite lacking formalities, does not stop being just or aligned with what is right. Some wars, when fought for just reasons, may not fully adhere to these formalities but are not necessarily contrary to the law, as will be elaborated later. Livy states that the law of nations allows for the use of force to respond to aggression; and Florentinus asserts that the law of nations permits us to defend ourselves against violence and harm in order to protect our lives.
V. A greater difficulty occurs respecting the divine voluntary law. Nor is there any force in the objection that as the law of nature is unchangeable, nothing can be appointed even by God himself contrary to it. For this is true only in those things, which the law of nature positively forbids or commands; not in those which are tacitly permitted by the same law. For acts of that kind, not falling strictly within the general rule, but37 being exceptions to the law of nature, may be either forbidden or commanded. The first objection usually made against the lawfulness of war is taken from the law given to Noah and his posterity, Gen. ix. 5, 6, where God thus speaks, "Surely the blood of your lives will I require; at the hand of every beast will I require it, and at the hand of every man; at the hand of every man's brother will I require the life of man. Whoever sheds man's blood, by man shall his blood be shed; for in the image of God made he man." Here some take the phrase of requiring blood, in the most general sense, and the other part, that blood shall be shed in its turn, they consider as a bare threat, and not an approbation; neither of which acceptations can be admitted. For the prohibition of shedding blood extends not beyond the law itself, which declares, Thou shalt not kill; but passes no condemnation upon capital punishments or wars undertaken by public authority.
V. A greater difficulty arises regarding the divine voluntary law. The argument that because the law of nature is unchangeable, nothing can be established by even God himself contrary to it, has no merit. This is only true for things that the law of nature explicitly forbids or commands; it does not apply to those that are tacitly permitted by the same law. Actions of this kind, which do not strictly fall under the general rule but are exceptions to the law of nature, may be either prohibited or mandated. The first objection often raised against the legitimacy of war comes from the law given to Noah and his descendants, Gen. ix. 5, 6, where God says, "Surely the blood of your lives will I require; at the hand of every beast will I require it, and at the hand of every man; at the hand of every man's brother will I require the life of man. Whoever sheds man's blood, by man shall his blood be shed; for in the image of God made he man." Here, some interpret the phrase about requiring blood in the broadest sense, and the part about blood being shed in return as merely a threat rather than an endorsement; neither interpretation can be accepted. The prohibition against shedding blood does not extend beyond the law itself, which states, You shall not kill; it does not condemn capital punishment or wars carried out by public authority.
Neither the law of Moses, nor that given to Noah established any thing new, they were only a declaratory repetition of the law of nature, that had been obliterated by depraved custom. So that the shedding of blood in a criminal and wanton manner is the only act prohibited by those commandments. Thus every act of homicide does not amount to murder, but only that, which is committed with a wilful and malicious intention to destroy the life of an innocent person. As to what follows about blood being shed in return for blood, it seems to imply not a mere act of personal revenge, but the deliberate exercise of a perfect right, which may be thus explained; it is not unjust, according to the principles of nature that any one should suffer in proportion to the evil he has done, conformably to the judicial maxim of Rhadamanthus, that if any one himself suffers what he has done, it is but just and right. The same opinion is thus expressed by Seneca the father; "it is but a just retaliation for any one to suffer in his own person the evil which he intended to inflict upon another." From a sense of this natural justice, Cain knowing himself guilty of his brother's blood said, "whosoever finds me shall kill me."
Neither the law of Moses nor the one given to Noah introduced anything new; they were just a clear restatement of the law of nature, which had been distorted by corrupt customs. Therefore, the only act prohibited by those commandments is the unjust and reckless shedding of blood. Not every act of killing is considered murder; only those committed with the intentional and malicious desire to take an innocent person's life. Regarding the idea of blood being shed in response to blood, it suggests not just personal revenge, but the careful application of a rightful response. This can be explained as follows: it isn't unreasonable, according to natural principles, for someone to suffer in proportion to the wrong they’ve done, aligning with the judicial principle of Rhadamanthus that if someone experiences the consequences of their actions, it is just and right. Seneca the Elder expresses the same view: "It is a fair retaliation for anyone to suffer the harm they intended for another." Understanding this sense of natural justice, Cain, aware of his guilt in his brother's death, said, "Whoever finds me will kill me."
But as in those early times, when men were few, and aggressions rare, there was less occasion for examples, God restrained by an express commandment the impulse of nature which appeared lawful, he forbad any one to38 kill the murderer, at the same time prohibiting all intercourse with him, even so far as not to touch him.6
But just like in those early days, when there were few people and acts of aggression were uncommon, there wasn't much reason for examples. God limited the natural impulse that seemed acceptable by giving a clear command: He forbade anyone from killing the murderer, while also prohibiting all interaction with him, even to the extent of not being allowed to touch him.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Plato has established this in his laws, and the same rule prevailed in Greece, as appears from the following passage in Euripides, "our fathers of old did well in banishing from their intercourse and sight any one that had shed another's blood; imposing banishment by way of atonement, rather than inflicting death." We find Thucydides of the same opinion, "that anciently lighter punishments were inflicted for the greatest crimes; but in process of time, as those penalties came to be despised, legislators were obliged to have recourse to death in certain cases." We may add to the above instances the remark of Lactantius, that as yet it appeared a sin to punish even the most wicked men with death.
Plato established this in his laws, and the same principle was true in Greece, as shown in the following passage from Euripides: "Our ancestors did well to banish anyone who had taken another's life from their presence, choosing banishment as a way to make amends rather than inflicting the death penalty." Thucydides shares a similar perspective, stating, "In the past, lighter punishments were given for the most serious crimes; but over time, as those penalties were looked down upon, lawmakers had to resort to death sentences in certain cases." Additionally, we can mention Lactantius's observation that it still seemed wrong to punish even the most evil individuals with death.
The conjecture of the divine will taken from the remarkable instance of Cain, whom no one was permitted to kill passed into a law, so that Lanech, having perpetrated a similar deed, promised himself impunity from this example.—Gen. iv. 24.
The idea of divine will, based on the notable case of Cain, who no one was allowed to kill, became a law. As a result, Lamech, having committed a similar act, believed he would be safe from consequences because of this precedent.—Gen. iv. 24.
But as before the deluge, in the time of the Giants, the practice of frequent and wanton murders had prevailed; upon the renewal of the human race, after the deluge, that the same evil custom might not be established, God thought proper to restrain it by severer means. The lenity of former ages was laid aside, and the divine authority gave a sanction to the precepts of natural justice, that whoever killed a murderer should be innocent. After tribunals were erected, the power over life was, for the very best reasons, conferred upon the judges alone. Still some traces of ancient manners remained in the right which was granted, after the introduction of the Mosaic Law, to the nearest in blood to the person killed.
But just like before the flood, during the time of the Giants, the practice of frequent and reckless killings had taken hold; following the renewal of the human race after the flood, God decided to prevent this evil habit from resurfacing through stricter measures. The leniency of previous ages was set aside, and divine authority backed the principles of natural justice, stating that anyone who killed a murderer would be considered innocent. Once courts were established, the power over life was, for very good reasons, given only to the judges. However, some remnants of ancient customs remained in the right granted, after the introduction of the Mosaic Law, to the closest relatives of the victim.
This interpretation is justified by the authority of Abraham, who, with a perfect knowledge of the law given to Noah, took arms against the four Kings, fully persuaded that he was doing nothing in violation of that law. In the same manner Moses ordered the people to fight against Amalekites, who attacked them; following in this case the dictates of nature, for he appears to have had no special communication with God. Exod. xvii. 9.39 Besides, we find that capital punishments were inflicted upon other criminals, as well as murderers, not only among the Gentiles, but among those who had been impressed with the most pious rules and opinions, even the Patriarchs themselves. Gen. xxxviii. 24.
This interpretation is supported by the authority of Abraham, who, fully aware of the law given to Noah, took up arms against the four kings, convinced that he was not violating that law. Similarly, Moses commanded the people to fight against the Amalekites, who attacked them; in this case, he seemed to be following natural instincts, as he didn’t appear to have any special communication with God. Exod. xvii. 9.39 Additionally, we see that capital punishment was applied to various criminals, not just murderers, both among the Gentiles and those who adhered to the most devout beliefs, including the Patriarchs themselves. Gen. xxxviii. 24.
Indeed upon comparing the divine will with the light of nature, it was concluded, that it seemed conformable to justice, that other crimes of great enormity should be subject to the same punishment as that of murder. For there are some rights, such as those of reputation, chastity, conjugal fidelity, submission of subjects to their princes, all of which are esteemed of equal value with life itself, because on the preservation of these the peace and comfort of life depend. The violation of any of those rights is little less than murder itself.
Indeed, when comparing divine will with the light of nature, it was determined that it seemed just for other serious crimes to be punished in the same way as murder. Some rights, like reputation, chastity, marital fidelity, and the loyalty of subjects to their rulers, are considered as valuable as life itself because the peace and comfort of life depend on their preservation. Violating any of these rights is almost as serious as committing murder.
Here may be applied the old tradition found among the Jews, that there were many laws, which were not ALL mentioned by Moses, given by God to the sons of Noah; as it was sufficient for his purpose, that they should afterwards be comprehended in the peculiar laws of the Hebrews. Thus it appears from xviii. chap. of Leviticus, that there was an ancient law against incestuous marriages, though not mentioned by Moses in its proper place. Now among the commandments given by God to the children of Noah, it is said, that death was expressly declared to be the punishment not only for murder, but for adultery, incest, and robbery, which is confirmed by the words of Job xxxi. 11. The law of Moses too, for the sanction of capital punishments, gives reasons which operate no less with other nations, than with the Jewish people. Levit. xviii. 25–30. Psa. ci. 5. Prov. xx. 8. And particularly respecting murder it is said, the land cannot be cleansed unless the blood of the murderer be shed. Numb. xxv. 31–33. Besides, it were absurd to suppose that the Jewish people were indulged with the privilege of maintaining the public safety, and that of individuals by capital punishments, and asserting their rights by war, and that other kings and nations were not allowed the same powers. Nor do we find that those kings or nations were forewarned by the Prophets, that the use of capital punishments, and that all wars, were condemned by God in the same manner as they were admonished of all other sins. On the other hand, can any one doubt, as the law of Moses bore such an express image of the divine will respecting criminal justice, whether other nations would40 not have acted wisely in adopting it for their example? It is certain that the Greeks, and the Athenians in particular did so. From hence came the close resemblance which the Jewish bore to the old Athenian law, and to that of the twelve tables of Rome. Enough has been said, to shew that the law given to Noah cannot bear the interpretation of those, who derive from it their arguments against the lawfulness of all war.
Here may be applied the old tradition found among the Jews that there were many laws not mentioned by Moses, given by God to the sons of Noah. It was sufficient for his purpose that they would later be included in the specific laws of the Hebrews. Thus, it seems from chapter 18 of Leviticus that there was an ancient law against incestuous marriages, even though it wasn’t mentioned by Moses in its proper place. Among the commandments given by God to the children of Noah, it is stated that death was explicitly declared as the punishment not only for murder but also for adultery, incest, and robbery, which is confirmed by Job 31:11. The law of Moses, regarding capital punishment, provides reasons that were just as relevant to other nations as they were to the Jewish people, as indicated in Leviticus 18:25–30, Psalm 101:5, and Proverbs 20:8. Specifically regarding murder, it is said that the land cannot be cleansed unless the blood of the murderer is shed (Numbers 35:31–33). Furthermore, it would be absurd to think that the Jewish people were allowed to maintain public safety and individual rights through capital punishment and war, while other kings and nations were not granted the same powers. There is no record of those kings or nations being warned by the Prophets that the use of capital punishment and all wars were condemned by God in the same way as they were cautioned about other sins. On the other hand, how could anyone doubt that, since the law of Moses so clearly reflected the divine will regarding criminal justice, other nations would not have benefited from adopting it as a model? It’s clear that the Greeks, particularly the Athenians, did just that. This is why there is such a close resemblance between Jewish law and the old Athenian law as well as the Twelve Tables of Rome. Enough has been said to show that the law given to Noah cannot be interpreted by those who use it to argue against the legitimacy of all war.
VI. The arguments against the lawfulness of war, drawn from the Gospel, are more specious. In examining which it will not be necessary to assume, as many do, that the Gospel contains nothing more than the law of nature, except the rules of faith and the Sacraments: an assumption, which in its general acceptation is by no means true. It may readily be admitted, that nothing inconsistent with natural justice is enjoined in the gospel, yet it can never be allowed, that the laws of Christ do not impose duties upon us, above those required by the law of nature. And those, who think otherwise, strain their arguments to prove that many practices forbidden by the gospel, as concubinage, divorce, polygamy, were made offences by the law of nature. The light of nature might point out the HONOUR of abstaining from such practices, but the SINFULNESS of them could not have been discovered without a revelation of the will of God. Who for instance would say, that the Christian precept of laying down our lives for others was an obligation of the law of nature? 1 John iii. 16. It is said by Justin the Martyr, that to live according to the bare law of nature is not the character of a true believer. Neither can we follow those, who, adopting another meaning of no inconsiderable import, construe the precept delivered by Christ in his sermon on the mount, into nothing more than an interpretation of the Mosaic Law. For the words, "you have heard it was said to them of old, but I say to YOU," which are so often repeated, imply something else. Those of old were no other than contemporaries of Moses: for what is there repeated as said to those of OLD are not the words of the teachers of the law, but of Moses, either LITERALLY, or in THEIR meaning. They are cited by our Saviour as his express words, not as interpretations of them: "Thou shalt not kill," Exod. xx. whoever killeth shall be in danger of Judgment, Levit. xxi. 21. Numb. xxxv. 16, 17, 30. "Thou shalt not commit adultery," Exod. xx. "whosoever shall put away his wife, let him41 give her a writing of divorcement." Deut. xxiv, 1. "Thou shalt not forswear thyself, but shalt perform unto the Lord thine oaths." Exod. xx. 7. Numb. xxx. 2. "An eye for an eye, and a tooth for a tooth," may be demanded in justice. Levit. xxxiv. 20. Deut. xix. 21. "Thou shalt love thy neighbour," that is, an Israelite. Levit. xix. 18. "and thou shalt hate thine enemy," that is, any one of the seven nations to whom friendship or compassion was forbidden to be shewn. Exod. xxxiv. 11. Deut. vii. 1. To these may be added the Amalekites, with whom the Israelites were commanded to maintain irreconcileable war. Exod. xxvii. 19. Deut. xxv. 19.
VI. The arguments against the legality of war based on the Gospel are more plausible. When examining this, it's unnecessary to assume, as many do, that the Gospel consists solely of the natural law, aside from the principles of faith and the Sacraments. This assumption is generally not true. It can be easily acknowledged that nothing contrary to natural justice is commanded in the Gospel, but it can never be accepted that the laws of Christ do not impose additional duties on us beyond those required by natural law. Those who believe otherwise stretch their arguments to claim that many practices condemned by the Gospel, such as concubinage, divorce, and polygamy, were offenses according to natural law. The light of nature might suggest the honor of avoiding such practices, but the sinful nature of them could not have been understood without a revelation of God's will. Who, for example, would argue that the Christian principle of laying down our lives for others is a requirement of natural law? 1 John iii. 16. Justin the Martyr said that living merely according to the natural law is not characteristic of a true believer. We also cannot accept those who, interpreting the significance of the command given by Christ in his Sermon on the Mount in a different way, reduce it to just an interpretation of the Mosaic Law. The phrases, "you have heard it said to the ancients, but I say to you," which are frequently repeated, suggest something else. The ancients referred to those who lived at the time of Moses; for what is stated as being said to those of OLD are not the words of the teachers of the law, but of Moses, either literally or in their meaning. Our Savior quotes these as his precise words, not as mere interpretations: "You shall not kill," Exod. xx. Anyone who kills will be in danger of judgment, Levit. xxi. 21. Numb. xxxv. 16, 17, 30. "You shall not commit adultery," Exod. xx. "Whoever puts away his wife, let him give her a certificate of divorce." Deut. xxiv, 1. "You shall not perjure yourself, but you must keep your oaths to the Lord." Exod. xx. 7. Numb. xxx. 2. "An eye for an eye, and a tooth for a tooth," can be demanded in justice. Levit. xxxiv. 20. Deut. xix. 21. "You shall love your neighbor," meaning an Israelite. Levit. xix. 18. "and you shall hate your enemy," referring to any of the seven nations towards whom friendship or compassion was prohibited. Exod. xxxiv. 11. Deut. vii. 1. This also includes the Amalekites, with whom the Israelites were commanded to wage unending war. Exod. xxvii. 19. Deut. xxv. 19.
But to understand the words of our Saviour, we must observe that the law of Moses is taken in a double sense, either as containing some principles in common with human laws, such as imposing restraint upon human crimes by the dread of exemplary punishments. Heb. ii. 2. And in this manner maintaining civil society among the Jewish people: for which reason it is called, Heb. vii. 16, the law of a carnal commandment, and Rom. iii. 17. the law of works: or it may be taken in another sense, comprehending the peculiar sanctions of a divine law, requiring purity of mind, and certain actions, which might be omitted without temporal punishments. In this sense it is called a spiritual law, giving life to the soul. The teachers of the law, and the Pharisees considering the first part as sufficient, neglected to instruct the people in the second and more important branch, deeming it superfluous. The truth of this may be proved, not only from our own writings, but from Josephus also, and the Jewish Rabbis. Respecting this second part we may observe, that the virtues which are required of Christians, are either recommended or enjoined to the Hebrews, but not enjoined in the same degree and extent as to Christians. Now in both these senses Christ opposes his own precepts to the old law. From whence it is clear, that his words contain more than a bare interpretation of the Mosaic law. These observations apply not only to the question immediately in hand, but to many others; that we may not rest upon the authority of the Mosaic law farther than is right.
But to understand the words of our Savior, we need to recognize that the law of Moses has a double meaning: it can refer to principles that are similar to human laws, like restraining human wrongdoing through the fear of punishment (Heb. ii. 2). This way, it helps maintain civil society among the Jewish people; that's why it's referred to as, Heb. vii. 16, the law of a carnal commandment, and Rom. iii. 17, the law of works. Alternatively, it can be seen in another light, encapsulating the specific rules of a divine law, which demand purity of mind and certain actions that might not incur immediate punishments. In this sense, it's called a spiritual law, which brings life to the soul. The teachers of the law and the Pharisees focused on the first aspect as sufficient, neglecting to teach people about the second, more crucial part, viewing it as unnecessary. We can confirm this not only from our own writings but also from Josephus and the Jewish Rabbis. Regarding this second part, we can note that the virtues expected of Christians are either encouraged or mandated for the Hebrews, but not to the same level and extent as for Christians. In both interpretations, Christ sets his own teachings against the old law. This makes it clear that his words carry more weight than just a straightforward interpretation of the Mosaic law. These points apply not just to the current discussion but to many others as well, reminding us not to rely on the authority of the Mosaic law more than is appropriate.
VII. Omitting therefore the less satisfactory proofs, as a leading point of evidence to shew that the right of war is not taken away by the law of the gospel, that passage in St. Paul's Epistle to Timothy may be referred42 to, where the Apostle says, "I exhort therefore that, first of all, supplications, prayers, intercessions, and giving of thanks be made for all men; for Kings, and for all that are in authority, that we may lead a quiet and peaceable life, in all godliness and honesty; for this is good and acceptable in the sight of God our Saviour, who would have all men to be saved, and to come to the knowledge of the truth." 1 Eph. ii. 1, 2, 3. From this passage, the following conclusions may be drawn; in the first place, that Christian piety in kings is acceptable to God, that their profession of Christianity does not abridge their rights of sovereignty. Justin the Martyr has said, "that in our prayers for Kings, we should beg that they may unite a spirit of wisdom with their royal power," and in the book called the Constitutions of Clement, the Church prays for Christian rulers, and that Christian Princes may perform an acceptable service to God, by securing to other Christians the enjoyment of quiet lives. The manner in which the Sovereign secures this important end, is explained in another passage from the same Apostle. Rom. xiii. 4. "He is the minister of God to thee for good. But if thou do evil, fear, for he beareth not the sword in vain; for he is the minister of God, an avenger to execute wrath upon them, that do evil." By the right of the sword is understood the exercise of every kind of restraint, in the sense adopted by the Lawyers, not only over offenders amongst his own people, but against neighboring nations, who violate his own and his people's rights. To clear up this point, we may refer to the second Psalm, which although it applies literally to David, yet in its more full and perfect sense relates to Christ, which may be seen by consulting other parts of scripture. For instance, Acts iv. 25. xiii. 33. For that Psalm exhorts all kings to worship the son of God, shewing themselves, as kings, to be his ministers, which may be explained by the words of St. Augustine, who says, "In this, kings, in their royal capacity, serve God according to the divine commandment, if they promote what is good, and prohibit what is evil in their kingdoms, not only relating to human society, but also respecting religion." And in another place the same writer says, "How can kings serve the Lord in fear, unless they can prohibit and punish with due severity offences against the law of God? For the capacities in which they serve God, as individuals, and as kings, are43 very different. In this respect they serve the Lord, as kings, when they promote his service by means which they could not use without regal power.
VII. Therefore, leaving out the less convincing arguments, as a main point of evidence to show that the right to wage war is not removed by the law of the gospel, we can refer to that passage in St. Paul's Letter to Timothy, where the Apostle says, "I urge, first of all, that petitions, prayers, intercessions, and thanksgiving be made for all people; for kings and all those in authority, that we may live peaceful and quiet lives in all godliness and holiness; for this is good and pleasing in the sight of God our Savior, who wants all people to be saved and to come to a knowledge of the truth." 1 Eph. ii. 1, 2, 3. From this passage, we can draw several conclusions; first, that Christian piety in kings is pleasing to God, and that their profession of Christianity does not limit their sovereign rights. Justin Martyr stated that in our prayers for kings, we should ask that they combine wisdom with their royal power, and in the book called the Constitutions of Clement, the Church prays for Christian rulers, so that Christian princes can provide acceptable service to God by ensuring that other Christians enjoy quiet lives. The way the Sovereign secures this important goal is explained in another passage from the same Apostle. Rom. xiii. 4. "He is God’s servant for your good. But if you do wrong, be afraid, for he does not bear the sword for nothing; he is God’s servant, an agent of wrath to bring punishment on the wrongdoer." The right of the sword is understood as the exercise of all kinds of restraint, in the sense understood by lawyers, not only over offenders within his own people, but also against neighboring nations that violate his rights and those of his people. To clarify this point, we can refer to the second Psalm, which, although it literally applies to David, in its fuller sense relates to Christ, as can be seen by consulting other parts of scripture. For example, Acts iv. 25. xiii. 33. This Psalm calls on all kings to worship the Son of God, demonstrating themselves, as kings, to be his ministers, which can be explained by St. Augustine's words, who says, "In this, kings, in their royal capacity, serve God according to divine command, if they promote what is good and prohibit what is evil in their kingdoms, relating not only to human society but also to religion." In another place, the same writer states, "How can kings serve the Lord in fear unless they can prohibit and punish offenses against the law of God with appropriate severity? For the roles in which they serve God, both as individuals and as kings, are very different. In this regard, they serve the Lord as kings, promoting his service by means that they could not use without royal power."
The same part of the Apostle's writings supplies us with a second argument, where the higher powers, meaning kings, are said to be from God, and are called the ordinance of God; from whence it is plainly inferred that we are to honour and obey the king, from motives of conscience, and that every one who resists him, is resisting God. If the word ordinance meant nothing more than a bare permission, that obedience which the Apostle so strenuously enjoins would only have the force of an imperfect obligation. But as the word ordinance, in the original, implies an express commandment and appointment, and as all parts of the revealed will of God are consistent with each other, it follows that the obedience of subjects to sovereigns is a duty of supreme obligation. Nor is the argument at all weakened by its being said, that the Sovereigns at the time when St. Paul wrote, were not Christians. For it is not universally true, as Sergius Paulus, the deputy governor of Cyprus, had long before professed the Christian religion. Acts xiii. 12. There is no occasion to mention the tradition respecting Abgarus the King of Edessa's Epistle to our Saviour; a tradition mingled with falsehood, though, in some measure founded upon truth. For the question did not turn upon the characters of the Princes, whether they were godly or not, but whether THEIR holding the kingly office was repugnant to the law of God. This St. Paul denies, maintaining that the kingly office, even under all circumstances, was appointed by God, therefore it ought to be honoured from motives of conscience, which, properly speaking, are under the controul of God alone. So that Nero, and King Agrippa whom Paul so earnestly entreats to become a Christian, might have embraced Christianity, and still retained, the one his regal, and the other his imperial authority, which could not be exercised without the power of the sword. As the legal sacrifices might formerly be performed by wicked Priests; in the same manner regal power would retain its indelible sanctity, though in the hands of an ungodly man.
The same part of the Apostle's writings gives us a second argument, where the higher powers, referring to kings, are said to be from God and are called the ordinance of God. It’s clear that we are to honor and obey the king out of conscience, and that anyone who resists him is resisting God. If the word ordinance meant nothing more than a simple permission, then the obedience that the Apostle strongly urges would only carry the weight of an imperfect obligation. However, the word ordinance, in the original text, implies a clear command and appointment, and since all aspects of God's revealed will are consistent with each other, it follows that the obedience of subjects to their sovereigns is a duty of the highest obligation. This argument is not weakened by the fact that the rulers at the time St. Paul wrote were not Christians. It is not universally true that they were all non-believers, as Sergius Paulus, the deputy governor of Cyprus, had long before professed Christianity (Acts xiii. 12). There’s no need to mention the tradition about King Abgarus of Edessa's letter to our Savior; although mixed with falsehood, it is somewhat based on truth. Because the issue is not about whether the rulers were godly, but whether their kingship is contrary to God's law. St. Paul denies this, asserting that the kingship, regardless of the circumstances, was appointed by God, therefore it should be honored from motives of conscience, which are ultimately under God's authority alone. Thus, Nero and King Agrippa, whom Paul earnestly urges to become Christians, could have embraced Christianity while still holding onto their royal and imperial powers, both of which could not be exercised without the authority of the sword. Just as legal sacrifices could once be performed by wicked priests, in the same way, regal power retains its undeniable sanctity, even in the hands of a wicked person.
A third argument is derived from the words of John the Baptist, who, at a time when many thousands of the Jews served in the Roman armies, as appears from the testimony of Josephus and others, being seriously asked44 by the soldiers, what they should do to avoid the wrath of God, did not command them to renounce their military calling, which he ought to have done, had it been inconsistent with the law and will of God, but to abstain from violence, extortion, and false accusation, and to be content with their wages. In reply to these words of the Baptist, so plainly giving authority to the military profession, many observed that the injunction of the Baptist is so widely different from the precepts of Christ, that He seemed to preach one doctrine and our Lord another. Which is by no means admissible, for the following reasons. Both our Saviour and the Baptist made repentance the substance of their doctrine; for the kingdom of heaven was at hand. By the Kingdom of Heaven is meant a new law, as the Hebrews used to give the name of Kingdom to their law. Christ himself says the Kingdom of Heaven began to suffer violence from the days of John the Baptist. Matt. xi. 12. John is said to have preached the baptism of repentance for the remission of sins. Mark i. 4. The Apostles are said to have done the same in the name of Christ. Acts xi. 38. John requires fruits worthy of repentance, and threatens destruction to those, who do not produce them. Matt. iii. 8, 10. He also requires works of charity above the law. Luke iii. 2. The law is said to have continued till John, that is, a more perfect law is said to have commenced from his instruction. He was called greater than the prophets, and declared to be one sent to give the knowledge of salvation to the people by announcing the gospel. He makes no distinction between himself and Jesus on the score of doctrine, only ascribing pre-eminence to Christ as the promised Messiah, the Lord of the Kingdom of Heaven, who would give the power of the holy spirit to those, who believed in him. In short, the dawning rudiments of knowledge, which proceeded from the forerunner, were more distinctly unfolded and cleared up, by Christ himself, the light of the world.
A third argument comes from the words of John the Baptist, who, at a time when many thousands of Jews served in the Roman armies, as shown by the testimonies of Josephus and others, was seriously asked by the soldiers what they should do to avoid God's wrath. He did not tell them to give up their military service, which he should have if it went against God's law and will, but advised them to avoid violence, extortion, and false accusations, and to be satisfied with their pay. In response to the Baptist’s words, which clearly supported the military profession, many noted that his instructions were quite different from Christ's teachings, suggesting that He preached one message while our Lord preached another. This isn’t acceptable for several reasons. Both our Savior and the Baptist emphasized repentance as the core of their message, because the kingdom of heaven was near. The Kingdom of Heaven refers to a new law, as the Hebrews used to refer to their law as a Kingdom. Christ himself said that the Kingdom of Heaven began to suffer violence from the days of John the Baptist. Matt. xi. 12. John is said to have preached the baptism of repentance for the remission of sins. Mark i. 4. The Apostles also did the same in the name of Christ. Acts xi. 38. John calls for fruits worthy of repentance and warns of destruction for those who do not produce them. Matt. iii. 8, 10. He also asks for charitable deeds beyond the law. Luke iii. 2. The law is said to have lasted until John, meaning that a more perfect law began with his teachings. He was called greater than the prophets and declared to be sent to give the people the knowledge of salvation through the gospel. He does not differentiate between himself and Jesus in terms of doctrine, only assigning preeminence to Christ as the promised Messiah, the Lord of the Kingdom of Heaven, who would give the gift of the Holy Spirit to those who believed in him. In short, the initial insights provided by the forerunner were more clearly explained and illuminated by Christ himself, the light of the world.
There is a fourth argument, which seems to have no little weight, proceeding upon the supposition, that if the right of inflicting capital punishments were abolished, and princes were deprived of the power of the sword to protect their subjects against the violence of murderers and robbers, wickedness would triumphantly prevail, and the world would be deluged with crimes, which, even under the best established governments, are with so much difficulty45 prevented or restrained. If then it had been the intention of Christ to introduce such an order of things as had never been heard of, he would undoubtedly by the most express and particular words, have condemned all capital punishments, and all wars, which we never read that he did. For the arguments, brought in favor of such an opinion, are for the most part very indefinite and obscure. Now both justice and common sense require such general expressions to be taken in a limited acceptation, and allow us, in explaining ambiguous words, to depart from their literal meaning, where our strictly adhering to it would lead to manifest inconvenience and detriment.
There’s a fourth point that seems quite significant. It assumes that if the right to impose capital punishment were taken away, and rulers lost the power to protect their citizens from violent criminals, evil would prevail, and the world would be overwhelmed with crimes that are already hard to prevent, even in well-established governments. If Christ intended to create such an unprecedented order, he would have clearly condemned all capital punishment and all wars, which we never see him do. The arguments in support of this view are mostly vague and unclear. Justice and common sense require that such broad statements be interpreted in a limited way, allowing us to move away from their literal interpretation when sticking to it would clearly cause problems and harm.
There is a fifth argument, maintaining that no proof can be adduced that the judicial part of the Mosaic Law, inflicting sentence of death, ever ceased to be in force, till the city of Jerusalem, and the civil polity of the Jews were utterly destroyed, without hopes of restoration. For in the Mosaic dispensation no assignable term is named for the duration of the law; nor do Christ and his Apostles ever speak of its abolition, except in allusion to the overthrow of the Jewish state. Indeed on the contrary, St. Paul says, that the High Priest was appointed to judge according to the law of Moses. Acts xxiv. 3. And Christ himself, in the introduction to his precepts, declares that he came not to destroy the law, but to fulfil it. Matt. v. 17. The application of his meaning to the ritual law is very plain, for it was only the outline and shadow of that perfect body, of which the Gospel formed the substance. But how is it possible that the judicial laws should stand, if Christ, according to the opinion of some, abolished them by his coming? Now if the law remained in force as long as the Jewish state continued, it follows that the Jewish converts to Christianity if called to the magisterial office, could not refuse it on the score of declining to pass sentence of death, and that they could not decide otherwise than the law of Moses had prescribed.
There’s a fifth argument stating that there’s no evidence to show that the judicial part of the Mosaic Law, which prescribed the death penalty, ever stopped being in effect until the city of Jerusalem and the Jewish civil authority were completely destroyed without any chance of recovery. In the Mosaic system, there’s no specific time mentioned for how long the law would last; nor do Jesus and his Apostles ever talk about its cancellation, except in reference to the downfall of the Jewish state. In fact, St. Paul mentions that the High Priest was appointed to judge according to the law of Moses. Acts xxiv. 3. And Jesus himself, when introducing his teachings, declares that he came not to abolish the law, but to fulfill it. Matt. v. 17. His meaning regarding the ritual law is quite clear, as it was merely a foreshadowing of the perfect substance that the Gospel provided. But how can the judicial laws still be in effect if some believe that Christ abolished them with his arrival? If the law remained valid as long as the Jewish state did, then Jewish converts to Christianity, if they held a magistrate position, could not refuse it on the grounds of not wanting to impose the death penalty, and they couldn’t rule any differently than what the law of Moses stipulated.
Upon weighing the whole matter, the slightest ground cannot be discovered for supposing that any pious man, who had heard those words from our Saviour himself, would have understood them in a sense different from that which has been here given. It must however be admitted that, before the Gospel dispensation permission or impunity was granted to certain acts and dispositions, which it46 would neither be necessary nor proper to examine at present, upon which Christ did not allow his followers to act. Of this kind was the permission to put away a wife for every offence, and to seek redress by law for every injury. Now between the positive precepts of Christ and those permissions there is a difference, but not a contradiction. For he that retains his wife, and he that forgoes his right of redress, does nothing CONTRARY to the law, but rather acts agreeably to the SPIRIT of it. It is very different with a judge, who is not merely permitted, but commanded by the law to punish a murderer with death, incurring guilt in the sight of God, if he should act otherwise. If Christ had forbidden him to put a murderer to death, his prohibition would have amounted to a contradiction, and it would have abolished the law.
Considering the whole situation, there’s no reasonable basis to believe that any devout person who heard those words from our Savior himself would interpret them differently than the explanation given here. However, it must be acknowledged that before the Gospel era, some actions and attitudes were allowed or overlooked, which Christ did not permit his followers to engage in. For example, during that time, a man could dismiss his wife for any reason and seek legal remedy for every wrong done to him. There’s a difference between the clear commands of Christ and those allowances, but they’re not contradictory. A person who keeps his wife or voluntarily gives up his right to seek justice isn’t acting against the law; rather, he is following the spirit of the law. This is quite different for a judge, who is not just allowed but required by law to sentence a murderer to death. If he fails to do so, he incurs guilt in the eyes of God. If Christ had prohibited him from carrying out the death penalty on a murderer, that would have contradicted the law and rendered it void.
The example of Cornelius the Centurion supplies a sixth argument in favor of this opinion. In receiving the holy spirit from Christ, he received an indubitable proof of his justification; he was baptized into the name of Christ by Peter, yet we do not find that he either had resigned or was advised by the Apostle to resign his military commission. In reply to which some maintain, that when instructed by Peter in the nature of the Christian religion, he must have been instructed to form the resolution of quitting his military calling. There would be some weight in their answer, if it could be shown that an absolute prohibition of war is to be found among the precepts of Christ. And as it can be found nowhere else, it would have been inserted in its proper place among the precepts of Christ, that after ages might not have been ignorant of the rules of duty. Nor as may be seen in the xix. chap. of the Acts of the Apostles and the 19th ver. is it usual with St. Luke, in cases where the personal character and situation of converts required an extraordinary change of life and disposition, to pass over such a circumstance without notice.
The example of Cornelius the Centurion provides a sixth argument in support of this view. By receiving the Holy Spirit from Christ, he received undeniable proof of his justification; he was baptized in the name of Christ by Peter, yet we don’t find any indication that he either gave up or was advised by the Apostle to give up his military position. In response, some argue that when instructed by Peter about the nature of the Christian faith, he must have been told to decide to leave his military job. Their argument might hold some weight if it could be shown that there is an outright prohibition of war among Christ's teachings. Since it cannot be found anywhere else, it should have been included in the relevant section of Christ's teachings, so that future generations would not be unaware of the rules of duty. Furthermore, as can be seen in Acts 19, it's not typical for St. Luke to overlook significant changes in life and character that were needed by converts.
The seventh argument is like the preceding, and is taken from the example of Sergius Paulus, which has been already mentioned. In the history of his conversion there is not the least intimation of his abdicating the magistracy, or being required to do so. Therefore silence respecting a circumstance, which would naturally and necessarily have been mentioned, may be fairly taken as a proof that it never existed. The conduct of St. Paul supplies us with an eighth argument on this subject.47 When he understood that the Jews lay in wait for an opportunity to seize and kill him, he immediately gave information of their design to the commander of the Roman garrison, and when the commander gave him a guard of soldiers to protect him on his journey, he made no remonstrance, nor ever hinted either to the commander or the soldiers that it was displeasing to God to repel force by force. Yet this is the same Apostle who, as appears from all his writings, 2 Tim. iv. 2. neither himself neglected nor allowed others to neglect any opportunity of reminding men of their duty. In addition to all that has been said, it may be observed, that the peculiar end of what is lawful and binding, must itself be lawful and binding also. It is lawful to pay tribute, and according to St. Paul's explanation, it is an act binding upon the conscience, Rom. xiii. 3, 4, 6. For the end of tribute is to supply the state with the means of protecting the good, and restraining the wicked. There is a passage in Tacitus very applicable to the present question. It is in the fourth book of his history, in the speech of Petilius Cerealis, who says, "the peace of nations cannot be preserved without armies, nor can armies be maintained without pay, nor pay supplied without taxation." There is a sentiment similar to this of the historian, in St. Augustin, he says, "for this purpose we pay tribute, that the soldier may be provided with the necessaries of life."
The seventh argument is similar to the previous one and is based on the example of Sergius Paulus, which has been mentioned before. In the story of his conversion, there's no indication that he gave up his position or was required to do so. Therefore, the lack of mention of a situation that would have naturally come up suggests that it never happened. The actions of St. Paul provide us with an eighth argument on this subject. When he discovered that the Jews were plotting to ambush and kill him, he immediately informed the commander of the Roman garrison. When the commander assigned soldiers to protect him on his journey, he made no objections and never suggested to either the commander or the soldiers that defending oneself against violence was displeasing to God. Yet, this is the same Apostle who, as shown in all his writings (2 Tim. iv. 2), neither ignored nor allowed others to ignore any chance to remind people of their responsibilities. Additionally, it should be noted that the specific purpose of something that is lawful and obligatory must also be lawful and obligatory. It is lawful to pay taxes, and according to St. Paul's explanation, it is an act that binds the conscience (Rom. xiii. 3, 4, 6). The purpose of taxes is to provide the state with the resources needed to protect the good and restrain the wicked. There’s a relevant quote from Tacitus that pertains to the current discussion. In the fourth book of his history, in the speech of Petilius Cerealis, he states, "the peace of nations cannot be preserved without armies, nor can armies be sustained without pay, nor can pay be supplied without taxes." A similar thought is expressed by St. Augustine, who says, "we pay taxes for the purpose of providing soldiers with the necessities of life."
The tenth argument is taken from that part of the xxv. chap. of the Acts of the Apostles, where Paul says, "If I have wronged any man, or done any thing worthy of death, I refuse not to die." From whence the opinion of St. Paul may be gathered, that, even after the publication of the gospel, there were certain crimes which justice not only allowed but required to be punished with death; which opinion St. Peter also maintains. But if it had been the will of God that capital punishments should be abolished, Paul might have cleared himself, but he ought not to have left an impression on the minds of men, that it was at that time equally lawful as before to punish the guilty with death. Now as it has been proved, that the coming of Christ did not take away the right of inflicting capital punishments, it has at the same time been proved, that war may be made upon a multitude of armed offenders, who can only be brought to justice by defeat in battle. The numbers, the strength and boldness of the aggressors, though they may have48 their weight in restraining our deliberations, cannot in the least diminish our right.
The tenth argument comes from that part of chapter 25 of the Acts of the Apostles, where Paul says, "If I have wronged anyone or done anything deserving of death, I do not refuse to die." From this, we can gather St. Paul’s opinion that even after the gospel was published, there were certain crimes that justice not only allowed but required to be punished with death; this view is also supported by St. Peter. However, if it were God's will that capital punishment be abolished, Paul could have defended himself but he should not have left people thinking that it was still just as lawful as before to punish the guilty with death. Now, since it has been proven that the coming of Christ did not eliminate the right to impose capital punishments, it has also been proven that war can be waged against a multitude of armed offenders, who can only be brought to justice by defeating them in battle. The number, strength, and boldness of the aggressors, while they may weigh on our discussions, do not in any way diminish our right.
The substance of the eleventh argument rests not only upon our Saviour's having abolished those parts of the Mosaic law, which formed a wall of separation between the Jews and other nations, but upon his allowing the moral parts to remain, as standing rules, approved by the law of nature, and the consent of every civilized people, and containing whatever is good and virtuous.
The essence of the eleventh argument is based not only on Jesus having removed the elements of the Mosaic law that created a division between Jews and other nations but also on his decision to keep the moral aspects intact as enduring guidelines. These rules are acknowledged by natural law and accepted by all civilized societies, encompassing everything that is good and virtuous.
Now the punishing of crimes, and the taking up arms to avenge or ward off injuries are among those actions, which by the law of nature rank as laudable, and are referred to the virtues of justice and beneficence. And here is the proper place to animadvert slightly upon the mistake of those, who derive the rights of war, possessed by the Israelites, solely from the circumstance of God having given them the land of Canaan and commissioned them to drive out the inhabitants. This may be one just reason, but it is not the sole reason.
Now, punishing crimes and taking up arms to seek revenge or protect oneself from harm are actions that, according to natural law, are considered commendable and relate to the virtues of justice and kindness. This is the right moment to briefly address the error of those who believe that the Israelites’ rights to war stem solely from God's gift of the land of Canaan and His command for them to expel the inhabitants. While this may be one valid reason, it is not the only one.
For, prior to those times, holy men guided by the light of nature undertook wars, which the Israelites themselves afterwards did for various reasons, and David in particular, to avenge the violated rights of ambassadors. But the rights, which any one derives from the law of nature, are no less his own than if God had given them: nor are those rights abolished by the law of the Gospel.
For, before those times, holy men guided by the light of nature went to war, which the Israelites later did for different reasons, and David, in particular, to avenge the rights of ambassadors that had been violated. However, the rights that anyone has from the law of nature are just as much their own as if God had given them: nor are those rights eliminated by the law of the Gospel.
VIII. Let us now consider the arguments, by which the contrary opinion is supported, that the pious reader may judge more easily, to which side the scale inclines.
VIII. Let’s now look at the arguments that support the opposing view, so the thoughtful reader can more easily determine which way the scale tips.
In the first place, the prophecy of Isaiah is generally alleged, who says the time shall come, "when nations shall beat their swords into plow-shares, and turn their spears into pruning hooks. Nation shall not lift up sword against nation, neither shall they learn war any more." ii. 4. But this prophecy, like many others, is to be taken conditionally, alluding to the state of the world that would take place, if all nations would submit to the law of Christ, and make it the rule of life, to which purpose God would suffer nothing to be wanting on his part. For it is certain, that if all people were Christians, and lived like Christians, there would be no wars, which Arnobius expresses thus, "If all men, knowing that it is not their corporeal form alone which makes them men, but the powers of the understanding, would lend a patient49 ear to his salutary and pacific instructions, if they would trust to his admonitions rather than to the swelling pride and turbulence of their senses, iron would be employed for instruments of more harmless and useful operations, the world enjoy the softest repose and be united in the bands of inviolable treaties." On this subject Lactantius, reproaching the Pagans with the deification of their conquerors, says, "what would be the consequence, if all men would unite in concord? Which might certainly be brought to pass, if, abandoning ruinous and impious rage, they would live in justice and innocence." Or this passage of the prophecy must be understood literally, and, if taken in that sense, it shews that it is not yet fulfilled, but its accomplishment must be looked for in the general conversion of the Jewish people. But, which ever way you take it, no conclusion can be drawn from it against the justice of war, as long as violent men exist to disturb the quiet of the lovers of peace.7
In the first place, the prophecy of Isaiah is often cited, where he says the time will come when "nations will turn their swords into plowshares and their spears into pruning hooks. Nation will not take up sword against nation, nor will they learn war anymore." ii. 4. However, this prophecy, like many others, should be understood conditionally, referring to a state of the world that would exist if all nations accepted the law of Christ and made it their guiding principle. To this end, God would ensure that nothing lacking on His part would prevent this. It’s clear that if everyone were Christians and lived like Christians, there would be no wars, which Arnobius expresses as follows: "If all people, understanding that it's not just their physical form that makes them human, but the powers of the mind, would listen patiently to His life-giving and peaceful teachings, trusting His guidance over the overwhelming pride and chaos of their senses, iron would be used for more harmless and useful tasks, the world would enjoy true peace, and be united in unbreakable agreements." On this topic, Lactantius criticizes the Pagans for worshipping their conquerors, asking, "What would happen if everyone united in harmony? This could definitely happen if, setting aside destructive and sinful rage, they chose to live justly and innocently." Alternatively, this prophecy might be taken literally, and if understood this way, it shows that it hasn't been fulfilled yet, with its achievement expected in the widespread conversion of the Jewish people. But whichever interpretation you choose, nothing can be concluded from it against the righteousness of war, as long as violent individuals exist to disrupt the peace of those who love tranquility.49
IX. In examining the meaning of written evidence, general custom, and the opinions of men celebrated for their wisdom have usually great weight; a practice which it is right to observe in the interpretation of holy scripture. For it is not likely that churches, which had been founded by the Apostles, would either suddenly or universally have swerved from those opinions, which the Apostles had briefly expressed, in writing, and afterwards more fully and clearly explained to them with their own lips, and reduced to practice. Now certain expressions of the primitive Christians are usually alleged by those who are adverse to all wars, whose opinions may be considered and refuted in three points of view.
IX. When looking at the meaning of written evidence, general customs and the thoughts of respected wise individuals typically carry a lot of weight; this is an approach we should apply when interpreting holy scripture. It's unlikely that churches founded by the Apostles would have suddenly or completely strayed from the beliefs that the Apostles initially expressed in writing and later explained more fully and clearly in person, and put into practice. Now, certain statements made by early Christians are often cited by those who oppose all wars, and their views can be analyzed and challenged from three different perspectives.
In the first place, from these expressions nothing more can be gathered than the private opinions of certain individuals, but no public opinion of the Churches. Besides these expressions for the most part are to be found only in the writings of Origen, Tertullian and some few others, who wished to distinguish themselves by the brilliancy of their thoughts, without regarding consistency in their opinions. For this same Origen says, that Bees were given by God as a pattern for men to follow in conducting just, regular, and necessary wars; and likewise Tertullian, who in some parts seems to disapprove of capital50 punishments, has said, "No one can deny that it is good the guilty should be punished." He expresses his doubts respecting the military profession, for in his book upon idolatry, he says, it is a fit matter of inquiry, whether believers can take up arms, or whether any of the military profession can be admitted as members of the Christian Church. But in his Book entitled, the Soldier's Crown, after some objections against the profession of arms, he makes a distinction between those who are engaged in the army before baptism, and those who entered after they had made the baptismal vow. "It evidently, says he alters the case with those who were soldiers before their conversion to Christianity; John admitted them to baptism, in one instance Christ approved, and in another Peter instructed a faithful Centurion: yet with this stipulation, that they must either like many others, relinquish their calling, or be careful to do nothing displeasing to God." He was sensible then that they continued in the military profession after baptism, which they would by no means have done, if they had understood that all war was forbidden by Christ. They would have followed the example of the Soothsayers, the Magi, and other professors of forbidden arts, who ceased to practice them, when they became Christians. In the book quoted above, commending a soldier, who was at the same time a Christian, he says, "O Soldier glorious in God."
In the first place, these statements mainly reflect the personal views of a few individuals, not the collective opinion of the Churches. Additionally, most of these comments are found only in the writings of Origen, Tertullian, and a few others who aimed to stand out with their brilliant ideas, often disregarding consistency in their beliefs. For instance, Origen claims that God gave bees as a model for humans to follow in conducting just, organized, and necessary wars; likewise, Tertullian, who sometimes seems against capital punishment, stated, "No one can deny that it's good for the guilty to be punished." He expresses uncertainty about military service, mentioning in his book on idolatry that it's worth investigating whether believers can bear arms or if any members of the military can be part of the Christian Church. However, in his book titled The Soldier's Crown, after raising some objections regarding military service, he differentiates between those serving in the army before baptism and those who joined after they had taken their baptismal vows. "It clearly," he says, "changes the situation for those who were soldiers before their conversion to Christianity; John allowed them to be baptized, in one case, Christ approved it, and in another, Peter guided a faithful Centurion: yet with the condition that they must either, like many others, give up their profession or be careful to do nothing displeasing to God." He realized that they remained in the military after baptism, which they wouldn't have done if they had believed that all war was forbidden by Christ. They would have followed the examples of the Soothsayers, the Magi, and others practicing forbidden arts, who stopped when they became Christians. In the aforementioned book, while praising a soldier who was also a Christian, he says, "O Soldier glorious in God."
The second observation applies to the case of those, who declined or even refused bearing arms, on account of the circumstances of the times, which would have required them to do many acts inconsistent with their Christian calling. In Dolabella's letter to the Ephesians, which is to be found in Josephus, we see that the Jews requested an exemption from military expeditions, because, in mingling with strangers, they could not conveniently have observed the rites of their own laws and would have been obliged to bear arms, and to make long marches on the Sabbaths. And we are informed by Josephus that, for the same reasons, the Jews obtained their discharge of L. Lentulus. In another part, he relates that when the Jews had been ordered to leave the city of Rome, some of them enlisted in the army, and that others, who out of respect to the laws of their country, for the reasons before mentioned, refused to bear arms, were punished. In addition to these a third reason may be given, which was that they would have to51 fight against their own people, against whom it was unlawful to bear arms, especially when they incurred danger and enmity for adhering to the Mosaic law. But the Jews, whenever they could do it, without these inconveniences, served under foreign princes, previously stipulating, as we are informed by Josephus, for liberty to live according to the laws and rules of their own country. Tertullian objects to the military service of his own times on account of dangers, and inconveniences very similar to those, which deterred the Jews. In his book on Idolatry, he says, "it is impossible to reconcile the oath of fidelity to serve under the banners of Christ, with that to serve under the banners of the Devil." Because the soldiers were ordered to swear by Jupiter, Mars, and the other Heathen Gods. And in his book on the Soldier's Crown, he asks, "if the soldier be to keep watch before the temples, which he has renounced, to sup where he is forbidden by the Apostle, and to guard in the night the Gods, whom he has abjured in the day?" And he proceeds with asking, "if there be not many other military duties, which ought to be regarded in the light of sins?"
The second observation is about those who chose not to bear arms, or even refused to do so, due to the circumstances of the time that would have forced them to act in ways that contradicted their Christian beliefs. In Dolabella's letter to the Ephesians, found in Josephus, it shows that the Jews asked for an exemption from military campaigns because interacting with non-Jews would make it hard for them to follow their laws and they would have to fight and march long distances on the Sabbath. Josephus tells us that for these same reasons, the Jews were released from service by L. Lentulus. In another part, he mentions that when the Jews were ordered to leave Rome, some joined the army, while others, respecting their country's laws and for the reasons stated before, refused to serve and faced punishment. A third reason can also be noted: they would have had to fight against their own people, which was against their beliefs, especially when they faced danger and hostility for sticking to the Mosaic law. However, when possible and without these issues, the Jews served under foreign rulers, having previously negotiated, as Josephus noted, the right to live according to their own laws. Tertullian criticized the military service of his time for dangers and inconveniences similar to those that deterred the Jews. In his book on Idolatry, he states, "it is impossible to reconcile the oath of loyalty to serve under Christ's banner with that to serve under the Devil's banner." This is because soldiers were required to swear by Jupiter, Mars, and other pagan gods. In his book on the Soldier's Crown, he asks, "if a soldier must stand guard before temples he has rejected, dine where he is forbidden by the Apostle, and keep watch at night over gods he has renounced during the day?" He continues to inquire, "are there not many other military duties that should be viewed as sins?"
The third point of view, in which the subject is to be considered, relates to the conduct of those primitive Christians, who, in the ardour of zeal, aimed at the most brilliant attainments, taking the divine counsels for precepts of obligation. The Christians, says Athenagoras, never go to law with those, who rob them.
The third perspective to consider is about the behavior of those early Christians who, driven by their passion, sought the most impressive achievements, treating divine guidance as mandatory rules. Athenagoras states that Christians never take legal action against those who steal from them.
Salvian says, it was commanded by Christ that we should relinquish the object of dispute, rather than engage in law suits. But this, taken in so general an acceptation, is rather by the way of counsel, in order to attain to a sublimer mode of life, than intended as a positive precept. Thus many of the primitive Fathers condemned all oaths without exception, yet St. Paul, in matters of great importance, made use of these solemn appeals to God. A Christian in Tatian said, "I refuse the office of Praetor," and in the words of Tertullian, "a Christian is not ambitious of the Aedile's office." In the same manner Lactantius maintains that a just man, such as he wishes a Christian to be, ought not to engage in war, nor, as all his wants can be supplied at home, even to go to sea. How many of the primitive fathers dissuade Christians from second marriages? All these counsels are good, recommending excellent attainments, highly acceptable to God, yet they are not required of52 us, by any absolute law. The observations already made are sufficient to answer the objections derived from the primitive times of Christianity.
Salvian says that Christ commanded us to give up our disputes instead of getting into lawsuits. However, this idea is more of a suggestion aimed at achieving a higher way of life rather than a strict rule. Many early Church Fathers condemned all oaths without exception, but St. Paul used these solemn appeals to God in serious matters. A Christian in Tatian stated, "I decline the role of Praetor," and according to Tertullian, "a Christian is not eager for the Aedile's role." Similarly, Lactantius argues that a just person, as he believes a Christian should be, should not go to war, and since all his needs can be met at home, he shouldn't even go to sea. Many early Church Fathers discourage Christians from remarrying. All of these suggestions are good and promote admirable qualities that are pleasing to God, but they are not strictly required of us by any definitive law. The points made so far are enough to address objections based on the early days of Christianity.
Now in order to confirm our opinions, we may observe that they have the support of writers, even of greater antiquity, who think that capital punishments may be inflicted, and that wars, which rest upon the same authority, may be lawfully engaged in by Christians. Clemens Alexandrinus says, that "a Christian, if, like Moses, he be called to the exercise of sovereign power, will be a living law to his subjects, rewarding the good, and punishing the wicked." And, in another place, describing the habit of a Christian, he says, "it would become him to go barefoot, unless he were a soldier." In the work usually entitled the Constitutions of Clemens Romanus, we find that "it is not all killing which is considered unlawful, but only that of the innocent; yet the administration of judicial punishments must be reserved to the supreme power alone." But without resting upon individual authorities, we can appeal to the public authority of the church which ought to have the greatest weight. From hence it is evident that none were ever refused baptism, or excommunicated by the church, merely for bearing arms, which they ought to have been, had the military profession been repugnant to the terms of the new covenant. In the Constitutions just quoted, the writer speaking of those who, in the primitive times, were admitted to baptism, or refused that ordinance, says, "let a soldier who desires to be admitted be taught to forbear from violence, and false accusations, and to be content with his regular pay. If he promises obedience let him be admitted." Tertullian in his Apology, speaking in the character of Christians, says, "We sail along with you, and we engage in the same wars," having a little before observed, "we are but strangers, yet we have filled all your cities, your islands, your castles, your municipal towns, your councils, and even your camps." He had related in the same book that rain had been obtained for the Emperor Marcus Aurelius by the prayers of the Christian soldiers.8 In his book of the crown, he commends a soldier, who had thrown away his garland, for a courage superior to that of his brethren in arms,53 and informs us that he had many Christian fellow soldiers.
Now, to back up our views, we can see that they are supported by even older writers who believe that capital punishment can be imposed, and that wars, based on the same justification, can be rightfully waged by Christians. Clemens Alexandrinus states that "a Christian, if called to take on sovereign power like Moses, will be a living law to his subjects, rewarding the good and punishing the wicked." In another part, discussing how Christians should live, he says, "it would be fitting for him to go barefoot unless he is a soldier." In the work usually titled the Constitutions of Clement of Rome, it is noted that "not all killing is considered unlawful, only that of the innocent; however, the enforcement of judicial punishments must be left to the supreme authority." But beyond citing individual authorities, we can reference the general authority of the church, which should carry significant weight. From this, it is clear that no one was ever denied baptism or excommunicated by the church simply for being a soldier, which would have been the case if military service was against the terms of the new covenant. In the Constitutions just mentioned, the author talks about those in the early days who were accepted for baptism or denied it, stating, "let a soldier who wishes to be baptized be instructed to refrain from violence and false accusations, and to be content with his regular pay. If he promises to obey, let him be accepted." Tertullian, in his Apology, speaks from the perspective of Christians, saying, "We sail alongside you and participate in the same wars," having remarked earlier, "we are just strangers, yet we have populated all your cities, your islands, your forts, your municipal towns, your councils, and even your camps." He had earlier mentioned that rain was granted for Emperor Marcus Aurelius through the prayers of Christian soldiers. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ In his book about the crown, he praises a soldier who cast aside his garland for showing more courage than his fellow soldiers,53 and informs us that he had many Christian comrades in arms.
To these proofs may be added the honours of Martyrdom given by the Church to some soldiers, who had been cruelly persecuted, and had even suffered death for the sake of Christ, among whom are recorded three of St. Paul's companions, Cerialis who suffered martyrdom under Decius; Marinus under Valerian; fifty under Aurelian, Victor, Maurus, and Valentinus, a lieutenant general under Maximian. About the same time Marcellus the Centurion, Severian under Licinius. Cyprian, in speaking of Laurentinus, and Ignatius, both Africans, says, "They too served in the armies of earthly princes, yet they were truly spiritual soldiers of God, defeating the wiles of the Devil by a steady confession of the name of Christ, and earning the palms and crowns of the Lord by their sufferings." And from hence it is plain what was the general opinion of the primitive Christians upon war, even before the Emperors became Christians.
To these proofs, we can add the honors of Martyrdom given by the Church to some soldiers who were severely persecuted and even killed for the sake of Christ. Among them are recorded three of St. Paul's companions: Cerialis, who was martyred under Decius; Marinus under Valerian; and fifty others under Aurelian, including Victor, Maurus, and Valentinus, a lieutenant general under Maximian. Around the same time, there was Marcellus the Centurion and Severian under Licinius. Cyprian, in referring to Laurentinus and Ignatius, both Africans, says, "They also served in the armies of earthly rulers, yet they were truly spiritual soldiers of God, overcoming the schemes of the Devil through their unwavering confession of Christ's name and earning the palms and crowns of the Lord through their sufferings." This clearly shows the general opinion of early Christians regarding war, even before the Emperors embraced Christianity.
It need not be thought surprising, if the Christians of those times were unwilling to appear at trials for life, since, for the most part, the persons to be tried were Christians. In other respects too, besides being unwilling to witness the unmerited sufferings of their persecuted brethren, the Roman laws were more severe than Christian lenity could allow of, as may be seen from the single instance of the Silanian decree of the Senate.9 Indeed capital punishments were not abolished even after Constantine embraced and began to encourage the Christian religion. He himself among other laws enacted one similar to that of the ancient Romans, for punishing parricides, by sewing them in a sack with certain animals, and throwing them into the sea, or the nearest river. This law is to be found in his code under the "title of the murders of parents or children." Yet in other respects he was so gentle in punishing criminals, that he is blamed by many historians for his excessive lenity. Constantine, we are informed by historians, had at that time many54 Christians in his army, and he used the name of Christ as the motto upon his standards. From that time too the military oath was changed to the form, which is found in Vegetius, and the soldier swore, "By God, and Christ, and the holy spirit, and the majesty of the Emperor, to whom as next to God, homage and reverence are due from mankind." Nor out of so many Bishops at that time, many of whom suffered the most cruel treatment for their religion, do we read of a single one, who dissuaded Constantine, by the terrors of divine wrath from inflicting capital punishments, or prosecuting wars, or who deterred the Christians, for the same reasons, from serving in the armies. Though most of those Bishops were strict observers of discipline, who would by no means dissemble in points relating to the duty of the Emperors or of others. Among this class, in the time of Theodosius, we may rank Ambrose, who in his seventh discourse says, "there is nothing wrong in bearing arms; but to bear arms from motives of rapine is a sin indeed," and in his first book of Offices, he maintains the same opinion, that "the courage which defends one's country against the incursions of barbarians, or protects one's family and home from the attacks of robbers, is complete justice." These arguments so decidedly shew the opinions of the primitive Christians in the support of just and necessary war, that the subject requires no farther proof or elucidation.
It shouldn't be surprising that Christians at that time were reluctant to attend life-threatening trials, as most of those on trial were Christians themselves. Additionally, besides not wanting to witness the unjust suffering of their persecuted fellow believers, Roman laws were harsher than Christian compassion allowed, which is evident from the example of the Silanian decree from the Senate. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__. In fact, capital punishment wasn't abolished even after Constantine adopted and began promoting Christianity. He himself enacted laws similar to those of ancient Rome, punishing parricides by sewing them into a sack with certain animals and throwing them into the sea or the nearest river. This law can be found in his code under the "title of the murders of parents or children." However, in other respects, he was so lenient in punishing criminals that many historians criticize him for being too soft. According to historians, Constantine had many Christians in his army at that time and used the name of Christ as the motto on his standards. From that point on, the military oath changed to a form found in Vegetius, where soldiers swore, "By God, and Christ, and the Holy Spirit, and the majesty of the Emperor, to whom, next to God, homage and reverence are due from all mankind." Out of the many Bishops during that time, many of whom faced severe persecution for their faith, not a single one is recorded as having dissuaded Constantine from imposing capital punishment or waging wars due to fears of divine wrath, nor did any discourage Christians from serving in the military for the same reasons. Although most of these Bishops strictly upheld discipline and would not hesitate to speak out on matters concerning the duties of Emperors or others. Among this group, during Theodosius's time, we can include Ambrose, who in his seventh discourse says, "there is nothing wrong with bearing arms; but to bear arms for the sake of plunder is truly a sin," and in his first book of Offices, he maintains that "the courage that defends one's country from barbarian invasions or protects one's family and home from robbers is complete justice." These arguments clearly demonstrate the views of early Christians on just and necessary war, requiring no further proof or explanation.
Nor is the argument invalidated by a fact pretty generally known, that Bishops and other Christians often interceded in behalf of criminals, to mitigate the punishment of death, and that any, who had taken refuge in churches, were not given up, but upon the promise of their lives being spared. A custom was introduced likewise of releasing all prisoners about the time of Easter. But all these instances, if carefully examined, will be found the voluntary acts of Christian kindness, embracing every opportunity to do good, and not a settled point of public opinion condemning all capital punishments. Therefore those favours were not universal; but limited to times and places, and even the intercessions themselves were modified with certain exceptions.10
The argument isn’t invalidated by a well-known fact that bishops and other Christians often advocated for criminals to lessen the death penalty. Anyone who sought refuge in churches wasn’t turned over unless it was guaranteed their lives would be spared. There was also a custom of releasing all prisoners around Easter. However, upon closer examination, these instances reveal acts of Christian compassion, seizing every opportunity to do good, rather than a fixed stance in public opinion against all capital punishment. So, these favors weren’t universal; they were restricted to certain times and places, and even the intercessions had specific exceptions.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
CHAPTER III.
The Distinction Between Public and Private War and the Nature of Sovereign Power.
The Division of War into public and private—Examples to prove that all private War is not repugnant to the Law of Nature since the erection of Courts of Justice—The Division of Public War into formal, and informal—Whether the suppression of Tumults by subordinate Magistrates be properly public War—Civil Power, in what it consists—Sovereign Power further considered—The opinion of those, who maintain that the Sovereign Power is always in the people, refuted, and their arguments answered—Mutual subjection refuted—Cautions requisite to understand the nature of Sovereign Power—Distinction of the real differences that exist under similar names—Distinction between the right to Sovereign Power, and the mode of exercising it.
The distinction between public and private war—Examples illustrating that not all private wars go against Natural Law since the creation of Courts of Justice—The classification of Public War into formal and informal—Whether the actions of lower-level officials in suppressing uprisings qualify as public war—What Civil Power entails—An in-depth examination of Sovereign Power—Challenging the belief that Sovereign Power is always held by the people and addressing their arguments—Disproving the concept of Mutual subjection—Precautions necessary to grasp the true nature of Sovereign Power—Clarifying the real differences that exist under similar terms—The difference between the right to Sovereign Power and how it is exercised.
I. The first and most necessary divisions of war are into one kind called private, another public, and another mixed. Now public war is carried on by the person holding the sovereign power. Private war is that which is carried on by private persons without authority from the state. A mixed war is that which is carried on, on one side by public authority, and on the other by private persons. But private war, from its greater antiquity, is the first subject for inquiry.
I. The primary and essential categories of war are divided into three types: private, public, and mixed. Public war is conducted by the person who holds sovereign power. Private war is fought by individuals without permission from the state. A mixed war occurs when one side is backed by public authority while the other is conducted by private individuals. However, because private war is older, it is the first topic to explore.
The proofs that have been already produced, to shew that to repel violence is not repugnant to natural law, afford a satisfactory reason to justify private war, as far as the law of nature is concerned. But perhaps it may be thought that since public tribunals have been erected, private redress of wrongs is not allowable. An objection which is very just. Yet although public trials and courts of justice are not institutions of nature, but erected by the invention of men, yet as it is much more conducive to the peace of society for a matter in dispute to be decided by a disinterested person, than by the partiality and prejudice of the party aggrieved, natural justice and reason will dictate the necessity and advantage of every one's submitting to the equitable decisions of public judges. Paulus, the Lawyer, observes that "what can be done by a magistrate with the authority of the state,56 should never be intrusted to individuals; as private redress would give rise to greater disturbance. And "the reason, says King Theodoric, why laws were invented, was to prevent any one from using personal violence, for wherein would peace differ from all the confusion of war, if private disputes were terminated by force?" And the law calls it force for any man to seize what he thinks his due, without seeking a legal remedy.
The evidence already presented shows that defending against violence is not contrary to natural law, providing a clear reason to justify private war, at least in terms of natural law. However, it might be argued that now that public courts exist, private retribution for wrongs isn't allowed. This is a valid point. Yet, even though public trials and courts are human inventions rather than natural institutions, it’s much more beneficial for society when disputes are resolved by an impartial party rather than by the bias and prejudice of the wronged individual. Natural justice and reason suggest that everyone should accept the fair decisions of public judges. Paulus, the lawyer, notes that "what can be done by a magistrate with the authority of the state,56 should never be left to individuals, as private retribution would cause greater disruptions. And "the reason," says King Theodoric, "laws were created was to stop anyone from using personal violence, because if private disputes were settled through force, how would peace differ from the chaos of war?" The law defines it as force for anyone to take what they believe is theirs without pursuing a legal solution.
II. It is a matter beyond all doubt that the liberty of private redress, which once existed, was greatly abridged after courts of justice were established. Yet there may be cases, in which private redress must be allowed, as for instance, if the way to legal justice were not open. For when the law prohibits any one from redressing his own wrongs, it can only be understood to apply to circumstances where a legal remedy exists. Now the obstruction in the way to legal redress may be either temporary or absolute. Temporary, where it is impossible for the injured party to wait for a legal remedy, without imminent danger and even destruction. As for instance, if a man were attacked in the night, or in a secret place where no assistance could be procured. Absolute, either as the right, or the fact may require. Now there are many situations, where the right must cease from the impossibility of supporting it in a legal way, as in unoccupied places, on the seas, in a wilderness, or desert island, or any other place, where there is no civil government. All legal remedy too ceases by fact, when subjects will not submit to the judge, or if he refuses openly to take cognizance of matters in dispute. The assertion that all private war is not made repugnant to the law of nature by the erection of legal tribunals, may be understood from law given to the Jews, wherein God thus speaks by the mouth of Moses, Exod. xxii. 2. "If a thief be found breaking up, that is, by night, and be smitten that he dies, there shall no blood be shed for him, but if the sun be risen upon him, there shall be blood shed for him." Now this law, making so accurate a distinction in the merits of the case, seems not only to imply impunity for killing any one, in self-defence, but to explain a natural right, founded not on any special divine command, but on the common principles of justice. From whence other nations have plainly followed the same rule. The passage of the twelve tables is well known, undoubtedly taken from the old Athenian Law,57 "If a thief commit a robbery in the night, and a man kill him, he is killed lawfully." Thus by the laws of all known and civilized nations, the person is judged innocent, who kills another, forcibly attempting or endangering his life; a conspiring and universal testimony, which proves that in justifiable homicide, there is nothing repugnant to the law of nature.
II. It's beyond doubt that the right to seek private justice, which used to exist, has been significantly limited since courts were established. Still, there may be situations where private justice is necessary, for example, if the path to legal justice is blocked. When the law prevents someone from addressing their own grievances, it can only apply to cases where a legal remedy is available. The obstruction to legal redress can be either temporary or permanent. Temporary, when the injured person cannot wait for a legal solution due to immediate danger or harm. For instance, if someone is attacked at night or in a hidden place with no help available. Permanent, either as a matter of right or as a fact, may be required. There are many scenarios where the right to seek remedy must end because it cannot be legally supported, such as in uninhabited areas, at sea, in wilderness, on a deserted island, or anywhere without civil government. Legal remedies also cease to exist when subjects refuse to comply with the judge, or if the judge is unwilling to handle the disputes. The assertion that all forms of private retaliation are not contrary to natural law due to the creation of legal courts can be understood from the laws given to the Jews, where God speaks through Moses in Exodus 22:2. "If a thief is found breaking in, meaning at night, and is killed, his blood will not be avenged, but if the sun has risen upon him, then blood will be avenged." This law, making a clear distinction regarding the merits of the case, suggests not only immunity for killing in self-defense but also clarifies a natural right not based on specific divine commands, but on common principles of justice. Other nations have clearly followed this same rule. The passage from the Twelve Tables is well known and is likely derived from the ancient Athenian law, 57 "If a thief commits robbery at night and is killed, it is lawful." Thus, according to the laws of all known and civilized nations, a person is deemed innocent if they kill another who is forcibly attempting to or putting their life in danger; a universal consensus that shows there is nothing against natural law in justifiable homicide.
IV.11 Public war, according to the law of nations, is either SOLEMN, that is FORMAL, or LESS SOLEMN, that is INFORMAL. The name of lawful war is commonly given to what is here called formal, in the same sense in which a regular will is opposed to a codicil, or a lawful marriage to the cohabitation of slaves. This opposition by no means implies that it is not allowed to any man, if he pleases, to make a codicil, or to slaves to cohabit in matrimony, but only, that, by the civil law, FORMAL WILLS and SOLEMN MARRIAGES, were attended with peculiar privileges and effects. These observations were the more necessary; because many, from a misconception of the word just or lawful, think that all wars, to which those epithets do not apply, are condemned as unjust and unlawful. Now to give a war the formality required by the law of nations, two things are necessary. In the first place it must be made on both sides, by the sovereign power of the state, and in the next place it must be accompanied with certain formalities. Both of which are so essential that one is insufficient without the other.
IV.11 Public war, according to international law, is either SERIOUS, meaning OFFICIAL, or LESS SERIOUS, meaning UNOFFICIAL. The term lawful war typically refers to what is called formal here, similar to how a regular will contrasts with a codicil, or a lawful marriage contrasts with the cohabitation of slaves. This distinction doesn’t imply that anyone is prohibited from creating a codicil or that slaves can't cohabit in marriage; it simply means that, according to civil law, Legal Wills and SERIOUS MARRIAGES come with specific privileges and consequences. These observations are particularly important because many mistakenly believe that all wars not described as just or lawful are automatically considered unjust and unlawful. To give a war the formal recognition required by international law, two conditions must be met. First, it must be declared by the sovereign power of both sides, and second, it must follow certain formal procedures. Both of these requirements are so crucial that one cannot substitute for the other.
Now a public war, LESS SOLEMN, may be made without those formalities, even against private persons, and by any magistrate whatever. And indeed, considering the thing without respect to the civil law, every magistrate, in case of resistance, seems to have a right to take up arms, to maintain his authority in the execution of his office; as well as to defend the people committed to his protection. But as a whole state is by war involved in danger, it is an established law in almost all nations that no war can be made but by the authority of the sovereign in each state. There is such a law as this in the last book of Plato on Laws. And by the Roman law, to make war, or levy troops without a commission from the Prince was high treason. According to the Cornelian law also, enacted by Lucius Cornelius Sylla, to do so without authority from58 the people amounted to the same crime. In the code of Justinian there is a constitution, made by Valentinian and Valens, that no one should bear arms without their knowledge and authority. Conformably to this rule, St. Augustin says, that as peace is most agreeable to the natural state of man, it is proper that Princes should have the sole authority to devise and execute the operations of war. Yet this general rule, like all others, in its application must always be limited by equity and discretion.
Now a public war, LESS SERIOUS, can be declared without formalities, even against private individuals, by any magistrate. In fact, viewed outside the context of civil law, any magistrate, in case of resistance, seems to have the right to take up arms to uphold his authority while fulfilling his duties, as well as to protect the people under his care. However, since a whole state is put in jeopardy by war, it is a well-established law in nearly all nations that no war can be declared without the authority of the sovereign in each state. This law can be found in the last book of Plato's on Laws. Under Roman law, waging war or raising troops without a commission from the Prince was considered high treason. According to the Cornelian law, enacted by Lucius Cornelius Sylla, doing so without the approval of58 the people was also seen as a similar crime. In Justinian's code, there is a rule established by Valentinian and Valens that no one should bear arms without their knowledge and authority. In line with this principle, St. Augustine argues that since peace aligns most closely with mankind's natural state, it is fitting for Princes to hold the exclusive authority to plan and conduct military operations. Nevertheless, like all general rules, its application must always be moderated by fairness and discretion.
In certain cases this authority may be communicated to others. For it is a point settled beyond all doubt that subordinate magistrates may, by their officers, reduce a few disobedient and tumultuous persons to subjection, provided, that to do it, it requires not a force of such enormous magnitude as might endanger the state. Again, if the danger be so imminent as to allow of no time for an application to the sovereign executive power, here too the necessity is admitted as an exception to the general rule. Lucius Pinarius the Governor of Enna, a Sicilian garrison, presuming upon this right, upon receiving certain information that the inhabitants had formed a conspiracy to revolt to the Carthaginians, put them all to the sword, and by that means saved the place. Franciscus Victoria allows the inhabitants of a town to take up arms, even without such a case of necessity, to redress their own wrongs, which the Prince neglects to avenge, but such an opinion is rejected by others.
In some situations, this authority can be passed on to others. It's well established that lower-ranking officials can, through their agents, bring a few disobedient and unruly individuals under control, as long as doing so doesn’t require such overwhelming force that it could threaten the state. Additionally, if the danger is so immediate that there’s no time to consult the sovereign executive power, this necessity is also considered an exception to the general rule. Lucius Pinarius, the Governor of Enna, a Sicilian garrison, asserted this right when he learned that the residents had conspired to revolt against the Carthaginians; he executed them all and thus saved the city. Franciscus Victoria argues that residents of a town can take up arms even without an urgent need, to address grievances that the Prince fails to rectify, but this view is not accepted by everyone.
V. Whether the circumstances, under which subordinate magistrates are authorised to use military force, can properly be called public war or not, is a matter of dispute among legal writers, some affirming and others denying it. If indeed we call no other public war, but that which is made by magisterial authority, there is no doubt but that such suppressions of tumult are public wars, and those who in such cases resist the magistrate in the execution of his office, incur the guilt of rebellion against superiors. But if public war is taken in the higher sense of FORMAL war, as it undoubtedly often is; those are not public wars; because to entitle them to the full rights of such, the declaration of the sovereign power and other requisites are wanting. Nor do the loss of property and the military executions, to which the offenders are subject, at all affect the question.12 For those casualties are59 not so peculiarly attached to formal war, as to be excluded from all other kinds. For it may happen, as in an extensive empire for instance, that persons in subordinate authority, may, when attacked, or threatened with attack, have powers granted to commence military operations. In which case the war must be supposed to commence by the authority of the sovereign power; as a person is considered to be the author of a measure which by virtue of his authority he empowers another to perform. The more doubtful point is, whether, where there is no such commission, a conjecture of what is the will of the sovereign power be sufficient. This seems not admissible. For it is not sufficient to consider, what we suppose would be the Sovereign's pleasure, if he were consulted; but what would be his actual will, in matters admitting of time for deliberation, even though he were not formally consulted; if a law was to be passed upon those matters. "For though UNDER SOME PARTICULAR CIRCUMSTANCES, it may be necessary to waive consulting the will of the sovereign, yet this would by no means authorise it as a GENERAL PRACTICE. For the safety of the state would be endangered, if subordinate powers should usurp the right of making war at their discretion. It was not without reason, that Cneus Manlius was accused by his Lieutenants of having made war upon the Galatians without authority from the Roman people. For though the Galatians had supplied Antiochus with troops, yet as peace had been made with him, it rested with the Roman people, and not with Manlius to determine in what manner the Galatians should be punished for assisting an enemy. Cato proposed that Julius Caesar should be delivered up to the Germans for having attacked them in violation of his promise, a proposal proceeding rather from the desire to be rid of a formidable rival, than from any principle of justice.
V. Whether the situations in which lower-ranking officials are allowed to use military force can accurately be termed public war is a subject of debate among legal scholars, with some affirming and others denying it. If we define public war strictly as that which is declared by authoritative officials, then it is clear that such actions taken to suppress riots qualify as public wars, and those who resist officials in carrying out their duties are guilty of rebelling against authorities. However, if we take public war in its broader sense of a OFFICIAL war, as it often is, then these do not qualify as public wars. This is because they lack the declaration of sovereign power and other necessary elements to be recognized as such. The loss of property and military actions faced by the offenders do not influence the question.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ These consequences are not exclusively tied to formal war and can arise in other scenarios as well. For instance, in a vast empire, those in lower authority may be given the power to initiate military actions when under attack or threatened. In this case, the war is assumed to start under the authority of the sovereign, as a person is seen as the initiator of an action when they empower someone else to carry it out by virtue of their authority. The more contentious issue is whether, in the absence of such a commission, an assumption about what the sovereign's will is would be adequate. This seems unacceptable. It is not enough to consider what we think the Sovereign's preference would be if consulted; the focus should be on what their actual will would be regarding matters that allow for deliberation, even if they weren't formally asked, especially if a law was to be enacted on these issues. "For although UNDER SPECIFIC CIRCUMSTANCES, it might be necessary to forgo consulting the sovereign's will, this would not justify it as a General Practice. The state's safety would be at risk if lower authorities could take it upon themselves to declare war at will. There was a good reason why Cneus Manlius was accused by his Lieutenants of waging war against the Galatians without authorization from the Roman people. Even though the Galatians had provided troops to Antiochus, with peace having been made with him, the decision on how to deal with the Galatians for aiding an enemy lay with the Roman people, not with Manlius. Cato suggested that Julius Caesar should be handed over to the Germans for attacking them in violation of his promise, a suggestion stemming more from a desire to eliminate a powerful rival than from any sense of justice.
The case was thus; the Germans had assisted the Gauls, enemies of the Roman people, therefore they had no reason to complain of the injury done to them, if the war against the Gauls, in which they had made themselves a party concerned, was just. But Caesar ought to have contented himself with driving the Germans out of Gaul, the province assigned him, without pursuing them into their own country, especially as there was no farther danger to be apprehended from them; unless he had first consulted the Roman people. It was plain, then,60 the Germans had no right to demand the surrender of Caesar's person, though the Romans had a right to punish him for having exceeded his commission. On a similar occasion the Carthaginians answered the Romans; "It is not the subject of inquiry whether Hannibal has besieged Saguntum, by his own private or by public authority, but whether justly or unjustly. For with respect to one of our own subjects it is our business to inquire by what authority he has acted; but the matter of discussion with you is, whether he has broken any treaty." Cicero defends the conduct of Octavius and Decimus Brutus, who had taken up arms against Antony. But though it was evident that Antony deserved to be treated as an enemy, yet they ought to have waited for the determination of the Senate and people of Rome, whether it were for the public interest not to take notice of his conduct or to punish it, to agree to terms of peace with him, or to have recourse to arms. This would have been proper; for no one is obliged to exercise the right of punishing an enemy, if it is attended with probable danger.
The situation was this: the Germans had helped the Gauls, who were enemies of the Roman people, so they had no reason to complain about the harm done to them if the war against the Gauls, in which they joined, was justified. However, Caesar should have settled for driving the Germans out of Gaul, the area assigned to him, without going after them in their own country, especially since there was no further danger from them; unless he had first consulted the Roman people. It was clear, then, 60 that the Germans had no right to demand Caesar's surrender, although the Romans had the right to punish him for exceeding his authority. In a similar situation, the Carthaginians responded to the Romans: "It’s not a question of whether Hannibal besieged Saguntum on his own initiative or with public authority, but whether he did so justly or unjustly. When it comes to one of our subjects, it's our responsibility to investigate what authority he acted upon; but with you, the discussion is whether he broke any treaties." Cicero defends the actions of Octavius and Decimus Brutus, who took up arms against Antony. But even though it was clear that Antony deserved to be treated as an enemy, they should have waited for the Senate and the people of Rome to decide whether it was in the public interest to ignore his actions or to punish them, to negotiate peace with him, or to resort to arms. That would have been appropriate; for no one is required to exercise the right to punish an enemy if it comes with probable danger.
But even if it had been judged expedient to declare Antony an enemy, the choice of the persons to conduct the war should have been left to the Senate and people of Rome. Thus when Cassius demanded assistance of the Rhodians, according to treaty, they answered they would send it, if the senate thought proper. This refutation of Cicero's opinion will serve, along with many other instances to be met with; as an admonition not to be carried away by the opinions of the most celebrated writers, particularly the most brilliant orators, who often speak to suit the circumstances of the moment. But all political investigation requires a cool and steady judgment, not to be biased by examples, which may rather be excused than vindicated.
But even if it had seemed wise to declare Antony an enemy, the decision on who should lead the war should have been left to the Senate and the people of Rome. So when Cassius asked the Rhodians for help as per the treaty, they replied that they would send it if the Senate deemed it appropriate. This rejection of Cicero's viewpoint will stand, along with many other examples to be encountered, as a reminder not to be swayed by the ideas of well-known writers, especially the most skilled orators, who often speak to fit the situation at hand. However, all political analysis requires a calm and steady judgment, not influenced by examples that may be more justifiable than defendable.
Since then it has already been established that no war can lawfully be made but by the sovereign power of each state, in respect to all the questions connected with war, it will be necessary to examine what that sovereign power is, and who are the persons that hold it.
Since then, it has been established that no war can be lawfully declared except by the sovereign power of each state. Regarding all issues related to war, we need to examine what that sovereign power is and who holds it.
VI. The moral power then of governing a state, which is called by Thucydides the civil power, is described as consisting of three parts which form the necessary substance of every state; and those are the right of making its own laws, executing them in its own manner, and61 appointing its own magistrates. Aristotle, in the fourth book of his Politics, comprises the sovereignty of a state in the exercise of the deliberative, executive, and judicial powers. To the deliberative branch he assigns the right of deciding upon peace or war, making or annulling treaties, and framing and passing new laws. To these he adds the power of inflicting death, banishment, and forfeiture, and of punishing also for public peculation. In the exercise of judicial power, he includes not only the punishment of crimes and misdemeanors, but the redress of civil injuries.13 Dionysius of Halicarnassus, points out three distinguishing marks of sovereign power; and those are, the right of appointing magistrates, the right of enacting and repealing laws, and the right of making war and peace. To which, in another part, he adds the administration of justice, the supreme authority in matters of religion, and the right of calling general councils.
VI. The moral authority of governing a state, referred to by Thucydides as civil power, is described as having three essential parts that make up every state: the right to create its own laws, enforce them as it sees fit, and appoint its own officials. Aristotle, in the fourth book of his Politics, summarizes a state's sovereignty in terms of its deliberative, executive, and judicial powers. He assigns the deliberative branch the authority to decide on matters of peace and war, to make or cancel treaties, and to draft and pass new laws. He also includes the power to impose death, exile, forfeiture, and to punish public corruption. In exercising judicial power, he covers not only the punishment of crimes and misdemeanors but also the resolution of civil injuries. Dionysius of Halicarnassus identifies three key features of sovereign power: the right to appoint officials, the right to create and repeal laws, and the right to make war and peace. Additionally, he notes the administration of justice, the highest authority in religious matters, and the right to convene general councils.
A true definition comprehends every possible branch of authority that can grow out of the possession and exercise of sovereign power. For the ruler of every state must exercise his authority either in person, or through the medium of others. His own personal acts must be either general or special. He may be said to do GENERAL acts in passing or repealing laws, respecting either temporal matters, or spiritual concerns, as far as the latter relate to the welfare of the state. The knowledge of these principles is called by Aristotle the masterpiece in the science of government.
A true definition includes every possible area of authority that can arise from having and using sovereign power. The ruler of every state must exercise their authority either directly or through others. Their personal actions can be either general or specific. They can be said to perform GENERAL acts when passing or repealing laws related to either secular issues or spiritual matters, as long as the latter impact the welfare of the state. Understanding these principles is referred to by Aristotle as the pinnacle of political science.
The particular acts of the Sovereign are either directly of a public nature, or a private, but even the latter bear reference to his public capacity. Now the acts of the sovereign executive power of a directly public kind are the making of peace and war and treaties, and the imposition of taxes, and other similar exercises of authority over the persons and property of its subjects, which constitute the sovereignty of the state. Aristotle calls the knowledge of this practice political and deliberative science.
The specific actions of the Sovereign are either directly public or private, but even the private ones relate back to their public role. The actions of the sovereign executive that are directly public include making peace and war, forming treaties, imposing taxes, and other similar exercises of authority over the people and property of its subjects, which define the sovereignty of the state. Aristotle refers to the understanding of this practice as political and deliberative science.
62 The private acts of the sovereign are those, in which by his authority, disputes between individuals are decided, as it is conducive to the peace of society that these should be settled. This is called by Aristotle the judicial power. Thus the acts of the sovereign are done in his name by his magistrates or other officers, among whom ambassadors are reckoned. And in the exercise of all those rights sovereign power consists.
62 The private actions of the ruler are those in which, through his authority, disputes between individuals are resolved, as it's important for societal peace that these issues are settled. Aristotle refers to this as the judicial power. Therefore, the ruler's actions are carried out in his name by his magistrates or other officials, including ambassadors. The exercise of all those rights constitutes sovereign power.
VII. That power is called sovereign, whose actions are not subject to the controul of any other power, so as to be annulled at the pleasure of any other human will. The term ANY OTHER HUMAN WILL exempts the sovereign himself from this restriction, who may annul his own acts, as may also his successor, who enjoys the same right, having the same power and no other. We are to consider then what is the subject in which this sovereign power exists. Now the subject is in one respect common, and in another proper, as the body is the common subject of sight, the eye the proper, so the common subject of sovereign power is the state, which has already been said to be a perfect society of men.
VII. The power that is called sovereign is one whose actions aren't controlled by any other power, meaning they can't be canceled at the whim of anyone else. The phrase ANY OTHER PERSON WILL means the sovereign isn't included in this limitation, as he can cancel his own actions, just like his successor can, since they share the same rights and powers. Now, we need to consider where this sovereign power exists. The subject is, in one sense, common, and in another sense, specific; just like the body is the common subject of sight and the eye is the specific one, the common subject of sovereign power is the state, which has been defined as a complete society of people.
Now those nations, who are in a state of subjugation to another power, as the Roman provinces were, are excluded from this definition. For those nations are not sovereign states of themselves, in the present acceptation of the word; but are subordinate members of a great state, as slaves are members of a household. Again it happens that many states, forming each an independent body, may have one head. For political are not like natural bodies, to only one of which the same head can belong. Whereas in the former, one person can exercise the function of the head to many distinct bodies. As a certain proof of which, when the reigning house has become extinct, the sovereign power returns to the hands of the nation. So it may happen, that many states may be connected together by the closest federal union, which Strabo, in more places than one calls a system, and yet each retain the condition of a perfect, individual state, which has been observed by Aristotle and others in different parts of their writings. Therefore the common subject of sovereign power is the state, taken in the sense already explained. The proper subject is one or more persons according to the laws and customs of each nation. This is called by Galen in the sixth book de placitis Hippocrate et Platonis, the first power of the state.
Now, nations that are under the control of another power, like the Roman provinces were, don’t fit this definition. These nations aren’t truly sovereign states in the current sense; they are subordinate parts of a larger state, similar to how slaves are part of a household. Additionally, it’s possible for many states, each operating independently, to share a single leader. Political entities aren’t like natural bodies, which can have only one head. In politics, one person can serve as the leader for multiple distinct entities. A clear example of this is when a ruling house goes extinct; the sovereign power then returns to the people. Therefore, many states can be closely linked through a federal union, which Strabo refers to as a system in multiple instances, while still maintaining their status as complete, individual states, as noted by Aristotle and others in various texts. Thus, the primary subject of sovereign power is the state, as previously defined. The specific subject can be one or more individuals, depending on the laws and customs of each nation. Galen refers to this in the sixth book of On the doctrines of Hippocrates and Plato as the primary power of the state.
63 VIII. And here is the proper place for refuting the opinion of those, who maintain that, everywhere and without exception, the sovereign power is vested in the people, so that they have a right to restrain and punish kings for an abuse of their power. However there is no man of sober wisdom, who does not see the incalculable mischiefs, which such opinions have occasioned, and may still occasion; and upon the following grounds they may be refuted.
63 VIII. This is the right moment to challenge the belief that the ultimate authority lies solely with the people, granting them the power to limit and punish kings for misusing their authority. Yet, anyone of sound judgment recognizes the immense harm these ideas have caused and could still cause; they can be countered for the following reasons.
From the Jewish, as well as the Roman Law, it appears that any one might engage himself in private servitude to whom he pleased. Now if an individual may do so, why may not a whole people, for the benefit of better government and more certain protection, completely transfer their sovereign rights to one or more persons, without reserving any portion to themselves? Neither can it be alleged that such a thing is not to be presumed, for the question is not, what is to be presumed in a doubtful case, but what may lawfully be done. Nor is it any more to the purpose to object to the inconveniences, which may, and actually do arise from a people's thus surrendering their rights. For it is not in the power of man to devise any form of government free from imperfections and dangers. As a dramatic writer says, "you must either take these advantages with those imperfections, or resign your pretensions to both."
From both Jewish and Roman law, it seems that anyone could choose to enter into private servitude with whoever they wanted. Now, if an individual can do this, why can’t an entire people, for the sake of better governance and greater protection, fully transfer their sovereign rights to one or more individuals, without holding back any part for themselves? It also can’t be argued that this isn’t something we should consider, because the issue isn’t what should be presumed in a doubtful situation, but rather what can be done lawfully. Additionally, it’s not relevant to point out the problems that may and often do arise when a people give up their rights. It’s beyond human ability to create any form of government that’s completely free from flaws and risks. As a playwright states, "you must either accept these benefits along with those imperfections or forfeit your claims to both."
Now as there are different ways of living, some of a worse, and some of a better kind, left to the choice of every individual; so a nation, "under certain circumstances, WHEN for instance, the succession to the throne is extinct, or the throne has by any other means become vacant," may chuse what form of government she pleases. Nor is this right to be measured by the excellence of this or that form of government, on which there may be varieties of opinion, but by the will of the people.
Now, just like there are different ways of living, some worse and some better, each person has the choice to decide. Similarly, a nation, "under certain circumstances, WHEN for example, the line of succession to the throne has ended, or the throne is vacant for any reason," can choose whatever form of government it wants. This right should not be judged by how good or bad a particular form of government is, which can vary based on opinion, but by the will of the people.
There may be many reasons indeed why a people may entirely relinquish their rights, and surrender them to another: for instance, they may have no other means of securing themselves from the danger of immediate destruction, or under the pressure of famine it may be the only way, through which they can procure support. For if the Campanians, formerly, when reduced by necessity surrendered themselves to the Roman people in the following terms:—"Senators of Rome, we consign to your dominion the people of Campania, and the city of Capua,64 our lands, our temples, and all things both divine and human," and if another people as Appian relates, offered to submit to the Romans, and were refused, what is there to prevent any nation from submitting in the same manner to one powerful sovereign? It may also happen that a master of a family, having large possessions, will suffer no one to reside upon them on any other terms, or an owner, having many slaves, may give them their liberty upon condition of their doing certain services, and paying certain rents; of which examples may be produced. Thus Tacitus, speaking of the German slaves, says, "Each has his own separate habitation, and his own household to govern. The master considers him as a tenant, bound to pay a certain rent in corn, cattle, and wearing apparel. And this is the utmost extent of servitude."
There are definitely many reasons why a group of people might completely give up their rights and hand them over to someone else. For example, they might not have any other way to protect themselves from the threat of immediate destruction, or in the case of famine, it might be the only way to get food. If, for instance, the Campanians, when faced with necessity, surrendered to the Roman people saying: “Senators of Rome, we hand over the people of Campania and the city of Capua, our land, our temples, and all things both divine and human,” and if another group, as Appian mentions, tried to submit to the Romans and was turned away, what stops any nation from submitting in the same way to a powerful ruler? It may also happen that a head of a household with significant possessions allows no one to live on them except under certain conditions, or a landowner with many slaves might grant them freedom on the condition that they perform specific services and pay certain rents; examples of this exist. For instance, Tacitus, when discussing German slaves, notes, “Each has his own separate dwelling and his own household to manage. The master sees him as a tenant, obligated to pay a certain rent in grain, livestock, and clothing. And this is the maximum level of servitude.”
Aristotle, in describing the requisites, which fit men for servitude, says, that "those men, whose powers are chiefly confined to the body, and whose principal excellence consists in affording bodily service, are naturally slaves, because it is their interest to be so." In the same manner some nations are of such a disposition that they are more calculated to obey than to govern, which seems to have been the opinion which the Cappadocians held of themselves, who when the Romans offered them a popular government, refused to accept it, because the nation they said could not exist in safety without a king. Thus Philostratus in the life of Apollonius, says, that it was foolish to offer liberty to the Thracians, the Mysians, and the Getae, which they were not capable of enjoying. The example of nations, who have for many ages lived happily under a kingly government, has induced many to give the preference to that form. Livy says, that the cities under Eumenes would not have changed their condition for that of any free state whatsoever. And sometimes a state is so situated, that it seems impossible it can preserve its peace and existence, without submitting to the absolute government of a single person, which many wise men thought to be the case with the Roman Republic in the time of Augustus Caesar. From these, and causes like these it not only may, but generally does happen, that men, as Cicero observes in the second book of his offices, willingly submit to the supreme authority of another.
Aristotle, while discussing the qualities that make people suited for servitude, claims that "those individuals whose abilities are mainly physical and whose main strength lies in providing physical labor are naturally slaves because it's in their best interest to be so." Similarly, some nations have a tendency that makes them more suited to obey than to rule, which seems to have been the view that the Cappadocians had of themselves. When the Romans offered them self-governance, they declined, arguing that their nation could not survive safely without a king. Philostratus, in the life of Apollonius, states that it was absurd to offer freedom to the Thracians, the Mysians, and the Getae, who weren't capable of handling it. The example of nations that have lived happily under a monarchy for many years has led many to prefer that system. Livy mentions that the cities under Eumenes wouldn’t have traded their situation for any free state. Sometimes, a state is positioned in such a way that it seems impossible for it to maintain peace and existence without submitting to the absolute rule of a single leader, which many wise individuals believed was true for the Roman Republic during Augustus Caesar’s time. For these reasons, and similar ones, it often happens, as Cicero notes in the second book of his offices, that people willingly submit to the supreme authority of another.
Now as property may be acquired by what has been already styled just war, by the same means the rights of65 sovereignty may be acquired. Nor is the term sovereignty here meant to be applied to monarchy alone, but to government by nobles, from any share in which the people are excluded. For there never was any government so purely popular, as not to require the exclusion of the poor, of strangers, women, and minors from the public councils. Some states have other nations under them, no less dependent upon their will, than subjects upon that of their sovereign princes. From whence arose that question, Are the Collatine people in their own power? And the Campanians, when they submitted to the Romans, are said to have passed under a foreign dominion. In the same manner Acarnania and Amphilochia are said to have been under the dominion of the Aetolians; Peraea and Caunus under that of the Rhodians; and Pydna was ceded by Philip to the Olynthians. And those towns, that had been under the Spartans, when they were delivered from their dominion, received the name of the free Laconians. The city of Cotyora is said by Xenophon to have belonged to the people of Sinope. Nice in Italy, according to Strabo, was adjudged to the people of Marseilles; and the island of Pithecusa to the Neapolitans. We find in Frontinus, that the towns of Calati and Caudium with their territories were adjudged, the one to the colony of Capua, and the other to that of Beneventum. Otho, as Tacitus relates, gave the cities of the Moors to the Province of Baetia. None of these instances, any more than the cessions of other conquered countries could be admitted, if it were a received rule that the rights of sovereigns are under the controul and direction of subjects.
Now, property can be acquired through what has been called just war, and similarly, the rights of sovereignty can also be acquired. The term sovereignty here refers not just to monarchy but also to governments run by nobles, from which the people are excluded. There has never been a government that is purely popular, as they still require excluding the poor, foreigners, women, and minors from public councils. Some states have other nations under them, just as subjects depend on their sovereign rulers. This raises the question: Are the Collatine people truly in control of themselves? And when the Campanians submitted to the Romans, they were said to fall under foreign control. Similarly, Acarnania and Amphilochia were said to be under the control of the Aetolians; Peraea and Caunus under the Rhodians; and Pydna was given by Philip to the Olynthians. The towns that had been under Spartan rule, when freed from their dominance, were called the free Laconians. Xenophon mentions that the city of Cotyora belonged to the people of Sinope. Nice in Italy, according to Strabo, was awarded to the people of Marseilles, and the island of Pithecusa to the Neapolitans. Frontinus tells us that the towns of Calati and Caudium and their territories were assigned, one to the colony of Capua and the other to Beneventum. Otho, as Tacitus describes, gave the cities of the Moors to the Province of Baetia. None of these instances, nor the transfers of other conquered lands, would be accepted if it were a widely recognized rule that the rights of sovereigns are controlled and directed by their subjects.
Now it is plain both from sacred and profane history, that there are kings, who are not subject to the controul of the people in their collective body; God addressing the people of Israel, says, if thou shalt say, "I will place a king over me"; and to Samuel "Shew them the manner of the king, who shall reign over them." Hence the King is said to be anointed over the people, over the inheritance of the Lord, over Israel. Solomon is styled King over all Israel. Thus David gives thanks to God, for subduing the people under him. And Christ says, "the Kings of the nations bear rule over them." There is a well known passage in Horace, "Powerful sovereigns reign over their own subjects, and the supreme being over sovereigns themselves." Seneca thus describes the three forms of government, "Sometimes the supreme66 power is lodged in the people, sometimes in a senate composed of the leading men of the state, sometimes this power of the people, and dominion over the people themselves is vested in a single person." Of the last description are those, who, as Plutarch says, exercise authority not according to the laws, but over the laws. And in Herodotus, Otanes describes a monarch as one whose acts are not subject to controul. Dion Prusaeensis also and Pausanias define a monarchy in the same terms.
Now it's clear from both sacred and secular history that there are kings who aren’t controlled by the people as a whole. God tells the Israelites, "If you say, 'I want a king over me'," and to Samuel, "Show them how a king will rule over them." So, the King is considered anointed over the people, over the Lord's inheritance, over Israel. Solomon is called King over all Israel. Thus, David thanks God for putting the people under his authority. And Christ says, "The kings of the nations rule over them." There's a well-known quote from Horace: "Powerful rulers govern their own subjects, and the supreme being governs the rulers themselves." Seneca describes the three forms of government: "Sometimes the supreme power is held by the people, sometimes by a senate made up of the leading men of the state, and sometimes this power is vested in a single individual." This last type includes those who, as Plutarch says, use authority not in accordance with the laws, but above the laws. And in Herodotus, Otanes describes a monarch as someone whose actions aren't subject to control. Dion Prusaeensis and Pausanias also define monarchy in the same way.
Aristotle says there are some kings, who have the same right, which the nation elsewhere possesses over persons and property. Thus when the Roman Princes began to exercise regal power, the people it was said had transferred all their own personal sovereignty to them, which gave rise to the saying of Marcus Antoninus the Philosopher, that no one but God alone can be judge of the Prince. Dion. L. liii. speaking of such a prince, says, "he is perfectly master of his own actions, to do whatever he pleases, and cannot be obliged to do any thing against his will." Such anciently was the power of the Inachidae established at Argos in Greece. For in the Greek Tragedy of the Suppliants, Aeschylus has introduced the people thus addressing the King: "You are the state, you the people; you the court from which there is no appeal, you preside over the altars, and regulate all affairs by your supreme will." King Theseus himself in Euripides speaks in very different terms of the Athenian Republic; "The city is not governed by one man, but in a popular form, by an annual succession of magistrates." For according to Plutarch's explanation, Theseus was the general in war, and the guardian of the laws; but in other respects nothing more than a citizen. So that they who are limited by popular controul are improperly called kings. Thus after the time of Lycurgus, and more particularly after the institution of the Ephori, the Kings of the Lacedaemonians are said by Polybius, Plutarch, and Cornelius Nepos, to have been Kings more in name than in reality. An example which was followed by the rest of Greece. Thus Pausanias says of the Argives to the Corinthians, "The Argives from their love of equality have reduced their kingly power very low; so that they have left the posterity of Cisus nothing more than the shadow of Kings." Aristotle denies such to be proper forms of government,67 because they constitute only a part of an Aristocracy or Democracy.
Aristotle argues that some kings have the same rights that the nation has over individuals and property. So, when the Roman Princes started to wield royal power, it was claimed that the people had handed over all their personal sovereignty to them. This led to the saying by Marcus Antoninus the Philosopher, that only God can judge the Prince. Dion. L. liii. mentions that such a prince is entirely in control of his own actions, able to do whatever he wants, and cannot be forced to do anything against his will. This was the nature of power held by the Inachidae in Argos, Greece. In the Greek Tragedy "The Suppliants," Aeschylus presents the people addressing the King: "You are the state, you are the people; you are the court with no appeals, you oversee the altars, and you manage all affairs by your ultimate will." King Theseus himself, in Euripides, speaks differently about the Athenian Republic: "The city is not ruled by one person, but in a popular manner, with rotating annual magistrates." According to Plutarch, Theseus was the military leader and protector of the laws, but in other aspects, he was just a citizen. Thus, those who are restricted by popular control are incorrectly referred to as kings. After Lycurgus' time, especially following the establishment of the Ephori, the Spartan kings were described by Polybius, Plutarch, and Cornelius Nepos as kings in title only. This example was emulated by the rest of Greece. Pausanias remarked about the Argives to the Corinthians, "The Argives, due to their desire for equality, have significantly diminished their royal power, leaving the descendants of Cisus with nothing more than the title of kings." Aristotle rejects these as legitimate forms of government, 67 because they are merely a part of either an aristocracy or democracy.
Examples also may be found of nations, who have not been under a perpetual regal form, but only for a time under a government exempt from popular controul. Such was the power of the Amimonians among the Cnidians, and of the Dictators in the early periods of the Roman history, when there was no appeal to the people, from whence Livy says, the will of the Dictator was observed as a law. Indeed they found this submission the only remedy against imminent danger, and in the words of Cicero, the Dictatorship possessed all the strength of royal power.
Examples can also be found of nations that haven't always been under a monarchy, but for a time were governed without popular control. Such was the case with the Amimonians among the Cnidians and the Dictators in the early days of Roman history, when there was no appeal to the people. Livy notes that the will of the Dictator was regarded as law. In fact, they found this submission to be the only solution against serious danger, and in Cicero's words, the Dictatorship held all the power of a king.
It will not be difficult to refute the arguments brought in favour of the contrary opinion. For in the first place the assertion that the constituent always retains a controul over the sovereign power, which he has contributed to establish, is only true in those cases where the continuance and existence of that power depends upon the will and pleasure of the constituent: but not in cases where the power, though it might derive its origin from that constituent, becomes a necessary and fundamental part of the established law. Of this nature is that authority to which a woman submits when she gives herself to a husband. Valentinian the Emperor, when the soldiers who had raised him to the throne, made a demand of which he did not approve, replied; "Soldiers, your election of me for your emperor was your own voluntary choice; but since you have elected me, it depends upon my pleasure to grant your request. It becomes you to obey as subjects, and me to consider what is proper to be done."
It won’t be hard to challenge the arguments made for the opposing viewpoint. First, the claim that the person who made the decision always has control over the sovereign power they helped establish is only true in situations where the continued existence of that power relies on the will and desire of that person. This isn’t the case when the power, even if it originated from that person, becomes a necessary and fundamental part of the established law. An example of this is the authority a woman accepts when she marries a man. When the soldiers who helped elevate Emperor Valentinian to the throne made a demand he didn’t agree with, he responded, “Soldiers, your choice to make me your emperor was your own decision; but now that you’ve chosen me, it’s up to me to decide whether to grant your request. You should obey as subjects, and I will determine what is right to do.”
Nor is the assumption true, that all kings are made by the people, as may be plainly seen from the instances adduced above, of an owner admitting strangers to reside upon his demesnes on condition of their obedience, and of nations submitting by right of conquest. Another argument is derived from a saying of the Philosophers, that all power is conferred for the benefit of the governed and not of the governing party. Hence from the nobleness of the end, it is supposed to follow, that subjects have a superiority over the sovereign. But it is not universally true, that all power is conferred for the benefit of the party governed. For some powers are conferred for the sake of the governor, as the right of a68 master over a slave, in which the advantage of the latter is only a contingent and adventitious circumstance. In the same manner the gain of a Physician is to reward him for his labour; and not merely to promote the good of his art. There are other kinds of authority established for the benefit of both parties, as for instance, the authority of a husband over his wife. Certain governments also, as those which are gained by right of conquest, may be established for the benefit of the sovereign; and yet convey no idea of tyranny, a word which in its original signification, implied nothing of arbitrary power or injustice, but only the government or authority of a Prince. Again, some governments may be formed for the advantage both of subjects and sovereign, as when a people, unable to defend themselves, put themselves under the protection and dominion of any powerful king. Yet it is not to be denied, but that in most governments the good of the subject is the chief object which is regarded: and that what Cicero has said after Herodotus, and Herodotus after Hesiod, is true, that Kings were appointed in order that men might enjoy complete justice.
The idea that all kings are created by the people isn't true, as demonstrated by the examples mentioned earlier, like a landowner allowing outsiders to live on their property as long as they obey, and nations submitting through conquest. Another argument comes from a saying by philosophers that all power is given for the benefit of the governed, not for those in power. This suggests that subjects are superior to the sovereign because the purpose is noble. However, it's not always true that all power is given for the benefit of those being governed. Some powers exist for the advantage of the ruler, like a master’s control over a slave, where the benefit to the slave is just a side effect. Similarly, a physician's fee rewards their labor, not just the good of their profession. There are also types of authority that benefit both parties, like the authority a husband has over his wife. Certain governments, especially those established through conquest, may serve the ruler's benefit without implying tyranny—originally, tyranny simply referred to the rule of a prince without any connotation of unjust or arbitrary power. Additionally, some governments can be set up for the mutual benefit of subjects and rulers, such as when a community that can’t defend itself chooses to submit to a powerful king. Still, it can’t be denied that in most governments, the well-being of the subject is the primary focus. As Cicero said after Herodotus, who quoted Hesiod, kings were appointed so that people could experience true justice.
Now this admission by no means goes to establish the inference that kings are amenable to the people. For though guardianships were invented for the benefit of wards, yet the guardian has a right to authority over the ward. Nor, though a guardian may for mismanagement be removed from his trust, does it follow that a king may for the same reason be deposed. The cases are quite different, the guardian has a superior to judge him; but in governments, as there must be some dernier resort, it must be vested either in an individual, or in some public body, whose misconduct, as there is no superior tribunal before which they can be called, God declares that he himself will judge. He either punishes their offences, should he deem it necessary; or permits them for the chastisement of his people.
Now, this admission certainly doesn’t suggest that kings are accountable to the people. While guardianships were created for the benefit of those they protect, the guardian still holds authority over the ward. Just because a guardian can be removed for mismanagement doesn't mean a king can be overthrown for the same reason. The situations are quite different; the guardian is judged by someone higher up, but in government, there must be some ultimate authority, which has to lie either with one person or some public body. Since there is no higher court to hold them accountable, God declares that He will judge them Himself. He either punishes their wrongdoings if He sees fit, or allows them to continue for the sake of disciplining His people.
This is well expressed by Tacitus: he says, "you should bear with the rapacity or luxury of rulers, as you would bear with drought, or excessive rains, or any other calamities of nature. For as long as men exist there will be faults and imperfections; but these are not of uninterrupted continuance, and they are often repaired by the succession of better times." And Marcus Aurelius speaking of subordinate magistrates, said, that they were under the controul of the sovereign: but that the sovereign was69 amenable to God. There is a remarkable passage in Gregory of Tours, where that Bishop thus addresses the King of France, "If any of us, Sir, should transgress the bounds of justice, he may be punished by you. But if you exceed them, who can call you to account? For when we address you, you may hear us if you please; but if you will not, who can judge you, except him, who has declared himself to be righteousness?" Among the maxims of the Essenes, Porphyry cites a passage, that "no one can reign without the special appointment of divine providence." Irenaeus has expressed this well, "Kings are appointed by him at whose command men are created; and their appointment is suited to the condition of those, whom they are called to govern." There is the same thought in the Constitutions of Clement, "You shall fear the King, for he is of the Lord's appointment."
This is well expressed by Tacitus: he says, "you should tolerate the greed or extravagance of rulers, just like you would tolerate drought, heavy rains, or any other natural disasters. As long as people exist, there will be flaws and shortcomings; however, these aren’t constant, and they're often fixed by the arrival of better times." And Marcus Aurelius, speaking about junior officials, said they are under the control of the ruler: but the ruler is69 accountable to God. There is a notable passage in Gregory of Tours, where that Bishop addresses the King of France, "If any of us, Sir, should cross the line of justice, you can punish him. But if you go beyond it, who can hold you accountable? When we talk to you, you may choose to listen; but if you decide not to, who can judge you, except the one who has defined righteousness?" Among the maxims of the Essenes, Porphyry cites a passage that "no one can rule without the specific appointment of divine providence." Irenaeus has articulated this well, "Kings are appointed by him who commands the creation of humanity; and their appointment fits the condition of those they are meant to govern." The same idea is found in the Constitutions of Clement, "You shall respect the King, for he is appointed by the Lord."
Nor is it an objection to what has been said, that some nations have been punished for the offences of their kings; for this does not happen, because they forbear to restrain their kings, but because they seem to give, at least a tacit consent to their vices, or perhaps, without respect to this, God may use that sovereign power which he has over the life and death of every man to inflict a punishment upon the king by depriving him of his subjects.
Nor is it a valid objection to what has been mentioned that some nations have been punished for the wrongdoings of their kings; this occurs not because they fail to control their kings, but because it appears they at least give silent approval to their vices. Or, perhaps regardless of this, God may exercise the sovereign power He has over every person's life and death to punish the king by taking away his subjects.
IX. There are some who frame an imaginary kind of mutual subjection, by which the people are bound to obey the king, as long as he governs well; but his government is subject to their inspection and controul. If they were to say that his duty to the sovereign does not oblige any one to do an act manifestly unjust and repugnant to the law of God; they would say nothing but what is true and universally admitted, but this by no means includes a right to any controul over the Prince's conduct in his lawful government. But if any people had the opportunity of dividing the sovereign power with the king, the privileges of the one, and the prerogatives of the other ought to be defined by certain bounds, which might easily be known, according to the difference of places, persons, or circumstances.
IX. Some people create a fictional idea of mutual submission, where the citizens must obey the king as long as he rules justly; however, his governance is subject to their oversight and control. If they claim that his obligation to the sovereign doesn't require anyone to act in a way that's clearly unjust and against the law of God, they would be stating something that is true and generally accepted. Nonetheless, this doesn’t give them the right to interfere with the king's actions in his legitimate government. But if any group had the chance to share sovereign power with the king, the rights of one and the privileges of the other should be clearly outlined by specific limits that could be easily understood based on different locations, individuals, or situations.
Now the supposed good or evil of any act, especially in political matters which admit of great variety of opinions and much discussion, is not a sufficient mark to ascertain these bounds. From whence the greatest confusion must follow, if under pretence of promoting70 good or averting evil measures, the people might struggle for the Prince's jurisdiction: a turbulent state of affairs, which no sober minded people ever wished to experience.
Now, the idea of what is good or bad about any action, especially in politics, where there are a lot of different opinions and much debate, isn't enough to determine these limits. This could lead to significant confusion if, under the guise of promoting good or preventing evil, people start fighting for the Prince's control: a chaotic situation that no reasonable person would ever want to face.
X. After refuting false opinions, it remains to apply some cautions, which may point out the way to ascertain correctly the person to whom sovereign power, in every state, of right belongs. The first caution necessary is to avoid being deceived by ambiguous terms, or appearances foreign to the real subject. For instance, among the Latins, although the terms PRINCIPALITY and KINGDOM are generally opposed to each other, when Caesar says, that the father of Vercingetorix held the principality of Gaul, and was put to death for aiming at sovereign power; and when Piso, in Tacitus calls Germanicus the son of a Roman Prince, not of a Parthian King; and when Suetonius says, that Caligula was on the point of converting the power of a prince into that of a king; and Velleius asserts that Maroboduus not contented with the authority of a prince over voluntary adherents and dependents, was grasping in his mind at regal power; yet we find these terms though in reality very distinct were often confounded. For the Lacedaemonian chiefs, the descendants of Hercules, though subject to the controul of the Ephori, were nevertheless called kings: and Tacitus says, that among the ancient Germans there were kings, who governed more by the influence of persuasion than by the authority of power. Livy too, speaking of king Evander, describes him as reigning more by personal authority than by his regal power; and Aristotle, Polybius, and Diodorus give the names of Kings to the Suffetes or Judges of the Carthaginians. In the same manner Solinus also calls Hanno King of the Carthaginians. Strabo speaks of Scepsis in Troas, that having incorporated the Milesians into the state, it formed itself into a Democracy, leaving the descendants of the ancient kings the title, and something of the dignity of kings.
X. After debunking false beliefs, it's important to take some precautions that can help identify who truly holds sovereign power in any state. The first precaution is to avoid getting misled by vague terms or by things that don't relate to the actual subject. For example, among the Latins, even though the terms PRINCIPALITY and Kingdom are usually seen as opposites, Caesar mentions that the father of Vercingetorix held the principality of Gaul and was executed for seeking sovereign power. Additionally, Piso, in Tacitus, refers to Germanicus as the son of a Roman Prince, not a Parthian King; and Suetonius notes that Caligula was about to transform the power of a prince into that of a king. Velleius claims that Maroboduus, not satisfied with the authority of a prince over willing followers and dependents, was aiming for royal power. Despite these terms being very different in reality, they were often confused. For instance, the Spartan leaders, descendants of Hercules, were called kings even though they were under the control of the Ephori. Tacitus mentions that among the ancient Germans, there were kings who ruled more through persuasion than through sheer power. Livy, when discussing King Evander, describes him as governing more through personal influence than through his royal authority. Likewise, Aristotle, Polybius, and Diodorus refer to the Suffetes or Judges of the Carthaginians as Kings. Solinus also designates Hanno as the King of the Carthaginians. Strabo talks about Scepsis in Troas, which, after integrating the Milesians into its state, evolved into a Democracy while allowing the descendants of the ancient kings to keep their title and some degree of royal dignity.
On the other hand, the Roman emperors, after they had exercised openly, and without any disguise, a most absolute monarchical power, were notwithstanding called Princes. And in some popular states the chief magistrates are graced with ensigns of royalty.
On the other hand, the Roman emperors, after they had openly and without any disguise exercised complete monarchical power, were still referred to as Princes. And in some democratic states, the chief officials are given symbols of royalty.
Again the states general, that is the convention of those who represent the people, divided into classes according to Gunther, consist of three orders, which are71 the Prelates, the Nobles, and Deputies of large towns. In some places, they serve as a greater council to the king, to communicate to him the complaints of his people, which might otherwise be kept from his ears; leaving him at the same time full liberty to exercise his own discretion upon the matters so communicated. But in other places they form a body with power to inquire into the prince's measures, and to make laws.
Again, the states general, which is the assembly of those who represent the people, are divided into classes according to Gunther. They consist of three orders, which are71 the Clergy, the Nobles, and Representatives of major towns. In some areas, they serve as a larger council for the king, relaying the complaints of his people that might otherwise go unheard; meanwhile, they allow him full freedom to exercise his own judgment on the matters presented. In other areas, they act as a body with the authority to investigate the prince's actions and to create laws.
Many think that in order to know whether a prince be sovereign or not, it is proper to inquire whether his title to the crown is by election or inheritance. For they maintain that hereditary monarchies alone are sovereign. But this cannot be received as a general criterion. For sovereignty consists not merely in the TITLE to the throne, which only implies that the successor has a right to all the privileges and prerogatives that his ancestors enjoyed, but it by no means affects the nature or extent of his powers. For right of election conveys all the powers, which the first election or appointment conferred. Among the Lacedaemonians the crown was hereditary even after the institution of the Ephori. And Aristotle describing the chief power of such a state, says, "Of these kingdoms, some are hereditary, and others elective." In the heroic times most of the kingdoms in Greece were of this description, as we are informed by Thucydides. The Roman empire, on the contrary, even after the power of the Senate and people was abolished, was given or confirmed by election.
Many people believe that to determine if a prince is truly sovereign, it's important to look at whether his claim to the throne comes from election or inheritance. They argue that only hereditary monarchies are sovereign. However, this cannot serve as a general rule. Sovereignty isn't just about the TITLE to the throne, which only means that the successor has the right to all the privileges and powers that his ancestors enjoyed; it doesn't necessarily influence the nature or extent of his authority. The right of election carries all the powers that the first election or appointment granted. Among the Lacedaemonians, the crown was hereditary even after the establishment of the Ephori. Aristotle notes the primary power in such a state, saying, "Of these kingdoms, some are hereditary, and others elective." During the heroic era, most Greek kingdoms were of this type, as Thucydides informs us. Conversely, the Roman Empire, even after the Senate and people's authority was removed, was appointed or confirmed through election.
XI. Another caution is necessary. For to inquire into the matter of a right is not the same thing as to examine the nature of its tenure. A distinction which takes place not only in corporeal but in incorporeal possessions. For a right of passage or carriage through a ground is no less a right than that which entitles a man to the possession of the land itself. Now some hold these privileges by a full right of property, some by an usufructuary, and others by a temporary right. Thus the Roman Dictator had sovereign power by a temporary right. In the same manner kings, both those who are the first of their line elected to the throne, and those who succeed them in the lawful order, enjoy an usufructuary right, or inalienable right. But some sovereigns hold their power by a plenary right of property; when for instance it comes into their possession by the right of lawful conquest, or when a people, to avoid greater evils, make an unqualified72 surrender of themselves and their rights into their hands.
XI. Another caution is important. Asking about the nature of a right isn’t the same as looking into how it’s held. This distinction applies not just to physical possessions but also to non-physical ones. A right of way or passage over someone's land is just as much a right as ownership of the land itself. Some people hold these privileges as full ownership, some as a temporary use, and others as a limited right. For instance, the Roman Dictator had ultimate power through a temporary right. Similarly, kings—both those who were originally elected to the throne and their lawful successors—have a limited right or inalienable right. However, some rulers have their power as full owners, like when they gain it through lawful conquest or when a group of people, to avoid greater harm, completely surrender themselves and their rights to them.
The opinion of those can never be assented to, who say that the power of the Dictator was not sovereign, because it was not permanent. For in the moral world the nature of things is known from their operations. The powers attended with equal effects are entitled to equal names. Now the Dictator for the time being performed all acts with the same authority as the most absolute sovereign; nor could any other power annul his acts. The permanence therefore of uncertainty alters not the nature of a right, although it would undoubtedly abridge its dignity, and diminish its splendour.14
The views of those who argue that the power of the Dictator wasn't sovereign because it wasn't permanent can't be accepted. In the moral world, we understand the nature of things by their actions. Powers that produce similar effects deserve equal recognition. The Dictator, while in office, executed all acts with the same authority as the most absolute sovereign; no other power could override his actions. So, the uncertainty of permanence doesn't change the nature of a right, although it would certainly reduce its dignity and lessen its splendor.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Book II.
CHAPTER I.
Defense of Person and Property.
Causes of War—Defence of person and property—What are called justifiable causes of war—Justifiable causes of War are Defence, recovery of one's property or debt, or the punishment of offences committed—War for defence of life, justifiable, and lawful—This kind of war lawful against an aggressor only—The danger must be present and real, not an imaginary danger—Lawful to kill any one attempting to maim one's person, or violate one's chastity—Occasions where this right may be lawfully waved—This right to be waved particularly with respect to the person of the Sovereign, which is sacred and inviolable—Homicide in defence of one's property allowed by the law of nature—How far homicide is permitted by the law of Moses—Self-defence in public war—Not lawful to attack any power solely on account of its increasing greatness—The hostile measures of an aggressor, not to be justified on the plea of self-defence.
Causes of War—Defense of person and property—What counts as justifiable reasons for war—Justifiable reasons for war include defending oneself, recovering one’s property or debts, or punishing wrongdoings—Waging war to protect life is justifiable and lawful—This kind of war is lawful only against an aggressor—The threat must be real and immediate, not fictional—It is lawful to kill anyone trying to harm you or violate your dignity—There are situations where this right may be lawfully set aside—This right is especially to be set aside regarding the person of the Sovereign, which is sacred and inviolable—Killing in defense of one’s property is allowed by natural law—The limitations on killing according to the law of Moses—Self-defense in public conflict—It’s not lawful to attack any power solely because it is becoming stronger—An aggressor’s actions cannot be justified by claiming self-defense.
I. The causes of war by which are meant the justifiable causes, are now to be considered. For in some cases motives of interest operate distinctly from motives of justice. Polybius accurately distinguishes these motives from each other, and from the beginning of the war, or that which gave occasion to the first acts of hostility; as was the case when Ascanius wounded the stag, which gave rise to the war between Turnus and Aeneas. But though there is an actual distinction between the justifiable causes, the pretexts, and the beginning of war; yet the terms used to express them are often confounded. For what we call justifiable causes, Livy, in the speech which he has put into the mouth of the Rhodians, calls beginnings. The Rhodian deputies said, "You Romans profess to believe that your wars are successful, because they are just; nor do you boast so much of their victorious issue, as of the just principles, upon which you make them." In which sense Aelian styles them ἀρχας πολεμων {archas polemôn} and Diodorus Siculus, in speaking of the war of the Lacedaemonians against the Eleans gives them the name of προφασεις {prophaseis} and ἀρχας {archas}.
I. Now let's look at the causes of war, specifically the justifiable ones. In some cases, motives driven by self-interest are clearly separate from those based on justice. Polybius effectively separates these motives, noting both the start of the war and what triggered the initial acts of aggression. For example, when Ascanius wounded the stag, it led to the war between Turnus and Aeneas. Although there is a real difference between justifiable causes, pretexts, and the start of war, the terms used to describe them are often mixed up. What we refer to as justifiable causes, Livy describes in a speech given to the Rhodians as beginnings. The Rhodian deputies said, "You Romans claim that your wars are successful because they are just; you don’t just brag about the victories, but also about the just principles behind them." In this way, Aelian refers to them as Beginnings of wars {archas polemôn}, and Diodorus Siculus, when discussing the war the Lacedaemonians fought against the Eleans, calls them excuses {prophaseis} and ἀρχας {archas}.
74 The principal drift of our argument rests upon these justifiable causes, to which the sentiment of Coriolanus in Dionysius of Halicarnassus, particularly applies, he says, "in the first place, I beseech you to consider how you may find pious and just pretexts for the war." And Demosthenes in his second Olynthiac, makes a similar observation, "I think, says he, that as in a ship, or house, or any other fabric, the lowest parts ought to be the strongest; so in all political measures the motives and pretexts ought to be laid deeply in the principles of truth and justice." The following language of Dion Cassius is no less applicable to the question. "Justice must be made the principal ground of our actions. For with such support there is the best hope of success to our arms. But without that, any point which may be gained for the moment has no firm ground to rest upon." To which may be added, the words of Cicero, who maintains those wars to be unjust, which are made without sufficient cause. And in another place, he reproves Crassus for having intended to pass the Euphrates, when there was no cause of war. Which is no less true of public than of private wars. Hence come the complaints of Seneca, "Why do we restrain homicide, and the murder of individuals, but glory in the crime of slaughter, which destroys whole nations? Avarice and cruelty know not any bounds. By decrees of the Senate, and of the people cruel acts are authorized, and measures, which are pursued by order of the state, are forbidden to individuals." Wars indeed undertaken by public authority are attended with certain effects of right, and have the sanction of opinion in their favour. But they are not the less criminal, when made without just cause. For which reason Alexander was not improperly styled a robber by the Scythian ambassadors, as may be seen in Quintus Curtius. Seneca and Lucan give him the same appellation; the Indian sages call him a madman; and a pirate once presumed to rank him with his own class. Justin speaks of Philip in the same terms, who, says he, in deciding a dispute between two rival kings, stripped both of their dominions with all the treachery and violence of a robber. Augustin has a pertinent remark on this subject. He says, what are unjustly acquired dominions, but the spoils of robbery? In the same strain, Lactantius says, "Men, captivated with the appearances of vain glory, give the names of virtues to their crimes." Injury, or the75 prevention of injury forms the only justifiable cause of war. "And, in the language of the same Augustin, all the evil consequences of war are to be laid at the door of the aggressor." Thus the Roman Herald in a declaration of war makes a solemn appeal against the aggressor, as having violated the laws of nations, and refused proper satisfaction.
74 The main point of our argument is based on these justifiable reasons, which align with Coriolanus's sentiment in Dionysius of Halicarnassus. He says, "First, I urge you to consider how you can find legitimate and just reasons for the war." Similarly, Demosthenes in his second Olynthiac makes a point, saying, "I believe that just like in a ship, house, or any other structure, the foundational parts should be the strongest; thus, in all political actions, the reasons and justifications should be deeply rooted in truth and justice." Dion Cassius's words are also relevant: "Justice must be the primary basis for our actions. Because with such support, there's the best chance of success in our endeavors. But without it, any temporary gain lacks a solid foundation." Cicero adds to this by stating that wars are unjust if waged without sufficient reason. He also criticizes Crassus for wanting to cross the Euphrates when there was no cause for war, which is just as true for public wars as it is for private ones. This leads to Seneca's complaints: "Why do we punish murder and the killing of individuals, yet take pride in the slaughter that annihilates entire nations? Greed and cruelty know no limits. By decrees of the Senate and the people, harsh actions are permitted, while actions taken by individuals are forbidden." Indeed, wars conducted by public authority come with certain legal effects and are supported by public opinion. However, they remain criminal if waged without just cause. This is why Alexander was accurately called a robber by the Scythian ambassadors, as noted in Quintus Curtius. Seneca and Lucan use the same term; Indian sages label him a madman; and a pirate once claimed him as one of their own. Justin describes Philip in similar terms, saying that when he resolved a dispute between two rival kings, he took their lands with all the treachery and violence of a thief. Augustine makes a relevant observation, stating that unjustly taken territories are merely the spoils of robbery. In the same vein, Lactantius notes, "People, captivated by the allure of false glory, label their crimes as virtues." Injury, or the prevention of injury, forms the only justifiable reason for war. "And, in Augustine's words, all the negative consequences of war should be blamed on the aggressor." Thus, the Roman Herald, when declaring war, makes a formal appeal against the aggressor for violating the laws of nations and failing to provide proper restitution. 75
II. The grounds of war are as numerous as those of judicial actions. For where the power of law ceases, there war begins. Now there are methods in law to prevent intended injuries, as well as actions for those actually committed. For CIVIL INJURIES various methods of redress, or prevention are appointed by the law; and by the same power securities are provided to prevent the commission of crimes and misdemeanors. In civil cases, the party aggrieved may recover damages for the injuries sustained; and in crimes, which are offences against the public, the aggressor must submit to actual punishment. Plato, in his ninth book on laws, very properly makes the same distinction, as Homer had done before him.
II. The reasons for war are as varied as those for legal actions. When the power of law ends, war starts. There are legal methods to prevent intended harm, as well as ways to address actions that have already occurred. For Civil Injuries, the law provides various methods of compensation or prevention; the same authorities also offer protections against crimes and misdemeanors. In civil cases, the harmed party can seek damages for the injuries they suffered; in criminal cases, which harm the public, the offender must face consequences. Plato, in his ninth book on laws, rightly makes the same distinction that Homer did before him.
Now reparation or indemnity relates to what either does or did belong to us; which gives rise to real and personal actions. These ascertain our right to the damages, which are our due, either from an agreement, or from an injury received. A right which is termed in law a right by contract, or injury. Crimes, which are offences against society, are prosecuted by indictment, that is by an accusation in the name of the sovereign.
Now, reparation or compensation is connected to what either belongs or used to belong to us; this leads to real and personal legal actions. These determine our right to the damages we deserve, either from an agreement or from a harm we've suffered. This right is known in law as a contractual right or a right arising from injury. Crimes, which are offenses against society, are prosecuted by indictment, meaning they are accused in the name of the state.
The justifiable causes generally assigned for war are three, defence, indemnity, and punishment, all which are comprised in the declaration of Camillus against the Gauls, enumerating all things, which it is right to defend, to recover, and the encroachment on which it is right to punish.
The common reasons given for war are three: defense, compensation, and punishment. These are included in Camillus's declaration against the Gauls, which lists everything that it is just to defend, reclaim, and retaliate against.
There is an omission in this enumeration, unless the word recover be taken in its most extensive sense. For recovering by war what we have lost, includes indemnity for the past, as well as the prosecution of our claim to a debt. Plato has not omitted to notice this distinction, for he has said, "that wars are made to punish not only oppression or robbery, but also fraud and deception." With whom Seneca agrees; for to command payment of what you owe, he calls, "an equitable sentence, stamped with the authority of the law of nations." Indeed the form which was prescribed for the Roman heralds to use in76 declarations of war, bears exactly the same import. For therein the aggressor is charged with having neither given, paid, nor done what was due. Sallust in one of his fragments, has made a Tribune, in his harangue to the people, say, "As a final settlement of all discussions, I demand restitution according to the law of nations."
There’s a missing piece in this list, unless we take the word “recover” to mean something broader. Recovering lost territory through war includes compensation for the past as well as pursuing a claim for a debt. Plato pointed this out, saying that wars are fought not just to punish oppression or theft, but also fraud and deception. Seneca agrees, stating that demanding payment for what you owe is “a fair judgment supported by international law.” In fact, the wording used by Roman heralds in declarations of war conveys the same idea. In those declarations, the aggressor is accused of having neither given, paid, nor done what was owed. In one of his fragments, Sallust has a Tribune address the people, saying, “To settle all disputes, I demand restitution according to international law.”
St. Augustin, in defining those to be just wars, which are made to avenge injuries has taken the word avenge in a general sense of removing and preventing, as well as punishing aggressions. This appears to be his meaning from the following sentence of the passage, in which he does not enumerate the particular acts, which amount to injury, but adds, by way of illustration, that "the state or nation, which has neglected to punish the aggressions of its own subjects, or to make reparation for the losses occasioned by those aggressions, is a proper object of hostility and attack." Prompted by this natural knowledge of right and wrong, the Indian King, as we are informed by Diodorus, accused Semiramis of having commenced war against him without having received any injury. Thus the Romans expostulated with the Senones, that they ought not to attack a people who had given them no provocation. Aristotle in the second book and second chapter of his Analytics, says, war generally is made upon those who have first done an injury. Quintus Curtius describes the Abian Scythians, as the best acquainted with the principles of justice of any of the Barbarians. For they declined having recourse to arms, unless provoked by aggression. A just cause then of war is an injury, which though not actually committed, threatens our persons or property with danger.
St. Augustine, in defining just wars as those fought to avenge injuries, uses the term "avenge" in a broad sense that includes removing and preventing harm, as well as punishing aggressors. This can be understood from the following part of the passage, where he doesn’t list specific acts that count as injuries but states, for example, that "the state or nation that fails to punish the aggressions of its own citizens or to compensate for the losses caused by those aggressions is a valid target for hostility and attack." Prompted by this natural understanding of right and wrong, the Indian king, as reported by Diodorus, accused Semiramis of starting a war against him without any provocation. Similarly, the Romans argued with the Senones that they shouldn’t attack a people who hadn’t provoked them. In the second book and second chapter of his Analytics, Aristotle states that wars are generally waged against those who have first caused an injury. Quintus Curtius describes the Abian Scythians as the most knowledgeable about justice among the Barbarians since they avoided resorting to arms unless provoked by aggression. Therefore, a just cause for war is an injury that, while not yet acted upon, threatens our safety or property.
III. It has already been proved that when our lives are threatened with immediate danger, it is lawful to kill the aggressor, if the danger cannot otherwise be avoided: an instance, as it has been shewn, on which the justice of private war rests. We must observe that this kind of defence derives its origin from the principle of self-preservation, which nature has given to every living creature, and not from the injustice or misconduct of the aggressor. Wherefore though he may be clear of guilt, as for instance a soldier in actual service, mistaking my person for that of another, or a madman in his frenzy, or a man walking in his sleep, none of these cases deprive me of the right of self-defence against those persons. For I am not bound to submit to the danger or77 mischief intended, any more than to expose myself to the attacks of a wild beast.
III. It has already been proven that when our lives are in immediate danger, it is acceptable to kill the aggressor if there’s no other way to avoid the threat. This is the basis for the justice of self-defense. We must note that this type of defense comes from the natural instinct of self-preservation that every living being has, not from the wrongdoing or bad behavior of the aggressor. Therefore, even if the aggressor is not guilty, like a soldier in combat who mistakenly thinks I'm someone else, a person who is insane, or someone who is sleepwalking, none of these situations take away my right to defend myself. I shouldn’t have to accept the danger or harm aimed at me, just like I wouldn’t have to face an attack from a wild animal.
IV. It admits of some doubt, whether those, who unintentionally obstruct our defence, or escape, which are necessary to our preservation, may be lawfully maimed or killed. There are some, even Theologians, who think they may. And, certainly if we look to the law of nature alone, according to its principles, our own preservation should have much more weight with us, than the welfare of society. But the law of charity, especially the evangelical law, which has put our neighbour upon a level with ourselves, does not permit it.
IV. There's some uncertainty about whether people who accidentally interfere with our defense or evade necessary actions for our survival can be justly hurt or killed. Some, including theologians, believe they can. And certainly, if we consider only the law of nature, our own survival should matter more to us than the well-being of society. However, the law of charity, especially the teachings of the gospel, which places our neighbor on the same level as ourselves, doesn't allow for that.
Thomas Aquinas, if taken in a right sense, has justly observed, that in actual self-defence no man can be said to be purposely killed. Indeed, it may some times happen that there is no other way for a person to save himself, than by designedly doing an act, by which the death of an aggressor must inevitably ensue. Yet here the death of any one was not the primary object intended, but employed as the only means of security, which the moment supplied. Still it is better for the party assaulted, if he can safely do it, to repel or disable the aggressor than to shed his blood.
Thomas Aquinas, if understood correctly, has rightly pointed out that in genuine self-defense, no one can be said to be intentionally killed. In fact, there are times when a person may have no other option to protect themselves than to deliberately take an action that will certainly lead to the death of an attacker. However, in this case, the death of anyone was not the main goal intended, but rather a necessary means of ensuring safety in that situation. Still, it is preferable for the person being attacked, if possible, to fend off or incapacitate the attacker rather than to spill their blood.
V. The danger must be immediate, which is one necessary point. Though it must be confessed, that when an assailant seizes any weapon with an apparent intention to kill me I have a right to anticipate and prevent the danger. For in the moral as well as the natural system of things, there is no point without some breadth. But they are themselves much mistaken, and mislead others, who maintain that any degree of fear ought to be a ground for killing another, to prevent his SUPPOSED intention. It is a very just observation made by Cicero in his first book of Offices, that many wrongs proceed from fear; as when the person, who intends to hurt another, apprehends some danger to himself unless he took that method. Clearchus, in Xenophon, says, I have known some men, who partly through misrepresentation, and partly through suspicion, dreading one another, in order to prevent the supposed intentions of their adversaries, have committed the most enormous cruelties against those who neither designed, nor wished them any harm.
V. The danger needs to be immediate, which is one essential point. Although it's true that when someone grabs a weapon with the clear intent to kill me, I have the right to predict and stop the danger. In both moral and natural systems, there’s no situation without some context. However, those who argue that any level of fear justifies killing someone to prevent their *supposed* intent are mistaken and lead others astray. Cicero makes a valid point in his first book of Offices, stating that many wrongs come from fear; for example, when someone planning to harm another feels threatened and believes they need to act first. Clearchus, in Xenophon, mentions that he’s seen people who, due to misunderstandings and suspicions, fearing each other, commit terrible acts against those who neither intended nor wished them any harm to begin with.
Cato in his speech for the Rhodians, says, "Are we to prevent them by doing first, what we say they intended to do to us?" On this subject there is a remarkable78 passage in Aulus Gellius, "When a Gladiator prepares to enter the lists for combat, such is his lot that he must either kill his adversary, or be killed himself. But the life of man is not circumscribed by the hard terms of such an over-ruling necessity, as to oblige him to do an injury to prevent him from receiving one." Quintilian has quoted a passage from Cicero, wherein the orator asks, "Whoever made such a decision, or to whom could such a point be yielded without the most imminent danger, that you have a right to kill the person, by whom you say, you fear that you shall afterwards be killed yourself?" To which this passage of Euripides, may be applied, "If your husband, as you say, intended to have killed you, you ought to have waited, till he actually did make the attempt." Conformably to which Thucydides, in the first book of his history, has expressed himself in the following terms, "The issue of war is uncertain, nor ought we to be so far transported by our fears, as to engage in immediate and open hostilities." The same writer too in his luminous description of the dangerous factions, that had arisen in the Grecian states, condemns the approbation bestowed on the person, that injured or destroyed another from whom he himself apprehended injury or destruction."
Cato, in his speech for the Rhodians, states, "Are we really going to stop them by doing first what we say they planned to do to us?" There's a significant78 point made by Aulus Gellius: "When a gladiator gets ready to fight, he faces a reality where he must either kill his opponent or be killed himself. However, a person's life shouldn't be limited by such a harsh necessity that forces them to do harm just to avoid receiving it." Quintilian quotes Cicero, who asks, "Who made such a decision, or to whom could such a point be conceded without facing serious danger, that you have the right to kill someone because you fear they might later kill you?" This aligns with a quote from Euripides: "If your husband, as you claim, intended to kill you, you should have waited until he actually tried." Similarly, Thucydides, in the first book of his history, expresses, "The outcome of war is uncertain, and we shouldn't let our fears drive us into immediate and open conflict." That same writer also, in his insightful description of the dangerous factions that emerged in the Greek states, criticizes the approval given to anyone who harms or destroys another simply because they fear harm or destruction themselves.
Livy says, "Men, to guard against their alarms, make themselves objects of terror; averting the danger from their own heads, by imposing upon others the necessity of either doing or suffering the evil which they themselves fear." Vibius asked a person, that appeared armed in the forum, "Who gave you permission to shew your fear in this manner?" A question not inapplicable to the present subject, and much commended by Quintilian. Livia also in Dion says, that great infamy redounds to those, who by anticipation perpetrate the criminal act, which they fear.
Livy says, "People, trying to protect themselves from their fears, make themselves terrifying; they push the danger away from themselves by forcing others to either face or endure the threat they dread." Vibius asked someone who looked armed in the forum, "Who gave you the right to show your fear like this?" This question relates well to the current topic and is highly praised by Quintilian. Livia also mentions in Dion that there is great shame for those who commit the crime they fear in advance.
Now if any one intend no immediate violence, but is found to have formed a conspiracy to destroy me by assassination, or poison, or by false accusation, perjury, or suborned witnesses, I have no right to kill him. For my knowledge of the danger may prevent it. Or even if it were evident that I could not avoid the danger without killing him; this would not establish my right to do so. For there is every presumption that my knowing it will lead me to apply for the legal remedies of prevention.
Now, if anyone plans no immediate violence but is found to have conspired to harm me through assassination, poison, false accusations, perjury, or hired witnesses, I have no right to kill them. My awareness of the danger might prevent it. Even if it were clear that I couldn't avoid the danger without killing them, that still wouldn’t give me the right to do so. There’s every reason to believe that my knowledge of the situation will prompt me to seek legal ways to stop it.
79 VI. and VII. The next thing to be considered is, what must be said upon the mutilation of a limb. Now, as the loss of a limb, especially that of a principal limb in the body, is a grievous detriment, and nearly equal to the loss of life, to which may be added the probability of death ensuing from such a calamity; the lawfulness of killing any one, who makes such an attempt, if the danger cannot otherwise be avoided, scarce admits of a doubt. Neither is there any more difficulty in allowing the same right for the personal defence of chastity, the preservation of which, both in the common estimation of men, and by the divine law, is deemed of equal value with life itself. We have an example of this in Cicero, Quintilian, and Plutarch, in the person of one of Marius's tribunes, who was killed by a soldier. Among the actions of women, who have defended themselves, Heliodorus records that of Heraclea, which he calls a just defence of her injured honour.
79 VI. and VII. The next thing to consider is what needs to be said about the mutilation of a limb. The loss of a limb, especially a major one, is a serious disadvantage that is almost as severe as losing a life, and there's also the potential for death that can result from such an injury. So, it's generally accepted that killing someone who attempts this, if there's no other way to avoid the danger, is justifiable. The same principle applies to defending one’s chastity, which is regarded as equally valuable as life itself, both in public opinion and by divine law. For example, Cicero, Quintilian, and Plutarch mention a case involving one of Marius's tribunes who was killed by a soldier. Among the stories of women who have defended themselves, Heliodorus notes the case of Heraclea, which he describes as a rightful defense of her honor.
VIII. Though some, as it has been already said, admit the lawfulness of killing the person, who attempts with open violence to destroy one's life, yet they deem it more commendable to spare the life of another, even at the hazard of one's own. Yet to persons, in whose preservation the public interest is involved, they will grant an exemption from this rule of forbearance. Indeed it seems unsafe to impose upon ANY, whose lives are of importance to others, a rule of forebearance so contrary to all the principles of all law. This exemption therefore must be allowed to all vested with any public office, which makes them responsible for the safety of others; as the generals who conduct armies, or the rulers of the state, and many others in similar situations; to whom may be applied the lines of Lucan—"When the lives and safety of so many nations depend upon yours, and so great a portion of the world has chosen you for its head; it is cruelty to expose yourself wilfully to death."
VIII. Although some, as mentioned earlier, believe it’s acceptable to kill someone who violently tries to take your life, they think it’s even more admirable to spare another person’s life, even if it puts your own at risk. However, for individuals whose safety is tied to the public good, they will allow an exception to this rule of restraint. In fact, it seems unsafe to impose a rule of restraint on anyone whose life is significant to others, as it contradicts the basic principles of all laws. Therefore, this exception must apply to anyone in a public position responsible for the safety of others; like generals leading armies or state leaders, and many others in similar roles. This is where the lines of Lucan come into play—“When the lives and safety of so many nations depend upon yours, and so large a part of the world has chosen you as its leader; it is cruel to willingly put yourself in danger of death.”
IX. On the other hand it may happen, that the aggressor may be one whose person is rendered sacred and inviolable by all divine, human, and natural laws; which is the case with respect to the person of the Sovereign. For the law of nature regards not only the principles of STRICT JUSTICE, but comprises other virtues also, as temperance, fortitude, and discretion, making the observance of them in certain cases, binding as well as honourable.80 To observe these we are bound also by the law of charity.
IX. On the other hand, it may happen that the aggressor is someone whose person is considered sacred and untouchable by all divine, human, and natural laws; this applies to the Sovereign. The law of nature doesn’t just concern itself with the principles of Fair Justice, but also includes other virtues like temperance, courage, and discretion, making the adherence to them in certain situations both obligatory and honorable.80 We are also obligated to observe these by the law of charity.
Nor is the truth of this argument at all weakened by what Vasquez has advanced, who maintains that the Sovereign who attempts the life of an individual loses, in reality, the character of Sovereign: a doctrine fraught with equal absurdity and danger. For sovereignty cannot any more than property be forfeited by any particular act of delinquency; unless it has been previously and expressly so enacted by the fundamental laws of the state. For such a rule of forfeiture, which would be productive of universal anarchy and confusion, never has been, nor ever will be established among any civilized people. For the maxim, "that all government is framed for the benefit of the subject and not of the Sovereign," which Vasquez and many other writers lay down as a fundamental law, though it may be generally true in theory, is by no means applicable to the question. For a thing loses not its existence, by losing some part of its utility. Nor is there sufficient consistency in his observation, that every individual desires the safety of the commonwealth on his own account, and therefore every one ought to prefer his own safety to that of the whole state. For we wish for the public welfare not on our own account alone, but also for the sake of others.
The truth of this argument is not weakened at all by what Vasquez claims, which is that a Sovereign who tries to take someone's life actually stops being a Sovereign. That idea is both absurd and dangerous. Sovereignty, like property, can't be lost due to any single wrongful act unless it's specifically laid out previously in the fundamental laws of the state. Such a rule about losing sovereignty would lead to total chaos and confusion, and this has never been and will never be accepted among any civilized people. The principle that "all government exists for the benefit of the subject and not the Sovereign," which Vasquez and others state as a fundamental law, may be generally true in theory, but it doesn't apply to this issue. Just because something loses part of its usefulness doesn’t mean it ceases to exist. Also, his point that everyone wants the safety of the state for their own sake, and therefore everyone should prioritize their own safety over that of the entire state, lacks enough consistency. We desire public welfare not just for ourselves but also for others.
The opinion of those who think that friendship arises from necessity alone, is rejected as false, by the more sound Philosophers; as we feel a spontaneous and natural inclination towards friendly intercourse. Charity indeed often persuades, and in some instances commands us to prefer the good of many to our own single advantage. To which the following passage from Seneca is very applicable. "It is not surprising that princes, and kings, or whatever name the guardians of the public welfare may bear, should be loved with a veneration and affection, far beyond those of private friendship. For all men of sober judgment, and enlarged information deem the public interest of higher moment than their own. Their attachment therefore must be warmest to the person on whom the well being and prosperity of the state depends." And to the same effect, St. Ambrose in his third book of Offices, says, "every man feels a greater delight in averting public than private danger." Seneca, the writer already quoted, produces two instances, the one of Callistratus at Athens, and the other of Rutilius at Rome,81 who refused to be restored from banishment thinking it better for two individuals to suffer hardship, than for the public to be plunged into calamities.
The viewpoint of those who believe that friendship only comes from necessity is dismissed as incorrect by more reasonable philosophers; we experience a spontaneous and natural desire for friendship. Kindness often encourages us, and sometimes even compels us, to prioritize the welfare of many over our own individual benefit. This aligns well with a quote from Seneca: "It's not surprising that princes and kings, or whatever title the protectors of public welfare hold, should be loved with a reverence and affection that surpasses private friendship. For all people of sound judgment and broad knowledge consider the public good to be more important than their own. Therefore, their strongest loyalty is to the person on whom the well-being and success of the state relies." Similarly, St. Ambrose in his third book of Offices states, "every person feels more joy in preventing public danger than private danger." Seneca, the writer previously mentioned, gives two examples: one of Callistratus in Athens and the other of Rutilius in Rome,81 who declined to return from exile, believing it was better for two individuals to endure hardship than for the public to face disasters.
XI.15 The next object to be considered, relates to injuries affecting our property. In strict justice, it cannot be denied that we have a right to kill a robber, if such a step is inevitably necessary to the preservation of our property. For the difference between the value of life and property is overbalanced by the horror which a robber excites, and by the favourable inclination felt by all men towards the injured and innocent. From whence it follows, that regarding that right alone, a robber may be wounded or killed in his flight with the property, if it cannot otherwise be recovered. Demosthenes in his speech against Aristocrates, exclaims, "By all that is sacred, is it not a dreadful and open violation of law, not only of written law, but of that law which is the unwritten rule of all men, to be debarred from the right of using force against the robber as well as against the enemy; who is plundering your property?" Nor is it forbidden by the precepts of charity, apart from all consideration of divine and human law, unless where the property is of little value, and beneath notice; an exception, which some writers have very properly added.
XI.15 The next issue to discuss involves injuries to our property. It’s clear that we have the right to kill a robber if it's absolutely necessary to protect our property. The value of life and property doesn't compare to the fear a robber brings and the sympathy people feel for the innocent victim. Therefore, based purely on that right, a robber can be injured or even killed while escaping with stolen goods if there's no other way to get the property back. Demosthenes, in his speech against Aristocrates, declares, "By all that is sacred, is it not a horrific and blatant violation of the law, both written and the unwritten laws recognized by all, to be denied the right to use force against a robber as well as against an enemy who is stealing your property?" Furthermore, it is not against the principles of charity, aside from all considerations of divine and human law, unless the property involved has little value and is not worth mentioning; an exception that some writers have rightly noted.
XII. The sense of the Jewish law on this point is now to be considered. The old law of Solon, to which Demosthenes, in his speech against Timocrates, appeals, agrees with it. From hence the substance of the Twelve Tables, and Plato's maxim in his ninth book of laws were taken. For they all agree in making a distinction between a thief who steals by day, and the robber, who commits the act by night; though they differ about the REASON of this distinction. Some think this distinction arises from the difficulty of discerning by night, whether an aggressor comes with an intent to murder or steal, and therefore he ought to be treated as an assassin. Others think the distinction is made, because as it is difficult to know the person of the thief, there is less probability of recovering the goods. In neither case do the framers of laws seem to have considered the question in its proper light. Their evident intention is to prohibit the killing of any one, merely on account82 of our property; which would happen, for instance, by killing a thief in his flight in order to recover the goods he had stolen. But if our own lives are endangered, then we are allowed to avert the danger, even at the hazard of another's life. Nor is our having run into the danger any objection; provided it was done to preserve or to recover our goods, or to take the thief. For no imputation of guilt can attach to us in any of these cases, while we are employed in doing a lawful act, nor can it be said that we are doing wrong to another by exercising our own right.
XII. Now let's consider what the Jewish law says about this issue. The ancient law of Solon, which Demosthenes refers to in his speech against Timocrates, aligns with it. This is where the core ideas of the Twelve Tables and Plato's principle in his ninth book of laws come from. They all differentiate between a thief who steals during the day and a robber who commits the act at night, although they vary in their reasoning for this distinction. Some believe this difference comes from the challenge of determining at night whether an attacker intends to harm or steal, so they argue the attacker should be treated as a potential murderer. Others feel the distinction is made because it's harder to identify the thief, making it less likely to recover stolen items. In neither instance do the lawmakers appear to have considered the issue fully. It's clear that their intention is to prevent the killing of anyone solely for the sake of our property, which could happen, for instance, if we killed a fleeing thief in order to retrieve the items he'd taken. However, if our own lives are at risk, we are allowed to protect ourselves, even at the cost of another's life. Additionally, it does not matter if we put ourselves in danger as long as it was to safeguard or reclaim our belongings, or to apprehend the thief. In any of these situations, we can't be blamed for acting lawfully, nor can it be said that we're wronging someone else by exercising our rights.
The difference therefore made between a thief in the night and a thief in the day, arises from the difficulty of procuring sufficient evidence of the fact. So that if a thief is found killed, the person who says, that he was found by him with a destructive weapon, and killed by him in his own defence, will easily gain belief. For the Jewish law supposes this, when it treats of a thief in the act of piercing, or, as some translate it, with a stabbing instrument. This interpretation accords with the law of the twelve tables, which forbids any one to kill a thief in the day time, except he defend himself with a weapon. The presumption therefore against a thief in the night is that he defended himself in such a manner. Now the term weapon comprehends not only an instrument of iron, but as Caius interprets this law, a club, or a stone. Ulpian on the other hand, speaking of a thief taken in the night, says that the person who kills him will incur no guilt, provided that in saving his property he could not spare his life, without endangering his own. There is a presumption, as it has been already observed, in favour of the person who has killed a thief taken in the night. But if there be evidence to prove, that the life of the person who killed the thief was in no danger; then the presumption in his favour fails, and the act amounts to murder.
The difference between a thief at night and a thief during the day comes from how hard it is to get enough proof of what happened. So, if a thief is found dead, the person claiming he was confronted with a deadly weapon and killed him in self-defense is likely to be believed. Jewish law assumes this when discussing a thief caught in the act of breaking in, or as some translate it, with a stabbing tool. This interpretation aligns with the law of the Twelve Tables, which prohibits someone from killing a thief during the day unless that person is defending themselves with a weapon. Thus, the assumption against a thief at night is that he defended himself in that way. The term weapon includes not just an iron tool, but also, as Caius explains, a club or a stone. Ulpian, on the other hand, talking about a thief caught at night, states that the person who kills him won't be guilty as long as, in protecting their property, they couldn't spare the thief's life without risking their own. There is a presumption, as mentioned before, in favor of someone who kills a thief caught at night. However, if there is evidence showing that the life of the person who killed the thief was not in danger, then that presumption fails and the act is considered murder.
The law of the twelve tables indeed required, that the person who took a thief either in the day time, or in the night, should make a noise that, if possible, the magistrates or neighbours might assemble to assist him and give evidence. But as such a concourse could more easily be assembled in the day time than in the night, as Ulpian observes upon the passage before quoted from Demosthenes, the affirmation of a person declaring the danger he was in during the night is more readily believed. To83 which an additional observation may be made, that, even under equal circumstances, the danger which happens by night can be less examined, and ascertained, and therefore is the more terrible. The Jewish law therefore, no less than the Roman, acting upon the same principle of tenderness forbids us to kill any one, who has taken our goods, unless for the preservation of our own lives.
The law of the Twelve Tables required that anyone who caught a thief, whether during the day or at night, should make noise so that, if possible, the magistrates or neighbors could come to help and give witness. However, as Ulpian notes in reference to a quote from Demosthenes, it's easier to gather a crowd during the day than at night, which makes someone's claim of danger at night more credible. Additionally, it's worth noting that even under the same conditions, danger at night can be harder to investigate and understand, making it feel more frightening. Therefore, Jewish law, just like Roman law, operates on the same principle of compassion and prohibits us from killing someone who has taken our belongings, unless it is to protect our own lives.
XVI.16 What has been already said of the right of defending our persons and property, though regarding chiefly private war, may nevertheless be applied to public hostilities, allowing for the difference of circumstances. For private war may be considered as an instantaneous exercise of natural right, which ceases the moment that legal redress can be obtained. Now as public war can never take place, but where judicial remedies cease to exist, it is often protracted, and the spirit of hostility inflamed by the continued accession of losses and injuries. Besides, private war extends only to self-defence, whereas sovereign powers have a right not only to avert, but to punish wrongs. From whence they are authorised to prevent a remote as well as an immediate aggression. Though the suspicion of hostile intentions, on the part of another power, may not justify the commencement of actual war, yet it calls for measures of armed prevention, and will authorise indirect hostility. Points, which will be discussed in another place.
XVI.16 What’s already been said about the right to defend our lives and property, while mainly concerning private conflict, can also apply to public warfare, taking into account the differences in circumstances. Private conflict can be seen as an immediate exercise of natural rights that ends as soon as legal remedies are available. Since public war only happens when legal remedies have failed, it often lasts longer and is fueled by ongoing losses and injuries. Additionally, private conflict is limited to self-defense, but sovereign powers have the right not just to prevent harm but also to punish wrongs. Therefore, they are authorized to stop both immediate and distant threats. Although merely suspecting hostile intentions from another power doesn’t justify starting a war, it does require preventive military measures and can legitimize indirect hostilities. These points will be discussed further elsewhere.
XVII. Some writers have advanced a doctrine which can never be admitted, maintaining that the law of nations authorises one power to commence hostilities against another, whose increasing greatness awakens her alarms. As a matter of expediency such a measure may be adopted, but the principles of justice can never be advanced in its favour. The causes which entitle a war to the denomination of just are somewhat different from those of expediency alone. But to maintain that the bare probability of some remote, or future annoyance from a neighbouring state affords a just ground of hostile aggression, is a doctrine repugnant to every principle of equity. Such however is the condition of human life, that no full security can be enjoyed. The only protection against uncertain fears must be sought, not from violence, but from the divine providence, and defensive precaution.
XVII. Some writers have put forward an argument that can never be accepted, claiming that international law allows one nation to start conflict against another whose growing power raises alarm. While such a move might be seen as practical, the principles of justice do not support it. The reasons that justify a war as "just" differ from those based solely on practicality. However, to suggest that merely the possibility of some distant or future threat from a neighboring country justifies aggressive action is a belief that contradicts every principle of fairness. Yet, such is the nature of human life that complete security is unattainable. The only defense against uncertain fears must be sought not through violence, but through divine guidance and defensive measures.
XVIII. There is another opinion, not more admissible,84 maintaining that the hostile acts of an aggressor, may be considered in the light of defensive measures, because, say the advocates of this opinion, few people are content to proportion their revenge to the injuries they have received; bounds which in all probability the party aggrieved has exceeded, and therefore in return becomes himself the aggressor. Now the excess of retaliation cannot, any more than the fear of uncertain danger, give a colour of right to the first aggression, which may be illustrated by the case of a malefactor, who can have no right to wound or kill the officers of justice in their attempts to take him, urging as a plea that he feared the punishment would exceed the offense.
XVIII. There’s another perspective, which isn’t really acceptable,84 suggesting that the aggressive actions of an attacker could be seen as defensive measures because, as supporters of this view argue, few people actually manage to keep their retaliation proportional to the harm they have suffered. Often, the person who has been wronged goes beyond reasonable limits, thereby becoming an aggressor themselves. However, this excess in revenge, like the fear of an uncertain threat, doesn’t justify the initial aggression, similar to how a criminal has no right to injure or kill law enforcement officers trying to apprehend them, arguing that they fear the punishment would be harsher than their crime.
The first step, which an aggressor ought to take, should be an offer of indemnity to the injured party, by the arbitration of some independent and disinterested state. And if this mediation be rejected, then his war assumes the character of a just war. Thus Hezekiah when he had not stood to the engagements made by his ancestors, being threatened with an attack from the King of Assyria on that account, acknowledged his fault, and left it to the King to assign what penalty he should pay for the offence. After he had done so, finding himself again attacked, relying on the justice of his cause, he opposed the enemy, and succeeded by the favour of God. Pontius the Samnite, after restoration of the prizes had been made to the Romans, and the promoter of the war delivered up into their hands, said, "We have now averted the wrath of heaven, which our violation of treaties had provoked. But the supreme being who was pleased to reduce us to the necessity of restoration, was not equally pleased with the pride of the Romans, who rejected our offer. What farther satisfaction do we owe to the Romans, or to Heaven, the arbiter of treaties? We do not shrink from submitting the measure of YOUR resentment, or of OUR punishment to the judgment of any people, or any individual." In the same manner, when the Thebans had offered the most equitable terms to the Lacedaemonians, who still rose higher in their demands, Aristides says, that the justice of the cause changed sides and passed from the Lacedaemonians to the Thebans.
The first step an aggressor should take is to offer compensation to the injured party, through the mediation of an independent and unbiased state. If this mediation is rejected, then their war is considered just. For example, Hezekiah, when he did not uphold the commitments made by his ancestors and was threatened with an attack from the King of Assyria for that reason, admitted his wrongdoing and let the King decide what penalty he should face for the offense. After doing this, when he found himself attacked again, trusting in the justice of his case, he fought back against the enemy and succeeded with God's support. Pontius the Samnite, after the Romans had been compensated for the wrongs done to them and the instigator of the war had been handed over, stated, "We have now averted the wrath of heaven that our breach of treaties had provoked. But the supreme being who required us to restore what was lost was not equally pleased with the Romans, who rejected our offer. What further satisfaction do we owe to the Romans or to Heaven, the judge of treaties? We are not afraid to leave the measure of YOUR resentment or OUR punishment to the judgment of any people or individual." Similarly, when the Thebans presented the most fair terms to the Lacedaemonians, who continued to raise their demands, Aristides noted that the justice of the situation shifted from the Lacedaemonians to the Thebans.
CHAPTER II.
The Fundamental Rights of Things.
The general rights of things—Division of what is our own—The origin and progress of property—Some things impossible to be made the subject of property—The Sea of this nature, in its full extent, or in its principal parts—Unoccupied lands may become the property of individuals, unless they have been previously occupied by the people at large—Wild beasts, fishes, birds, may become the property of him who seizes them—In cases of necessity men have a right of using that which has already become the property of others—To sanction this indulgence, the necessity must be such that it cannot otherwise be avoided—This indulgence not allowed where the possessor is in an equal degree of necessity—The party thus supplying his wants from another's property, bound to make restitution whenever it is possible. The application of this principle to the practice of war—The right to use the property of another, provided that use be no way prejudicial to the owner—Hence the right to the use of running water—The right of passing through countries, and by rivers explained—An inquiry into the right of imposing duties on merchandise—The right of residing for a time in a foreign state—The right of exiles to reside in the dominions of a foreign state, provided they submit to its laws—In what manner the right of occupying waste places is to be understood—The right to certain articles necessary to the support of human society, and life—The general right of purchasing those articles at a reasonable price—The right to sell, not of equal force and extent—The right to those privileges which are promiscuously granted to foreigners—Inquiry whether it be lawful to contract with any people for the purchase of their productions on condition of their not selling the same to others.
The general rights regarding ownership—How we divide what belongs to us—The origins and growth of property—Certain things that cannot be owned—The sea in this context, whether entirely or in its major parts—Unclaimed land can be taken by individuals unless it's already claimed by the community—Wild animals, fish, and birds can belong to whoever catches them—In emergencies, people can use what belongs to others—This use must be absolutely necessary—This allowance doesn’t apply if the owner is in a similar situation of need—The person who takes from another's property must compensate whenever possible. This principle is also relevant in the context of war—The right to use someone else's property as long as it doesn’t harm the owner—This includes the right to use flowing water—The right to cross lands and rivers is clarified—An exploration into the right to impose taxes on goods—The right to stay in another country temporarily—The right of exiles to live in a foreign country as long as they abide by its laws—How the right to occupy uninhabited lands should be understood—The right to essential goods for human society and life—The general right to purchase those goods at a reasonable price—The right to sell is not as strong or extensive—The right to privileges typically granted to foreigners—An investigation into whether it’s acceptable to agree with any group to purchase their goods on the condition that they don’t sell them to others.
I. Among the causes assigned to justify war, we may reckon the commission of injury, particularly such as affects any thing which belongs to us. Now we establish this claim to any thing as our own either by a right COMMON to us as men, or acquired by us in our INDIVIDUAL capacity. But to begin with that which is the common right of all mankind; we may observe that it comprises what is called by legal authorities, Corporeal and Incorporeal rights.17
I. Among the reasons given to justify war, we can include the act of causing harm, especially when it affects something that belongs to us. We claim ownership of something either through a right that we all share as human beings or through what we have acquired individually. To start with the common right of all humanity, we see that it includes what legal authorities refer to as corporeal and incorporeal rights.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
86 Things corporeal are either unappropriated, or made the subjects of private property. Now the things unappropriated, are such that it may be either possible or impossible for them to be reduced to a state of private property.18 In order therefore to understand this more clearly, it will be necessary to take a survey of the origin of property.
86 Physical things are either unowned or have been claimed as private property. The unowned things are those that can either potentially be owned or cannot be turned into private property at all. To understand this better, we need to look at the origins of property.
II. God gave to mankind in general, dominion over all the creatures of the earth, from the first creation of the world; a grant which was renewed upon the restoration of the world after the deluge. All things, as Justin says, formed a common stock for all mankind, as the inheritors of one general patrimony. From hence it happened, that every man seized to his own use or consumption whatever he met with; a general exercise of a right, which supplied the place of private property. So that to deprive any one of what he had thus seized, became an act of injustice. Which Cicero has explained in his third book, on the bounds of good and evil, by comparing the world to a Theatre, in which the seats are common property, yet every spectator claims that which he occupies, for the time being, as his own. A state of affairs, which could not subsist but in the greatest simplicity of manners, and under the mutual forbearance and good-will of mankind. An example of a community of goods, arising from extreme simplicity of manners, may be seen in some nations of America, who for many ages have subsisted in this manner without inconvenience. The Essenes of old, furnished an example of men actuated by mutual affection and holding all things in common, a practice adopted by the primitive Christians at Jerusalem, and87 still prevailing among some of the religious orders. Man at his first origin, requiring no clothing, afforded a proof of the simplicity of manners in which he had been formed. Yet perhaps, as Justin says of the Scythians, he might be considered as ignorant of vice rather than acquainted with virtue; Tacitus says, that in the early ages of the world, men lived free from the influence of evil passions, without reproach, and wickedness; and consequently without the restraints of punishment. In primitive times there appeared among mankind, according to Macrobius, a simplicity, ignorant of evil, and inexperienced in craft: a simplicity which in the book of Wisdom seems to be called integrity, and by the Apostle Paul simplicity in opposition to subtilty. Their sole employment was the worship of God, of which the tree of life was the symbol, as it is explained by the ancient Hebrews, whose opinion is confirmed by the Book of Revelation.
II. God gave humanity dominion over all the creatures of the earth from the very beginning of the world; a gift that was reaffirmed after the world was restored following the flood. Everything, as Justin states, was part of a common resource for everyone, as inheritors of a shared legacy. This led to individuals taking whatever they came across for their own use or consumption; a collective exercise of a right that acted as a substitute for private property. Therefore, taking away what someone had taken for themselves became an act of injustice. Cicero illustrated this in his third book on the nature of good and evil, likening the world to a theater where the seats are communal property, yet each viewer claims what they occupy as their own, for that moment. Such a situation could only exist under the highest simplicity of behavior and through mutual respect and goodwill among people. An example of shared resources stemming from this extreme simplicity can be found in certain tribes in America, who have lived this way for many generations without issues. The Essenes of old serve as an example of individuals motivated by mutual affection and sharing everything, a practice also adopted by the early Christians in Jerusalem, and still seen in some religious orders today. At first, man needed no clothing, which illustrated the simplicity of the nature in which he was created. Yet, as Justin notes about the Scythians, he might be seen as simply unaware of vice rather than truly knowing virtue. Tacitus wrote that in early times, humans lived free from corrupting passions, without blame and wickedness; thus, they were also free from the need for punishment. In ancient times, there existed among people, as Macrobius points out, a simplicity that was unaware of evil and unskilled in deceit: a simplicity that the Book of Wisdom refers to as integrity, and which the Apostle Paul calls simplicity in contrast to craftiness. Their only focus was the worship of God, symbolized by the tree of life, as explained by the ancient Hebrews, an idea supported by the Book of Revelation.
Men at that period subsisted upon the spontaneous productions of the ground: a state of simplicity to which they did not long adhere, but applied themselves to the invention of various arts, indicated by the tree of knowledge of good and evil, that is the knowledge of those things which may be either used properly, or abused; which Philo calls a middle kind of wisdom. In this view, Solomon says, God hath created men upright, that is, in simplicity, but they have sought out many inventions, or, in the language of Philo, they have inclined to subtilty. In the sixth oration of Dion Prusaeensis it is said, "the descendants have degenerated from the innocence of primitive times, contriving many subtile inventions no way conducive to the good of life; and using their strength not to promote justice, but to gratify their appetites." Agriculture and pasturage seem to have been the most ancient pursuits, which characterized the first brothers. Some distribution of things would necessarily follow these different states; and we are informed by holy writ, that the rivalry thus created ended in murder. At length men increasing in wickedness by their evil communications with each other, the race of Giants, that is of strong and violent men appeared, whom the Greeks denominate by a title, signifying those who make their own hands and strength the measure of justice.
Men during that time lived off the natural resources of the land: a simple way of life they didn’t stick to for long, as they turned to creating various skills and crafts, symbolized by the tree of knowledge of good and evil, representing the understanding of things that can be used correctly or misused; a concept Philo describes as a middle form of wisdom. In this regard, Solomon mentions that God made men upright, meaning simple, but they have pursued many inventions, or, in Philo's terms, they have leaned toward cleverness. In the sixth speech of Dion Prusaeensis, it is noted, "the descendants have fallen from the innocence of early times, inventing many clever creations that do nothing to enhance life; using their strength not to advance justice, but to satisfy their desires." Farming and herding seem to have been the earliest activities that defined the first brothers. Some form of distribution of resources would naturally arise from these different states; and the scriptures inform us that the competition this created led to murder. Eventually, as men grew more wicked due to their corrupt interactions with one another, the race of Giants emerged, referring to strong and violent individuals, whom the Greeks called by a term meaning those who define justice through their own strength and power.
The world in progress of time being cleared of this race by the deluge, the savage was succeeded by a softer and more sensual way of life, to which the use of wine88 proved subservient, being followed by all the evil consequences of intoxication. But the greatest breach in the harmony of men was made by ambition, which is considered in some measure, as the offspring of a noble mind. Its first and most eminent effects appeared in the attempt to raise the tower of Babel; the failure of which caused the dispersion of mankind, who took possession of different parts of the earth.
The world, over time, moved past this race because of the flood, and the savage lifestyle was replaced by a softer, more indulgent way of living, which included the use of wine88 that led to all the negative results of drunkenness. However, the biggest disruption in human harmony came from ambition, which is seen as somewhat the product of a noble mind. Its most significant early impact was the attempt to build the Tower of Babel; the failure of this project resulted in the scattering of humanity, who then settled in different parts of the earth.
Still after this a community of lands for pasture, though not of flocks, prevailed among men. For the great extent of land was sufficient for the use of all occupants, as yet but few in number, without their incommoding each other. In the words of the Poet, it was deemed unlawful to fix a land mark on the plain, or to apportion it out in stated limits. But as men increased in numbers and their flocks in the same proportion, they could no longer with convenience enjoy the use of lands in common, and it became necessary to divide them into allotments for each family. Now in the hot countries of the East, wells would be objects of great importance, for the refreshment of their herds and flocks; so that in order to avoid strife and inconvenience, all would be anxious to have them as possessions of their own. These accounts we derive from sacred history, and they are found to agree with the opinions maintained upon this subject by Philosophers and Poets, who have described the community of goods, that prevailed in the early state of the world, and the distribution of property which afterwards took place. Hence a notion may be formed of the reason why men departed from the primaeval state of holding all things in common, attaching the ideas of property, first to moveable and next to immoveable things.
Even after this, there was still a shared community of land for grazing, though not for flocks, among people. The vast amount of land available was enough for all the users, as there were still only a few of them, so they didn't interfere with one another. As the Poet put it, it was considered wrong to set a boundary in the open field or to divide it into fixed sections. However, as the population grew and their livestock increased at the same rate, they could no longer conveniently share the land, making it necessary to divide it into sections for each family. In the hot regions of the East, wells were extremely important for watering their herds and flocks, so to avoid conflict and difficulties, everyone wanted to claim them as their own. We get this information from sacred history, and it aligns with what Philosophers and Poets have said about the shared ownership that existed in the early days of the world, and the later division of property. This gives us an idea of why people moved away from the original state of sharing everything, starting with movable property and then extending that idea to immovable property.
When the inhabitants of the earth began to acquire a taste for more delicate fare than the spontaneous productions of the ground, and to look for more commodious habitations than caves, or the hollow of trees, and to long for more elegant cloathing than the skins of wild beasts, industry became necessary to supply those wants, and each individual began to apply his attention to some particular art. The distance of the places too, into which men were dispersed, prevented them from carrying the fruits of the earth to a common stock, and in the next place, the WANT of just principle and equitable kindness would destroy that equality which ought to subsist both89 in the labour of producing and consuming the necessaries of life.
When people on Earth started to prefer more refined food than what could be found naturally, looked for better living spaces than caves or tree hollows, and desired more stylish clothing than animal skins, they needed to work to meet these desires. Each person began to focus on a specific skill. The distance between the places where people lived made it hard for them to share the earth's resources, and on top of that, the lack of fairness and kindness would undermine the equality that should exist in both producing and consuming the essentials of life.
At the same time, we learn how things passed from being held in common to a state of property. It was not by the act of the mind alone that this change took place. For men in that case could never know, what others intended to appropriate to their own use, so as to exclude the claim of every other pretender to the same; and many too might desire to possess the same thing. Property therefore must have been established either by express agreement, as by division, or by tacit consent, as by occupancy. For as soon as it was found inconvenient to hold things in common, before any division of lands had been established, it is natural to suppose it must have been generally agreed, that whatever any one had occupied should be accounted his own. Cicero, in the third book of his Offices says, it is admitted as an universal maxim, not repugnant to the principles of natural law, that every one should rather wish himself to enjoy the necessaries of life, than leave them for the acquisition of another. Which is supported by Quintilian, who says, if the condition of life be such, that whatever has fallen to the private use of any individual, becomes the property of such holder, it is evidently unjust to take away any thing which is possessed by such a right. And the ancients in styling Ceres a law-giver, and giving the name of Thesmophoria to her sacred rights, meant by this to signify that the division of lands had given birth to a new kind of right.
At the same time, we learn how things transitioned from being shared to becoming private property. This change didn’t happen solely through thought. If that were the case, people wouldn’t be able to know what others intended to claim for themselves, which would prevent anyone from excluding others who also wanted the same thing. Many might want to possess the same item. Therefore, property must have been established by either explicit agreement, like through division, or by implied consent, like through taking possession. As soon as it became inconvenient to hold things in common, before any land division had been established, it’s reasonable to think there was a general agreement that anything someone occupied would be considered their own. Cicero, in the third book of his Offices, states that it’s widely accepted as a fundamental principle, not conflicting with natural law, that everyone would prefer to enjoy the necessities of life rather than give them up for someone else’s gain. This is echoed by Quintilian, who argues that if the state of life is such that whatever someone privately uses becomes their property, it’s clearly unjust to take anything from that rightful owner. The ancients referred to Ceres as a law-giver and called her sacred rights Thesmophoria, which indicated that the division of lands led to the creation of a new type of right.
III. Notwithstanding the statements above made, it must be admitted that some things are impossible to be reduced to a state of property, of which the Sea affords us an instance both in its general extent, and in its principal branches. But as some are willing to make this concession with regard to individuals, but not with regard to nations, the position advanced in the beginning of this section may be proved from the following moral argument, that as in this case the reason no longer subsists why men should hold all things in common, the practice ceases also. For the magnitude of the sea is such, as to be sufficient for the use of all nations, to allow them without inconvenience and prejudice to each other the right of fishing, sailing, or any other advantage which that element affords. The same may be said of air as common property, except that no one can use or90 enjoy it, without at the same time using the ground over which it passes or rests. So that the amusement of fowling cannot be followed, except by permission, without trespassing upon the lands of some owner, over which the birds fly.
III. Despite the statements made above, it must be acknowledged that some things cannot be owned, with the Sea serving as an example both in its vastness and in its main branches. However, while some people are willing to accept this for individuals, they refuse to do so for nations. The argument presented at the start of this section can be explained with the following moral reasoning: since there is no longer a valid reason for people to share everything, the practice stops as well. The size of the sea is such that it can provide for all nations, allowing them to fish, sail, or access any other benefits it offers without causing inconvenience or harm to one another. The same can be said about air as shared property, except that no one can utilize or enjoy it without also making use of the land it passes over or rests on. Therefore, hunting birds cannot happen without permission, as it would involve trespassing on someone else's land where the birds fly.
The same appellation of COMMON may be given to the sand of the shore, which being incapable of cultivation, is left free to yield its inexhaustible supplies for the use of all.
The same label of Standard can be applied to the sand on the beach, which, since it can't be farmed, is available for everyone to use its endless resources.
There is a natural reason also, which renders the sea, considered in the view already taken, incapable of being made property: because occupancy can never subsist, but in things that can be confined to certain permanent bounds. From whence Thucydides gives the name of infinite space to unoccupied lands, and Isocrates speaking of that occupied by the Athenians calls it that which has been measured by us into alloted parts. But fluids, which cannot be limited or restrained, except they be contained within some other substance, cannot be occupied. Thus ponds, and lakes and rivers likewise, can only be made property as far as they are confined within certain banks. But the ocean as it is equal to, or larger than the earth, cannot be confined within the land: so that the ancients said the earth was bounded in by the sea like a girdle surrounding it. Nor can any imaginable division of it have been originally framed. For as the greatest part of it was unknown, it was impossible that nations far removed from each other could agree upon the bounds to be assigned to different parts.
There’s a natural reason why the sea, when viewed this way, can’t be owned: because ownership can only exist in things that can be contained within specific, permanent boundaries. This is why Thucydides referred to unoccupied land as infinite space, and Isocrates spoke of the land occupied by the Athenians as that which we’ve divided into designated parts. However, fluids, which can’t be limited or held back unless contained within something else, can’t be owned. Thus, ponds, lakes, and rivers can only be owned as far as they are enclosed by specific banks. But the ocean, being equal to or larger than the earth, can’t be confined by land: hence the ancients said the earth is surrounded by the sea like a girdle. No conceivable division of it could have been established originally. Since much of it was unknown, it was impossible for distant nations to agree on the boundaries for different areas.
Whatever therefore was the common property of all, and after a general division of all other things, retained its original state, could not be appropriated by division, but by occupancy. And the marks of distinction and separation by which its different parts were known, followed such appropriation.
Whatever was the common property of everyone, and after a general distribution of everything else, remained in its original state, couldn't be claimed through division, but through occupancy. The distinguishing marks and separations that identified its different parts came after that appropriation.
IV. The next matters to be noticed are those things, which though not yet made property, may be reduced to that condition. Under this description come waste lands, desert islands, wild beasts, fishes, and birds. Now in these cases there are two things to be pointed out, which are a double kind of occupancy that may take place; the one in the name of the Sovereign, or of a whole people, the other by individuals, converting into private estates the lands which they have so occupied. The latter kind of individual property proceeds rather from91 assignment than from free occupancy. Yet any places that have been taken possession of in the name of a sovereign, or of a whole people, though not portioned out amongst individuals, are not to be considered as waste lands, but as the property of the first occupier, whether it be the King, or a whole people. Of this description are rivers, lakes, forests, and wild mountains.
IV. The next things to consider are those items that, while not formally owned yet, can be claimed as property. This includes wasteland, uninhabited islands, wild animals, fish, and birds. In these situations, there are two important aspects to note regarding how ownership can occur: one is on behalf of the Sovereign or an entire community, and the other is by individuals who turn the occupied land into private property. The latter form of individual ownership arises more from assignment than from simple occupation. However, any areas that have been claimed in the name of a sovereign or a community, even if not divided among individuals, should not be viewed as wasteland but as the property of the first claimant, be it the King or the community as a whole. This includes rivers, lakes, forests, and untamed mountains.
V. As to wild beasts, fishes, and birds, it is to be observed that the sovereign of the respective lands, or waters where they are found, has a legal right to prohibit any one from taking them, and thereby acquiring a property in them. A prohibition extending to foreigners, as well as subjects. To foreigners; because by all the rules of moral law they owe obedience to the sovereign, for the time during which they reside in his territories. Nor is there any validity in the objection founded on the Roman Law, the Law of nature, or the Law of nations, which, it is said, declare such animals to be beasts of chace free to every one's hunting. For this is only true, where there is no civil law to interpose its prohibition; as the Roman law left many things in their primitive state, which by other nations were placed upon a very different footing. The deviations therefore from the state of nature, which have been established by the civil law, are ordained by every principle of natural justice to be obeyed by mankind. For although the civil law can enjoin nothing which the law of nature prohibits, nor prohibit any thing which it enjoins, yet it may circumscribe natural liberty, restraining what was before allowed; although the restraint should extend to the very acquisition of property, to which every man AT FIRST had a right by the law of nature.
V. When it comes to wild animals, fish, and birds, it’s important to note that the ruler of the lands or waters where they are found has the legal authority to stop anyone from capturing them and thereby claiming ownership. This prohibition applies to both locals and foreigners. For foreigners, this is because, according to moral law, they must obey the ruler while they are in his territory. There is no ground for the argument based on Roman Law, natural law, or international law that claims these animals are free to hunt for everyone. That’s only true when there are no local laws that prohibit hunting. Roman law left many matters in their natural state, while other nations handled them differently. Consequently, the changes made to the state of nature by civil law must be followed by everyone, as required by natural justice. Although civil law cannot command anything that natural law prohibits or prohibit anything that natural law commands, it can limit natural liberty, restricting what was previously permitted, even if these restrictions affect the right to own property, which every person originally had under natural law.
VI. The next thing to be considered is the right, which men have to the common use of things, already appropriated; terms, in which at the first sight there appears to be some inconsistency, as it appears that the establishment of property has absorbed every right that sprung from a state of things held in common. But this is by no means the case. For the intention of those, who first introduce private property, must be taken into the account. And it was but reasonable to suppose, that in making this introduction of property, they would depart as little as possible from the original principles of natural equity. For if written laws are to be construed in a sense, approaching as nearly as possible to the laws of92 nature, much more so are those customs which are not fettered with the literal restrictions of written maxims. From hence it follows that in cases of extreme necessity, the original right of using things, as if they had remained in common, must be revived; because in all human laws, and consequently in the laws relating to property, the case of extreme necessity seems to form an exception.
VI. The next thing to consider is the right that people have to the common use of things that have already been claimed. At first glance, this seems inconsistent, as it appears that the establishment of private property has taken away every right that came from a situation where things were shared. But that’s not the case at all. We have to consider the intentions of those who first introduced private property. It makes sense to think that when they established property, they would stick as closely as possible to the original principles of fairness. If written laws are meant to be interpreted in a way that aligns closely with natural law, then customs, which aren’t bound by the strict limitations of written rules, should be interpreted even more flexibly. This leads to the conclusion that in cases of extreme necessity, the original right to use things as if they were still shared must be restored; because in all human laws, and specifically in property laws, extreme necessity seems to be an exception.
Upon this principle is built the maxim that if in a voyage provisions begin to fail, the stock of every individual ought to be produced for common consumption; for the same reason a neighbouring house may be pulled down to stop the progress of a fire: or the cables or nets, in which a ship is entangled, may be cut, if it cannot otherwise be disengaged. Maxims, none of which were introduced by the civil law, but only explained by it according to the rules of natural equity.
Upon this principle is built the maxim that if on a voyage supplies start to run low, the stock of each person should be shared for everyone's benefit; similarly, a neighboring house may be demolished to prevent a fire from spreading: or the cables or nets that have tangled a ship may be cut if there’s no other way to free it. These maxims were not introduced by civil law but were explained by it according to principles of natural fairness.
Now among Theologians also it is a received opinion, that if in urgent distress, any one shall take from another what is absolutely necessary for the preservation of his own life, the act shall not be deemed a theft. A rule not founded, as some allege, solely upon the law of charity, which obliges every possessor to apply some part of his wealth to relieve the needy; but upon the original division of lands among private owners, which was made with a reservation in favour of the primitive rights of nature. For if those who at first made the division had been asked their opinion upon this point, they would have given the same reason that has just been advanced. Necessity, says Seneca, the great protectress of human infirmity breaks through all human laws, and all those made in the spirit of human regulations. Cicero in his eleventh Philippic, says, that Cassius went into Syria, which might be considered as another's province, if men adhered to written laws, but if these were abolished, it would be considered as his own by the law of nature. In the sixth book and fourth chapter of Quintus Curtius, we find an observation, that in a common calamity every man looks to himself.
Now among theologians, it is a widely accepted belief that if someone is in urgent distress, and they take what’s absolutely necessary from another person to save their own life, that act will not be considered theft. This principle isn’t just based on the law of charity, which compels everyone to use some of their wealth to help those in need, but is rooted in the original division of lands among private owners, which was made with consideration for the fundamental rights of nature. If those who initially set the boundaries had been asked about this issue, they would have provided the same reasoning just mentioned. Necessity, as Seneca states, the great defender of human weakness, overrides all human laws and those made with human intent. Cicero, in his eleventh Philippic, mentions that Cassius went to Syria, which could be seen as someone else's territory if people strictly followed written laws. However, if those laws were disregarded, it would be regarded as his own by the law of nature. In the sixth book and the fourth chapter of Quintus Curtius, there is a remark that in a common disaster, everyone looks out for themselves.
VII. Now this indulgence must be granted with precautions and restrictions, to prevent it from degenerating into licentiousness. And of these precautions, the first requires the distressed party to try every mode of obtaining relief, by an appeal to a magistrate, or by trying the effect of entreaty to prevail upon the owner to grant what is necessary for his pressing occasions.93 Plato allows any one to seek water from his neighbour's well, after having dug to a certain depth in his own without effect. Solon limits the depth to forty cubits; upon which Plutarch remarks, that he intended by this to relieve necessity and difficulty, but not to encourage sloth. Xenophon in his answer to the Sinopians, in the fifth book of the expedition of Cyrus, says, "wherever we come, whether into a barbarous country or into any part of Greece, and find the people unwilling to afford us supplies, we take them, not through motives of wantonness, but from the compulsion of necessity."
VII. This indulgence must come with precautions and restrictions to prevent it from turning into misconduct. The first precaution requires the person in distress to attempt every possible way to seek help, either by appealing to a magistrate or by trying to persuade the owner to provide what is needed for urgent situations.93 Plato allows anyone to draw water from a neighbor's well after they've dug to a certain depth in their own without success. Solon sets the limit at forty cubits; Plutarch notes that he meant this to assist people in need and difficulty, but not to encourage laziness. In Xenophon's reply to the Sinopians in the fifth book of the expedition of Cyrus, he states, "wherever we go, whether into an uncivilized land or any part of Greece, and find the people unwilling to provide us supplies, we take them, not out of wantonness, but out of necessity."
VIII. In the next place this plea of necessity cannot be admitted, where the possessor is in an equal state of necessity himself. For under equal circumstances the owner has a better right to the use of his possessions. Though Lactantius maintains that it is no mark of folly to forbear thrusting another from the same plank in a shipwreck in order to save yourself. Because you have thereby avoided hurting another: a sin which is certainly a proof of wisdom to abstain from. Cicero, in the third book of his offices, asks this question, if a wise man, in danger of perishing with hunger, has not a right to take the provisions of another, who is good for nothing? To which he replies; By no means. For no one's life can be of such importance as to authorize the violation of that general rule of forbearance, by which the peace and safety of every individual are secured.
VIII. Next, this argument of necessity can't be accepted when the person in possession is in an equal state of necessity themselves. Because under equal conditions, the owner has a stronger right to use their belongings. Although Lactantius argues that it's not foolish to avoid pushing someone off the same plank during a shipwreck to save yourself, since you’re preventing harm to another person—a choice that shows wisdom in restraint. Cicero, in the third book of his duties, poses the question: if a wise person, facing starvation, has the right to take the supplies of someone who isn’t useful? He answers firmly: Absolutely not. No one's life is so crucial that it justifies breaking that general rule of restraint that ensures the peace and safety of everyone.
IX. In the third place, the party thus supplying his wants from the property of another, is bound to make restitution, or give an equivalent to the owner, whenever that is possible. There are some indeed, who deny this, upon the ground that no one is bound to give an indemnity for having exercised his own right. But strictly speaking, it was not a full and perfect right, which he exercised; but a kind of permission, arising out of a case of necessity, and existing no longer than while the necessity continued. For such a permissive right is only granted in order to preserve natural equity in opposition to the strict and churlish rigour of exclusive ownership.
IX. Thirdly, if someone takes what they need from someone else's property, they're required to return it or provide something of equal value to the owner whenever possible. Some people argue against this, claiming that no one should have to compensate for exercising their own rights. However, technically, the right they exercised wasn't complete and absolute; it was more of a temporary permission that existed only as long as the necessity did. This kind of permissive right is granted to maintain fairness against the harshness of strict ownership.
X. Hence it may be inferred, that, in the prosecution of a just war, any power has a right to take possession of a neutral soil; if there be real grounds, and not imaginary fears for supposing the enemy intends to make himself master of the same, especially if the enemy's occupying it would be attended with imminent and irreparable94 mischief to that same power. But in this case the restriction is applied that nothing be taken but what is actually necessary to such precaution and security. Barely occupying the place is all that can be justified: leaving to the real owner the full enjoyment of all his rights, immunities, and jurisdiction, and all the productions of his soil. And this must be done too with the full intention of restoring the place to its lawful Sovereign, whenever the necessity, for which it was occupied, may cease. The retaining of Enna, Livy says, was either an act of violence, or a necessary measure; by violence meaning the least departure from necessity. The Greeks, who were with Xenophon being in great want of ships, by Xenophon's own advice, seized upon those that were passing, still preserving the property untouched for the owners, supplying the sailors with provisions, and paying them wages. The principal right therefore, founded upon the original community of goods, remaining since the introduction of property, is that of necessity, which has just been discussed.
X. Therefore, it can be concluded that in the pursuit of a just war, any power has the right to take control of neutral territory, if there are valid reasons—rather than just unfounded fears—to believe that the enemy intends to take it for themselves, especially if the enemy’s occupation would result in immediate and irreversible harm to that power. However, in this case, the restriction applies that only what is actually necessary for precaution and security may be taken. Simply occupying the area is the only action that can be justified: allowing the true owner to retain full enjoyment of all their rights, privileges, and jurisdiction, along with the products of their land. This must also be done with the genuine intention of returning the area to its rightful Sovereign once the necessity for occupying it has ended. Livy states that the retention of Enna was either an act of violence or a necessary measure, with violence meaning the least departure from necessity. The Greeks, who were with Xenophon and badly needed ships, followed his advice to seize those that were passing by, while still preserving the property intact for the owners, providing sailors with food, and paying them wages. Therefore, the fundamental right, rooted in the original community of goods that has existed since the introduction of property, is that of necessity, which has just been discussed.
XI. There is another right, which is that of making use of the property of another, where such use is attended with no prejudice to the owner. For why, says Cicero, should not any one, when he can do it without injury to himself, allow another to share with him those advantages, which are useful to the receiver, and no way detrimental to the giver? Seneca therefore observes, that it is no favour to allow another to light his fire from your flame. And in the 7th book of Plutarch's Symposiacs, we find an observation, that when we have provisions more than sufficient for our own consumption it is wicked to destroy the remainder; or after supplying our own wants, to obstruct or destroy the springs of water; or after having finished our voyage, not to leave for other passengers the sea-marks, that have enabled us to steer our course.
XI. There is another right, which is the ability to use someone else's property, as long as it doesn't harm the owner. Because, as Cicero says, why shouldn't anyone, when they can do so without hurting themselves, let another person benefit from things that are helpful to them and not at all harmful to the one sharing? Seneca therefore points out that it's not a favor to let someone else take fire from your flame. And in the 7th book of Plutarch's Symposiacs, there's a note that when we have food that exceeds our own needs, it’s wrong to waste what’s left; or after meeting our own needs, to block or ruin the sources of water; or after completing our journey, not to leave behind sea marks that helped us navigate.
XII. Upon the principles already established, a river, as such, is the property of that people, or of the sovereign of that people, through whose territories it flows. He may form quays, and buttresses upon that river, and to him all the produce of it belongs. But the same river, as a running water, still remains common to all to draw or drink it. Ovid introduces Latona thus addressing the Lydians, "Why do you refuse water, the use of which is common?" where he calls water a public gift that is95 common to men, taking the word public in a more general sense than as applied to any PEOPLE, a meaning in which some things are said to be public by the law of nations. And in the same sense Virgil has asserted water to be free and open to all men.
XII. Based on the principles we've already established, a river is owned by the people or the ruler of the area it flows through. They can create docks and supports along that river, and all its resources belong to them. However, the river itself, in its natural state, remains accessible to everyone for drawing or drinking water. Ovid has Latona saying to the Lydians, "Why do you deny water, which is meant to be shared?" He refers to water as a public gift that is95 available to everyone, using the term public in a broader sense than just applying it to any PEOPLE, a definition in which some things are considered public by international law. Similarly, Virgil claimed that water is free and available to all people.
XIII. It is upon the same foundation of common right, that a free passage through countries, rivers, or over any part of the sea, which belongs to some particular people, ought to be allowed to those, who require it for the necessary occasions of life; whether those occasions be in quest of settlements, after being driven from their own country, or to trade with a remote nation, or to recover by just war their lost possessions. The same reason prevails here as in the cases above named. Because property was originally introduced with a reservation of that use, which might be of general benefit, and not prejudicial to the interest of the owner: an intention evidently entertained by those, who first devised the separation of the bounteous gifts of the creator into private possessions. There is a remarkable instance of this in the Mosaic history, when the leader of the children of Israel required a free passage for that people, promising to the King of Edom, and to the King of the Amorites, that he would go by the highway, without setting a foot upon the soil of private possessions, and that the people should pay the price of everything, which they might have occasion to use. Upon these equitable terms being rejected, Moses was justified in making war upon the Amorites. Because, says Augustin, an inoffensive passage, a right interwoven with the very frame of human society, was refused. The Greeks under the command of Clearchus, said, "we are upon the way to our home, if no one interrupt us; but every attempt to molest us, we are, with the assistance of heaven, determined to avenge."
XIII. It is based on the same principle of common right that free passage through countries, rivers, or any part of the sea, owned by certain people, should be granted to those who need it for essential life activities; whether those activities involve seeking new homes after being expelled from their own country, trading with distant nations, or reclaiming lost possessions through rightful conflict. The same reasoning applies here as in the earlier cases. Property was originally established with an understanding that it would serve a purpose that benefits the community without harming the owner's interests—an intention clearly reflected in the minds of those who first divided the generous gifts of the creator into private ownership. A notable example can be found in the Mosaic account when the leader of the Israelites requested free passage for his people, assuring the King of Edom and the King of the Amorites that they would travel along the highway without stepping on any private land, and that they would pay for any resources they used. When these fair terms were denied, Moses was justified in waging war against the Amorites. For, as Augustine said, a peaceful passage, a right woven into the very fabric of human society, was denied. The Greeks under Clearchus claimed, "We are on our way home, as long as no one interferes; but any attempt to disturb us will face our wrath, with the support of heaven."
Not unlike this answer of the soldiers under Clearchus is the question put to the different nations of Thrace by Agesilaus, who desired to know whether they wished him to pass through their country as a friend, or as an enemy. When the Boeotians hesitated upon some propositions made to them by Lysander, he asked them whether they intended that he should pass with erected or inclined spears, meaning by the expression in a hostile or a quiet manner. We are informed by Tacitus, that the Batavians, as soon as they came near the camp at Bonn, sent a message to Herennius Gallus, importing that "they had96 no hostile design; that if not obstructed, they would march in a peaceable manner; but if they met with opposition they would cut their way sword in hand." When Cimon in carrying supplies to the Lacedaemonians, had marched with his troops through some part of the Corinthian district, the Corinthians expostulated upon his conduct as a violation of their territory, because he had done it without asking their leave, at the same time observing, that no one knocks at another man's door, or presumes to enter the house without obtaining the master's leave. To whom he replied, you never knocked at the gates of Cleone and Megara, but broke them down, believing, I suppose, that no right ought to withstand the force of the mighty.
Not unlike the response from the soldiers under Clearchus, Agesilaus posed a question to the various nations of Thrace, wanting to know if they wanted him to pass through their land as a friend or as an enemy. When the Boeotians hesitated over some proposals made by Lysander, he asked them whether they wanted him to approach with raised or lowered spears, meaning in a hostile or peaceful way. Tacitus informs us that the Batavians, upon nearing the camp at Bonn, sent a message to Herennius Gallus saying that they had no hostile intentions; if not stopped, they would march in a peaceful manner, but if they faced resistance, they would fight their way through. When Cimon was bringing supplies to the Lacedaemonians and had marched with his troops through part of the Corinthian area, the Corinthians complained about his actions as a violation of their territory since he did it without their permission. They pointed out that no one knocks on someone else's door or assumes they can enter a house without the owner’s consent. Cimon replied that they never knocked at the gates of Cleone and Megara but broke them down, believing, I suppose, that no right should stand against the power of the strong.
Now between these two extremes there is a middle course, requiring a free passage to be first asked; the refusal of which will justify the application of force. Thus Agesilaus in his return from Asia when he had asked a passage of the King of the Macedonians, who answered that he would consider of it, said, you may consider, if you please, but we shall pass in the mean time.
Now between these two extremes, there is a middle ground that requires permission for passage to be requested first; the denial of which will justify the use of force. So, Agesilaus, on his way back from Asia, asked the King of the Macedonians for permission to pass. When the king replied that he would think about it, Agesilaus said, "You can think it over if you want, but we will pass through in the meantime."
The fears, which any power entertains from a multitude in arms passing through its territories, do not form such an exception as can do away the rule already laid down. For it is not proper or reasonable that the fears of one party should destroy the rights of another. Especially, as necessary precautions and securities may be used, such as those, for instance, of requiring that the troops shall pass without arms, or in small bodies; a promise which the Agrippinians made to the Germans. And, as we are informed by Strabo, the practice still prevails in the country of the Eleans. Another security may be found in providing garrisons at the expense of the party, to whom the passage is granted; or in giving hostages; the condition, which Seleucus demanded of Demetrius, for permitting him to remain within his territories. Nor is the fear of offending that power, which is the object of attack, a sufficient pretext for refusing the passage of the troops to the state that is engaged in a just war. Nor is it a proper reason to assign for a refusal, to say that another passage may be found; as every other power might allege the same, and by this means the right of passage would be entirely defeated. The request of a passage therefore, by the nearest and most commodious way, without doing injury and mischief,97 is a sufficient ground upon which it should be granted. It alters the case entirely, if the party making the request is engaged in unjust war, and is marching with the troops of a power hostile to the sovereign of that territory; for in this instance, a passage may be refused. For the sovereign has a right to attack that power in his own territory, and to oppose its march.
The concerns that any authority has about a large group of armed individuals moving through its land don't create an exception to the established rule. It's neither fair nor reasonable for one party's fears to override another's rights. Especially since there are necessary precautions and safeguards that can be put in place, like requiring troops to pass unarmed or in small groups, which the Agrippinians promised to the Germans. Strabo informs us that this practice is still followed in the region of the Eleans. Another safeguard could be stationing garrisons at the expense of the party requesting passage or requiring hostages, as Seleucus demanded from Demetrius to allow him to stay within his territories. The fear of offending the attacking party isn't a valid reason to deny passage to a state engaged in a just war. It’s also not a valid excuse to refuse by suggesting an alternative route since any other power could claim the same, leading to the complete undermining of the right to passage. Therefore, a request for passage by the most direct and convenient route, without causing harm or damage, 97 provides a valid basis for granting it. However, if the party making the request is engaged in an unjust war and is marching with troops from a power that's hostile to the sovereign of that area, then passage can be denied because the sovereign has the right to confront that power on its own land and to resist its advance.
Now a free passage ought to be allowed not only to persons, but to merchandise. For no power has a right to prevent one nation from trading with another at a remote distance; a permission which for the interest of society should be maintained. Nor can it be said that any one is injured by it. For though he may be thereby deprived of an exclusive gain, yet the loss of what is not his due, as a MATTER OF RIGHT, can never be considered as a damage or the violation of a claim.
Now, there should be open trade allowed not just for people, but for goods too. No nation has the right to stop another nation from trading, even if they are far apart; this should be upheld for the benefit of society. It can’t be argued that anyone is harmed by this. Even if someone misses out on a unique profit, losing something that is not rightfully theirs can never really be seen as a loss or a violation of their claim.
XIV. But it will form a subject of inquiry, whether the sovereign of the country has a right to impose duties on goods carried by land, or upon a river or upon any part of the sea, which may form an accession to his dominions. It would undoubtedly be unjust for any burdens foreign to the nature of trade to be imposed upon such goods. Thus strangers merely passing through a country would have no right to pay a poll-tax, imposed to support the exigencies of the state. But if the sovereign incurs expence by providing security and protection to trade, he has a right to reimburse himself by the imposition of moderate and reasonable duties. It is the REASONABLENESS of them, which constitutes the justice of customs and taxes. Thus Solomon received tolls for horses and linen that passed over the Isthmus of Syria. Pliny, speaking of frankincense, observes that as it could not be transported but by the Gebanites, a duty upon it was paid to their king. In the same manner, as Strabo informs us in his fourth book, the people of Marseilles derived great wealth from the canal which Marius had made from the Rhone to the sea, by exacting tribute of all that sailed upon it to and fro with vessels. In the eighth book of the same writer, we are told that the Corinthians imposed a duty upon all goods, which, to avoid the dangerous passage of Cape Malea, were transported by land from sea to sea. The Romans too made the passage of the Rhine a source of tribute, and Seneca relates that a toll was paid for going over bridges.98 The works of legal writers abound in instances of this kind. But it frequently happens that extortion is practised in these matters, which Strabo forms into a subject of complaint against chiefs of the Arabian tribes, concluding that it would be unlikely for men of that lawless kind to impose upon the goods of merchants any duties that were not oppressive.
XIV. However, it raises the question of whether the ruler of the land has the authority to impose taxes on goods transported overland, along a river, or through any part of the sea that might extend their territory. It would certainly be unfair to impose any burdens unrelated to trade on such goods. For instance, outsiders simply passing through a country should not be required to pay a poll tax meant to fund the state's needs. But if the ruler incurs expenses to provide security and protection for trade, they have the right to recoup those costs through moderate and reasonable taxes. The fairness of these taxes is what makes them just. For example, Solomon collected tolls on horses and linen that passed through the Isthmus of Syria. Pliny notes that since frankincense could only be transported by the Gebanites, they paid a tax to their king for it. Similarly, as Strabo mentions in his fourth book, the people of Marseilles gained significant wealth from the canal that Marius built from the Rhone to the sea by charging a tribute on all vessels traveling through it. In the eighth book of the same author, we learn that the Corinthians taxed all goods transported overland to bypass the dangerous passage around Cape Malea. The Romans also collected tribute from those crossing the Rhine, and Seneca mentions that a toll was charged for crossing bridges.98 Legal scholars provide numerous examples of this nature. However, it's common for extortion to occur in these situations, which Strabo highlights as a complaint against leaders of Arabian tribes, suggesting it’s unlikely that such lawless individuals would impose anything but oppressive duties on merchants’ goods.
XV. Those going with merchandise or only passing through a country, ought to be allowed to reside there for a time, if the recovery of health, or any other just cause should render such residence necessary. For these may be reckoned among the innocent uses of our right. Thus Ilioneus in Virgil calls heaven to witness the injustice of the Africans in driving him and his shipwrecked companions from the hospitable use of the shore, and we are informed by Plutarch in his life of Pericles that all the Grecians approved of the complaint, which the Megarensians made against the Athenians, who had prohibited them from setting foot upon the soil of their territories, or carrying a vessel into their harbours. So the Lacedaemonians regarded this as the most sufficient grounds to justify the war.
XV. People traveling with goods or just passing through a country should be allowed to stay for a while if they need to recover their health or have another valid reason. These situations can be seen as legitimate uses of our rights. For example, Ilioneus in Virgil calls on heaven to witness the unfairness of the Africans for driving him and his shipwrecked companions away from the welcoming shore. Plutarch also tells us in his life of Pericles that all the Greeks supported the complaint made by the Megarensians against the Athenians, who had banned them from stepping foot on their land or entering their harbors. The Lacedaemonians considered this a strong justification for going to war.
From hence results the right of erecting a temporary hut, upon the shore, although, for instance, the same shore is allowed to be the property of the people of that place. For what Pomponius says of its being necessary to obtain the Praetor's leave, before a building can be raised upon the public shore, relates to structures of a permanent kind, when the massy piles of stone, as the Poet says, encroach upon the sea, and the affrighted fish feel their waves contracted.
From this comes the right to set up a temporary hut on the shore, even if that shore is owned by the local people. What Pomponius says about needing the Praetor's permission before constructing anything on public shore only applies to permanent structures, where heavy stone piles, as the poet says, invade the sea, and frightened fish feel their waters getting smaller.
XVI. Nor ought a permanent residence to be refused to foreigners, who, driven from their own country, seek a place or refuge. But then it is only upon condition that they submit to the established laws of the place, and avoid every occasion of exciting tumult and sedition. A reasonable rule, which the divine poet has observed, when he introduces Aeneas making an offer that Latinus, who had become his father-in-law, should retain all military and civil power. And in Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Latinus admits the proposal of Aeneas to be just; as he came through necessity in quest of a settlement. To drive away refugees, says Strabo, from Eratosthenes, is acting like barbarians; and a conduct like this in the99 Spartans was also condemned. St. Ambrose passes the same sentence of condemnation upon those powers, who refuse all admission to strangers. Yet settlers of this description have no right to demand a share in the government. A proposal of this kind made by the Minyae to the Lacedaemonians, who had received them, is very properly considered by Herodotus as insolent, and unreasonable.
XVI. Foreigners should not be denied a permanent residence when they are forced to leave their own country and seek refuge. However, this is only if they follow the local laws and avoid causing any unrest or rebellion. This is a fair rule, as the divine poet illustrates with Aeneas offering Latinus, who became his father-in-law, the chance to keep all military and civil authority. Dionysius of Halicarnassus also notes that Latinus considers Aeneas's proposal to be fair since he came out of necessity to find a home. Strabo mentions that driving away refugees, as noted by Eratosthenes, is barbaric; similar behavior from the Spartans was condemned as well. St. Ambrose also criticizes those powers that refuse to accept strangers. However, these kinds of settlers do not have the right to demand a role in the government. Herodotus rightly views a proposal made by the Minyae to the Lacedaemonians, who took them in, as rude and unreasonable.
XVII. It is indeed but an act of common humanity in a sovereign to allow strangers, at their request, liberty to fix their residence upon any waste or barren lands within his dominions, still reserving to himself all the rights of sovereignty. Seven hundred acres of barren and uncultivated land, as Servius observes, were given by the native Latins to the Trojans. Dion Prusaeensis, in his seventh oration, says, that they commit no crime of trespass, who take upon them to cultivate waste lands. The refusal of this privilege made the Ansibarians exclaim, "the firmament over our heads is the mansion of the deity: the earth was given to man; and what remains unoccupied, lies in common to all." Yet that complaint did not apply exactly to their case. For those lands could not be called unoccupied, as they served to supply the Roman army with forage for their cattle, which certainly furnished the Romans with a just pretext for refusing to grant their request. And with no less propriety the Romans asked the Galli Senones if it were right to demand lands already possessed, and to threaten to take them by force.
XVII. It’s truly a basic act of humanity for a ruler to allow outsiders, at their request, the freedom to settle on any unused or barren lands within his territory, while still keeping all the rights of sovereignty for himself. As Servius points out, seven hundred acres of barren and uncultivated land were given by the native Latins to the Trojans. Dion Prusaeensis, in his seventh speech, states that there is no wrongdoing in cultivating unused lands. The Ansibarians complained, “the sky above us is the home of the deity: the earth was given to humanity; and what remains unoccupied belongs to everyone.” However, that complaint didn’t really apply to their situation. Those lands couldn’t be considered unoccupied, as they were used to provide forage for the Roman army's cattle, which definitely gave the Romans a valid reason to refuse their request. Likewise, the Romans properly asked the Galli Senones if it was right to demand lands that were already occupied and to threaten to take them by force.
XVIII. Since the COMMON RIGHT TO THINGS has been established, the COMMON RIGHT TO ACTIONS follows next in order, and this right is either absolute, or established by the supposition of a general agreement amongst mankind. Now all men have absolutely a right to do such or such acts as are necessary to provide whatever is essential to the existence or convenience of life. Convenience is included in this right; for there is no occasion here to imagine an existence of the same necessity as was requisite to authorize the seizing of another's property. Because the point of discussion here is not whether any act is done AGAINST THE WILL of an owner, but whether we acquire what is necessary for our wants ACCORDING TO THE TERMS to which the owner has agreed.19100 Supposing there is nothing illegal in the contract, nor any wilful intention on his part to make it null and void. For any impediment created by the owner in such transactions, is repugnant to the very principles of natural justice, which suppose an equality of upright dealing to subsist in both the parties concerned. St. Ambrose calls a fraudulent conduct of that kind, an attempt to deprive men of their share in the goods of a common parent, to withhold the productions of nature which are the birthright of all, and to destroy that commerce which is the very support of life. For we are not treating of superfluities and luxuries, but of those things, which are essential to life, as physic, food and cloathing.
XVIII. Since the COMMON RIGHT TO THINGS has been established, the Common right to sue follows next in line, and this right can be either absolute or based on the assumption of a general agreement among people. Now everyone has an absolute right to perform necessary actions to obtain whatever is essential for life and comfort. Convenience is part of this right; there is no need to envision a necessity as great as what would justify taking someone else's property. The discussion here isn’t about whether an act is done Against one's will of an owner, but whether we are acquiring what we need ACCORDING TO THE TERMS that the owner has agreed. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__100 assuming there’s nothing illegal in the contract and no intentional act on their part to invalidate it. Any obstruction caused by the owner in these transactions goes against the basic principles of natural justice, which assume fairness and honesty in dealings between both parties involved. St. Ambrose refers to such fraudulent behavior as an attempt to deny people their share of goods from a common source, to withhold the resources of nature that belong to everyone, and to undermine the trade that sustains life. We are not talking about excesses or luxuries, but rather about essentials for survival, like medicine, food, and clothing.
XIX. From what has already been proved, it follows that all men have a right to purchase the necessaries of life at a reasonable price, except the owners want them for their own use. Thus in a great scarcity of corn, there would be no injustice in their refusing to sell. And yet in such a time of necessity foreigners, who have been once admitted, cannot be driven away; but as St. Ambrose shews in the passage already quoted, a common evil must be borne by all alike.
XIX. Based on what has already been established, it follows that everyone has the right to buy essential goods at a fair price, unless the owners need them for their own use. Therefore, during a significant shortage of grain, it wouldn’t be unfair for them to refuse to sell. However, in such a time of need, foreigners who have already been allowed in cannot be turned away; as St. Ambrose points out in the previously mentioned passage, a common hardship should be shared by everyone.
XX. Now owners have not the same right in the sale of their goods: for others are at full liberty to determine whether they will purchase certain articles or not. The ancient Belgians, for instance, allowed not wines and other foreign merchandise to be imported among them. The same rule, we are informed by Strabo, was practised by the Nabathaean Arabians.
XX. Nowadays, owners don’t have the same freedom when it comes to selling their goods: others have complete liberty to decide whether or not they want to buy certain items. For example, the ancient Belgians didn’t allow wines and other foreign products to be imported into their territory. Strabo informs us that the same rule was followed by the Nabataean Arabs.
XXI. It is supposed to be generally agreed among mankind, that the privileges, which any nation grants promiscuously to the subjects of foreign powers or countries,101 are the common right of all.20 Consequently the exclusion of any one people from these rights would be considered as an injury to that people. Thus, wherever foreigners in general are allowed to hunt, to fish, to shoot, to gather pearls, to succeed to property by testament, to sell commodities, or to form intermarriages, the same privileges cannot be refused to any particular people, unless they have by misconduct forfeited their right. On which account the tribe of Benjamin was debarred from intermarrying with other tribes.
XXI. It's generally accepted among people that the privileges any nation offers equally to the citizens of foreign countries are the common rights of all. Consequently, excluding any group from these rights would be seen as a harm to that group. Therefore, wherever foreigners are permitted to hunt, fish, shoot, gather pearls, inherit property through wills, sell goods, or marry, those same privileges cannot be denied to any specific group unless they have lost that right due to wrongdoing. This is why the tribe of Benjamin was restricted from intermarrying with other tribes.
XXII. It has sometimes been a subject of inquiry whether one nation may lawfully agree with another to exclude all nations but herself from purchasing certain productions, which are the peculiar growth of her soil. An agreement which, it is evident, may be lawfully made; if the purchaser intends to supply other nations with those articles at a reasonable price. For it is a matter of indifference to other nations OF WHOM they purchase, provided they can have a reasonable supply for their wants. Nor is there any thing unlawful in allowing one people an advantage over another in this respect, particularly for a nation who has taken another under her protection and incurred expence on that account. Now such a monopoly, under the circumstances already mentioned, is no way repugnant to the law of nature,21102 though it may be sometimes for the interest of the community to prohibit it by express laws.
XXII. There have been discussions about whether one country can legally agree with another to block all other countries from buying certain products unique to its land. It's clear that such an agreement can be legally made if the buyer plans to sell those products to other countries at a fair price. Other nations don't really care who they buy from, as long as they can obtain what they need at a reasonable price. There’s nothing wrong with giving one country an advantage over another in this way, especially for a nation that has taken another under its protection and has incurred costs because of it. So, this kind of monopoly, given the circumstances outlined, is not against the law of nature, although it might sometimes be in the community's interest to ban it through specific laws.
CHAPTER III.
On the Original Acquisition of Things and the Right to Property in Seas and Rivers.
Specification of moveable property—The difference between sovereignty and property—The right to moveables by occupancy may be superseded by law—Rivers may be occupied—Right to seas—On the treaties binding a people not to navigate the seas beyond certain bounds—Inquiry into the nature of the change which a river, changing its course, makes in the adjoining territories—What determination is to be made, where the river has entirely changed its channel—Sometimes a whole river may accrue to a territory—Things deserted belong to the first occupier.
Specifications of movable property—The distinction between sovereignty and property—The right to movable property through occupancy can be overridden by law—Rivers can be claimed—The right to seas—On treaties that prevent a community from navigating the seas beyond certain limits—An examination of how a river changing its course impacts the surrounding lands—What decision must be made when a river has completely changed its channel—Sometimes, an entire river may become part of a territory—Abandoned items belong to the first person to claim them.
I. Among the means of acquiring property, Paulus the Lawyer reckons one, which seems most natural, and that is, if by the ingenuity of art, or the exertions of labour we have given to any production its existence among the works of man. Now as nothing can naturally be produced, except from some materials before in existence, it follows that, if those materials were our own, the possession of them under any new shape, or commodity is only a CONTINUATION of our former property; if they belonged to no one, our possession comes under the class of title by occupancy: but if they were another's, no improvement of ours can by the law of nature give us a right of property therein.
I. Among the ways to acquire property, Paulus the Lawyer identifies one that seems the most natural: if we, through skill or hard work, create something that exists among human creations. Since nothing can be made naturally without using some pre-existing materials, it follows that if those materials belonged to us, then possessing them in a new form or product is just a CONTINUATION of our previous ownership. If the materials belonged to no one, then our possession is classified as title by occupancy. However, if they were owned by someone else, no improvement we make grants us ownership according to natural law.
II. Among those things, which belong to no one, there are two that may become the subjects of occupancy; and those are jurisdiction, or sovereignty and property. For jurisdiction and property are distinct from each other in their effects. The objects over which sovereignty may be exercised are of a twofold description, embracing both persons and things. But this is not the case with property, the right of which can extend only to the irrational and inanimate part of the creation. Though it might originally, for the most part, be the same act by which sovereignty and property were acquired, yet they are in their nature distinct. Sovereignty, says Seneca, belongs to Princes and PROPERTY to INDIVIDUALS. The sovereignty therefore, not only over subjects at home, but104 over those in the prince's foreign dominions passes with the hereditary descent of the crown.
II. Among things that don't belong to anyone, there are two that can be claimed: jurisdiction (or sovereignty) and property. Jurisdiction and property have different effects. The subjects of sovereignty can include both people and objects. However, property rights only extend to non-thinking and non-living things. While the act of acquiring sovereignty and property might have originally been similar, they are fundamentally different. Independence, as Seneca says, belongs to Royals and PROPERTY belongs to People. So, the sovereignty over subjects both at home and 104 in the prince's foreign territories passes down with the hereditary succession of the crown.
III. In places, where sovereignty is already established, the right to moveables by occupancy, and indeed every original right must give way to the superior sanction of law. And what any man before held by any such right, he would afterwards be considered as holding by the laws of the country. For those original rights were PERMISSIONS of the law of nature, and not commands that were to be PERPETUALLY enforced. For the continued establishment of such a right as that by prior occupancy, so far from promoting the welfare, would operate to the very destruction of human society. Although it may be said by way of objection, that the law of nations seems to admit of such a right, yet we may answer that if such a rule either is or has been commonly received in any part of the world, it has not the force of a general compact binding upon different independent nations; but may be considered as one branch of the civil law of many nations, which any state has a right to continue, or repeal according to its own pleasure or discretion. There are many other things indeed which legal writers, in treating of the division and acquisition of property, consider as forming a part of the law of nations.
III. In places where sovereignty is already established, the right to moveable property through occupancy, and really every original right, must yield to the superior authority of the law. What a person previously held by such a right will now be regarded as being held according to the laws of the country. Those original rights were Permissions of natural law, not commands meant to be Always enforced. The continued recognition of a right based on prior occupancy would not promote welfare but would actually threaten the very existence of human society. Although some might argue that the law of nations appears to recognize such a right, we can counter that if such a rule is or has been widely accepted in any part of the world, it does not carry the weight of a general agreement binding different independent nations; rather, it may be seen as one aspect of the civil law of various nations, which any state can choose to uphold or abolish at its discretion. Indeed, there are many other aspects that legal writers consider part of the law of nations when discussing the division and acquisition of property.
IV. Rivers may be occupied by a country, not including the stream above, nor that below its own territories. But the waters which wash its lands form an inseparable part of the current, making its way to the main sea. For to constitute the right to a property in its channel, it is sufficient that its sides, inclosed by the banks of that territory form its greatest part, and that the river itself compared with the land, makes but a small portion.
IV. A country can claim ownership of rivers, but this doesn't include the water upstream or downstream of its borders. The waters that flow over its land are an essential part of the current as it moves toward the main sea. To establish a right to property in its riverbed, it’s enough that the riverbanks, which belong to that territory, make up a large part of the river, while the river itself is just a small portion compared to the land.
V. In the same manner, the sea appears capable of being made a property by the power possessed of the shore on both sides of it; although beyond those limits it may spread to a wide extent, which is the case with a bay, and with a straight beyond each of its outlets into main sea or ocean. But this right of property can never take place where the sea is of such a magnitude, as to surpass all comparison with that portion of the land which it washes. And the right, which one people or prince possesses, may also be shared by a great number of states, among whose respective territories the sea flows. Thus rivers separating two powers may be105 occupied by both, to each of whom their use and advantages may be equal.
V. Similarly, the sea seems to be capable of being owned by the power of the land on both sides. However, beyond those boundaries, it can extend widely, as seen with a bay and the strait leading to the open sea or ocean beyond each of its outlets. Yet, the right to own part of the sea can't apply when its size far exceeds that of the adjacent land. Additionally, the rights that one nation or ruler has can also be shared by many states, through whose territories the sea flows. For example, rivers that separate two powers can be105 used by both, allowing each to enjoy equal benefits.
VI. Instances may be found of treaties by which one nation binds itself to another, not to navigate particular seas beyond certain bounds. Thus between the Egyptians and the Princes inhabiting the borders of the Red Sea, it was agreed, in ancient times, that the former should not enter that sea with any ship of war, nor with more than one merchant ship. In the same manner, in the time of Cimon, the Persians were bound by a treaty, made with the Athenians, not to sail with any ship of war between the Cyanean rocks and the Chelidonian islands; a prohibition, which, after the battle of Salamis, restricted any Persian armed vessel from sailing between Phaselis and the above named rocks. In the one year's truce of the Peloponnesian war, the Lacedaemonians were prohibited from sailing with any ships of war whatever, or indeed with any other ships of more than twenty tons burden. And in the first treaty, which the Romans, immediately after the expulsion of their kings, made with the Carthaginians, it was stipulated that neither the Romans, nor their allies should sail beyond the promontory of Pulchrum, except they were driven thither by stress of weather, or to avoid being captured by an enemy. But in either case they were to take nothing more than necessaries, and to depart before the expiration of five days. And in the second treaty, the Romans were prohibited from committing any acts of piracy, or even from trading beyond the promontory of Pulchrum, Massia and Tarseius.
VI. There are examples of treaties where one nation agrees with another not to navigate certain seas beyond specific boundaries. For instance, in ancient times, the Egyptians and the rulers of the Red Sea's coastal areas agreed that the Egyptians would not enter that sea with any warship or more than one merchant ship. Similarly, during Cimon's time, the Persians made a treaty with the Athenians, agreeing not to sail any warships between the Cyanean rocks and the Chelidonian islands; this ban continued after the battle of Salamis, preventing any Persian armed vessel from sailing between Phaselis and those rocks. In the one-year truce of the Peloponnesian War, the Lacedaemonians were forbidden from sailing any warships or any other vessels over twenty tons. In the first treaty made by the Romans after expelling their kings with the Carthaginians, it was agreed that neither the Romans nor their allies could sail past the promontory of Pulchrum unless compelled by bad weather or to escape capture by an enemy. In such cases, they could only take essentials and had to leave within five days. In the second treaty, the Romans were banned from committing acts of piracy or trading beyond the promontory of Pulchrum, Massia, and Tarseius.
In a treaty of peace between the Illyrians and Romans, the latter required that they should not pass beyond the Lissus with more than two frigates, and those unarmed. In the peace with Antiochus, he was bound not to sail within the capes of Calycadnius and Sarpedon, except with ships carrying tribute, ambassadors, or hostages. Now the instances alluded to do not prove the actual occupancy of the sea, or the right of navigation. For it may happen that both individuals and nations may grant as a matter of favour or compact, not only what they have a competent right to dispose of, but that which is the common right of all men as well as of themselves. When this happens, we may say as Ulpian did on a like occasion, where an estate had been sold with a reservation, that the purchaser should not fish for Tunny to the106 prejudice of the seller. He observed that the sea could not be rendered subject to a service, but still the purchaser and those who succeeded to his possession, were bound in honour to observe that part of the contract.
In a peace treaty between the Illyrians and Romans, the Romans required that the Illyrians do not go past the Lissus with more than two frigates, and those had to be unarmed. In the peace deal with Antiochus, he was restricted from sailing within the capes of Calycadnius and Sarpedon, except with ships that were carrying tribute, ambassadors, or hostages. However, these examples do not show the actual control of the sea or the right to navigate it. It’s possible for both individuals and nations to grant, as a favor or agreement, not only what they have the right to manage, but also what is the common right of all people along with their own. When this happens, we can say, as Ulpian once noted in a similar situation where property was sold with conditions, that the buyer should not fish for Tunny to the 106 detriment of the seller. He pointed out that the sea cannot be subjected to such an obligation, but still, the buyer and those who take over his property are honor-bound to uphold that part of the agreement.
VII. Whenever a river has changed its course, disputes have arisen between neighboring states to decide whether such an alteration creates any change in the adjoining territories, and to whom any addition of land occasioned by that change accrues. Disputes which must be settled according to the nature and manner of such acquisition. Writers, who have treated of the division of land, have described it as of a threefold nature: one kind they name DIVIDED and ASSIGNED land, which Frontinus the Lawyer calls LIMITED, because it is marked out by artificial boundaries. By land ASSIGNED, is meant that which has been appropriated to a whole community, comprehending a certain number of families; a hundred for instance: from whence it has derived that name. And those portions are called hundreds. There is another division called ARCIFINIUM, which is applied when the land is defended against an enemy by the natural boundaries of rivers or mountains. These lands Aggenus Urbicus calls OCCUPATORY, being such as have been occupied either by reason of their being vacant, or by the power of conquest. In the two first kinds of lands, because their extent and bounds are fixed and determined, though a river should change its course, it occasions no change of territory, and what is added by alluvion will belong to the former occupant.
VII. Whenever a river changes its course, conflicts arise between neighboring states over whether this change affects the surrounding territories and who receives any added land resulting from that change. These disputes must be resolved based on the nature and method of the land acquisition. Writers discussing land division describe it as having three types: one type is called DIVIDED and ASSIGNED land, which Frontinus the Lawyer refers to as LIMITED because it is marked by artificial boundaries. ASSIGNED land refers to land designated for an entire community, typically comprising a certain number of families; for example, a hundred: hence the term. These divisions are known as hundreds. Another type is called ARCIFINIUM, which applies when the land is protected from enemies by natural boundaries like rivers or mountains. Aggenus Urbicus refers to this land as OCCUPYING, as it has been occupied either because it was unclaimed or through conquest. In the first two types of land, since their size and boundaries are fixed, even if a river changes its course, it does not alter the territory, and any land gained from erosion will belong to the original occupant.
In arcifinious lands, where the bounds are formed by nature, any gradual change in the course of the river makes a change also in the boundaries of territory, and whatever accession is given by the river to one side, it will belong to the possessor of the land on that side. Because the respective nations are supposed originally to have taken possession of those lands, with an intention of making the MIDDLE of that river, as a natural boundary, the line of separation between them. Thus Tacitus in speaking of the Usipians and Tencterians, who border on the Cattians, says, "their territory lies on the banks of the Rhine, where that river, still flowing in one regular channel, forms a sufficient boundary."
In areas defined by natural features, any change in the river's path also affects the territorial boundaries. Whatever land the river adds to one side will belong to the owner of that land. The nations are thought to have originally claimed these lands with the intention of using the MIDDLE of the river as a natural border. This acts as the dividing line between them. As Tacitus mentions when discussing the Usipians and Tencterians, who are next to the Cattians: "their territory lies on the banks of the Rhine, where that river, still flowing in one regular channel, forms a sufficient boundary."
VIII. Decisions like those above can only take place in instances, where the river has not altered its channel.107 For a river, dividing territories, is not to be considered barely as so much water, but as water flowing in a PARTICULAR CHANNEL, and inclosed WITHIN CERTAIN BANKS. For which reason an addition, a decrease, or such a change of small portions, as leaves the ancient appearance, upon the whole, nearly the same, allows us to consider the river as still the same. But if the whole face of the river is changed, the case will be entirely altered. For as a river may be entirely destroyed by the erection of dams upon the higher parts of its stream, or by digging canals, which carry off its waters in another direction: so by the desertion of its old channel, and breaking out for itself another course, it will not continue to be same river it was before, but will be completely a new one. In the same manner if a river has been dried up, the middle of its channel will remain as the boundary between neighbouring states, who in taking possession of the neighbouring territory originally intended the middle of such a river to be the line of separation, and under all changes to preserve the same as a permanent limit. But in doubtful cases, the territories bordering upon a river ought to be considered as arcifinious, because nothing can be a more apt mark of distinction than those impassable bounds assigned by nature. It very seldom indeed happens, that the artificial or civil admeasurements of territory can be regulated by such natural bounds, as they are, in general, the effect of original acquisition, or have been ceded by treaty.
VIII. Decisions like these can only happen in cases where the river hasn’t changed its course.107 A river that separates territories should not be seen simply as water, but as water flowing in a SPECIFIC CHANNEL and contained IN SOME BANKS. This is why a small addition or reduction or a change that keeps the overall appearance of the river nearly the same lets us consider it as still being the same river. However, if the entire shape of the river changes, then the situation is completely different. Just as a river can be completely destroyed by building dams upstream or by digging canals that redirect its flow, if it shifts to a new channel, it will no longer be the same river it once was, but will instead be a completely new one. Similarly, if a river has dried up, the center of its former channel will still mark the boundary between neighboring states, which originally intended for the middle of that river to serve as the dividing line and aimed to keep it as a permanent limit despite any changes. But in uncertain situations, the lands next to a river should be considered as arcifinious, since nothing marks a boundary better than those natural barriers made by nature. It’s quite rare for artificial or civil measures of territory to align with such natural boundaries, as these are generally the result of original possession or have been granted by treaty.
IX. Although in doubtful cases, it has been said that the territories on each side of a river are determined by the middle of the channel; yet it may happen, and has happened, that the sole right to a river may belong to the territories on one side of it. Because that on the opposite side was of later occupancy, and subsequent to the possession of that river by the other power: or because this sole right may have been so settled by treaty.
IX. Although in uncertain situations, it's been stated that the boundaries on each side of a river are determined by the middle of the channel, it can happen—and has happened—that the exclusive right to a river belongs to the territories on one side. This is because the land on the other side was occupied later and came after the other power had claimed possession of the river, or because this exclusive right was established by treaty.
X. It is not unworthy of observation that things which have had an owner, but have ceased to have one, become subject to the right by original acquisition. They are supposed to have been abandoned from the want of an owner, and therefore have returned to the original state of common stock. But at the same time it is proper to observe, that some times the original acquisition may have been made by a people or their sovereign, in such a manner as to give them or him not only those pre-eminent108 rights which constitute prerogative, but also the full title of property.
X. It's worth noting that things that once had an owner but no longer do become subject to the right of original acquisition. They're considered to have been abandoned due to the absence of an owner and, as a result, have returned to their original status as common property. However, it's also important to point out that sometimes the original acquisition may have been made by a people or their ruler in such a way that grants them or him not only the superior rights that define prerogative but also full ownership rights.
And this property again may be divided into smaller grants, and those again subdivided into other portions, to be held as dependent upon the original grantor, the Sovereign, or the Lord. Though the land may not be held by base service, or vassalage, yet it is possessed by some conditional tenure. For things are occupied by many kinds of right; among which may be reckoned the right of a person who expects property to be left to him under the condition of a trust. Seneca says, that an owner's being debarred from selling his lands, committing waste upon them, or even making improvements, is not to be taken as a proof that the property is not his. For that is a man's own, which he holds under any certain conditions. Since then property distributed in the manner above named is held of the sovereign, or of some intermediate Lord, who himself is tenant of the sovereign, it follows that any thing which wants an owner does not become the property of him, who can first seize it, but reverts to the state or to the sovereign.
And this property can again be divided into smaller grants, which can be subdivided into other portions, to be held as dependent on the original grantor, the Sovereign, or the Lord. Although the land may not be held by base service or vassalage, it is still owned through some conditional tenure. Various rights can be associated with ownership; one of these is the right of a person who expects an inheritance based on a trust. Seneca states that if an owner is prevented from selling their land, causing waste to it, or even making improvements, it doesn’t mean the property isn’t theirs. What belongs to a person is based on any specific conditions they hold. Since property distributed in this way is held by the sovereign or some intermediate Lord, who is a tenant of the sovereign, it follows that anything without an owner does not become the property of whoever seizes it first but instead reverts to the state or the sovereign.

WAR
CONFLICT
By Gari Melchers—From a panel painting in Library of Congress.
By Gari Melchers—From a panel painting in the Library of Congress.
CHAPTER IV.
Ownership of Desert Land through Occupancy, Possession, and Prescription.
Why Usucaption or Prescription cannot subsist between independent States, and Sovereigns—Long possession alleged as a ground of right—Inquiry into the intentions of men, which are not to be judged of by words alone—Intention to be judged of by acts—Intentions also to be judged of by omissions—How far length of time, silence, and non-possession, may confirm the conjecture of an abandoned right—Time immemorial generally thought to bar any claim—What constitutes time immemorial—Objections to a presumed desertion of property, considered without any conjecture, time immemorial appears to transfer and constitute a property—Inquiry whether persons yet unborn may thus be deprived of their right—Rules of civil law respecting Usucaption and Prescription as applied to the case of Sovereign Princes, explained.
Why Usucaption or Prescription can't exist between independent States and Sovereigns—Long possession claimed as a basis for rights—Examining people's intentions, which can't be judged solely by words—Intentions judged by actions—Intentions also judged by inactions—To what extent can the length of time, silence, and non-possession support the idea of an abandoned right—Time immemorial is generally believed to eliminate any claim—What defines time immemorial—Considering objections to a presumed abandonment of property, without any speculation, time immemorial seems to transfer and establish property—Exploring whether future generations can be deprived of their rights this way—Rules of civil law regarding Usucaption and Prescription as they apply to Sovereign Princes, explained.
I. A great difficulty arises here respecting the right to property by uninterrupted possession for any certain time. For though time is the great agent, by whose motion all legal concerns and rights may be measured and determined, yet it has no effectual power of itself to create an express title to any property. Now those rights were introduced by the civil law; and it is not their long continuance, but the express provisions of the municipal law, which gives them their validity. They are of no force therefore, in the opinion of Vasquez, between two independent nations or sovereigns, or between a free nation and a sovereign: between a sovereign and an individual who is not his subject, or between two subjects belonging to different kings or nations. Which indeed seems true; and is actually the case; for such points relating to persons and things, are not left to the law of nature, but are settled by the respective laws of each country. As the unqualified admission of this principle would lead to great inconvenience, and prevent the disputes of kings and nations respecting the bounds of territory from ever being adjusted; in order to eradicate the seeds of perpetual warfare and confusion, so repugnant to the interests and feelings of every people; the settlement of such boundaries is not left to the claims110 of prescriptive right; but the territories of each contending party are, in general, expressly defined by certain treaties.
I. A significant issue arises here regarding the right to property through uninterrupted possession over a specific period. While time is the main factor by which all legal matters and rights can be measured and determined, it doesn’t have the actual power to create an explicit title to any property. These rights were established by civil law; it's not their long duration but the explicit provisions of municipal law that give them validity. According to Vasquez, these rights hold no weight between two independent nations or sovereigns, or between a free nation and a sovereign; between a sovereign and an individual who isn’t their subject, or between two subjects from different kings or nations. This seems accurate and is indeed the case, as matters concerning people and property aren’t governed by natural law, but instead are determined by each country’s specific laws. Accepting this principle without qualification could lead to significant issues and would prevent disputes between kings and nations regarding territorial boundaries from ever being resolved; to eliminate the roots of ongoing warfare and confusion, which are against the interests and feelings of every nation, the resolution of such boundaries isn’t left to claims of prescriptive right; instead, the territories of each party involved are generally clearly defined by certain treaties.
II. To disturb any one in the actual and long possession of territory, has in all ages been considered as repugnant to the general interests and feelings of mankind. For we find in holy writ, that when the King of the Ammonites demanded the lands situated between the rivers Arnon and Jabok, and those extending from the deserts of Arabia to the Jordan, Jepthah opposed his pretentious by proving his own possession of the same for three hundred years, and asked why he and his ancestors had for so long a period neglected to make their claim. And the Lacedaemonians, we are informed by Isocrates, laid it down for a certain rule admitted among all nations, that the right to public territory as well as to private property was so firmly established by length of time, that it could not be disturbed; and upon this ground they rejected the claim of those who demanded the restoration of Messena.
II. Disturbing someone who has held onto their territory for a long time has always been seen as going against the common interests and feelings of humanity. For instance, in the scriptures, when the King of the Ammonites asked for the lands between the Arnon and Jabok rivers, as well as those stretching from the Arabian deserts to the Jordan, Jephthah countered his claim by proving he had possessed the land for three hundred years and questioned why he and his ancestors had waited so long to make their claim. Additionally, Isocrates tells us that the Lacedaemonians established a rule accepted by all nations that the right to public land as well as private property was so well established over time that it couldn't be contested; for this reason, they dismissed the demands for the return of Messena.
Resting upon a right like this, Philip the Second was induced to declare to Titus Quintius, "that he would restore the dominions which he had subdued himself, but would upon no consideration give up the possessions which he had derived from his ancestors by a just and hereditary title. Sulpitius, speaking against Antiochus, proved how unjust it was in him to pretend, that because the Greek Nations in Asia had once been under the subjection of his forefathers, he had a right to revive those claims, and to reduce them again to a state of servitude. And upon this subject two historians, Tacitus and Diodorus may be referred to; the former of whom calls such obsolete pretensions, empty talking, and the latter treats them as idle tales and fables. With these opinions Cicero, in his 2nd book of Offices, agrees, asking "what justice there can be in depriving an owner of the land, which he has for many ages quietly possessed?"
Resting on a right like this, Philip II was prompted to tell Titus Quintius that he would restore the territories he had conquered himself, but he would never give up the lands his ancestors rightfully inherited. Sulpitius, speaking against Antiochus, demonstrated how unjust it was for him to claim that because the Greek nations in Asia were once under his ancestors' control, he had the right to revive those claims and bring them back into servitude. Two historians can be referenced on this topic: Tacitus, who calls such outdated claims empty talk, and Diodorus, who considers them idle stories and fables. Cicero, in his second book of Offices, agrees with these views, asking what justice there is in taking away land from someone who has possessed it peacefully for many ages.
III. Can it be said, in order to justify the disturbance of long enjoyed possessions, that the rightful owner INTENDED to assert his claim, when he never manifested such intention by any outward visible act? The effect of right which depends upon a man's intentions can never follow from a bare conjecture of his will, unless he has declared and proved it by some express and visible act. For actions being the only evidence of intentions,111 intentions can never of themselves alone without such acts be the object of human laws. No conjectures indeed respecting the acts of the mind can be reduced to mathematical certainty, but only to the evidence of probability at the utmost. For men by their words may express intentions different from their real ones, and by their acts counterfeit intentions which they have not. The nature of human society, however, requires that all acts of the mind, when sufficiently indicated, should be followed by their due effects. Therefore the intention, which has been sufficiently indicated, is taken for granted against him who gave such indication.
III. Can we really say that to justify disrupting long-held possessions, the rightful owner INTENDED to assert his claim when he never showed any such intention through any visible actions? The effect of a right that depends on a person's intentions can never arise from mere speculation about their will unless they have declared and proven it through some clear and visible act. Since actions are the only proof of intentions,111 intentions alone, without such actions, can never be the focus of human laws. Indeed, no guesses about mental acts can be reduced to mathematical certainty, only to the highest degree of probability. People might express intentions through their words that are different from their true feelings, and their actions can fake intentions they don't actually have. However, the nature of human society demands that all sufficiently indicated mental acts should lead to their proper consequences. Therefore, the intention that has been clearly indicated is assumed against the person who made that indication.
IV. But to proceed to proofs derived from actions. A thing is understood to be abandoned, when it is cast away; except it be under particular circumstances, as throwing goods overboard in a storm to lighten a ship, where the owner is not supposed to have abandoned all intention of recovery, should it ever be in his power. Again, by giving up or cancelling a promissory note, a debt is deemed to be discharged. Paulus the Lawyer, says, a right to property may be renounced not only by words, but also by actions, or any other indication of the will. Thus, if an owner knowingly make a contract with any one who is in possession, treating him as if he were the rightful proprietor, he is naturally supposed to have relinquished his own pretensions. Nor is there any reason, why the same rule may not take place between sovereign princes, and independent states, as between individuals. In the same manner, a Lord by granting certain privileges to his Vassal, which he could not legally enjoy without a release from his former obligations, was supposed by such act to have given him his freedom. A power derived not from the civil law only, but from the law of nature, which allows every man to relinquish what is his own, and from a natural presumption that a person designed to do the act which he has given manifest proofs of his intention to do. In this sense, Ulpian may be rightly understood, where he says, that ACCEPTILATION or the verbal discharge of a debt is founded upon the law of nations.
IV. Now, let's move on to evidence based on actions. Something is considered abandoned when it is thrown away; unless there are specific circumstances, such as when goods are tossed overboard in a storm to lighten a ship, where the owner is not thought to have completely given up on any intention of recovering them if possible. Additionally, by giving up or canceling a promissory note, a debt is regarded as settled. Paulus the Lawyer states that a right to property can be relinquished not just through words, but also through actions or any other sign of intent. For instance, if an owner knowingly makes a contract with someone who is in possession, treating that person as if they were the rightful owner, it’s assumed that the owner has given up their own claims. There's also no reason why the same principle shouldn't apply between sovereign princes and independent states, just as it does between individuals. Similarly, a lord who grants specific privileges to their vassal, which the vassal couldn't lawfully enjoy without being released from previous obligations, is understood to have given them their freedom through that act. This power comes not only from civil law but also from natural law, which permits every person to give up what belongs to them, along with a natural assumption that a person intends to perform the act that they have clearly shown intent to do. In this view, Ulpian can be accurately understood when he states that Acceptance or the verbal release of a debt is based on the law of nations.
V. Even omissions, taking all proper circumstances into consideration, come under the cognizance of the law. Thus the person, who knowing of an act, and being present at the commission of it, passes it over in silence, seems to give his consent to it; this was admitted by the Mosaic Law. Unless indeed it can be shewn that the112 same person was hindered from speaking either by fear or some other pressing circumstance. Thus a thing is accounted as lost when all hope of recovering it is given up; as for instance, if a tame animal, which was in our possession, be seized and carried off by a wild beast. Goods too lost by shipwreck, Ulpian says, cease to be considered as our own, not immediately, but when they are lost beyond all possibility of being reclaimed, and when no proofs of the owner's intention to reclaim them can be discovered.
V. Even omissions, considering all relevant circumstances, are under the law's authority. So, if someone knows about an act and is present when it happens but says nothing, it seems like they are agreeing to it; this was recognized by Mosaic Law. Unless it can be shown that the same person was prevented from speaking due to fear or some other urgent situation. Likewise, something is considered lost when all hope of getting it back is given up; for example, if a pet we had is taken away by a wild animal. Goods lost in a shipwreck, according to Ulpian, are no longer seen as ours, not right away, but when they are lost without any chance of recovery, and when there’s no evidence of the owner's intention to recover them.
Now the case is altered, if persons were sent to inquire after the lost goods, or property, and a reward was promised to the finder. But if a person knows his property to be in the possession of another, and allows it to remain so for a length of time, without asserting his claim, unless there appear sufficient reasons for his silence, he is construed to have entirely abandoned all pretensions to the same. And to the same purpose he has said elsewhere, that a house is looked upon to be abandoned on account of the long silence of the proprietor.
Now the situation is different if people are sent to look for the lost goods or property, and a reward is offered to the finder. However, if someone knows their property is in someone else's possession and permits it to stay that way for a long time without claiming it—unless there are good reasons for their silence—they are considered to have completely given up any right to it. He has also stated elsewhere that a house is seen as abandoned due to the owner's prolonged silence.
The Emperor Antoninus Pius, in one of his rescripts, said there was but little justice in claiming interest upon money after a long period; for the length of time elapsed was an indication that the debtor had been excused from payment, from some motive of kindness.
The Emperor Antoninus Pius, in one of his letters, stated that there was hardly any fairness in charging interest on money after a long time; because the time that had passed suggested that the debtor had been forgiven for the payment out of some act of kindness.
There appears something similar to this in the nature of custom. For apart from the authority of civil laws, which regulate the time and manner of custom, and its introduction, it may arise from the indulgence of a sovereign to a conquered people. But the length of time from which custom derives the force of right, is not defined, but left to the arbitrary decision of what is sufficient to indicate general consent. But for silence to be taken as a valid presumption that property is deserted, two things are requisite: it must be a silence with a knowledge of the fact, and with a perfect freedom of will in the person concerned. For a silence founded in ignorance can have no weight; and where any other reason appears, the presumption of free consent must fail.
There’s something similar going on with customs. Beyond the authority of civil laws that govern when and how customs are established, they can also develop through a ruler's leniency toward a conquered people. However, the length of time a custom needs to gain the force of law isn't clearly defined; it’s left up to subjective judgment about what shows enough general agreement. For silence to be considered a valid assumption that property is abandoned, two conditions must be met: the silence must occur with knowledge of the situation, and the person involved must act freely. Silence based on ignorance doesn’t carry any weight, and if there are any other reasons at play, the assumption of free consent breaks down.
VI. Although the two requisites already named may be produced, yet other reasons have their weight; among which length of time is not the least important. For in the first place, it can scarcely happen, that for a great length of time a thing belonging to any one should not some way or other come to his knowledge, as time might113 supply many opportunities. Even if the civil law did not interpose to bar remote pretensions, the very nature of things would shew the reasonableness of a shorter period of limitation being allowed to present than to absent claimants. If impressions of fear were pleaded by any one in excuse, yet their influence would not be of perpetual duration, and length of time would unfold various means of security against such fears, either from resources within himself, or from the assistance of others. Escaping beyond the reach of him he dreaded, he might protest against his oppression, by appealing to proper judges and arbitrators.
VI. Even though the two mentioned requirements can be met, there are still other important factors to consider, and time is among the most significant. First, it's hard to imagine that over a long period of time someone wouldn't find out about something that belongs to them since time would likely offer many chances for discovery. Even if the law didn't step in to block distant claims, it makes sense that a shorter timeframe for bringing claims should apply to those who are present rather than those who are absent. If someone claimed they were too afraid to act, that fear wouldn't last forever, and time would reveal various ways to overcome those fears, whether through their own options or help from others. By distancing themselves from the person they feared, they could challenge their oppression by seeking justice from appropriate judges and arbitrators.
VII. Now as time immemorial, considered in a moral light, seems to have no bounds, silence for such a length of time appears sufficient to establish the presumption that all claim to a thing is abandoned, unless the strongest proofs to the contrary can be produced. The most able Lawyers have properly observed, that time according to the memory of man is not an hundred years, though probably it may not fall far short of that space. For a hundred years are the term beyond which human existence seldom reaches; a space, which in general completes three ages or generations of men. The Romans made this objection to Antiochus, that he claimed cities, which neither he himself, his father, nor his grandfather had ever possessed.
VII. Now, when we consider time in a moral sense, it seems to have no limits. A long period of silence makes it reasonable to assume that any claim to something is given up, unless there's strong evidence to prove otherwise. The best lawyers have pointed out that a hundred years isn’t the only measure of time according to human memory, although it may come close. A hundred years is typically the maximum human lifespan and generally encompasses three generations. The Romans challenged Antiochus on the basis that he claimed cities that neither he, nor his father, nor his grandfather had ever owned.
VIII. From the natural affection which all men have for themselves, and their property, an objection may be taken against the presumption of any one's abandoning a thing which belongs to him, and consequently negative acts, even though confirmed by a long period of time, are not sufficient to establish the above named conjecture.
VIII. Because all people naturally care for themselves and their belongings, one might argue against the idea that anyone would willingly give up something that is theirs. Therefore, negative actions, even if they have lasted a long time, are not enough to support this assumption.
Now considering the great importance deservedly attached to the settlement of CROWNS, all conjectures favourable to the possessors ought to be allowed. For if Aratus of Sicyon thought it a hard case, that PRIVATE possessions of fifty years' standing should be disturbed, how much weightier is that maxim of Augustus, that it is the character of a good man and a good subject to wish for no change in the present government, and, in the words, which Thucydides has assigned to Alcibiades, to support the constitution, under which he has been born? But if no such rules in favour of possession could be adduced, yet a more weighty objection might114 be found against the presumption, drawn from the inclination of every one to preserve his own right, which is the improbability of one man's allowing another to usurp his property for any length of time, without declaring and asserting his own right.
Now considering the great importance rightly attached to the settlement of CROWNS, all favorable assumptions about the owners should be accepted. If Aratus of Sicyon thought it unreasonable that CONFIDENTIAL possessions that have been held for fifty years should be disturbed, how much more significant is Augustus's principle that a good person and a good citizen should desire no changes in the current government, and, in the words attributed to Alcibiades by Thucydides, support the system under which they were born? But even if no such rules favoring possession could be presented, a stronger argument against the assumption could be found. This argument stems from the natural inclination of everyone to protect their own rights, which makes it unlikely that one person would allow another to take over their property for an extended period without declaring and asserting their own rights.
IX. Perhaps it may reasonably be said, that this matter does not rest upon presumption only, but that it is a rule, introduced by the voluntary law of Nations, that uninterrupted possession, against which no claim has been asserted, will entirely transfer such property to the actual possessor. For it is most likely that all nations by consent gave their sanction to such a practice, as conducive to their common peace. The term uninterrupted possession therefore has been very properly used to signify, as Sulpitius says in Livy, "that which has been held by one uniform tenour of right, without intermission." Or as the same author, in another place, calls it, "perpetual possession, that has never been called in question." For a transitory possession creates no title. And it was this exception which the Numidians had urged against the Carthaginians, alleging that as opportunity offered, sometimes the Kings of the Numidians had appropriated to themselves the disputed possessions, which had always remained in the hands of the stronger party.
IX. It can reasonably be said that this issue isn't just based on assumptions, but rather that there's a rule established by the agreed-upon laws of nations: uninterrupted possession, which has no claims against it, fully transfers ownership to the current possessor. It's highly likely that all nations agreed to this practice as it promotes their mutual peace. The term uninterrupted possession has been accurately used to mean, as Sulpitius says in Livy, "that which has been held under a consistent right, without interruption." Or as the same author states elsewhere, "perpetual possession, which has never been challenged." Because temporary possession does not create a valid title. This was the argument the Numidians presented against the Carthaginians, claiming that when the opportunity arose, sometimes the Kings of the Numidians had taken the disputed properties, which had always been in the hands of the stronger party.
X. But here another question, and that of considerable difficulty, arises, which is, to decide, whether, by this desertion, persons yet unborn may be deprived of their rights. If we maintain that they MAY NOT, the rule already established would be of no avail towards settling the tranquillity of kingdoms, and security of property. For in most things some thing is due to the interests of posterity. But if we affirm that they MAY, it then seems wonderful that silence should prejudice the rights of those, who were unable to speak, before they had any existence, and that the act of OTHERS should operate to their injury. To clear up this point, we must observe that no rights can belong to a person before he has any existence, as, in the language of the schools, there can be no accident without a substance. Wherefore if a Prince, from urgent motives of policy, and for the advantage of his own native dominions, and subjects, should decline to accept an additional sovereignty, or for the same reasons, should relinquish that, which he had already accepted, he would not be charged with injuring115 his heirs and successors, then unborn, who could have no rights before they had a natural existence.
X. But here comes another tough question: can unborn people lose their rights because of this abandonment? If we say they CANNOT, then the established rule won’t help with maintaining peace in kingdoms and protecting property. In many cases, we owe something to future generations. But if we say they CAN, it seems strange that the silence of those who couldn’t speak yet, because they didn’t exist, could harm their rights, and that the actions of OTHERS could be detrimental to them. To clarify this, we need to note that no rights can belong to a person before they exist, just like there can’t be an accident without a substance, as the scholars say. Therefore, if a prince, for important political reasons and for the benefit of his own territories and people, chooses not to accept more power, or for the same reasons, decides to give up power he’s already taken, he wouldn’t be considered to be harming115 his heirs and future successors, who couldn’t have any rights before they had a natural existence.
Now as a sovereign may EXPRESSLY declare a change of his will respecting such dominions, so that change may, in certain cases, be implied without such declaration.
Now, just as a ruler can CLEARLY announce a change of his decision regarding his territories, that change can, in some situations, be understood without such an announcement.
In consequence of such a change either expressed or implied, before the rights of heirs and successors can be supposed to have any existence, the possession may be considered as entirely abandoned. The case here has been considered according to the LAW OF NATURE: for the civil law, among other fictions, introduced that of the law's personating those, who are not yet in being, and so preventing any occupancy from taking place to their prejudice; a regulation of law established upon no slight grounds in order to preserve estates in families, although every means of PERPETUATING property to individuals, which prevents its transfer from hand to hand, may in some measure be detrimental to the public interest. From whence it is a received opinion, that length of time will give a property in those fees, which were originally conveyed, not by right of succession, but by virtue of primitive investiture. Covarruvias, a lawyer of great judgment, supports this opinion with the strongest arguments in favour of primogeniture, and applies it to estates left in trust. For nothing can prevent the civil law from instituting a right, which, though it cannot be lawfully alienated by the act of one party without consent of the other, yet, to avoid uncertainty in the tenure of present proprietors, may be lost by neglect of claim for a length of time. Still the parties thus deprived may maintain a personal action against those, or their heirs, through whose neglect their right has been forfeited.
As a result of such a change, whether stated or implied, the rights of heirs and successors can only be considered valid if possession is not seen as completely abandoned. This situation has been discussed according to the Natural Law: because civil law, among other fictions, allows for the creation of rights for those who are not yet alive, preventing any occupancy that could harm them. This legal principle is established on solid grounds to keep estates within families, even though the various methods of Keeping it going property for individuals, which stop it from being passed around, may somewhat harm the public interest. Therefore, it is widely believed that over time, ownership can arise for those properties that were originally given out not through succession but through primary endowment. Covarruvias, a highly regarded lawyer, backs this view with strong arguments in favor of primogeniture and applies it to estates held in trust. Nothing stops civil law from creating a right that, while it cannot be legally transferred by one party without the other’s approval, can still be lost due to the lack of action over time to protect current holders from uncertainty in their ownership. However, the parties who lose their rights can still file a personal claim against those, or their heirs, responsible for the neglect that caused the forfeiture of their rights.
XI. It is an inquiry of importance whether the law of usucaption and prescription, if it prevail in a prince's dominions, can be applied to the tenure of the crown, and all its prerogatives. Many legal writers, who have treated of the nature of sovereign power according to the principles of the Roman civil law, seem to affirm that it may be so applied. But this is an opinion to which we cannot accede in its full extent. For to make a law binding upon any one, it is requisite that the legislator should possess both power and will. A legislator is not bound by his law, as by the irrevocable and unchangeable controul of a superior. But occasions may arise that116 will demand an alteration or even a repeal of the law which he has made. Yet a legislator may be bound by his own law, not directly as a legislator, but as an individual forming part of the community: and that too according to natural equity, which requires that all the component parts should bear a reference to the whole. We find in holy writ, this rule observed by Saul in the beginning of his reign.
XI. It is an important question whether the laws of usucaption and prescription, if they apply in a prince's territories, can also be applied to the crown's tenure and all its privileges. Many legal scholars who have discussed the nature of sovereign power based on Roman civil law seem to suggest that it can. However, we cannot fully agree with this view. For a law to be binding on anyone, the legislator must have both the power and the intention to enforce it. A legislator is not confined by their laws in the same way they are by an unchangeable authority above them. However, circumstances may arise that116 call for a change or even a repeal of the law they established. Still, a legislator may be bound by their own law, not directly as a legislator, but as a member of the community; and this aligns with natural equity, which demands that all parts relate to the whole. We see this principle reflected in the actions of Saul at the beginning of his reign in sacred scriptures.
Now that rule does not take place here. For we are considering the lawgiver, not as a part but as the REPRESENTATIVE and SOVEREIGN of the whole community. Nor indeed can any such intention in the lawgiver be presumed to have existed. For legislators are not supposed to comprehend themselves within the rule of the law, except where the nature and subject of it are general. But sovereignty is not to be compared with other things; it so far surpasses them in the nobleness of its end, and the dignity of its nature. Nor is any civil law to be found which either does, or designs to comprehend sovereign power within the rules of prescription.
Now, that rule doesn’t apply here. We’re looking at the lawmaker not as a part but as the REPRESENTATIVE and Sovereign of the entire community. In fact, it can’t be assumed that any such intention existed in the lawmaker. Legislators aren’t expected to include themselves within the rule of the law, except when the law’s nature and purpose are general. But sovereignty can’t be compared to other things; it greatly outshines them in the nobleness of its purpose and the dignity of its nature. There’s no civil law that includes or intends to include sovereign power within the limits of established rules.
CHAPTER IX.22
When Jurisdiction and Property Come to an End.
Jurisdiction and property cease, when the family of the owner has become extinct—In what manner the rights of a people may become extinct—A people becomes extinct when its essential parts are destroyed—A people does not become extinct by emigration—The existence of separate states not destroyed by a federal union.
Jurisdiction and property end when the owner’s family has died out. Here’s how a group can become extinct: a group becomes extinct when its essential parts are removed. A group doesn’t become extinct just because members move away. The existence of separate states doesn’t disappear due to a federal union.
I. and II. After the preceding inquiries into the manner in which private property as well as sovereign power may be acquired and transferred, the manner, in which they cease, naturally comes next under consideration. It has been shewn before that the right to property may be lost by neglect; for property can continue no longer than while the will of ownership continues. There is also another manner in which property may cease to exist, without any express or implied alienation: and that is where the family either of a sovereign, or an owner, becomes extinct, a contingency for which provision must be made somewhat similar to a succession to the property of one who dies intestate. Wherefore if any one die, without any declaration of his will, and have no relations by blood, all the right, which he had, becomes extinct, and reverts, if a sovereign, to the hands of the nation, except where express provisions of law have been made to the contrary.
I. and II. After looking into how private property and sovereign power can be acquired and transferred, we now consider how they can cease to exist. It has already been shown that the right to property can be lost through neglect because property can only exist as long as the intention to own it remains. There's also another way property can cease to exist without any explicit or implied transfer: if the family of a sovereign or an owner dies out, similar to how property is dealt with when someone passes away without a will. Therefore, if someone dies without expressing their wishes and has no blood relatives, all their rights become void and, if it’s a sovereign, revert to the nation, unless specific legal provisions state otherwise.
III. The same mode of reasoning applies to a nation. Isocrates, and after him the Emperor Julian, has said that states are immortal, or may be so. For a people is one of that kind of bodies which are formed of distinct parts, following each other in regular succession, and supplying the place of the deceased. This body goes under one name, forming, as Plutarch says, one constitution;118 or, in the language of Paulus the Lawyer, one spirit. Now the spirit or constitution in a people is the full and perfect harmony of civil life, from which emanates the sovereign power, the very soul of all government, and, as Seneca says, the vital breath which so many thousands draw.
III. The same line of thinking applies to a nation. Isocrates, and later the Emperor Julian, stated that states are immortal or can be. A people is like a body made up of different parts that replace each other in a regular way, ensuring continuity even after some members pass away. This body is known by one name, forming, as Plutarch puts it, one constitution;118 or, as Paulus the Lawyer describes it, one spirit. The spirit or constitution of a people is the complete and harmonious structure of civil life, from which the sovereign power arises—the very essence of all government, and, as Seneca says, the vital force that sustains so many thousands.
These artificial bodies bear a close resemblance to the natural body, which, notwithstanding the alteration of its component particles, loses not its identity, so long as the general form remains. And therefore in the passage of Seneca, where he says, that no one is the same in his old age that he was in his youth, he means only as to natural substance. In the same manner Heraclitus, as cited by Plato in Cratylus, and Seneca in the place already quoted, has said, that we cannot descend TWICE into the same river. But Seneca afterwards corrects himself, adding, that the river retains its name, though the watery particles of which it is composed are perpetually changing. So Aristotle, too, in comparing nations to rivers, has said that the rivers are always called by the same name, though their several parts are fluctuating every moment. Nor is it the name alone which continues, but that principle also which Conon calls the constitutional system of the body, and Philo the spirit, that holds it together. So that a people, as Alphenus and Plutarch, in speaking of the late, but unerring approach of divine vengeance, maintain, though not one of its members of a former period be now living, is the same at present that it was a hundred years ago, as long as the spirit, which first framed and afterwards kept the body together, preserves its identity.
These artificial bodies look a lot like natural bodies, which, despite the changes in their individual parts, don’t lose their identity as long as their overall shape stays the same. So when Seneca says that no one is the same in old age as they were in youth, he’s just referring to natural substance. Similarly, Heraclitus, as quoted by Plato in Cratylus and Seneca in the previously mentioned passage, states that we cannot step into the same river twice. However, Seneca later refines this point, noting that the river keeps its name even though the water particles that make it up are constantly changing. Aristotle also compares nations to rivers, saying that rivers are always known by the same name, even though their parts are always shifting. It’s not just the name that persists, but also that principle which Conon calls the constitutional system of the body, and Philo calls the spirit, which keeps it intact. Thus, as Alphenus and Plutarch state regarding the inevitable arrival of divine retribution, even if not a single member of a previous generation is alive, the community today is still the same as it was a hundred years ago, as long as the spirit that originally formed and then maintained the body keeps its identity.
Hence has originated the custom, in addressing a people, of ascribing to them, who are now living, what happened to the same people many ages before; as may be seen both in profane historians, and in the books of holy writ. So in Tacitus, Antony the First serving under Vespasian, reminds the soldiers of the third legion of what they had done in former times, how under Mark Antony they had beaten the Parthians, and under Corbulo the Armenians. There was more of prejudice, therefore, than truth in the reproach, which Piso cast upon the Athenians of his own time, refusing to consider them as Athenians since they had become extinct by so many disasters, and were nothing more than a base mixture of all nations of the earth. We say there was more of119 prejudice than truth in this reproach. For though such a mixture might diminish the dignity, it could not destroy the existence of a people. Nor was he himself ignorant of this. For he reproaches the Athenians of his own day with their feeble efforts in former times against Philip of Macedon, and their ingratitude to their best friends. Now as a change of its component parts cannot destroy the identity of a people, not even for a thousand years or more; so neither can it be denied that a people may lose its existence in two ways; either by the extinction of all its members, or by the extinction of its form and spirit.
Thus has developed the practice, when speaking to a people, of attributing to them the actions of the same group many ages ago; this is evident in both secular historians and the books of sacred scripture. For example, Tacitus describes how Antony the First, serving under Vespasian, reminds the soldiers of the third legion about their past achievements, including defeating the Parthians under Mark Antony and the Armenians under Corbulo. Therefore, there was more prejudice than truth in the criticism that Piso directed at the Athenians of his time, dismissing them as no longer true Athenians due to their numerous disasters, suggesting they were merely a lowly mix of all the nations. We assert that there was more of119prejudice than truth in this claim. Although such a mixture might lessen their dignity, it could not erase the existence of a people. Piso was not unaware of this himself. He scornfully notes the Athenians of his time for their weak attempts against Philip of Macedon and their ingratitude towards their best allies. Just as a change in the makeup of a people does not erase their identity, even over a thousand years or more; it’s also undeniable that a people can lose their existence in two ways: either through the complete extinction of their members or through the loss of their identity and spirit.
IV. A body is said to die, when its essential parts, and necessary form of subsistence are destroyed. To the former case may be referred the instance of nations swallowed up by the sea, as Plato relates, and others whom Tertullian mentions: or if a people should be destroyed by an earthquake, of which there are many instances in history, or should destroy themselves, as the Sidonians and Saguntines did. We are informed by Pliny, that in ancient Latium, fifty-three nations were destroyed without a single trace of them remaining.
IV. A body is considered dead when its essential parts and necessary means of survival are gone. The first case includes nations swallowed by the sea, as Plato describes, and others mentioned by Tertullian. This can also apply if a people are wiped out by an earthquake, of which there are many historical examples, or if they bring about their own destruction, like the Sidonians and Saguntines did. Pliny tells us that in ancient Latium, fifty-three nations were destroyed without leaving a single trace behind.
But what, it may be said will be the case, if out of such a nation so few remain that they cannot form a people? They will then retain that property, which they had before as private persons, but not in a public capacity. The same is the case with every community.
But what happens if, from such a nation, so few people are left that they can't form a society? They will still keep the property they had as individuals, but not as part of a public group. The same applies to every community.
V. A people loses its form, by losing all or some of those rights, which it had in common; and this happens, either when every individual is reduced to slavery, as the Mycenaeans, who were sold by the Argives; the Olynthians by Philip, the Thebans by Alexander, and the Brutians, made public slaves by the Romans: Or when, though they retain their personal liberty, they are deprived of the rights of sovereignty. Thus Livy informs us respecting Capua, that the Romans determined, though it might be inhabited as a city, that there should be no municipal body, no senate, no public council, no magistrates, but that deprived of political deliberation, and sovereign authority, the inhabitants should be considered as a multitude; subject to the jurisdiction of a Praefect sent from Rome. Therefore Cicero, in his first speech against Rullus, says that there was no image of a republic left at Capua. The same may be said of nations reduced to the form of Provinces, and of those subjugated120 by another power; as Byzantium was to Perinthus, by the Emperor Severus, and Antioch to Laodicea, by Theodosius.
V. A people loses its identity when they lose all or some of the rights they once shared; this can happen either when every individual is made a slave, like the Mycenaeans who were sold by the Argives, or the Olynthians by Philip, the Thebans by Alexander, and the Brutians who were turned into public slaves by the Romans. Alternatively, it can occur when, even if they keep their personal freedom, they are stripped of their rights to govern themselves. Livy points out that regarding Capua, the Romans decided that, even though it could be inhabited as a city, there would be no municipal body, no senate, no public council, and no magistrates, meaning that the residents, devoid of political decision-making and sovereign authority, would be treated as a mass, subject to the authority of a Prefect sent from Rome. Therefore, Cicero, in his first speech against Rullus, states that there was no sign of a republic left in Capua. The same can be said for nations turned into Provinces and those conquered by another power; like Byzantium was to Perinthus under Emperor Severus, and Antioch to Laodicea under Theodosius.120
VI. But if a nation should emigrate, either spontaneously, on account of scarcity or any other calamity, or if by compulsion, which was the case with the people of Carthage in the third Punic war, while she retains her form, she does not cease to be a people; and still less so, if only the walls of her cities be destroyed, and therefore when the Lacedaemonians refused to admit the Messenians to swear to the peace of Greece, because the walls of their city were destroyed, it was carried against them in the General Assembly of the Allies.
VI. But if a nation were to emigrate, whether voluntarily due to scarcity or some other disaster, or if it was forced to, like the people of Carthage during the third Punic War, it still retains its identity as a people; and even less so if only the walls of its cities are destroyed. This was evident when the Lacedaemonians refused to let the Messenians swear to the peace of Greece because their city walls were gone, leading to a resolution against them in the General Assembly of the Allies.
Nor does it make any difference in the argument, whatever the form of government may be, whether regal, aristocratical, or democratical. The Roman people for instance was the same, whether under kings, consuls, or emperors. Even indeed under the most absolute form, the people is the same that it was in its independent state, while the king governs it as head of that people, and not of any other. For the sovereignty which resides in the king as the head, resides in the people likewise as the body of which he is the head; and therefore in an elective government, if the king or the royal family should become extinct, the rights of sovereignty, as it has been already shewn, would revert to the people.
It doesn’t matter what type of government it is—whether it’s a monarchy, an aristocracy, or a democracy. The Roman people, for example, were essentially the same under kings, consuls, or emperors. Even under the most absolute monarchy, the people remained as they were in their independent state, while the king ruled them as the leader of that people, not as a separate entity. The sovereignty held by the king as the leader also resides in the people as the group he leads; therefore, in an elective government, if the king or royal family were to die out, the rights of sovereignty, as previously shown, would go back to the people.
Nor is this argument overthrown by the objection drawn from Aristotle, who says that, if the form of government is changed, the state no longer continues to be the same, as the harmony of a piece of music is entirely changed by a transition from the Doric to the Phrygian measure.
Nor is this argument disproven by the objection raised by Aristotle, who says that if the form of government changes, the state no longer remains the same, just like the harmony of a piece of music is completely altered by a shift from the Doric to the Phrygian measure.
Now it is to be observed, that an artificial system may possess many different forms, as in an army under one supreme commander there are many subordinate parts, and inferior powers, while in the operations of the field it appears but as one body. In same manner, the union of the legislative and executive in a state gives it the appearance of one form, while the distinction between subject and sovereign, and their still mutual relation give it another. The executive power is the politician's concern; the judicial, the lawyer's. Nor did this escape the notice of Aristotle. For he says it belongs to a science different from that of politics to determine whether, under a change in the form of government,121 the debts contracted under the old system ought to be discharged by the members of the new. He does this, to avoid the fault which he blames in many other writers, of making digressions from one subject to another.
Now, it should be noted that an artificial system can have many different forms. Just like an army with one supreme commander has many subordinate units and lesser powers, it acts as one cohesive body in the field. Similarly, the combination of the legislative and executive branches in a state gives it a unified appearance, while the distinction between the governed and the governing, along with their ongoing relationship, offers a different perspective. The executive power is the responsibility of politicians, while the judicial power falls to lawyers. Aristotle was aware of this as well. He mentioned that it is a matter for a different field of study, not politics, to decide whether debts owed under an old government should be paid by members of a new one after a change in governance.121 He makes this point to avoid the mistake he criticizes in many other writers, who tend to stray from one topic to another.
It is evident that a state, which from a commonwealth has become a regal government, is answerable for the debts incurred before that change. For it is the same people, possessing all the same rights, and powers, which are now exercised in a different manner, being no longer vested in the body, but in the head. This furnishes a ready answer to a question some times asked, which is, what place in general assemblies of different states, ought to be assigned to a sovereign, to whom the people of a commonwealth have transferred all their power? Undoubtedly the same place which that people or their representatives had occupied before in such councils. Thus in the Amphictyonic council, Philip of Macedon succeeded to the place of the Phocensians. So, on the other hand, the people of a commonwealth occupy the place assigned to sovereigns.
It’s clear that a state that has transitioned from a commonwealth to a royal government is responsible for the debts incurred before that change. The same people have all the same rights and powers, but now they’re exercised differently, as they are no longer held by the community but by the leader. This provides a straightforward answer to a question sometimes asked: what position in the general assemblies of different states should be given to a sovereign to whom the people of a commonwealth have transferred all their power? Certainly, it should be the same position that the people or their representatives occupied before in those councils. For example, in the Amphictyonic council, Philip of Macedon took the place of the Phocensians. Conversely, the people of a commonwealth occupy the position assigned to sovereigns.
VIII.23 Whenever two nations become united, their rights, as distinct states, will not be lost, but will be communicated to each other. Thus the rights of the Albans in the first place, and afterwards those of the Sabines, as we are informed by Livy, were transferred to the Romans, and they became one government. The same reasoning holds good respecting states, which are joined, not by a federal Union, but by having one sovereign for their head.
VIII.23 Whenever two nations come together, their rights as separate states don't disappear; they are shared with one another. So, the rights of the Albans first, and later the Sabines, as Livy tells us, were passed on to the Romans, and they formed a single government. This same logic applies to states that are united, not through a federal Union, but by having a single sovereign as their leader.
IX. On the other hand, it may happen that a nation, originally forming but one state, may be divided, either by mutual consent, or by the fate of war; as the body of the Persian Empire was divided among the successors of Alexander. When this is the case, many sovereign powers arise in the place of one, each enjoying its independent rights, whatever belonged to the original state, in common, must either continue to be governed as a common concern, or be divided in equitable proportions.
IX. On the other hand, it can happen that a nation, which initially was one state, gets divided, either by mutual agreement or as a result of war; like how the Persian Empire was split among the successors of Alexander. When this occurs, multiple sovereign powers emerge in place of one, each having its own independent rights. Anything that belonged to the original state collectively must either keep being managed as a common issue or be fairly divided.
To this head may be referred the voluntary separation, which takes place when a nation sends out colonies. For122 thus a new people as it were is formed, enjoying their own rights; and as Thucydides says, sent out not upon terms of slavery, but equality, yet still owing respect and obedience to their mother-country. The same writer, speaking of the second colony sent by the Corinthians to Epidamnus, says, "they gave public notice that such as were willing to go should enjoy equal privileges with those that staid at home."
To this point, we can talk about voluntary separation, which happens when a nation sends out colonies. For122 this creates a new people, so to speak, who enjoy their own rights; and as Thucydides mentions, they are sent out not under conditions of slavery, but of equality, while still owing respect and loyalty to their home country. The same author, when discussing the second colony sent by the Corinthians to Epidamnus, states, "they made a public announcement that those who were willing to go would have the same rights as those who stayed behind."
CHAPTER X.
The Duty from Property.
Origin and nature of the obligation to restore what belongs to another—Obligation to restore to the rightful owner the profits that have accrued from the unjust possession of his personal or real property—A bona-fide possessor not bound to restitution if the thing has perished—Such bona-fide possessor bound to the restitution of the profits remaining in his hands—Bound to make reparation for the consumption occasioned by his possession—A possessor not bound to make a recompence for a gift, with an exception—The sale of any thing that has been bought, obliges the seller to make restitution, with a certain exception—In what cases a bona-fide purchaser of what belongs to another may retain the price, or a part of it—He who has purchased a thing of one who is not the real owner, cannot return it to that seller—The possessor of a thing whose real owner is unknown, not bound to give it up to any one—A person not bound to restore money received upon a dishonest account, or for service done—Opinion that the property of things valued by weight, number and measure, may be transferred without consent of the owner, refuted.
Origin and nature of the obligation to return what belongs to someone else—The duty to return to the rightful owner any profits gained from unfairly possessing their personal or real property—A good-faith possessor doesn’t have to return the item if it has been lost—However, a good-faith possessor must return any profits they still have—They must also compensate for the use caused by their possession—A possessor isn’t required to repay for a gift, with one exception—Selling something that was bought requires the seller to provide restitution, with a specific exception—Under what conditions a good-faith buyer of something that belongs to someone else can keep the price, or part of it—Someone who buys an item from someone who isn’t the actual owner can’t return it to that seller—The possessor of an item whose true owner is unknown isn’t obligated to give it to anyone—A person isn’t required to return money received through deception or for services rendered—The idea that ownership of items measured by weight, number, and measure can change hands without the owner's consent is contested.
I. Having explained in the preceding part the nature and rights of property, it remains for us to consider the obligation which we incur from thence.
I. Having explained in the previous section the nature and rights of property, we now need to consider the obligations that arise from them.
Now this obligation proceeds from things either in existence, or not in existence, comprehending, under the name of things, the right also over persons, as far as is beneficial to us. The obligation, arising from things in existence, binds the person, who has our property in his power, to do all he can to put us again into possession of it. We have said to do all he can: for no one is bound to an impossibility, nor to procure the restoration of a thing at his own expence. But he is obliged to make every discovery which may enable another to recover his own property. For as in a community of things, it was necessary that a certain equality should be preserved, to prevent one man from having an undue share of the common stock; so upon the introduction of property, it became, as it were, a kind of established rule of society among the owners, that the person, who had in his possession anything belonging to another should restore it to the lawful proprietor. For if the right of property124 extended no farther than barely to enable the owner to make a demand of restitution without ENFORCING it by LEGAL PROCESS, it would rest upon a very weak foundation, and scarce be worth the holding. Nor does it make any difference, whether a person has fairly or fraudulently obtained possession of a thing not belonging to him. For he is equally bound to restore it, both by the positive obligations of law, and by the principles of natural justice. The Lacedaemonians had nominally cleared themselves of the crime, by condemning Phaebidas, who, in violation of their treaty with the Thebans, had seized upon the citadel of Cadmea, but in reality they where guilty of injustice, by retaining the possession. And Xenophon has remarked that, such a singular act of injustice was punished by the signal providence of God. For the same reason Marcus Crassus, and Quintus Hortensius, are blamed for having retained part of an inheritance left them by a will, the making of which had been procured upon false pretences, but in the management of which they had no share. Cicero blames them, because it is understood to be settled by general agreement, that all men are to restore what they are possessed of, if another is proved to be the rightful owner. A principle by which property is firmly secured, and upon which all special contracts are founded, and any exceptions to this rule, contained in them, must be expressly named as such. This throws light upon the passage of Tryphoninus. "If a robber, says he, has spoiled me of my goods, which he has deposited with Seius, who knows nothing of the fact; the question is, whether he ought to restore them to the robber or to me. If we consider him as giving and receiving on his own account, GOOD FAITH requires that the deposit should be restored to him who gave it. If we consider the equity of the whole case, including all the persons concerned in the transaction, the goods should be restored to me, as the person unjustly deprived of them." And he properly adds, "I prove it to be strict justice to assign every one his due, without infringing on the more just claims of another." Now it has been shewn that the justest title on which any one can claim, is that which is coaeval with the property itself. From whence the principle laid down by Tryphoninus, that if any one unknowingly received goods as a deposit, and afterwards discovers them to be his own, he is not bound to restore them. And the question, which the same125 author puts a little before respecting goods deposited by one, whose property had been confiscated, is better settled by this principle, than by what he says elsewhere on the utility of punishment. For as to the nature of property, it makes no difference, whether it arises from the law of nations, or from the civil law; as it always carries with it peculiar qualities, among which may be reckoned the obligation, under which every possessor lies to restore a thing to its rightful owner. And hence it is said by Martian, that according to the law of nations, restitution may be demanded, of those, who have no legal title to the possession. From the same origin springs the maxim of Ulpian, that whoever has found a thing belonging to another, is bound to restore it, even without claiming or receiving a reward for finding it. The profits also are to be restored, with a deduction only of reasonable charges.
Now this obligation arises from things either currently existing or not, covering, under the term "things," the rights we have over people, to the extent that it benefits us. The obligation that comes from existing things requires the person who has our property in their control to do everything possible to return it to us. We’ve said “do everything possible” because no one is obligated to do the impossible or to return something at their own expense. However, they must make every effort to help someone else recover their own property. In a community of resources, it was necessary to maintain a certain balance to prevent any one person from unfairly holding too much of the common resources; with the introduction of property, it became an established rule among owners that anyone who has something belonging to another should return it to the rightful owner. If property rights only allowed the owner to demand its return without enforcing it through legal action, it would rest on a very weak foundation and hardly be worth keeping. It doesn’t matter if someone obtained possession of something fairly or fraudulently; they are equally obligated to return it by both legal and moral principles. The Lacedaemonians might have nominally absolved themselves of wrongdoing by condemning Phaebidas, who captured the citadel of Cadmea against their treaty with the Thebans, but in reality, they were guilty of injustice by keeping possession of it. Xenophon pointed out that such a unique act of injustice was punished by God’s clear providence. Similarly, Marcus Crassus and Quintus Hortensius are criticized for retaining part of an inheritance they received from a will that was created under false pretenses, even though they had no part in making the will. Cicero criticizes them because it is generally accepted that everyone must return what they hold if it can be proven that someone else is the rightful owner. This principle firmly secures property rights and serves as the foundation for all specific contracts, with exceptions to this rule needing to be explicitly stated. This clarifies a statement from Tryphoninus: "If a robber," he says, "has stolen my goods, which he has left with Seius, who is unaware of the situation; the question is whether they should be returned to the robber or to me. If we consider him as acting for himself, good faith requires that the deposit should be returned to the one who gave it. However, if we look at the overall fairness of the situation, considering all parties involved, the goods should be returned to me, since I am the one unjustly deprived of them." He rightly adds, "It is strict justice to assign everyone their due without violating another's more just claims." It has been shown that the most legitimate claim anyone can have is one that coincides with the property itself. This leads to Tryphoninus’s principle that if someone unknowingly received goods as a deposit and later realizes they are their own, they do not have to return them. The question he raises earlier about goods deposited by someone whose property has been confiscated is better resolved by this principle than by what he discusses elsewhere regarding the usefulness of punishment. Regarding the nature of property, it makes no difference whether it comes from international law or civil law, as it always carries specific qualities, including the obligation for every possessor to return something to its rightful owner. Thus, Martian states that under international law, restitution can be demanded from those who have no legal claim to possession. From this same basis arises Ulpian's maxim that whoever finds something belonging to another is obligated to return it, even without claiming or receiving a reward for finding it. The profits must also be returned, with only reasonable expenses deducted.
II. Respecting things, non-existent, or whose identity cannot be ascertained, is a principle generally received among mankind, that the person, who has become richer by that property, of which the rightful owner has been dispossessed, is bound to make him reparation in proportion to the benefit, which he has derived from his property. For the true proprietor may be justly said to have lost, what HE has gained. Now the very introduction of property was intended to preserve that equality, which assigns to every one his own.
II. Respecting things that don't exist or whose identity can't be determined is a principle widely accepted among people. If someone becomes richer because of property that rightfully belongs to someone else, they are obligated to compensate the original owner based on the benefit they've gained from it. The true owner can rightly be said to have lost what the other person has gained. The very idea of property was meant to maintain that equality, ensuring everyone has their own.
Cicero has said, that it is contrary to natural justice, for one man to improve his own advantage at the expence of another, and in another place, that nature does not allow us to increase our resources, riches, and power, from the spoils of others. There is so much of equity in this saying, that many legal writers have made it the basis of their definitions, to supply the deficiency of the strict letter of the law, always appealing to equity as the most sure and clear rule of action.
Cicero has stated that it's against natural justice for one person to gain an advantage at the expense of another. He also noted that nature doesn’t permit us to enhance our resources, wealth, and power by taking from others. This statement holds so much fairness that many legal scholars have used it as the foundation for their definitions, aiming to fill in the gaps of the strict letter of the law, always turning to equity as the most reliable and clear guideline for action.
If any one employ a slave, as his factor, to trade for him, he is bound by the acts of that factor, unless he has previously given notice that he is not to be trusted. But even if such notice has been given, where the factor has a property in the concern, or the master a profit, the notice shall be deemed a fraud. For, says Proculus, whoever makes an advantage from the loss of another is guilty of a fraud; a term implying every thing repugnant to natural justice and equity. He, who, at the instance126 of a mother, has put in bail for her son's advocate, has no action on the case against the advocate for what is called an assumpsit or undertaking. For it was not strictly his business, which the advocate managed; the bail was put in at the INSTANCE of the MOTHER. Yet according to the opinion of Papinian, an action on the case for the assumpsit, or undertaking will lie against the advocate, because it is with the bailor's money that he is discharged from the risque of the costs.
If someone hires a slave to act as their agent and trade on their behalf, they are responsible for the actions of that agent unless they have previously informed others that the agent cannot be trusted. However, even with such a notice, if the agent has a stake in the business or the master benefits from it, the notice will be considered a fraud. As Proculus says, anyone who profits from someone else's loss is committing fraud; this term encompasses everything that goes against natural justice and fairness. If someone, at the request of a mother, has put up bail for her son’s lawyer, they cannot take legal action against the lawyer for what is known as an assumpsit or undertaking. This is because it wasn't strictly their responsibility that the lawyer managed; the bail was made at the request of the mother. Nonetheless, according to Papinian, an action for the assumpsit or undertaking can be brought against the lawyer because it is the bailor's money that allows the lawyer to avoid the risk of the costs.
So a wife who has given to her husband money, which she may by law demand again, has a personal action of recovery against him, or an indirect action upon any thing purchased with the money. Because, as Ulpian says, it cannot be denied, that the husband has been richer by it, and the question is, whether what he possesses belongs to his wife?
So a wife who has given her husband money, which she can legally demand back, has a personal legal action to recover it, or an indirect claim on anything bought with that money. Because, as Ulpian says, it's undeniable that the husband is wealthier because of it, and the question is whether what he has belongs to his wife?
If I have been robbed by my slave, and any one has spent the money under the supposition that it was the slave's own property, an action may be maintained against that person, as being unjustly in possession of my property. According to the Roman laws, minors are not answerable for money borrowed. Yet if a minor has become richer by the loan, an indirect action will lie against him, or, if anything, belonging to another, has been pawned and sold by a creditor, the debtor should be released from the debt in proportion to what the creditor has received. Because, says Tryphoninus, whatever the obligation may be, since the money raised accrued from the debt, it is more reasonable that it should redound to the benefit of the debtor than the creditor. But the debtor is bound to indemnify the purchaser, for it would not be reasonable that he should derive gain from another's loss. Now if a creditor, holding an estate in pledge for his money, has received from it rents and profits amounting to more than his real debt; all above that shall be considered as a discharge of so much of the principal.
If my slave has stolen from me, and someone has spent that money thinking it was the slave's own, I can take legal action against that person for having my property unjustly. Under Roman law, minors aren't responsible for borrowed money. However, if a minor benefits from the loan, I can still pursue a claim against him. Additionally, if a creditor has sold something that belonged to someone else, the debtor should be released from the debt based on what the creditor received. As Tryphoninus says, regardless of the obligation, since the money earned came from the debt, it makes more sense for the debtor to benefit rather than the creditor. The debtor must compensate the buyer, since it's not fair for the buyer to profit from someone else's loss. Now, if a creditor has a property as collateral and has collected rents and profits that exceed the actual debt, the amount over that should be considered a reduction of the principal debt.
But to proceed with other cases. If you have treated with my debtor, not supposing him to be indebted to me, but to another person, and have borrowed my money of him, you are obliged to pay me; not because I have lent you money; for that could only be done by mutual consent; but because it is reasonable and just, that my money, which has come into your possession, should be restored to me.
But to move on to other cases. If you've made an arrangement with my debtor, thinking he's in debt to someone else, and you borrowed my money from him, you need to pay me back; not because I lent you money, as that would require mutual agreement, but because it's fair and just that the money of mine, which you've received, should be returned to me.
127 The later writers on the law have adduced this kind of reasoning in support of similar cases. Thus, for instance, if the goods of any one, who has been cast through default, have been sold, if he can make any good exception to the decision, he shall be entitled to the money arising from such sale. Again, when any one has lent money to a father for the maintenance of his son; if the father should become insolvent, he may bring an action against the son, provided the son is possessed of any thing through his mother.
127 Later legal writers have brought up this type of reasoning to support similar cases. For example, if someone loses their goods due to default and those goods are sold, they have the right to contest that decision and collect the money from the sale if they can present a valid objection. Additionally, if someone lends money to a father to support his son, and the father goes bankrupt, they can take legal action against the son, as long as the son has any inheritance from his mother.
These two rules being perfectly understood, there will be no difficulty in answering the questions often proposed by Lawyers and Theologians on such subjects.
These two rules being clearly understood, there will be no difficulty in answering the questions often raised by lawyers and theologians on such subjects.
III. In the first place it appears, that a person who has obtained possession of goods by fair means, is not bound to restitution, if those goods have perished, because they are no longer in his possession, nor has he derived any advantage from them. The case of unlawful possession which is left to the punishment of the law is entirely out of the question.
III. First of all, it seems that a person who has obtained goods through fair means is not required to return them if those goods have been lost, since they are no longer in their possession and they haven’t gained any benefit from them. The situation of unlawful possession, which is subject to legal penalties, is completely irrelevant.
IV. In the next place a bona-fide possessor of a thing is bound to a restitution of the fruits or profits thereof remaining in his hand. The FRUITS or PRODUCE of the THING ITSELF are here meant. For the benefit derived from a thing owing to the industry bestowed upon it by the occupier thereof, cannot belong to the thing itself, though originally proceeding from it. The reason of this obligation arises from the institution of property. For the true proprietor of a possession is naturally proprietor of the fruits or produce of the same.
IV. Next, a legitimate possessor of an item is required to return any fruits or profits that remain in their possession. The Fruits or Produce of the THE ACTUAL THING are what is being referred to here. The benefits gained from an item due to the effort put into it by the person using it cannot be claimed as belonging to the item itself, even though they originally come from it. This obligation exists because of the concept of property. The rightful owner of a possession naturally owns the fruits or produce it generates.
V. Such possessor in the third place is bound to make restitution of the thing, or reparation for the consumption of it occasioned by his possession. For he is conceived to have been made the richer thereby. Thus Caligula is praised for having, in the beginning of his reign, restored to different Princes along with their crowns, the intermediate revenues of their kingdoms.
V. The possessor in this case is required to return the item or compensate for its use while in their possession. This is because they are seen to have benefited from it. For example, Caligula is commended for having, at the start of his reign, returned to various princes not only their crowns but also the earnings from their kingdoms during the time they were away.
VI. In the fourth place, an occupier of lands, for instance, is not bound to make a compensation for the produce thereof which he has not reaped. For if dispossessed, he has neither the thing itself, nor any thing in the place of it.
VI. Fourthly, a land occupier, for example, isn’t required to compensate for the produce they haven’t harvested. Because if they are removed from the land, they have neither the land itself nor anything that replaces it.
VII. In the fifth place, a possessor who has granted to a third person a thing of which a gift had been made to himself, is not bound to make a recompence to the128 original giver, unless he received it under stipulation, that if he granted it to a third person, and thereby spared his own property, he should make a return proportionable to such gain.
VII. Fifth, if someone who has received a gift gives that item to another person, they don’t have to give anything back to the original giver unless they received it with the agreement that if they gave it to someone else, and thereby saved their own resources, they would return a portion reflecting that benefit.
VIII. Sixthly, if any one has sold a thing which he has bought, he is not bound to restitution of more than the surplus arising from the sale. But if he had received it under stipulation to sell, he is bound to make restitution of the whole price, unless, in transacting the sale he has incurred an expence, amounting to the whole price, which he would not otherwise have done.24
VIII. Sixth, if someone has sold something they bought, they only need to give back the profit from the sale. But if they received it with the agreement to sell, they must return the full price unless, in the process of selling, they incurred an expense equal to the full price, which they wouldn't have done otherwise. done.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
IX. Seventhly, a bona-fide purchaser of what belongs to another is obliged to make restitution to the real owner, nor can the price he paid be recovered. To this however there seems to be one exception, which is, where the owner could not have recovered possession without some expence; so for instance, if his property were in the hands of pirates. For then a deduction may be made of as much as the owner would willingly have spent in the recovery. Because the actual possession, especially of a thing difficult to be recovered, may be ascertained, and the owner deemed so much the richer by such recovery. And therefore, though in the ordinary course of law, the purchase of what belongs to one's self can never constitute a bargain, yet Paulus the Lawyer says, that it may do so, if it has been originally agreed that we are to pay for the re-possession of what another has belonging to us in his hands.
IX. Seventhly, a genuine buyer of something that belongs to someone else must return it to the actual owner, and they can't get back the money they spent. However, there seems to be one exception: if the owner couldn't have gotten their property back without incurring some costs; for example, if their property was in the hands of pirates. In that case, a deduction can be made for whatever amount the owner would have been willing to spend to recover it. This is because actual possession, especially of something that's hard to get back, can be determined, and the owner is considered that much richer for having recovered it. Therefore, even though, under normal legal circumstances, buying something that belongs to oneself is never a valid transaction, Paulus the Lawyer states that it can be considered so if it was originally agreed that we would pay for getting back what belongs to us that someone else has.
Nor is it in the least material, whether a thing has been bought with an intention of restoring it to the owner; in which case, some say, that an action for costs may be maintained, whilst others deny it. For an action on the case, to recover a compensation for business done arises from the artificial rules of CIVIL LAW, and not solely129 from the simple dictates of natural justice; which are here the principal subject of inquiry.
Nor does it really matter whether something was bought with the intention of giving it back to the owner; in that case, some argue that a lawsuit for costs can be pursued, while others disagree. A lawsuit for damages to recover compensation for services provided comes from the complex rules of Civil Law, not just from the basic principles of natural justice; which are the main focus of this discussion.
Not unlike to this is what Ulpian has written on funeral expences, in which he says, that a compassionate judge will not rigidly regard the bare labour that has been given, but allowing some relaxation in favour of equity, will shew indulgence to the feelings of human nature.
Not unlike this is what Ulpian has written about funeral expenses, where he says that a compassionate judge won't strictly focus on the minimum effort that has been made, but will allow some flexibility in favor of fairness, showing understanding for human emotions.
The same writer, in another place has said, that if any one has transacted my business, not out of regard to me, but for his own interest, and has incurred expence on my account, he may bring an action on the case, not for what he has given, but for what I have gained by his labour and expence.
The same writer, elsewhere, has stated that if someone has handled my affairs, not out of consideration for me, but for their own benefit, and has spent money on my behalf, they can file a lawsuit not for what they have given, but for what I have benefited from their work and expenses.
In the same manner, owners, by throwing whose goods overboard a ship has been lightened, may recover a compensation from others whose goods were by that means saved. Because those persons are considered so much the richer by the preservation of what would otherwise have been lost.
In the same way, owners who have had their goods thrown overboard to lighten a ship can receive compensation from others whose goods were saved because of that action. This is because those individuals are considered to be that much richer from the preservation of what would have otherwise been lost.
X. Eighthly, the person that has bought a thing of one, who is not the owner, cannot return it to that seller; because from the time that the thing came into his possession, he incurred an obligation to restore it to the lawful owner.
X. Eighthly, a person who buys something from someone who isn't the owner cannot return it to that seller; because once the item is in their possession, they have a responsibility to return it to the rightful owner.
XI. Again, if any one is in possession of a thing, whose real owner is unknown, he is not naturally, and necessarily bound to give it to the poor; although this may be considered as an act of piety, a custom very properly established in some places. The reason of which is founded on the introduction of property. For, in consequence of that, no one except the real owner, can claim a right to any thing. To the person therefore, who cannot discover such an owner, it is the same as if there really were none.
XI. Again, if someone has something but doesn't know who the real owner is, they aren't naturally or necessarily required to give it to the poor; although this can be seen as a charitable act, which is a tradition in some places. The reason for this is based on the concept of property. Because of that, only the real owner can claim a right to anything. So for a person who can't find the owner, it's as if there is none at all.
XII. Lastly, a person is not obliged by the law of nature to restore money, which has been received upon a dishonest account, or for the performance of a legal act, to which that person was of himself bound. However it is not without reason that some laws have required restitution in such cases. The reason of this is, because no one is bound to part with any thing unless it belongs to another. But here the property is voluntarily transferred by the first owner.
XII. Finally, a person is not required by natural law to return money that was received under false pretenses or for a legal act that they were already obligated to perform. However, it makes sense that some laws mandate restitution in these situations. This is because no one is obligated to give up anything unless it belongs to someone else. In this case, though, the property is willingly given up by the original owner.
The case will be altered, if there be any thing iniquitous130 in the manner of acquiring the thing; as if, for instance, it be gained by extortion. This gives rise to the obligation of submitting to penalties, which is not immediately to the present purpose.
The situation will change if there's anything unethical130 about how the item was obtained; for example, if it was secured through coercion. This leads to the requirement of facing consequences, which is not our main focus right now.
XIII. The present subject may be concluded with a refutation of Medina's false opinion, that a property in things, belonging to another, may be transferred without consent of the owner; provided the things are such as are usually valued by weight, number and measure. Because things of that nature can be repaid in kind, or by an equivalent. But this is only, where such a mode of repayment has been previously agreed upon; or where it is understood to be established by law or custom; or where the thing itself has been consumed, and cannot be identically restored. But without such consent, either expressed or implied, or excepting the impossibility just mentioned, the things themselves must be restored.
XIII. This topic can be wrapped up with a rebuttal against Medina’s incorrect belief that someone can transfer ownership of someone else’s property without the owner’s consent, as long as the items can typically be measured by weight, number, or size. This is because such items can be replaced in kind or by an equivalent. However, this applies only when there is a prior agreement on the method of repayment, when it is recognized by law or custom, or when the item has been consumed and cannot be replaced exactly. Without that consent, whether stated or implied, or except for the situations mentioned, the items must be returned.
CHAPTER XI.
About Promises.
Opinion, that the obligation to fulfil promises is not enacted by the law of nature, refuted—A bare assertion not binding—A promiser bound to fulfil his engagements, though no right to exact the performance of them, is thereby conveyed to another—What kind of promise gives such right—The promiser should possess the right use of reason—Difference between natural and civil law with respect to minors—Promises made under an error, or extorted by fear, how far binding—Promises valid, if in the power of the promiser to perform them—Promise made upon unlawful considerations, whether binding—Manner of confirming the promises made by others, and the conduct of Ambassadors who exceed their instructions, considered—Owners of ships, how far bound by the acts of the masters of such vessels, and merchants by the acts of their factors—Acceptance requisite to give validity to a promise—Promises sometimes revokable—The power of revoking a promise, explained by distinctions—Burdensome conditions annexed to a promise—Means of confirming invalid promises—Natural obligation arising from engagements made for others.
The view that the obligation to keep promises isn't upheld by natural law is challenged—A simple statement isn’t enough—A person who makes a promise is expected to keep it, even if they can’t demand that from others—What kind of promise gives that kind of right—The person who makes the promise should be able to reason correctly—Differences between natural and civil law concerning minors—How binding are promises made under mistake or pressure—Promises are valid if the person making them can actually fulfill them—Is a promise made for illegal reasons still binding—How to verify promises made by others, and the actions of Ambassadors who exceed their authority—Shipowners, to what extent are they responsible for their captains’ actions, and merchants for their agents’ actions—Acceptance is necessary to make a promise valid—Promises can sometimes be retracted—The right to revoke a promise is clarified by distinctions—Conditions attached to a promise that impose a burden—Ways to verify invalid promises—Natural obligations that arise from commitments made for others.
I. The course of the subject next leads to an inquiry into the obligation of promises.25 Where the first object, that presents itself, is the opinion of Franciscus Connanus, a man of no ordinary learning. He maintains an opinion that the law of nature and of nations does not enforce the fulfilment of those agreements, which do not include an express contract.26 Yet the fulfilment of them is right, in cases, where, even without a promise, the performance would be consonant to virtue and equity. In support of his opinion, he brings not only the sayings of Lawyers, but likewise the following reasons. He says, that the person, who makes, and he who believes, a rash promise,132 are equally to blame. For the fortunes of all men would be in imminent danger, if they were bound by such promises, which often proceed from motives of vanity rather than from a settled deliberation, and are the result of a light and inconsiderate mind. Lastly, the performance of whatever is any way just in itself, ought to be left to the free will of every one, and not exacted according to the rigid rules of necessity. He says that it is shameful not to fulfil promises; not because it is unjust, but because it argues a levity in making them.
I. The next topic we'll explore is the obligation of promises. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__. The first thing to consider is the view of Franciscus Connanus, a highly knowledgeable individual. He argues that the law of nature and nations does not require the fulfillment of agreements that don't involve a clear contract.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__. However, fulfilling these agreements is still considered right when, even without a promise, acting would align with virtue and fairness. To support his viewpoint, he cites not only legal opinions but also the following reasoning. He claims that both the person who makes a hasty promise and the one who accepts it are at fault. If people were bound by such promises, which often arise from vanity instead of careful thought, everyone’s fortunes would be at serious risk; such promises stem from a careless and superficial mindset. Lastly, any action that is just in its own right should rely on individual free will and shouldn’t be enforced by strict rules of necessity. He argues that failing to keep promises is disgraceful, not because it’s unjust, but because it reflects a lack of seriousness in making them.
In support of his opinion, he appeals also to the testimony of Tully, who has said, that those promises are not to be kept, which are prejudicial to the person to whom they are made, nor, if they are more detrimental to the giver than beneficial to the receiver. But if the performance of an engagement is begun upon the strength of a promise, but not finished, he does not require a complete fulfilment of the promise, but only some compensation to the party for the disappointment. Agreements, he continues, have no intrinsic force of obligation, but only what they derive from the express contracts, in which they are included, or to which they are annexed, or from the delivery of the thing promised. From whence arise actions, on the one side, and exceptions on the other, and bars to all claims of recovery.
In support of his view, he also references Tully's testimony, which states that promises should not be kept if they harm the person they’re made to, or if they cause more harm to the giver than good to the receiver. However, if someone starts to fulfill a commitment based on a promise but doesn’t complete it, he doesn’t insist on full completion of that promise; instead, he believes that some compensation should be given to the party for the disappointment. He goes on to say that agreements don’t have any inherent obligation; their binding nature comes only from the express contracts they’re part of, or from the delivery of what was promised. This leads to actions on one side and exceptions on the other, along with limits on any claims for recovery.
But it is through favour of the laws alone, which give the efficacy of obligation to what is only fair and equitable in itself, that obligatory agreements, such as express covenants and other things of that kind, derive their force.
But it is only through the favor of the laws that what is inherently fair and just gains the power of obligation, which is how binding agreements, like explicit contracts and similar matters, derive their strength.
Now there is no consistency in this opinion, taken in the general sense intended by its author. For in the first place it immediately follows from thence, that there is no force in treaties between kings and different nations, till some part of them be carried into execution, especially in those places, where no certain form of treaties or compacts has been established. But no just reason can be found, why laws, which are a kind of general agreement among a people, and indeed are called so by Aristotle, and Demosthenes, should be able to give the force of obligation to compacts, and why the will of an individual, doing every thing to bind himself, should not have the same power; especially where the civil law creates no impediment to it. Besides, as it has been already said that the property of a thing may be transferred, where a sufficient indication of the will is given. Why may we133 not then convey to another the right to claim a transfer of our property to him, or the fulfilment of our engagements, as we have the same power over our actions, as over our property?
Now, there's no consistency in this opinion, taken in the overall sense intended by its author. First of all, it follows that there’s no real power in treaties between kings and different nations until some part of them is put into action, especially in places where there isn't a clear format for treaties or agreements. However, there's no valid reason why laws, which are sort of a collective agreement among people—and are indeed referred to as such by Aristotle and Demosthenes—should provide the binding force to agreements, while an individual's intention to bind themselves doesn’t have the same effect, especially when civil law doesn't create any obstacles. Furthermore, as has already been mentioned, property can be transferred when there is a clear expression of intent. So why can’t we convey to someone else the right to claim a transfer of our property to them, or the fulfillment of our commitments, considering we have the same authority over our actions as we do over our property?
This is an opinion confirmed by the wisdom of all ages. For as it is said by legal authorities, that since nothing is so consonant to natural justice, as for the will of an owner, freely transferring his property to another, to be confirmed, so nothing is more conducive to good faith among men, than a strict adherence to the engagements they have made with each other. Thus a legal decision for the payment of money, where no debt has been incurred, except by the verbal consent of the party promising, is thought conformable to natural justice. Paulus the Lawyer also says, that the law of nature and the law of nations agree in compelling a person, who has received credit, to payment. In this place the word, COMPELLING, signifies a moral obligation. Nor can what Connanus says be admitted, which is, that we are supposed to have credit for a full performance of a promise, where the engagement has been in part fulfilled. For Paulus in this place is treating of an action where nothing is due; which action is entirely void, if money has been paid, in any way, whether according to the manner expressly stipulated, or any other. For the civil law, in order to discourage frequent causes of litigation, does not interfere with those agreements which are enforced by the law of nature and of nations.
This is a belief supported by the wisdom of all time. As legal experts state, nothing aligns more with natural justice than for an owner to willingly transfer their property to someone else, and nothing builds good faith among people like sticking to the commitments they’ve made to each other. Thus, a legal ruling for the payment of money, where no debt has been created except by the verbal agreement of the person promising, is seen as consistent with natural justice. Paulus the Lawyer also points out that both natural law and international law require a person who has received credit to make payment. In this context, the term ENGAGING refers to a moral obligation. Additionally, Connanus's claim that we assume full credit for a promise if the commitment has been partially fulfilled is not valid. Paulus is discussing a case where nothing is owed; this case is entirely void if money has been paid in any form, whether according to the specified terms or otherwise. Civil law, in order to reduce frequent lawsuits, does not interfere with those agreements upheld by natural and international law.
Tully, in the first book of his Offices, assigns such force to the obligation of promises, that he calls fidelity the foundation of justice, which Horace also styles the sister of justice, and the Platonists often call justice, TRUTH, which Apuleius has translated FIDELITY, and Simonides has defined justice to be not only returning what one has received, but also speaking the truth.
Tully, in the first book of his Offices, emphasizes the importance of keeping promises so much that he describes fidelity as the foundation of justice, which Horace also refers to as the sister of justice, and the Platonists often call justice, TRUTH, which Apuleius has translated as Loyalty, and Simonides has defined justice as not only returning what one has received but also telling the truth.
But to understand the matter fully, we must carefully observe that there are three different ways of speaking, respecting things which ARE, or which, it is supposed, WILL be in our power.
But to fully understand the issue, we need to carefully note that there are three different ways to talk about things that ARE, or that it is believed we WILL have control over.
II. The first of these ways is, where an assurance is given of future intentions, and if the assurance be SINCERE at the time it is given, though it should not be carried into effect, no blame is incurred, as it might afterwards not be found expedient. For the human mind has not only a natural power, but a right to change its purpose. Wherefore if any blame attaches to a change134 of opinion, or purpose, it is not to be imputed to the BARE ACT OF CHANGING, but to the CIRCUMSTANCES, under which it happens, especially when the former resolution was the best.
II. The first way is when someone makes a promise about their future intentions. If that promise is made sincerely at the time, even if it’s not followed through later on, there’s no blame because it might not be practical to do it. The human mind has not only the ability but also the right to change its mind. So, if there’s any blame for a change of opinion or intention, it shouldn’t be directed at the simple act of changing but rather at the circumstances that led to it, especially when the original decision was the best one.
III. The second way is, when future intentions are expressed by outward acts and signs sufficient to indicate a resolution of abiding by present assurances. And these kind of promises may be called imperfect obligations, but conveying to the person to whom they are given no RIGHT to exact them. For it happens in many cases that we may be under an obligation of duty, to the performance of which another has no right to compel us. For in this respect the duty of fidelity to promises, is like the duties of compassion and gratitude. In such kinds of promises therefore the person to whom they are made, has no right, by the law of nature to possess himself of the effects of the promiser, as his own, nor to COMPEL him to the performance of his promise.
III. The second way is when future intentions are shown through actions and signs that clearly indicate a commitment to uphold current promises. These kinds of promises can be called imperfect obligations, but they do not give the person receiving them the RIGHT to demand fulfillment. In many instances, we may have a duty to act in a certain way, but another person has no right to force us to do so. In this sense, the duty to keep promises is similar to the duties of kindness and gratitude. Therefore, in these kinds of promises, the person they’re made to does not have the right, according to natural law, to take the promiser's belongings as their own or to FORCE them to fulfill their promise.
IV. The third way is, where such a determination is confirmed by evident signs of an intention to convey a peculiar right to another, which constitutes the perfect obligation of a promise, and is attended with consequences similar to an alienation of property.
IV. The third way is when this determination is backed by clear signs that show an intention to grant a specific right to someone else, which creates a strong obligation of a promise and has effects similar to transferring property.
There may be two kinds of alienation, the one of our property, the other of a certain portion of our liberty. Under those of the former kind we may class the promises of gifts, and under the latter the promises of doing certain actions. On this subject we are supplied with noble arguments from the divine oracles, which inform us, that God himself, who can be limited by no established rules of law, would act contrary to his own nature, if he did not perform his promises. From whence it follows that the obligations to perform promises spring from the nature of that unchangeable justice, which is an attribute of God, and common to all who bear his image, in the use of reason. To the proofs of scripture here referred to, we may add the judgment of Solomon, "My son if thou hast been surety for thy friend, thou hast tied up thy hands to a stranger; thou art ensnared by the words of thy mouth, then art thou taken by the words of thine own mouth." Hence a promise is called by the Hebrews a bond or chain, and is compared to a vow. Eustathius in his notes on the second book of the Iliad, assigns a similar origin to the word ὑποσχεσεως {hyposcheseôs} or engagement. For he who has received the promise, in some135 measure takes and holds the person, that has made the engagement. A meaning not ill expressed by Ovid in the second book of his Metamorphoses, where the promiser says to him, to whom he had promised, "My word has become yours."
There may be two types of alienation: one regarding our property and the other concerning a certain part of our freedom. We can categorize the former as promises of gifts, and the latter as promises to perform specific actions. On this topic, we have strong arguments from sacred texts that tell us God himself, who isn’t bound by any set laws, would go against his own nature if he didn’t keep his promises. This means that the obligation to fulfill promises comes from the nature of unchanging justice, which is a quality of God and shared by all who reflect his image through reason. Along with the scriptural evidence mentioned, we can consider Solomon’s wisdom: "My son, if you have made a pledge for your friend, you have ensnared yourself; you are trapped by the words of your mouth." Thus, the Hebrews refer to a promise as a bond or chain, comparing it to a vow. Eustathius, in his notes on the second book of the Iliad, suggests that the word promise {hyposcheseôs} or engagement comes from a similar origin. For the person who receives the promise, to some extent, takes hold of the individual who made the promise. This idea is expressed well by Ovid in the second book of his Metamorphoses, where the person giving the promise says to the one to whom he made it, "My word has become yours."
After knowing this, there remains no difficulty in replying to the arguments of Connanus. For the expressions of the lawyers, respecting BARE PROMISES, refer only to what was introduced by the Roman laws, which have made a FORMAL STIPULATION the undoubted sign of a deliberate mind.
After knowing this, it’s easy to respond to Connanus's arguments. The statements made by the lawyers about Empty promises only relate to what was brought in by Roman laws, which established a Formal Agreement as a clear indication of a thoughtful intention.
Nor can it be denied that there were similar laws among other nations. For Seneca, speaking of human laws, and promises made without proper solemnities, says, "What law, of any country, we may add, obliges us to the performance of bare promises?" But there may naturally be other signs of a deliberate mind, besides a formal stipulation, or any other similar act which the civil law requires, to afford grounds for a legal remedy. But what is not done with a deliberate mind, we are inclined to believe does not come under the class of perfect obligations; as Theophrastus has observed in his book on laws. Nay, even what is done with a deliberate mind, but not with an intention of conceding our own right to another; though it cannot give any one a natural right of exacting its fulfilment, yet it creates an obligation not only in point of duty, but in point of moral necessity. The next matter to be considered is, what are the requisites to constitute a perfect promise.
Nor can we deny that similar laws existed in other nations. Seneca, discussing human laws and promises made without proper formalities, says, "What law, of any country, we may add, binds us to fulfill mere promises?" However, there can naturally be other signs of an intentional mind, beyond a formal agreement or any similar act that civil law requires to provide grounds for a legal remedy. But what is not done with intent is generally seen as not falling under the category of perfect obligations, as Theophrastus noted in his book on laws. Furthermore, even actions taken with intent, but not with the purpose of giving up our own rights to another, while they don't grant anyone a natural right to require their fulfillment, do create an obligation that is both a matter of duty and a moral necessity. The next issue to address is what is needed to constitute a perfect promise.
V. The use of reason is the first requisite to constitute the obligation of a promise, which ideots, madmen, and infants are consequently incapable of making. The case of minors is somewhat different. For although they may not have a sound judgment, yet it is not a permanent defect, nor sufficient of itself to invalidate all their acts. It cannot be certainly defined at what period of life reason commences. But it must be judged of from daily actions, or from the particular customs of each country. Amongst the Hebrews a promise made by a male at the age of thirteen, and by a female at the age of twelve, was valid. In other nations, the civil laws, acting upon just motives, declare certain promises made by wards and minors to be void, not only among the Romans, but among the Greeks also, as it has been observed by Dion Chrysostom in his twenty-fifth oration. To do away the136 effect of improvident promises, some laws introduce actions of recovery, or restitution. But such regulations are peculiar to the civil law, and have no immediate connection with the law of nature and of nations, any farther than that wherever they are established, it is consonant to natural justice that they should be observed. Wherefore if a foreigner enter into an agreement with a citizen or subject of any other country; he will be bound by the laws of that country, to which, during his residence therein, he owes a temporary obedience. But the case is different, where an agreement is made upon the open sea, or in a desert island, or by letters of correspondence. For such contracts are regulated by the law of nature alone, in the same manner as compacts made by sovereigns in their public capacity.
V. The use of reason is the first requirement to establish the obligation of a promise, which idiots, madmen, and infants are therefore unable to make. The situation with minors is a bit different. Even though they may not have sound judgment, this isn't a permanent deficiency and is not enough on its own to invalidate all their actions. It can't be clearly defined at what age reason begins. However, it should be assessed based on everyday behaviors or the specific customs of each country. Among the Hebrews, a promise made by a male at the age of thirteen and by a female at the age of twelve was considered valid. In other nations, civil laws, guided by just principles, declare certain promises made by wards and minors to be void, not just among the Romans, but also among the Greeks, as noted by Dion Chrysostom in his twenty-fifth speech. To counter the effects of hasty promises, some laws allow for actions of recovery or restitution. However, these regulations are specific to civil law and don't directly relate to the law of nature and nations, except that wherever they exist, it is in line with natural justice for them to be respected. Therefore, if a foreigner enters into an agreement with a citizen or subject of another country, they will be bound by the laws of that country, to which they owe temporary obedience during their stay. The situation is different when an agreement is made on the open sea, on a deserted island, or through correspondence. Such contracts are governed solely by the law of nature, just like agreements made by sovereigns in their official roles.
VI. The consideration of promises, made under an error, is a subject of some intricacy. For it, in general, makes a difference, whether the promiser knew the full extent of his promise, and the value of the thing promised, or not, or whether the contract, which was made, originated in fraudulent intention, or not, or whether one of the parties was privy to the fraud; and whether the fulfilment of it was an act of strict justice, or only of good faith. For according to the variety of these circumstances, writers pronounce some acts void and others valid, leaving the injured party a discretionary power to rescind or amend them.
VI. The issue of promises made under a misunderstanding is quite complicated. Generally, it matters whether the person making the promise understood the full extent of it and the value of what they promised, or not, or whether the contract was formed with dishonest intent, or not, or whether one of the parties knew about the dishonesty; and whether fulfilling it was simply a matter of fairness or just good faith. Depending on these different circumstances, some legal scholars declare certain acts invalid and others valid, allowing the wronged party the option to cancel or adjust them.
Most of these distinctions originate in the ancient civil, and praetorian Roman law. Though some of them are not strictly founded in reason and truth. But the most obvious and natural way of discovering the truth is by referring to laws, which derive their force and efficacy from the general consent of mankind; so that if a law rests upon the presumption of any fact, which in reality has no existence, such a law is not binding. For when no evidence of the fact can be produced, the entire foundation, on which that law rests must fail. But we must have recourse to the subject, to the words and circumstances of a law, to determine when it is founded on such a presumption.27
Most of these distinctions come from ancient civil and praetorian Roman law. Although some of them aren’t strictly based on reason and truth. The most obvious and natural way to uncover the truth is by looking at laws, which gain their strength and effectiveness from the general agreement of people; so if a law is based on the assumption of any fact that doesn’t actually exist, that law isn’t binding. When no evidence of the fact can be presented, the whole foundation on which that law is based must collapse. But we need to refer to the subject, the wording, and the context of a law to determine when it is based on such a presumption.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
137 The same rule applies to the interpretation of promises. For where they are made upon the supposition of a fact, which in the end proves not to be true, they lose the force of obligations. Because the promiser made them upon certain conditions only, the fulfilment of which becomes impossible. Cicero, in his first book on the talents and character of an orator, puts the case of a father, who, under the supposition or intelligence that his son was dead, promised to devise his property to his nephew. But the supposition proving erroneous, and the intelligence false, the father was released from the obligation of the promise made to his relative. But if the promiser has neglected to examine the matter, or has been careless in expressing his meaning, he will be bound to repair the damage which another has sustained on that account. This obligation is not built on the strength of the promise, but on the injury, which it has occasioned. An erroneous promise will be binding, if the error was not the OCCASION of the promise. For here there is no want of consent in the party, who made it. But if the promise was obtained by fraud, the person so obtaining it shall indemnify the promiser for the injury sustained, if there has been any partial error in the promise, yet in other respects it shall be deemed valid.
137 The same rule applies to how we interpret promises. When promises are made based on a fact that turns out to be untrue, they lose their binding force. This happens because the promiser created them under specific conditions that become impossible to fulfill. Cicero, in his first book about the skills and qualities of an orator, gives the example of a father who, believing his son was dead, promised to leave his property to his nephew. But since that belief was incorrect and the information false, the father was no longer obligated to uphold his promise to his relative. However, if the promiser failed to investigate the situation or expressed himself carelessly, he will be responsible for compensating any damage caused to another person because of it. This obligation isn’t based on the promise itself but on the harm it caused. A mistaken promise will still be valid if the mistake wasn’t the reason for making the promise in the first place. Here, the promiser didn’t lack consent. But if the promise was obtained through deceit, the person who deceived will have to compensate the promiser for any damage suffered. If there's been any partial error in the promise, it will still be considered valid in other respects.
VII. Promises extorted by fear are a subject of no less intricate decision. For here too a distinction is usually made between a well founded and a chimerical fear, between a just fear and a bare suspicion, and between the persons who occasion it, whether it be the person to whom the promise is given, or some other. A distinction is also made between acts purely gratuitous, and those in which both parties have an interest. For according to all this variety of circumstances some engagements are considered as void, others as revocable at the pleasure or discretion of the maker, and others as warranting a claim to indemnity for the inconvenience occasioned. But on each of these points there is great diversity of opinion.
VII. Promises coerced by fear are a topic of equally complicated decisions. Here, a distinction is usually made between legitimate and unfounded fear, between justifiable fear and mere suspicion, and between the individuals causing it, whether it’s the person receiving the promise or someone else. There's also a distinction between purely voluntary actions and those where both parties have an interest. Depending on all these varying circumstances, some commitments are seen as void, others can be revoked at the discretion of the person who made them, and some may lead to a claim for compensation for any trouble caused. However, there is significant disagreement on each of these points.
There is some shew of reason in the opinion of those who, without taking into consideration the power of the civil law to annul or diminish an obligation, maintain that a person is bound to fulfil a promise which he has given under impressions of fear. For even in this case there was CONSENT, though it was extorted; neither was it conditional, as in erroneous promises, but absolute.138 It is called CONSENT. For as Aristotle has observed, those who consent to throw their goods overboard in a storm, would have saved them, had it not been for the fear of shipwreck. But they freely part with them considering all the circumstances of time and place.
There's some reasoning behind the view of those who, without considering the civil law's ability to cancel or reduce an obligation, argue that a person must fulfill a promise made under duress. Because even in this case, there was CONSENT, even if it was forced; it wasn't conditional like promises made in error, but absolute.138 This is what we call Consent. As Aristotle pointed out, those who agree to throw their belongings overboard in a storm would have saved them if it weren't for the fear of sinking. But they willingly let them go, taking into account all the circumstances of time and place.
VIII. To render a promise valid, it must be such as it is in the power of the promiser to perform. For which reason no promises to do illegal acts are valid; because no one either has, or ever can have a right to do them. But a promise, as was said before, derives all its force from the right of the promiser to make it, nor can it extend beyond that.
VIII. For a promise to be valid, it must be something the person making the promise can actually do. That's why promises to do illegal things aren't valid; no one has the right to do them, now or ever. As mentioned earlier, a promise gets its strength from the ability of the person making it to actually fulfill it, and it can't go beyond that.
If a thing is not now in the power of the promiser, but may be so at some future time; the obligation will remain in suspense. For the promise was only made under the expectation of some future ability to fulfil it. But if a person has a controul over the condition upon which the promise is made, to realise it or not, he lies under a moral obligation to use every endeavour to fulfil it. But in obligations of this kind also, the civil law, from obvious motives of general utility, occasionally interposes its authority to make them void: obligations, which the law of nature would have confirmed.
If someone can't fulfill a promise right now but might be able to in the future, the obligation is on hold. The promise was made with the expectation of being able to fulfill it later. However, if a person can control the condition on which the promise is based and can make it happen or not, they have a moral obligation to do everything they can to keep that promise. Nonetheless, in situations like this, civil law, for obvious reasons of public interest, sometimes steps in to void those obligations—obligations that natural law would have upheld.
IX. The next general inquiry, for the most part, refers to the validity of promises made upon any immoral or unlawful consideration; as if, for instance, any thing is promised to another on condition of his committing a murder. Here the very promise itself is wicked and unlawful, because it encourages the commission of a crime. But it does not follow every FOOLISH or IMPROVIDENT promise loses the force of an obligation, as in the confirmation of imprudent or prodigal grants, for no further evil can result from a confirmation of what has been already given: and the invalidity of promises would be a greater evil than any that could result from a confirmation of the most improvident. But in promises made upon IMMORAL and UNLAWFUL considerations, there is always a criminality remaining, even while they continue unfulfilled. For during the whole of that time, the expectation of fulfilment carries with it the indelible mark of encouragement to the commission of a crime.
IX. The next general inquiry mostly concerns the validity of promises made for any immoral or illegal reasons; for example, if someone promises something to another person on the condition that they commit a murder. In this case, the promise itself is wrong and illegal because it encourages criminal behavior. However, not every Silly or Reckless promise loses its binding nature, as seen with the confirmation of unwise or reckless grants, since no further harm can come from confirming what has already been given. In fact, declaring promises invalid would be a greater harm than any that could arise from confirming the most reckless ones. But in promises made for UNETHICAL and ILLEGAL reasons, there is always an element of wrongdoing, even while they remain unfulfilled. For as long as that time lasts, the expectation of fulfillment carries the lasting weight of encouraging crime.
XII.28 We are obliged to confirm the engagements made by others, acting in our name, if it is evident that they139 had special, or general instructions from us to do so. And in granting a commission with full powers to any one, it may so happen that we are bound by the conduct of that agent, even if he exceed the secret instructions which he has received. For he acts upon that ostensible authority, by which we are bound to ratify whatever he does, although we may have bound him to do nothing but according to his private instructions. This rule, we must observe, applies to the promises made by ambassadors in the name of their sovereigns, when, by virtue of their public credentials, they have exceeded their private orders.
XII.28 We are required to uphold the commitments made by others acting on our behalf if it’s clear that they139 had specific or general instructions from us to do so. And when we grant someone a commission with full authority, it might happen that we are held accountable for that agent's actions, even if they go beyond the secret guidelines they received. They operate under that visible authority, which obligates us to approve whatever they do, even if we have directed them to act only according to their private instructions. We must note that this principle applies to the promises made by ambassadors on behalf of their sovereigns when, due to their official credentials, they have acted beyond their private orders.
XIII. From the preceding arguments, it is easy to understand how far owners of ships are answerable for the acts of the masters employed by them in those vessels, or merchants for the conduct of their factors. For natural equity will qualify the actions brought against them, according to the instructions and powers which they give. So that we may justly condemn the rigour of the Roman law, in making the owners of ships absolutely bound by all the acts of the masters employed. For this is neither consonant to natural equity, which holds it sufficient for each party to be answerable in proportion to his share, nor is it conducive to the public good. For men would be deterred from employing ships, if they lay under the perpetual fear of being answerable for the acts of their masters to an unlimited extent. And therefore in Holland, a country where trade has flourished with the greatest vigour, the Roman law has never been observed either now or at any former period. On the contrary, it is an established rule that no action can be maintained against the owner for any greater sum than the value of the ship and cargo.
XIII. From the arguments above, it’s clear how responsible ship owners are for the actions of the masters they hire for their vessels, or how merchants are accountable for the behavior of their agents. Natural fairness will adjust the claims made against them based on the instructions and authority they provide. We can fairly criticize the strictness of Roman law, which holds ship owners completely liable for all actions of their masters. This doesn’t align with natural fairness, which suggests that each party should be responsible according to their stake, nor does it serve the common good. People would hesitate to hire ships if they constantly feared being fully responsible for their masters' actions. Therefore, in Holland, a country where trade has thrived robustly, Roman law has never been followed, either now or in the past. Instead, there’s a well-established rule that no legal action can be taken against the owner for any amount greater than the value of the ship and cargo.
For a promise to convey a right, acceptance is no less necessary than in a transfer of property. And in this case there is supposed to have been a precedent request, which is the same as acceptance. Nor is this contradicted by the promises which the civil law implies every one to have made to the state, WITHOUT ANY REQUEST OR FORMAL ACCEPTANCE.
For a promise to grant a right, acceptance is just as important as in a transfer of property. In this situation, there is presumed to have been a prior request, which is equivalent to acceptance. This is not contradicted by the promises that civil law assumes everyone has made to the state, WITHOUT ANY REQUEST OR FORMAL ACCEPTANCE.
XIV. A reason which has induced some to believe that the sole act of a promiser, by the law of nature, is sufficient. Our first position is not contradicted by the Roman law. For it no where says, that a promise has its full effect before acceptance, but only forbids the140 revocation of it which might prevent acceptance: and this effect results, not from NATURAL but from purely LEGAL rules.
XIV. A reason that has led some to believe that just the act of making a promise, according to natural law, is enough. Our first point is not contradicted by Roman law. It does not state that a promise takes full effect before it is accepted, but only prohibits the140 revocation of it that could stop acceptance. This effect comes not from NATURAL but from strictly LEGAL rules.
XV. Another question is, whether the acceptance alone of a promise is sufficient, or whether it ought to be communicated to the promiser before it can be made binding.
XV. Another question is whether just accepting a promise is enough, or if it needs to be communicated to the person who made the promise before it becomes binding.
It is certain that a promise may be made two ways, either upon condition of its being fulfilled, if accepted, or upon condition of its being ratified, if the promiser is apprised of its being accepted. And in cases of mutual obligation, it is presumed to be taken in the latter sense; but it is better to take promises that are purely gratuitous in the former sense, unless there be evidence to the contrary.
It’s clear that a promise can be made in two ways: either on the condition that it’s fulfilled if accepted, or on the condition that it’s confirmed if the person making the promise knows it’s been accepted. In situations involving mutual obligations, it’s assumed to be understood in the second way. However, it’s usually better to interpret purely voluntary promises in the first way, unless there’s proof to suggest otherwise.
XVI. From hence it follows, that a promise may be revoked, without the imputation of injustice or levity, BEFORE ACCEPTANCE, as no right has yet been conveyed; especially if ACCEPTANCE were made the condition of its being fulfilled. It may be revoked too if the party to whom it was made, should die before acceptance. Because it is evident that the power to accept it or not, was conferred upon HIM, and not upon his HEIRS. For to give a man a right, which may POSSIBLY descend to his heirs, is one thing, and to express an intention of giving it to his heirs is another. For it makes an essential difference upon what person the favour is conferred. This is understood in the answer made by Neratius, who said, that he did not believe the prince would have granted to one who was dead, what he granted, supposing him still alive.
XVI. From this, it follows that a promise can be revoked without it being considered unjust or careless, BEFORE AGREEMENT, as no right has been granted yet; especially if ACCEPTANCE was made a condition for its fulfillment. It can also be revoked if the person to whom it was made dies before acceptance. This is because it’s clear that the right to accept or reject it was given to Him, not to his Heirs. Granting someone a right that could MAYBE pass to his heirs is one thing, while expressing an intention to give that right to his heirs is another. There is a significant difference in who receives the favor. This is reflected in Neratius's response, where he stated that he didn’t believe the prince would have granted something to someone who was dead if he had assumed they were still alive.
XVII. A promise may be revoked, by the death of the person appointed to communicate to a third the intention of the promiser. Because the obligation to the third person rested upon such communication. The case is different, where a public messenger is employed, who is not himself the obligatory instrument, but only the means through which it is conveyed. Therefore letters indicating a promise, or consent may be conveyed by any one. Yet there is a distinction to be made between a minister appointed to communicate a promise, and one appointed to make the promise in his own name.
XVII. A promise can be canceled if the person chosen to inform a third party of the promiser's intent dies. This is because the obligation to the third person relies on that communication. However, it’s different when a public messenger is used, as they are not the direct means of obligation but just the channel for delivering the message. So, letters that state a promise or consent can be delivered by anyone. Still, there is a difference between someone appointed to communicate a promise and someone designated to make the promise on their own behalf.
For in the former case, a revocation will be valid, even though it has not been made known to the minister employed; but in the latter case, it will be entirely void,141 because the right of promising was committed to the minister, and fully depended upon his will; therefore the obligation of the promise was complete, as he knew of no intended revocation. So also in the former case, where a second person is commissioned to communicate the intentions of a donor to a third; even if the donor should die, the acceptance of the gift will be deemed valid, all that was requisite being performed on one part; though till that period the intention was revocable, as is evident in the case of bequests. But in the other case, where a person has received a full commission to execute a promise during the LIFE of the donor, should the donor die before the execution of it, and the person employed be apprised of his death; the commission, the promise, and the acceptance of it will then, at once, become void.
In the first case, a revocation will be valid, even if the minister involved hasn’t been informed; however, in the second case, it will be completely invalid,141 because the right to make promises was assigned to the minister and fully relied on his discretion. Therefore, the obligation of the promise was fulfilled, as he was unaware of any intended revocation. Similarly, in the first case, when a second person is tasked with conveying the donor’s intentions to a third party; even if the donor passes away, the acceptance of the gift will still be considered valid, as all that was necessary has been completed by one party; although until that time, the intention was revocable, which is clear in the context of bequests. In the other case, when someone has been fully authorized to fulfill a promise during the LIFE of the donor, if the donor dies before the promise is carried out and the person assigned is made aware of the donor’s death, the commission, the promise, and its acceptance will then immediately become void.
In doubtful cases, it is reasonable to suppose that it was the intention of the promiser, that the commission which he gave should be executed, unless some great change, as for instance, his own death should occur. Yet reasons in favour of a contrary opinion may easily be found and admitted, especially with respect to pious donations, which, at all events, ought to stand good. And in the same manner may be decided the long disputed question, whether an action on account of such a bequest could be brought against the heir. Upon which the author of the second book to Herennius says, that Marcus Drusus the praetor decided one way, and Sextus Julius another.
In uncertain situations, it's reasonable to think that the person who made the promise intended for the task they assigned to be completed, unless a significant change, like their own death, occurred. However, there are valid reasons for a different viewpoint, particularly regarding charitable donations, which should always be honored. The same approach can be taken to resolve the long-debated issue of whether a lawsuit over such a bequest can be filed against the heir. The author of the second book to Herennius mentions that Marcus Drusus, the praetor, ruled one way, while Sextus Julius ruled another.
XVIII. The acceptance of a promise for a third person is a matter subject to discussion, in which there is a distinction to be observed between a promise made to a person of a thing, which is to be given to another, and a promise made directly to the person himself, on whom the former is to be conferred. If a promise is made to any one, where his own personal interest is not concerned, a consideration introduced by the Roman law, by acceptance he seems naturally to acquire a right which may be transferred to another for HIS acceptance, and this right will pass so fully, that in the mean time the promise cannot be revoked by the person who gave, though it may be released by him who received it. For that is a meaning by no means repugnant to the law of nature, and it is entirely conformable to the words of such a promise; nor can it be a matter of indifference to142 the person, through whom another is to receive a benefit.
XVIII. The acceptance of a promise for someone else is a topic that sparks debate, highlighting a difference between a promise made to someone for a benefit that goes to another person, and a promise made directly to the individual who is supposed to receive it. When a promise is made to someone whose personal interest isn’t involved, which is a principle from Roman law, that person seems to gain a right upon acceptance that can be passed on to another for their acceptance. This right will be fully transferred, meaning the original promisor can't take back the promise, although the person who accepted it can choose to release it. This interpretation isn’t against natural law and aligns perfectly with the language of the promise; it also matters to the individual through whom another person stands to gain a benefit.
But if a promise is made directly to one, on whom a thing is to be conferred, a distinction must be made, whether the person receiving such a promise has SPECIAL commission for acceptance, or one so GENERAL as to include acceptance, or has it not. When a commission has been previously given, no farther distinction is necessary, whether the person be free or not, a condition which the Roman laws require. But it is plain that from such an acceptance, let the condition of the person be what it will, the promise is complete: because consent may be given and signified through the medium of another. For a person is supposed to have fully intended, what he has put into the power of another to accept or refuse.
But if a promise is made directly to someone to whom something is to be given, we need to distinguish whether the person receiving that promise has a SPECIAL authorization to accept, or one so GENERAL that it includes acceptance, or if they don't have any. When authorization has already been granted, no further distinction is needed, whether the person is free or not, which is a condition required by Roman laws. However, it is clear that from such acceptance, no matter what the person’s condition is, the promise is complete: because consent can be given and communicated through someone else. A person is assumed to have fully intended what they have allowed someone else to accept or refuse.
Where there is no such commission, if another, to whom the promise was not directly made, accepts it with the consent of the promiser, the promise will be so far binding, that the promiser will not be at liberty to revoke it, before the person, in whose favour it was made has ratified, and afterwards chosen to release the engagement. Yet, in the mean time, the accepter cannot release it, as having derived no peculiar right from it himself, but only been used as an instrument in promoting the kind intentions and good faith of the promiser. The promiser therefore himself, by revoking it, is not doing violence to the perfect right of another, but only acting in contradiction his own good faith.
Where there is no such commission, if someone else, to whom the promise wasn't directly made, accepts it with the promiser’s consent, the promise will be binding enough that the promiser can't take it back until the person it was made for has approved it and later decided to release the obligation. However, in the meantime, the accepter can't release it since they haven't gained any special right from it themselves; they've only served as a means to support the good intentions and honesty of the promiser. Therefore, if the promiser revokes it, they aren't violating anyone else's perfect right, but merely contradicting their own good faith.
XIX. From what has been said before, it is easy to conceive what opinion ought to be entertained of a burdensome condition annexed to a promise. For it may be annexed at any time, till a promise has been completed by acceptance, or an irrevocable pledge to fulfil it has been given. But the condition of a burden annexed to a favour intended to be conferred upon a third person, through the medium of any one, may be revoked before the person has confirmed it by his acceptance. On this point there is great difference of opinion. But upon impartial consideration the natural equity of any case may be easily seen without any great length of arguments.
XIX. From what has been said earlier, it's easy to understand what opinion should be held about a burdensome condition attached to a promise. It can be added at any time until the promise has been accepted or there’s been an irrevocable commitment to fulfill it. However, the condition of a burden linked to a favor meant to be given to a third person, through someone else, can be revoked before that person has confirmed it by accepting it. There are varying opinions on this point. But with fair consideration, the natural fairness of any situation can be clearly seen without lengthy arguments.
XX. XXI. XXII. Another point of discussion relates to the validity of an erroneous promise, when the person, who made it, upon being apprised of his error is willing to adhere to his engagement. And the same inquiry143 applies to promises, which, arising out of fear or any other such motive, are prohibited by the civil law. What, it may be asked, will become of these promises, if that fear, or that motive has been removed?
XX. XXI. XXII. Another point of discussion relates to the validity of a mistaken promise when the person who made it, upon realizing their mistake, is willing to stick to their commitment. The same question143 applies to promises that are made out of fear or other prohibited motives under civil law. What happens to these promises if that fear or motive has been removed?
To confirm such obligations, some think an internal consent of the mind alone in conjunction with some previous external act is sufficient. Others disapprove of this opinion, because they do not admit that an external act is a real sign of a subsequent intention. Therefore they require an express repetition of the promise and acceptance. Between these two opinions, the truth is most likely to be found. There may be an external act expressive of a promise, though unaccompanied with words; where one party's accepting and retaining a gift, and the other's relinquishing his right in it are sufficient to constitute a full consent.
To confirm these obligations, some believe that just an internal agreement in the mind, along with some prior external action, is enough. Others disagree with this view because they don't see an external act as a true indicator of a later intention. As a result, they insist on a clear restatement of the promise and acceptance. The truth likely lies somewhere between these two perspectives. There can be an external action that shows a promise, even without words; where one party accepts and keeps a gift, while the other party gives up their claim to it, that is enough to establish full consent.
To prevent civil laws from being confounded with natural justice, we must not omit noticing, in this place, that promises though founded in no EXPRESS motive, are not, any more than gifts, void by the law of nature.
To keep civil laws from being confused with natural justice, we should point out here that promises, even if they’re not made with any clear motive, are just like gifts and are not considered void by natural law.
Nor is a person who has engaged for another's performing any thing, bound to pay damages and interest for neglect, provided he has done every thing that was necessary on his part towards obtaining its accomplishment. Unless the express terms of the agreement, or the nature of the business require a stricter obligation, positively declaring that, under all circumstances whatever, the thing shall be performed.
A person who has arranged for someone else to perform a task is not responsible for paying damages or interest for neglect, as long as they have done everything necessary on their part to make it happen. This is unless the specific terms of the agreement or the nature of the business demand a stricter obligation that clearly states that the task must be completed under all circumstances.
CHAPTER XII.
About Contracts.
Human actions divided into simple or mixed—Gratuitous, or accompanied with mutual obligation—Acts by way of exchange, adjustment of what is to be given or done—Partnership—Contracts—Previous equality—As to knowledge of all circumstances—As to freedom of consent, requisite in contracts of exchange, of sale, of commission and loan—Price of things in what manner to be rated—Transfer of property by sale—What kind contrary to the law of nature—Money—Its use as the standard value of all things—No abatement in the rent or hire of a thing on account of ordinary accidents—Increase or diminution of just salaries—Usury, by what law forbidden—Interest not coming under the name of usury—Insurance—Partnerships of Trade, Naval Associations—Inequality in the terms of a contract no way repugnant to the law of nations.
Human actions can be categorized as either simple or mixed; they can be free or involve mutual obligations. This includes acts of exchange and adjustments regarding what is to be given or done in partnerships, contracts, and previous equality. It involves understanding all circumstances and ensuring freedom of consent, which is essential in contracts for exchange, sale, commission, and loan. There are also considerations on how to evaluate the price of items and the transfer of property through sale, as well as identifying actions that violate the law of nature. Money serves as the standard value for all things, with no reductions in rent or hire for items due to ordinary accidents and changes in fair salaries. Usury, which is prohibited by law, is distinct from interest. Other topics include insurance, trade partnerships, and naval associations; inequalities in contract terms do not violate the law of nations.
I. and II. Of all human actions, wherein the interest of others is concerned, some are simple, and some are mixed. In those of the former description all service is purely gratuitous, but in the latter it is a traffic of exchange. In the one case the service is granted without a requital, but in the other it is accompanied with an obligation on both sides. Gratuitous services are either immediate in their effect, or to take place at some future time. A beneficial service may be said to be immediately performed, when it confers an advantage, to which the person so benefitted has no direct or absolute right. As a gift transfers property, where there is no previous right. A subject, which has been already discussed. And promises may be said to relate to some future gift, or action, of which a full and sufficient explanation has before been given.
I. and II. Among all human actions that involve the interests of others, some are straightforward, while others are more complex. In the straightforward cases, all help is completely voluntary, but in the complex cases, there’s an exchange happening. In the first scenario, the help is given without expecting anything in return, while in the second, there’s a mutual obligation. Voluntary services can either have an immediate effect or take place later. A beneficial service is considered immediate when it provides an advantage that the recipient has no direct or absolute claim to, similar to how a gift transfers ownership without any prior right. This has been discussed previously. Promises can be viewed as relating to a future gift or action, which has been thoroughly explained earlier.
Services accompanied with mutual obligation are those where the use of a thing is allowed to any one without a complete alienation, or where labour is given in expectation of some valuable consideration. Under the first of these heads we may reckon the loan and use of all consumable or inconsumable property: and under the latter we may place all commissions to transact business, or all trusts to preserve the property of another. Similar to which are all promises of something to be done, except that they regard a future time. And in this view145 we may consider all the actions, which are now to be explained.
Services that come with mutual obligations are those where someone can use something without fully taking ownership, or where work is done with the expectation of receiving something valuable in return. In the first category, we can include the loan and use of both consumable and non-consumable property; in the second, we can include any commissions for conducting business or trusts set up to protect someone else's property. This is similar to all promises made to do something in the future. With this understanding, we can look at all the actions that will now be explained.
III. In all acts of exchange, there is either an adjustment of shares, or the profits are regarded as a common stock. And such adjustments are made by the Roman Lawyers in the following terms, "I give this to receive that in return, I do this in order for you to do that, or I do this for you to give me that."29 But the Romans exclude from that adjustment certain kinds of contracts, which they call EXPRESS ENGAGEMENTS. Not because they are entitled to any such peculiar name more than the simple acts of exchange already mentioned: but because from frequent use they have naturally derived a character similar to that of the original contract, from which they are named, though they are not attended exactly with the same circumstances, nor expressed directly in the same terms. Whereas in other contracts less frequently in use, the form was confined to an exact statement of all the circumstances of the case. An action upon which was therefore called by the Roman law an ACTION IN PRESCRIBED WORDS.
III. In all exchange transactions, there’s either an adjustment of shares or the profits are considered a shared resource. The Roman Lawyers express these adjustments with phrases like, "I give this to get that in return, I do this so that you will do that, or I do this for you to give me that."__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ However, the Romans exclude certain types of contracts from this adjustment, which they refer to as Express Engagements. This is not because these contracts deserve a special name more than the simple exchange acts mentioned earlier, but because they have developed a character similar to the original contract they’re named after due to frequent use, even though they don’t necessarily share the same circumstances or terms. In contrast, other, less commonly used contracts were strictly defined with a precise statement of all relevant circumstances. An action based on these was therefore called by Roman law an ACTION IN PRESCRIBED WORDS.
For the same reason, if those contracts, which are in general use, be accompanied with any of the requisite formalities, as in a bargain or sale, if the price had been agreed upon, though no part of the agreement had been performed by either of the parties, the civil law enforced an obligation to fulfil them. But as it considers those contracts which are seldom used, more in the light of voluntary engagements, depending upon the good faith of the respective parties, than upon legal obligation, it leaves both sides at liberty to relinquish them at any time prior to their being naturally performed.
For the same reason, if those contracts that are commonly used come with any of the necessary formalities, like in a sale, and if the price has been agreed upon, even if neither party has fulfilled any part of the agreement, civil law requires that they be honored. However, it views contracts that are rarely used more as voluntary commitments that rely on the good faith of both parties rather than strict legal obligations, allowing both sides to back out at any time before they are naturally carried out.
Distinctions of this kind are unknown to the law of nature, which gives SIMPLE AGREEMENTS equal authority with those, that are included by civilians in the class of EXPRESS CONTRACTS. And on the score of antiquity their pretensions are far superior. It is therefore perfectly conformable to the principles of nature to reduce the adjustment of all agreements, without any regard to the distinction between SIMPLE and EXPRESS CONTRACTS, to the three species already named. Thus, for instance,146 one thing is given for another, which constitutes barter, the most ancient kind of traffic; the next step in the progress of commercial intercourse is where one kind of money is given for another, a transaction which by merchants is called exchange; and a third species of contract is where money is given for any thing, as in the acts of selling and buying. Or the USE of one thing may be given for that of another; money also may be given for the USE of a thing, which last method constitutes the acts of letting and hiring.
Distinctions like these don’t exist in the law of nature, which grants Simple agreements equal weight to those categorized by legal experts as Express Agreements. In terms of historical significance, their claims are much stronger. Therefore, it aligns perfectly with natural principles to simplify all agreements, ignoring the difference between EASY and Express Agreements, into the three types already mentioned. For example, 146 one item is exchanged for another, which defines barter, the oldest form of trade. The next stage in commercial interaction is when one type of currency is exchanged for another, a transaction that merchants refer to as exchange. The third type of contract occurs when money is given for goods, as in buying and selling. Alternatively, the Use of one item may be traded for the use of another; money can also be exchanged for the Use of a thing, which involves leasing and renting.
The term use is to be understood here as applied not only to the bare unproductive use of a thing, but to that which is attended with profit, whether it be temporary, personal, hereditary or circumscribed, as was the case among the Hebrews with regard to transfers, which could be made for no longer a time than till the year of Jubilee. The very essence of a loan consists in a return of the same kind of thing after a stated period. A return which can take place only in things regulated by weight, number, or measure, whether it be in commodities or money. But the exchange of labour branches out into various kinds of recompence or return. As, for instance, a person gives his labour for money, which in the daily transactions of life is called hire or wages: where one undertakes to indemnify another for accidental losses or damages, it is called insurance: a species of contract scarce known to the ancients, but now forming a very important branch in all mercantile and maritime concerns.
The term "use" here refers not just to the simple, non-productive use of something, but to its usage that comes with profit, whether that profit is temporary, personal, hereditary, or limited, as seen among the Hebrews regarding transfers, which could only last until the year of Jubilee. The core idea of a loan is that it involves returning the same type of item after a specific period. This return can only happen with items that are measured by weight, number, or measure, whether they are goods or money. However, labor can lead to various forms of compensation or return. For example, someone might offer their labor in exchange for money, commonly known as hire or wages in everyday life; when one party agrees to compensate another for unexpected losses or damages, that’s called insurance. This kind of contract was hardly known to ancient societies but has become a crucial part of all commercial and maritime activities today.
IV. Acts of communication are those, where each contributes a share to the joint stock. Perhaps on one side, money, and on the other, skill and labour may be given. But in whatever way these concerns are regulated, they come under the denomination of partnerships. With this class we may rank the alliances of different states in war. And of the same description are those naval associations of individuals, so frequently formed in Holland for protection against pirates or other invaders, which is generally called an Admiralty, and to which the Greeks gave the name of a joint fleet.
IV. Acts of communication are those where each participant contributes to the shared effort. On one side, there might be money, and on the other, skills and labor. However these contributions are organized, they fall under the category of partnerships. This classification also includes alliances between different states during wartime. Similarly, there are naval associations formed by individuals, commonly established in Holland for protection against pirates or other invaders, which is generally referred to as an Navy, and which the Greeks called a joint fleet.
V. and VI. Now mixed actions are either such in themselves, or made so by some adventitious circumstance. Thus if I knowingly give one person a greater price for a thing than I can purchase it for of another, the excess of price may be considered partly as a gift, and partly as a purchase. Or if I engage a goldsmith to make me any147 article with his own materials, the price which I give will be partly a purchase, and partly wages. The feudal system too might be considered as a train of mixed contracts. Where the grant of the fee might be considered as a beneficial act; but the military service required by the Lord, in return for his protection, gave the fee the nature of a contract, where a person did one thing expecting for it the performance of another. But if any payment is attached to it by way of acknowledgement, it partakes of the nature of a quit rent. So money sent to sea by way of venture is something compounded of a contract, of a loan, and of an insurance.
V. and VI. Mixed actions can either be inherently mixed or become so due to certain circumstances. For example, if I knowingly pay one person more for something than I could buy it for from another, the extra amount can be viewed as partly a gift and partly a purchase. Similarly, if I hire a goldsmith to create an item using his own materials, the payment I make will be seen as partly a purchase and partly wages. The feudal system could also be seen as a series of mixed contracts, where granting a fee might be considered a beneficial act. However, the military service required by the lord in exchange for his protection gives the fee a contractual nature, as one party does something expecting a performance in return. If any payment is involved as a form of acknowledgment, it resembles a quit rent. Furthermore, money sent to sea as a venture combines aspects of a contract, a loan, and insurance.
VII. All acts beneficial to others, except those that are purely gratuitous, come under the denomination of contracts.
VII. All actions that benefit others, except for those that are completely voluntary, fall under the category of contracts.
VIII. In all contracts, natural justice requires that there should be an equality of terms: insomuch that the aggrieved party has an action against the other for overreaching him. This equality consists partly in the performance, and partly in the profits of the contract, applying to all the previous arrangements, and to the essential consequences of the agreement.
VIII. In all contracts, fairness demands that there should be equal terms: so much so that the wronged party has a right to take action against the other for taking advantage of them. This equality involves both the fulfillment of the contract and the benefits derived from it, relating to all prior arrangements and the fundamental outcomes of the agreement.
IX. As to an equality of terms previous to the contract, it is evident that a seller is bound to discover to a purchaser any defects, which are known to him, in a thing offered for sale; a rule not only established by civil laws, but strictly conformable to natural justice. For the words of agreement between contracting parties are even stronger than those, on which society is founded. And in this manner may be explained the observation of Diogenes the Babylonian, who in discussing this topic said, it is not every degree of silence, which amounts to concealment; nor is one person bound to disclose every thing, which may be of service to another. Thus for instance, a man of science is not strictly bound to communicate to another that knowledge, which might redound to his advantage. For contracts, which were invented to promote a beneficial intercourse among mankind, require some closer and more intimate connection than bare good-will to enforce their obligation. Upon which Ambrose has justly remarked, "that, in contracts, the faults of things exposed to sale ought to be made known, of which unless the seller has given intimation, though he may have transferred the right of property by sale, yet he is liable to an action of fraud."
IX. Regarding the equality of terms before the contract, it’s clear that a seller must disclose any defects in a product that they are aware of to a buyer. This rule is not only set by civil laws but also aligns with basic fairness. The agreements made between the parties involved are even more binding than the foundations of society. This idea helps explain Diogenes the Babylonian's comment on the matter: not every instance of silence constitutes concealment, and one person isn’t obligated to share everything that could benefit another. For example, a knowledgeable person isn’t strictly required to pass on information that might help someone else. Contracts were created to foster beneficial exchanges among people and require a deeper connection than mere goodwill to uphold their obligations. Ambrose rightly pointed out that in contracts, sellers must disclose any faults in the items for sale; if the seller fails to inform the buyer, even if they have transferred ownership through the sale, they can still be held liable for fraud.
148 But the same cannot be said of things not coming under the nature of contracts. Thus if any one should sell his corn at a high price, when he knows that many ships laden with grain are bound for that place, though it would be an act of kindness in him to communicate such intelligence to the purchasers, and though no advantage could be derived to him, from withholding the communication, but at the expence of charity, yet there is nothing unjust in it, or contrary to the general rules of dealing. The practice is vindicated by Diogenes in the passage of Cicero alluded to, he says, "I carried my commodities and offered them to sale, in selling them I demanded no greater price than others did; if the supply had been greater I would have sold them for less, and where is the wrong done to any one?" The maxim of Cicero therefore cannot generally be admitted, that, knowing a thing yourself, to wish another, whose interest it is to know it also, to remain ignorant of it, merely for the sake of your own advantage, amounts to a fraudulent concealment. By no means; for that only is a fraudulent concealment which immediately affects the nature of the contract: as for instance, in selling a house, to conceal the circumstance of its being infected with the plague, or having been ordered by public authority to be pulled down. But it is unnecessary to mention, that the person, with whom a seller treats, ought to be apprised of every circumstance attending the thing offered for sale; if it be lands, whether the tenure be subject to a rent-charge, or service of any kind, or be entirely free.
148 But the same can’t be said for situations that aren’t related to contracts. So, if someone sells their grain at a high price while knowing that many ships carrying grain are on their way to that location, it would be kind of them to share that information with the buyers. Even though they wouldn’t gain anything from keeping it a secret, except at the cost of being charitable, there’s nothing unjust about it or against general business practices. Diogenes justifies this in the passage from Cicero, stating, "I brought my goods and offered them for sale; I didn’t ask for a higher price than others were asking. If the supply had been larger, I would have sold them for less, so where’s the harm done to anyone?” Therefore, Cicero's principle cannot be universally accepted—that if you know something, wanting another person, who would benefit from knowing, to stay in the dark just for your own advantage, counts as fraudulent concealment. Not at all; the only time there’s fraudulent concealment is when it directly impacts the nature of the contract. For example, if you’re selling a house, hiding the fact that it’s infested with disease or that public authorities have ordered it to be demolished is wrong. It’s also important to mention that the buyer should be informed of all relevant details about the item being sold; if it’s land, whether the ownership comes with any rent obligations, services, or is completely free.
X. and XI. Nor is the equality that has been explained confined solely to the communication of all the circumstances of the case to the contracting parties, but it includes also an entire freedom of consent in both.
X. and XI. The equality we've talked about isn't limited just to sharing all the details of the case with the parties involved, but it also encompasses complete freedom of consent for both.
In the principal act itself, the proper equality requires that no more should be demanded either party than what is just. Which can scarce have a place in gratuitous acts. To stipulate for a recompence in return for a loan, or for the service of labour or commission is doing no wrong, but constitutes a kind of mixed contract, partaking of the nature of a gratuitous act, and an act of exchange. And in all acts of exchange, this equality is to be punctually observed. Nor can it be said that if one party promises more, it is to be looked upon as a gift. For men never enter into contracts with such intentions,149 nor ought the existence of such intentions ever be presumed, unless they evidently appear. For all promises or gifts, in these cases, are made with an expectation of receiving an equivalent in return. "When, in the words of Chrysostom, in all bargains and contracts, we are anxious to receive MORE and give LESS than is due, what is this but a species of fraud or robbery?" The writer of the life of Isidorus in Photius, relates of Hermias, that when any thing, which he wished to purchase was valued at too low a rate, he made up the deficiency of the price, thinking that to act otherwise was a species of injustice, though it might escape the observation of others. And in this sense, may be interpreted the law of the Hebrews.
In the main act itself, it’s essential that neither party demands more than what is fair. This principle hardly applies to voluntary acts. Asking for a reward in exchange for a loan, or for labor or services, is not wrong; it creates a type of mixed contract that has aspects of both a voluntary act and an exchange. In all exchanges, this fairness must be strictly maintained. It's also not accurate to claim that if one party offers more, it should be seen as a gift. People do not enter into contracts with that intention, and we shouldn’t assume such intentions exist unless they are clearly evident. In these cases, all promises or gifts expect some form of equivalent return. “When, in the words of Chrysostom, in all trades and contracts, we are eager to receive MORE and give LESS than what is fair, what is this if not a form of fraud or theft?” The writer of the life of Isidorus in Photius recounts that Hermias, when something he wanted to buy was priced too low, would cover the difference, believing that to do otherwise would be unjust, even if it went unnoticed by others. In this way, the law of the Hebrews can be understood.
XII. There remains another degree of equality to be considered, arising out of the following case. It may happen in contracts that although nothing is concealed, which ought to be made known, nor more exacted or taken by one party than is due, yet there may be some inequality without any fault in either of the parties. Perhaps, for instance there might be some unknown defect in the thing, or there might be some mistake in the price. Yet, in such cases, to preserve that equality, which is an essential requisite in all contracts, the party suffering by such defect or mistake, ought to be indemnified by the other. For in all engagements it either is, or ought to be a standing rule, that both parties should have equal and just advantages.
XII. There's another level of equality to consider, arising from the following situation. In contracts, it may happen that even if nothing is hidden that should be disclosed, and neither party takes more than what's fair, there might still be some inequality without any wrongdoing by either side. For example, there could be an unknown flaw in the item, or there might be a miscalculation in the price. In such cases, to maintain the equality, which is crucial in all contracts, the party affected by the flaw or mistake should be compensated by the other. In all agreements, it should be a rule that both parties receive equal and fair benefits.
It was not in every kind of equality that the Roman law established this rule, passing over slight occasions, in order to discourage frequent and frivolous litigation. It only interposed its judicial authority in weighty matters, where the price exceeded the just value by one half. Laws indeed, as Cicero has said, have power to compel, or restrain men, whereas philosophers can only appeal to their reason or understanding. Yet those, who are not subject to the power of civil laws ought to comply with whatever reason points out to them to be just: So too ought they, who are subject to the power of human laws, to perform whatever natural and divine justice requires, even in cases, where the laws neither give nor take away the right, but only forbear to enforce it for particular reasons.
It wasn’t in every type of equality that Roman law established this rule, skipping over minor issues to discourage frequent and trivial lawsuits. It only intervened in serious matters where the price exceeded the fair value by one half. Laws, as Cicero said, have the power to compel or restrain people, while philosophers can only appeal to their reason or understanding. However, those who are not subject to the authority of civil laws should follow what reason indicates as just. Likewise, those under human laws should act according to what natural and divine justice demands, even in situations where the laws neither grant nor take away rights but simply choose not to enforce them for specific reasons.
XIII. There is a certain degree of equality, too, in beneficial or gratuitous acts, not indeed like that prevailing150 in contracts of exchange, but proceeding upon a supposition of the hardship, that any one should receive detriment from voluntary services, which he bestows. For which reason a voluntary agent ought to be indemnified for the expence or inconvenience, which he incurs, by undertaking the business of another. A borrower too is bound to repair a thing that has been damaged or destroyed. Because he is bound to the owner not only for the thing itself, by virtue of the property which he retains in it, but he owes a debt of gratitude also for the favour of the loan; unless it appears that the thing so lent would have perished, had it even remained in possession of the owner himself. In this case, the owner loses nothing by the loan. On the other hand, the depositary has received nothing but a trust. If the thing therefore is destroyed, he cannot be bound to restore what is no longer in existence, nor can he be required to make a recompence, where he has derived no advantage; for in taking the trust he did not receive a favour, but conferred one. In a pawn, the same as in a thing let out for hire, a middle way of deciding the obligation may be pursued, so that the person taking it is not answerable, like a borrower, for every accident, and yet he is obliged to use greater care, than a bare depositary, in keeping it safe. For though taking a pledge is a gratuitous acceptance, it is followed by some of the conditions of a contract. All these cases are conformable to the Roman law, though not originally derived from thence, but from natural equity. Rules, all of which may be found among other nations. And, among other works, we may refer to the third book and forty-second chapter of the Guide for doubtful cases, written by Moses Maimonides, a Jewish writer.
XIII. There is a certain level of equality in beneficial or voluntary acts, not like that found in exchange contracts, but based on the assumption that it's unfair for someone to suffer loss from voluntary services they provide. For this reason, a person who acts voluntarily should be compensated for the expenses or inconvenience they incur while taking on someone else’s work. A borrower is also responsible for repairing anything that gets damaged or destroyed. This is because they owe the owner not just for the item itself, due to their ongoing possession of it, but also have a debt of gratitude for the favor of the loan; unless it can be shown that the item would have been lost even if the owner had kept it. In that case, the owner gains nothing from the loan. Conversely, the person who holds a deposit has received only a trust. Therefore, if the item is destroyed, they cannot be required to return something that no longer exists, nor can they be asked to compensate for something they didn't benefit from; because in taking the trust, they did not receive a favor, but offered one instead. In the case of a pawn, similar to something rented out, a balanced approach can be taken regarding obligation, so that the taker is not held responsible like a borrower for every unexpected event, yet still must exercise more care than a simple depositary in keeping it safe. While accepting a pledge is voluntary, it comes with some contractual conditions. All these situations align with Roman law, though they didn’t originate from it, but rather from natural fairness. These principles can be found in other cultures as well. Notable works, such as the third book and forty-second chapter of the Guide for Uncertain Situations by Moses Maimonides, a Jewish scholar, contain similar discussions.
Upon the same principles the nature of all other contracts may be explained; but the leading features in those of certain descriptions seemed sufficient for a treatise like the present.
Based on the same principles, we can explain the nature of all other contracts; however, the main aspects of certain types seem to be enough for a discussion like this one.
XIV. The general demand for any thing, as Aristotle has clearly proved, constitutes the true measure of its value, which may be seen particularly from the practice prevailing among barbarous nations of exchanging one thing for another. But this is not the only standard: for the humours and caprice of mankind, which dictate and controul all regulations, give a nominal value to many superfluities. It was luxury, says Pliny, that first discovered151 the value of pearls, and Cicero has somewhere observed, that the worth of such things can only be estimated by the desires of men.
XIV. The overall demand for anything, as Aristotle clearly demonstrated, serves as the true measure of its value, which can especially be seen in the practice among primitive societies of trading one item for another. But this isn't the only standard: the moods and whims of people, which influence and control all rules, assign a nominal value to many unnecessary items. Luxury, Pliny states, was what first revealed the value of pearls, and Cicero has noted that the worth of such items can only be assessed by people's desires.
But on the other hand, it happens that the plentiful supply of necessaries lowers their price. This Seneca, in the 15th chapter of his sixth book on benefits, proves by many instances, which he concludes with the following observation, "the price of every thing must be regulated by the market, and notwithstanding all your praises, it is worth nothing more than it can be sold for." To which we may add the authority of Paulus the Lawyer, who says, the prices of things do not depend upon the humours and interest of individuals, but upon common estimation, that is, as he explains himself elsewhere, according to the worth which they are of to all.
But on the other hand, having a lot of goods available can actually lower their prices. Seneca proves this in the 15th chapter of his sixth book on benefits with many examples, concluding with, "the price of everything must be set by the market, and regardless of all your compliments, it’s worth nothing more than what it can sell for." Additionally, we can reference the views of Paulus the Lawyer, who states that prices aren’t determined by individual preferences and interests but by common perception, which he explains in another context as the value they hold for everyone.
Hence it is that things are valued in proportion to what is usually offered or given for them, a rule admitting of great variation and latitude, except in certain cases, where the law has fixed a standard price. In the common price of articles, the labour and expence of the merchant in procuring them is taken into the account, and the sudden changes so frequent in all markets depend upon the number of buyers, whether it be great or small, and upon the money and marketable commodities, whether they be plentiful or scarce.
Hence, things are valued based on what is typically offered or given for them, a principle that allows for a lot of variation, except in specific cases where the law has set a standard price. In the usual pricing of items, the labor and costs the merchant incurs in obtaining them are considered, and the sudden changes that frequently happen in all markets depend on the number of buyers, whether large or small, and on the availability of money and goods, whether they are abundant or scarce.
There may indeed be casualties, owing to which a thing may be lawfully bought or sold above or below the market price. Thus for instance, a thing by being damaged may have lost its original or common value, or that, which otherwise would not have been disposed of, may be bought or sold from some particular liking or aversion. All these circumstances ought to be made known to the contracting parties. Regard too should be had to the loss or gain arising from delay or promptness of payment.
There may indeed be losses, which can lead to things being legally bought or sold for more or less than the market value. For example, an item that has been damaged might have lost its original or typical worth, or something that wouldn’t normally be sold might be due to a specific preference or dislike. All these details should be communicated to the parties involved in the contract. Attention should also be given to the potential loss or gain that comes from whether payment is made quickly or delayed.
XV. In buying and selling we must observe, that the bargain is completed from the very moment of the contract, even without delivery, and that is the most simple way of dealing. Thus Seneca says, that a sale is a transfer of one's right and property in a thing to another, which is done in all exchanges. But if it be settled that the property shall not be transferred immediately, still the seller will be bound to convey it at the stated period, taking in the mean time all the profits and losses.
XV. In buying and selling, we need to recognize that a deal is finalized the moment the contract is made, even without delivery, and that’s the simplest way to do business. As Seneca points out, a sale is the transfer of someone's rights and ownership of a thing to someone else, which happens in all exchanges. However, if it’s agreed that the property won't be transferred right away, the seller is still required to give it over at the agreed time, while also taking on all the profits and losses in the meantime.
152 Whereas the completion of bargain and sale, by giving the purchaser a right of possession and ejectment, and conveying to him the hazard with all the profits of the property, even before it is transferred, are regulations of the civil law not universally observed. Indeed some legislators have made the seller answerable for all accidents and damages, till the actual delivery of possession is made, as Theophrastus has observed in a passage in Stobaeus, under the title of laws, where the reader will find many customs, relating to the formalities of sale, to earnest, to repentance of a bargain, very different from the rules of the Roman law. And among the Rhodians, Dion Prusaeensis informs us that all sales and contracts were confirmed by being entered in a public register.
152 While completing a sale gives the buyer the right to possess and eject others, along with the risk and all the profits of the property even before it's officially transferred, these rules of civil law aren't always followed everywhere. In fact, some lawmakers hold the seller responsible for any accidents or damages until possession is actually delivered, as noted by Theophrastus in a section of Stobaeus titled laws, where you'll find various customs regarding the formalities of sale, earnest money, and the option to back out of a deal, which differ significantly from Roman law. Additionally, Dion Prusaeensis tells us that in Rhodes, all sales and contracts were validated by being recorded in a public register.
We must observe too that, if a thing has been twice sold, of the two sales the one is valid, where an immediate transfer of the property has been made, either by delivery of possession, or in any other mode. For by this means the seller gives up an absolute right, which could not pass by a promise alone.
We also need to note that if something has been sold twice, the valid sale is the one where the property was immediately transferred, either through delivery or by any other method. This is because the seller is giving up a complete right, which can't be transferred by just a promise.
XVI. It is not every kind of monopoly that amounts to a direct violation of the laws of nature. The Sovereign power may have very just reasons for granting monopolies, and that too at a settled price: a noble instance of which we find in the history of Joseph, who governed Egypt under the auspices of Pharaoh.30 So also under the Roman government the people of Alexandria, as we are informed by Strabo, enjoyed the monopoly of all Indian and Ethiopian goods.
XVI. Not every type of monopoly is a clear violation of natural laws. The ruling authority may have valid reasons for granting monopolies, even at a fixed price: a good example of this is found in the story of Joseph, who governed Egypt with the backing of Pharaoh. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__. Similarly, during the Roman Empire, the people of Alexandria, as noted by Strabo, had the exclusive rights to all goods from India and Ethiopia.
A monopoly also may, in some cases, be established by individuals, provided they sell at a reasonable rate. But all combinations to raise the necessary articles of life to an exorbitant rate, or all violent and fraudulent attempts to prevent the market from being supplied, or to buy up certain commodities, in order to enhance the price, are public injuries and punishable as such.31 Or indeed153 ANY WAY of preventing the importation of goods, or buying them up in order to sell them at a greater rate than usual, though the price, UNDER SOME PARTICULAR CIRCUMSTANCES, may not seem unreasonable, is fully shewn by Ambrose in his third book of Offices to be a breach of charity; though it come not directly under the prohibition of laws.
A monopoly can sometimes be established by individuals as long as they sell their products at a fair price. However, any attempts to raise the prices of essential goods to an unreasonable level, or any forceful and deceptive efforts to restrict market supply, or to buy up certain products to drive up prices, are harmful to the public and punishable as such.. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ In fact, 153 ANY WAY of preventing goods from being imported, or purchasing them to sell at a higher price than usual—even if the price, UNDER CERTAIN CIRCUMSTANCES, may not seem unreasonable—is clearly demonstrated by Ambrose in his third book of Offices to be a violation of fairness, even though it might not directly violate the law.
XVII. As to money, it may be observed that its uses do not result from any value intrinsically belonging to the precious metals, or to the specific denomination and shape of coin, but from the general application which can be made of it, as a standard of payment for all commodities. For whatever is taken as a common measure of all other things, ought to be liable, in itself, to but little variation. Now the precious metals are of this description, possessing nearly the same intrinsic value at all times and in all places. Though the nominal value of the same quantity of gold and silver, whether paid by weight or coin will be greater or less, in proportion to the abundance or scarcity of the things for which there is a general demand.
XVII. When it comes to money, it’s important to note that its usefulness doesn't come from any intrinsic value tied to precious metals or the specific design and shape of coins. Instead, it arises from its widespread use as a standard for payment across all goods. Anything that serves as a common measure for everything else should have minimal fluctuations in its own value. Precious metals fit this description because they generally have a consistent intrinsic value everywhere and at all times. Although the stated value of a certain amount of gold or silver—whether paid by weight or as coins—can vary based on how abundant or scarce the desired items are, their fundamental value remains stable.
XVIII. Letting and hiring, as Caius has justly said, come nearest to selling and buying, and are regulated by the same principles. For the price corresponds to the rent or hire, and the property of a thing to the liberty of using it. Wherefore as an owner must bear the loss of a thing that perishes, so a person hiring a thing or renting a farm must bear the loss of all ordinary accidents, as for instance, those of barrenness or any other cause, which may diminish his profits.32 Nor will the154 owner, on that account, be the less entitled to the stipulated price or rent, because he gave the other the right of enjoyment, which at that time was worth so much, unless it was then agreed that the value should depend upon such contingencies.
XVIII. Leasing and renting, as Caius has rightly pointed out, are very similar to buying and selling, and are governed by the same principles. The cost corresponds to the rent or fee, and ownership of an item relates to the right to use it. Therefore, just as an owner must accept the loss of something that is destroyed, someone renting an item or leasing land must also bear the risk of all ordinary incidents, such as poor harvests or any other issues that could reduce their profits.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Additionally, the 154 owner is still entitled to the agreed price or rent, even if they allowed someone else to use the property, which had a certain value at the time, unless it was specifically decided that the value would depend on such uncertainties.
If an owner, when the first tenant has been prevented from using a thing, shall have let it to another, all the profits accruing from it are due to the first tenant, for it would not be equitable that the owner should be made richer by what belonged to another.
If an owner has let a property to someone else after the first tenant was unable to use it, all the profits from that property go to the first tenant. It's not fair for the owner to benefit financially from something that belongs to someone else.
XIX. The next topic, that comes under consideration, is the lawfulness of taking interest for the use of a consumable thing; the arguments brought against which appear by no means such as to command our assent. For as to what is said of the loan of consumable property being a gratuitous act, and entitled to no return, the same reasoning may apply to the letting of inconsumable property for hire, requiring a recompence for the use of which is never deemed unlawful, though it gives the contract itself a different denomination.
XIX. The next topic we need to consider is whether it’s legal to charge interest for the use of something that can be consumed. The arguments against this do not seem convincing. When it’s said that lending consumable property is a free act and should not expect any return, the same logic can apply to renting out non-consumable property, where charging for its use is never considered wrong, even though it gives the contract a different label.
Nor is there any more weight in the objection to taking interest for the use of money, which in its own nature is barren and unproductive. For the same may be said of houses and other things, which are unproductive and unprofitable without the industry of man.33
Nor is there any more validity in the objection to charging interest for the use of money, which is inherently unproductive and inactive. The same can be said about houses and other assets, which are unproductive and yield no profit without human effort. man.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
There is something more specious in the argument, which maintains, that, as one thing is here given in return for another, and the use and profits of a thing cannot155 be distinguished from the thing itself, when the very use of it depends upon its consumption, nothing more ought to be required in return for the use, than what is barely equivalent to the thing itself.
There’s something questionable in the argument that states, since one thing is given in exchange for another, and the benefits of a thing can’t be separated from the thing itself, especially when its use relies on its consumption, nothing more should be expected in return for its use than what is simply equal to the thing itself.
But it is necessary to remark, that when it is said the enjoyment of the profits of consumable things, whose property is transferred, in the use, to the borrower or trustee, was introduced by an act of the senate, this does not properly come under the notion of Usufruct, which certainly in its original signification answers to no such right. Yet it does not follow that such a right is of no value, but on the contrary money may be required for surrendering it to the proprietor. Thus also the right of not paying money or wine borrowed till after a certain time is a thing whose value may be ascertained, the delay being considered as some advantage. Therefore in a mortgage the profits of the land answer the use of money. But what Cato, Cicero, Plutarch and others allege against usury, applies not so much to the nature of the thing, as to the accidental circumstances and consequences with which it is commonly attended.34
But it’s important to note that when it’s stated that the enjoyment of the profits from consumable goods, whose ownership is transferred, is granted through an act of the senate, this doesn’t quite fit the definition of Usufruct, which certainly in its original meaning doesn’t refer to such a right. However, this doesn’t mean that such a right has no value; on the contrary, money may be required to return it to the owner. Similarly, the right to delay payment for borrowed money or wine until a certain time has an ascertainable value, as the delay itself is seen as an advantage. Thus, in a mortgage, the profits from the land serve as the equivalent of money. However, what Cato, Cicero, Plutarch, and others say about usury doesn’t directly relate to the nature of the concept itself, but rather to the incidental circumstances and consequences that usually accompany it.
XX. There are some kinds of interest, which are thought to wear the appearance of usury, and generally come under that denomination, but which in reality are contracts of a different nature. The five shillings commission which a banker, for instance, charges upon every hundred pounds, is not so much an interest in addition to five per cent, as a compensation for his trouble, and156 for the risk and inconvenience he incurs, by the loan of his money, which he might have employed in some other lucrative way. In the same manner a person who lends money to many individuals, and, for that purpose, keeps certain sums of cash in his hands, ought to have some indemnity for the continual loss of interest upon those sums, which may be considered as so much dead stock. Nor can any recompence of this kind be branded with the name of usury. Demosthenes, in his speech against Pantaenetus, condemns it as an odious act of injustice, to charge with usury a man, who in order to keep his principal undiminished, or to assist another with money, lends out the savings of his industry and frugal habits, upon a moderate interest.
XX. There are certain types of interest that appear to be usury and are usually labeled as such, but they are actually different types of contracts. For example, the five shillings commission that a banker charges on every hundred pounds isn't just an additional interest to the five percent; it's a fee for his time and for the risk and hassle he takes on by lending his money, which he could have used in other profitable ways. Similarly, someone who lends money to multiple people and keeps a certain amount of cash on hand should receive some compensation for the ongoing loss of interest on that money, which could be seen as inactive assets. This kind of compensation can't be considered usury. Demosthenes, in his speech against Pantaenetus, condemns it as a shameful injustice to label someone as a usurer when they lend their hard-earned savings at a reasonable interest rate to keep their principal intact or to help someone else.
XXI. Those human laws, which allow a compensation to be made for the use of money or any other thing, are neither repugnant to natural nor revealed law. Thus in Holland, where the rate of interest upon common loans was eight per cent, there was no injustice in requiring twelve per cent of merchants; because the hazard was greater. The justice and reasonableness indeed of all these regulations must be measured by the hazard or inconvenience of lending. For where the recompence exceeds this, it becomes an act of extortion or oppression.
XXI. The laws that permit compensation for the use of money or anything else aren't against natural law or revealed law. In Holland, for example, where the interest rate on regular loans was eight percent, it was fair to charge merchants twelve percent because the risk was higher. The fairness and reasonableness of these rules should be assessed based on the risk or inconvenience of lending. If the compensation goes beyond this, it turns into an act of extortion or oppression.
XXII. Contracts for guarding against danger, which are called insurances, will be deemed fraudulent and void, if the insurer knows beforehand that the thing insured is already safe, or has reached its place of destination, and the other party that it is already destroyed or lost. And that not so much on account of the equality naturally requisite in all contracts of exchange, as because the danger and uncertainty is the very essence of such contract. Now the premium upon all insurances must be regulated by common estimation.35
XXII. Contracts meant to protect against risk, known as insurances, will be considered fraudulent and invalid if the insurer is aware that the insured item is already safe or has arrived at its destination, and the other party knows that it has been destroyed or lost. This is not only due to the fairness that is usually required in any exchange agreement, but also because the risk and uncertainty are the core elements of this type of contract. Now, the premium for all insurances must be determined by common estimation.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
157 XXIII. In trading partnerships, where money is contributed by both parties; if the proportions be equal, the profits and the losses ought to be equal also. But if they be unequal, the profits and the losses must bear the same proportion, as Aristotle has shewn at the conclusion of the eighth book of his Ethics. And the same rule will hold good where equal or unequal proportions of labor are contributed. Labor may be given as a balance against money, or both labor and money may be given, according to the general maxim that one man's labour is an equivalent for another man's money.
157 XXIII. In trading partnerships where both parties contribute money, if the contributions are equal, then the profits and losses should also be equal. However, if the contributions are unequal, the profits and losses must reflect the same ratio, as Aristotle demonstrated at the end of the eighth book of his Ethics. This principle also applies whether the contributions of labor are equal or unequal. Labor can be considered a counterbalance to money, or both labor and money can be contributed, following the general principle that one person’s labor is equivalent to another person’s money.
But there are various ways of forming these agreements. If a man borrows money to employ his skill upon in trading for himself, whether he gains or loses the whole, he is answerable to the owner for the principal. But where a man unites his labor to the capital of another in partnership, there he becomes a partner in the principal, to a share of which he is entitled. In the first of these cases the principal is not compared as a balance against the labor, but it is lent upon terms proportioned to the risk of losing it, or the probable gains to be derived from it. In the other case, the price of labour is weighed, as it were, against the money, and the party who bestows it, is entitled to an equivalent share in the capital.
But there are different ways to form these agreements. If a person borrows money to use their skills in their own business, whether they make a profit or a loss, they are responsible to the lender for the original amount. However, when someone combines their work with another person's capital in a partnership, they become a partner in the principal and are entitled to a share of it. In the first case, the principal isn't measured against the labor, but it is lent based on the risk of losing it or the potential profits that might come from it. In the second case, the value of the labor is compared to the money, and the person providing the labor is entitled to an equivalent share of the capital.
What has been said of labour may be applied to voyages, and all other hazardous undertakings. For it is contrary to the very nature of partnerships for any one to share in the gain, and to be exempt from the losses. Yet it may be so settled without any degree of injustice. For there may be a mixed contract arising out of a contract of insurance in which due equality may be preserved, by allowing the person, who has taken upon himself the losses, to receive a greater share of the gain than he would otherwise have done. But it is a thing quite inadmissible that any one should be responsible for the losses without partaking of the gains; for a communion of interests is so natural to society that it cannot subsist without it.
What has been said about work can also apply to trips and other risky ventures. It's against the very nature of partnerships for someone to benefit from the profits while being protected from the losses. However, this can be arranged without any unfairness. There can be a mixed agreement stemming from an insurance contract where fair balance is maintained by allowing the person who takes on the losses to receive a larger share of the profits than they would normally get. But it is completely unacceptable for someone to bear the losses without sharing in the profits; a shared interest is so fundamental to society that it cannot survive without it.
What has been said by writers on the civil law, that the shares are understood to be equal where they are not expressly named, is true where equal quotas have158 been contributed. But in a GENERAL partnership the shares are not to be measured by what may arise from this or that article, but from the probable profits of the whole.
What writers on civil law have said is true: shares are considered equal when they aren't specifically named, as long as equal contributions have been made. However, in a GENERAL partnership, shares shouldn't be based on specific items, but rather on the expected profits of the entire business.
XXIV. In naval associations the common motive of utility is self-defence against pirates: though they may sometimes be formed from less worthy motives. In computing the losses to be sustained by each, it is usual to estimate the number of men, the number of ships, and the quantity of merchandise protected. And what has hitherto been said will be found conformable to natural justice.
XXIV. In naval alliances, the main reason for coming together is self-defense against pirates, although they can sometimes be created for less honorable reasons. When calculating the losses each party may face, it's common to consider the number of men, the number of ships, and the amount of goods being protected. Everything that has been mentioned so far aligns with natural justice.
XXV. Nor does the voluntary36 law of nations appear to make any alteration here. However, there is one exception, which is, that where equal terms have been agreed upon, if no fraud has been used, nor any necessary information withheld, they shall be considered as equal in an external37 point of view. So that no action can be maintained in a court for such inequality. Which was the case in the civil law before Dioclesian's constitution. So among those, who are bound by the law of nations alone, there can be no redress or constraint on such account.38
XXV. The voluntary __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ law of nations doesn't seem to change anything here. However, there is one exception: where equal terms have been agreed upon, as long as there has been no fraud or essential information withheld, they should be viewed as equal from an external__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ perspective. Therefore, no legal action can be taken in court for such inequality. This was similarly the case in civil law before Dioclesian's constitution. Thus, for those bound only by the law of nations, there can be no remedy or enforcement regarding such account.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
159 And this is the meaning of what Pomponius says, that in a bargain and sale, one man may NATURALLY overreach another: an allowance which is not to be construed, as a right, but is only so far a permission, that no legal remedy can be used against the person, who is determined to insist upon the agreement.
159 This is what Pomponius means: in a deal, one person can naturally take advantage of another. This should not be seen as a right, but rather as a permission, since no legal action can be taken against someone who insists on sticking to the agreement.
In this place, as in many others, the word natural signifies nothing more than what is received by general custom. In this sense the Apostle Paul has said, that it is naturally disgraceful for a man to wear long hair; a thing, in which there is nothing repugnant to nature, but which is the general practice among some nations. Indeed many writers, both sacred and profane, give the name of NATURAL to what is only CUSTOMARY and HABITUAL.
In this place, as in many others, the word "natural" simply means what is accepted by common practice. In this context, the Apostle Paul mentioned that it's considered naturally disgraceful for a man to wear long hair; this isn't something that goes against nature, but it's the usual behavior in some cultures. In fact, many writers, both sacred and secular, refer to what is merely CUSTOMARY and HABITUAL as NATURAL.
CHAPTER XIII.
On Oaths.
Efficacy of oaths among Pagans—Deliberation requisite in oaths—The sense, in which oaths are understood to be taken, to be adhered to—To be taken according to the usual meaning of the words—The subject of them to be lawful—Not to counteract moral obligations—In what sense oaths are an appeal to God—The purport of oaths—To be faithfully observed in all cases—The controul of sovereigns over the oaths of subjects—Observations on our Saviour's prohibition of oaths—Forms substituted for oaths.
The effectiveness of oaths among Pagans—It's important to think carefully before making oaths—Understanding how oaths are taken and kept—They should align with the common meaning of the words used—The topic of the oath must be lawful—They should not violate moral responsibilities—How oaths serve as a call to God—The reason for oaths—They should be honored in every situation—The authority that rulers have over the oaths of their subjects—Comments on our Savior's prohibition of oaths—Other options used instead of oaths.
I. The sanctity of an oath with regard to promises, agreements, and contracts, has always been held in the greatest esteem, in every age and among every people. For as Sophocles has said in his Hippodamia, "The soul is bound to greater caution by the addition of an oath. For it guards us against two things, most to be avoided, the reproach of friends, and the wrath of heaven." In addition to which the authority of Cicero may be quoted, who says, our forefathers intended that an oath should be the best security for sincerity of affirmation, and the observance of good faith. "For, as he observes in another place, there can be no stronger tie, to the fulfilment of our word and promise, than an oath, which is a solemn appeal to the testimony of God."
I. The importance of an oath in relation to promises, agreements, and contracts has always been highly valued throughout history and among all cultures. As Sophocles stated in his Hippodamia, "The soul is bound to be more careful with the addition of an oath. For it protects us from two things we should avoid the most: the criticism of friends and the anger of the divine." Additionally, we can reference Cicero, who said that our ancestors believed an oath should be the best assurance of honesty and good faith. "For, as he notes elsewhere, there is no stronger bond to keep our word and promise than an oath, which is a solemn appeal to the testimony of God."
II. The next point, to be considered, is the original force and extent of oaths.
II. The next point to consider is the power and scope of oaths.
And in the first place the arguments, that have been used respecting promises and contracts, apply to oaths also, which ought never to be taken but with the most deliberate reflection and judgment. Nor can any one lawfully take an oath, with a secret intention of not being bound by it. For the obligation is an inseparable and necessary consequence of an oath, and every act accompanied with an obligation is supposed to proceed from a deliberate purpose of mind. Every one is bound likewise to adhere to an oath in that sense, in which it is usually understood to be taken. For an oath being an appeal to God, should declare the full truth in the sense in which it is understood. And this is the sense upon which Cicero insists that all oaths should be performed161 and adhered to in that sense, in which the party imposing them intended they should be taken. For although in other kinds of promises a condition may easily be implied, to release the promiser; yet that is a latitude by no means admissible in an oath. And on this point an appeal may be made to that passage, where the admirable writer of the Epistle to the Hebrews has said, God willing more abundantly to shew unto the heirs of the promise the immutability of his counsel confirmed it by an oath: that by two immutable things, in which it was impossible for God to deceive, we might have a strong consolation. In order to understand these words, we must observe that the sacred writers, in speaking of God, often attribute to him human passions, rather in conformity to our finite capacities, than to his infinite nature. For God does not actually change his decrees, though he may be said to do so, and to repent, whenever he acts otherwise than the words seemed to indicate, the occasion, on which they were delivered, having ceased. Now this may easily be applied in the case of threats, as conferring no right; sometimes too in promises, where a condition is implied. The Apostle therefore names two things denoting immutability, a promise which confers a right, and an oath, which admits of no mental reservations.
And first of all, the arguments that have been made about promises and contracts also apply to oaths, which should never be taken without careful thought and consideration. No one can lawfully take an oath with the secret intention of not being bound by it. The obligation that comes with an oath is an inseparable and necessary result of it, and every act accompanied by an obligation is assumed to come from a deliberate intent. Everyone is also bound to uphold an oath in the way it is typically understood. Since an oath is an appeal to God, it should express the full truth in the sense in which it is understood. This is the meaning that Cicero insists should guide how all oaths are performed and honored, based on the intention of the person who imposed them. While in other types of promises a condition can easily be implied to release the person making the promise, that flexibility is not acceptable with an oath. We can refer to the passage in the Epistle to the Hebrews, where the writer beautifully states that If all goes well to more fully show the heirs of the promise the unchangeable nature of His counsel confirmed it with an oath: that by two unchangeable things, in which it was impossible for God to lie, we might have strong comfort. To understand these words, we need to notice that sacred writers often ascribe human emotions to God, more to fit our limited understanding than to reflect His infinite nature. God doesn’t actually change His decisions, even though it may seem that way when He acts differently than the words suggested, as the circumstances for which they were given have changed. This can easily apply to threats, as they confer no right; sometimes it can also apply to promises where a condition is implied. Therefore, the Apostle mentions two things that signify unchangeability: a promise that grants a right and an oath that allows for no mental reservations.
From the above arguments it is easy to comprehend what is to be thought of an oath fraudulently obtained. For if it is certain that a person took the oath upon a supposition, which afterwards was proved to have no foundation, and but for the belief of which he would never have taken it, he will not be bound by it. But if it appears that he would have taken it without that supposition; he must abide by his oath, because oaths allow of no evasion.
From the arguments above, it's clear what to think about an oath that was obtained through deceit. If it's certain that a person took the oath based on a belief that later turned out to be false, and that belief was the reason he took it, he won’t be held to it. However, if it seems he would have taken the oath regardless of that belief, he must stick to his oath, as oaths provide no way out.
III. The meaning of an oath should not be stretched beyond the usual acceptation of words. Therefore there was no breach of their oath in those, who, having sworn that they would not give their daughters in marriage to the Benjamites, permitted those that had been carried off to live with them. For there is a difference between giving a thing, and not recovering that which is lost.
III. The meaning of an oath shouldn't be expanded beyond the usual understanding of the words. So, there was no violation of their oath by those who, after swearing they wouldn't give their daughters in marriage to the Benjamites, allowed those who had been taken to live with them. Because there's a difference between giving something and not getting back what is lost.
IV. To give validity to an oath, the obligation, which it imposes ought to be lawful. Therefore a sworn promise, to commit an illegal act, to do any thing in violation of natural or revealed law, will be of no effect.
IV. For an oath to be valid, the obligation it creates must be lawful. So, a sworn promise to carry out an illegal act or to do anything against natural or divine law will be meaningless.
162 V. Indeed if a thing promised upon oath be not actually illegal, but only an obstruction to some greater moral duty, in that case also the oath will not be valid. Because it is a duty which we owe to God not to deprive ourselves of the freedom of doing all the good in our power.
162 V. If something promised under oath isn't actually illegal but just hinders a more important moral obligation, then the oath won't hold up. It's our responsibility to God not to limit our ability to do all the good we can.
VI. Oaths may differ in form, and yet agree in substance. For they all ought to include an appeal to God, calling upon him to witness the truth, or to punish the falsehood of their assertions, both of which amount to the same thing. For an appeal to the testimony of a superior, who has a right to punish, is the same as requiring him to avenge an act of perfidy. Now the omniscience of God gives him power to punish, as well as to witness every degree of falsehood.
VI. Oaths may vary in form, but they should all agree in meaning. They should all involve a call to God, asking Him to witness the truth or to punish any lies in what is being said, and both serve the same purpose. Calling on a higher power who has the authority to punish is like asking Him to address a betrayal. God's all-knowing nature gives Him the power to both punish and witness every level of falsehood.
VII. It was a custom with the ancients to swear by persons or beings expressly distinct from the supreme creator, either imprecating the wrath of those by whom they swore, whether it were the sun, the heavens, or the earth; or swearing by their own heads, by their children, their country or their prince, and calling for destruction upon THEM, if there were any falsehood in their oaths.
VII. The ancients had a tradition of swearing by figures or entities clearly separate from the supreme creator, either invoking the anger of those they swore by, whether it was the sun, the skies, or the land; or swearing by themselves, their kids, their nation or their ruler, and asking for their own downfall if they were lying in their oaths.
Nor was this practice confined to Heathen nations only, but, as we are informed by Philo, it prevailed among the Jews. For he says that we ought not, in taking an oath upon every occasion, to have recourse to the maker and father of the universe, but to swear by our parents, by the heavens, the earth, the universe. Thus Joseph is said to have sworn by the life of Pharaoh, according to the received custom of the Egyptians. Nor does our Saviour, in the fifth chapter of St. Matthew's Gospel, intend, as it is supposed by some, to consider these oaths to be less binding than those taken expressly by the name of God. But as the Jews were too much inclined to make use of, and yet disregard them, he shews them that they are real oaths. For, as Ulpian has well observed, he who swears by his own life, seems to swear by God, bearing a respect and reference to his divine power. In the same manner Christ shews that he, who swears by the temple, swears by God who presides in the temple, and that he who swears by Heaven, swears by God, who sits upon the Heavens. But the Jewish teachers of that day thought that men were not bound by oaths made in the name of created beings, unless some penalty were annexed, as if the thing, by163 which they swore, were consecrated to God. For this is the kind of oath implied in the word κορβᾶν {korban} as BY A GIFT. And it is this error of theirs, which Christ refutes.
Nor was this practice limited to pagan nations; according to Philo, it was common among the Jews as well. He states that we shouldn't always swear by the creator and father of the universe, but rather by our parents, by the heavens, by the earth, and by the universe. For instance, Joseph reportedly swore by Pharaoh's life, in line with Egyptian customs. Furthermore, in the fifth chapter of St. Matthew's Gospel, Jesus doesn't imply that these oaths are less binding than those taken in God's name. Instead, he aims to show the Jews, who tended to use and then disregard such oaths, that they are indeed serious. As Ulpian has pointed out, someone who swears by their own life is effectively swearing by God, acknowledging His divine power. Similarly, Christ explains that swearing by the temple means swearing by God, who is present in the temple, and that swearing by Heaven means swearing by God, who reigns in Heaven. However, the Jewish teachers of that time believed people were not accountable for oaths made in the names of created beings unless a penalty was attached, as if the thing they swore by were dedicated to God. This type of oath is what the term κορβᾶν {korban} as WITH A GIFT refers to. And it is this misconception that Christ addresses.
VIII. The principal effect of oaths is to cut short disputes. "An oath for confirmation, as the inspired writer of the Epistle to the Hebrews has said, is the end of all strife." So too we find in Diodorus Siculus, that an oath was regarded among the Egyptians as the surest pledge of sincerity that men could give. So that every one, in taking an oath, should express the real purpose of his mind, and render his actions conformable to those expressions. There is a beautiful passage on this subject, in Dionysius of Halicarnassus, who says, "the last pledge among men, whether Greeks or Barbarians, and it is a pledge, which no time can blot out, is that which takes the Gods, as witnesses to oaths and covenants."
VIII. The main effect of oaths is to resolve disputes quickly. "An oath for confirmation, as the inspired writer of the Epistle to the Hebrews said, puts an end to all arguments." Similarly, Diodorus Siculus noted that an oath was seen by the Egyptians as the strongest guarantee of honesty that a person could provide. Therefore, when someone takes an oath, they should clearly express their true intentions and ensure their actions align with those statements. Dionysius of Halicarnassus beautifully writes on this topic, saying, "the final commitment among people, whether Greeks or Barbarians, is one that no time can erase, and it involves calling the Gods as witnesses to oaths and agreements."
IX. The substance of an oath too should be such, and conceived in such words, as to include not only the divine, but the human obligations, which it implies. For it should convey to the person, who receives it, the same security for his right, as he would derive from an express promise or a contract. But if either the words bear no reference to a person so as to confer upon him a right, or if they do refer to him but in such a manner that some opposition may be made to his claim, the force of the oath will, in that case, be such as to give that person no right from it; yet he who has taken it must still submit to the divine obligation, which the oath imposes. An example of which we have in a person, from whom a sworn promise has been extorted by fear. For here the oath conveys no right, but what the receiver ought to relinquish, for it has been obtained to the prejudice of the giver. Thus we find the Hebrew Kings were reproved by the prophets, and punished by God for not observing the oaths, which they had taken to the kings of Babylon.
IX. The essence of an oath should be such, and formulated in such a way, as to encompass not only divine obligations but also human ones that it implies. It should give the person receiving it the same assurance for their rights as they would have from a clear promise or a contract. However, if the wording does not relate to a person in a way that grants them a right, or if it does relate but in a way that allows for challenges to their claim, then the impact of the oath will be such that it grants that person no rights. Still, the individual who has taken the oath must adhere to the divine obligation that comes with it. An example of this is when a sworn promise has been forced from someone out of fear. In this case, the oath provides no rights to the receiver, who should renounce it, since it has been obtained at the giver's expense. This is why the Hebrew Kings were condemned by the prophets and punished by God for failing to uphold the oaths they had made to the kings of Babylon.
X. The same rule applies not only to transactions between public enemies, but to those between any individuals whatsoever. For he, to whom the oath is taken, is not the only person to be considered; but a solemn regard must be paid to God, in whose name the oath is taken, and who possesses authority to enforce the obligation. For which reason it is impossible to admit the position of Cicero, that it is no breach of an oath to164 refuse paying to robbers the sum stipulated for having spared one's life; because such men are not to be ranked in the number of lawful enemies, but treated as the common enemies of all mankind, so that towards them no faith ought to be kept, nor even the sanctity of an oath observed.
X. The same rule applies not only to dealings between public enemies but also to those between any individuals. The person to whom the oath is sworn is not the only one to consider; there must also be a serious consideration of God, in whose name the oath is taken, and who has the authority to enforce the obligation. For this reason, it's impossible to agree with Cicero that it’s not a breach of an oath to refuse to pay robbers the amount agreed upon for sparing one's life; because such individuals should not be considered lawful enemies, but treated as common enemies of all humanity, meaning that no trust should be given to them, nor should the sacredness of an oath be upheld.
XI. The power of superiors over inferiors, that is of sovereigns over subjects, with respect to oaths, is the next topic that comes under consideration. Now the act of a superior cannot annul the perfect obligation of an oath, which rests upon natural and revealed law. But as we are not, in a state of civil society, entirely masters of our own actions, which in some measure depend upon the direction of the sovereign power, which has a twofold influence with respect to oaths, in the one case applying to the person who takes, and in the other, to the person who receives them. This authority may be exercised over the person taking the oath, either by declaring, before it is taken, that it shall be made void, or by prohibiting its fulfilment, when taken. For the inferior or subject, considered as such, could not bind himself to engagements, beyond those allowed by the sovereign legislature. In the same manner, by the Hebrew Law, husbands might annul the oaths of wives, and fathers those of children, who were still dependent.
XI. The authority of superiors over subordinates, meaning the control of rulers over their subjects, regarding oaths is the next topic for discussion. The actions of a superior cannot cancel the binding obligation of an oath, which is based on natural and revealed law. However, in civil society, we are not completely in control of our actions, as they are partly influenced by the sovereign power. This power has a dual impact on oaths: one aspect relates to the person taking the oath, and the other to the person receiving it. This authority can be exercised over the person taking the oath by either declaring beforehand that it will be rendered void or by prohibiting its fulfillment after it has been taken. An inferior or subject, considered in that context, cannot bind themselves to commitments beyond what is permitted by the sovereign legislature. Similarly, under Hebrew Law, husbands could annul their wives' oaths, and fathers could annul their children's oaths while they were still dependent.
XII. In this place we may cursorily observe, that what is said in the precepts of Christ, and by St. James, against swearing at all, applies not to an oath of affirmation, many instances of which are to be found in the writings of St. Paul, but to promissory oaths respecting uncertain and future events. This is plain from the opposition in the words of Christ. "You have heard it hath been said by them of old time, thou shalt not forswear thyself, but shalt perform unto the Lord thine oath. But I say to you, swear not at all." And the reason given for it by St. James, is that "you fall not into hypocrisy," or be found deceivers; for so the word HYPOCRISY signifies in the Greek.
XII. Here, we can briefly note that the teachings of Christ and St. James against swearing apply not to affirming oaths, which can be found in St. Paul's writings, but to oaths related to uncertain and future events. This is clear from Christ's contrasting statements: "You have heard it said by those of old, you shall not forswear yourself, but you shall fulfill your oath to the Lord. But I say to you, do not swear at all." St. James explains that this is so "you do not fall into hypocrisy," meaning you should not be seen as deceivers; the word HYPOCRISY means this in Greek.
Again it is said by St. Paul, that all the promises of God in Christ are Yea and Amen, that is are certain and undoubted. Hence came the Hebrew phrase, that a just man's YEA is YEA, and his NO is NO. On the other hand, persons, whose actions differ from their affirmations, are said to speak YEA and NO, that is their affirmation is a denial, and their denial an affirmation.165 In this manner St. Paul vindicates himself from the charge of lightness of speech, adding that his conversation had not been YEA, and NO.
Again, St. Paul says that all of God's promises in Christ are Yes and Amen, meaning they are certain and undeniable. This is where the Hebrew saying comes from, that a righteous person's YES is YES, and his NO is NO. In contrast, people whose actions don’t match their words are said to speak YES and NO, meaning their affirmations are actually denials, and their denials are affirmations.165 In this way, St. Paul defends himself against the accusation of being flaky with his words, adding that his conversation was not YES and NO.
XIII. Affirmations are not the only modes of obligation. For in many places signs have been used as pledges of faith; thus among the Persians giving the right hand was considered the firmest tie. So that where any form is substituted for an oath, the violation of it will be an act of perjury. It has been said of Kings and Princes in particular, that their faith is the same as an oath. On which account Cicero, in his speech for Dejotarus, commends Caesar no less for the vigour of his arm in battle, than for the sure fulfilment of the pledge and promise of his right hand.
XIII. Affirmations aren't the only ways to create obligations. Many cultures have used signs as guarantees of faith; for example, among the Persians, giving the right hand was regarded as the strongest bond. Therefore, when any form is substituted for an oath, breaking it counts as perjury. It’s said that the promises made by Kings and Princes are just as binding as an oath. For this reason, Cicero, in his speech for Dejotarus, praises Caesar not only for his strength in battle but also for his reliable commitment to the pledges made with his right hand.
CHAPTER XV.39
Regarding Treaties and Engagements Made by Delegates, Exceeding Their Authority.
Public Conventions—Divided into treaties, engagements, and other compacts—Difference between treaties and the engagements made by delegates exceeding their powers—Treaties founded on the law of nature—Their origin—Treaties founded on still more extensive principles—Treaties with those, who are strangers to the true religion, prohibited neither by the Jewish nor Christian law—Cautions respecting such treaties—Christians bound to unite against the enemies of the Christian religion—Among a number of Allies in war, which of them have the first pretensions to assistance—Tacit renewal of treaties—The effect of perfidy in one of the contracting parties considered—How far the unauthorized engagements of delegates are binding, when the sovereigns refuse to ratify them—The Caudian Convention considered—Whether the knowledge and silence of the Sovereign makes those unauthorized conventions binding—The Convention of Luctatius considered.
Public Treaties—Divided into treaties, agreements, and other pacts—The difference between treaties and agreements made by delegates who exceed their authority—Treaties based on natural law—Their origins—Treaties based on broader principles—Treaties with entities that don’t follow the true religion aren’t forbidden by Jewish or Christian law—Precautions concerning such treaties—Christians must unite against the enemies of their faith—Among several Allies in war, which one has the primary claim to assistance—Implicit renewal of treaties—The consequences of betrayal by one party—How binding the unauthorized agreements of delegates are when the sovereigns refuse to approve them—Discussion of the Caudian Convention—Whether the knowledge and silence of the Sovereign make those unauthorized agreements binding—Examination of the Convention of Luctatius.
I. Ulpian has divided conventions into two kinds, public and private, and he has not explained a public convention upon the usual principles, but has confined it to a treaty of peace, which he alleges as his first example, and he has made use of the engagements entered into by the generals of two contending powers, as an instance of private conventions. By public conventions therefore he means those, which cannot be made but by the authority and in the name of the sovereign power, thus distinguishing them not only from the private contracts of individuals, but ALSO from the PERSONAL contracts of sovereigns themselves. And indeed private injuries and contracts, no less than public treaties frequently prove the origin of wars. And as private contracts have been already so amply discussed, the higher order of contracts, which come under the denomination of treaties, will necessarily form the leading part in our farther inquiries.
I. Ulpian has divided agreements into two types: public and private. He hasn’t defined a public agreement based on the usual principles but has limited it to a peace treaty, which he cites as his first example. He also uses the commitments made by the generals of two warring powers as an example of private agreements. By public agreements, he refers to those that can only be made by the authority and in the name of the sovereign power, thus distinguishing them not only from the private contracts of individuals but ALSO from the Private contracts of sovereigns themselves. In fact, private wrongs and contracts, just like public treaties, often lead to wars. Since private contracts have already been thoroughly discussed, the higher level of contracts known as treaties will be the main focus of our further inquiries.
167 II. and III. Now public conventions may be divided into treaties, engagements, and other compacts.
167 II. and III. Public agreements can now be categorized into treaties, commitments, and other arrangements.
The ninth book of Livy may be consulted on the distinction between treaties and engagements, where the historian informs us, that treaties are those contracts, which are made by the express authority of the sovereign power, and in which the people invoke the divine vengeance on their heads, if they violate their engagements. Among the Romans the persons employed in declaring war and making peace, were in the conclusion of these solemn treaties, always accompanied by the principal herald, who took the oath in the name of the whole people. A sponsio, or ENGAGEMENT, is what was made by persons, who had no express commission for that purpose from the sovereign power, and whose acts consequently required a further ratification from the sovereign himself.40
The ninth book of Livy discusses the difference between treaties and agreements, explaining that treaties are contracts made with the explicit authority of the sovereign power, where the people call down divine retribution on themselves if they break their promises. In Rome, those tasked with declaring war and making peace were always accompanied by the chief herald when finalizing these formal treaties, and he would take an oath on behalf of the entire populace. A sponsio, or Engagement, was made by individuals who did not have direct permission from the sovereign power, and their actions needed additional approval from the sovereign himself.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
The Senate of Rome, we are informed by Sallust, judged very properly in passing a decree, that no treaty could be made without their consent and that of the people. Livy relates that Hieronymus, king of Syracuse, having entered into a convention with Hannibal, sent afterwards to Carthage to have it converted by the state into a league. For which reason Seneca the elder has said, applying the expression to persons invested with a special commission for that purpose, that a treaty, negotiated by the general, binds the whole of the Roman people, who are supposed to have made it.
The Senate of Rome, as Sallust tells us, wisely decided to pass a decree stating that no treaty could be made without their approval and that of the people. Livy mentions that Hieronymus, the king of Syracuse, entered into an agreement with Hannibal and later contacted Carthage to have it turned into an official alliance. For this reason, Seneca the Elder remarked, referring to those given a specific mandate for that purpose, that a treaty negotiated by the general is binding on all of the Roman people, who are assumed to have consented to it.
168 But in monarchies, the power of making treaties belongs to the king alone, a maxim which the language of poetry, no less than the records of history, shews to have been held in all ages. Euripides, whose sentiments are always conformable to nature, and popular opinion, in his Tragedy of the Suppliants, says, "It rests with Adrastus to take the oath, to whom, as sovereign, the sole right of binding the country by treaties belongs."
168 In monarchies, the king has the exclusive power to make treaties, a principle that both poetry and history demonstrate has been observed throughout the ages. Euripides, whose views align with nature and public opinion, states in his play The Suppliants, "It is up to Adrastus to take the oath, as he, as the ruler, holds the sole right to bind the country through treaties."
No subordinate magistrates have such a power of binding the people; nor will the acts of a smaller portion bind the greater, an argument used in favour of the Romans against the Gauls. For there was a majority of the people with Camillus, the dictator.
No lower-ranking officials have the power to bind the people; nor can the actions of a smaller group obligate the larger one, a point used by the Romans against the Gauls. There was a majority of the people supporting Camillus, the dictator.
But it remains to be considered how far the acts of those, who have engaged for the people, without any public authority, are binding. Perhaps it may be said that the contracting parties have discharged their responsibility when they have done all in their power towards the fulfilment of their obligation. That might be the case in promises, but the obligation in public contracts is of a stricter kind. For the party contracting requires something in return for the engagements he makes. Hence the civil law, which rejects all promises made by one person for the performance of some act by another, renders him who engages for the ratification of a thing liable to pay damages and interest.
But it remains to be seen how far the actions of those who have stepped in for the people, without any official authority, hold any weight. One might argue that the parties involved have fulfilled their responsibility once they have done everything they can to meet their obligation. This could be true for personal promises, but the obligation in public contracts is stricter. The party entering the contract requires something in exchange for the commitments they make. Therefore, the civil law, which invalidates any promises made by one person for the actions of another, makes anyone who commits to guaranteeing something liable for damages and interest.
IV. The most accurate distinction in treaties, is that which makes the foundation of some rest purely upon the law of nature, and others upon the obligations, which men have either derived from the law of nature, or added to it. Treaties of the former kind are, in general,169 made, not only between enemies, as a termination of war; but in ancient times were frequently made, and, in some degree, thought necessary among men in the formation of every contract. This arose from that principle in the law of nature, which established a degree of kindred among mankind. Therefore it was unlawful for one man to be injured by another. And this natural justice universally prevailed before the deluge. But after that event, in process of time, as evil dispositions and habits gained ground, it was by degrees obliterated. So that one people's robbing and plundering another, even when no war had been commenced or declared, was deemed lawful. Epiphanius calls this the Scythian fashion. Nothing is more frequent in the writings of Homer than for men to be asked, if they are robbers? A question, as Thucydides informs us, by no means intending to convey reproach, but purely for information. In an ancient law of Solon's mention is made of companies formed for robbery: and, we find from Justin, that, till the times of Tarquin, piracy was attended with a degree of glory.
IV. The clearest distinction in treaties is that some are based purely on natural law, while others stem from obligations that people have either derived from natural law or added to it. Treaties of the first type are generally169 made not only between enemies to end a war but were also often established in ancient times and were somewhat considered necessary among people when forming any contract. This came from the principle in natural law that created a sense of kinship among humanity. Thus, it was wrong for one person to harm another. This natural justice was widely accepted before the flood. However, over time, after that event, as negative traits and habits took hold, this principle gradually faded away. As a result, one group robbing and pillaging another, even without a declared war, became seen as acceptable. Epiphanius refers to this as the Scythian way. In the writings of Homer, it is very common for people to be asked if they’re robbers. This question, as Thucydides notes, was not meant to insult, but was simply for information. An ancient law from Solon mentions groups formed for robbery; and we find from Justin that until the time of Tarquin, piracy was seen as somewhat honorable.
In the law of the Romans it was a maxim, that nations, which had not entered into terms of amity, or into treaties with them were not to be considered as enemies. But if any thing belonging to the Romans fell into their hands, it became theirs; or any citizen of Rome, taken by them, became a slave; and the Romans would treat any person belonging to that nation, in the same manner. In this case the right of postliminium41 is observed. So at a remote period, before the times of the Peloponnesian war, the Corcyraeans were not considered as enemies by the Athenians, though there was no treaty of peace subsisting between them, as appears from the speech of the Corinthians given by Thucydides. Aristotle commends the practice of plundering barbarians, and in ancient Latium an enemy signified nothing but a foreigner.
In Roman law, there was a principle that nations that hadn’t established friendly relations or treaties with them were not regarded as enemies. However, if something belonging to the Romans fell into their hands, it became theirs; similarly, any Roman citizen captured by them became a slave, and the Romans would treat anyone from that nation the same way. In this situation, the right of postliminium__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ applies. Long before the Peloponnesian war, the Athenians did not see the Corcyraeans as enemies, even in the absence of a peace treaty, as noted in the speech of the Corinthians by Thucydides. Aristotle praised the practice of raiding barbarians, and in ancient Latium, an enemy simply meant a foreigner.
In the class of treaties referred to in this section may be ranked those made between different states for the mutual preservation of the rights of hospitality and commerce, as far as they come under the law of nature.170 Arco makes use of this distinction, in his speech to the Achaeans, as reported by Livy, where he says he does not require an offensive and defensive alliance, but only such a treaty as may secure their rights from infringement by each other, or prevent them from harbouring the fugitive slaves of the Macedonians. Conventions of this kind were called by the Greeks, strictly speaking, PEACE in opposition to TREATIES.
In the category of treaties mentioned in this section, we can include those made between different states to mutually protect the rights of hospitality and trade, as far as they fall under natural law.170 Arco uses this distinction in his speech to the Achaeans, as reported by Livy, where he states he doesn't need an offensive and defensive alliance, but only a treaty that secures their rights from being violated by each other or prevents them from sheltering the runaway slaves of the Macedonians. The Greeks referred to such agreements as, strictly speaking, Peace in contrast to AGREEMENTS.
V. Treaties founded upon obligations added to those of the law of nature are either equal, or unequal. Equal treaties are those, by which equal advantages are secured on both sides. The Greeks call them ALLIANCES, and sometimes alliances upon an equal scale. But treaties of the latter kind are more properly leagues than treaties, and where one of the parties is inferior in dignity, they are called INJUNCTIONS, or INJUNCTIONS ANNEXED TO COVENANTS. Demosthenes in his speech on the liberty of the Rhodians says, all nations ought to guard against forming such leagues, as approaching too near to servitude.
V. Treaties based on obligations that go beyond natural law can be either equal or unequal. Equal treaties are those that provide equal benefits to both parties. The Greeks refer to them as ALLIANCES, and sometimes as alliances of equal standing. However, such treaties are more accurately referred to as leagues than treaties, and when one party is of lesser status, they are called INJUNCTIONS or Injunctions Linked to Covenants. In Demosthenes' speech on the freedom of the Rhodians, he states that all nations should be wary of entering into such leagues, as they come dangerously close to servitude.
Treaties of both kinds, whether of peace or alliance are made from motives of some advantage to the parties. By equal treaties of peace, the restoration of prisoners, the restoration or cession of conquered places, and other matters providing for its due maintenance, are settled, a subject that will be more fully treated of hereafter, in stating the effects and consequences of war. Treaties of alliance upon equal conditions relate either to commerce, or to contributions for the joint prosecution of a war, or to other objects of equal importance. Equal treaties of commerce may vary in their terms. For instance it may be settled that no duties shall be imposed upon the goods of the subjects, belonging to each of the contracting powers: or that the duties upon their respective commodities shall be lower than the duties upon those of any other nation. The first of these examples may be found in an ancient treaty between the Romans and Carthaginians, in which there is a clause, making an exception of what is given to the notary and public crier. Or it may be settled that no higher duties than those existing at the time the treaty is made shall be imposed, or that they shall not be augmented beyond a certain rate.
Treaties of both types, whether for peace or alliance, are created based on some advantages for the parties involved. Equal peace treaties address matters like the return of prisoners, the restoration or transfer of conquered territories, and other issues necessary for proper maintenance, which will be discussed in more detail later when looking at the impacts and consequences of war. Equal alliance treaties typically involve commerce, contributions for joint military efforts, or other significant matters. Equal trade treaties can differ in their terms. For example, it might be agreed that no duties will be charged on the goods of the citizens of each contracting party, or that the duties on their respective products will be lower than those imposed on any other nation. The first example can be found in an ancient treaty between the Romans and Carthaginians, which includes a clause exempting what is given to the notary and public crier. Alternatively, it may be agreed that no higher duties than those in place at the time of the treaty will be levied, or that they won't be increased beyond a specified rate.
So in alliances of war the contracting parties are required to furnish equal numbers of troops or ships, a kind of alliance which, as Thucydides explains it, calls upon171 the united powers to hold the same states for common enemies or friends: we find, in many parts of Livy, alliances of this description among states, for the mutual defence of their territories or for the prosecution of some particular war, or against some particular enemy, or against all states excepting their respective allies. Polybius has given a treaty of this kind, made between the Carthaginians and Macedonians. In the same manner the Rhodians bound themselves by treaty to assist Atigonus Demetrius against all enemies except Ptolemy. There are other objects too for which equal treaties are made. Thus one power may bind another to build no forts in their neighbourhood which might prove an annoyance, to give no encouragement to rebellious subjects, to allow the troops of an enemy no passage through their country.
In wartime alliances, the parties involved are expected to provide equal numbers of troops or ships. Thucydides describes this type of alliance as requiring the united powers to support the same states against common enemies or friends. In many sections of Livy, we see similar alliances among states for mutual defense of their territories, for pursuing specific wars, or against particular enemies, or even against all states except their own allies. Polybius mentions a treaty of this sort between the Carthaginians and Macedonians. Similarly, the Rhodians made a treaty to help Antigonus Demetrius against all enemies except Ptolemy. There are also other reasons for forming equal treaties. For example, one power may agree with another not to build forts close to each other that could be bothersome, not to support rebellious subjects, and not to let enemy troops pass through their territory.
VI. From equal treaties, the nature of unequal treaties may easily be understood. And where two powers contract, this inequality may be on the side either of the superior, or of the inferior power. A superior power may be said to make an unequal treaty, when it promises assistance without stipulating for any return, or gives greater advantages than it engages to receive. And on the part of the inferior power this inequality subsists when, as Isocrates says in his PANEGYRIC, her privileges are unduly depressed; so that engagements of this kind may be called injunctions or commands rather than treaties. And these may, or may not, be attended with a diminution of their sovereign power.
VI. The nature of unequal treaties can be easily understood by looking at equal treaties. When two powers enter into agreements, this inequality can either favor the stronger or the weaker power. A stronger power is considered to create an unequal treaty when it offers help without expecting anything in return or provides more benefits than it receives. On the other hand, the weaker power experiences this inequality when, as Isocrates mentions in his Eulogy, its privileges are unfairly reduced; thus, agreements like these can be seen as orders or commands rather than true treaties. These arrangements may or may not lead to a reduction in their sovereignty.
Such a diminution of sovereign power followed the second treaty between the Carthaginians and Romans, by which the former were bound to make no war but with the consent of the Roman people; so that from that time, Appian says, the Carthaginians were compelled by treaty to comply with the humour of the Romans. To this kind may be added a conditional surrender, except that it leads not to a DIMINUTION, but to an ENTIRE TRANSFER of the sovereign dignity and power.
Such a reduction of sovereign power came after the second treaty between the Carthaginians and Romans, which required the Carthaginians to only go to war with the approval of the Roman people. From that point on, Appian states, the Carthaginians were forced by treaty to cater to the whims of the Romans. This type can also include a conditional surrender, except that it results not in a Decrease, but in an FULL TRANSFER of sovereign dignity and power.
VII. The burdens attached to unequal treaties, where no diminution of sovereignty takes place, may be either transitory or permanent.
VII. The burdens that come with unfair treaties, where sovereignty isn't reduced, can be either temporary or permanent.
Transitory burdens are those, by which the payment of certain sums of money is imposed, the demolition of certain works and fortifications, the cession of certain countries and the delivery of ships or hostages are172 required. But PERMANENT conditions are those, which require the tribute of homage and submission from one power to another.
Temporary burdens are those that require the payment of specific amounts of money, the tearing down of certain structures and defenses, the giving up of certain territories, and the handing over of ships or hostages172. But Permanent conditions are those that demand tribute of respect and submission from one power to another.
Nearly approaching to such treaties are those, by which one power is debarred from having any friends or enemies, but at the pleasure of another, or from allowing a passage and supplies to the troops of any state, with whom that power may be at war. Besides these there may be conditions of an inferior and less important kind; such as those, which prohibit the building of forts in certain places; maintaining armies, or having ships beyond a certain number; navigating certain seas, or raising troops in certain countries; attacking allies or supplying enemies. Some conditions indeed go so far as to prohibit a state from admitting refugees, and to demand annulling all former engagements with every other power. Numerous examples of such treaties are to be found in historians both ancient and modern.
Nearly similar to those treaties are those that prevent one power from having friends or enemies, except at the discretion of another, or that restrict the passage and supplies to the troops of any state with which that power may be at war. In addition to these, there are conditions of lesser significance, such as those that ban the construction of forts in specific locations; limit the size of armies or fleets; control navigation in certain seas, or restrict the recruitment of troops in specific countries; prohibit attacks on allies or support for enemies. Some conditions even go so far as to forbid a state from accepting refugees and demand the cancellation of all previous agreements with any other power. Numerous examples of such treaties can be found in the writings of both ancient and modern historians.
Unequal treaties may be made not only between the conquerors and the conquered but also between mighty and impotent states, between whom no hostilities have ever existed.
Unequal treaties can be formed not only between the conquerors and the conquered but also between powerful and weak states, even if there has never been any conflict between them.
VIII. In considering treaties, it is frequently asked, whether it be lawful to make them with nations, who are strangers to the Christian religion; a question, which, according to the law of nature, admits not of a doubt. For the rights, which it establishes, are common to all men without distinction of religion.
VIII. When discussing treaties, people often wonder if it’s acceptable to make them with nations that are unfamiliar with the Christian religion. This is a question that, according to natural law, leaves no room for doubt. The rights it establishes are applicable to all people, regardless of their religion.
The gospel has made no change in this respect, but rather favours treaties, by which assistance in a just cause may be afforded even to those, who are strangers to religion. For to embrace opportunities of doing good to all men is not only permitted as laudable, but enjoined as a precept. For in imitation of God, who makes his sun to rise upon the righteous and the wicked, and refreshes them both with his gracious rain, we are commanded to exclude no race of men from their due share of our services. Yet, in equal cases, it admits of no doubt, that those within the pale of our own religious communion have a preferable claim to our support.
The gospel hasn’t changed this idea; instead, it supports agreements that allow us to help, in a just cause, even those who don’t follow a religion. Helping others is not only allowed and commendable, but it's also a requirement. Just like God, who lets his sun shine on both the good and the bad and blesses them all with rain, we're told to offer our help to everyone, regardless of their background. However, in similar situations, it’s clear that those who share our faith have a stronger claim to our support.
IX. In addition to the foregoing arguments we may observe that as all Christians are considered as members of one body, which are required to feel for the pains and sufferings of each other, this precept applies not only to individuals, but to nations and kings in their public173 capacity. For the rule of duty is not to be measured by the inclination of individuals, but by the injunctions of Christ. And in some cases the ravages of an impious enemy can only be opposed by a firm alliance among Christian kings, and governments. And it is a duty from which nothing, but inevitable necessity, and their immediate attention being engrossed by the prosecution of other wars, can excuse them.
IX. Along with the previous arguments, we can see that since all Christians are viewed as members of one body, they are meant to empathize with each other's pain and suffering. This principle applies not just to individuals but also to nations and kings in their official roles. The standard for what is required is not determined by individual preferences but by the commands of Christ. In some situations, the destruction caused by a wicked enemy can only be countered by a strong alliance among Christian kings and governments. And this duty is one that can only be set aside due to unavoidable necessity or if they are fully occupied with other wars.
X. Another question frequently arises, which is, when two states are engaged in war with each other, to which of them a power, equally allied to both, ought in preference to give assistance. Here too we must observe there can be no obligation to support unjust wars. On which account that confederate power, which has justice on its side, will have a claim to preference, if engaged in war with another not comprehended in the number of confederates, or even if engaged with one of the confederates themselves.
X. Another question that often comes up is when two states are at war with each other, which of them a power, equally allied to both, should ideally support. Here, we must note that there’s no obligation to back unjust wars. For this reason, the allied power that has justice on its side will have a stronger claim to support if it is at war with a party not part of the allies or even if it’s at war with one of the allies themselves.
But if two powers engage in a war, equally unjust on both sides, a third power, united in confederacy with both, will prudently abstain from interference. Again, if two powers allied to us are engaged in a just war against others, with whom we have no connection; in the supplies of men or money that we furnish to either we ought to follow the rule, observed in the case of personal creditors.42
But if two powers go to war, both being equally unjust, a third power, allied with both, will wisely choose not to get involved. On the other hand, if two powers we are allied with are fighting a just war against others with whom we have no ties, the support we provide in terms of manpower or finances to either side should adhere to the principle followed in the case of personal creditors.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
But if personal assistance, which cannot be divided, is required of the contracting party, in that case the preference must be given to the engagements of the longest standing. However the case of a subsequent treaty, which makes the engagements of a more binding and extensive nature, will form an exception to this rule.
But if personal assistance, which can't be split up, is required from the contracting party, then priority should be given to the commitments that have been in place the longest. However, if there's a later treaty that makes the commitments more binding and extensive, that will be an exception to this rule.
XI. The tacit renewal of a treaty ought not to be presumed upon at the expiration of the period, limited for its continuance, unless certain acts be performed, which can expressly be construed as a renewal of it, and can be taken in no other sense.
XI. The automatic renewal of a treaty should not be assumed when the period set for its continuation expires, unless specific actions are taken that can clearly be interpreted as a renewal and cannot be understood in any other way.
XII. If one of the parties violates a treaty, such a violation releases the other from its engagements. For every clause has the binding force of a condition. And as an example of this, a passage from Thucydides may be quoted, where that historian says that "for one power to accede to a new confederacy, and to desert an ally who has neglected to fulfil his engagements, is no breach of a treaty; but not to assist another power in conformity to sworn engagements amounts to a violation thereof." And this is generally true, except where it has been agreed to the contrary, that a treaty shall not be null and relinquished for trifling disgusts and miscarriages.
XII. If one party breaks a treaty, that violation frees the other party from its commitments. Every clause acts as a binding condition. For instance, Thucydides mentions that "for one power to join a new alliance and abandon an ally who has not met their obligations is not a breach of a treaty; however, failing to assist another power according to sworn commitments is a violation." This is generally true, unless there has been an agreement that a treaty will not be voided or abandoned over minor grievances and failures.
XIII. Conventions are as various and numerous as treaties, and the distinction made between them is owing more to the difference of power in those by whom they are made, than to any real difference in their own nature. But there are two particular points of inquiry materially connected with all conventions, the first of which relates to the extent of the negotiator's obligation, when the sovereign or the state refuses to ratify a convention, whether he is bound to make an indemnity to the other party for the disappointment, to restore things to the situation they were in before he treated, or to deliver up his own person. The first opinion seems conformable to the Roman civil law, the second to equity as it was urged by the tribunes of the people, L. Livius, and J. Melius, in the dispute about the peace of Caudium;43 but the third is that most generally adopted, as was done respecting the two famous conventions of Caudium and Numantia. But there is one caution particularly to be observed, and that is, that the sovereign is no way bound by such unauthorised conventions, until he has ratified them. In the convention alluded to, if the Samnites had intended to bind the Roman people, they should have retained the army at Caudium, and sent ambassadors to the senate and people at Rome, to discuss the treaty, and learn upon what terms they chose to redeem their army.
XIII. Treaties can be just as varied and numerous as conventions, and the differences between them are more about the power of those who make them than any real differences in their nature. However, there are two key points related to all conventions. The first is about the negotiator's obligations when the sovereign or state refuses to ratify a convention. Is the negotiator required to compensate the other party for the disappointment, restore things to how they were before negotiations, or surrender themselves? The first viewpoint seems to align with Roman civil law; the second aligns with equity as argued by the tribunes L. Livius and J. Melius during the dispute over the peace of Caudium;__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, but the third option is the most commonly accepted, as seen with the two well-known conventions of Caudium and Numantia. One important caution is that the sovereign is not bound by unauthorized conventions until they are ratified. In the mentioned convention, if the Samnites wanted to hold the Roman people accountable, they should have kept the army at Caudium and sent ambassadors to the senate and people in Rome to discuss the treaty and determine how they wished to redeem their army.
175 XIV. Another question is, whether the knowledge and silence of the sovereign bind him to the observance of a convention. But here it is necessary to make a distinction between an absolute convention, and one made upon condition of its being ratified by the sovereign. For as all conditions ought to be literally fulfilled, such a condition, on failure of fulfilment, becomes void.
175 XIV. Another question is whether the knowledge and silence of the sovereign commit him to follow a convention. Here, it’s important to differentiate between an absolute convention and one that is contingent on being ratified by the sovereign. Since all conditions should be fulfilled exactly, if a condition is not met, it becomes null.
This principle was very properly observed in the convention made between Luctatius and the Carthaginians; to which the people refused to accede, as it had been made without their consent.44 A new treaty therefore was made by public authority.
This principle was rightly followed in the agreement made between Luctatius and the Carthaginians, which the people refused to accept since it was made without their consent.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Therefore, a new treaty was created with public approval.
The next thing to be considered is, whether there may not be some act of consent besides silence. For without some visible act, silence is not of itself sufficient to warrant a probable conjecture of intention. But if certain acts are done which can be accounted for upon no other grounds than those of consent, they are supposed to ratify a treaty. Thus if the convention of Luctatius had contained many clauses, some of them relinquishing certain rights, and those clauses had been always duly observed by the Romans, such observance would be justly taken for a ratification of the treaty.
The next thing to consider is whether there might be some act of consent beyond just silence. Because without some visible act, silence alone isn’t enough to justify a reasonable assumption of intention. However, if certain actions are taken that can only be explained by consent, they are assumed to confirm a treaty. For example, if the agreement of Luctatius included many clauses, some giving up certain rights, and those clauses had consistently been followed by the Romans, such adherence would fairly be seen as a confirmation of the treaty.
CHAPTER XVI.
Understanding Treaties.
The external obligation of promises—Words where other conjectures are wanting to be taken in their popular meaning—Terms of art to be interpreted according to the acceptation of the learned in each art, trade, and science—Conjectures requisite to explain ambiguous or seemingly contradictory terms—Interpretation of treaties from the subject-matter—From consequences, from circumstances and connection—Conjectures taken from motives—The more strict or more extensive interpretation—Treaties favourable, odious, mixed or indifferent—The good faith of kings and nations in treaties of equal validity with law—Rules of interpretation formed from the above named distinctions—Whether the word allies, in a treaty, is limited to those, who were such at the time of making it, or applies to all who are, or hereafter may become such—Interpretation of the prohibition of one party's making war without the consent or injunction of the other—Of the freedom granted to Carthage—Distinction between personal and real treaties—A treaty made with a king continues even during his expulsion by an usurper, such a treaty extends not to an invader—What kind of promises ought to have the preference—The extent of obvious conjectures—The performance of a commission by doing something equivalent—Interpretation restricted more closely than the bare signification of the words implies—From an original defect of intention—From failure of the sole motive—From a defect in the subject—Observations on the last named conjectures—Emergencies repugnant to the original intention, by rendering it unlawful or burdensome—Conjectures taken from a comparison of one part of the writings with another—Rules to be observed—In dubious cases, writings not absolutely requisite to the validity of a contract—Contracts of Sovereigns not to be interpreted by the Roman law—Whether the words of the person accepting or offering the engagement ought to be most regarded—This explained by a distinction.
The obligation of promises—Words should be understood in their usual meaning when there are no other interpretations—Technical terms should be interpreted as experts in those fields understand them—Interpretations are needed to clarify ambiguous or seemingly contradictory terms—Treaties should be interpreted based on their topics—Considering outcomes, circumstances, and context—Interpretations based on intentions—The interpretation can be strict or broad—Treaties can be favorable, unfavorable, mixed, or neutral—The good faith of kings and nations in treaties carries as much weight as the law—Rules for interpretation depend on these distinctions—Whether the term allies in a treaty refers only to those who were allies when it was made or includes all current or future allies—Interpretation of the clause that prevents one party from declaring war without the consent of the other—Concerning the autonomy given to Carthage—The difference between personal and real treaties—A treaty with a king remains valid even if he is overthrown by a usurper, but it does not extend to an invader—Which types of promises should take priority—The extent of clear interpretations—Carrying out a commission by doing something similar—Interpretation that is stricter than what the plain meaning of the words suggests—Due to an original lack of intent—Because of the failure of the sole motive—Due to a deficiency in the subject—Notes on the latter interpretations—Emergencies that contradict the original intent by making it illegal or burdensome—Interpretations derived from comparing parts of the texts with each other—Rules that should be followed—In uncertain situations, writings not absolutely necessary for the validity of a contract—Contracts of Sovereigns should not be interpreted using Roman law—Whether the words of the person accepting or offering the engagement should be prioritized—This is clarified by a distinction.
I. If we consider the promiser alone, he is naturally bound to fulfil his engagements. Good faith, observes Cicero, requires that a man should consider as well what he intends, as what he says. But as acts of the mind are not, of themselves visible, it is necessary to fix upon some determinate mark, to prevent men from breaking their engagements, by allowing them to affix their own interpretation to their words. It is a right, which natural reason dictates, that every one who receives a promise, should have power to compel the promiser to do what a fair interpretation of his words suggests. For177 otherwise it would be impossible for moral obligations to be brought to any certain conclusion. Perhaps it was in this sense that Isocrates, treating of agreements, in his prescription against Callimachus, maintains that the laws enacted on this subject are the common laws of all mankind, not only Greeks, but barbarians also. It is for this very reason, that specific forms have been assigned for treaties, which are to be drawn up in terms of unequivocal and certain meaning. The proper rule of interpretation is to gather the intention of the parties pledged, from the most probable signs. And these are of two kinds, namely, words and conjectures, which may be considered either separately, or together.
I. When focusing on the promiser alone, he is naturally obligated to keep his promises. Good faith, as Cicero points out, requires that a person considers both what he intends and what he says. But since thoughts are not visible on their own, it is important to establish clear criteria to prevent people from breaking their promises by interpreting their words however they choose. Natural reason suggests that anyone who receives a promise should have the right to compel the promiser to fulfill what a fair interpretation of his words indicates. Otherwise, moral obligations could never be conclusively defined. Perhaps this is what Isocrates meant when discussing agreements in his comments against Callimachus, stating that the laws regarding this matter are universal, applicable to all humanity, not just Greeks but also outsiders. That’s why specific formats have been established for treaties, which must be drafted in clear and definite terms. The appropriate way to interpret these is to determine the intention of the parties involved from the most likely indications. These indications fall into two categories: words and inferences, which may be considered either separately or together.
II. Where we have no other conjecture to guide us, words are not to be strictly taken in their original or grammatical sense, but in their common acceptation, for it is the arbitrary will of custom, which directs the laws and rules of speech.45 It was a foolish act of perfidy therefore in the Locrians, when they promised they would adhere to their engagements as long as they stood upon that soil, and bore those heads upon their shoulders, in order to evade their promise to cast away the mould, which they had previously put within their shoes, and the heads of garlick, which they had laid upon their shoulders. Acts of treachery like these, Cicero, in the third book of his Offices, has properly observed, instead of mitigating, tend to aggravate the guilt of perjury.
II. When we have no other guess to guide us, words shouldn't be taken too literally in their original or grammatical sense, but rather in their everyday meaning, since it's the habit of custom that shapes the laws and rules of speech.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ The Locrians acted foolishly when they promised to keep their commitments as long as they were on that land and had those heads on their shoulders, just to get around their promise to discard the molds they had previously put in their shoes and the garlic heads they had placed on their shoulders. Acts of betrayal like these, as Cicero noted in the third book of his Offices, actually make the guilt of perjury worse instead of lessening it.
III. In terms of art which are above the comprehension of the general bulk of mankind, recourse, for explanation, must be had to those, who are most experienced in that art; thus from consulting legal writers, we may conceive the nature of particular crimes, or from the pages of the same authors, derive our notions of sovereign power.
III. For art forms that are beyond the understanding of most people, we need to turn to those who are most knowledgeable in that area for explanations. By consulting legal writers, we can understand the nature of specific crimes, or from their writings, gain insight into the concept of sovereign power.
178 It is a just remark of Cicero's, that the language of logic is not that of daily and familiar intercourse: the writers of that class have phrases peculiar to themselves: which indeed is the case with arts of every description. So in treaties, where military arrangements occur, an army is defined to be a number of soldiers capable of OPENLY invading a foreign, or an enemy's country. For historians everywhere make a distinction between the private incursions of robbers, and what is done by a lawful and regular army. What constitutes an army must be therefore judged of by the enemy's force. Cicero defines an army to consist of six legions and auxiliaries. Polybius says, that a Roman army in general amounted to sixteen thousand Romans, and twenty thousand auxiliaries. But a military force might be composed of a less number of troops than this. In the same manner the number of ships sufficient for any purpose will amount to a fleet, and a place able to hold out against an enemy may be called a fort.
178 Cicero rightly points out that the language of logic isn’t the same as the everyday language we use in casual conversation: those who write in this style have their own unique phrases, which is true for all kinds of arts. Similarly, in treaties where military plans are discussed, an army is defined as a group of soldiers ready to openly invade a foreign or enemy nation. Historians everywhere note the difference between the private raids of thieves and actions taken by an official, organized army. What qualifies as an army should be assessed based on the enemy's strength. Cicero states that an army consists of six legions and their support troops. Polybius mentions that a typical Roman army consists of about sixteen thousand Romans and twenty thousand support troops. However, a military force can be made up of fewer soldiers than that. Likewise, the number of ships adequate for a specific mission can be called a fleet, and a location capable of defending against an enemy can be referred to as a fort.
IV. It is necessary to make use of conjecture, where words or sentences admit of many meanings: A mode of expression when included in one word, is called by Logicians, a synonymous term, and, when extending to two or more words, a doubtful phrase. In the same manner it is necessary to have recourse to conjecture whenever a seeming contradiction occurs in the expressions of a treaty. For in that case we must try to discover such conjectures, as will reconcile, if possible, one part with another. For if there be an evident contradiction, the contracting parties by their latter determinations, must have intended to abrogate their former; as no one can design to make contradictory resolutions at the same time. Indeed all acts depending upon the human will, as in the case of laws and testaments, which depend upon the will of one party, and in contracts and treaties, which depend upon that of two or more, all these acts are liable to changes, with a subsequent change of will in the parties concerned. In all such cases any obscurity in the language obliges us to have recourse to conjectures, which are sometimes so obvious, as to point out a meaning directly contrary to that of the words in their usual acceptation. Now the principal sources of conjecture are to be found in the subject-matter, the consequences, and the circumstances and connection.
IV. It's important to use speculation when words or sentences can have multiple meanings. When a concept is captured in a single word, it's referred to by logicians as a synonym, and when it involves two or more words, it’s called a vague phrase. Similarly, we need to rely on speculation whenever there's a seeming contradiction in the terms of a treaty. In that case, we must attempt to find interpretations that will reconcile different parts, if possible. If there’s a clear contradiction, the parties involved must have intended to override their earlier agreements, as no one would intend to create conflicting decisions simultaneously. In fact, all actions dependent on human will, such as laws and wills—which depend on one person's decision—and contracts and treaties, which involve two or more parties, are subject to change with any subsequent shift in the parties' intentions. In all these situations, any ambiguity in the language forces us to turn to speculation, which can sometimes point to a meaning that is directly opposite to the usual understanding of the words. The main sources of speculation are found in the subject matter, the outcomes, and the context and relationships involved.
179 V. From the subject or matter, as for instance, in the word day. Thus if a truce be made for thirty days, here civil and not natural days are meant.46
179 V. From the topic or subject, like in the word day. So if a truce is agreed upon for thirty days, it refers to civil days, not natural days. meant. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
So the word donation is sometimes used to signify a transfer, according to the nature of the business. In the same manner too the word arms, which in general signifies military instruments, is sometimes applied to troops, and may be taken in either sense, according to the particular occasion. Every interpretation must be given according to the intention understood. Thus the promise of a free passage given upon the evacuation of a town, implies also that the troops shall pass without molestation. If a number of ships are to be given up, perfect and not mutilated ships are meant. And in all similar cases a similar judgment must be formed according to the natural tenor of the words.
So the term donation is sometimes used to mean a transfer, depending on the context of the business. Similarly, the word arms, which typically refers to military equipment, can also refer to troops and can be understood in either way, depending on the situation. Every interpretation must align with the intended meaning. For example, a promise of safe passage granted after the evacuation of a town also means that the troops should pass without interference. If several ships are to be surrendered, it means intact ships, not damaged ones. In all comparable situations, a judgment must be made based on the usual meaning of the words.
VI. Another source of interpretation is derived from the consequences, especially where a clause taken in its literal meaning would lead to consequences foreign or even repugnant to the intention of a treaty. For in an ambiguous meaning such an acceptation must be taken as will avoid leading to an absurdity or contradiction. The cavil of Brasidas therefore is highly abominable, who, promising that he would evacuate the Boeotian territory, said he did not consider that as Boeotian territory, which he occupied with his army; as if the ancient bounds were not intended, but only what remained unconquered, an evasion, which entirely annulled the treaty.
VI. Another source of interpretation comes from the consequences, especially when a clause taken literally would lead to results that are completely out of line or even contrary to the purpose of a treaty. In cases of ambiguity, an interpretation should be made that avoids absurdity or contradiction. Therefore, Brasidas's argument is absolutely unacceptable; he promised to leave the Boeotian territory but claimed that the land he occupied with his army wasn't actually Boeotian territory. He acted as if only the ancient boundaries mattered, disregarding anything that remained unconquered, which completely undermined the treaty.
VII. From the circumstances or context another source of interpretation is derived. No inconsiderable light may be thrown upon the meaning of an expression from the circumstance of its being used by the same person to express the same intentions on other similar occasions, and from its relation to what goes before, and what follows the place, where it stands. For in all doubtful cases, we have reason to suppose that the contracting parties mean to be consistent with their former opinions and intentions. Thus in Homer, in the agreement between Paris and Menelaus, that Helen should be given180 up to the conqueror, when compared with what follows, it is evident that by the conqueror is meant the combatant, who killed the other. This rule of interpretation, Plutarch illustrates by the conduct of judges, "who passing by what is obscure rest their decisions upon clear and unambiguous points."
VII. From the circumstances or context, another way to interpret is created. We can gain significant insight into the meaning of a phrase based on how it’s used by the same person to express similar intentions on other occasions, as well as its connection to what comes before and after where it appears. In all uncertain situations, we can reasonably assume that the parties involved aim to remain consistent with their previous thoughts and intentions. For example, in Homer’s story, when Paris and Menelaus agree that Helen should be given180 to the winner, it’s clear from what follows that the winner refers to the fighter who defeats the other. Plutarch illustrates this rule of interpretation by referring to judges, “who, when faced with ambiguity, base their decisions on clear and straightforward points.”
VIII. As to the motives, which are sometimes taken for a rule of interpretation, there may be other substantial ones, besides those immediately expressed, for the passing of a law or the making of a treaty. Yet the strongest conjecture is that which arises from certain proof that the will was actuated by some reason, operating as a sole and sufficient motive. For there are frequently MANY motives, and sometimes the will is influenced by its own choice independent of any other reason. In the same manner a grant made, in contemplation of a marriage, will be void, if the marriage never takes place.
VIII. When it comes to motives, which are sometimes used as a guide for interpretation, there can be other significant reasons beyond those explicitly stated for passing a law or making a treaty. However, the strongest assumption is based on clear evidence that the decision was driven by a specific reason that served as the sole and sufficient motive. Often, there are MANY motives at play, and sometimes the decision is made independently of any other reason. Similarly, a grant made with the expectation of a marriage will be void if the marriage doesn’t happen.
IX. It is further to be observed that many words have a variety of acceptations, some more limited and others more extensive; which may be owing either to the application of a general name to a particular class of things, as in the words kindred and adoption; or to the use of masculines to express animals both of the male and female kind, where nouns of a common gender are wanting. In terms of art too, words are often taken in a metaphorical or extended sense: thus in the civil law death signifies banishment; but in its popular acceptation a dissolution of the parts of the natural body.
IX. It should also be noted that many words have multiple meanings, some more specific and others broader. This can happen either because a general term is applied to a specific group of things, like the words "kindred" and "adoption," or because masculine terms are used to refer to both male and female animals when there aren't common gender nouns available. In technical language as well, words are often used in a metaphorical or broader sense: for example, in civil law, "death" means banishment; but in everyday language, it typically refers to the breakdown of the physical body.
X. In promises likewise, some things are of a favourable, some an odious, and others of a mixed or indifferent description. Favourable promises are those which contain an equality of terms, or which bear some relation to the common good, the magnitude and extent of which increases the favour of the promise: so that all engagements more conducive to peace than to war are to be considered as those of a favourable complexion, and alliances for mutual defence are always regarded as a more laudable object than those for offensive war.
X. In promises, there are some that are positive, some that are negative, and others that are neutral or mixed. Positive promises are those that offer balanced terms or relate to the common good, where the significance and scale enhance the positivity of the promise. Therefore, any commitments that promote peace rather than conflict are seen as favorable, and alliances for mutual defense are always viewed as more commendable than those for offensive warfare.
Treaties of an odious kind are those which lay greater burdens on one party than on the other, which contain penalties for non-performance, or which lead to an abrogation or infraction of former treaties. Whereas, though engagements of a mixed nature may create a deviation from former treaties, they may be taken either in a181 favourable or odious light, according to the magnitude, or object of the change produced. If it be for the sake of peace, it is better, taking all circumstances into consideration, to rank them with those of a favourable kind.
Treaties that are considered unfair impose heavier burdens on one side than the other, include penalties for failing to comply, or result in the cancellation or violation of existing treaties. On the other hand, mixed agreements may diverge from previous treaties and can be viewed either positively or negatively, depending on the significance or purpose of the change. If the change is made for the sake of peace, it's generally better, considering all circumstances, to categorize them as favorable.
XI. The distinction made by the Roman law between acts of equity and those of strict justice, cannot GENERALLY be applied to the law of nations, though it may in some cases be adopted. Thus in any transaction between the subjects of two countries, in each of which the same form of legal proceeding is observed, the parties are supposed to treat without any intention of deviating from the common rule and form, unless they have expressly determined to the contrary. But in acts for which no common rule is prescribed, as in donations and free promises, there the parties are supposed to treat according to the strict letter of the agreement.
XI. The distinction made by Roman law between acts of fairness and those of strict justice can't USUALLY be applied to international law, although it might be relevant in some cases. In any transaction between the citizens of two countries, where both follow the same legal procedures, the parties are assumed to operate without intending to stray from the common rules and forms unless they have explicitly agreed otherwise. However, in situations where no common rules are set, such as in gifts and free promises, the parties are expected to adhere strictly to the terms of the agreement.
XII. After the establishment of the former positions, the subject naturally proceeds to the rules themselves, which are to be observed in the interpretation of treaties. And in the first place we may remark, that in things, which are not of an odious nature, words are to be taken strictly in their popular meaning, and where they admit of exceptions, or have more significations than one, it is lawful to use that which is most extensive. As it has been already observed, that both Logicians and Grammarians frequently use particular terms in a general sense. Thus Cicero in pleading for Caecina, justly maintains that the interlocutory decree, ordering THAT THE PERSON EJECTED FROM HIS INHERITANCE SHOULD BE REINSTATED IN THE POSSESSION, implies not only an ejectment, but extends to any forcible prevention of the owner's taking possession.
XII. After establishing the previous points, we naturally move on to the rules that should be followed when interpreting treaties. First, we should note that, in matters that aren't offensive, words should be understood in their common meaning. When words have exceptions or multiple meanings, it's acceptable to choose the broadest interpretation. As mentioned before, both logicians and grammarians often use specific terms in a more general sense. For example, Cicero, while defending Caecina, rightly argues that the interlocutory decree stating THAT THE PERSON REMOVED FROM HIS INHERITANCE SHOULD BE RESTORED TO HIS POSSESSION not only indicates an ejection but also covers any forceful prevention of the owner from taking possession.
In things of a favourable nature, if the parties engaged are acquainted with the legal principles, upon which they proceed, or rest upon the judgment of those who are so, the words used may be taken in their most extensive signification, including even terms of art and of law.47182 Again, we must never have recourse to a metaphorical interpretation, except where the literal meaning would lead to a direct absurdity, or would defeat the intention of a treaty.
In favorable situations, if the parties involved understand the legal principles they are following or rely on the judgment of those who do, the words used can be interpreted in their broadest sense, including specific legal terms and jargon. law.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__182 Again, we should only use a metaphorical interpretation when the literal meaning would lead to obvious absurdity or contradict the purpose of a treaty.
On the other hand a passage may be interpreted in a more limited signification, than the words themselves bear, if such interpretation be necessary, to avoid injustice or absurdity. If no such necessity exist, but equity or utility manifestly require a restriction to the literal meaning, it must be most rigidly adhered to, except where circumstances compel us to do otherwise. But in things of an odious nature a figurative expression may be allowed in order to avoid inconvenience or injustice. Therefore, when any one makes a grant, or relinquishes his right, though he express himself in the MOST GENERAL terms, his words are usually RESTRICTED to that meaning, which it is probable he intended. And in cases of this kind, the hope of retaining a thing is sometimes taken for the act of possession. In the same manner it is understood that subsidies of men, promised by one party only, are to be maintained at the expence of the power, who requires them.
On the other hand, a passage can be interpreted in a more limited way than the words themselves suggest if such an interpretation is necessary to prevent injustice or absurdity. If there’s no such need, but fairness or practicality clearly require sticking to the literal meaning, that meaning must be strictly applied unless circumstances force us to do otherwise. However, in matters that are particularly objectionable, a figurative expression may be used to avoid inconvenience or injustice. So, when someone makes a grant or gives up their right, even if they use the MOST GENERAL terms, their words are typically RESTRICTED to the meaning they likely intended. In these cases, the expectation of keeping something is sometimes considered equivalent to having possession. Similarly, it's understood that support from individuals promised by one side only is to be covered by the authority that requires them.
XIII. It is a famous question whether the word ALLIES includes only those who were such at the time of making the treaty, or those who might afterwards become so: as was the case in the treaty made between the Roman people and the Carthaginians at the conclusion of the war that had originated in a dispute about Sicily, by which treaty it was stipulated that both powers should forbear attacking the allies of each other. Hence the Romans inferred that although the convention made with Asdrubal, by which he was prohibited from passing the Iberus, had been of no service to them, as it had not been ratified by the Carthaginians, yet if the Carthaginians183 sanctioned the conduct of Hannibal in his attack upon the people of Saguntum with whom the Romans, after the making of that convention, had entered into an alliance, they should consider themselves as authorised to declare war against the Carthaginians for having violated a solemn treaty. Upon which Livy reasons in the following manner, "By the clause in favour of allies on both sides, there was sufficient security for the Saguntines. For there was no limitation of the words to those, who were allies at that time, nor were they such as to exclude either power from making new alliances. But if both sides were at liberty to make new alliances, who could think it just to deprive the new allies of that protection to which they would be entitled from treaties of amity? The exclusion could reasonably go no further than to declare that the allies of the Carthaginians should not be seduced to renounce their engagements, nor if they did so, be admitted into alliance with the Romans."
XIII. There's an ongoing debate about whether the term FRIENDS refers only to those who were allies at the time the treaty was signed, or if it also includes those who might become allies later on. This was evident in the treaty made between the Roman people and the Carthaginians at the end of the war that started over a disagreement about Sicily, which stated that both powers would not attack each other's allies. As a result, the Romans concluded that, even though the agreement with Asdrubal, which prevented him from crossing the Iberus, had been ineffective since it wasn't ratified by the Carthaginians, if the Carthaginians approved Hannibal's actions against the Saguntines—who had formed an alliance with the Romans after that agreement—they would then feel justified in declaring war against the Carthaginians for breaking a formal treaty. Livy argues this point, stating, "The clause protecting allies on both sides offered enough security for the Saguntines. There was no limitation on the words restricting them to allies present at that time, nor was there any prohibition against either side forming new alliances. If both parties could create new alliances, it wouldn't be fair to deny the new allies the protections they should receive from treaties of friendship. The limitations could reasonably assert that Carthaginian allies should not be encouraged to abandon their commitments, nor should they be allowed to join alliances with the Romans if they did so."
The last passage is taken, almost word for word, from the third book of Polybius. On which we may observe that the word ALLIES may strictly mean those, who were so at the time, when the treaty was made, and, without any forced interpretation, may also be extended to embrace those, who afterwards became such. To which of these interpretations the preference is to be given may be seen from the rules above given: and according to those rules, it will be found, that alliances formed after the making of the treaty will not be comprehended in it, because it relates to the breach of a treaty, the violation of which is an odious act, and tends to deprive the Carthaginians of the liberty of redressing themselves by force against those who were supposed to have injured them; a liberty sanctioned by the law of nature, and not to be abandoned on any slight occasion. Were the Romans debarred then by this rule from making any treaty with the Saguntines, and defending them after they became allies? No! they had a right to defend them, not by virtue of any treaty, but upon principles of natural justice, which no treaty can annul. The Saguntines therefore with respect to both powers were in the same situation, as if no engagement had been made in favour of allies. In this case, it was no breach of treaty for the Carthaginians, upon just grounds, to commence hostilities against the Saguntines, nor for the184 Romans to defend them. Upon the same principle, in the time of Pyrrhus, it had been stipulated, by treaty, between the Carthaginians and Romans, that if either of them afterwards entered into any engagement with Pyrrhus, the party so contracting should reserve to itself the right of sending succours to the other, if attacked by that king. Though in that case the war ON BOTH SIDES could not be just, yet it would involve no infraction of any treaty. This is an example of a case in equal treaties.
The last passage is taken almost word for word from the third book of Polybius. We can note that the term Partners may strictly refer to those who were allies at the time the treaty was made, and it can also reasonably include those who later became allies. Which of these interpretations should be preferred can be determined from the rules provided above: according to those rules, alliances formed after the treaty won’t fall under it because it addresses the breach of a treaty, and violating it is a despicable act. It deprives the Carthaginians of the right to defend themselves by force against those who they believed had harmed them; a right supported by natural law and should not be easily given up. Were the Romans prevented by this rule from making any treaty with the Saguntines and defending them once they became allies? No! They had the right to defend them, not due to any treaty, but based on principles of natural justice that no treaty can override. Therefore, the Saguntines, in relation to both powers, were in the same situation as if no agreement had been made in favor of allies. In this case, it wasn’t a breach of treaty for the Carthaginians to start hostilities against the Saguntines, nor was it a breach for the 184 Romans to defend them. Similarly, during the time of Pyrrhus, a treaty was established between the Carthaginians and Romans that stated if either party later made any agreement with Pyrrhus, that party would still reserve the right to send aid to the other if they were attacked by him. Although in that case the war ON BOTH SIDES might not be just, it wouldn’t constitute a violation of any treaty. This is an example of a case in equal treaties.
XIV. The case of an unequal treaty may be put, where it is agreed that one of the confederate parties shall not make war, without the consent, or by the injunction of the other, which was stipulated in the treaty between the Romans and Carthaginians, after the conclusion of the second Punic war. When the term WAR is applied to war of every description, particularly to offensive rather than defensive war; in a dubious case, it must be limited to its proper signification, lest the treaty should operate as too great a restraint upon the liberty of that power, which has engaged in the unequal treaty.
XIV. An example of an unequal treaty can be cited, where it is agreed that one of the allied parties will not engage in war without the approval or instruction of the other, as stipulated in the treaty between the Romans and Carthaginians after the second Punic war. When the term WAR refers to all kinds of warfare, especially to offensive rather than defensive actions; in uncertain situations, it should be confined to its specific meaning, so that the treaty does not impose an excessive restriction on the freedom of the party that entered into the unequal treaty.
XV. Of the same kind is the promise given by the Romans, that Carthage should be free, which could never mean the enjoyment of complete independence, by a people, who had long before lost the right of making war, and many of their other privileges. Yet it left them some degree of liberty, so much at least, that they should not be obliged to remove the seat of their government at the command of any foreign power, and gave them a pledge that their city should not be disturbed. It was in vain then for the Romans to urge that it was only the city which was intended. Whereas those acquainted with the use of metaphorical language know that by the city is frequently meant the inhabitants, and government with its privileges, and not the mere walls and houses. For the term, BEING LEFT FREE, implies that the people should enjoy their own laws.
XV. Similarly, the promise made by the Romans that Carthage would be free could never mean true independence for a people who had long since lost the right to make war and many of their other privileges. However, it still allowed them some degree of freedom, enough that they wouldn't be forced to move their government at the command of any foreign power, and it assured them that their city wouldn't be disturbed. It was pointless for the Romans to claim that only the city was meant. Those familiar with metaphorical language understand that when referring to the city, it often means the people and the government along with their privileges, not just the physical walls and buildings. The term, Freedom to be yourself, suggests that the people should have the right to enjoy their own laws.
XVI. The nature of personal and real treaties is a frequent subject of inquiry, which may properly be examined in this place. Indeed in all transactions with a free people, the engagements entered into with them are of a real nature; because the subject of them is a permanent thing. So permanent, that, although a republican be changed into a regal government, a treaty will remain in185 force: for the political body continues the same, although the head be changed, and the sovereign power, which before was diffused among many members, is now centered in one. Yet this rule will admit of an exception, where it is evident that the specific form of government made an essential part of the treaty, as when two states make a federal union for the mutual preservation of their political systems. But if a treaty be made with a King or Sovereign Prince, it does not consequently follow that it is to be considered only as a PERSONAL and not a REAL treaty. For the name of a person may be inserted in a treaty, not merely to give it the character of a personal treaty, but to point out the contracting parties. And this will be still more evident, if, as is usual in most treaties, a clause is annexed declaring it to be perpetual, or made for the good of the kingdom, or with the king himself, and his successors, and it will also be considered as a real treaty, even if it is stated to be passed for a definite time. The treaty between the Romans and Philip, King of the Macedonians, seems to have been of this description, which, upon the refusal of his son to continue it, gave rise to a war.
XVI. The nature of personal and real treaties is a common topic of discussion, which can be appropriately examined here. In fact, in all dealings with a free people, the commitments made with them are fundamentally real; because their subject matter is something permanent. So permanent, that even if a republic transforms into a monarchy, a treaty will still be185 in effect: because the political entity remains the same, even though the leadership has changed, and the sovereign power, which was previously spread among many members, is now concentrated in one. However, there are exceptions to this rule, particularly when it is clear that the specific form of government was integral to the treaty, such as when two states form a federal union to protect their political systems. But if a treaty is made with a King or Sovereign Prince, it does not automatically mean it should be viewed solely as a PERSONAL treaty and not a REAL treaty. A person's name may be included in a treaty not just to designate it as personal but also to identify the parties involved. This becomes even clearer if, as is common in many treaties, there is a clause stating it is perpetual, or made for the benefit of the kingdom, or with the king and his successors. It will also be regarded as a real treaty, even if it specifies a limited duration. The treaty between the Romans and Philip, King of the Macedonians, appears to fall under this category, which ultimately led to war when his son refused to continue it.
Other forms too besides those already named, and the subject itself, will frequently supply no improbable grounds of conjecture. But if the conjectures are equal on both sides, it will remain that favourable treaties are supposed to be real or permanent, and odious ones only personal. All treaties of peace or commerce are favourable. Yet all treaties of war are not odious, especially those of the defensive kind, such a character belonging only to offensive wars, from the contemplation of the calamities which they inflict. It is presumed too, that in the formation of treaties, the character of each party is taken into the account, and that both are persuaded that neither of them will commence hostilities, but from just and important causes.
Other forms, in addition to those already mentioned, along with the subject itself, often provide reasonable grounds for speculation. However, if the speculations are equally valid on both sides, it will be assumed that favorable treaties are seen as real or lasting, while unfavorable ones are regarded as merely personal. All peace or trade treaties are considered favorable. Yet, not all war treaties are viewed as unfavorable, especially those related to defense; that label typically applies only to offensive wars, given the suffering they cause. It is also assumed that when treaties are created, the character of each party is taken into account, with both parties believing that neither will start hostilities except for just and significant reasons.
What is usually said of societies terminating with the death of the parties, has no connection with this subject, but relates to private societies, the cognizance of which belongs to the civil law. Whether it was right or wrong therefore in the people of Fidenae, the Latins, Tuscans and Sabines, upon the death of Romulus, Tullus, Ancus, Priscus, Servius, to abandon the respective treaties made with those kings, it is impossible for us now to decide, those treaties being no longer extant. On the same point,186 Justin maintains a discussion, whether those states, which had been tributary to the Medes, were upon a change of government, released from their obligations. For the thing to be considered is, whether the convention with the Medes had been a voluntary act of their own. Indeed the argument of Bodinus can by no means be admitted, which is, that treaties made with kings extend not to their successors; For the obligation of an oath is limited to the person of him, who takes it. It is true that the oath itself can bind only the person who takes it; yet the engagements, which it confirms, will be binding upon his heirs. Nor is it to be taken for an established maxim, that oaths are the only foundation, on which treaties rest. The engagement itself is sufficiently binding, the oaths being only added to give it the greater sanctity. In the Consulship of Publius Valerius, the Roman people had taken an oath to muster at the command of the Consul. Upon his death, he was succeeded by Lucius Quintius Cincinnatus. Some of the tribunes began to quibble, pretending that the people were released from their obligation. Upon which Livy, in his third book, remarks, that "at that time they had not degenerated into the disregard of religious obligations, which marked his age: nor did every one allow himself a latitude in explaining oaths, and laws, but thought that he was bound to conform to their literal meaning."
What is often said about societies ending with the death of their members has no relation to this topic, but pertains to private societies governed by civil law. It’s impossible for us to determine whether the people of Fidenae, the Latins, Tuscans, and Sabines were right or wrong to abandon the treaties made with Romulus, Tullus, Ancus, Priscus, and Servius upon their deaths, as those treaties are no longer available. In the same vein, 186 Justin discusses whether states that were subject to the Medes were released from their obligations after a change in government. The issue at hand is whether the agreement with the Medes was a voluntary act on their part. Bodinus's argument, which claims that treaties made with kings do not apply to their successors, cannot be accepted. The obligation of an oath is confined to the individual who takes it. While it’s true that the oath binds only the person who took it, the agreements it supports will still be binding on their heirs. It should not be assumed that oaths are the sole basis of treaties. The commitment itself is sufficiently binding, with oaths added merely to enhance its solemnity. During the consulship of Publius Valerius, the Roman people took an oath to assemble at the command of the consul. After his death, Lucius Quintius Cincinnatus succeeded him. Some tribunes began to argue, claiming that the people were released from their obligation. In response, Livy notes in his third book that "at that time they had not devolved into a disregard for religious obligations, which characterized his era: nor did everyone mistakenly interpret oaths and laws, but felt obligated to adhere to their straightforward meaning."
XVII. A treaty made with a king continues in force, even though the same king or his successor should be banished from the kingdom by rebellious subjects. For the rights of a king, among which his alliances may be reckoned, remain unimpaired, during the temporary loss of his throne. A case to which the expression of Lucan may be applied, that "order never loses its rights under any change of circumstances."
XVII. A treaty made with a king remains valid, even if that king or his successor is removed from the kingdom by rebellious subjects. The rights of a king, including his alliances, stay intact during the temporary loss of his throne. This aligns with Lucan's saying that "order never loses its rights under any change of circumstances."
XVIII. On the other hand, any war, if it be with the consent of the lawful sovereign, made upon the invader of his kingdom, or upon the usurper of a free people's rights before his usurpation has received public sanction, will be deemed no infraction of any former treaty with the established authorities of that kingdom or country. For acts of usurpation convey not immediately any right beyond that of bare possession. And this is what was said by Titus Quintius to Nabis, "We made no treaty of alliance and amity with you, but with the just and lawful king of the Lacedaemonians." For in treaties the187 characters of King, Successor, and the LIKE, carry with them an idea of a peculiar and lawful right, which must always render the cause of USURPERS odious.
XVIII. On the other hand, any war, if it’s with the consent of the rightful ruler, conducted against an invader of his territory or against someone who has taken over the rights of a free people before that takeover has received public approval, will not be seen as a violation of any previous treaty with the established authorities of that kingdom or country. Acts of usurpation don’t immediately grant any rights beyond mere possession. This is what Titus Quintius said to Nabis: "We didn’t make any treaty of alliance and friendship with you, but with the just and rightful king of the Lacedaemonians." In treaties, the titles of 187 King, Successor, and the LIKE, carry a notion of a specific and lawful right, which always makes the cause of Usurpers repugnant.
XIX. It was a question formerly discussed by Chrysippus, whether a prize promised to him, who first reached the goal, could be given to two, who reached it at the same time, or to neither. But as rewards of merit are things of a favourable nature, it is the juster opinion that they should divide the prize. Although Scipio, Caesar and Julian acted more liberally, in giving the entire prizes to each of those who had ascended the walls together.
XIX. There was a debate in the past, brought up by Chrysippus, about whether a prize promised to the first person to reach the goal could be awarded to two people who reached it at the same time, or if neither should receive it. However, since rewards for merit are generally positive, the fairer viewpoint is that they should share the prize. Although Scipio, Caesar, and Julian were more generous by giving the full prizes to each of those who climbed the walls together.
What has been already said upon the literal or figurative application of the words, in interpreting treaties, will be sufficient.
What has already been said about the literal or figurative application of the words in interpreting treaties is enough.
XX. There is also another kind of interpretation, arising from conjectures, which apply exactly to the signification of the words containing a promise or engagement; and that is of a twofold description, either extending or limiting the meaning. But it is more difficult to extend than to limit the acceptation of expressions. For as in all matters the want of one essential requisite is sufficient to defeat their effect; so in engagements, those conjectures, which extend the obligation are not readily to be admitted. And it is much more difficult here than in the case above mentioned; where words allow a more extensive but less familiar acceptation. For here it is seeking a conjecture to extend the words of a promise: the conjecture therefore, which is to create an obligation, ought to be very certain. Nor is it sufficient that there is some resemblance in the motives; for the motive produced to confirm an obligation must be exactly the same as that of the case under consideration. Neither is it always proper to allege a motive for extending an obligation; because, as it has been already said, motives, in actuating us to form engagements, may sometimes be swayed by the will which often acts independently of any just motive. To authorise therefore such an extension, it must be evident that the motive, produced as an example and authority, was the sole and effectual cause, which influenced the promiser, and that he considered it in the same extensive view; for otherwise it would have been unjust and prejudicial. The ancients in their treatises on rhetoric follow the same rule, when, in speaking of the LETTER and DESIGN, they188 give us one invariable form of expressing the same sentiment, but in their syllogisms or arts of reasoning they point out a way of interpreting what is not written, by what is written. In the same manner too legal writers lay down rules for avoiding frauds. Now if at a time, when there was no other mode of fortifying towns, than by surrounding them with walls, it were stipulated that a certain place should not be so surrounded, it is evident that to employ any other means of fortification would be a breach of that treaty.
XX. There’s also another type of interpretation that comes from guesses, which are specifically related to the meaning of words that contain a promise or commitment; and this can be either broadening or narrowing the meaning. However, it’s usually harder to broaden the interpretation than to narrow it down. Just as in any situation, the absence of one key element can undermine its effect; in commitments, guesses that expand the obligation are not easily accepted. This is much more challenging compared to the earlier case, where words allow for a broader yet less familiar meaning. Here, it’s about finding a guess to expand the words of a promise: therefore, the guess that creates an obligation must be very certain. It’s not enough for there to be some similarity in the motives; the motive given to support an obligation must be exactly the same as that in the situation being considered. It’s also not always appropriate to cite a motive for expanding an obligation; as mentioned before, motives that drive us to make commitments can sometimes be influenced by the will, which often acts independently of any valid motive. To allow such an expansion, it must be clear that the motive presented as an example and authority was the sole and effective cause that influenced the promiser, and that he viewed it in the same broad context; otherwise, it would be unfair and detrimental. The ancients, in their discussions on rhetoric, follow the same principle when talking about the NOTE and Design, they188 provide us with a consistent way of expressing the same idea, but in their syllogisms or reasoning methods, they demonstrate a way to interpret what isn’t written based on what is. Likewise, legal writers establish rules to prevent fraud. Now, if at a time when the only way to fortify towns was by surrounding them with walls, it was agreed that a certain area would not be surrounded, it’s clear that using any other means of fortification would breach that agreement.
As in the above case the interpretation must be extended to guard against every possible evasion, so in the following example, the prohibition to assemble an armed force to assail us includes all kinds of violence and force, by which our lives and security may be endangered.48
As in the above case, the interpretation must be broadened to protect against any possible evasion. Similarly, in the following example, the ban on gathering an armed force to attack us covers all types of violence and force that could endanger our lives and security. endangered. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
XXI. Hence may be solved the question to be found in Gellius, respecting a commission, whether it can be fulfilled by doing, not the immediate act required, but some thing equivalent to it, or in a manner more beneficial than in the form prescribed. For this deviation from the written rule may be proper and lawful, where the prescribed form is not essential towards attaining the object, or where, by departing from it, that object can be better accomplished, according to the answer given by Scaevola, that the person required to be bail and security for another, may give an order to a third person to pay that money to the creditor. But where such a latitude of interpretation is not evidently admissible, we must adhere to what Gellius has said in the same place, that it would be a dissolution of all trusts, if the party acting in commission were, in all cases, left to his own discretion, rather than bound by his written instructions.
XXI. Therefore, we can address the question found in Gellius about a commission—whether it can be fulfilled by doing something equivalent instead of the exact required action, or in a manner that is more beneficial than the prescribed method. This deviation from the written rule can be appropriate and lawful when the prescribed form isn't essential to achieving the objective, or when straying from it allows for a better accomplishment of that objective. This is in line with Scaevola's response, stating that someone required to act as bail and security for another can instruct a third person to pay that money to the creditor. However, when such flexibility in interpretation isn't clearly permissible, we must follow what Gellius stated in the same context: that it would undermine all trust if the person acting in commission could always rely on their own judgment instead of being bound by their written instructions.
XXII. An interpretation, restricted more closely than the literal signification of the words containing a promise absolutely requires, may arise either from some original defect in the intention of the promiser, or from some subsequent emergency repugnant to such intention. Thus if it were evident that an absurdity would follow the fulfilment of a promise, this would be sufficient to prove an189 original defect in the intention, because no man can be supposed to have deliberately intended doing an absurd act. Or if the sole and effectual reason, by which the promise was influenced, should have ceased, the obligation also would be void, the sole ground on which it rested being no longer in existence.
XXII. A narrower interpretation than the literal meaning of the words in a promise is definitely required, and it can come from either a flaw in the promiser's original intention or from a later situation that conflicts with that intention. For example, if it became clear that fulfilling a promise would lead to an absurd outcome, that would be enough to show there was a flaw in the original intention, since no one would intentionally aim to do something absurd. Also, if the main reason that influenced the promise has disappeared, the obligation would no longer be valid, as the only basis for it no longer exists.
XXIII. In the next place, where any sufficient reason can evidently be assigned for a promise or engagement, it is not the substance of the promise itself, which is to be considered, so much as the reason for which that promise was given.
XXIII. Next, when there is a clear reason for a promise or commitment, it's not just the promise itself that matters, but the reason behind why that promise was made.
XXIV. Thirdly, the contending parties must always be supposed to have in contemplation the subject, and nothing but the subject, however extensive a signification the words may seem to bear. This method of interpretation also is handled by the ancient rhetorical writers, in speaking of expression and design, and they place it under the head of Variations in opinion.
XXIV. Thirdly, the parties involved must always be understood to focus on the subject, and nothing but the subject, no matter how broad the implications of the words may appear. This approach to interpretation is also addressed by ancient rhetorical writers when discussing expression and intent, and they categorize it under the heading of Differing opinions.
XXV. In speaking of motives and reasons, it is proper to observe, that they some times comprehend things, considered not according to their actual existence, but according to their moral consequences: in which case it is by no means right to limit the words of a treaty to their literal meaning, but the utmost extent of interpretation is allowable, in order to maintain the spirit as well as the letter of such treaties. Thus if it be stipulated that no troops or ships shall be brought to a certain place, or within a certain distance, the prohibition excludes ALL ships or troops from being brought thither, even under the fairest and most harmless pretences. For the purport of the treaty is to guard not only against actual mischief but even against remote danger.
XXV. When discussing motives and reasons, it’s important to note that they sometimes involve things considered not just for their actual existence, but for their moral outcomes. In this case, it’s not right to restrict the terms of a treaty to their literal meaning; instead, we should allow for a broad interpretation to uphold the spirit as well as the letter of such treaties. So, if it’s agreed that no troops or ships are to be brought to a specific location or within a certain distance, that prohibition means that ALL ships or troops are excluded from being brought there, even under the most innocent and harmless pretenses. The purpose of the treaty is to protect against not only immediate harm but also potential future risks.
It is a point often disputed, whether the continuance of things in their present state is a tacit condition, on which the fulfilment of all promises is founded. A position that can by no means be maintained, unless it appears that such continuance was the sole motive upon which the treaties were made. As in many parts of history, we read of ambassadors having relinquished their missions, and returned home, upon finding the state of things so changed that the object of their embassies was at an end.
It’s often debated whether the ongoing state of things is an unspoken condition on which all promises are based. This idea can’t really be upheld unless it’s shown that this ongoing state was the only reason the agreements were made. Throughout history, we read about ambassadors who have given up their missions and gone home when they found the situation had changed so much that the purpose of their embassies was no longer valid.
XXVI. When an emergency arises repugnant to the general intention of an act, it is explained by the ancient masters of rhetoric under the head of expression and190 design. Now this variation between the emergency and the intention is of a twofold nature. For the will and its intention are to be collected either from natural reason or from some outward sign. In judging of the will by natural reason, Aristotle, who has treated the subject with great accuracy, makes the MIND the SEAT OF JUDGMENT, and the WILL the SEAT OF EQUITY, which he nobly defines to be the correction of that, wherein the law, by reason of its universal nature is defective.49
XXVI. When an emergency comes up that goes against the overall intention of a law, it’s explained by the ancient experts in rhetoric under the concepts of expression and design. This difference between the emergency and the intention has two aspects. The will and its intention can be understood either through natural reason or some external sign. When judging the will through natural reason, Aristotle—who has addressed this topic very precisely—states that the MIND is the SEAT OF JUDGMENT, and the WILL is the SEAT OF EQUITY, which he accurately defines as the correction for where the law, due to its universal nature, is deficient.defective.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
And upon this principle all wills and treaties ought to be interpreted. For as all cases could neither be foreseen nor expressed by the lawgiver, it is necessary to leave a power of excepting the cases, which he himself would have excepted if he were present. Yet this is not to be done upon light grounds; for that would be exercising a controul over the acts of another; but is only to be established upon the clearest evidence and strongest proofs. The clearest proof we can have of a want of equity, is where following the literal meaning of the words would be unlawful, that is, repugnant to natural or divine precepts. For such things, as are incapable of obligation, are necessarily to be excepted. Quintilian the elder, says, "some things although comprehended within the meaning of no law form a natural exception." Thus any one, who has promised to return a sword, that has been given up to him, ought not to return it into the hands of a madman, as danger might result from it to himself or to other innocent persons. Likewise a thing, which has been deposited with any one, ought not to be returned to the hands of the person, who gave the pledge, if the real owner demands it. I prove this says Triphonius to be justice, which assigns to every one his own without disturbing the still juster claims of another. For the reason, it has been already observed, is founded on191 the institution of property, which makes it unjust not to return a thing when the real owner is known.
And based on this principle, all wills and agreements should be interpreted. Since the lawmaker couldn't foresee or express every situation, it's necessary to allow exceptions for those cases he would have excluded if he were present. However, this shouldn't be done casually, as it would mean controlling someone else's actions; it should only be established with the clearest evidence and strongest proof. The clearest indication we have of a lack of fairness is when following the literal meaning of the words would be illegal, meaning it conflicts with natural or divine principles. Things that cannot impose an obligation must be excluded. Quintilian the Elder states, "some things, even if included in no law, form a natural exception." So, if someone promised to return a sword that was given to them, they shouldn't return it to a madman, as it could be dangerous for them or for other innocent people. Similarly, an item that has been deposited with someone shouldn't be returned to the person who made the pledge if the real owner demands it. Triphonius argues that this is justice, which gives everyone what is rightfully theirs without undermining the more rightful claims of others. This reasoning is based on the institution of property, which makes it unjust not to return something when the real owner is known.
XXVII. The need of equity too will appear in cases, where following the literal meaning of the words will not be absolutely unlawful, yet, upon a fair estimation, will be found too hard and intolerable. It might impose a hardship inconsistent with the general condition of human nature, or, upon comparing the person and matter under consideration with each other, it might be found at variance with the general intent of all law, which is to prevent evil and to redress injury. Thus, if a person has lent a sum of money, or any other thing, for a CERTAIN time, he may justly require the repayment or restoration of it WITHIN that time, if he has great need of it himself: for acts of kindness are of such a nature, that no one can be supposed intentionally to bind himself thereby to manifest inconvenience or prejudice. In the same manner a sovereign, who has promised assistance to an ally, will, IN EQUITY, be excused from fulfilling his engagement, if he wants all his strength at home to ward off danger or hostilities. The grant also of immunities or privileges in ORDINARY cases, cannot be pleaded as an exemption or exception from the services, which the state in PARTICULAR emergencies requires.
XXVII. The need for fairness will be evident in situations where following the exact wording of the law isn’t necessarily illegal but, upon a fair assessment, feels excessively harsh and unbearable. It could create a burden that conflicts with the basic nature of humanity or, when comparing the individual and the situation at hand, might contradict the overall purpose of the law, which is to prevent harm and remedy wrongs. For instance, if someone has lent money or any other item for a CERTAIN period, they can rightfully ask for repayment or return INSIDE that period, especially if they really need it: acts of kindness are such that no one should be expected to willingly put themselves in a position of hardship or disadvantage. Similarly, a ruler who has promised help to an ally will, In fairness, be excused from keeping that promise if they need all their resources at home to fend off threats or attacks. Additionally, granting immunities or privileges in NORMAL situations cannot be used as a defense or reason to avoid the duties that the state requires in SPECIFIC emergencies.
From the above instances it appears that Cicero has too loosely worded his proposition, "that such promises, as are prejudicial to the person, to whom they are given, are not to be kept, nor, if they are more prejudicial to the party giving, than beneficial to the person receiving them." For it should not be left to the promiser to judge, whether the fulfilment of his engagement will be serviceable to the party receiving it, except in the case of the madman cited above: nor is any TRIVIAL or IMAGINARY prejudice that might result from it, sufficient to release the obligation. But it ought to be such, as, according to the nature of the act, would necessarily be supposed to form an exception. Thus any one, having promised his assistance to a neighbour at a certain period, would not be bound to his engagement, if he were detained at home by the sickness of a father or a child. A case, which Cicero, in his first book of offices, has put in the following terms, "If any one has undertaken to manage a cause, and, in the mean time, his son is taken ill, it will be no breach of duty in him not to perform what he has promised." There is a passage in the fourth book192 of Seneca, On Benefits, to the same effect. "I am liable, says he, to be charged with levity, and a breach of faith, if, things continuing as they were, when I made a promise, I do not perform my engagement. But if any change has taken place, it leaves me at liberty to reconsider the matter, and releases the obligation. I promised my support in court, and it afterwards appeared that the cause would be prejudicial to my own father. I promised to take a journey, but afterwards heard that the road was infested with robbers. I promised my presence on some particular occasion, but was prevented from attending by the sickness of a son. In all these cases, to bind me to my engagement, the circumstances ought to remain exactly the same as they were when I made the promise."
From the examples above, it seems that Cicero has worded his statement too loosely: "Promises that harm the person they're made to should not be kept, especially if they are more harmful to the person making them than beneficial to the one receiving them." The promiser shouldn't be the one to determine if fulfilling their promise would actually help the person receiving it, except in the case of the madman mentioned earlier. Nor should any trivial or imaginary harm that might come from it be enough to release them from their obligation. Instead, the harm should be such that, given the nature of the act, it would clearly allow for an exception. For instance, if someone promised to help a neighbor at a certain time, they wouldn't be bound to that promise if they were kept home due to a sick father or child. Cicero illustrates this in his first book of offices: "If someone has promised to handle a case, and in the meantime their child becomes ill, it would not be a breach of duty for them to not fulfill their promise." There's a similar passage in the fourth book of Seneca’s About Benefits: "I can be accused of being reckless or breaking my promise if things remain unchanged from when I made my promise and I don't follow through. But if something changes, I can reconsider and the obligation is lifted. I promised to support a case, but then I realized it would harm my own father. I promised to take a trip but later learned the road was dangerous. I promised to attend a specific event, but couldn't go because my son was sick. In all these situations, I can only be held to my promise if the circumstances are exactly the same as they were when I made it."
XXVIII. It has been said that there are other indications of intention, which require an equitable exception in favour of the present case. And among such proofs there can be nothing stronger than the same words used in another place, not where they directly oppose the present meaning, for that would amount to a contradiction, but where they clash with it, owing to some unexpected emergency, which the Greek Rhetoricians call a circumstantial disagreement.50
XXVIII. It's been said that there are other signs of intention that call for a fair exception for this case. Among these proofs, nothing is stronger than the same words used elsewhere, not when they directly contradict the current meaning, as that would be a contradiction, but when they conflict with it due to some unexpected circumstance, which the Greek Rhetoricians refer to as a circumstantial disagreement.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
XXIX. When there is any accidental collision between one part of a written document and another, Cicero, in the second book of his treatise On Invention, has given rules for deciding which of them ought to have the preference. Though his arrangement is not very accurate, yet it is by no means to be neglected. To supply therefore this defect of accuracy, the rules may be digested in the following order.
XXIX. When there is an accidental conflict between different parts of a written document, Cicero, in the second book of his work On Invention, has provided guidelines for determining which should take precedence. While his organization isn't completely precise, it's definitely worth considering. To address this issue of precision, the guidelines can be organized in the following way.
In the first place, a PERMISSION ought to give way to a COMMAND: because a permission appears to be granted only in case there is no weightier objection than its being193 an exception to a positive precept, nor any preponderance in favour of an opposite determination. Consequently, as the writer to Herennius says, what is positively prescribed is more powerful than a bare permission.
In the first place, a Permission should yield to a COMMAND: because permission seems to be given only when there’s no stronger objection than it being 193 an exception to a clear rule, nor any stronger case for a contrary decision. Therefore, as the writer to Herennius states, what is clearly prescribed is more powerful than just a permission.
In the next place what is required to be done at a FIXED time should have the preference to what may be done at ANY time. From whence it follows that the PROHIBITIONS of a treaty are generally of more weight than its INJUNCTIONS: because the prohibitory power operates at ALL times. But it is not so with injunctions, unless an express time for their fulfilment is named, or they contain a tacit prohibition.
Next, things that need to be done at a FIXED time should take priority over those that can be done at ANY time. This means that the BANS in a treaty usually carry more weight than its RESTRAINING ORDERS, because prohibitory power is active at ALL times. However, this isn't the case with injunctions unless a specific time for their completion is stated, or they implicitly include a prohibition.
Among those treaties, which, in the above named respects, are equal, the preference is given to such as are more particular, and approach nearer to the point in question. For where particulars are stated, the case is clearer, and requires fewer exceptions than general rules do.51
Among those treaties that are equal in the respects mentioned above, preference is given to those that are more specific and closer to the point in question. When details are provided, the situation is clearer and needs fewer exceptions than general rules do. do.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Those prohibitions which have a penalty annexed to them, are of greater weight than those, which have not; and those with a greater penalty are enforced in preference to those that have a less. Those engagements also which are founded upon causes of less magnitude and importance ought to give way to those which have more laudable and useful objects in view.
Those rules that come with a penalty are more significant than those that don’t; and those with a larger penalty are prioritized over those with a smaller one. Commitments based on less important reasons should take a backseat to those aiming for more admirable and beneficial goals.
Lastly it is to be observed that a subsequent law or treaty always repeals a former.
Lastly, it should be noted that a later law or treaty always overrides an earlier one.
From what has been said an inference may be drawn in favour of sworn treaties or agreements that they ought to be taken in the most usual acceptation of the words, rejecting all implied limitations and exceptions, and such as are not immediately necessary to the subject. Consequently in a case, where a sworn treaty or engagement may happen to clash with another not enforced by the obligation of an oath, the preference ought to be given to the former.
From what has been said, we can conclude that sworn treaties or agreements should be understood in their most common sense, disregarding any implied limitations or exceptions that are not directly related to the subject. Therefore, in a situation where a sworn treaty or agreement conflicts with another one that isn’t backed by an oath, the former should take priority.
XXX. It is often asked whether in doubtful points, a contract should be deemed perfect, before the writings194 are made and delivered. We find in Appian's history of the Mithridatic war, that it was upon this very ground Murena objected to the convention between Sylla and Mithridates. However it appears plain, unless it has been settled to the contrary, that writing ought to be considered admissible as evidence of a contract, though not as part of the substance, otherwise it is usually expressed, as in the truce with Nabis, which was to be ratified from the day the terms were WRITTEN and DELIVERED to him.
XXX. People often wonder if a contract should be seen as valid on uncertain matters before the documents194 are created and handed over. In Appian's history of the Mithridatic war, we see that Murena raised this exact issue regarding the agreement between Sylla and Mithridates. However, it seems clear, unless stated otherwise, that writing should be accepted as evidence of a contract, even though it isn’t part of the essential agreement. This is typically referred to, as in the truce with Nabis, which was to be confirmed from the day the terms were WRITTEN and SENT to him.
XXXI. We can by no means admit the rule laid down by some writers, who maintain, that all engagements of kings, and states, ought to be explained, as far as it is possible, upon the principles of the Roman law: unless indeed it can be made to appear that among some states, in their intercourse with each other, the CIVIL LAW is received as the LAW OF NATIONS; a presumption which ought not to be hastily granted.
XXXI. We absolutely cannot accept the rule proposed by some authors, who claim that all agreements made by kings and states should be interpreted, whenever possible, according to the principles of Roman law. Unless it can be demonstrated that in interactions among certain states, the Civil Law is recognized as the International Law; a presumption that should not be accepted lightly.
XXXII. As to the doubt, which Plutarch advances in his Symposiacs, whether the words of the party offering, or those of the one accepting a condition ought to be most attended to, it appears that where the party accepting the terms is the promiser, the nature and substance of the transaction will depend upon his words, if they are absolute and unqualified. For if the offer is regarded as a positive engagement to do certain acts, then the full extent of it will be seen by the necessary repetition of the same words in the promise. But before a condition is accepted, it is evident, as was seen in the chapter on promises, that the promiser is not bound to its fulfilment; for no right has been conferred by the one party, or acquired by the other. Therefore the offer of a condition of this kind does not amount to a perfect promise.
XXXII. Regarding the question that Plutarch raises in his Symposiacs about whether to pay more attention to the words of the party making the offer or those of the party accepting a condition, it seems that when the accepting party is the one making the promise, the nature and essence of the agreement will rely on their words if they are clear and straightforward. If the offer is seen as a binding commitment to perform certain actions, then the full meaning will be clear through the necessary repetition of those same words in the promise. However, before a condition is accepted, as discussed in the chapter on promises, the promiser is not obligated to fulfill it; no rights have been granted by one party or obtained by the other. So, the offer of such a condition does not constitute a complete promise.
CHAPTER XVII.
On Damages Caused by Injury and the Responsibility to Fix Them.
On Damages occasioned by injury, and the obligation to repair them—Every misdemeanor obliges the aggressor to repair the loss—By loss is meant any thing repugnant to right strictly so called—Distinction between fitness and strict right—Loss or diminution of possession includes every injury done to the produce as well as the property itself—Loss estimated from the time that gain ceases—Injuries done by principals—By accessories—Injuries done by the neglect of principal or of secondary agents—What persons are implicated in those charges, and in what degrees—The parties engaged answerable for all consequences—The case where homicide or any other act of violence ensues—Case of robbery—Or theft—Promises obtained through fraud or unjust fear—In what cases the consequences are imputable to the suffering party—How far the law of nations authorises states to take advantage of an enemy's fear—How far sovereigns are answerable for any acts of violence committed by their subjects—The case where subjects in violation of their sovereign's permission and orders commit acts of piracy upon allied or neutral states—No one answerable by the law of nature for the mischief done by his cattle, his slaves, or his ship—Damages allowed for injuries done to reputation or honour—What kind of reparation allowed.
On damages from injury and the duty to address them—Every wrongdoing requires the offender to make up for the loss—By loss, we mean anything that violates a strict sense of right—There's a difference between what's appropriate and what's strictly right—Loss or reduction of possession includes every injury to both the yield and the property itself—Loss is determined from the moment gains stop—Injuries caused by main offenders—By accomplices—Injuries resulting from the negligence of primary or secondary agents—Which individuals are involved in these allegations, and to what extent—The involved parties are accountable for all consequences—In cases of homicide or any violent acts—In cases of robbery—Or theft—Promises gained through deceit or unjust threats—In what situations the consequences are assigned to the injured party—How far international law allows states to exploit an enemy's fear—To what extent sovereigns are responsible for violent acts committed by their subjects—The situation where subjects commit acts of piracy against allied or neutral states without their sovereign’s permission—No one is held liable by natural law for harm caused by their cattle, slaves, or ships—Damages can be awarded for harm to reputation or honor—What type of compensation is permitted.
I. It has been said above that the rights due to us arise from three sources, which are contract, injury and law. It is unnecessary here to dwell upon the nature of contracts which has been already so fully discussed. The next point therefore to which we proceed is an inquiry into the rights resulting to us from injuries received. Here the name of crime or misdemeanor is applied to every act of commission or neglect repugnant to the duties required of all men, either from their common nature or particular calling. For such offences naturally create an obligation to repair the loss or injury that has been sustained.
I. As mentioned earlier, the rights we have come from three sources: contracts, injuries, and laws. There's no need to go over the nature of contracts since that has already been thoroughly discussed. So, the next point we’ll look into is the rights that arise from injuries we experience. In this context, the terms crime or misdemeanor refer to any action we take or fail to take that goes against the responsibilities expected of all individuals, whether because of their common humanity or specific roles. Such offenses create a natural obligation to compensate for the loss or injury that has occurred.
II. By loss is meant a diminution of what any one possesses, whether it be a right derived to him purely from the law of nature, or from the addition of human authority, that is from the law of property, contract, or civil law. God has given life to man, not to destroy,196 but to preserve it; assigning to him for this purpose a right to the free enjoyment of personal liberty, reputation, and the controul over his own actions. The manner, in which property and contracts convey to any one a right to things, as well as to the service of another, has been shewn in the preceding part of this treatise. In the same manner from the law every man derives his peculiar right; because the law has the same, if not greater power over persons and things than individuals themselves have. Thus by the appointment of law, a ward has a right to demand the strictest diligence of a guardian, the state of a magistrate, and not only the state, but every subject has a right to require it; where the law expressly declares or evidently implies that certain acts shall be performed. But the bare circumstance of an action being fit or proper gives not the right of POLITICAL justice to demand its performance, nor does the neglect of it entitle the party suffering to any legal redress. Because it does not follow that a thing must belong to a person because it is fit or beneficial for him. Thus, as Aristotle says, there is no actual injustice, though it may be illiberal to refuse assisting another with money. To the same purpose Cicero, in his speech for Cneius Plancus, says, that giving their votes to whom they please, or withholding them if they think proper, is the true characteristic of a free people. He afterwards, indeed, corrects his assertion by adding, that they may happen to do what they like, rather than what they ought to do, taking the word OUGHT to signify propriety.
II. By loss, we mean a reduction of what someone has, whether it comes from natural law or from human authority, like property law, contracts, or civil law. God has given life to humans, not to destroy it, but to protect it; assigning them the right to enjoy personal freedom, reputation, and control over their own actions. The way property and contracts grant someone a right to things and to another's service has been explained earlier in this text. Similarly, everyone derives their specific rights from the law, because the law has at least as much, if not more, power over people and things than individuals do. Thus, under the law, a ward has the right to expect the utmost diligence from a guardian, just as a magistrate and every citizen has the right to demand it when the law clearly states or implies that certain actions must be carried out. However, just because an action seems suitable or appropriate does not give someone the right to demand its performance through political justice, nor does the failure to perform it give the harmed party any legal compensation. Just because something is beneficial for someone does not mean it must belong to them. As Aristotle says, there is no real injustice if someone refuses to help another with money, though it may be ungracious. In a similar vein, Cicero, in his speech for Cneius Plancus, asserts that a true characteristic of a free people is that they can vote as they wish or withhold their votes if they see fit. He later clarifies his point by adding that people may act according to their desires rather than what they ought to do, interpreting "ought" to mean what is proper.
III. A precaution is necessary here, in order to avoid confounding things of a different kind.
III. A precaution is needed here to avoid mixing things that are different.
Now those who are entrusted with the power of appointing magistrates, are bound, from motives of public good, to chuse the properest persons, and this is what the state has a RIGHT to require of them. They are bound therefore to repair any loss which the state may sustain by the choice of improper persons. So any subject who is not disqualified, though he has no peculiar right to an office, has an equal right with others to endeavour to obtain it. In the exercise of which right, if, he is obstructed by violence or fraud, he may recover damages, not to the full value of the office which he sought, but according to the probable loss which he may reasonably be supposed to have suffered. Similar which is the right of a legatee, when a testator has been197 prevented by fraud or violence from making a bequest. For the capability of receiving a legacy is a kind of right, which to obstruct a testator from conferring, is undoubtedly an injury.
Now, those who hold the power to appoint magistrates are obligated, for the sake of the public good, to choose the most suitable individuals, and this is what the state has a RIGHT to expect from them. They are therefore responsible for making up for any loss that the state may experience due to the selection of unsuitable candidates. Thus, any individual who is not disqualified, even if they do not have a specific right to an office, has an equal right to try to obtain it. If, in exercising this right, they are hindered by violence or fraud, they can seek damages, not equal to the full value of the office they sought, but based on the likely loss they can reasonably claim to have incurred. This is similar to the right of a legatee when a testator has been 197 prevented by fraud or violence from making a bequest. The ability to receive a legacy is a type of right, and obstructing a testator from granting it is undoubtedly a form of injury.
IV. The loss or diminution of any one's possessions is not confined to injuries done to the SUBSTANCE alone of the property, but includes every thing affecting the produce of it, whether it has been gathered or not. If the owner himself had reaped it, the necessary expence of reaping, or of improving the property to raise a produce, must also be taken into the account of his loss, and form part of the damages. For it is an established maxim that no one ought to derive benefit from the loss of another.
IV. The loss or reduction of someone’s belongings isn't just limited to damage done to the actual property, but also includes everything that affects its yield, whether the yield has been collected or not. If the owner had harvested it themselves, the necessary costs of harvesting or improving the property to produce a yield must also be considered in assessing their loss and counted as part of the damages. It is a well-established principle that no one should profit from someone else's loss.
V. Damages are to be computed too, not according to any ACTUAL gain, but according to the REASONABLE expectation of it. Which in the case of a growing crop may be judged of by the general abundance or scarcity of that particular season.
V. Damages should also be calculated not based on any ACTUAL gain, but rather on the Fair expectation of it. In the case of a growing crop, this can be assessed by the overall abundance or scarcity of that specific season.
VI. But besides the person immediately doing an injury, others may be bound also to repair the losses of the suffering party. For as a person may be guilty of offences by negligence as well as by the commission of certain acts, so they may be done also by accessories, as well as principals. Now a principal in any crime or offence is one, that urges to the commission of it, that gives all possible consent, that aids, abets, or in any shape is a partner in the perpetration of it.
VI. However, in addition to the person directly causing the harm, others may also be obligated to compensate the victim for their losses. Just as someone can be liable for wrongdoing due to negligence, they can also be responsible for actions taken by accomplices as well as the main offender. A principal in any crime or offense is someone who encourages its commission, provides full consent, assists, supports, or in any way participates in carrying it out.
VII. An accessory is one who gives his counsel, approbation, and assent. For where is the difference, says Cicero, in his second Philippic, between advising an act, and approving of it?
VII. An accessory is someone who gives their advice, approval, and agreement. For what’s the difference, says Cicero in his second Philippic, between suggesting an action and endorsing it?
VIII. and IX. The obligation to repair the losses suffered by negligence may be considered in a two-fold light. Firstly, when any person, whose peculiar office it is, neglects either to forbid the commission of an injury, or to assist the injured party. And secondly, when the person, who ought to do it, either does not dissuade from the commission of an offence, or passes over in silence, what he is bound to make known. In these cases, when it is said that a person OUGHT to do, or to forbear doing certain actions, it is meant that he is bound by that right, which strict justice requires, whether that duty arises from law, or from the capacity, which the person bears. For though it may be wrong to omit any duty enjoined by the law of charity, there can be no redress198 for such omission, but every LEGAL REMEDY must be founded on some PECULIAR RIGHT.
VIII. and IX. The responsibility to compensate for losses caused by negligence can be viewed in two ways. First, when someone whose specific role it is fails to either prevent harm from happening or to help the person who has been harmed. Second, when the person who is supposed to act either doesn’t discourage the wrongdoing or ignores what they are supposed to disclose. In these instances, when we say that a person SHOULD to perform or refrain from certain actions, it means they are obligated by the rights that strict justice demands, whether that obligation comes from the law, or from the position that the person holds. Even though it might be wrong to neglect any duty required by the law of kindness, there can be no remedy198 for that neglect, and every Legal remedy must be based on some UNIQUE RIGHT.
X. It is to be observed also that all the parties above-mentioned, if they have been the real occasion of loss to any one, or have abetted the person doing him the injury, are so far implicated in the guilt, as to be liable to full damages, or, at least, proportionably to the part they have taken. For it may and often does happen that a crime would have been committed by an offender, even without the aid of other principals or accessories. In which case he alone is answerable. Yet neither principals nor accessories will be allowed to plead as an excuse, that if they had not aided or abetted, others would have been found to assist and encourage the perpetrator in the commission of the act. Especially, if it appears that without such assistance from them the crime would never have been committed. For those other imaginary abettors would themselves have been answerable, if they had given their advice or aid.
X. It should also be noted that all the parties mentioned above, if they caused any loss to someone or supported the person causing the harm, are implicated in the wrongdoing to the extent that they are liable for full damages, or at least proportionate to their involvement. It can and often does happen that a crime would have been committed by an offender even without the help of other main or accessory participants. In that case, the offender alone is responsible. However, neither the main actors nor the accessories can claim as a defense that if they hadn’t helped or supported, others would have stepped in to assist and encourage the perpetrator. Especially if it’s clear that without their assistance, the crime would never have happened. Because those other hypothetical supporters would themselves be accountable if they had offered their advice or help.
XI. In the scale of implication the first degree applies to those, who by their authority, or other means have compelled or urged any one to the commission of an offence. On failure of these the perpetrator himself has the greatest share of guilt, and next to him, others who have been concerned. In short, all individuals, whose hands have been engaged in the perpetration, are guilty, though they have not been the sole authors of the act.
XI. In terms of blame, the first degree applies to those who, using their authority or other methods, have forced or encouraged someone to commit a crime. If those individuals are not available, then the person who actually committed the offense carries the most guilt, followed by others who were involved. In short, everyone whose hands were involved in the act is guilty, even if they weren't the only ones who initiated it.
XII. Now he who is answerable for an act, is answerable for all the injurious consequences attending it. Seneca in one of his controversies, treating upon this point, puts the case of a plane-tree set on fire, by which a house was burnt, and he subjoins the following remark, "although the mischief went further than was intended, yet the person doing it was answerable for the WHOLE, as much, as if he had done it by design. For any one that puts his defence upon the plea of UNINTENTIONAL INJURY, ought to have abstained from all mischief whatsoever." When Ariarathes, king of Cappadocia had wantonly obstructed the channel of the river Melas, which discharges itself into the Euphrates, the swell of waters bursting the mounds, the Euphrates rose to such a height, as to occasion excessive damage to the Cappadocians, the Galatians, and the Phrygians. Upon which the decision of the matter being left to the Romans, they imposed upon him a fine of three hundred talents.
XII. Anyone who is responsible for an action is also responsible for all the harmful consequences that come with it. In one of his discussions, Seneca presents an example of a plane tree that was set on fire, leading to the destruction of a house. He adds, "Even if the damage went beyond what was intended, the person who caused it is responsible for the ALL, just as if it had been done on purpose. Anyone who defends their actions claiming Accidental Injury should have avoided causing any harm at all." When Ariarathes, the king of Cappadocia, carelessly blocked the flow of the river Melas, which feeds into the Euphrates, the water pressure caused the barriers to burst, making the Euphrates rise to a level that caused severe damage to the people of Cappadocia, Galatia, and Phrygia. As a result, the matter was referred to the Romans, who imposed a fine of three hundred talents on him.
199 XIII. XIV. XV. and XVI. But to proceed with other instances of injury, which render the parties committing them liable to repair the losses occasioned thereby. The case of excusable homicide may be alleged as one, wherein the person, who has committed it, is bound to make every reasonable compensation to the family, dependents, and connections of the deceased party, in proportion to the loss, which they have sustained from his death. As Michael the Ephesian in the fifth book of Aristotle's Ethics has observed, that the compensation made to the parents, the wife or children of the deceased is nearly the same as if it could be made to himself. The writer is here speaking of excusable homicide, that is, when the person by whom it is committed, does it not in the immediate discharge of some legal duty. Wherefore if any one, in defending himself, has killed another from whom he might have escaped, though he may have violated the law of charity, yet he has not incurred the penalty of a capital offence.
199 XIII. XIV. XV. and XVI. But let's move on to other cases of harm that make those responsible accountable for the damages caused. The situation of justifiable homicide can be mentioned as one example, where the person who committed it is obligated to provide reasonable compensation to the family, dependents, and associates of the deceased, based on the loss they have suffered from the person's death. As Michael the Ephesian noted in the fifth book of Aristotle's Ethics, the compensation given to the parents, spouse, or children of the deceased is almost equivalent to what could be given directly to the deceased. The author is referring to justifiable homicide, which is when the act was not committed in the immediate fulfillment of a legal duty. Therefore, if someone, while defending themselves, kills another person from whom they could have escaped, even if they have breached the law of compassion, they have not faced the consequences of a capital offense.
Upon the same principle the person, who has maimed or mutilated another, will be bound to make him a compensation, proportionably to the means of subsistence which he is deprived of by such a calamity.
Based on the same principle, anyone who has injured or disfigured another person must compensate them according to the level of support they lose due to this misfortune.
A thief or a robber is bound to restore what has been taken, and to return it with all the improvements it may have acquired, or to make reparation to the owner, in proportion to the gain, which the privation has prevented him from making, or to the actual value of the thing itself. If the thing has been irretrievably consumed, the estimation of damages must be made, according to a medium between the highest and the lowest value.
A thief or a robber has to return what they took and also give back any improvements it may have gained, or compensate the owner based on the profits they missed out on because of the theft, or based on the actual value of the item itself. If the item has been completely used up, the damage assessment should be determined by finding a middle ground between its highest and lowest value.
To this class of offences and due reparation may be referred all frauds upon the public revenue, all unjust decisions, or all false evidence, by which states or individuals are injured.
To this category of offenses and suitable compensation may be referred all frauds against public revenue, any unjust decisions, or any false evidence that harm states or individuals.
XVII. Contracts, or promises obtained by fraud, violence or undue fear entitle the injured party to full restitution. For perfect freedom from fraud or compulsion, in all our dealings, is a RIGHT which we derive from natural law and liberty.
XVII. Contracts or promises made under fraud, force, or excessive fear give the injured party the right to complete restitution. For total freedom from fraud or coercion in all our interactions is a RIGHT that we gain from natural law and liberty.
With the same class of offenders we may rank all men in office, who are unwilling to discharge their duty without a bribe.
With the same group of offenders, we can include all men in office who refuse to do their job without being bribed.
XVIII. When a person has HIMSELF been the occasion of the fraud or violence, the consequences are imputable to200 his own conduct. For where a voluntary act gives rise to INVOLUNTARY consequences, those consequences, considered in a moral light, are to be deemed the fruits growing out of the exercise of a free will.
XVIII. When someone has Himself caused the fraud or violence, the consequences fall back on200 their own actions. If a voluntary act leads to UNINTENTIONAL consequences, those consequences, viewed from a moral standpoint, are seen as the results of exercising free will.
XIX. But to connect the preceding cases and arguments with public and national concerns, it is necessary to observe, that it is a maxim introduced and established by the consent of all nations that the wars which are declared and conducted by the authority of the sovereign power on both sides are alone entitled to the denomination of just wars: And the enemy has no right to demand restitution for what the prosecution of such wars has reduced him to abandon through fear. It is upon this principle we admit the distinction which Cicero has made between an enemy, towards whom the consent and law of nations oblige us to observe many common rights, and between robbers and pirates. For any thing given up to pirates or robbers, through fear, is no lawful prize: but it may be recovered, unless a solemn oath of renunciation has been taken. This is not the case with the captures made in just war.
XIX. To connect the previous cases and arguments with public and national interests, it's important to note that there's a principle accepted by all nations: only wars declared and conducted by the sovereign authority of both sides are considered just wars. The enemy cannot demand compensation for what the pursuit of such wars has forced them to give up out of fear. This principle supports Cicero's distinction between an enemy, with whom we have to respect many common rights according to international law, and robbers and pirates. Anything surrendered to pirates or robbers out of fear is not a legitimate prize and can be reclaimed, unless a formal oath of renunciation has been made. This does not apply to captures made in a just war.
The justification which Polybius makes for the Carthaginians, in the second Punic war, carries with it an appearance of equity, though it is not a question immediately founded upon the law of nations. They alleged as a reason for their making that war, that, when they were engaged in quelling a mutiny of their own mercenaries, the Romans had declared war, seized upon Sardinia, and levied contributions of money.
The justification that Polybius provides for the Carthaginians during the Second Punic War seems fair, even though it isn't directly based on international law. They argued that they started the war because, while they were dealing with a revolt by their own mercenaries, the Romans declared war, took control of Sardinia, and demanded payments.
XX. Sovereign Princes and States are answerable for their neglect, if they use not all the proper means within their power for suppressing piracy and robbery. And on this account the Scyrians were formerly condemned by the Amphictyonic council.
XX. Sovereign princes and states are accountable for their inaction if they don’t use all the appropriate means available to them to stop piracy and robbery. Because of this, the Scyrians were previously condemned by the Amphictyonic council.
When some of the states of the united Provinces had, on a particular occasion, granted commissions to many privateers, and those adventurers plundered friends and enemies alike, and became general pirates, it was a subject of great discussion, whether those states were justified in having made use of the services of desperate and abandoned men, without exacting sufficient security for their good conduct. At that time, it was maintained that they were bound to nothing more, than to punish or deliver up the offenders, if they could be found, and to see justice done by a forfeiture of their property.201 For they themselves had neither authorised those UNJUST acts of plunder, nor shared in the fruits of them. They had even strictly prohibited the privateers from molesting the subjects of friendly powers. As to their taking securities, there was no obligation to do that: for they had a right to grant a GENERAL commission to all their subjects to seize upon the enemy's property: a thing, which had frequently been done. Nor could that particular commission be considered as an act of injustice against either allies or neutrals; since even without such permission individuals might have fitted and sent out armed vessels. The states could not foresee, nor consequently provide against the misconduct of those adventurers, who had exceeded their commission; and if nations were to decline using the assistance of wicked men, no army could ever be collected. And it has been confirmed by the authority both of France and England, that a sovereign cannot answer for every injury done to the subjects of a friendly power by his naval or military forces; especially if it is plain that they acted in violation of his orders.
When some of the states in the United Provinces, on a certain occasion, granted commissions to numerous privateers, those adventurers plundered both friends and enemies and became general pirates. This raised a significant debate about whether those states were justified in using the services of desperate and lawless men without securing adequate guarantees for their good behavior. At that time, it was argued that they were only obligated to punish or hand over the offenders if they could be found and to ensure justice was served through a forfeiture of their property.201 They had neither authorized these UNFAIR acts of plunder nor benefited from them. They had even explicitly prohibited the privateers from harassing the subjects of friendly powers. Regarding taking securities, there was no obligation to do so: they had the right to issue a GENERAL commission to all their subjects to seize enemy property, which had been done frequently. Additionally, that specific commission could not be seen as an act of injustice against allies or neutrals, since even without such permission, individuals could have outfitted and sent out armed vessels. The states could not anticipate or, therefore, prevent the misconduct of those adventurers who exceeded their commission; and if nations were to avoid using the help of unscrupulous individuals, no army could ever be assembled. It has also been affirmed by both France and England that a sovereign cannot be held accountable for every injury inflicted on the subjects of a friendly power by his naval or military forces, especially if it is clear that they acted against his orders.
But in what cases any one is released from being answerable for what is done by his subordinate agents, is a point not so much for the law of nations, as for the municipal law, and particularly the maritime code of each country to decide. In a case similar to that alluded to, a decision of the supreme court of judicature was made against the Pomeranians two centuries at least before.
But in what situations someone is not held responsible for what their subordinate agents do is more of an issue for domestic law rather than international law, and especially for the maritime laws of each country to determine. In a similar case mentioned, a ruling by the supreme court was made against the Pomeranians at least two centuries ago.
XXI. It is the CIVIL law too, which makes an owner answerable for the mischief or damage done by his slave, or by his cattle. For in the eye of natural justice he is not to blame. So neither is the person, whose ship, by running foul of another, has damaged it, though by the laws of many nations, and of ours among the rest, the damages are usually divided between both parties, owing to the difficulty of deciding, who was in fault.
XXI. It's also the CIVIL law that holds an owner responsible for the harm or damage caused by their slave or livestock. In terms of natural justice, they aren't at fault. Similarly, if a ship collides with another and causes damage, the owner of that ship isn't considered to blame. However, according to the laws of many countries, including ours, the damages are typically split between both parties because it's often hard to determine who was at fault.
XXII. Damages are allowed too for any injury done to our honour or reputation, by assault, slander, or various other ways. In which, as well as in theft and other crimes the nature of the offence is to be estimated by its consequences. For the reparation in such cases answers to the penalty imposed for crimes. And that reparation is made some times by acknowledging the injured party's innocence; and some times by a compensation in money, which is a standard value of all things.
XXII. Damages are also granted for any harm done to our honor or reputation, whether through assault, slander, or other means. In these cases, as well as in theft and other crimes, the severity of the offense is judged by its consequences. The compensation in such instances corresponds to the penalty for crimes. This compensation is sometimes provided by acknowledging the injured party's innocence, and at other times through a monetary payment, which serves as a standard measure of value for all things.
CHAPTER XVIII.
On the Right of Embassies.
Right of Embassies, an obligation arising out of the law of nations—Where it obtains—Whether Embassies are always to be admitted—Dismissal or punishment of ambassadors engaging in plots not to be considered as a harsh measure, but an act of self-defence—A power to whom no ambassador has been sent, not bound to respect the rights of embassy—An enemy to whom an ambassador is sent bound to respect his rights—The law of retaliation no plea for ill treatment of an ambassador—This right of protection extends to an ambassador's suite, if he thinks proper to claim it—To his moveable property—Examples of obligation without the right of compulsion—Importance of the sacred character of ambassadors.
Rights of Embassies, an obligation from international law—Where it applies—Whether embassies should always be recognized—The removal or punishment of ambassadors involved in conspiracies should not be seen as a severe action, but as a measure of self-defense—A country that has not received an ambassador is not obliged to honor embassy rights—An enemy country that accepts an ambassador must uphold his rights—The principle of retaliation does not justify mistreating an ambassador—This protection also applies to the ambassador's staff, if he chooses to request it—Regarding his movable property—Examples of obligations that exist without a right of enforcement—The significance of the sacred role of ambassadors.
I. Hitherto the pursuit of our inquiries has led us to examine those rights to which we are entitled by the law of nature, occasionally touching upon those points where its authority is farther confirmed by the voluntary law of nations. And that voluntary law as it is called, gives rise to certain obligations, which now remain for our discussion, and in which the rights of ambassadors form a leading feature. Almost every page of history offers some remark on the inviolable rights of ambassadors, and the security of their persons, a security sanctioned by every clause and precept of human and revealed law. Nor is it surprising that the persons of those should be deemed inviolable, who form the principal link in that chain, by which sovereigns and independent states maintain their intercourse with each other. To offer violence to them is not only an act of INJUSTICE, but, as Philip in his letter to the Athenians says, is acknowledged by all to be an act of IMPIETY.
I. Until now, our exploration has led us to look into the rights we have under the law of nature, while occasionally addressing areas where this law is further supported by the voluntary law of nations. This voluntary law, as it's called, creates certain obligations that we will discuss now, in which the rights of ambassadors are a key focus. Almost every page of history includes some comments on the inviolable rights of ambassadors and the protection of their persons—a protection validated by every clause and principle of human and revealed law. It’s not surprising that those who serve as the main link in the chain connecting sovereigns and independent states are seen as inviolable. To harm them is not only an act of Injustice, but, as Philip mentions in his letter to the Athenians, is recognized by everyone as an act of IRRELIGION.
II. But whatever rights the law of nations may confer upon ambassadors, it is necessary in the first place to observe, that none are entitled to them, but those, who are sent by the sovereigns of independent countries to each other. For the privileges of provincial, or municipal deputies sent to the states general of any country are regulated by the particular laws of that country and not by the law of nations.52
II. However, no matter what rights international law may give to ambassadors, it's important to first note that only those who are sent by the rulers of independent countries to each other are entitled to them. The privileges of provincial or local representatives sent to the general assemblies of any country are governed by the specific laws of that country, not by international law.nations.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
203 Thus we find, in the first book of Livy, an ambassador styling himself a public messenger of the Roman People; and, in the sixth book of the same historian, we have a declaration of the senate, confining the rights of embassies to the intercourse between foreign powers, and excluding citizens from the same privileges in their transactions with each other. Upon this topic, the authority of Cicero may be cited, who, in order to shew the impropriety of sending ambassadors to Antony, observes, that they are not dealing with a Hannibal or a foreign enemy, but with one of their own citizens.
203 In the first book of Livy, we see an ambassador calling himself a public messenger of the Roman People. Then, in the sixth book of the same historian, there's a statement from the senate that limits the rights of embassies to interactions between foreign nations, excluding citizens from those privileges when dealing with each other. Regarding this topic, Cicero’s authority can be referenced; he points out the absurdity of sending ambassadors to Antony by stating that they are not confronting a Hannibal or a foreign enemy, but rather one of their own citizens.
Now Virgil has so clearly explained WHO are to be reckoned FOREIGNERS, that we need not have recourse to lawyers, to understand what is so well expressed by the poet, who says, "I look upon every country as foreign, which owns not the sway of our sceptre." Aen. vii. 369.
Now Virgil has clearly explained who should be considered NON-NATIVE SPEAKERS, so we don’t need to consult lawyers to understand what the poet expresses well when he says, "I view every country as foreign that does not recognize our rule." Aen. vii. 369.
A state therefore connected with another though by an unequal treaty, if it retain its independence, will have a right of sending embassies. The Princes of Germany, who were in some respects subject to the Emperor, as their head, being Sovereign Princes possessed the right of sending ambassadors to foreign states. But Kings who have been entirely subdued in just war, and stripped of their dominions, have, with all their other sovereign rights, lost that of sending ambassadors. It was for this reason, that Paulus Aemilius made prisoners of the messengers sent to him by Perseus, whom he had conquered.
A state that is connected to another through an unequal treaty, but still maintains its independence, has the right to send embassies. The Princes of Germany, who were somewhat subject to the Emperor as their leader, were Sovereign Princes and had the right to send ambassadors to foreign states. However, kings who have been completely defeated in a just war and stripped of their territories lose that right along with all their other sovereign rights. This is why Paulus Aemilius captured the messengers sent to him by Perseus, whom he had conquered.
In civil wars necessity sometimes gives birth to new rights in violation of former rules. When for instance, a kingdom is so equally divided between two parties, that it is a matter of doubt which of them constitutes the nation, or in a disputed succession between two claimants of the crown; the kingdom may be considered as forming two nations at the same time. Tacitus, considering each party in such cases, as entitled to the rights of the law of nations, condemns the Flavians for having, in the rage of civil dissensions, violated, in the persons of the Vitellian ambassadors, those privileges, which are respected even among FOREIGN nations.204 Pirates and robbers, as they form no civil community, cannot rest any claim to protection and support upon the law of nations. Tiberius, as we are informed by Tacitus, when Tacfarinas sent ambassadors to him, spurned at the idea of treating with a robber, as with a lawful enemy. Yet sometimes a pledge of public faith, and the rights of embassy are allowed to men of that description, which was done by Pompey to the fugitives from the Pyrenean forest.
In civil wars, necessity can create new rights that go against previous rules. For example, when a kingdom is so evenly split between two factions that it’s unclear which one actually represents the nation, or during a disputed succession between two claimants to the throne, the kingdom might effectively exist as two nations at once. Tacitus notes that each side in such situations is entitled to the rights under international law, criticizing the Flavians for having, in their civil strife, violated the privileges of the Vitellian ambassadors, privileges that are respected even among ABROAD nations.204 Pirates and thieves, lacking any civil community, cannot assert a claim to protection under international law. Tiberius, as Tacitus tells us, dismissed the idea of negotiating with a thief as if he were a legitimate enemy when Tacfarinas sent ambassadors his way. However, there are times when public faith and the rights of diplomacy are granted to individuals in such a situation, as Pompey did for the fugitives from the Pyrenean forest.
III. There are two points upon which the privileges granted by the law of nations to ambassadors turn. In the first place, they have a right to be admitted into any country, and secondly to be protected from all personal violence. Respecting the former of these points, there is a passage in the eleventh book of Livy, where Hanno, a Carthaginian senator inveighs against Hannibal for not having admitted into his camp ambassadors, who came from the allies, and on their behalf; as he had thereby overturned the law of nations.
III. There are two main points regarding the privileges granted to ambassadors by international law. First, they have the right to enter any country, and second, they must be protected from any personal harm. Concerning the first point, there is a passage in the eleventh book of Livy, where Hanno, a Carthaginian senator, criticizes Hannibal for not allowing ambassadors from the allies to enter his camp, arguing that he violated international law by doing so.
But this rule by no means compels nations to give an UNQUALIFIED admission to all ambassadors. For that is what the law of nations can never intend: it only prohibits the refusal of admission without sufficient grounds.
But this rule doesn’t mean that countries have to accept all ambassadors without question. That’s not what international law is meant to say; it only prevents the denial of entry without valid reasons.
There are various motives which may afford a sufficient plea for such refusal. There may be an objection to the power who offers to treat, to the person sent upon the embassy, or perhaps to the object of his mission. Thus at the suggestion of Pericles, Melesippus, the Lacedaemonian ambassador, was sent out of the territories of Athens; because he came from an enemy, who had no pacific intentions. The senate of Rome said, that they could receive no embassy from Carthage, as long as the Carthaginian army remained in Italy. The Achaeans refused to admit the ambassadors of Perseus, who were secretly MEDITATING war against the Romans. Upon the same grounds Justinian rejected an embassy from Totilas, and the same was done by the Goths at Urbino to messengers from Belisarius. Polybius relates in the third book of his history, that every power drove away the ambassadors of the Cynethensians, as they were so infamous a people.
There are several reasons that could justify such a refusal. There might be an objection to the power that offers to negotiate, to the person sent as an ambassador, or possibly to the purpose of their mission. For instance, on the advice of Pericles, Melesippus, the Spartan ambassador, was expelled from Athens because he came from an enemy with no peaceful intentions. The Roman Senate stated that they could not accept an embassy from Carthage as long as the Carthaginian army was in Italy. The Achaeans turned away the ambassadors of Perseus, who were secretly planning war against the Romans. Similarly, Justinian rejected an embassy from Totilas, and the Goths at Urbino did the same with messengers from Belisarius. Polybius notes in the third book of his history that every power rejected the ambassadors of the Cynethensians because they were such a notorious people.
We have an instance of the second kind, where the objection is made to the PERSON sent on an embassy, in the case of Theodore, who was called the atheist, and205 whom Lysimachus refused to receive in the character of an ambassador sent from Ptolemy, and the same thing has frequently happened to others, against whom peculiar motives of aversion have existed.
We have an example of the second type, where the objection is raised against the PERSON sent on a mission, specifically in the case of Theodore, who was labeled the atheist. Lysimachus declined to accept him as an ambassador from Ptolemy, and similar situations have often occurred with others who were subjects of particular dislike.
In the third place, there may be sufficient grounds for refusing to admit an ambassador, if the object of his mission be of a suspicious kind, as was the case with that of Rhabshakeh the Assyrian, whom Hezekiah had reason to suspect of coming with a design to excite his people to rebellion. Or the refusal may be justified, where it is not consistent with the dignity or circumstances of one power to enter into any treaty, or intercourse with another. For this reason the Romans sent a declaration to the Aetolians, that they should send no embassy, but with the permission of their general, and Perseus was not allowed to send one to Rome, but to Licinius. Jugurtha's ambassadors too, as Sallust informs us, were ordered to leave Italy within the space of ten days, unless they came with offers from that prince to surrender himself, and his kingdom.
In the third place, there may be good reasons to refuse an ambassador's entry if the purpose of his mission is suspicious, like with Rhabshakeh the Assyrian, whom Hezekiah had reason to believe was trying to incite his people to rebel. A refusal can also be justified if it doesn't align with the dignity or situation of one power to engage in any treaty or interaction with another. For this reason, the Romans declared to the Aetolians that they should not send any embassy without their general's permission, and Perseus was not allowed to send one to Rome, only to Licinius. Jugurtha's ambassadors, as Sallust informs us, were ordered to leave Italy within ten days unless they came with offers from that prince to surrender himself and his kingdom.
There may often be the best reasons for a sovereign's refusing to allow of a RESIDENT minister at his court; a practice, so general in the present day, but totally unknown to the ages of antiquity.
There might often be valid reasons for a ruler's refusal to let a RESIDENT minister at their court; a practice that is so common today but completely unheard of in ancient times.
IV. As to the personal exemption of ambassadors from arrest, constraint, or violence of any kind, it is a subject of some difficulty to determine, owing to the varieties of opinion entertained by the most celebrated writers on the question. In the consideration of this matter, our attention is directed in the first place to the personal privileges and exemptions of ambassadors themselves, and next to those of their attendants, and their goods. With respect to their persons, some writers are of opinion, that it is ONLY from UNJUST VIOLENCE, and ILLEGAL CONSTRAINT, that the law of nations protects ambassadors. For they imagine that their privileges are to be explained according to the common principles of the law of nature. Others again suppose that ambassadors are not amenable to punishment for ALL offences, but only for such as amount to a transgression of the law of NATIONS, the principles of which are of such general extent, as to include the law of nature: consequently there can be no offences for which an ambassador is not punishable, except for those actions that are made such by the positive rules of MUNICIPAL or CIVIL LAW.
IV. When it comes to the personal immunity of ambassadors from arrest, coercion, or any form of violence, it’s quite challenging to define due to the differing opinions held by many well-known writers on the topic. Initially, we focus on the personal rights and exemptions of the ambassadors themselves, and then on those of their staff and their belongings. Regarding their individuals, some writers believe that the law of nations protects ambassadors ONLY from Unfair violence and ILLEGAL CONSTRAINT. They think these privileges can be explained through the common principles of natural law. Others argue that ambassadors aren't subject to punishment for ALL offenses, but only for those that violate the law of COUNTRIES, which broadly incorporates the law of nature. Therefore, the only actions for which ambassadors can’t be punished are those designated as offenses by the explicit rules of LOCAL or Civil Law.
206 Others again consider these public representatives of states and crowned heads, as only liable to punishment for offences affecting the dignity or governments of the sovereigns to whom they are sent. While, on the other hand, there are some writers who maintain that for any state to punish an ambassador for ANY CRIME WHATEVER is highly dangerous to the independence of foreign powers; but that all offenders of that description ought to be left to the laws of their respective countries, to be punished or not according to their deserts, upon due complaint being made to the sovereigns by whom they were sent.
206 Some people believe that these public representatives of states and royalty should only be punished for offenses that impact the dignity or governance of the rulers they represent. On the other hand, some writers argue that if a state punishes an ambassador for ANY CRIME AT ALL, it poses a significant threat to the independence of foreign powers. They believe that all offenders in this category should be subject to the laws of their own countries and punished or not based on their actions, provided a proper complaint is made to the rulers who sent them.
Some few writers, indeed, in laying down the rule to be observed in such cases, have decided that an appeal should be made to other independent and disinterested powers, which may be considered rather as a matter of DISCRETION, than of ABSOLUTE RIGHT. But the advocates of all these various systems have come to no definite conclusion in support of their favourite opinions. For this is a right which cannot, like the law of nature, be established upon unchangeable rules, but derives all its efficacy from the will of nations. Nations if they had thought proper, certainly might have laid down ABSOLUTE rules of security for ambassadors, or coupled them with certain exceptions. The argument is supported on one side by the urgent necessity of heinous crimes being punished, and on the other, the utmost latitude of exemption is favoured on account of the utility of embassies, the facility of sending which ought to be encouraged by every possible privilege, and security. To settle the point therefore, we must consider how far nations have agreed among themselves upon these principles; the proofs of which can only be found in the evidence of history.
Some writers, in defining the rules that should be followed in such situations, have suggested that an appeal be made to other independent and unbiased powers, which might be viewed more as a matter of discretion than of Absolute right. However, the supporters of these various systems haven't reached a clear agreement to back their preferred views. This is a right that cannot, like the law of nature, be established on unchanging rules but draws its authority from the will of nations. If nations had deemed it necessary, they certainly could have established ABSOLUTE rules of safety for ambassadors or attached certain exceptions to them. One side of the argument emphasizes the urgent need to punish serious crimes, while the other side advocates for maximum exemption due to the usefulness of embassies, which should be supported by every privilege and security possible. To resolve this issue, we need to consider how far nations have agreed on these principles; the evidence for this can only be found in historical records.
Many instances may be produced in favour of both opinions. And in cases like this, the opinions of those celebrated for their judgment and knowledge will be of no small weight, but in some cases we must rest upon conjectures. On this subject the two eminent historians, Livy and Sallust, may be quoted as authorities, the former of whom, in mentioning the ambassadors of Tarquin, who had been guilty of fomenting treasonable conspiracies at Rome, says, "that although they deserved to be treated as enemies for their guilty conduct, yet the privilege, which they derived from the law of nations, prevailed over every other consideration." Here we see that the207 rights of ambassadors could not be annulled even by the most criminal acts of hostility. But the observation made by Sallust, relates rather to those who come in the train of an embassy than to ambassadors themselves. The law of nations surely then will not deny the same privilege to a principal, which it evidently allows to those who form but a subordinate part in the public mission. The historian says, that "Bomilcar was arraigned and tried rather upon principles of equity and natural justice, than in conformity to the law of nations, as he belonged to the train of Jugurtha; who had come to Rome under the pledge of public faith."
Many examples can be provided to support both opinions. In situations like this, the views of those renowned for their judgment and knowledge will carry significant weight, but in some cases, we have to rely on speculation. In this regard, the two notable historians, Livy and Sallust, can be cited as authorities. Livy notes that the ambassadors of Tarquin, who had engaged in treasonous conspiracies at Rome, "although they deserved to be treated as enemies for their guilty conduct, yet the privilege, which they derived from the law of nations, prevailed over every other consideration." Here we see that the207 rights of ambassadors cannot be canceled even by the most criminal acts of hostility. However, Sallust’s comment pertains more to those who accompany an embassy rather than the ambassadors themselves. The law of nations surely cannot deny the same privilege to a principal that it clearly allows to those who are merely part of the public mission. The historian states that "Bomilcar was arraigned and tried rather on principles of equity and natural justice than in accordance with the law of nations, as he belonged to the entourage of Jugurtha; who had come to Rome under the protection of public faith."
Equity and natural justice require punishment to be inflicted on ALL offenders, whereas the law of nations makes an exception in favour of ambassadors, and those who have the public faith for their protection. Wherefore to try or punish ambassadors, is contrary to the law of nations, which prohibits many things, that are permitted by the law of nature.
Equity and natural justice require that punishment be imposed on ALL offenders, while international law makes an exception for diplomats and those who have public protection. Therefore, trying or punishing diplomats goes against international law, which forbids many actions that natural law permits.
The law of nations, thus deviating from the law of nature, gives rise to those interpretations and conjectures, which reconcile with the principles of justice a greater extension of privileges than the law of nature strictly allows. For if ambassadors were protected against nothing more than violence and illegal constraint, their privileges would confer no extraordinary advantage. Besides, the security of ambassadors is a matter of much greater moment to the public welfare than the punishment of offences. Because reparation for the misconduct of an ambassador may be looked for from the sovereign, by whom he is sent, unless that sovereign chuses to expose himself to hostilities by approving of his crimes. An objection to such privileges is made by some, who assert, that it is better for one person to be punished than for whole nations to be involved in war. But if a sovereign has SECRETLY given his sanction to the misconduct of his ambassador, his APPARENT intentions to punish that ambassador will not deprive the injured power of the right to seek redress by commencing hostilities.
The law of nations, diverging from natural law, leads to interpretations and assumptions that align with justice yet grant more privileges than natural law strictly permits. If ambassadors were only protected from violence and illegal restraint, their privileges wouldn't offer any significant benefit. Moreover, the safety of ambassadors is much more crucial to the public good than the punishment of wrongdoing. This is because the responsibility for an ambassador's misconduct can be expected to fall on the sovereign who sent him, unless that sovereign chooses to put himself at risk by endorsing his ambassador's wrongdoings. Some argue against such privileges, claiming it’s better for one individual to be punished than for entire nations to go to war. However, if a sovereign has SECRETLY approved of his ambassador's misconduct, his OBVIOUS willingness to punish that ambassador does not strip the injured nation of its right to seek redress through conflict.
On the other hand, the right of ambassadors would rest upon a very slippery foundation if they were accountable, for their actions, to any one but their own sovereigns. For as the interests of powers sending, and of those receiving ambassadors, are in general different, and some times even opposite, if a public minister were208 obliged to consult the inclinations of both, there would be no part of his conduct, to which they might not impute some degree of blame. Besides although some points are so clear, as to admit of no doubt, yet universal danger is sufficient to establish the equity and utility of a general law. For this reason it is natural to suppose, that nations have agreed, in the case of ambassadors, to dispense with that obedience, which every one, by general custom, owes to the laws of that foreign country, in which, at any time, he resides. The character, which they sustain, is not that of ordinary individuals, but they represent the Majesty of the Sovereigns, by whom they are sent, whose power is limited to no local jurisdiction. As Cicero, in his eighth Philippic, speaking of a certain ambassador, says, "he carried with him the Majesty of the Senate, and the authority of the State." From hence it is concluded, that an ambassador is not bound by the laws of the country, where he resides. If he commit an offence of a trivial nature, it may either be suffered to pass unnoticed, or he may be ordered to leave the country.
On the other hand, the rights of ambassadors would rest on a very shaky foundation if they were held accountable for their actions to anyone other than their own sovereigns. Since the interests of the sending and receiving powers are generally different, and sometimes even opposing, if a public minister had to consider the wishes of both, there would be no part of his conduct to which they couldn’t assign some degree of blame. Furthermore, while some issues are so clear that there’s no doubt, the existence of universal danger is enough to justify the fairness and usefulness of a general law. For this reason, it’s reasonable to assume that nations have agreed, in the case of ambassadors, to waive the obligation that everyone usually has to obey the laws of the foreign country in which they reside. The role they hold isn’t that of ordinary individuals; they represent the dignity of the sovereigns who sent them, whose authority isn’t confined to a specific jurisdiction. As Cicero mentions in his eighth Philippic, referring to a certain ambassador, "he carried with him the Majesty of the Senate, and the authority of the State." From this, it’s concluded that an ambassador is not bound by the laws of the country where he resides. If he commits a minor offense, it may either be overlooked or he may be asked to leave the country.
Polybius relates an instance of an ambassador, who was ordered to leave Rome, for having assisted some hostages in making their escape. Hence it is obvious why the Romans inflicted corporeal punishment upon an ambassador of Tarentum, because the Tarentines were at that time their own subjects, by right of conquest.
Polybius tells a story about an ambassador who was ordered to leave Rome for helping some hostages escape. This explains why the Romans punished an ambassador from Tarentum with physical punishment, as the Tarentines were at that time their subjects due to conquest.
If a crime is of a notorious nature, affecting the government, an ambassador may be sent home, and his sovereign required to punish, or deliver him up, as we read of the Gauls having done to the Fabians. But, as we have before occasionally observed, all human laws are framed upon such principles, as, in cases of extreme necessity, to admit of equitable relaxations, among which the privileges of ambassadors may be reckoned. But these extreme cases of necessity may, according to the law of nations, as will be seen hereafter, in discussing the effects of just and solemn war, prevent punishment in CERTAIN cases, though not in ALL. For it is not the act of punishment itself, which is objected to, either in respect to time, or manner, but the exemption is created to prevent the greater public evil, which might arise from the punishment of the offender. To obviate therefore any imminent danger, if no other proper method can be devised, ambassadors may be detained and interrogated.209 Thus the Roman Consuls seized the ambassadors of Tarquin, previously taking care to secure their papers, to prevent the evidence, which they might afford, from being destroyed. But if an ambassador excites and heads any violent insurrection, he may be killed, not by way of punishment, but upon the natural principle of self-defence. The Gauls therefore might have put to death the Fabii, whom Livy calls violators of the law of nature.
If a crime is notorious and impacts the government, an ambassador can be sent back home, and their leader can be asked to punish them or hand them over, just like we read about the Gauls doing to the Fabians. However, as we've pointed out before, all human laws are designed with principles that, in extreme situations, allow for fair relaxations, which includes the privileges of ambassadors. These extreme situations may, according to international law, as we will see later when discussing the effects of a just and solemn war, prevent punishment in SURE cases, though not in ALL. It's not the act of punishment itself that is objected to, regarding time or manner, but the exemption is put in place to prevent a greater public harm that could result from punishing the offender. To avoid any immediate danger, if no other suitable method can be found, ambassadors may be detained and questioned.209 In this way, the Roman Consuls captured the ambassadors of Tarquin, making sure to secure their documents to prevent any evidence they might provide from being destroyed. However, if an ambassador incites and leads a violent rebellion, they can be killed, not as punishment, but based on the natural principle of self-defense. Therefore, the Gauls could have executed the Fabii, whom Livy refers to as violators of natural law.
V. Mention has before been frequently made of the exemptions, by which ambassadors are protected from all personal constraint and violence, and it is understood that all powers are bound by a tacit agreement, as it were, from the time of admitting an ambassador, to respect these exemptions. It MAY and indeed sometimes DOES happen, that one power gives notice to another that no ambassador will be received, and if one is sent, that he will be treated as an enemy. A declaration to this effect was made by the Romans to the Aetolians, and, on another occasion, the Vejentian ambassadors were ordered to leave Rome, with a menace, if they refused to comply, of being treated in the same manner as the Roman ambassadors had been treated by their king Tolumnius, who had put them to death. The Samnites too forbade the Romans to go to any council in Samnium, under pain of forfeiting their lives, or, at least, their personal safety.
V. There has often been mention of the exemptions that protect ambassadors from any personal restraint or violence. It is understood that all powers have an unspoken agreement, so to speak, starting from the moment they accept an ambassador, to honor these exemptions. It MAY and sometimes DOES happen that one power informs another that they will not accept any ambassador, and if one is sent, they will be treated as an enemy. The Romans made a declaration to the Aetolians to this effect, and on another occasion, the Vejentian ambassadors were ordered to leave Rome, with a threat that if they didn’t comply, they would face the same treatment that the Roman ambassadors received from their king Tolumnius, who had killed them. The Samnites also prohibited the Romans from attending any council in Samnium, under the threat of losing their lives, or at least their personal safety.
The above law does not bind a power, through whose territories ambassadors pass without leave. For, if they are going to an enemy of that power, or returning from him, or are engaged in any hostile design, they may lawfully be treated as enemies; which was done by the Athenians in the case of the messengers passing between the Persians and Spartans, and by the Illyrians in that of those, who carried on the intercourse between the Essians and Romans. Xenophon maintains that in certain cases they may be made prisoners, as Alexander made those, who were sent from Thebes and Lacedaemon to Darius, and the Romans those, whom Philip sent to Hannibal, and Latius those of the Volscians. For to treat ambassadors with any degree of rigour, EXCEPT UPON THOSE SUFFICIENT GROUNDS, would be deemed not only a breach of the law of nations, but a personal offence against the sovereigns, to whom they are going, or by whom they are sent. Justin informs us, that Philip II, king of Macedon, sent an ambassador to Hannibal with credentials, empowering him to make an alliance,210 and that, when this ambassador was seized and carried before the Senate of Rome, they dismissed him without farther molestation, not out of respect to the king, but to prevent a doubtful enemy from becoming a decided one.
The law mentioned above does not bind a power if ambassadors pass through its territories without permission. If they're going to an enemy of that power, coming back from an enemy, or involved in any hostile actions, they can be treated as enemies. This was done by the Athenians with messengers traveling between the Persians and Spartans, and by the Illyrians with those who facilitated communication between the Essians and Romans. Xenophon argues that in certain situations, they can be taken prisoner, as Alexander did with those sent from Thebes and Lacedaemon to Darius, and the Romans did with those Philip sent to Hannibal, and Latius did with the Volscians. Treating ambassadors harshly, EXCEPT ON THOSE VALID GROUNDS, would be seen not only as a violation of international law but also as a personal offense against the sovereigns they are visiting or sending them. Justin tells us that Philip II, the king of Macedon, sent an ambassador to Hannibal with credentials to form an alliance,210 and that when this ambassador was captured and brought before the Senate of Rome, they let him go without further hassle, not out of respect for the king, but to stop a potential enemy from turning into a certain one.
VI. But if an embassy, admitted by an ENEMY is entitled to all the privileges of the law of nations, much more so is one, admitted by a power UNFRIENDLY, but not engaged in ACTUAL HOSTILITIES. Diodorus Siculus says, that a messenger with a flag of truce claims all the security of peace, even in the midst of war. The Lacedaemonians, who had murdered the heralds of the Persians, were said by that act to have confounded every distinction between right and wrong, as it is acknowledged by all nations. For legal writers lay it down as a rule, that to offer personal violence to ambassadors, whose characters are deemed sacred, is a defiance of the law of nations, and Tacitus calls the privileges we are now discussing, the rights of embassy, sanctified by the law of nations.
VI. If an embassy recognized by an RIVAL is entitled to all the privileges under international law, then an embassy recognized by a UNFRIENDLY power that is not engaged in ACTIVE CONFLICT is even more deserving of those privileges. Diodorus Siculus states that a messenger with a flag of truce is entitled to all the security of peace, even amid war. The Lacedaemonians, who killed the Persian heralds, were said to have blurred the lines between right and wrong, as recognized by all nations. Legal scholars assert that assaulting ambassadors, whose roles are considered sacred, is a violation of international law, and Tacitus refers to these privileges we are discussing as the rights of embassy, sanctified by international law.
Cicero, in his first speech against Verres, asks, if ambassadors ought not to be safe in the midst of an enemy's country, or even in his camp? Innumerable other instances of this kind might be produced from the highest authorities both ancient and modern. And it is with reason that such privileges are revered, for in the midst of war many circumstances arise, which cannot be decided but through ambassadors, and it is the only channel through which proposals of peace can be made, and confirmed.
Cicero, in his first speech against Verres, asks whether ambassadors shouldn't be safe even in the heart of enemy territory or their camp. Countless other examples can be cited from top authorities, both ancient and modern. It's no wonder these privileges are respected, as war creates many situations that can only be resolved through ambassadors, making them the sole means for proposing and confirming peace agreements.
VII. It is frequently made a subject of inquiry, whether the ambassador of a sovereign, who has exercised any act of cruelty or rigour, will be subject to the law of retaliation. History furnishes many instances, in which punishment has been inflicted in such a manner. But history is sometimes nothing more than a catalogue of actions marked with injustice, and ungovernable fury. Whereas the law of nations, by its privileges, designs to secure the dignity not only of sovereigns themselves, but also that of the ambassadors whom they employ. Consequently there is a tacit agreement understood to be made with the latter, that HE shall be exempt, not only from any ill treatment, that may affect the principal, but from such likewise, as may affect himself. So that it was a magnanimous answer, conformable to the law of nations, which Scipio made, when the Roman ambassadors had been211 ill-treated by the Carthaginians, and the Carthaginian ambassadors were brought before him, upon his being asked, in what manner they should be treated, he replied, not as the Roman ambassadors had been by the Carthaginians. Livy adds, that he said, he would do nothing unbecoming the character and laws of the Roman people. Valerius Maximus assigns the same language to the Consuls, on an occasion similar, but prior to this. In addressing Hanno, they said, "the pledge of faith, which our state has given, releases you from any such fear." For even at that time, Cornelius Asina, in violation of his public character, had been arrested and thrown into prison by the Carthaginians.
VII. It is often questioned whether an ambassador of a ruler, who has committed any act of cruelty or harshness, will face the law of retaliation. History provides several examples where punishment has been carried out in such cases. However, history can sometimes just be a list of actions marked by injustice and uncontrollable anger. The law of nations, through its privileges, aims to protect the dignity of not only the rulers themselves but also the ambassadors they send. As a result, there is an unspoken understanding that HE will be free from any mistreatment that may impact the ruler as well as from any that may affect himself. Therefore, it was a noble response, in line with the law of nations, that Scipio gave when the Roman ambassadors were 211 mistreated by the Carthaginians. When asked how the Carthaginian ambassadors should be treated, he replied, not in the way the Carthaginians treated the Roman ambassadors. Livy mentions that he stated he would do nothing unworthy of the character and laws of the Roman people. Valerius Maximus records similar remarks from the Consuls on a previous occasion; when addressing Hanno, they said, "the promise of faith our state has made frees you from such concerns." Even at that time, Cornelius Asina had been arrested and imprisoned by the Carthaginians, violating his public role.
VIII. The train too of an ambassador, and all the plate belonging to him are entitled to a peculiar kind of protection. Which gave rise to the passage in the ancient song of the Heralds, "O Sovereign, do you make me a royal messenger from the Roman citizens? and do you confer the same privileges on my train and every thing, which belongs to me?" And by the Julian law, an injury affecting not only ambassadors, but even their attendants, is pronounced to be a violation of public right.
VIII. The entourage of an ambassador, along with all their belongings, has a special kind of protection. This led to the line in the old song of the Heralds, "O Sovereign, will you make me a royal messenger for the Roman citizens? And will you grant the same privileges to my entourage and everything that belongs to me?" According to Julian law, harming not just ambassadors but even their attendants is considered a violation of public rights.
But these privileges of attendants are only granted so far as an ambassador himself may think proper: so that if any of them has committed an offence, he must be required to deliver up the offender to punishment. He must be REQUIRED to give him up. Because no violence, in taking an offender of that description must be used. When the Achaeans had arrested some Lacedaemonians who were along with the Roman ambassadors, the Romans raised a great outcry against the act, as a violation of the law of nations. Sallust's opinion in the case of Bomilcar has already been referred to.
But these privileges for attendants are only given as far as an ambassador believes is appropriate. So if any of them has committed an offense, the ambassador must hand over the offender for punishment. He must be REQUIRED to turn them in. No force should be used when taking an offender of that kind. When the Achaeans arrested some Lacedaemonians who were with the Roman ambassadors, the Romans protested loudly, claiming it violated international law. Sallust's opinion on the case of Bomilcar has already been mentioned.
But should the ambassador refuse to give up such offender, redress must be sought in the same manner, as would be done with respect to the ambassador himself. As to his authority over his household, and the asylum, which he may afford in his house to fugitives, these depend upon the agreement made with the power, to whom he is sent, and do not come within the decision of the law of nations.
But if the ambassador refuses to hand over such an offender, a solution must be sought in the same way as it would be for the ambassador himself. Regarding his authority over his household and the protection he can offer to fugitives in his home, these depend on the agreement made with the government he represents and are not subject to international law.
IX. Neither can the moveable property of an ambassador, nor any thing, which is reckoned a personal appendage, be seized for the discharge of a debt, either by process of law, or even by royal authority. For, to212 give him full security, not only his person but every thing belonging to him must be protected from all compulsion. If an ambassador then has contracted a debt, and, as is usual, has no possession in the country, where he resides: first of all, courteous application must be made to himself, and, in case of his refusal, to his sovereign. But if both these methods of redress fail, recourse must be had to those means of recovery, which are used against debtors residing out of the jurisdiction of the country.
IX. An ambassador's movable property, or anything considered a personal belonging, cannot be seized to pay off a debt, whether through legal action or even royal authority. To ensure his complete security, not just his person but everything that belongs to him must be shielded from any pressure. If an ambassador incurs a debt and, as often happens, does not own anything in the country where he lives: first, a polite approach must be made to him directly, and if he refuses, then to his government. But if both of these attempts to resolve the issue fail, one must resort to methods of recovery typically used against debtors who are outside the country's jurisdiction.
X. Nor is there, as some think, any reason to fear, that if such extensive privileges were established, no one would be found willing to enter into any contract with an ambassador, or to furnish him with necessary articles. For the same rule will hold good in the case of ambassadors, as in that of Kings. As sovereigns, who for the best of reasons, are placed above the reach of legal compulsion, find no difficulty in obtaining credit.
X. There’s no reason to worry, as some might believe, that if such broad privileges were established, no one would be willing to make contracts with an ambassador or provide him with necessary items. The same principle applies to ambassadors as it does to kings. Just like sovereigns, who for very good reasons are beyond the reach of legal enforcement, have no trouble getting credit.
XI. The importance of such exemptions may be easily inferred from the innumerable instances, in which both sacred and profane history abound, of wars undertaken on account of the ill-treatment of ambassadors. The war which David made against the Ammonites, on that account, affords us a memorable instance from holy writ; and as a profane writer, Cicero may be cited, who deemed it the most justifiable ground of the Mithridatic war.
XI. The significance of these exemptions is clear from the countless examples, found in both sacred and secular history, of wars fought over the mistreatment of ambassadors. The conflict that David waged against the Ammonites for this reason serves as a notable example from the Scriptures; and Cicero, a secular author, can also be referenced, as he regarded it as the most justified cause for the Mithridatic war.

PEACE
Peace
By Gari Melchers—From a panel painting in Library of Congress.
By Gari Melchers—From a panel painting in the Library of Congress.
CHAPTER XIX.
On Burial Rights.
Right of burying the dead founded on the law of nations—Origin of this right—Due to enemies—Whether due to those guilty of atrocious crimes—Whether to those, who have committed suicide—Other rights also authorised by the law of nations.
The right to bury the dead according to international law—Origin of this right—Granted to enemies—Is it granted to those guilty of serious crimes?—Is it granted to those who have taken their own lives?—Other rights also allowed under international law.
I. The right of burying the dead is one of those originating in the voluntary law of nations. Next to the right of ambassadors Dion Chrysostom places that of burying the dead, and calls it a moral act, sanctioned by the unwritten law of nature: And Seneca, the elder, ranks the law, which commands us to commit the bodies of the dead to their parent earth, among the UNWRITTEN precepts, but says, they have a stronger sanction than the RECORDED laws of all ages can give. For, in the language of the Jewish writers, Philo and Josephus, they are marked with the seal of nature, and under the name of nature, we comprehend the customs, that are common to all mankind, and agreeable to natural reason.
I. The right to bury the dead is one of those rights that comes from the voluntary law of nations. Right after the right of ambassadors, Dion Chrysostom places the right to bury the dead and calls it a moral act, supported by the unwritten law of nature. Seneca the Elder ranks the law that instructs us to return the bodies of the dead to the earth among the UNWRITTEN precepts, asserting that it carries a stronger authority than the RECORDED laws of all times. In the words of Jewish writers like Philo and Josephus, these laws bear the mark of nature, and by nature, we understand the customs shared by all humanity that align with natural reason.
We find it some where said by Aelian, that our common nature calls upon us to cover the dead, and some writer, in another place, observes that all men are reduced to an equality by returning to the common dust of the earth. Tacitus informs us, in b. vi. of his Annals, that, when Tiberius made a general massacre of all, who had been connected with Sejanus, and that he forbad them the rites of burial, every one was struck with horror to see the last offices of humanity refused; offices, which Lysias the orator calls the common hopes of our nature.
We find it somewhere noted by Aelian that our shared humanity compels us to bury the dead, and another writer points out that all people become equal when they return to the dust of the earth. Tacitus tells us in Book VI of his Annals that when Tiberius ordered a massacre of everyone associated with Sejanus and forbade them burial rites, everyone was horrified to see the last acts of humanity denied—acts that Lysias the orator refers to as the common hopes of our nature.
As the ancients measured the moral character of every people by their observance or neglect of these rights, in order to give them a greater appearance of sanctity, they ascribed their origin to the authority and institutions of their Gods; so that in every part of their writings we meet with frequent mention of the rights of ambassadors, and the rights of burial, as founded upon divine appointment.
As ancient cultures assessed the moral character of different societies based on how well they upheld or ignored these rights, they elevated their importance by claiming they came from the authority and institutions of their gods. This is why we often see references in their writings to the rights of ambassadors and burial rights as being divinely ordained.
In the Tragedy of the Suppliants, Euripides calls it the law of the Gods, and in the Antigone of Sophocles, the heroine makes the following reply to Creon, who had forbidden214 any one under pain of death, to give the rites of burial to Polynices, "A prohibition, like this, was not revealed by the supreme will, nor by that heaven-born justice, which has established those laws of respect for the dead: nor did I think that you could command mortals to transgress the unwritten and inviolable laws of God. They were not established to-day, nor yesterday, but from all eternity and will for ever be in force. Their sources are unknown. Am I through fear of a mortal, and by obeying his unjust commands, to incur the wrath of Heaven?"
In the Tragedy of the Suppliants, Euripides refers to it as the law of the Gods, and in Sophocles' Antigone, the heroine responds to Creon, who has prohibited anyone under the threat of death from giving burial rites to Polynices, saying, "A command like this wasn't revealed by the ultimate authority, nor by that divine justice which has set those laws of respect for the dead in place. I never thought you could order mortals to violate the unwritten and sacred laws of God. They weren't established today or yesterday, but have existed for all eternity and will always be in effect. Their origins are unknown. Am I supposed to fear a mortal and, by obeying his unfair commands, invite the anger of Heaven?"
The authority of Isocrates, and of Herodotus, and that of Xenophon, in the sixth book of his Grecian History, may be appealed to in support of the honours, that have at all times been paid to the dead. In short, these offices of humanity are recommended by the conspiring testimony of the orators, historians, poets, philosophers and divines of all ages, who have dignified them with the names of the most splendid virtues.
The authority of Isocrates, Herodotus, and Xenophon, in the sixth book of his Grecian History, can be referenced to support the honors that have always been given to the dead. In short, these acts of kindness are backed by the collective testimony of orators, historians, poets, philosophers, and theologians throughout history, who have celebrated them as the highest virtues.
II. There seems to be no general agreement of opinion upon the origin of funeral rites, and the variety of ways, in which they were performed. The Egyptians EMBALMED, and most of the Greeks BURNED the bodies of the dead before they committed them to the grave. Cicero, in the 22d chapter of his second Book on Laws, speaks of the interment alone, which is now in use, as the most ancient method, and that, which is most congenial to nature, and in this he is followed by Pliny.
II. There doesn't seem to be any general agreement on the origin of funeral rites or the various ways they were carried out. The Egyptians Embalmed their dead, while most of the Greeks BURNED the bodies before burying them. Cicero, in the 22nd chapter of his second Book on Laws, refers to burial as the oldest method, which is the most natural, and Pliny agrees with him.
Some think that men paid it as a VOLUNTARY debt of nature, which they knew that, AT ANY RATE, they would be obliged to discharge. For the divine sentence, that the body should return to the dust, from which it was taken, was not passed upon Adam only, but, as we find it acknowledged by the writings of Greece and Rome, extended to the whole human race. Cicero, from the Hypsipyle of Euripides, says, "Earth must be returned to earth," and in the twelfth chapter of Solomon's Ecclesiastes, there is a passage to the same purport, that "the dust shall return to the earth as it was, but the spirit to God, who gave it." Euripides has enlarged on this subject in the character of Theseus in his Suppliants, "Suffer the dead to be laid in the lap of the earth; for every thing returns to its original state, the spirit to heaven, and the body to the earth: Neither of them is given in plenary possession, but only for a short use: The earth215 soon demands back the bodies, to which she had given birth and nourishment." In the same manner Lucretius calls the earth "a prolific parent and a common grave." Pliny also describes the earth, as receiving us at our birth, cherishing our growth, supporting us to the very last, and, when all the other parts of nature have forsaken us, taking us to her maternal bosom, and covering us with a mantle.
Some believe that men see it as a Optional debt to nature, which they know they will have to repay ANYWAY. The divine decree that the body should return to the dust from which it came wasn't just for Adam; it applies to all of humanity, as recognized by ancient Greek and Roman writings. Cicero quotes Euripides, stating, "Earth must be returned to earth," and in the twelfth chapter of Ecclesiastes, Solomon writes, "the dust shall return to the earth as it was, but the spirit to God, who gave it." Euripides expands on this through the character of Theseus in his Suppliants, saying, "Let the dead be laid to rest in the earth; for everything returns to its original state, the spirit to heaven and the body to the earth: Neither is given in full possession, but only for temporary use: The earth215 soon demands back the bodies that she gave birth to and nurtured." Similarly, Lucretius refers to the earth as "a fruitful mother and a common grave." Pliny describes the earth as welcoming us at our birth, nurturing our growth, supporting us until the end, and when all other parts of nature abandon us, taking us into her embrace and covering us with a shroud.
There are some, who think that the custom of burial was bequeathed to us by our first parents as a testamentary hope of a resurrection. For we are instructed by Democritus to believe, that our bodies are preserved in the earth under the promise of a restoration to life. And Christians in particular have frequently ascribed the custom of decent burial to the same hope. Prudentius a Christian poet says, "What can be the meaning of hallowed rocks, or splendid monuments, except that they are the depositories of bodies, consigned not to death, but to a temporary sleep?"
Some people believe that the practice of burial was passed down to us by our first parents as a hopeful sign of resurrection. Democritus taught us to think that our bodies are kept in the ground with the promise of being brought back to life. Christians, in particular, often connect the custom of respectful burial to this same hope. Prudentius, a Christian poet, asks, "What could the purpose of sacred ground or impressive monuments be, other than that they hold the bodies, which are not given to death, but to a temporary sleep?"
But the most obvious explanation is to be found in the dignity of man, who surpassing other creatures, it would be a shame, if his body were left to be devoured by beasts of prey. It is an act of compassion then, said Quintilian, to preserve the bodies of men from ravages of birds and beasts. For to be tore by wild beasts, as Cicero observes in his first book On Invention, is to be robbed of those honours, in death, which are due to our common nature. And the Roman Poet, makes a lamentation over one of his heroes, that he had no pious mother to lay his body in the grave, but he would be left a prey to birds, or thrown into the river as food for fishes. Aen. x. 557–560.
But the most obvious explanation lies in the dignity of humanity, which, being superior to other creatures, would make it shameful for a person's body to be eaten by predatory animals. It's an act of compassion, as Quintilian said, to protect human bodies from the destruction caused by birds and beasts. Being torn apart by wild animals, as Cicero points out in his first book On Innovation, strips us of the honors that we deserve in death because of our shared humanity. The Roman poet laments over one of his heroes that he had no caring mother to bury him properly, leaving him to be a meal for birds or tossed into the river as food for fish. Aen. x. 557–560.
But to speak from still higher authority, God, by the mouth of his prophets, threatens the wicked that they shall have burial like that of the brutes, and that the dogs shall lick their blood. Such a menace denounced against the wicked, as a punishment, shews that it is an indignity done to our nature, when, in the words of Lactantius, the image of God is cast out, to the insults of beasts of prey. But in such indignity if there was even nothing repugnant to the feelings of men, still the nakedness and infirmities of our perishable nature should not be exposed to the eye of day.
But to reference a higher authority, God, through his prophets, warns the wicked that they will be buried like animals, and that dogs will lick their blood. Such a threat directed at the wicked as punishment shows that it's a humiliation to our nature when, in the words of Lactantius, the image of God is cast out to be mocked by wild beasts. Even if there was nothing offensive to human feelings in such humiliation, the nakedness and weaknesses of our fragile nature should not be exposed to the public eye.
Consequently the rights of burial, the discharge of which forms one of the offices of humanity, cannot be216 denied even to enemies, whom a state of warfare has not deprived of the rights and nature of men. For, as Virgil observes, all animosity against the vanquished and the dead must cease. Aen. xi. 104. Because they have suffered the last of evils that can be inflicted. "We have been at war, I grant, says Statius, but our hatred has fallen, and all our enmity is buried in the grave." And Optatus Milevitanus assigns the same reason for reconciliation. "If there have been struggles among the living, your hatred surely must be satisfied with the death of an adversary. For the tongue of strife is now silenced."
Consequently, the rights of burial, which are a basic aspect of our humanity, cannot be denied even to enemies, who, despite being in a state of war, still retain their rights as human beings. As Virgil notes, all hostility towards the defeated and the dead must come to an end. Aen. xi. 104. They have already endured the worst suffering that can be inflicted on them. "We have been at war, I admit," says Statius, "but our hatred has fallen, and all our enmity is buried in the grave." Optatus Milevitanus gives the same reason for reconciliation: "If there have been conflicts among the living, your hatred should be satisfied with the death of an opponent. For the voice of conflict is now silenced."
III. Upon the principles advanced above, it is agreed by all that public enemies are entitled to burial. Appian calls it the common right of war, with which, Tacitus says, no enemy will refuse to comply. And the rules, respecting this, are, according to Dio Chrysostom, observed, even while the utmost rage of war still continues. "For the hand of death, as the writer just quoted observes, has destroyed all enmity towards the fallen, and protected their bodies from all insult." Examples to this purpose may be found in various parts of history. Alexander ordered those of the enemy, that were killed at the battle of Issus to be honoured with the rites of burial, and Hannibal did the same to Caius Flaminius, Publius Aemilius, Tiberius Gracchus, and Marcellus, the Roman Generals. So that you would suppose, says Silius Italicus, he had been paying these honours to a Carthaginian General. The Romans treated Hanno, and Pompey Mithridates in the same manner. If it were necessary to quote more instances, the conduct of Demetrius on many occasions, and that of Antony to king Archelaus might be named.
III. Based on the principles mentioned earlier, everyone agrees that public enemies deserve a burial. Appian refers to it as the common right of war, which, according to Tacitus, no enemy will refuse to follow. According to Dio Chrysostom, the rules regarding this are observed even while the fury of war is still ongoing. "For the hand of death, as the writer just quoted observes, has removed all animosity towards the fallen and protected their bodies from any disrespect." There are various historical examples to support this. Alexander ordered that the enemy dead from the battle of Issus be honored with burial rites, and Hannibal did the same for Caius Flaminius, Publius Aemilius, Tiberius Gracchus, and Marcellus, the Roman generals. Silius Italicus remarks that one might think he was honoring a Carthaginian general. The Romans also treated Hanno and Pompey Mithridates in the same way. If more examples were needed, we could mention Demetrius's conduct on many occasions and Antony's treatment of King Archelaus.
When the Greeks were at war with the Persians, in one part of their military oath they swore to bury all the dead belonging to the ALLIES, and when they were victorious, to bury even the BARBARIANS. After a battle, it was usual for both sides to obtain leave to bury the dead. Pausanias, in his account of the Athenian affairs, mentions the practice of the Athenians who buried the Medes, regarding it as an act of piety due to all men. We find from the Jewish writers, that for the same reason, their high priests, who were forbidden to come near a dead body, if they found one, were obliged to bury it. But Christians deemed BURIAL an act of such importance,217 that they would allow their church-plate to be melted down, and sold to defray the expences as they would have done to maintain the poor, or to redeem captives.
When the Greeks were fighting the Persians, part of their military oath included a promise to bury all the dead from the FRIENDS, and after they won, to even bury the BARBARIANS. After a battle, it was common for both sides to get permission to bury their dead. Pausanias, in his account of Athenian affairs, talks about how the Athenians buried the Medes, seeing it as a respectful act toward all people. Jewish writings show that for the same reason, their high priests, who were not allowed to approach a dead body, were still required to bury one if they came across it. Christians considered Burial to be so significant,217 that they would even let their church silver be melted down and sold to cover the costs, just as they would to help the poor or free captives.
There are some few instances to the contrary, but they are reprobated by the universal feelings of mankind, and such cruelty deprecated in the most solemn terms. Claudian calls it a bloody deed to plunder the dead, and still more so to refuse them the covering of a little sand.
There are a few exceptions to this, but they are condemned by the universal feelings of humanity, and such cruelty is denounced in the strongest terms. Claudian refers to it as a bloody act to rob the dead, and even worse to deny them the comfort of a little bit of sand.
IV. Respecting those, who have been guilty of atrocious crimes, there is reason to entertain some doubt, whether the right of burial is due to them.
IV. Regarding those who have committed terrible crimes, there is reason to question whether they are entitled to a proper burial.
The divine law indeed, that was given to the Hebrews, and which is fraught with every precept of virtue and humanity, ordered those, who were crucified, which was the most ignominious kind of punishment that could be inflicted, to be buried on the same day. Owing to this law, as Josephus observes, the Jews paid such regard to burial, that the bodies of those, who were executed publicly as criminals, were taken away before sun-set, and committed to the ground. And other Jewish writers are of opinion that this was intended as a degree of reverence to the divine image, after which man was formed.
The divine law given to the Hebrews, filled with every principle of virtue and humanity, required that those who were crucified, the most shameful form of punishment, be buried on the same day. Because of this law, as Josephus notes, the Jews held burial in such high regard that the bodies of those publicly executed as criminals were removed before sunset and buried. Other Jewish writers believe this practice was meant as a sign of respect for the divine image in which humans were created.
To allow burial to criminals must have been the practice in the time of Homer: for we are told, in the third book of the Odyssey, that Ægisthus, who had added the crime of murder to that of adultery, was honoured with funeral ceremonies by Orestes, the son of the murdered king. It was the custom with the Romans, as may be seen from Ulpian, never to refuse giving the bodies of criminals to their relatives, to bury. The Emperors, Diocletian, and Maximian, in a rescript, declared, that they did not refuse to deliver up, for burial, those, who had deservedly been put to death for their crimes.
Allowing the burial of criminals seems to have been common during Homer’s time, as we learn in the third book of the Odyssey, where Ægisthus, who committed murder alongside adultery, received funeral honors from Orestes, the son of the murdered king. The Romans had a similar practice, as noted by Ulpian, who stated that they never denied relatives the right to bury the bodies of criminals. Emperors Diocletian and Maximian confirmed in a rescript that they would not refuse to hand over the bodies of those who had justly been executed for their crimes for burial.
In reading the history of civil wars; we find more frequent instances of indignities offered to the dead, than in the accounts of any foreign wars. In some cases, the bodies of executed criminals are exposed to public view, and hung in chains, a custom the propriety of which is very much doubted both by Theological and Political writers. So far from approving of the practice, we find such writers bestowing praises upon many, who had ordered funeral honours to be paid to those, who would not themselves have allowed the same to others. An action of this kind was done by Pausanias the Lacedaemonian,218 who, being urged by the people of Aegina to retaliate upon the Persians for their treatment of Leonidas, rejected the advice, as unbecoming his own character and the Grecian name. The Pharisees allowed burial even to King Jannaeus Alexander, who had treated the dead bodies of their countrymen with every kind of insult. Though indeed on certain occasions, God may have punished some offenders with the loss of such a right, he did so by virtue of his own prerogative, which places him above the restrictions of all law. And when David exposed the head of Goliah, it was done to one, who was an alien, and a despiser of God, and might be justified by that law, which confined the name and privileges of neighbour to the Hebrews.
In studying the history of civil wars, we notice that there are more frequent examples of disrespect shown to the dead compared to accounts of foreign wars. In some instances, the bodies of executed criminals are displayed for public view and hung in chains, a practice that is widely questioned by both theological and political scholars. Rather than endorsing this behavior, these scholars often praise those who have ensured that funeral honors are given to individuals, even when those individuals themselves would not have permitted the same for others. One notable instance of this was Pausanias the Lacedaemonian, who, when urged by the people of Aegina to take revenge on the Persians for their treatment of Leonidas, turned down the suggestion, believing it was unworthy of his character and the Greek identity. The Pharisees permitted burial even for King Jannaeus Alexander, who had shown extreme disrespect to the bodies of his fellow countrymen. While it is true that on certain occasions, God may have punished some offenders by denying them the right to a burial, He did so by His own authority, which is beyond any legal limitations. Additionally, when David displayed the head of Goliath, it was directed at someone who was an outsider and a foe of God, which can be justified by the law that restricted the concepts of neighbor and entitlements to the Hebrews.
V. There is one thing not improper to be observed, that the rule prevailing among the Hebrews with respect to burying the dead, contained an exception, as we are informed by Josephus, excluding those, who had committed suicide. Nor is it surprising that a mark of ignominy should be affixed to those, on whom death itself cannot be inflicted as a punishment. Aristotle in the fifth book of his Ethics, speaks of the infamy universally attached to suicide. Nor is the observation at all weakened by the opinions of some of the Grecian poets, that as the dead are void of all perception, they cannot be affected either by loss or shame. For it is a sufficient reason to justify the practice, if the living can be deterred from committing actions, for which they see a mark of infamy set upon the dead.
V. It’s worth noting that the rule among the Hebrews regarding burying the dead had an exception, as noted by Josephus, which excluded those who had committed suicide. It’s not surprising that a stigma would be placed on those for whom death itself cannot be imposed as a punishment. Aristotle, in the fifth book of his Ethics, discusses the disgrace that is universally associated with suicide. This observation isn't diminished by the views of some Greek poets who argue that since the dead lack perception, they cannot experience loss or shame. The main point is that the practice is justified if it discourages the living from actions that would bring dishonor to the dead.
In opposition to the Stoics, and others, who admitted the dread of servitude, sickness, or any other calamity, or even the ambitious love of glory to be a just cause of voluntary death, in opposition to them, the Platonists justly maintain, that the soul must be retained in the custody of the body, from which it cannot be released, but at the command of him, who gave it. On this subject there are many fine thoughts in Plotinus, Olympiodorus, and Macrobius on the dream of Scipio.
In contrast to the Stoics and others who believed that fear of slavery, illness, or any other misfortune, or even a strong desire for glory, could justify choosing to die, the Platonists rightly argue that the soul should remain in the body until it is released only by the one who created it. There are many insightful ideas on this topic in the works of Plotinus, Olympiodorus, and Macrobius's discussion of Scipio's dream.
Brutus, following the opinions of the Platonists, had formerly condemned the death of Cato, whom he himself afterwards imitated. He considered it as an act of impiety for any one to withdraw himself from his allegiance to the supreme being, and to shrink from evils, which he ought to bear with fortitude. And Megasthenes, as may be seen, in Strabo book xv. remarked the disapprobation,219 which the Indian sages expressed of the conduct of Calanus: for it was by no means agreeable to their tenets, that any one, through impatience, should quit his post in life. In the fifth book of Quintus Curtius, there is an expression of King Darius to this effect, that he had rather die by another's guilty hand than by his own. In the same manner the Hebrews call death a release, or dismission, as may be seen not only in the Gospel of St. Luke, ch. ii. v. 19, but in the Greek version of the Old Testament, Gen. xv. 2, and Numb. xx, towards the conclusion: and the same way of speaking was used by the Greeks. Plutarch, in speaking of consolation, calls death the time, when God shall relieve us from our post.
Brutus, following the views of the Platonists, had previously condemned Cato's death, which he later chose to emulate. He viewed it as an act of disrespect to abandon loyalty to the supreme being and to shy away from hardships that one should face with courage. Megasthenes, as noted in Strabo book xv., commented on the disapproval that Indian sages showed toward Calanus’ actions: they believed it was unacceptable for anyone to leave their responsibilities out of impatience. In the fifth book of Quintus Curtius, King Darius expresses that he would prefer to die by someone else’s wrongdoing than his own. Similarly, the Hebrews refer to death as a release, as seen in the Gospel of St. Luke, ch. ii. v. 19, as well as in the Greek version of the Old Testament, Gen. xv. 2, and Numb. xx, near the end. The Greeks also used this expression. Plutarch, when discussing consolation, refers to death as the moment when God will free us from our responsibilities.
VI. There are certain other rights too, which owe their origin to the voluntary law of nations, such as the right of possession from length of time, the right of succession to any one who dies intestate, and the right resulting from contracts, though of an unequal kind. For though all these rights, in some measure, spring from the law of nature, yet they derive their confirmation from human law, whether it be in opposition to the uncertainty of conjecture, or to certain other exceptions, suggested by natural reason: points, all of which have been slightly touched upon in our discussions on the law of nature.
VI. There are also other rights that come from the voluntary law of nations, like the right to possess something after a certain period, the right of inheritance for someone who dies without a will, and rights arising from contracts, even if they are imbalanced. While all these rights are somewhat based on natural law, they are reinforced by human law, whether it contradicts uncertain guesses or addresses other exceptions indicated by common sense: topics we have briefly mentioned in our discussions on natural law.
CHAPTER XX.
On Punishments.
Definition and origin of punishment—In what manner punishment relates to strict justice—The right of punishing allowed by the law of nature, to none, except to those, who are innocent of the crimes and misdemeanours to be punished—Difference of motive between human and divine punishment—In what sense revenge is naturally unlawful—The advantages of punishment, threefold—The law of nature allows any one to inflict punishment upon an offender, yet with a distinction—The regard which the law of nations pays to the benefit of the injured party, in the infliction of punishment—General utility of punishments—What is determined by the law of the Gospel, in this respect—Answer to the objections founded upon the mercy of God, as displayed in the Gospel—Capital punishments objected to as cutting off all possibility of repentance—Not safe for private Christians to inflict punishments, even when allowed to do so, by the law of nations—Prosecutions, for certain offences, to be carried on in the name of the public and not of individuals—Internal acts not punishable by man—Open acts, when inevitable through human infirmity not punishable—Actions, neither directly nor indirectly injurious to society, not punishable by human laws—The reasons of that exemption—The opinion, that pardon can never be granted, refuted—Pardon shewn to be allowable before the establishment of penal law—But not in all cases—Allowable also subsequently to the establishment of penalties—Internal and external reasons—Opinion, that there can be no just reason for dispensing with laws, except where such dispensation can be implied as authorised by the law, examined and refuted—Punishment estimated by the desert of the offender—Different motives compared—Motives which ought to restrain men from sin—Scale of offences according to the precepts of the Decalogue—Capacity of the offender—Punishment mitigated from motives of charity, except where there are stronger motives of an opposite kind—Facility or familiarity of crimes aggravates their nature—Clemency, proper exercise of—Views of the Jews and Romans in inflicting punishment—War considered as a punishment—Whether hostilities can justly be commenced for intended aggressions—Whether Kings and Nations are justified in making war to punish offences against the law of nature, not immediately affecting themselves or their subjects—The opinion, that jurisdiction is naturally necessary to authorise punishment, refuted—Distinction between the law of nature, and civil customs, and the divine voluntary law—The question, whether war can be undertaken to punish acts of impiety—considered—The being of God, whence known—Refusal to embrace the Christian religion not a sufficient cause of war—Cruel treatment of Christians, justifiable cause of war—Open defiance of religion punishable.
Definition and origin of punishment—How punishment connects to strict justice—Only those who are innocent of the crimes being punished have the natural right to enforce punishment—Differences in motivations for human and divine punishment—Why revenge is inherently wrong—There are three main benefits of punishment—While the law of nature permits anyone to punish an offender, there are distinctions to consider—International law acknowledges the injured party’s benefit in punishment—The overall usefulness of punishments—What the Gospel law expresses about this—Responses to objections based on God’s mercy shown in the Gospel—Criticism of capital punishment for removing all chances of repentance—It’s risky for individual Christians to carry out punishments, even when allowed by international law—Prosecutions for certain crimes should be conducted in the name of the public, not individuals—Internal acts aren't punishable by humans—Public acts stemming from unavoidable human flaws aren't punishable—Actions that don't harm society directly or indirectly aren't subject to human laws—Reasons for this exemption—The notion that pardon is never possible is disproven—Pardon is shown to be acceptable before penal law is established—But not in every situation—It's also acceptable after penalties are set—Internal and external factors—The idea that there’s no valid reason to go against laws, unless such exceptions are implied, is examined and refuted—Punishment is grounded in the offender's wrongdoing—Different motivations are compared—Motivations that should discourage sin—A scale of offenses based on the principles of the Decalogue—The offender's capacity—Punishment can be lessened based on charitable motives, unless stronger opposing motives exist—The familiarity of crimes makes them worse—Proper use of clemency—Jewish and Roman perspectives on punishment—War is seen as a form of punishment—Whether hostilities can justly begin for potential attacks—Whether kings and nations have the right to wage war to punish offenses against the law of nature that don't directly impact themselves or their people—The belief that authority is naturally necessary to legitimize punishment is challenged—The distinction between the law of nature, civil customs, and divine voluntary law—The question of whether war can be waged to punish acts of impiety is discussed—The existence of God and how it's known—Rejecting the Christian religion is not a valid reason for war—Cruel treatment of Christians is a justifiable reason for war—Open defiance of religion warrants punishment.
221 I. In the preceding part of this treatise, where the causes, for which war may be undertaken, were explained, it was considered in a two-fold light, either as a reparation for injuries, or as a punishment. The first of these points having been already cleared up, the latter, which relates to punishments, remains to be discussed, and it will require a more ample investigation; for the origin and nature of punishment, not being perfectly understood, has given rise to many errors.
221 I. In the earlier section of this paper, where the reasons for going to war were explained, it was viewed in two ways: either as a way to make up for injuries or as a form of punishment. Since the first point has already been addressed, we will now focus on the second, which concerns punishments, and this will need a more thorough examination; because the origins and nature of punishment are not completely understood, it has led to many misconceptions.
Punishment taken in its most general meaning signifies the pain of suffering, which is inflicted for evil actions. For although labour may some times be imposed instead of punishment; still it is considered in that case, as a hardship and a grievous burden, and may therefore properly be classed with sufferings. But the inconveniences, which men are some times exposed to, by being excluded from the intercourse of society and the offices of life, owing to infectious disorders, or other similar causes, which was the case with the Jews on account of many legal impurities, these temporary privations are not to be strictly taken for punishments: though from their resemblance to each other, they are often, by an abuse of terms, confounded.
Punishment, in its broadest sense, refers to the pain inflicted on someone for wrongdoing. While sometimes hard labor may be assigned instead of punishment, it is still viewed as a hardship and a serious burden, so it can be correctly categorized as a form of suffering. However, the hardships that people sometimes face when excluded from social interactions and the responsibilities of life due to contagious diseases or similar issues—like the situation with the Jews who faced many legal restrictions—should not be strictly regarded as punishments. Even though they are often confused with punishments due to their similarities, these temporary deprivations are not the same.
But among the dictates laid down by nature, as lawful and just, and which the ancient Philosophers call the law of Rhadamanthus, the following maxim may be placed, THAT IT IS RIGHT FOR EVERY ONE TO SUFFER EVIL PROPORTIONED TO THAT WHICH HE HAS DONE.
But among the rules established by nature, which are lawful and just, and which the ancient philosophers refer to as the law of Rhadamanthus, the following principle can be stated, IT IS JUST FOR EVERYONE TO FACE EVIL IN PROPORTION TO THEIR ACTIONS..
Which gave occasion to Plutarch, in his book on exile, to say that "justice is an attribute of God, avenging all transgressions of the divine law; and we apply it as the rule and measure of our dealings with each other. For though separated by the arbitrary or geographical bounds of territory, the eye of nature looks upon all, as fellow subjects of one great empire." Hierocles gives a fine character of justice, calling it the healing remedy of all mischief. Lactantius in speaking of the divine wrath calls it "no inconsiderable mistake in those, who degrade human or divine punishment with the name of cruelty or rigour, imagining that some degree of blame must always attach to the punishment of the guilty." What has been said of the inseparable connection of a penalty with every offense is similar to the remark of Augustin, "that to make a punishment JUST, it must be inflicted for some crime." He applies the expression to explain222 the divine justice, where through human ignorance, the offence is often undiscoverable though the judgment may be seen.
Which gave Plutarch the opportunity, in his book on exile, to say that "justice is a characteristic of God, punishing all violations of divine law; and we use it as the standard and guideline for our interactions with each other. For although separated by arbitrary or geographical boundaries, nature sees us all as fellow subjects of one vast empire." Hierocles provides a great description of justice, referring to it as the healing remedy for all harm. Lactantius, while discussing divine wrath, calls it "a significant mistake for those who label human or divine punishment as cruelty or harshness, thinking that some level of blame must always be attached to punishing the guilty." What has been said about the essential connection of a penalty to every offense is similar to Augustin's remark that "to make a punishment JUST, it must be imposed for some crime." He uses this term to clarify222 the concept of divine justice, where due to human ignorance, the offense can often go unnoticed even though the judgment may be apparent.
II. There are diversities of opinion whether punishment comes under the rank of ATTRIBUTIVE or that of STRICT justice. Some refer it to justice of the attributive kind, because offences are punished more or less, in proportion to their consequences, and because the punishment is inflicted by the whole community, as it were, upon an individual.
II. There are different opinions on whether punishment falls under ATTRIBUTIVE justice or STRICT justice. Some consider it to be a form of attributive justice because offenses are punished to varying degrees based on their impact, and because the punishment is imposed by the entire community, so to speak, on an individual.
It is undoubtedly one of the first principles of justice to establish an equality between the penalty and the offence. For it is the business of reason, says Horace, in one of his Satires, to apply a rule and measure, by which the penalty may be framed upon a scale with the offence, and in another place, he observes, that it would be contrary to all reason to punish with the rack a slave, who deserved nothing more than the whip. I. Sat. iii. v. 77, and 119. The divine law, as may be seen from the xxv. Chapter of Deuteronomy, rests upon the same principle.
It is definitely one of the fundamental principles of justice to create a balance between the punishment and the crime. As Horace states in one of his Satires, it is the role of reason to apply a standard and measure that allows the penalty to be sized appropriately to the offense. He also notes that it would be completely unreasonable to torture a slave with the rack when all they deserve is a whipping. I. Sat. iii. v. 77, and 119. The divine law, as shown in the xxv. Chapter of Deuteronomy, is based on the same principle.
There is one sense, in which all punishment may be said to be a matter of strict justice. Thus, when we say that punishment is due to any one, we mean nothing more than that it is right he should be punished. Nor can any one inflict this punishment, but the person, who has a right to do so. Now in the eye of the law, every penalty is considered, as a debt arising out of a crime, and which the offender is bound to pay to the aggrieved party. And in this there is something approaching to the nature of contracts. For as a seller, though no EXPRESS stipulation be made, is understood to have bound himself by all the USUAL, and NECESSARY conditions of a sale, so, punishment being a natural consequence of crime, every heinous offender appears to have VOLUNTARILY incurred the penalties of law. In this sense some of the Emperors pronounced sentence upon malefactors in the following manner, "you have brought this punishment upon Yourselves." Indeed every wicked action done by design was considered as a voluntary contract to submit to punishment. For, as Michael the Ephesian observes on the fifth book of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics, the ancients gave the name of contract, not only to the voluntary agreements which men made with each other, but to the obligations arising from the sentence of the law.
There’s a way in which all punishment can be seen as a matter of strict justice. When we say that someone deserves punishment, we simply mean that it’s right for them to be punished. Only the person who has the authority can impose this punishment. According to the law, every penalty is viewed as a debt that arises from a crime, which the offender is obligated to pay to the victim. This situation resembles the nature of contracts. Just as a seller, even without an explicit agreement, is understood to have committed to all the usual and necessary terms of a sale, punishment is a natural consequence of a crime; therefore, every serious offender seems to have voluntarily accepted the penalties of the law. In this way, some emperors stated sentences against wrongdoers with the remark, "you have brought this punishment upon yourselves." In fact, every deliberate wicked action was viewed as a voluntary agreement to face punishment. As Michael the Ephesian points out in the fifth book of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics, the ancients referred to a contract not just as the voluntary agreements people made with one another but also to the obligations that arose from legal sentences.
223 III. But to whom the right of punishing properly belongs, is a matter not determined by the law of NATURE. For though reason may point out the necessity of punishing the guilty, it does not specify the PERSON, to whom the execution of it is to be committed.
223 III. However, the question of who has the rightful authority to punish isn't settled by the law of NATURE. While reason might indicate that punishing the guilty is necessary, it doesn't determine the PERSON who should carry it out.
Natural reason indeed does so far point out the person, that it is deemed most SUITABLE for a SUPERIOR ONLY to be invested with the power of inflicting punishment. Yet this demonstration does not amount to an ABSOLUTE NECESSITY, unless the word superior be taken in a sense implying, that the commission of a crime makes the offender inferior to every one of his own species, by his having degraded himself from the rank of men to that of the brutes, which are in subjection to man; a doctrine, which some Theologists have maintained. Philosophers too agreed in this. For Democritus supposed that power naturally belonged to superior merit, and Aristotle was of opinion that both in the productions of nature and art the inferior were provided for the use of the superior parts.
Natural reason indicates that it's considered most APPROPRIATE for a SUPERIOR ONLY to have the authority to punish. However, this argument doesn't reach an MUST-HAVE unless "superior" is understood to mean that committing a crime makes the offender lesser than everyone else in their group, as they have lowered themselves from the status of humans to that of the animals that are under human control; a belief upheld by some theologians. Philosophers have also agreed on this point. Democritus believed that power naturally belonged to those with superior merit, and Aristotle thought that both in nature and in art, the inferior were meant to serve the superior.
From this opinion there arises a necessary consequence, that in a case where there are equal degrees of guilt in two parties, the right of punishment belongs to neither.
From this opinion, a necessary conclusion follows: in a situation where two parties share equal levels of guilt, the right to punish does not belong to either.
In conformity to which, our Saviour, in the case of the woman taken in adultery, pronounced that whoever of the accusers was without sin, meaning sins of equal enormity, should cast the first stone. John viii. 7. He said so for this reason, because in that age the manners of the Jews were so corrupt, that, under a great parade of sanctity, the most enormous vices, and the most wicked dispositions were concealed. A character of the times which the Apostle has painted in the most glowing colours, and which he closes with a reproof similar to what his divine master had given, "therefore thou art inexcusable, O man, whosoever thou art that judgest: for wherein thou judgest another thou condemnest thyself; for thou that judgest doest the same things." Rom. ii. 1. Applicable to which there is a remark of Seneca's, that "no sentence, which is passed by a guilty person can have any weight." And in another place, the same writer observes, that "if we look into ourselves and consider whether we have been guilty of the offences we are going to condemn, we shall be more moderate in our judgments."
In line with this, our Savior, regarding the woman caught in adultery, declared that whoever among the accusers is without sin—meaning sins of the same severity—should throw the first stone. John 8:7. He said this because, during that time, the morals of the Jews were so corrupt that, beneath a great show of holiness, they concealed the most terrible vices and wicked attitudes. The Apostle described the state of the times in vivid detail and concluded with a rebuke similar to that of his divine teacher: "Therefore you are inexcusable, O man, whoever you are that judges; for in judging another, you condemn yourself; for you who judge do the same things." Rom. 2:1. This relates to a remark by Seneca that "no judgment made by a guilty person can hold any weight." In another instance, the same writer notes that "if we look within ourselves and reflect on whether we have been guilty of the offenses we are about to condemn, we will be more moderate in our judgments."
224 IV. Another part of our inquiry respects the end proposed by punishment. For by what has hitherto been said, it was only meant to shew that in punishing the guilty no injury is done to them. Still the absolute necessity of punishment does not follow from thence. For the pardon of the guilty on many occasions has been considered as the most beauteous feature in the divine and human character. Plato is celebrated for his saying that "justice does not inflict punishment for the evils that are done and cannot be retrieved; but to prevent the same from being done for the time to come." From Thucydides we find that Diodorus in addressing the Athenians on the conduct of the Mitylenaeans, advises them "to forbear punishing their avowed injustice, unless it was probable that the punishment would be attended with some good effect."
224 IV. Another part of our inquiry concerns the purpose of punishment. What we have discussed so far aims to show that punishing the guilty does not harm them. However, this does not mean that punishment is absolutely necessary. In many situations, forgiving the guilty has been seen as one of the most admirable traits in both divine and human character. Plato is famous for saying that "justice does not impose punishment for wrongs that cannot be undone; it aims to prevent similar wrongs in the future." From Thucydides, we learn that Diodorus, in speaking to the Athenians about the actions of the Mitylenaeans, advised them "to refrain from punishing their blatant injustice unless it was likely that the punishment would lead to some positive outcome."
These maxims may be true with regard to human punishments: for one man being so nearly allied to another by blood, no degree of suffering should be inflicted, but for some consequent good. But the case is different with respect to God, to whom Plato injudiciously applies the above sentiments. For though the divine counsels will undoubtedly have the good of men in view, as the end of all punishment, yet the bare reformation of the offender cannot be the sole object. Since the divine justice, though tempered with mercy must adhere to the truth of the revealed word, which threatens the wicked with punishment or destruction.
These sayings might hold true regarding human punishments: since one person is so closely related to another by blood, no one should suffer unless there’s some resulting benefit. But the situation is different when it comes to God, to whom Plato incorrectly applies these ideas. While divine plans certainly aim for the good of humanity as the ultimate goal of all punishment, simply reforming the wrongdoer can’t be the only purpose. Divine justice, even though it’s softened by mercy, must still align with the truth of the revealed word, which warns the wicked of punishment or destruction.
The honour therefore of God, as well as the example held up to men, will be a consequence resulting from his punishment of the wicked.
The honor of God, as well as the example set for people, will come from his punishment of the wicked.
V. A dramatic writer has said that "the pain of an enemy is a healing remedy to a wounded spirit," in which he agrees with Cicero and Plutarch: in the opinion of the former "pain is mitigated by the punishment of an adversary," and in that of the latter "satisfaction is a sweet medicine to a troubled mind."
V. A playwright once said that "the pain of an enemy is a healing remedy for a wounded spirit," which aligns with what Cicero and Plutarch believed: Cicero thought "pain is lessened by the punishment of an opponent," while Plutarch felt "satisfaction is a soothing medicine for a troubled mind."
But a disposition like this, when stripped of all disguise and false colouring, will be found by no means suitable to the reasonable soul of man, whose office it is to regulate and controul the affections. Nor will that disposition receive any sanction from the law of nature, who in all her dictates, inclines to unite men in society by good will, rather than to separate them by cherishing animosity. For it is laid down by reason, as a225 leading axiom in her code of laws, that no man shall do any thing which may hurt another, unless it be for the purpose of some evident and essential good. But the pain of an enemy considered solely of such, is no benefit to us, but a false and imaginary one, like that derived from superfluous riches or things of the same kind.53
But a mindset like this, when stripped of all pretense and false appearances, is definitely not suitable for the reasonable nature of humans, whose role is to manage and control their emotions. Additionally, this mindset won’t be supported by the law of nature, which in all its guidance tends to encourage individuals to come together in society through goodwill, rather than pushing them apart by fostering animosity. Reason establishes a key principle in its laws: no one should do anything that could harm another person, unless it aims at some clear and essential good. However, the suffering of an enemy, when viewed solely on its own, brings us no real benefit, but rather a false and illusory one, similar to the kind gained from excessive wealth or things of that nature.
In this acceptation revenge is condemned both by Christian teachers and heathen philosophers. In this respect, the language of Seneca approaches very near to the perfection of Christian morals. He calls revenge, in its usual and proper acceptation, a term of inhumanity, differing from injury only in degree. For retaliation of pain can be considered as nothing better than excusable sin. Juvenal, after describing the different tempers, over which revenge exercises the most powerful dominion, and shewing the amiable characters over which it has no influence, concludes it to be the pleasure of a little and infirm mind.
In this sense, both Christian teachers and pagan philosophers condemn revenge. In this regard, Seneca's language comes very close to embodying Christian morals. He refers to revenge, in its usual and proper sense, as a term for inhumanity, differing from injury only in degree. Retaliating against pain can be seen as nothing more than an excusable sin. Juvenal, after describing the various temperaments that revenge has the most control over, and showing the kind characters that it doesn’t affect, concludes that it’s a pleasure of a small and weak mind.
From the preceding arguments it is plain that punishment cannot justly be inflicted from a spirit of revenge. We proceed therefore to consider the advantages attending its just infliction.
From the previous points, it's clear that punishment shouldn't be handed out from a place of revenge. We will now look at the benefits of administering punishment justly.
VI. This seems the most proper place for reviewing those distinctions in the motives of punishment, which have been used by Plato in his Gorgias, and by Taurus the philosopher in a passage quoted by Gellius in the fourteenth chapter of his fifth book. These distinctions seem to result naturally from the end of all punishment. Plato indeed considers the amendment of the offender, and the example given to others, as the two principal motives: but Taurus has added a third, which he calls satisfaction, and which is defined by Clemens Alexandrinus, to be repayment of evil, contributing to the benefit226 of both the aggrieved and avenging party. Aristotle passing over example as a motive, confines the object of punishment to the amendment or correction of the offender. But Plutarch has not made the same omission: for he has said, that "where immediate punishment follows the execution of a heinous crime, it both operates to deter others from committing the same crime, and administers some degree of consolation to the injured and suffering person." And this is what Aristotle calls commutative justice. But these matters require a more minute inquiry. We may observe therefore that there is nothing contrary either to human or divine law, in punishments, which have the good of the offender, or that of the injured party, or of any persons whatsoever in view.
VI. This seems to be the best place to review the different motives behind punishment that Plato discussed in his Gorgias and that Taurus the philosopher mentioned in a passage cited by Gellius in the fourteenth chapter of his fifth book. These distinctions appear to arise naturally from the purpose of all punishment. Plato considers the reformation of the offender and the example set for others as the two main motives. However, Taurus adds a third motive, which he calls satisfaction, defined by Clemens Alexandrinus as repayment for wrongdoing, benefiting both the harmed and the avenger. Aristotle, on the other hand, overlooks setting an example as a motive and focuses solely on the purpose of punishment being the reformation or correction of the offender. Plutarch does not make this omission, stating that "when immediate punishment follows the commission of a serious crime, it serves to deter others from committing the same offense and provides some comfort to the victim and those suffering." This aligns with what Aristotle refers to as commutative justice. Nevertheless, these topics require a deeper examination. Therefore, we can see that there is nothing against either human or divine law in punishments that consider the well-being of the offender, the injured party, or anyone else involved.
The three proper ends are obtained by that kind of punishment, which some philosophers have called correction, some chastisement, and others admonition. Paulus the Lawyer, has given it the name of correction; Plato styles it a lesson of instruction, and Plutarch a medicine of the soul, reforming and healing the sufferer, while it operates as a painful remedy. For as all deliberate acts, by frequent repetition, produce a propensity, which ripens into habit, the best method of reforming vices in their earliest stage is to deprive them of their sweet savour by an infusion of subsequent pain. It is an opinion of the Platonists, repeated by Apuleius, that "impunity and the delay of reproof are more severe and pernicious to an offender than any punishment whatsoever," and, in the words of Tacitus, "violent disorders must be encountered with remedies proportionably strong."
The three proper purposes are achieved through a type of punishment that some philosophers call correction, others call chastisement, and some refer to as admonition. Paulus the Lawyer names it correction; Plato refers to it as a lesson of instruction, and Plutarch describes it as a medicine for the soul, reforming and healing the person while acting as a painful remedy. Just as all deliberate actions, through consistent repetition, create a tendency that develops into a habit, the best way to correct vices in their early stages is to strip them of their appeal by introducing subsequent pain. The Platonists, echoed by Apuleius, believe that "not facing any consequences and delaying criticism are more harmful to an offender than any punishment," and as Tacitus puts it, "violent disorders must be addressed with remedies that are equally strong."
VII. The power of inflicting the punishment, subservient to this end, is allowed by the law of nature to any one of competent judgment, and not implicated in similar or equal offences. This is evident as far as verbal reproof goes, from the maxim of Plautus, that "to bestow merited reproof upon a friend is useful, upon certain occasions, though by no means a grateful office." But in all kinds of constraint and compulsion, the difference made between the persons, who are allowed, and who are not allowed to exercise it is no appointment of natural law, but one of the positive institutions of the civil law. For no such natural distinction could be made, any farther than that reason would intrust parents with the227 peculiar use of such an authority, in consideration of their affection. But laws, in order to avoid animosities, have, with respect to the authority of punishing, passed over the common kindred subsisting among mankind, and confined it to the nearest degrees of relation: as may be seen in many records, and particularly in the code of Justinian, under the title of the POWER OF RELATIVES TO CORRECT IN ORDER TO REFORM OFFENDERS. And Cyrus, in the v. book and viii. chapter of Xenophon's history of the Expedition, addresses the soldiers to the following purport, "If I punish any one for his good, I am willing to submit to justice; but would it not be equally reasonable that parents and masters should submit to justice, for having corrected children, or the Surgeon be responsible for having used the incision-knife, where the patient's case required it?"
VII. The ability to administer punishment for this purpose is granted by natural law to anyone with good judgment who is not involved in similar offenses. This is clear in terms of verbal criticism, as indicated by the saying of Plautus that "giving rightful criticism to a friend can be helpful on certain occasions, even if it’s not a popular task." However, when it comes to any form of constraint or compulsion, the distinction between who can and cannot exercise this power is not a matter of natural law, but rather a result of civil law regulations. No natural difference could be established beyond the idea that reason allows parents to have this authority due to their affection. But to prevent conflicts, laws have limited the authority to punish to close relatives, as seen in various legal records, particularly in the code of Justinian under the title of the POWER OF RELATIVES TO INTERVENE TO REFORM OFFENDERS. In the fifth book and eighth chapter of Xenophon's history of the Expedition, Cyrus addresses the soldiers, saying, "If I punish someone for their own good, I'm willing to face justice for it; but shouldn't it also be fair that parents and masters face consequences for correcting their children, or that a surgeon be held accountable for using a scalpel when it was necessary for the patient?"
But this kind of corrective punishment does not extend to death, which cannot be considered, as a benefit in itself, except INDIRECTLY and BY WAY OF REDUCTION, as it is called by Logicians, who, in order to confirm negatives, reduce them to things of an opposite kind. Thus, in Mark xiv. 21, when our Saviour says, that it were better for some, they had never been born, so, for incurable dispositions, it is better, that is would be a less evil, to die than to live; since it is certain that by living they will grow worse. Plutarch calls such men a pest to others, but the greatest pest to themselves. Galen says that capital punishments are inflicted to prevent men from doing harm by a longer course of iniquity, and to deter others by the fear of punishment, adding that it is better men should die, when they have souls so infected with evil, as to be incurable.
But this type of corrective punishment doesn't extend to death, which can't be seen as a benefit in itself, except INDIRECTLY and As a result of reduction, as Logicians say, who confirm negatives by reducing them to opposing things. So, in Mark 14:21, when our Savior says that it would be better for some if they had never been born, it's similar for incurable conditions—it's better, or less bad, to die than to live, since it's clear that they will only worsen by living. Plutarch refers to such people as a plague to others, but the biggest plague to themselves. Galen argues that capital punishment is imposed to prevent people from doing harm through a longer path of wrongdoing and to deter others through fear of punishment, claiming that it's better for people to die when their souls are so corrupted by evil that they can't be cured.
There are some, who think that these are the persons meant by the Apostle John, who describes them as sinning a sin unto death. But as their arguments are not satisfactory, charity requires that no one should be deemed incorrigible, except upon the clearest grounds. So that punishment with such an end in view can only be inflicted for important causes.
There are some who believe that these are the people referred to by the Apostle John, who describes them as committing a sin that leads to death. However, since their arguments are not convincing, kindness dictates that no one should be considered beyond redemption, except for the clearest reasons. Therefore, punishment aimed at this outcome should only be imposed for significant reasons.
VIII. The benefit accruing to an injured person from the punishment of an offender consists in his being secured in future against a recurrence of the same injury from that offender, or from others. There are three ways of preventing this recurrence—by removing the offender—by depriving him of the power of doing harm,228 or lastly by compelling him to better habits of thought or action, which is the reformation produced by the punishment already spoken of. It is not every kind of punishment, which can produce such effects; it must be open and conspicuous, to operate as an example, that may deter others from the commission of the same crimes. A vindictive punishment, inflicted by an injured individual, or by any other person, when it is restrained by bounds and limitations of this kind, has nothing unlawful in it considering the law of nature by itself, apart from all human and divine institutions, and every adventitious circumstance, that may create a deviation from the primitive dictates of nature. We have said that it may be inflicted by any other individual, as well as by the injured person: for it is conformable to nature, that one man should assist another. But as our judgment is apt to be biassed by our affections, in cases, where our interest is concerned; since the formation of families into states, judges have been appointed, and invested with the power of punishing the guilty, whereby the natural liberty of personal redress, originally allowed to individuals, was abolished, or at least abridged. And it is only in places, on the seas for instance, where no judicial remedy can be obtained, that this natural liberty continues in force. There is a circumstance related of Julius Caesar, applicable to this subject. While he was only in a private station, being taken prisoner by some pirates, after he had redeemed himself by a sum of money, he applied to the proconsul for redress. But his application being neglected, he fitted out a certain number of ships, attacked and defeated the pirates, and ordered them all to be crucified.
VIII. The benefit an injured person gets from punishing an offender is that they’re protected in the future from experiencing the same harm from that offender or from others. There are three ways to prevent this from happening again—by removing the offender, by taking away their ability to cause harm,228 or by forcing them to develop better habits of thought or behavior, which is the reformation that punishment is meant to achieve. Not every kind of punishment can create these effects; it must be noticeable and clear to serve as a warning, deterring others from committing similar crimes. A retaliatory punishment, inflicted by the victim or anyone else, when limited in scope, isn’t considered unlawful according to the law of nature alone, independent of all human and divine institutions, and any other circumstances that might lead to a departure from the basic principles of nature. We’ve mentioned that it can be carried out by anyone, not just the victim: it’s natural for one person to help another. But since our judgment can be swayed by our feelings when our interests are involved, states have established judges who are granted the power to punish offenders, which has done away with, or at least limited, the natural right to personal revenge previously held by individuals. This natural right still exists only in places like the seas where there is no judicial remedy available. There’s an account of Julius Caesar that relates to this topic. While he was still a private citizen, he was captured by pirates, and after paying a ransom to free himself, he sought help from the proconsul for justice. When his request was ignored, he outfitted some ships, attacked the pirates, defeated them, and ordered that they all be crucified.
The practice of private individuals, exercising punishment, was the origin of single combats, so familiar to the Germans before the introduction of Christianity, and not yet sufficiently laid aside. We are informed by Velleius Paterculus, in his second book, that the Germans were surprised to see the forms of Roman jurisprudence, and those disputes, which they themselves decided by the sword, settled by law. By the Jewish law, the nearest in blood to the deceased were allowed to kill a murderer, if taken beyond the places of refuge. And the Jewish interpreters observe, that in GENERAL the infliction of punishment, as a retaliation for murder, it intrusted to no hand, but that of the judge: as it is difficult for an individual in229 his own case to moderate his resentment. The same custom of allowing individuals to avenge their own wrongs prevailed among the ancient Greeks, as we find from the words of Theoclymenes, in Homer's Odyssey. But it prevailed most in countries, where public courts of justice were not established. From hence St. Augustin defines those wars to be just, which are intended to avenge injuries. And Plato, in his twelfth book ON A COMMONWEALTH, justifies the prolongation of hostilities, till the aggressor is reduced to submit to just, and equitable terms.
The practice of individuals taking punishment into their own hands was the origin of single combats, which were common among the Germans before Christianity arrived and still hadn't completely faded away. Velleius Paterculus tells us in his second book that the Germans were surprised to see how Roman law handled disputes, which they settled themselves with swords. According to Jewish law, relatives of a deceased person were allowed to kill a murderer if he was caught outside designated places of refuge. Jewish scholars note that, in general, the responsibility for punishing murderers was not left to individuals but was reserved for judges, since it’s hard for someone to keep their emotions in check in a personal situation. The same practice of allowing personal vengeance existed among the ancient Greeks, as illustrated by Theoclymenes in Homer's Odyssey. This was especially common in regions without public courts. This is why St. Augustine defines wars intended to avenge wrongs as just. And Plato, in his twelfth book ON A COMMONWEALTH, supports continuing hostilities until the aggressor agrees to fair and just terms.
IX. General utility which was considered as the third end proposed by punishment, may be divided into the same number of parts, as the benefit accruing from thence to individuals. For these are the objects in view, either to prevent the individual, who has injured one person, from doing injury to others: an object which can be accomplished only by removing the offender, disarming him of the means of farther injury, or by reforming him: or it may be inflicted to deter others from being allured, by an example of impunity, to commit acts of molestation or enmity. And the infliction of punishment, for such reasons, is a RIGHT granted by the law of nature to every individual. Upon this principle, Plutarch observes in the life of Pelopidas, that good men are designed by nature for the office of perpetual magistracy, and superiority belongs to those, in whom the characters of truth and justice unite.
IX. General utility, which is considered the third purpose of punishment, can be divided into the same number of parts as the benefits that result for individuals. The goals here are either to prevent the individual who has harmed someone from causing harm to others, which can be achieved only by removing the offender, taking away their means to cause further injury, or by reforming them. Alternatively, punishment may be enforced to deter others from being tempted, by the example of someone getting away with it, from committing acts of harm or hostility. Inflicting punishment for these reasons is a RIGHT granted by the law of nature to every person. Based on this idea, Plutarch notes in the life of Pelopidas that good people are naturally suited for the role of everlasting magistrates, and those who embody truth and justice hold a superior status.
But as it requires a painful degree of patience to examine into facts, and no inconsiderable share of skill and equity to affix the extent of punishments; in order to prevent quarrels from arising through the presuming conceit, which every man entertains of his own wisdom, and to which others are averse to yield; in all well regulated communities, it has been usual to select for the tribunals of justice those, who were deemed worthy of such honour, or likely to become so, from their integrity and wisdom. Democritus has said, there would have been no occasion for laws to prevent every man from living according to his own humour, if one had not done injury to another. For envy was the origin of strife. But as we have just observed, that it happens, in the case of revenge, so in this kind of punishment, inflicted for the sake of example, there are traces and remains of ancient law, in those places, and among those persons, that are subject to no230 CIVIL jurisdiction; and in certain other cases besides. Thus any Hebrew, according to the customs of that people, if he should turn away from God, or from the law of God, or should seduce others to false worship, might immediately be put to death by any one whatsoever. The Hebrews call that an act of ZEAL, which was first done by Phinehas, and which afterwards became a custom. Thus Mattathias slew a Jew, who was polluting himself with Grecian rites. In the same manner, in the book commonly called the third book of Maccabees, it is related that three hundred other Jews were put to death by their own countrymen. Nor could any other pretext be assigned for stoning Stephen, and conspiring against Paul. Philo, and Josephus abound in instances of this kind. There are many countries where we may trace the remains of primitive law, in the plenary power allowed to masters over their slaves, and to parents over their children, extending even to inflict the punishment of death. So the Ephori of Sparta might put a citizen to death without the formality of trial. From what has been said, it is easy to infer what punishment the law of nature authorises, and how far it has remained in force.
But it takes a lot of patience to look into facts, and a considerable amount of skill and fairness to determine the appropriate punishments. To avoid conflicts that often arise from people's overconfidence in their own judgment, which others are reluctant to accept, it has been common in well-organized societies to choose those deemed worthy or likely to earn respect in their roles as judges based on their integrity and wisdom. Democritus noted that there wouldn’t be a need for laws to stop everyone from behaving as they please if no one wronged anyone else. Envy is the root of strife. As we've mentioned, similar to the case of revenge, in the case of punishment given as an example, there are remnants of ancient law in places and among groups that fall outside any civil jurisdiction, as well as in other scenarios. For instance, any Hebrew, by their customs, who turns away from God or tries to lead others into false worship could be executed by anyone. The Hebrews refer to this as an act of zeal, originally carried out by Phinehas, which later became a tradition. Similarly, Mattathias killed a Jew who was defiling himself with Greek practices. In addition, the book called the Third Book of Maccabees recounts that three hundred other Jews were put to death by their fellow countrymen. There was no other reason for stoning Stephen or conspiring against Paul. Philo and Josephus have many examples of this kind. In many places, we can see traces of ancient law in the absolute power given to masters over their slaves and parents over their children, even extending to the death penalty. For example, the Ephori of Sparta could execute a citizen without a trial. From all this, it’s clear what punishments natural law permits and how much of it still applies today.
X. We come now to consider whether the law of the Gospel has confined that liberty within closer bounds. It has been observed in another part of this treatise, that it is not surprising that some things, which are allowed by natural and civil law, should be forbidden by the divine law, owing to its great perfection, and the superiority of its rewards over any thing that human nature can bestow. To the attainment of which it is not unreasonable that virtues should be required, far exceeding the simple precepts of nature. Those kinds of correction that leave neither any mark of infamy, nor any permanent injury, but are suited to the age, or other circumstances of the sufferer, if inflicted by those, who derive such a permission from human laws, for instance by parents, guardians, or masters, contain nothing repugnant to the precepts of the Gospel, as may be clearly understood from the nature of the thing itself. For they are remedies to the mind no less harmless than medicines ungrateful to the palate are to the body. But as to revenge the case is different. For the infliction of punishment, only to gratify resentment, so far from being conformable to the Gospel, has been shewn above to be repugnant even to the law of nature.
X. Now let's discuss whether the law of the Gospel has restricted that liberty even further. It's been noted elsewhere in this treatise that it’s not surprising if some actions allowed by natural and civil law are prohibited by divine law, due to its perfect nature and the greater rewards it offers compared to anything humanity can provide. To achieve these rewards, it makes sense that virtues should be expected that go far beyond the basic principles of nature. The types of correction that do not leave any marks of disgrace or cause permanent harm, but are appropriate for the age or situation of the person receiving them, when carried out by those who have the authority to do so under human laws, like parents, guardians, or masters, are not contrary to the teachings of the Gospel, as can be clearly understood from their very nature. They serve as remedies for the mind that are as harmless as unpleasant-tasting medicines are for the body. However, when it comes to revenge, the situation is different. Inflicting punishment solely to satisfy anger is not aligned with the Gospel and has been shown to be contrary to the law of nature.
231 The Jewish law indeed not only forbids the cherishing of hatred against a neighbour, that is, one of the same country and people, but requires certain common acts of kindness to be bestowed even upon enemies of that description. The Gospel therefore, comprehending all men under the appellation of neighbour, not only forbids us to hurt our enemies, but commands us to do them good; a commandment clearly stated in the Gospel of St. Matthew. Yet the law permitted the Jews to seek revenge for injuries of a more grievous kind, not with their own hands, but by appealing to the judge. But Christ does not give us the same permission, as appears from that opposition which he makes between the permissions of former times, and those of his own law. "You have heard that it was said an eye for an eye—but I say unto you, love your enemies, etc."
231 Jewish law not only forbids holding onto hatred for a neighbor, meaning someone from the same country and community, but also requires that we show kindness even to those who are considered enemies. The Gospel, therefore, includes everyone as a neighbor, not only prohibiting us from harming our enemies but also instructing us to treat them well; this clear command can be found in the Gospel of St. Matthew. However, the law allowed Jews to seek revenge for serious injuries, not by taking matters into their own hands, but by going to a judge. In contrast, Christ does not give us that same option, which is evident from how he contrasts the allowances of the past with those of his own teachings. "You have heard that it was said, an eye for an eye—but I say to you, love your enemies, etc."
For although what follows relates peculiarly to the repelling of injury, and, in some measure, abridges this permission, yet it passes a much greater censure upon revenge, rejecting it as an indulgence suitable only to a more imperfect, and carnal state.
For even though what comes next specifically deals with preventing harm, and somewhat limits this allowance, it also issues a much stronger criticism of revenge, dismissing it as a behavior appropriate only for a less developed and more base state.
To inflict punishment by way of retaliation was disapproved of even by those of the Jews, who were distinguished for their worth and wisdom; because they regarded not only the LETTER, but the PURPOSE and SPIRIT of the law. This appears from Philo, in whose writings we find the Jews of Alexandria, upon the calamity of Flaccus, their persecutor, addressing themselves to God in the following language, "We do not rejoice, O Lord, in the calamity or punishment of an enemy, being taught by thy holy laws to feel for the miseries of men." And in this case we may apply that general command given by Christ to forgive all who have offended or injured us, that is, neither to do, nor to wish them evil, through resentment of the evil they have done to us. But what can be said of revenge, not as regarding the past, but as providing security for the future? Here too Christ requires of his followers the same disposition to pardon injuries, particularly, if the offender shews any probable signs of repentance. Luke xvii. 3. Eph. iv. 32. Col. iii. 13. In those passages a full remission is intended, such a remission as restores the offender to his former situation of friendship or confidence: and consequently nothing can be required of him under the name of punishment. Besides, if there were no such marks of repentance, the reparation232 of a loss is not to be pursued with too much rigour; a doctrine inferred from the precept of Christ enjoining us to give up the garment along with the cloak.
To punish someone out of revenge was frowned upon, even by the wise and respected Jews. They focused not just on the MESSAGE but also on the GOAL and SPIRIT of the law. This is evident in Philo's writings, where the Jews of Alexandria, in response to the misfortunes facing their persecutor Flaccus, spoke to God saying, "We do not take pleasure, O Lord, in the suffering or punishment of our enemy, as your holy laws teach us to empathize with the suffering of others." In this context, we can refer to the general command given by Christ to forgive everyone who has wronged us, meaning we should neither commit nor wish harm upon them out of bitterness for what they’ve done to us. But what about revenge, not just as a response to the past, but as a way to ensure future safety? In this case, Christ still demands that his followers maintain a forgiving attitude, especially if the wrongdoer shows genuine signs of remorse. Luke xvii. 3. Eph. iv. 32. Col. iii. 13. In these passages, a complete forgiveness is meant—one that restores the wrongdoer to their previous state of friendship or trust, meaning nothing should be expected of them in terms of punishment. Furthermore, if there are no signs of repentance, the compensation for a loss should not be pursued too harshly, a principle that comes from Christ’s teaching to give your shirt along with your coat.
But if it is likely that connivance at an offence will be attended with imminent inconvenience and even danger to ourselves, we should be contented with such securities as may be effectual, and at the same time operate with as little prejudice as possible to the offender. For even among the Jews, the law of retaliation was not in use, as we are informed by Josephus, and other writers of that nation. But in addition to the expence incurred, which the law treats of as a separate point, the injured party usually received a pecuniary fine instead of retaliation; the repayment of expences being considered simply as a restitution, and not a penalty.
But if it seems likely that ignoring an offense will lead to serious trouble and even put us in danger, we should settle for protections that are effective while causing as little harm as possible to the offender. Even among the Jews, the law of retaliation wasn’t practiced, as noted by Josephus and other writers from that culture. Besides the expenses involved, which the law addresses as a separate issue, the person harmed typically received a monetary fine instead of revenge; covering the expenses was seen merely as a way to restore what was lost, not as a punishment.
It remains now to consider punishment, as providing for the PUBLIC and not INDIVIDUAL security, which is accomplished either by removing the guilty person out of the way or by restraining him from doing farther mischief, or by deterring others through the severity of example, none of which means it has been clearly proved were abolished by Christ; for in giving his precepts he affirmed that he destroyed no part of the law. The law of Moses indeed, which in these respects was to remain in force as long as the Jewish Polity existed, strictly enjoined magistrates to punish murder and other similar crimes. But if the precepts of Christ could exist in conjunction with the law of Moses, as far as it imposed capital punishments, surely they may exist in conjunction with human laws, which in this respect are but an imitation of the divine laws.
It’s now time to discuss punishment, which serves the PUBLIC rather than PERSON safety. This is achieved either by removing the guilty person from the situation, preventing them from causing further harm, or by deterring others through the severity of their example. None of these means have been clearly disproven as abolished by Christ, who stated that he did not eliminate any part of the law. The law of Moses, which was intended to remain in effect as long as the Jewish state existed, strictly required magistrates to punish murder and similar offenses. If Christ's teachings could coexist with the law of Moses regarding capital punishment, then they can surely coexist with human laws, which are merely a reflection of divine laws.
XI. Some, in support of an opposite opinion, allege the supreme mercy of God, as it is displayed in the new covenant, and which is given as an example for men, and for magistrates, in particular, to follow, who, in the exercise of authority, execute the laws of the Deity. This opinion may in some measure be true, but not to that extent, which the authors of it intend. For the great mercy of God displayed in the new covenant has a peculiar reference to offences against the primitive law, or even against the law of Moses, before the time that men had received a knowledge of the Gospel. For offences committed after the promulgation of the Gospel, especially if they are accompanied with a hardened obstinacy, are treated with much severer judgments than233 any that were declared by Moses. For God punishes sins of that kind not only in a future state, but in the present life. But for sins of that kind, to obtain the act of mercy and indulgence, the offender must inflict punishment upon himself, not in a slight or trivial manner, but with a heartfelt sorrow, and resolution to sin no more.
XI. Some people, supporting a different viewpoint, argue that God's supreme mercy, as shown in the new covenant, serves as an example for everyone, especially for leaders, to follow when enforcing God's laws. This idea may hold some truth, but not to the extent that its proponents suggest. God's immense mercy in the new covenant specifically addresses offenses against the original law or even against the Mosaic law, before people were aware of the Gospel. Offenses committed after the Gospel has been revealed, particularly if accompanied by stubbornness, are met with much harsher judgments than any declared by Moses. God punishes these sins not only in the afterlife but also in our current lives. However, for such sins, to receive mercy and forgiveness, the wrongdoer must genuinely punish themselves, not in a minor or superficial way, but with deep remorse and a firm commitment to not sin again.
In the same manner it is maintained that if men are actuated by repentance, they are ENTITLED to impunity. We do not say that men are never actuated by sincere repentance; but it is not every kind of avowal or acknowledgment, by which God is moved to remit the WHOLE of a punishment, as appears from the case of David. As the supreme judge therefore might dispense with the full penalty of the law, inflicting death, and yet exercise no inconsiderable severity upon offenders, so now he may dispense with the sentence of eternal death, at the same time leaving the sinner to find an early grave by the stroke of some calamity, or by the hand of human justice.
In the same way, it’s argued that if people truly feel remorse, they are Privileged to forgiveness. We’re not saying that people are never genuinely remorseful; however, not every confession or acknowledgment will lead God to completely lift a punishment, as shown in the case of David. Just as the supreme judge can lighten the full penalty of the law, which includes death, while still imposing significant consequences on wrongdoers, he can also waive the sentence of eternal death while allowing the sinner to meet an early end due to some misfortune or the actions of human justice.
XII. and XIII. Another objection made against capital punishments is that such a kind of sentence and execution is cutting off a criminal from all possibility of repentance. But those, who make the objection, must know, that in cases of that kind, venerable and upright judges use the greatest precautions, and suffer no one to be hurried away to execution, without a reasonable time allowed for reflection and deep abhorrence of his crime: a repentance, which though prevented by the interposing hand of death from producing the fruits of righteousness, we have reason to suppose, from the case of the thief pardoned on the cross, may be accepted with God.
XII. and XIII. Another argument against capital punishment is that it completely removes a criminal's chance for repentance. However, those who raise this concern should understand that in such cases, respected and ethical judges take significant precautions and ensure that no one is rushed to execution without sufficient time for reflection and a deep sense of remorse for their crime. This repentance, even if death halts it from resulting in positive actions, may still be accepted by God, as we can infer from the story of the thief who was forgiven on the cross.
But if on the other hand it be said that longer life might have been of more avail to serious repentance, we may observe that, in some cases, the reply of Seneca may be made, that to men of that description death is often the greatest blessing which can be bestowed; for, in the words of Eusebius, their career of wickedness cannot otherwise be shortened, or reformed. These in addition to the preceding arguments in the former part of this treatise may be deemed a sufficient answer to those, who assert that all capital punishments, and even all punishments, without exception, are abolished by the precepts of our Saviour. The Apostle, consigning to234 the office of kings the use of the sword, as an exercise of his divine commission to avenge all wrongs, instructs us to pray for kings, that, as true Christians, in their royal capacity, they may be a protection to the innocent. An end, which even after the introduction of the gospel, could not easily be obtained, owing to the depravity of mankind, if the violence of some were not restrained by the exemplary punishment of others. Such authority is the more necessary, when even in the midst of so many examples and punishments, the lives of the innocent are scarcely secure. There have been indeed, it cannot be denied, happy instances where the sentence of death was changed for that of perpetual labour, a practice, as we are informed by Diodorus, followed by Sabacon, king of Egypt, a prince renowned for his piety. Balsamon observes that the penal laws of Rome, inflicting death, were most of them changed by the Christian emperors of later times, and other kinds of punishment were substituted, that the guilty might receive deeper impressions of repentance, and their punishment operate as a more durable example.
But if it's said that a longer life could have been more helpful for serious repentance, we can point out that, in some cases, Seneca’s reply may apply: for those individuals, death is often the greatest blessing that can be given; because, as Eusebius noted, their path of wickedness cannot otherwise be shortened or transformed. These points, along with the arguments made earlier in this treatise, should be enough to respond to those who claim that all capital punishments, and even all punishments in general, are eliminated by our Savior's teachings. The Apostle, assigning to234 the role of kings the use of the sword, as a part of his divine authority to right all wrongs, tells us to pray for kings, so that, as true Christians, in their royal duties, they may protect the innocent. This goal, even after the gospel was introduced, could not be easily achieved due to human depravity, unless the violence of some is restrained by the severe punishment of others. Such authority is even more necessary when, despite so many examples and punishments, the lives of the innocent are barely secure. Indeed, there have been fortunate cases where a death sentence was commuted to one of perpetual labor, a practice that Diodorus tells us was followed by Sabacon, king of Egypt, a ruler known for his piety. Balsamon notes that the penal laws of Rome, which imposed death, were mostly changed by later Christian emperors, who substituted other forms of punishment so that the guilty might experience deeper repentance and their punishment serve as a more lasting example.
XIV. From what has been said, it may be inferred, how unsafe it is for a private Christian, whether from motives of personal interest, or from those of the public good, to take upon himself the punishment of an offender, and particularly to inflict death. Although, as it has been said before, it may, IN SOME CASES, be allowed by the law of nations. A permission, that has given rise to the laudable practice, prevailing in some countries of furnishing adventurers with public instructions and commissions to chase and capture pirates, wherever they may be found. But those adventurers may be considered as discharging a public duty rather than as acting upon their own authority.
XIV. From what has been said, we can conclude how risky it is for an individual Christian, whether motivated by personal gain or public good, to take on the punishment of a wrongdoer, especially to impose death. Although, as mentioned before, it may, In some instances, be allowed by international law. This permission has led to the commendable practice, existing in some countries, of giving adventurers official instructions and licenses to pursue and capture pirates wherever they are found. However, these adventurers should be seen as fulfilling a public duty rather than acting on their own authority.
XV. A custom not unlike to which prevails in many places, of not allowing individuals to bring criminal charges against others at their own pleasure: that office belonging to persons invested with public authority to undertake it. So that no one can contribute towards shedding the blood of another, but as an act of necessary duty. In reference to this custom, a canon of the council of Eliberis excluded from the communion any believer who had been instrumental in causing the proscription or death of another.
XV. There's a common practice, similar to what exists in many areas, where individuals can't just bring criminal charges against others whenever they want; that responsibility belongs to those in public office. This means no one can be involved in causing harm to another person except as a matter of necessary duty. According to this practice, a canon from the council of Eliberis barred from communion any believer who had played a role in causing the punishment or death of another.
235 XVIII.54 It is proper now to consider whether all wicked acts are of that kind, which are punishable by human laws. In reply to which we may answer that they certainly are not.—In the first place, mere acts of the mind, or criminal intentions, though by subsequent confession, or some other accident, they may come to the knowledge of others, are not punishable by human laws. Because, as it was proved in a former part of this treatise, it is not consonant to the law of nature, that INTENTIONS ONLY should give rise to any right, or obligation amongst men. And in this sense the maxim of the Roman law is to be taken, THAT NO ONE DESERVES PUNISHMENT FOR MERE THOUGHTS. Yet this does not prevent intentions, when they have an influence upon the conduct, from being considered as actual deeds, and equally deserving of punishment.
235 XVIII.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ It's time to think about whether all wicked acts are the kind that can be punished by human laws. To that, we can say that they definitely are not. First of all, just thoughts or criminal intentions, even if they come to light later through confession or some other way, aren't punishable by human laws. This is because, as we established earlier in this discussion, it's not in line with the law of nature that JUST INTENTIONS should create any rights or obligations among people. In this regard, we should interpret the Roman law maxim, NO ONE SHOULD BE PUNISHED FOR JUST HAVING THOUGHTS.. However, this doesn’t stop intentions that influence behavior from being seen as actual acts, and equally deserving of punishment.
XIX. In the second place, even outward acts, cannot be punished by men where they arise through some inevitable infirmity of human nature. For although there can be no sin, except where there is a freedom of will, yet to be at all times free from all infirmity and sin, is more than can be expected from the condition of man. So that Sopater, Hierocles and Seneca among the Philosophers; Philo among the Jews; Thucydides among the historians; and innumerable writers among Christians have maintained that sin is interwoven with our very nature. Nay indeed, a doubt may be entertained whether such acts can rightly and properly be called sins. For though seeming to be voluntary actions, they will be found, when minutely considered, not to proceed from a free and deliberate exercise of the will. "Laws, says Plutarch in the life of Solon, should be framed to suit possible cases, the legislator may obtain every beneficial end by punishing a few offenders, where the indiscriminate punishment of multitudes would be attended with no good effect."
XIX. Secondly, even outward actions cannot be punished by people when they arise from an unavoidable flaw in human nature. While there can be no sin without the freedom of will, it's unrealistic to expect anyone to be completely free from all flaws and sin, given the human condition. Philosophers like Sopater, Hierocles, and Seneca, as well as Philo among the Jews, and Thucydides among historians, and countless Christian writers, have argued that sin is deeply rooted in our very nature. Indeed, one might question whether such actions can truly be labeled as sins. Although they may appear to be voluntary actions, upon closer examination, they may not stem from a free and conscious exercise of will. "Laws, says Plutarch in the life of Solon, should be designed to address possible situations; a legislator can achieve all beneficial outcomes by punishing a few offenders, whereas punishing large numbers indiscriminately would yield no positive results."
There are some actions, which though not imputable to human nature itself, are inevitable consequences of the influence of bodily habits on the mind. Actions like these are punishable in human courts, owing to the criminality of voluntary contracting, or of not sufficiently guarding against, those habits.
There are certain actions that, while not directly caused by human nature, are unavoidable results of how physical habits affect the mind. Actions like these can be punished in human courts because of the wrongdoing involved in willingly engaging in them or failing to adequately protect against those habits.
236 XX. In the third place, human courts of justice cannot take cognizance of those offences, which neither directly nor indirectly, affect the public or individuals. For no reason can be assigned, why such offences should not be left to the judgments of God, whose all-seeing eye must know them, whose equity will weigh them, and whose power can punish them. It would be unnecessary therefore, and presumptuous in human tribunals to assume such decisions. However we must except from this rule those corrective kinds of punishment, designed for the reformation of offenders, even where their conduct is no way injurious to others.
236 XX. First of all, human courts can’t deal with offenses that don’t directly or indirectly impact the public or individuals. There’s no good reason why such offenses shouldn’t be left to God’s judgment, who sees everything, understands justice, and has the power to punish. It would be unnecessary and arrogant for human courts to make such judgments. However, we should make an exception for forms of punishment meant to reform offenders, even if their actions don’t harm anyone else.
Neither are those actions punishable, which are directly opposite to the virtues of compassion, liberality, or gratitude, in the performance of which virtues natural justice allows of no compulsion.
Neither are those actions punishable that are directly opposed to the virtues of compassion, generosity, or gratitude, in the practice of which virtues natural justice does not permit any coercion.
XXI. The point, necessarily to be considered next, is the opinion, whether it is lawful some times to grant pardon. For the Stoics maintain it not to be lawful, as may be seen from a fragment in Stobaeus, under the title of Magistracy, from Cicero's speech for Murena, and towards the conclusion of Seneca's books on Clemency; but their arguments are fallacious, and unsubstantial. They say "that pardon is the remission of a penalty, that OUGHT to be paid; but a wise man does every thing, which he OUGHT to do." Here the fallacy lies in the use of the word OUGHT. For if it means that an offender owes a penalty, that is, that he may be punished without injustice, it will not necessarily follow that the person who does not punish him, is doing what he ought not to do. But if the word be taken to imply that a good man, or a wise man, ought at all events, to exact the penalty, it may be observed in reply that THIS does not always happen, and therefore, in this sense, the penalty or punishment may be considered, not as a debt, but only a permission. And this will hold good, both before and after the establishment of penal laws.
XXI. The next point to consider is whether it's ever lawful to grant a pardon. The Stoics argue that it isn't lawful, as shown in a fragment from Stobaeus, in Cicero's speech for Murena, and towards the end of Seneca's books on Clemency; however, their arguments are flawed and weak. They say that "pardon is the cancellation of a penalty that should be paid; but a wise person does everything they should." The flaw here is in the use of the word "should." If it means that an offender owes a penalty, meaning they can be punished without wrongdoing, it doesn't necessarily follow that someone who chooses not to punish them is doing something wrong. But if "should" means that a good or wise person must enforce the penalty, it can be argued in response that this isn't always the case, so in this sense, the penalty or punishment can be seen not as a debt but merely as an option. This holds true both before and after the establishment of penal laws.
XXII. Before the establishment of penal laws, punishment, beyond all doubt, might be inflicted; because by the law of nature, every offender made himself subject to punishment; but it is not a natural and inevitable consequence of its being lawful, that it should be enforced. For this depends upon the connection between the ends, for which punishments were established, and the punishments themselves. If the ends proposed therefore are237 not immediately necessary, in a moral point of view, or if other ends of a different kind, but not less wise and salutary should be devised, or that the ends originally designed may be obtained by some other means, in all these cases, the right of punishment may be saved, there being no immediate occasion to inflict it. Thus for instance, where an offence is known to very few, there can be no immediate occasion for a public punishment, by way of exemplary exposure, which in some cases might be even injurious to society rather than productive of advantage. Upon which Cicero in a letter to his brother makes a pertinent remark, respecting one Zeuxis, observing, that "had he once been brought into court, he could not have been released, but there was no necessity that a search should be made for him, in order to bring him to trial."—In the next place the right and end of punishment may be dispensed with, where a man's own services, or those of his family are sufficient to outweigh the consideration of his offences. "For, in the words of Seneca, an act of kindness eclipses the fault of an injury."—And in the last place, where reproof operates upon an offender, as a means of correction and amendment, or where the injured party is satisfied with an acknowledgment of the offence, the occasion for punishment is done away. It was this motive to clemency, which the son of David had in view, where he observes that it behoves the righteous to be merciful. For as all punishment, especially of the more severe cast, has in it some thing, which tho' not repugnant to justice, is at variance, at least, with charity, reason easily suffers us to forbear inflicting it, unless that forbearance is opposed by some weightier, juster, and more undeniable motive of charity.
XXII. Before the creation of penal laws, punishment could definitely be imposed; because according to the law of nature, every offender subjected themselves to punishment. However, it’s not a natural and inevitable result of it being legal that punishment should be enforced. This depends on the relationship between the purposes for which punishments were established and the punishments themselves. If the proposed goals are not immediately necessary from a moral standpoint, or if other equally wise and beneficial goals could be devised, or if the original goals could be achieved through different means, in all these cases, the right to punish may be preserved, since there’s no immediate need to impose it. For example, when an offense is known to very few people, there’s no urgent need for public punishment as a form of exemplary exposure, which could even harm society rather than benefit it. Cicero, in a letter to his brother, makes a relevant point about Zeuxis, stating that "if he had ever been taken to court, he couldn’t have been released, but there was no need to search for him to bring him to trial." Additionally, the right and purpose of punishment may be waived when a person’s own contributions, or those of their family, are enough to outweigh the significance of their offenses. "For, in the words of Seneca, an act of kindness overshadows the fault of an injury." Lastly, if reproof serves as a means of correction and improvement for an offender, or if the victim is satisfied with an acknowledgment of the wrongdoing, there is no longer a reason to punish. This motive for mercy was what King David had in mind when he noted that it is important for the righteous to be merciful. Since all punishment, especially the more severe types, contains elements that, while not contradictory to justice, are at least contrary to charity, reason readily allows us to refrain from inflicting it unless that refraining is countered by a stronger, more justifiable, and undeniable motive of charity.
XXIII. Cases may occur where it is absolutely necessary to inflict punishment, as upon notorious, and atrocious criminals, or where it is for the public good, to dispense with that severity, or where the judicial authorities may use their own discretion in mitigating or enforcing the sentence of the law. Upon which Seneca pertinently remarks, that the exercise of lenity should always be an act of free deliberation. As to the disputes of the Stoics on these points, they are, in the opinion of Cicero and others, debates upon words rather than things: consequently they are less worthy of philosophical contemplation.
XXIII. There are situations where it's absolutely necessary to impose punishment, like in the case of notorious and heinous criminals, or when it's for the public good to be less harsh, or when judges have the discretion to lighten or enforce the legal sentence. Seneca wisely points out that showing mercy should always be a thoughtful choice. Regarding the Stoics' arguments on these matters, Cicero and others believe they are more about semantics than substance, making them less deserving of serious philosophical consideration.
238 XXIV. There seems to be a greater difficulty in deciding what is to be done, subsequently to the establishment of penal laws; because a legislator is bound, in some measure, by his own laws. But this, as it was proved in a former part of this treatise, is only true with respect to the legislator, in his individual capacity, as a private member of the state, but not in his public character, in which he represents the whole Majesty and Authority of the state itself. As such, he can entirely repeal the law: for it is the nature of all human laws, to depend upon the will of the maker, not only for their origin, but also for their duration. Yet a lawgiver ought not, upon trivial grounds, to repeal a statute, for, in so doing he would be acting against the rules of sovereign justice. But as the legislator has power to repeal the whole of a law, so in the case of some particular person, or individual action, he may relax its rigour, allowing it to remain in other respects, as it stood before. As an example of this, the actions of the Deity may be cited, who, according to the testimony of Lactantius, in enacting his laws, did not deprive himself of the exercise of his mercy, to grant pardons. "The Emperor, says Augustin, may recall his sentence, pardon and release a criminal; because, as he further explains it, the person who has power to make laws, is not INVARIABLY bound to observe them." Yet this privilege of departing from the letter must never be used but for the most important reasons. Although such reasons cannot be precisely defined, yet it is certain that, since the establishment of civil law, more weighty ones are required to authorise such pardons, than before that period. Because punishments have derived an additional sanction from the authority of the law, which ought to be respected and observed.
238 XXIV. It seems more challenging to decide what to do after establishing penal laws because a legislator is somewhat bound by their own laws. However, as was demonstrated earlier in this text, this holds true only for the legislator in their personal role as a private citizen, not in their capacity as a public representative of the entire state's authority. In that role, they can entirely repeal the law because all human laws depend on the will of their creator not just for their origin but also for their continuation. Still, a lawmaker shouldn't repeal a statute for minor reasons, as that would go against the principles of sovereign justice. Yet, while a legislator has the power to repeal an entire law, they can also ease its strictness for a specific person or unique situation while keeping the law intact in other respects. An example of this is seen in the actions of the Deity, who, as Lactantius pointed out, did not forego the ability to exercise mercy by granting pardons when enacting laws. "The Emperor," says Augustin, "can reverse his sentence, pardon, and release a criminal; because," as he further explains, "the one who has the power to make laws is not ALWAYS bound to follow them." However, this privilege of deviating from the letter of the law should only be used for the most significant reasons. While these reasons can't be precisely defined, it’s clear that since the establishment of civil law, more compelling reasons are needed to justify such pardons than were required before that time. This is because punishments have gained additional credibility from the law's authority, which should be upheld and respected.
XXV. The reasons for releasing any one from the penalties of the law, are of two kinds, either internal or external.
XXV. The reasons for freeing someone from the penalties of the law fall into two categories: internal or external.
An internal reason, to justify a departure from the sentence of the law, must be one, where the punishment is severe when compared with the offence.
An internal reason for justifying a deviation from the law's sentence must be one where the punishment is harsh compared to the offense.
XXVI. An external reason is one arising from some favourable circumstance in the character of the offender, or some fair hopes that may be entertained of his future conduct. And these reasons will have the most weight in cases, where the particular motives for making the law cease to operate. For although a general reason,239 unopposed by any other of a weightier kind, may sufficiently authorise the enaction of a law; yet where the peculiar reason, for which that law was made, has ceased to exist, the relaxation of it, or even a total dispensation will be attended with less danger to the universal authority of law in general.
XXVI. An external reason is one that comes from some positive aspect of the offender’s character or from hopeful expectations about their future behavior. These reasons will carry more weight in situations where the specific reasons for the law no longer apply. Because even though a general reason,239 not challenged by any stronger reasons, can justify creating a law; when the specific reason that law was based on is no longer relevant, relaxing or even completely disregarding it will pose less risk to the overall authority of law.
Such a dispensation indeed is most allowable, where an offence has been committed through ignorance, though the party so committing it is not entirely free from blame, or through some invincible infirmity of mind, in all which cases, a Christian ruler will have an eye to the example of God, who, under the old covenant, appointed many such offences to be atoned for by certain expiatory offerings: Levit. iv. and v.: and, in the New Testament, he has expressly declared his intention to pardon such offences, upon due repentance. Luke xxiii. 34.; Heb. iv. 15. and v. 2.; 1 Tim. 1. 13. And Chrysostom observes, that Theodosius, impressed with those words of our Saviour, "Father, forgive them, for they know not what they do," was led to grant a pardon to the people of Antioch.
Such a situation is certainly acceptable when an offense has happened out of ignorance, even though the person who committed it isn’t completely blameless, or due to some overwhelming mental weakness. In these cases, a Christian leader will look to God’s example, who, under the old covenant, set up many offenses to be atoned for with specific offerings: Levit. iv. and v. In the New Testament, He clearly stated His intention to forgive such offenses when genuine repentance occurs. Luke xxiii. 34; Heb. iv. 15 and v. 2; 1 Tim. 1. 13. Chrysostom points out that Theodosius, moved by our Savior’s words, “Father, forgive them, for they know not what they do,” was inspired to forgive the people of Antioch.
XXVII. And hence it is evident, how mistaken Ferdinand Vasquez is in his judgment, when he maintains that there can be no just reason for dispensing with a law, that is, for releasing any one from its obligations, except where the lawgiver, upon being consulted, expressly declares that he never intended it should be observed to its full extent. For he does not make the proper distinction between an equitable interpretation, and the entire relaxation of a law. For which reason, in another place, he reproves Thomas, and Sotus, because they say that a law is binding although the particular reason of its being made may have ceased, as if they supposed that the mere letter of the law was the source of its obligation, an opinion which they never did entertain. So far from every relaxation coming under the idea of equity, properly so called; those relaxations may be freely granted or refused, which could not be done in matters of equity, to which even acts of charity or those of reasonable policy do not strictly belong. For there is a great difference between the repeal of a law upon fair or urgent grounds, and a legislator's declaring that at the time of passing the law he had not the particular offence or case in contemplation.
XXVII. It's clear how wrong Ferdinand Vasquez is in his opinion when he argues that there can be no valid reason for getting rid of a law, meaning for freeing someone from its requirements, unless the lawmaker, when asked, clearly states that he never intended for it to be fully enforced. He doesn't differentiate between a fair interpretation and completely relaxing a law. That's why, in another instance, he criticizes Thomas and Sotus for saying that a law is still binding even if the specific reason for its creation no longer applies, as if they believed that just the text of the law was what created its obligation, which they never thought. In reality, not every relaxation falls under the category of true equity; those relaxations can be given or denied freely, unlike matters of equity, which don’t strictly include acts of charity or reasonable policy. There is a significant difference between abolishing a law for valid or urgent reasons and a legislator stating that when they passed the law, they did not consider the specific offense or situation.
Having thus far considered the nature of dispensations, we proceed to a review of the merits upon which they may be granted.
Having looked at the nature of dispensations so far, we will now review the merits on which they can be granted.
240 XXVIII. From what has been said above, it appears that in punishments, two things are to be regarded, the offence, and the object for which they are inflicted. It is consonant to justice that no one should receive greater punishment than he deserves; upon which Cicero, in one of his letters, observes, that, "the same moderation, which is commended in all other things, ought to be observed in punishments." Papinian therefore calls punishment an estimation of demerit; but this equality established between crime and punishment, says Demosthenes in his Letter in behalf of the children of Lycurgus, is not the only thing to be considered: the object and intention also of the delinquent must be weighed and taken into the account. But, if care be taken to inflict no more punishment than is due for an offence; it may be greater or less, in proportion to the utility to be derived from thence.
240 XXVIII. Based on what we've discussed, it seems that in punishments, we need to consider two things: the crime and the reason behind the punishment. It's fair that no one should face a harsher punishment than they deserve; as Cicero notes in one of his letters, "the same moderation that is praised in everything else should be applied to punishments." Papinian therefore describes punishment as a measurement of wrongdoing, but this balance between crime and punishment, as Demosthenes points out in his letter advocating for the children of Lycurgus, isn't the only factor to consider: we must also take into account the offender's motives and intentions. However, if we ensure that no more punishment is given than is warranted for an offense, the punishment can be adjusted based on the benefits that can come from it.
XXIX. In examining the different degrees of guilt, we ought to take into the account the motives which impelled the offender to commit the act—the motives, which ought to have restrained him therefrom, and how far he was capable of yielding to either. Scarce any one does a wicked action without some motive, or so far strips himself of the nature of man, as to delight in such acts from pure malignity. Most men are led away by the indulgence of their appetites, which engender sin. Under the name of appetite also may be comprehended the strong desire of avoiding evil, which is the most consonant to nature, and therefore to be reckoned amongst the most laudable of all desires. So that offences committed for the sake of avoiding death, imprisonment, pain, or extreme want are generally deemed the most excusable.
XXIX. When we look at the different levels of guilt, we need to consider the reasons that drove the person to commit the act—those reasons that should have held them back, and how much they were able to give in to either. Hardly anyone does something wrong without some motivation, or completely loses their humanity to enjoy such acts purely out of spite. Most people are led astray by their cravings, which lead to sin. The term "appetite" can also include the strong desire to avoid harm, which is most aligned with our nature and therefore should be counted among the most commendable of all desires. So, offenses committed to avoid death, imprisonment, pain, or extreme need are usually seen as the most forgivable.
Which gave occasion to Demosthenes to say, "that we are justly more exasperated against those, who, abounding in riches, commit evil actions, than against those, who are impelled by want to do the same. Humane judges are always ready to make allowance for necessity: but where wealth is united with injustice, no pretext can be pleaded in excuse." On this score, Polybius excuses the Acarnanians, for having neglected, when threatened with impending danger themselves, to fulfil the terms of a defensive treaty made with the Greeks against the Aetolians.
Which led Demosthenes to say, "we are rightly more upset with those who, being wealthy, commit wrongful acts, than with those who are driven by need to do the same. Compassionate judges are always willing to consider necessity: but when wealth is paired with injustice, no excuse can be accepted." For this reason, Polybius excuses the Acarnanians for neglecting to uphold the terms of a defensive treaty made with the Greeks against the Aetolians when they themselves faced imminent danger.
Besides the desire of avoiding evil there are other desires tending to some good, either real or imaginary.241 Real advantages, considered apart from virtues, and those actions, which have a virtuous tendency, are either such as give delight themselves, or, like abundance of riches, can procure those things, which administer to pleasure. Among advantages purely imaginary, we may reckon that of desiring to excel others, from a spirit of rivalry, rather than from any laudable intention, or the power of gratifying resentments, which the farther they deviate from natural justice the more shocking they are to natural feeling. These appetites the Apostle has described in terms of marked censure, calling them, the "lust of the flesh, the lust of the eye, the pride of life." Here the first member of the sentence expresses the love of pleasure, the second implies the insatiable love of riches, and the third comprehends the pursuit of vain glory, and the desire of revenge.
Besides the desire to avoid evil, there are other desires aimed at some good, whether real or imagined.241 Real benefits, when considered separately from virtues, and those actions that have a virtuous tendency, are either those that bring joy themselves or, like a lot of wealth, can buy things that contribute to pleasure. Among purely imaginary benefits, we might include the desire to outshine others out of rivalry rather than any admirable intention, or the ability to satisfy grudges, which become more repulsive the further they stray from natural justice. The Apostle has described these cravings with significant criticism, referring to them as the "lust of the flesh, the lust of the eye, the pride of life." Here, the first part of the sentence expresses a love for pleasure, the second indicates an insatiable love for wealth, and the third encompasses the pursuit of empty glory and the desire for revenge.
XXX. The very injustice of all offences ought to be a GENERAL motive with men, to restrain them from the commission of them. For at present we are not considering sins of any kind, but those, which extend their consequences beyond the offender himself, and affect others. And injustice is the more heinous and criminal in proportion to the greatness of the injury, which it inflicts.
XXX. The very injustice of all offenses should be a GENERAL reason for people to hold back from committing them. Right now, we're not talking about sins in general, but those that have consequences beyond the offender and impact others. The injustice is more serious and wrong the greater the harm it causes.
In the highest rank of crimes and misdemeanours therefore, we may place those, which are carried into complete execution: and lower in the scale we find those criminal designs, which have proceeded some degrees, but not to the last stage of completion. For the aggravation of a criminal intent is measured by the length to which it goes. In either class that kind of injustice is most notorious, which tends to disturb the common peace of society, and therefore is injurious to greater numbers. Private wrongs follow in the next degree. The greatest of which are those affecting life, and very great, though somewhat inferior in the degrees of enormity, are those, that disturb the peace of families, which is founded on the marriage-contract. And the last description of wrongs are those affecting the property of individuals, either by taking it with open violence, or obtaining or injuring it by fraudulent means.
In the highest category of crimes and wrongdoings, we place those that are fully carried out; and lower down the scale, we find criminal plans that have progressed to a certain point but have not reached completion. The severity of a criminal intent is determined by how far it goes. In both categories, the most significant type of injustice is the one that disrupts the common peace of society, harming greater numbers. Private wrongs follow next in severity. The worst private wrongs are those that threaten life, while those that disrupt family peace, based on the marriage contract, are also very serious, though slightly less so. The final category of wrongs involves violations of individual property, whether through outright violence or by deceitful means.
Some are of opinion that a more accurate order of division might have been used; but that which is here followed is the same used by God himself in the delivery of his commandments. For under the name of parents242 are included not only those, who are naturally such, but sovereign princes, magistrates, and rulers of every description, whose authority is the key-stone of the fabric of society. Next follows the prohibition of murder; the prohibition of adultery, as a violation of the marriage bond; the prohibition of theft, and false evidence: and the catalogue of offences concludes with the prohibition of criminal desires. Among the immediate causes to restrain the commission of a crime, not only the cruelty of the act itself, but all the remote and possible consequences should be taken into the account. If a fire is begun, or the barriers, that keep out the waves, are broken down, the perpetrator brings upon his own head the blood of thousands, and all the guilt of that ruin by which they perish.
Some people believe that a more accurate way to categorize these things could have been used; however, the order followed here is the same one used by God when he delivered his commandments. Under the term parents242, it refers not just to biological parents, but also to sovereign leaders, magistrates, and rulers of all kinds, whose authority is the foundation of society. Next is the ban on murder; then comes the ban on adultery, which violates the sanctity of marriage; followed by the ban on theft and false testimony; and the list of offenses wraps up with the ban on wrongful desires. When considering the immediate reasons to prevent a crime, one must account for not just the brutality of the act itself, but also all potential distant and consequential effects. If a fire is started, or if the barriers that protect against floods are destroyed, the person responsible brings upon themselves the death of thousands and all the guilt of the devastation that leads to their demise.
In addition to the general characters of injustice above described, we may annex the crime of being undutiful to parents, unkind to relatives, or ungrateful to benefactors, which are each of them a violation of natural, and in some respects of civil law. The repetition of these offences too aggravates their enormity: because wicked habits are sometimes worse than wicked actions. Hence we may comprehend the natural justice of that rule, which the Persians followed, comparing the past life of an offender with his present transgression. And this ought to have some weight in cases where a crime does not originate from habit, but from a momentary occasion. But not so, where a course of former rectitude has been changed into an unvaried course of wickedness. For in such cases, God himself has declared by the mouth of his prophet Ezekiel, that he has no regard to the former life. Even profane writers have the same clear views upon the subject; for Thucydides observes, that degeneracy from a righteous to a wicked course incurs double punishment: for offences are least pardonable in those, who know the difference between right and wrong. In this respect all praise and admiration are due to the wisdom of the primitive Christians, who, in estimating the magnitude of offences, weighed the preceding and the subsequent conduct of a transgressor against the action, for which he was to be punished, as may be seen from the council of Ancyra, and other councils. It heightens the enormity of an offence, where it is committed in violation of an express prohibition of the law. For, in the language of Tacitus, "the fear of prohibition may sometimes243 operate as a restraint, but where men once act in defiance of that, fear and shame have lost all their force."
In addition to the general traits of injustice mentioned above, we can add the crime of being disobedient to parents, unkind to relatives, or ungrateful to those who have helped you. Each of these is a breach of natural law, and in some ways, civil law as well. Repeating these offenses only makes them worse, because bad habits can sometimes be more damaging than bad actions. Therefore, we can understand the natural justice behind the rule that the Persians followed, which involved comparing an offender's past life with their current wrongdoing. This should hold some weight in cases where a crime doesn’t stem from habit but from a momentary impulse. However, it doesn’t apply when a previously upright life has turned into a continuous pattern of wrongdoing. In such situations, God has stated through the prophet Ezekiel that He doesn’t consider the offender's past life. Even secular writers have similar views; Thucydides notes that shifting from a righteous path to a wicked one results in double punishment, as offenses are less forgivable for those who understand the difference between right and wrong. In this regard, we should commend the wisdom of early Christians, who, when assessing the severity of offenses, took into account the previous and subsequent behavior of a wrongdoer compared to the action for which they were being punished, as seen in the council of Ancyra and other councils. It intensifies the seriousness of an offense when it violates a clear prohibition of the law. As Tacitus puts it, "the fear of prohibition may sometimes operate as a restraint, but when people act in defiance of it, fear and shame lose all their power."
XXXI. The capacity of the person too, with respect to judgment, disposition, age, education, and every other circumstance must be taken into consideration, when we look for resistance, or submission to the suggestions of wicked inclinations. The thought of immediate danger augments fear, and recent, unallayed pain inflames anger; so that in either case the calm dictates of reason cannot be heard. Offences therefore springing from the influence of such impressions, are of a less odious complexion than those arising from the love of pleasure, or the indulgence of hatred. Because there is less excuse for actions of the latter kind, the delay, or total forbearance of which could occasion no serious inconvenience. For it must always be kept in mind, that where there are more powerful impediments to the exercise of judgment, and more urgent persuasives to natural feeling, the criminality of an offence is proportionably softened. And these are the rules for measuring the degrees of pardon or punishment.
XXXI. We also need to consider a person's capacity in terms of judgment, character, age, education, and all other circumstances when we examine resistance or submission to wrongful urges. The thought of immediate danger heightens fear, and recent, unresolved pain intensifies anger; as a result, the calm reasoning cannot be heard in either case. Offenses that stem from these kinds of influences are less morally reprehensible than those that come from the pursuit of pleasure or the expression of hate. There’s less justification for actions of the latter kind since delaying or completely refraining from them wouldn’t cause any serious problems. It’s important to remember that when there are stronger barriers to the exercise of judgment and more pressing motivations for natural feelings, the severity of an offense is correspondingly reduced. These are the principles for determining the levels of forgiveness or punishment.
XXXII. The Pythagoreans maintain that justice lies in proportioning the punishment to the offence: a rule which cannot be admitted to the full extent of requiring an aggressor to suffer nothing more than a bare requital of the injury he has occasioned. For this is at variance with the most perfect laws, which in cases of theft sometimes require fourfold, and sometimes fivefold restitution to be made. And the Athenian law, besides compelling a thief to pay double the value of what he had taken sentenced him to many days' imprisonment. Among the Indians, as we are informed by Strabo, the person, who had maimed another, was condemned, in addition to the penalty of retaliation, to lose his hand. Nor is it right, as Philo, in explaining the punishment of murder, justly observes, for the suffering of an innocent and guilty person to be exactly the same. And hence it is easy to see why certain crimes not carried into actual execution, and therefore less injurious than those, which are so, are punished only proportionably to the design.—In this manner false witnesses were treated by the Jewish law; and by the Roman law, those who walked ready armed to commit murder. Consequently a greater degree of punishment is due, where the criminal intention is completed. But as death is the severest punishment that244 can be inflicted, and one that can never be repeated; the sentence of all human law rests there: though by the custom of some countries death is accompanied with torture, in cases of extreme atrocity.
XXXII. The Pythagoreans believe that justice means matching the punishment to the crime, but this idea can't go as far as saying that someone who commits an offense should only face the exact same harm they caused. That would contradict the best laws, which in cases of theft sometimes require restitution of four or five times the value taken. Athenian law, for example, not only made a thief pay double for what they stole but also sentenced them to several days in prison. According to Strabo's account, in India, someone who injured another person would not only face retaliation but also lose their hand as punishment. It's also unjust, as Philo pointed out regarding the punishment for murder, for an innocent person and a guilty person to face the same consequences. Thus, it's clear why some crimes that aren't fully carried out, and are therefore less harmful than those that are, receive only a proportionate punishment. This is how false witnesses were treated under Jewish law, and how Roman law treated those who were armed and ready to commit murder. As a result, a harsher punishment is warranted when the criminal intent is fully realized. Since death is the most severe punishment that can be imposed and cannot be undone, it forms the basis of all human laws, although in some places, death is sometimes accompanied by torture in cases of extreme cruelty.
XXXIII. In many instances, the magnitude of a punishment can only be measured by the situation of the person on whom it is to be inflicted. Thus a fine imposed upon the poor would be a heavy sentence, though it would scarcely affect the rich; and a man of high rank would feel the weight of a disgrace, that would but lightly touch an ignoble person. Such distinctions are frequently used by the Roman law, often degenerating into acts of partiality; a fault from which the law of Moses is entirely free. And the above rules may be considered as the scale for estimating the different degrees of punishment.
XXXIII. In many cases, the severity of a punishment can only be judged by the circumstances of the person receiving it. For example, a fine imposed on someone poor would be a heavy burden, while it would hardly impact someone wealthy; similarly, a person of high status would feel the shame of a disgrace that would barely bother someone of low status. These kinds of distinctions are often present in Roman law, sometimes leading to favoritism, a flaw that the law of Moses does not have. The rules mentioned above can be viewed as a guideline for assessing different levels of punishment.
XXXIV. Though punishment does not exceed the bounds of justice, yet in certain cases it may be mitigated in favour of a criminal, from motives of mercy, except where such lenity to the guilty is deemed cruelty to the innocent, whose safety is thereby endangered. For the escape of a criminal is often an encouragement to his own perseverance in iniquity, and to that of others, who are encouraged by the example. Necessity indeed requires the sharpest remedies for the suppression of crimes; especially, where the incentives of habit and a facility to commit them prevail.
XXXIV. While punishment should stay within the limits of justice, there are times when it can be softened for a criminal out of mercy, unless that leniency is considered cruel to the innocent, putting their safety at risk. The escape of a criminal often motivates them to continue their wrongdoing and inspires others by their example. In fact, the situation demands the strongest measures to suppress crimes, especially when habitual behavior and easy opportunities to commit those crimes are present.
XXXV. The divine law given to the Hebrews punished the stealing of cattle from a pasture with more severity than breaking into a house, on account of the ease with which the former of those crimes might be committed. Exod. xxii. 1–9. Justin in speaking of the Scythians, describes them as "punishing theft with more severity than any other crime; for as they have no covered habitations to protect their flocks, and herds from depredations, what could be safe, if thieving were allowed?" Though the FAMILIARITY of certain crimes may prevent us from being surprised at their perpetration, it by no means diminishes their atrocity, or demands a mitigation of punishment. But, as Saturninus says, "the giant-strides of crimes must be impeded with the strongest bands." In trials for offences, clemency may be indulged, but in the passing of laws severity should be regarded: For the GENERAL nature of law requires that offences should be pursued with rigour: but in trials, in which individuals are the245 objects concerned, there may be circumstances to aggravate or diminish the offence: which leaves room for the discretionary exercise of rigour or lenity.
XXXV. The divine law given to the Hebrews punished stealing cattle from a pasture more harshly than breaking into a house because it was easier to commit the former crime. Exod. xxii. 1–9. Justin, when talking about the Scythians, says they punish theft more severely than any other crime; since they have no covered homes to protect their flocks and herds from theft, nothing would be safe if stealing were allowed. Although we might become accustomed to certain crimes and not be surprised by them, it doesn't lessen their severity or call for a lighter punishment. But, as Saturninus says, "the giant strides of crimes must be stopped with the strongest chains." In trials for offenses, leniency may be shown, but when it comes to making laws, we should focus on severity: The general nature of law requires that offenses be pursued rigorously; however, in trials, where individuals are the central focus, there may be circumstances that aggravate or lessen the offense, allowing room for discretion in applying either strictness or mercy.
XXXVI. and XXXVII. The inclination to mitigate penalties, where the urgent motives to enforce them no longer exist, is a point of compassion perfectly distinct from the abolition of punishment altogether.
XXXVI. and XXXVII. The tendency to reduce penalties when the pressing reasons to enforce them are no longer present is a matter of compassion that is completely different from completely eliminating punishment.
Nor has any thing been omitted, that might tend to clear up this difficult and delicate question. But every point, we trust, has been examined in its proper place, either respecting the magnitude of crimes, as measured by the injury done, the habitual commission of such offences, or the influence of the motives, sufficient to encourage or restrain them. Indeed the character of the offender affords the most conclusive means for judging of his capacity to commit the crime; and that of the sufferer often contributes something towards enabling us to estimate the due proportion of the penalty. The circumstances of the time, when—the place, where—or the facility, with which a crime is perpetrated, tend to aggravate, or lessen its enormity. The length of time intervening between a criminal design and its execution gives us some opportunity to examine how far the perpetrator was actuated by a malicious purpose. But the true complexion of a crime is to be discovered, partly from the nature of those appetites, to which it owes its birth; and partly, on the other hand, from the nature of the motives which ought to have restrained them. By this class of appetites the magnitude of a crime may be judged of; and the consequences are the motives which should operate to restrain them.
Nor has anything been left out that might help clarify this challenging and sensitive question. We believe that every aspect has been examined in its appropriate context, whether regarding the severity of crimes, based on the harm done, the repeated occurrence of such offenses, or the influence of the motives that could either promote or deter them. In fact, the character of the offender provides the most reliable means to evaluate their capacity to commit the crime; and the background of the victim often helps us gauge the appropriate level of punishment. The circumstances of the time when it happened, the location, and the ease with which a crime is carried out can either intensify or diminish its seriousness. The time elapsed between the intention to commit a crime and its execution gives us a chance to assess how much the perpetrator was driven by a malicious intent. However, the true nature of a crime is revealed, in part, by the types of desires that led to it, and also by the nature of the motives that should have held those desires in check. The severity of a crime can be judged by these desires, while the consequences are the motives that ought to have restrained them.
XXXVIII. It has been shewn before, and it is a truth founded upon historical fact, that wars are undertaken, as acts of punishment, and this motive, added to that of redress for injuries, is the source, from which the duties of nations, relating to war, take their rise. But it is not every injury, that can be construed into a just ground of war. For laws, whose vengeance is meant to protect the innocent, and to fall upon the guilty, do not regard every case, as a sufficient warrant for their exertion. So that there is much truth in the opinion of Sopater, who says that there are trivial and common offences, which it is better to pass over unnoticed, than to punish.
XXXVIII. It has been shown before, and it's a truth based on historical fact, that wars are started as acts of punishment, and this motive, along with seeking redress for injuries, is where the responsibilities of nations concerning war originate. However, not every injury can be seen as a valid reason for war. Laws that aim to protect the innocent and target the guilty do not view every situation as a sufficient justification for their enforcement. Thus, there is a lot of truth in Sopater's view that there are minor and common offenses that are better left unpunished than to take action against them.
XXXIX. The maxim laid down by Cato, in his speech in defence of the Rhodians, that it is not right any one246 should be punished upon the bare suspicion of his having intended to commit aggression or injury, was well applied in that place; because no positive decree of the people of Rhodes could be alleged against them, nor was there any other proof beyond the CONJECTURE of their wavering in their policy. But this maxim is not universally true.
XXXIX. The principle stated by Cato in his speech defending the Rhodians—that no one should be punished merely based on a suspicion of intending to commit harm—was rightly applied in that context. This is because there was no clear decree from the people of Rhodes against them, nor was there any evidence beyond mere GUESS regarding their inconsistent actions. However, this principle is not always applicable.
For where intention has proceeded to any outward and visible signs of insatiable ambition and injustice, it is deemed a proper object of jealousy, and even of punishment. Upon this principle, the Romans, as may be seen from Livy's account in the xlii. book and xxx. chapter of his history, thought themselves justified in declaring war against Perseus, King of Macedon, unless he gave satisfactory proof, that he had no hostile intentions against them, in the naval and military armaments, which he was preparing. And we are informed by the same historians, that the Rhodians urged it as a rule established by the laws and customs of all civilized states; that if any one wished the destruction of an enemy, he could not punish him with death, unless he had actually done something to deserve it.
For where intention has led to any clear signs of relentless ambition and injustice, it is seen as a valid cause for jealousy and even punishment. Based on this idea, the Romans, as noted in Livy's account in the xlii book and xxx chapter of his history, believed they were justified in declaring war against Perseus, King of Macedon, unless he provided convincing evidence that he had no hostile intentions towards them, given the naval and military preparations he was making. The same historians inform us that the Rhodians insisted it was a rule established by the laws and customs of all civilized nations that if someone wished to eliminate an enemy, they couldn’t punish them with death unless that person had actually done something to deserve it.
But it is not every unjust design, though indicated by some outward act, which can authorize and direct hostilities. For if the actual commission of crimes and aggressions is, in some cases, proper to be overlooked, much more will it be a mark of deliberate caution to use the same forbearance, where nothing further than the pure design of aggression appears. A forbearance which Cicero justifies upon the possibility that the enemy may have repented of his design, before the execution of it. No conclusive inference can be drawn from the severity of Mosaic Law against all intended acts of impiety and murder. For, in comparing human laws with the divine counsels, whose depths we cannot sound, we are liable to run into error; and the impulse of anger, where it is attended with no fatal consequence, is a case in which the infirmity of human nature calls for pardon. For altho' the precepts of the decalogue are designed to lay a restraint upon unlawful desires as well as upon unlawful actions, yet in addition to the spiritual sense, that which is called the carnal, or external commandment applies to those dispositions that are manifested by some open act. This interpretation may be deduced from a passage in the gospel of St. Mark, c. x.247 19, where the prohibition to defraud is immediately preceded by the injunction not to steal. So that intended aggressions are not to be punished by force of arms, except in cases of atrocity, where the very design threatens consequences of the greatest danger. All punishment therefore must have in view either security against future aggressions, reparation for the injury done to national or private honour, or it must be used as an example of awful severity.
But not every unjust plan, even if shown by some outward action, justifies and directs hostility. If, in some cases, actual crimes and attacks are sometimes ignored, it’s even more prudent to show the same restraint when only the intention to attack is apparent. This restraint is something Cicero defends by pointing out the possibility that the enemy might have regretted their intention before acting on it. We can’t draw definitive conclusions from the harshness of Mosaic Law against all intended acts of wrongdoing and murder. When we compare human laws with divine principles, which we can't fully understand, we risk making mistakes; and when anger doesn’t lead to serious harm, human frailty calls for forgiveness. Although the commandments are meant to control both unlawful desires and actions, the so-called "carnal" or external commandments apply to those intentions that are evident through some visible act. This interpretation can be inferred from a passage in the Gospel of Mark, chapter 10, verse 19, where the prohibition against cheating immediately follows the command not to steal. Therefore, intended attacks shouldn't be met with armed force, except in extreme cases where the very intent poses the greatest danger. All punishment should aim for either protection against future attacks, restitution for the harm done to national or private honor, or serve as a severe warning.
XL. It is proper also to observe that kings and those who are possessed of sovereign power have a right to exact punishment not only for injuries affecting immediately themselves or their own subjects, but for gross violations of the law of nature and of nations, done to other states and subjects. For the liberty of inflicting punishment for the peace and welfare of society, which belonged to individuals in the early ages of the world, was converted into the judicial authority of sovereign states and princes; a right devolving upon them not only as rulers of others, but as subject to the controul of no earthly power. For that is a right, which can belong to no subject. It is never safe to leave the entire assertion of a man's own rights, or the punishment of his wrongs, to his own judgment; for he cannot be entirely disinterested in his own cause. Partiality will make him fall short of, or prejudice will make him exceed the bounds of justice. It was the theme of praise bestowed upon the heroes of antiquity, that in their most arduous undertakings they avenged the wrongs of others rather than their own. Upon this principle there can be no hesitation in pronouncing all wars to be just, that are made upon pirates, general robbers, and enemies of the human race. So far this opinion agrees with that of Innocentius and others, who maintain all war to be lawful against those who have renounced the ties and law of nature. An opinion directly the reverse is held by Victoria, Vasquez, Azorius, Molina, and others, who deem an aggression done to a prince, his government, or his subjects, or civil jurisdiction over the aggressor, the only justifiable warrant for inflicting punishment, particularly the punishment of hostilities. For they suppose punishment to be an effect purely arising from the authority of civil law, whereas, according to the proofs established in the beginning of this treatise, it was shewn to be a right resulting entirely from the law of nature.
XL. It’s also important to note that kings and those with sovereign power have the right to impose punishment not only for injuries affecting themselves or their own subjects but also for serious violations of the laws of nature and nations committed against other states and their subjects. The right to enforce punishment for the peace and welfare of society, which belonged to individuals in the early days of the world, has transformed into the judicial authority of sovereign states and rulers; a right that they hold not just as leaders of others but as individuals not subject to any earthly authority. This is a right that cannot belong to any subject. It is never safe to leave the total determination of one’s own rights or the punishment for wrongs to their own judgment because they cannot be completely impartial in their own cases. Bias can lead them to either underestimate or overestimate the bounds of justice. It was often praised in the heroes of ancient times that in their most challenging endeavors, they sought to avenge the wrongs of others rather than their own. Based on this principle, there can be no doubt in declaring all wars just that are waged against pirates, general robbers, and enemies of humanity. This view aligns with that of Innocentius and others who argue that all war is lawful against those who have severed the ties of nature and law. Conversely, Victoria, Vasquez, Azorius, Molina, and others hold a directly opposing view, believing that only an aggression against a prince, their government, or their subjects grants a justifiable reason for punishment, especially in terms of hostilities. They think of punishment as a consequence that arises purely from civil law authority, while the evidence presented at the start of this treatise shows it to be a right that comes entirely from the law of nature.
248 If the opinion of those, from whom we differ, be admitted, no enemy will have a right to punish another, by the prosecution of a just war; a right, which notwithstanding is allowed and confirmed by the practice of all nations, not only after the defeat of an enemy, but during the continuance of a war; and that too, not from any civil jurisdiction, but from a natural right, which prevailed long before the foundation of states, and which still exists in all its force, in places, where the community consists of families distinct, and united as the subjects of one sovereign.
248 If we accept the opinions of those we disagree with, then no enemy will have the right to punish another through the pursuit of a just war; a right that, nonetheless, is recognized and upheld by all nations, not just after defeating an enemy, but also during an ongoing war. This right comes not from any civil authority, but from a natural right that existed long before states were formed, and still exists strongly in places where the community is made up of distinct families united under one sovereign.
XLI., XLII., XLIII. But certain precautions are necessary to prevent us from being carried away by an opinion that civil customs, though founded upon just reasons, and received among many nations, are to be reckoned as a part of the law of nature. And in the next place, it is necessary to guard against enumerating as prohibitions of natural law, things which are not proved to be so, as certain kinds of marriages the taking of interest for the use of money, and other positive injunctions of the divine, or Mosaic law. The third rule is, to make an accurate distinction between general principles, such as the duty of living according to the dictates of reason, and those of a more particular though not less obvious meaning; as the duty of forbearing to take what belongs to another. To which many truths may be added though not quite so easy of apprehension: among which may be named the cruelty of that kind of punishment, which consists in revenge, delighting in the pain of another. This is a method of proof similar to that which occurs in mathematics, the process of which rises from self-evident truths to demonstrations, the latter of which, though not intelligible to all alike, upon due examination obtain assent.
XLI., XLII., XLIII. However, we need to take certain precautions to avoid getting swept away by the belief that civil customs, even if based on valid reasons and accepted by many nations, should be considered a part of natural law. Moreover, we must be careful not to list things as prohibitions of natural law that haven't been proven as such, like specific types of marriages, charging interest on loans, and other rules from divine or Mosaic law. The third guideline is to clearly differentiate between broad principles, such as the obligation to act according to reason, and more specific, yet still clear, principles like the duty not to take what belongs to someone else. Additionally, several truths can be mentioned that might not be as easily understood, such as the cruelty of punishment that stems from revenge and finds pleasure in another person's suffering. This method of proof resembles that which is used in mathematics, starting from self-evident truths and moving toward demonstrations, which, while not equally comprehensible to everyone, can gain agreement upon careful consideration.
As then in matters of civil law, ignorance is deemed an excuse, so with respect to the law of nature, wherever infirmity of understanding forms an invincible obstruction to the knowledge of its rules, such infirmity may be alleged as a vindication. For as, in cases of unavoidable ignorance a great degree of the guilt of sin is removed; so it is in some measure softened wherever this ignorance subsists, though it may be owing to former negligence. And for this reason, Aristotle compares barbarians, in their rude, unformed state, to persons, whose appetites are rendered sickly by disease. Plutarch also249 observes that there are certain infirmities and disorders, which naturally infect the soul. Once for all, by way of conclusion we may add that wars undertaken to inflict punishment may be suspected of injustice, except there be manifest and enormous aggressions, with other conspiring causes, to vindicate nations for having recourse to arms.
As in civil law, ignorance is considered a valid excuse; the same goes for the law of nature. When a lack of understanding creates an insurmountable barrier to knowing its rules, that lack of understanding can be used as a defense. Just as unavoidable ignorance lessens the guilt of a sin, it also mitigates the situation when that ignorance exists, even if it stems from past negligence. For this reason, Aristotle compares uncivilized people in their rough, unrefined state to individuals whose appetites are weakened by illness. Plutarch also249 notes that there are certain weaknesses and disorders that can naturally affect the soul. In conclusion, it can be said that wars waged for punishment may be seen as unjust unless there are clear and significant aggressions, along with other contributing factors, to justify nations resorting to arms.
XLIV. The progress of the work has necessarily led to the consideration of offences against God; the propriety or impropriety of punishing which by force of arms is a fit subject of inquiry.
XLIV. The advancement of the work has naturally resulted in the examination of offenses against God; whether it is appropriate or inappropriate to punish these with force is worth exploring.
Admitting the affirmative part of the question, we may observe that as in ecclesiastical affairs Bishops are intrusted with a Catholic, or general power; so kings, besides the care of their own immediate states and subjects, may be regarded as protectors of the human race. The best argument, on the negative side of the question, against the justice of such wars, is the sufficiency of the divine omnipotence to avenge its own wrongs. Yet the same may be said of other offences. For the Deity possesses sufficient power to punish them, although he leaves them to the sentence of human tribunals. Some will urge and maintain that other kinds of offences are punished only in cases, where others are uninjured or endangered by the commission of them. On the other hand, it may be said that men punish not only offences, which directly hurt others, but even those, which affect them indirectly, as suicide and other similar crimes.
Acknowledging the positive aspect of the question, we can see that just as bishops are given a universal or general authority in church matters, kings, in addition to overseeing their own territories and subjects, can be seen as protectors of humanity. The strongest argument against the righteousness of such wars is the idea that divine omnipotence is capable of addressing its own grievances. However, the same can be said about other wrongdoings. The deity has enough power to punish these as well, even though they are often left to human courts for judgment. Some will argue that other types of offenses are punished only when they directly harm or threaten others. Conversely, it can be argued that humans punish not only those offenses that harm others directly but also those that impact them indirectly, such as suicide and related crimes.
Although religion is a concern between the soul of man and his Maker alone, its influence on human morals is of no inconsiderable importance. So that Plato had reason to call it the bulwark of authority and law, and the bond of every thing venerable in social order and discipline. Every false opinion in divine things, says Plutarch, is pernicious, betraying itself in the disorders of the imagination, wherever it takes root, and springs up into action. So that Aristotle reckons the care and support of religion the first of public concerns. This is a truth applying not to any particular state, but to all governments, and to human society in every shape. An avowal which Xenophon makes the characteristic of a great and wise prince, attributing to Cyrus a declaration of his firm persuasion that the more his subjects feared God, the more obedient he should find them to his laws, and the more attached to his person. But once remove the motives of religion, says250 Tully, and you destroy faith, the intercourse between man and man, and justice the most excellent of all virtues.
Although religion is fundamentally a matter between a person and their Creator, its impact on human morals is very significant. This is why Plato referred to it as the foundation of authority and law, and the bond that holds social order and discipline together. Plutarch notes that any false beliefs about divine matters are harmful, revealing themselves through chaotic thinking wherever they take hold and lead to action. Aristotle considers the care and maintenance of religion to be the most important public concern. This is a universal truth that applies to all governments and human society in general. Xenophon highlights this as a defining trait of a great and wise leader, attributing to Cyrus a belief that the more his subjects respected God, the more obedient they would be to his laws and the more they would be devoted to him. But once you remove the motivations of religion, Tully states, you destroy trust, relationships between people, and justice, which is the greatest of all virtues.
The opinions of Epicurus afford a sufficient proof of this: for in banishing the providence of God from his system, he made justice nothing but an empty name, springing from human conventions, founded on self-interest, and restraining men from the commission of crimes by no other principle but that of fear.
The views of Epicurus provide clear evidence of this: by removing God's providence from his philosophy, he turned justice into just a meaningless term, arising from human agreements, based on self-interest, and preventing people from committing crimes solely through fear.
But there is a wider sphere, than the internal welfare of independent states, on which religion operates. In the separate society, which every kingdom, state, or country forms within itself, the place of religion may occasionally be supplied by the influence and execution of municipal laws. But in all the transactions of the great community at large, where civil laws are silent, and tribunals give way to the decision of the sword, the law of nature and of nations, founded upon the fear of God, and obedience to his will, is the standard of right to which Kings and Sovereign states appeal; a violation of which is regarded as a violation of the divine law.
But there is a broader realm beyond the internal well-being of independent states where religion has an impact. In the unique society that each kingdom, state, or country creates within itself, religion can sometimes be replaced by the influence and enforcement of local laws. However, in all the dealings of the larger community, where civil laws are absent and courts yield to the decision of force, the law of nature and of nations—based on the fear of God and obedience to His will—serves as the standard of right to which kings and sovereign states turn; a breach of this is seen as a breach of divine law.
XLV. But to take a closer view of the subject, we must observe that true religion, which is the same at all periods of time, rests upon four evident and universally acknowledged truths. The first of which is the being and unity of God,—the second, that God is not any of the things, that can be seen, but of a nature too sublime to be the object of human conception, or of human sight,—the third is, that with the eye of his providence he regards the events of this world, and regulates them with the most equitable and unerring judgments,—the fourth is, that he is the creator of all things, except himself. And these four truths are unfolded and laid down in an equal number of commandments, the first of which plainly declares the unity of God—the second forbids any representation, by painting or image, to be made of that being, who is invisible to mortal eye. Tacitus bears testimony to the spiritual nature of the Jewish religion: for he says, that "the Jews have nothing but a mental conception of one God, and they look upon every attempt to represent him under the appearance of human form, as a profanation of his heavenly nature."—From the third commandment we deduce his knowledge of all human transactions, even of our very thoughts; an omniscience upon which the obligation and251 sanctity of oaths is founded. For God is a witness even of the secret designs of the heart, so that every solemn oath is an appeal to his justice and his power, for the vindication of truth, and the punishment of falsehood.—The fourth commandment presents us with an account of the creation of the world, to commemorate which God appointed the sabbath, commanding it to be observed with a degree of reverence above every other sacred institution. For the violation of any other rites, such as those respecting forbidden meats, was left to the discretionary punishment of the law: but offences against the sabbath were capital; because, considering the nature and design of its origin, such contempt implied a disbelief, that the world was created by God. Now the creation of the world by God affords a tacit proof of his goodness, wisdom, eternity and power: and the effect of this contemplative knowledge is the offering of honour, love, worship and obedience to God. So that Aristotle says that the man, who denies that God ought to be honoured, or parents loved, should be taught to renounce his error, not by reasoning, but by punishment. And, in another place, he observes that some actions are proper on certain occasions, but reverence for the majesty of God is requisite at all times, and in all places.
XLV. To take a closer look at the topic, we need to recognize that true religion, which remains the same throughout history, is based on four clear and universally accepted truths. The first is the existence and oneness of God; the second is that God is not something visible, but of a nature too exalted to be grasped by human understanding or sight; the third is that God observes the happenings of this world with providence and judges them with perfect fairness; and the fourth is that He is the creator of everything except Himself. These four truths are expressed in an equal number of commandments, with the first clearly asserting God's unity—the second prohibits any physical representation, whether through painting or imagery, of that being who is invisible to human sight. Tacitus confirms the spiritual essence of the Jewish faith by stating, "the Jews have nothing but a mental conception of one God, and they view every attempt to depict Him in human form as a violation of His divine nature." From the third commandment, we understand God's awareness of all human actions, including our innermost thoughts; this omniscience establishes the obligation and sanctity of oaths. God witnesses even the secret intentions of our hearts, so every solemn oath appeals to His justice and power for the affirmation of truth and the punishment of falsehood. The fourth commandment provides an account of the world's creation, for which God designated the Sabbath, commanding it to be observed with greater reverence than any other sacred practice. Violating other rituals, such as those concerning forbidden foods, was subject to the law's discretionary punishment, but offenses against the Sabbath were severe; because, given its origin and purpose, such contempt suggested a disbelief in God's creation of the world. The act of creation by God serves as a silent testament to His goodness, wisdom, eternity, and power: and the result of this reflective understanding is the offering of honor, love, worship, and obedience to God. Aristotle notes that a person who denies that God deserves honor or parents deserve love should be corrected, not through debate, but through punishment. Additionally, he remarks that certain actions may be appropriate at specific times, but reverence for God's majesty is necessary at all times and in all places.
The truth of those contemplative opinions may undoubtedly be proved from the nature of things; the clearest of which proofs is the evidence of sense, shewing the existence of things, which naturally leads us to consider the time, when they had no being.
The truth of those thoughtful opinions can definitely be shown by looking at the nature of things; the strongest proof comes from our senses, which reveal the existence of things and naturally makes us think about the time when they didn't exist.
But as all are not able to understand these arguments and others of the same kind, it is sufficient to observe that in all ages and all countries of the world, with very few exceptions, these opinions have found a general reception with those who were too plain in their dealings, and ingenuous in their designs, to impose upon others, and with many, who had too much sagacity to be deceived themselves. But when amid such variety of laws, customs, and opinions, there is so general an agreement upon one point; that agreement may be adduced as a proof, that such a belief owes its origin to the primitive ages of the world, from whence it has been derived to us: when we consider too that it has never been clearly refuted, it is a sufficient reason to establish our faith.
But since not everyone can grasp these arguments and similar ones, it is enough to note that throughout history and across the world, with very few exceptions, these beliefs have been widely accepted by those who were straightforward in their actions and sincere in their intentions, as well as by many who were too wise to be misled. However, when there is such a broad consensus on one point amidst a variety of laws, customs, and opinions, that consensus can be taken as evidence that this belief originated in the early days of humanity, from which it has been passed down to us; especially when we consider that it has never been clearly disproven, this serves as a strong reason to support our faith.
252 XLVI. There is no excuse therefore for the rejection of those opinions, even in cases, where there is no intuitive sagacity to discover new proofs, or to comprehend old ones: as there are so many guides both in nature and reason to lead men to the knowledge of those truths, and as no solid arguments have ever been produced to establish a contrary belief. But as human punishments form the subject of our present inquiry, it is right to make a distinction between opinions themselves, and the manner of deviating from them. The belief in a supreme being, and in the controul of his providence over human affairs, is one of those universal tenets to be found in all religions, whether true or false. And in reality to deny the being of a God, and to deny the interposal of his providence in human affairs, amounts in its moral consequences to the same thing. And it is for this reason these two opinions have been inseparably united in all ages, and among every civilized people. Consequently we find, that in all well governed states, wholesome laws have been enacted to restrain those, who disturb those opinions, which have always been regarded as the chief support of social order; and all contempt, shewn to those opinions, has always been considered as contempt shewn to society itself, which it consequently has a right to punish.
252 XLVI. There’s no justification for dismissing these beliefs, even when we can’t intuitively find new evidence or understand the old. There are plenty of guides in both nature and reason that help us understand these truths, and no strong arguments have ever been presented to support a conflicting view. Since we're currently discussing human punishments, it’s important to differentiate between the beliefs themselves and how people stray from them. The belief in a supreme being and in His control over human affairs is a universal principle found in every religion, whether true or false. In fact, denying the existence of God and denying His involvement in human matters have the same moral implications. This is why these two beliefs have been closely linked throughout history and across all civilized societies. As a result, we see that in well-governed states, sensible laws have been created to restrict those who challenge these beliefs, which have always been viewed as essential to maintaining social order; any disrespect shown toward these beliefs has been regarded as a disrespect toward society itself, which therefore has the right to address it.
XLVII. There are other truths not equally self-evident, such as these, that there are not more Gods than one; that no visible thing, neither the world, nor the heavens, nor the sun, nor the air is God; that the world, and the matter of which it is formed, have not existed from all eternity, but were made by God. So that we see the knowledge of these truths disfigured, and almost entirely obliterated among many nations by the lapse of time. And this might the more easily happen, as there were no legal provisions made to preserve the purity of these truths, which were not considered as essential to the very existence of all religion. The law indeed given to that people, who were instructed in the clear knowledge of these truths, by the mouths of the prophets, by miracles seen with their own eyes, or brought to their ears by the reports of the most undoubted testimony, that law, though it expresses the greatest abhorrence of the worship of false gods, does not inflict the punishment of death upon all convicted of that crime, but only in particular instances, where they have seduced others253 into idolatry,—or where a state has introduced the worship of unknown Gods,—or where the true worship of God, and obedience to his laws have been forsaken for the worship of the stars, which St. Paul calls serving the creature above the creator, an offence, which was, for some time, punished among the descendants of Esau. Those too who offered their children to Moloch, that is, to Saturn, were punished with death. Yet the Canaanites, and the neighbouring nations, who had long been sunk into the most depraved superstitions, were not consigned by God to immediate punishment, but were left to fill up the measure of their crimes. And there were other nations, where, in the language of Scripture, God winked at the times of this ignorance. Where men have had no means of arriving at the knowledge of a true God, as their superstitions and errors are excusable, so where, in despite of knowledge, they have deified Daemons, and vices, which they knew to be such, their superstitions are not to be called errors, but impieties. And no less impious is the supposed homage, that is paid to God with the blood of innocent human victims, and Darius king of the Persians, and Gelo king of Syracuse, are commended for abstaining from such practices. Plutarch informs us of some barbarians, who would have been punished by the Romans for offering human victims to the deity, had they not pleaded the antiquity of the custom, which was admitted as an excuse, though they were strictly enjoined not to follow the same custom in future.
XLVII. There are other truths that aren’t as obvious, like the fact that there is only one God; that nothing visible—neither the world, the heavens, the sun, nor the air—is God; that the world and the matter it’s made of didn’t exist forever but were created by God. Because of this, we see that the understanding of these truths has been distorted and nearly erased over time among many nations. This could happen more easily since there weren’t any legal measures in place to preserve the purity of these truths, as they weren’t regarded as essential to the very existence of religion. The law given to that people, who were taught these truths clearly through prophets, miracles they witnessed, or reports from highly reliable sources, expresses a strong disgust for the worship of false gods but doesn’t impose the death penalty on everyone convicted of that crime. It only applies in specific cases, like when someone has led others into idolatry, when a state has introduced the worship of unknown gods, or when true worship of God and obedience to His laws have been abandoned in favor of star worship, which St. Paul refers to as serving the creature instead of the creator—a crime that was sometimes punished among the descendants of Esau. Those who sacrificed their children to Moloch, or Saturn, were sentenced to death, too. However, the Canaanites and neighboring nations, who had long fallen into extreme superstitions, weren't immediately punished by God but were allowed to fill up the measure of their crimes. There were other nations where, as Scripture puts it, God overlooked their times of ignorance. In places where people didn’t have access to the knowledge of the true God, their superstitions and mistakes can be excused. But where, despite having knowledge, they worshipped demons and recognized them as such, their superstitions are not just mistakes but acts of impiety. And the supposed homage paid to God with the blood of innocent victims is equally impious, while Darius, king of the Persians, and Gelo, king of Syracuse, are praised for avoiding such practices. Plutarch tells us about some barbarians who would have been punished by the Romans for offering human victims to their deity if they hadn’t claimed the long-standing nature of the custom as an excuse, although they were strictly ordered not to continue that practice in the future.
XLVIII. From the kind of evidence on which Christianity rests, it is plain that no force should be used with nations to promote its acceptance. It is not merely by natural arguments it can gain assent; for it has made an addition of many things to natural religion. Its evidence rests upon the history of Christ's resurrection, and upon the miracles performed by himself and his Apostles. So that it is a matter of fact proved by the most undeniable evidence, and of great antiquity. Therefore a doctrine of this kind cannot be thoroughly received upon the first hearing of it, without the secret assistance of God: an assistance not given as a reward for the merit of works; so that wherever it is withheld or less copiously bestowed; it is done for reasons, which though just, are generally unknown to us, and therefore not punishable by human judgments. For it is the custom in the sacred writings254 to assign the divine pleasure as the cause of things unknown to us.
XLVIII. Based on the type of evidence Christianity relies on, it's clear that no force should be used with nations to encourage its acceptance. It doesn't just rely on natural arguments for agreement; it has added many elements to natural religion. Its evidence is based on the history of Christ's resurrection and the miracles performed by Him and His Apostles. So, it's a factual matter supported by undeniable evidence and has a long history. Therefore, a doctrine like this can't be fully accepted upon first hearing it without God's hidden assistance; this assistance is not given as a reward for good deeds. Whenever this assistance is withheld or provided less abundantly, it's for reasons that, while just, are usually unknown to us and therefore not punishable by human judgments. In sacred writings, it's common to attribute the divine will as the reason for things that are unknown to us.254
There is another reason of no less weight, which is that Christ being the author of a new law, will have no one brought to embrace his doctrine by the fear of human punishments. Nor is the reason at all weakened by the objection drawn from the parable of the marriage-supper, where it is said the messengers are commanded to compel the guests to come in. For the term, COMPEL, here signifies nothing more than an earnest entreaty, a sense, in which it is used in other parts of the New Testament, implying an earnest request made to any one.
There’s another equally important reason: Christ, as the author of a new law, doesn’t want anyone to accept his teachings out of fear of human punishments. The argument isn’t weakened at all by the objection from the parable of the marriage-supper, where it’s stated that the messengers are instructed to compel the guests to come in. The term, FORCE, here simply means a sincere invitation, in a sense that’s used in other parts of the New Testament, indicating a heartfelt request made to someone.
XLIX. But to obstruct the teachers of Christianity by pains and penalties is undoubtedly contrary to natural law and reason: for the doctrine of Christ, apart from all the corruptions added by the inventions of men, contains nothing hurtful, but every thing beneficial to society. The thing speaks for itself, and even those who were strangers to the doctrine itself were obliged to acknowledge the truth of this. Pliny says that the Christians bound themselves by an oath to commit neither theft, nor robbery, nor to violate their word. It was a common saying "Caius Seius is a good man, but he is a Christian."
XLIX. But blocking the teachers of Christianity with punishments and penalties clearly goes against natural law and reason. The teachings of Christ, stripped of all the corruptions added by human inventions, provide nothing harmful but everything beneficial to society. This is evident, and even those unfamiliar with the doctrine had to recognize its truth. Pliny mentions that Christians committed to an oath not to steal, commit robbery, or break their word. It was a common saying, "Caius Seius is a good man, but he is a Christian."
Nor indeed can any danger be apprehended from the spreading of doctrines, calculated to inspire greater sanctity of manners, and the purest principles of obedience to lawful sovereigns. Philo has recorded a beautiful saying of Augustus, who observed that the assemblies of the Jews were not Bacchanalian revels, or meetings to disturb the public peace, but schools of virtue.
Nor can any danger be expected from the spread of beliefs aimed at promoting greater decency in behavior and the highest principles of obedience to rightful rulers. Philo noted a beautiful saying from Augustus, who remarked that Jewish assemblies were not Bacchanalian parties or gatherings that disrupt public order, but rather schools of virtue.
L. It seems unjust to persecute with punishments those who receive the law of Christ as true, but entertain doubts or errors on some external points, taking them in an ambiguous meaning or different from the ancient Christians in their explanation of them. A point which is proved by what has been said above, and by the ancient example of the Jews. For, possessing a law, which allowed them to inflict temporal punishments, they never exercised that authority upon the Sadducees, who denied the doctrine of a resurrection: a doctrine of the greatest truth, though but faintly delivered in that law, and under a typical application of words and circumstances.
L. It seems unfair to punish those who accept the law of Christ as true but have doubts or misunderstandings about some external aspects, interpreting them in a way that differs from how early Christians explained them. This is shown by what was mentioned earlier and by the ancient example of the Jews. They had a law that allowed them to impose temporal punishments, yet they never used that power against the Sadducees, who rejected the belief in resurrection—a belief that is fundamentally true, even though it is only vaguely expressed in that law and under a symbolic interpretation of words and circumstances.
255 But if there should be any weighty error, that discerning judges could easily refute by an appeal to sacred authority, or to the opinions of antiquity; here too it would be necessary to make allowance for ingrafted opinions, that have grown up to form an inseparable part of the human mind, and for the zealous attachment of every one to his own tenets; an evil which Galen says is more difficult to be eradicated than any constitutional disease.
255 However, if there's a significant mistake that knowledgeable judges could easily disprove through references to religious authority or ancient beliefs, we must also consider deeply rooted opinions that have become an essential part of our thinking, as well as the strong loyalty everyone has to their own beliefs. This is a problem that Galen claims is harder to eliminate than any inherent illness.
CHAPTER XXI.
On Punishment Communication.
How accessories are liable to punishment—Sovereign Princes or States answerable for the misconduct of their subjects, when they know it, and do not endeavour to prevent it—Sovereigns bound not to protect offending subjects, but to deliver them up or punish them—The rights of suppliants belong to the unfortunate and not to the guilty—Suppliants may be protected while the inquiry into their case is still pending—How far states are amenable to punishment—All the different exceptions stated—Children not answerable for the offences of parents—The moral government of God in this respect considered—Individuals not answerable for offences, to which they have not given consent—Heirs, how far answerable for the acts of their ancestors.
How accessories can be punished—Sovereign Princes or States are accountable for the actions of their subjects when they are aware of them and do nothing to intervene—Sovereigns cannot shield wrongdoers but must either punish them or hand them over—The rights of petitioners are meant for the unfortunate, not the guilty—Petitioners can receive protection while their case is still being investigated—The limits of what states can face in terms of punishment—All the various exceptions explained—Children are not held responsible for their parents' wrongdoings—The moral governance of God on this issue considered—Individuals are not liable for actions they did not agree to—Heirs carry some responsibility for the actions of their ancestors.
I. The next topic of inquiry relates to the communication of punishment, as inflicted upon accomplices, who, in that capacity, cannot be said to be punished for the guilt of others, but for their own. And from what has been said above upon the loss sustained from injury, it may be understood who are the persons, that come under this description. For the partnership in loss, and the partnership in guilt are regulated by nearly the same principles. Yet the obligation to repair a loss does not always imply guilt, except where there has been any notorious malice, in which case every damage renders the party, who has occasioned it, liable to make reparation. So that persons ordering the commission of any wicked or hostile act, giving the requisite consent to it, supplying the aggressor with assistance, or protection, or, in any other shape, partaking of the crime, by giving counsel, commendation, or assent to his act, or when they have power to forbid the commission of such an act, by forbearing to exercise their authority, or by refusing to afford the succour, which they are bound by the law of nature, or by treaty to give to the injured party, by not using with the offender that power of dissuasion, which they have a right to do, or lastly by concealing what they ought to make known, in257 all these cases, such persons are punishable as accomplices, if they are convicted of that degree of malice, which constitutes a crime, and merits punishment: points which have before been discussed.
I. The next topic of discussion is about how punishment is communicated to accomplices, who, in this role, are not punished for the wrongdoing of others but for their own actions. From what has been previously mentioned regarding the loss incurred from harm, we can identify those who fall into this category. The sharing of loss and the sharing of guilt are governed by very similar principles. However, being obligated to compensate for a loss does not always mean that one is guilty unless there is clear malice involved; in that case, any harm caused makes the responsible party liable for compensation. Therefore, individuals who order the commission of any wrongful or hostile act, give their consent, assist or protect the perpetrator, or in any way participate in the crime by offering advice, support, or approval, or those who have the power to prevent such actions but choose not to exercise that authority, or who refuse to provide help that they are naturally or contractually obligated to give to the harmed party, or who do not use their right to dissuade the offender, or finally, who hide information that should be disclosed, in257 all these situations, those individuals can be punished as accomplices if they are found guilty of the level of malice that qualifies as a crime, warranting punishment: points that have been discussed earlier.
II. The case will be made clearer by examples. A civil community is no more bound than any other society by an act of individual members, except that act be done by its express consent and authority, or it has neglected to disavow such a proceeding. Hence it is formally stipulated in almost all treaties that no acts or aggressions are to be ascribed to a state, except those, which are done in the name of the sovereign, and by persons acting expressly under the authority of his commission. So a father is not answerable for the misconduct of his children, a master for that of his servants, nor a ruler for the acts of those under him, unless there appears in any of these some connivance, or encouragement in promoting that misconduct, or those acts.
II. Examples will clarify the case. A civil community is no more obligated than any other society by the actions of individual members, unless those actions are undertaken with its explicit consent and authority, or it has failed to reject such actions. Therefore, it is typically stated in almost all treaties that no acts or aggressions can be attributed to a state, except those performed in the name of the sovereign, and by individuals acting directly under the authority of his commission. Similarly, a father is not held accountable for the misbehavior of his children, a master for that of his servants, nor a leader for the actions of those beneath him, unless there is evidence of complicity or encouragement in fostering that wrongdoing or those actions.
In the case of a sovereign's responsibility for the acts of his subjects, there are two things to be considered, which require minute inquiry, and mature deliberation, and those are the forbearance, and the encouragement or protection, which he has shewn to their transgressions.
In the case of a ruler’s responsibility for the actions of their subjects, there are two things to consider that require careful examination and thoughtful consideration: the tolerance and the support or protection they have shown toward those wrongdoings.
As to forbearance, it is an acknowledged point, that when he knows of a delinquency, which he neither forbids nor punishes, when he is both able and bound to do so, he becomes an accessory to the guilt thereof. Cicero, in his speech against Piso, says, "it makes no great difference especially in a consul, whether he harasses the government by moving ruinous laws, and making mischievous speeches, or suffers others to do the same. If a slave has committed a murder with the knowledge of his master, the master becomes answerable for the entire deed, as it was done with his concurrence."
As for forbearance, it's widely recognized that when someone is aware of wrongdoing and neither prohibits nor punishes it—despite being both able and obliged to do so—they become complicit in the wrongdoing. Cicero, in his speech against Piso, states, "it doesn't really matter, especially for a consul, whether he disrupts the government by proposing destructive laws and making harmful speeches, or allows others to do the same. If a slave commits murder with the master's knowledge, the master is fully responsible for the act, as it was done with his consent."
But, as we have said before, besides the knowledge of a deed, to constitute a participation in the guilt, the person so knowing it, must possess the power to prevent it. And this is what is meant by the legal phrase, that the knowledge of a crime, when it is ordered to be punished, is taken in the sense of forbearance or connivance, and it is supposed that the person, who ought to have prevented it, did not do so. In this place knowledge implies a concurrence of will, and connivance a concurrence of design. A master therefore is not bound by the act of258 a slave, who has claimed his freedom, and done any thing in despite of his master, because the knowledge of a crime without ability to prevent it, by disclosure or some other means, cannot be construed into an act of guilt. So parents are bound by the acts of children; but only in cases where they have the children under their authority. On the other hand, altho' by having them in their power, they might have prevented their misconduct, they will not be answerable for it, unless they had a knowledge of it also. For there ought to be a concurrence of knowledge, and forbearance or encouragement to involve any one in the guilt of another's actions; circumstances all of which by a parity of reasoning may be applied to the connection between sovereigns and subjects: a connection founded on principles both of natural and civil law.
But as we’ve mentioned before, in addition to knowing about an act to be considered guilty by association, the person who knows must also have the ability to stop it. This is what the legal term means when it states that knowledge of a crime, when it’s set to be punished, is understood as forbearance or tolerance, assuming that the person who should have stopped it didn't. Here, knowledge suggests a shared willingness, while connivance suggests a shared plan. Therefore, an owner isn’t responsible for the actions of a slave who asserted their freedom and acted against their owner, because knowing about a crime without the ability to stop it, whether by revealing the information or another means, can’t be seen as an act of guilt. Similarly, parents are responsible for the actions of their children, but only when they have authority over them. Conversely, even though they could have prevented inappropriate behavior by having power over their children, they won’t be held accountable unless they also knew about it. There needs to be both knowledge and forbearance or encouragement to implicate someone in the wrongdoing of another. These principles can also be applied to the relationship between rulers and their subjects, a relationship based on rules of both natural and civil law.
III. The matter that necessarily comes next under consideration is the case of those, who screen delinquents from punishment. It was before observed that, according to the law of nature, no one could inflict punishment, but a person entirely free from the guilt of the crime which he was going to punish. But since established governments were formed, it has been a settled rule, to leave the offences of individuals, which affect their own community, to those states themselves, or to their rulers, to punish or pardon them at their discretion. But they have not the same plenary authority, or discretion, respecting offences, which affect society at large, and which other independent states or their rulers have a right to punish, in the same manner, as in every country popular actions are allowed for certain misdemeanors. Much less is any state at liberty to pass over in any of its subjects crimes affecting other independent states or sovereigns. On which account any sovereign state or prince has a right to require another power to punish any of its subjects offending in the above named respect: a right essential to the dignity and security of all governments.
III. The next thing we need to discuss is the issue of those who protect wrongdoers from punishment. It was previously noted that, according to natural law, only someone completely free from the guilt of a crime can impose punishment on another. However, since governments have been established, it has become a standard practice for individual offenses that impact their own community to be left to those states or their leaders to punish or forgive as they see fit. They do not have the same complete authority or discretion over offenses that affect society as a whole, which can be punished by other independent states or their leaders. This is similar to how every country allows civil actions for certain misdemeanors. Even less is any state allowed to ignore crimes committed by its citizens that affect other independent states or sovereigns. For this reason, any sovereign state or ruler has the right to ask another power to punish any of its citizens who violate these standards, a right that is essential to the dignity and security of all governments.
IV. But as it is not usual for one state to allow the armed force of another to enter her territories under the pretext of inflicting punishment upon an offender, it is necessary that the power, in whose kingdom an offender resides, should upon the complaint of the aggrieved party, either punish him itself, or deliver him up to the discretion of that party. Innumerable instances of such demands to deliver up offenders occur both in sacred and profane259 history. Thus the other Israelites required the Benjamites to deliver up offenders, Jud. xx.—And the Philistines demanded of the Hebrews the surrender of Samson, as a criminal, Jud. xv.—In the same manner the Gauls made a demand that the Fabii should be surrendered for having fought against them. Sylla too, as Sallust informs us, urged Bocchus to deliver up Jugurtha, and by so doing to relieve the Romans from the bitter necessity of implicating HIM for his erroneous conduct in the same guilt with that most desperate villain. Yet all these instances are to be understood not as strictly binding a people or Sovereign Prince to the actual surrender of offenders, but allowing them the alternative of either punishing or delivering them up. For it was upon this ground, as we are informed, that the Eleans made war upon the Lacedaemonians, because the latter neglected to punish their subjects, who had committed aggressions upon that people; that is, they had neither punished nor delivered them up: for the obligation may be taken either way, that being left to the choice of the aggrieved person, or nation, in order to make the satisfaction the more complete.
IV. However, since it's not common for one state to let another state's military enter its territory claiming to punish an offender, it’s essential that the state where the offender lives either punishes him itself or hands him over to the complaining party. Numerous examples of demands to hand over offenders can be found in both religious and secular history. For instance, the other Israelites demanded the Benjamites surrender offenders, Jud. xx.—And the Philistines asked the Hebrews to turn over Samson as a criminal, Jud. xv.—Similarly, the Gauls demanded that the Fabii be surrendered for fighting against them. Sylla also urged Bocchus to hand over Jugurtha, relieving the Romans from the need to entangle him in the same guilt as that ruthless villain, as Sallust tells us. Yet, all these examples shouldn't be viewed as binding a people or Sovereign Prince to actually deliver offenders, but rather offering the option to either punish or surrender them. This was the basis for the Eleans going to war against the Lacedaemonians because the latter failed to punish their subjects who had wronged the Eleans; that is, they neither punished the offenders nor surrendered them: the obligation can be viewed in either way, left to the choice of the aggrieved individual or nation to ensure complete satisfaction.
The surrender here meant is nothing more than delivering up a citizen or subject to the power of another state to decide upon his punishment. But this permission neither gives nor takes away any right, it only removes an impediment to the prosecution of a right. Wherefore if that other people make no use of the permitted right, the offender, who has been delivered up, is in such a situation, that he either MAY or may NOT be punished: either of which may happen in the case of many offences. But the right of a state, as to the enjoyment of its own laws, and many other advantages, is not lost by any particular act without a formal decree and judgment, unless in any way it has been previously enacted, that certain acts, or certain omissions, shall amount to a forfeiture of some particular rights and privileges. In the same manner, goods, if surrendered, but not accepted, will remain the property of the former owner. But if the surrender of a citizen has been accepted, and, by some accident, the person so surrendered shall afterwards return home, he will no longer be a citizen, except by some new act of grace. What has been said of punishing or giving up aggressors, applies not only to those, who always have been subjects of the sovereign, in whose dominions they are now found, but260 to those also, who, after the commission of a crime, have fled to some place for refuge.
The surrender being discussed here is simply handing over a citizen or subject to another state's authority to determine their punishment. This transfer of power neither grants nor removes any rights; it just clears the way for pursuing a right. Therefore, if the other state doesn't take action on the right given, the surrendered person may or may not be punished, depending on the specific offense. However, a state retains the right to uphold its own laws and various benefits and does not lose these rights through an individual act unless there’s a formal decree or judgment stating that certain actions or failures to act lead to a loss of specific rights and privileges. Similarly, if goods are surrendered but not accepted, they remain the property of the original owner. But if the surrender of a citizen is accepted and, by chance, the surrendered person returns home, they will no longer be a citizen unless they are granted that status again. The principles regarding punishment or surrendering offenders apply not only to those who have always been subjects of the sovereign in whose territory they are found but also to those who have fled to seek refuge after committing a crime.260
V. Nor do the so much talked of rights of suppliants, and the inviolable nature of asylums at all weaken the argument that has been advanced. For the advantages of such protection are designed only for those, who are the victims of unmerited persecution, not for those who have committed crimes injurious to mankind, and destructive to society. Gylippus, the Lacedaemonian, as may be seen in the xiii. book of Diodorus Siculus, speaking of the rights of suppliants, says, that they were originally introduced, as measures of compassion to the unfortunate, and not a screen for malicious and wanton offenders, who have nothing but punishment to expect. And a little after he says, when such men, prompted by malice, or rapacity have plunged into evils, they have no right to talk of misfortune or to wear the name of suppliants. For that is a privilege granted by the laws of nature to the innocent, who are beaten down by the hard and oppressive strokes of ill fortune. But the refuge of compassion is withheld, where every line of a life has been marked with cruelty and injustice. Thus according to that law, which partakes of the wisdom of its divine author, asylums were open to those who had killed any one by a weapon escaping from their hand: slaves too were allowed places of refuge, but deliberate murderers, or those, who had disturbed the peaceful order of the state, found no protection even from the altar of God. Philo, in explaining this law says, that even the temple affords no refuge to the impious.
V. The so-called rights of supplicants and the sacred nature of asylums don’t weaken the argument that has been made. The benefits of such protection are meant only for those who are victims of unjust persecution, not for those who have committed crimes that harm humanity and are destructive to society. Gylippus, the Spartan, as noted in Book XIII of Diodorus Siculus, states that the rights of supplicants were originally established as acts of compassion for the unfortunate, not as a shield for malicious and reckless offenders, who should expect nothing but punishment. He further states that when such individuals, driven by malice or greed, engage in wrongdoing, they have no right to claim misfortune or to be regarded as supplicants. That privilege is reserved by the laws of nature for the innocent who are crushed by the harsh blows of misfortune. Compassion is withheld from those whose lives are marked by cruelty and injustice. Thus, according to that law, which reflects the wisdom of its divine author, asylums were open to anyone who accidentally killed someone in self-defense: slaves were also granted places of refuge, but deliberate murderers or those who disrupted the peace of the state found no protection, even at the altar of God. Philo, in his explanation of this law, says that even the temple offers no refuge to the wicked.
The more ancient of the Greeks acted upon the same principle. It is said that the Chalcidians refused to deliver up Nauplius to the Grecians, and the reason alleged was his having cleared himself of the charges made against him. There was among the Athenians an altar dedicated to Mercy; it is mentioned by Cicero, Pausanias, Servius, and also by Theophilus, and it is described at full length by Statius in the xii. book of his Thebais. The poet explains to what description of men it afforded shelter: it was, he says, to those who were driven from their homes by the calamity of war, or stripped of their kingdoms by usurpers. Tacitus in the third book of his Annals, and 60th chapter, reprobates the custom, prevailing in his time among the cities of Greece, of making it an act of religion to protect offenders from the punishment due to their261 crimes. Such offenders therefore ought either to be punished, or delivered up, or, at least, ordered to withdraw. Perseus the Macedonian king, clearing himself to Martius from the charge of screening those, who had attempted the life of Eumenes; said, "as soon as I was apprised by you of their being in Macedonia, I ordered immediate search to be made for them, peremptorily commanding their perpetual banishment from my kingdom."
The ancient Greeks operated on the same principle. It is said that the Chalcidians refused to hand over Nauplius to the Greeks, claiming he had cleared himself of the accusations against him. Among the Athenians, there was an altar dedicated to Mercy; it’s mentioned by Cicero, Pausanias, Servius, and also by Theophilus, and it's described in detail by Statius in the twelfth book of his Thebais. The poet explains who found refuge there: it was for those who had been forced from their homes by the disasters of war, or who had lost their kingdoms to usurpers. Tacitus, in the third book of his Annals and the sixtieth chapter, criticizes the practice, which was common in his time among Greek cities, of making it a religious duty to protect offenders from the punishments they deserved for their crimes. Therefore, these offenders should either be punished, handed over, or at the very least, ordered to leave. Perseus, the Macedonian king, explaining to Martius that he wasn’t protecting those who had tried to kill Eumenes, said, "As soon as I was informed by you that they were in Macedonia, I ordered a search for them and firmly commanded their permanent banishment from my kingdom."
The right of demanding the surrender or punishment of criminals that have fled into other kingdoms, has, in most parts of Europe, during the present, and the immediately preceding centuries, been generally exercised in cases, where the crimes were such as affected the safety of the state, or were attended with notorious atrocity. It has been usual to pass over, with mutual connivance, crimes of an inferior kind, except where it has been agreed to the contrary by express treaty. Nor can it be concealed that where robbers and pirates have gained a truly formidable power, it has often been deemed an act of humane policy both in Sovereign Princes, and States to exercise forbearance towards them, rather than to drive them to greater acts of desperation by treating them with all the rigour, which they deserve.
The right to demand the return or punishment of criminals who have escaped to other countries has, for most of Europe, been commonly exercised in recent and previous centuries, particularly in cases where the crimes threatened state safety or were remarkably brutal. Generally, lesser crimes have been overlooked through mutual agreement, except where there are explicit treaties stating otherwise. It’s also clear that when robbers and pirates have gained significant power, it has often been seen as a compassionate policy by both rulers and states to show restraint towards them, rather than provoke them into more desperate actions by treating them with the full severity they deserve.
VI. If the act, of which refugees and suppliants are accused, is not prohibited by the law of nature or of nations, the matter must be decided by the civil law of the country, from which they come. This was a received opinion in ancient times, as we find from the language of Aeschylus, in whose Tragedy of the Suppliants, the King of Argos, addressing a number of the daughters of Danaus, on their coming from Egypt, says, "If the sons of Egypt exercise controul over you, maintaining that they are authorised to do so by the law of the state, as being the nearest allied by blood, who can resist them? It is for you to prove that, according to the laws of your country, they have no authority over you."
VI. If the actions that refugees and those seeking help are accused of are not against natural law or international law, the issue should be settled by the civil law of their home country. This was a common belief in ancient times, as shown in the words of Aeschylus in his play, the Suppliants, where the King of Argos speaks to the daughters of Danaus, who have come from Egypt, saying, "If the sons of Egypt claim control over you, insisting they have the right to do so under state law because they are closest relatives by blood, who can oppose them? It's up to you to show that, according to your country's laws, they have no authority over you."
VII. and VIII. It has often been a celebrated topic of discussion, whether a whole community can be punished for misconduct. And this is the proper place for that inquiry.
VII. and VIII. It has often been a popular topic of discussion whether an entire community can be punished for wrongdoing. And this is the right place for that inquiry.
It was shewn in a former part of this treatise, that a body politic though it may seem to vary by a succession of new members, continues the same, as long as it retains its form. In which case it seems liable to punishment no less than individuals. On the other hand bodies262 politic seem to possess many privileges peculiar to themselves, such as having a common treasury, a common seal, laws, and other similar advantages. But there are some distinctions, which they particularly derive from the INDIVIDUALS of which they are composed. Thus we say that Universities are learned, or Garrisons brave, according to the number of learned or gallant men, which they respectively contain. Merit is a distinction of this kind, as being a gift of nature to individuals, or an individual acquirement, which no public body, OF ITSELF, can have. So that upon the death or departure of those meritorious individuals, the degree of merit, which any public society derived from their presence, must become extinct. In the same manner, the debt of punishment which is considered as arising from some act of demerit, must cease with the debt of the individual delinquents.
It was shown earlier in this document that a political body, despite changing members over time, remains the same as long as it keeps its structure. In this situation, it seems just as subject to punishment as individuals are. On the other hand, political bodies have many special privileges, such as a shared treasury, a common seal, laws, and other similar benefits. However, there are certain distinctions that come specifically from the individual members that make up these bodies. For example, we say that universities are knowledgeable or garrisons are brave based on the number of learned or courageous individuals they have. Merit is a distinction of this kind, as it’s a quality that individuals possess, either by nature or through personal achievement, which no public body can have on its own. Thus, when those outstanding individuals pass away or leave, the level of merit that any public organization gained from their presence will fade. Similarly, the obligation to face punishment resulting from wrongdoing will end with the individual offenders.
Arrian is justly commended for censuring the vengeance retorted upon the Persians by Alexander, at a time, when those, who had committed the original aggressions on the Greeks, had long been laid in their graves. He passes a like sentence upon the burning of Persepolis, as a retaliation for what the Persians had done at Athens. Such acts of retaliation, after a lapse of years, have been vindicated by some writers, as an imitation of the slow, but unerring progress of divine justice. But we must remember that the ways of God are not as our ways, nor is the exercise of his justice to be measured by our counsels. For if descendents can claim no merit for the actions of their FOREFATHERS, neither is it right they should be punished for THEIR transgressions. The consequences of merit indeed may be transmitted without injury, and therefore without injustice; but it is not so with punishments.
Arrian is rightly praised for criticizing the revenge taken on the Persians by Alexander at a time when those who had originally attacked the Greeks had long been dead. He judges the burning of Persepolis in the same light, seeing it as retaliation for what the Persians did to Athens. Some writers have justified these acts of revenge after many years, claiming they reflect the slow but certain nature of divine justice. However, we must remember that God's ways are not our ways, and His justice shouldn't be measured by our standards. If descendants can’t take credit for their ancestors' actions, it’s also unfair for them to be punished for their wrongdoings. While the benefits of good deeds can indeed be passed down without harm and, therefore, without injustice, the same cannot be said for punishment.
IX. Having thus shewn that a communication of punishment is necessarily connected with a participation in guilt, it remains to consider whether punishment can be extended to those, who are no way concerned in the crime. In order to understand this clearly, and to prevent the mistakes that may arise from a similarity of expression, where there is no similarity of facts, it will be necessary to make use of some precautions.
IX. Having shown that a communication of punishment is necessarily linked to a sharing in guilt, we should now consider whether punishment can be applied to those who are in no way involved in the crime. To fully understand this and to avoid confusion that may come from similar terms being used for different situations, it's important to take certain precautions.
X. In the first place there is a difference between a loss DIRECTLY occasioned by any act, and one resulting but INDIRECTLY from it. Now it may be called a direct injury to deprive any one of what peculiarly belongs to him as his right. An indirect injury is that which prevents263 any one from possessing what he otherwise would have done, by destroying the condition or means, which gave him such a right. As an example, Ulpian says, "if any one has opened a well in his own ground, by which the subterraneous streams of water, that would have passed to the lands of another, are cut off, here no fault is imputable to the person who has only exercised his own right." And in another place, he says, it makes a great difference, whether any one directly does an injury, or is only indirectly and unintentionally instrumental in preventing another from reaping advantages, which he would otherwise have enjoyed. And it is absurd, says Paulus, another legal authority, for men to be called rich before they possess the means of being so. Thus when the property of parents is forfeited, it is felt as an inconvenience by their children; though it cannot be considered as a direct punishment inflicted upon them, because that property would never have been theirs, unless the parents had retained it to their last breath. On which Alphenus has made a just observation, in saying, that, by the punishment of the father, children lose that which would have come to them from him, but things, which they do not receive from him, such as the gifts of nature, or those derived from any other quarter, remain untouched. Cicero relates that in this manner the children of Themistocles were reduced to want, nor does he think it unjust that the children of Lepidus should share the same fate. And he says that it is an ancient custom, and the received usage of all states, the hardship of which nevertheless was greatly softened by the laws of Rome at a later period. Thus when a whole people is implicated in the misconduct of the majority, which holds the representative character of the state, and consequently loses its civil liberties, its fortifications, and other privileges, the loss affects innocent individuals, but only in those things, which they could not have enjoyed, except as belonging to that community.
X. First, there's a difference between a loss that happens STRAIGHTAWAY because of an action, and one that happens INDIRECTLY from it. A direct injury is when someone is deprived of what rightfully belongs to them. An indirect injury, on the other hand, is one that prevents someone from owning something they would have had by damaging the conditions or means that granted them that right. For example, Ulpian states, "if someone has dug a well on their own land, cutting off the underground streams of water that would have flowed to another person's land, then that person can’t be blamed for just exercising their own right." He also mentions that it matters greatly whether someone directly causes an injury or only unintentionally helps prevent another from getting benefits they would have otherwise enjoyed. Paulus, another legal expert, notes that it's ridiculous for people to be considered wealthy before they actually have the means to be so. So when a parent's property is lost, it affects their children, though it can't be seen as a direct punishment for them, since that property would never have been theirs unless the parents kept it until they died. Alphenus rightly points out that, through the father's punishment, children lose what they might have inherited from him, but things they don’t receive from him, like natural gifts or anything from elsewhere, remain intact. Cicero recounts how the children of Themistocles fell into poverty, and he doesn't find it unfair that the children of Lepidus should face the same fate. He notes that this has been a longstanding custom, accepted by all states, although the hardship was considerably eased by Roman laws later on. So when an entire population suffers due to the wrongdoings of a majority, which represents the state and consequently loses civil rights, fortifications, and other privileges, it impacts innocent individuals, but only in ways they couldn’t have enjoyed apart from being part of that community.
XI. Besides, we must observe, that the offence of one man may sometimes occasion inconvenience or loss to another, and yet that offence may not be considered as the immediate cause of the action, which is grounded on the exercise of a right. This may be explained by an example. Thus if any one has engaged for another's debt, he brings himself into the dilemma named in the264 ancient proverb, that being bound for any one is the next stage to ruin; but it is a MAN'S OWN PROMISE, and NOT ANOTHER'S HAVING INCURRED A DEBT, that is the real cause of his obligation. For as a person, who has given security for a purchaser, is not, properly speaking, bound by the PURCHASE, but by his own PROMISE: so if any one has engaged to be responsible for a delinquent, it is his own ENGAGEMENT, and not the ACT OF THAT DELINQUENT, which creates his obligation. And hence the inconvenience of that kind which any one incurs, must be measured not by the delinquency of another, but by his own power to enter into any such voluntary engagement. In consequence of which no one can give surety to suffer death for another; because no one has such power over his own life, as to take it away himself, or to be bound to forfeit it for another. Though the ancient Greeks and Romans thought otherwise, and therefore they maintained that a surety might be put to death for any one, as may be seen in the well known story of Damon and Pythias, and hostages were frequently punished in this manner.
XI. Additionally, we should note that one person's wrongdoing can sometimes result in trouble or loss for someone else, yet that wrongdoing may not be seen as the direct cause of the action, which is based on the exercise of a right. This can be illustrated with an example. If someone guarantees another person's debt, they find themselves in the predicament referred to in the ancient saying that being responsible for someone else is a step toward ruin; however, it is a PERSON'S OWN COMMITMENT, and NOT THE FACT THAT SOMEONE ELSE HAS GOTTEN INTO DEBT, that is the true reason for their obligation. Just as a person who has provided security for a buyer is not technically bound by the Buy, but by their own Promise: similarly, if someone has agreed to take responsibility for a wrongdoer, it is their own Commitment, and not the ACTIONS OF THAT OFFENDER, that creates their obligation. Therefore, any inconvenience they face should not be assessed by another's wrongdoing, but by their own ability to enter into such a voluntary commitment. Consequently, no one can act as a guarantor to face death for another; because no one has control over their own life to the extent of taking it away or being obligated to risk it for someone else. Although the ancient Greeks and Romans believed otherwise, which is why they thought a guarantor could be executed on behalf of another, as seen in the well-known story of Damon and Pythias, and hostages were often punished in this manner.
What has been said of life may be applied to the limbs also, which no man has a right to part with, except for the preservation of the whole body. But if any one has engaged to suffer banishment, to submit to a pecuniary fine, or any other means of satisfying justice, any thing he suffers on this account will not, strictly speaking, be considered as a PERSONAL punishment, but as the performance of an agreement.
What has been said about life can also apply to the limbs, which no one has the right to give up, except to protect the whole body. However, if someone has agreed to face exile, pay a fine, or any other form of satisfying justice, anything they suffer because of that will not be considered a PERSONAL punishment in the strict sense, but rather as fulfilling a contract.
Something like this occurs in the right, which any one possesses dependent on another's will, both with respect to the right of individuals to private property, and to the more extensive right to demesnes possessed by a state. For if any one is deprived of such a thing owing to another's fault, here the executive power depriving that person, is not inflicting a punishment on HIM, but only exercising a prior right.
Something like this happens in the case of a right that anyone holds based on someone else's will, whether it's about an individual's right to private property or the broader rights to lands owned by a state. If someone is deprived of such a thing because of someone else's mistake, the authority taking it away from that person isn't punishing Him, but rather just exercising a prior right.
XII. and XIII. Having laid down these distinctions, we may observe that it is impossible that an innocent person should suffer for another's crime. This does not proceed from the reasons given by Paulus, who maintains that punishment is designed for the reformation of the offender. For it seems possible that an example may be made, extending beyond the person of the criminal himself, when it affects, in its consequences, those, who are nearly265 related to him. So that it is not for the sake of example only that punishment is inflicted, but because the obligation thereto arises from the demerit of the offending party. Now every demerit must be of a personal nature, as it proceeds from a man's own will, over which he is supposed to exercise a perfect controul.
XII. and XIII. After establishing these distinctions, we can note that it’s impossible for an innocent person to be punished for someone else’s crime. This doesn't stem from the reasons given by Paulus, who argues that punishment is meant to reform the offender. It seems possible to set an example that goes beyond the criminal himself, impacting those who are closely related to him. Therefore, punishment isn't just about setting an example; it arises from the wrongdoing of the person involved. Each wrongdoing must be personal, as it originates from an individual’s own will, which he is expected to fully control.
XIV. In the law given to the Hebrews, God threatens to avenge the impiety of fathers upon their children. But he has sovereign dominion over our lives and substance, as being his gift, which he may take away from any one, whenever he pleases, without assigning his reasons. Therefore if he thinks proper to take away by a premature or violent death the children of Achan, Saul, Jeroboam or Ahab, he is exercising over them the right of sovereignty, as well as that of punishment; imposing by that awful example the more severe penalty upon the parents. For if they survive their children, which was what the divine law had most in view, and therefore did not extend these threats beyond the time of great grand-children, a period to which the age of man might reach, it is certain that parents would be severely punished by such a sight, the most afflicting of any they could witness. Or if they should not survive such an event, to die under such an apprehension would be a great calamity.
XIV. In the law given to the Hebrews, God warns that he will hold fathers accountable for their wrongdoing against their children. However, He has complete authority over our lives and possessions, as they are His gifts, which He can take away at any time without having to explain Himself. So, if He decides to take the lives of Achan's, Saul's, Jeroboam's, or Ahab's children through an early or violent death, He is exercising His sovereign right, as well as His right to punish; imposing, through that chilling example, a more serious consequence on the parents. For if the parents outlive their children, which is what the divine law most intended to address, and thus did not extend these warnings beyond the time of great-grandchildren—a point in life to which humans might reach—it is clear that parents would suffer greatly from such a sight, the most painful of any they could witness. Or if they do not survive such an event, dying under that fear would be a significant misfortune.
But it is proper to remark that examples like those are never employed by God, except against crimes affecting his divine Majesty, as false worship, perjury or sacrilege. Indeed those threats of divine vengeance are not always enforced; especially where any extraordinary virtue shines in the characters and conduct of the children: as may be seen in the xviii. chapter of the prophesy of Ezekiel. Plutarch has discussed this topic with great eloquence in his book on the remote vengeance of God.
But it's important to note that examples like those are never used by God, except in cases of crimes that go against His divine Majesty, like false worship, perjury, or sacrilege. In fact, those threats of divine punishment aren't always carried out, especially when there’s some extraordinary virtue in the actions and behavior of the individuals involved, as seen in chapter 18 of the prophecy of Ezekiel. Plutarch has talked about this subject with great eloquence in his book on the distant vengeance of God.
As the Gospel so clearly unfolds the future punishments of the wicked, all the threats contained in that new covenant terminate in the persons of the offenders themselves. But the ways of providence in these respects are not the rule which men can follow. For God, even without any reference to crime, is the sovereign lord and disposer of human life, a commission which man is only allowed to execute against the perpetrators of certain crimes. Wherefore as that same divine law forbids parents to be put to death for the offences of children, so it exempts children from the same punishment for the actions of their fathers: a lenity which is greatly commended266 by Josephus and Philo. The same commendation is bestowed by Isocrates upon the laws of Egypt; and by Dionysius of Halicarnassus upon those of Rome.
As the Gospel clearly reveals the future punishments for the wicked, all the threats in that new covenant fall solely on the offenders themselves. However, the ways of providence aren't a guideline for people to follow. God, without regard to crime, is the supreme ruler and guide of human life, a role that people are only permitted to take on against those who commit certain crimes. Thus, just as divine law prohibits executing parents for their children's offenses, it also protects children from the same punishment for their fathers' actions—a mercy that is highly praised266 by Josephus and Philo. Isocrates offers similar praise for the laws of Egypt, and Dionysius of Halicarnassus does so for those of Rome.
XV. But if it is unjust in human laws to punish the misconduct of parents in the persons of their children, how much more severe was the law of the Persians and Macedonians extending the penalties for crimes against the state to every branch of the offender's relatives, in the most remote degree, a law surpassing all others in rigour?
XV. But if it’s unfair in human laws to punish parents for their wrongdoing through their children, how much harsher was the law of the Persians and Macedonians that applied penalties for crimes against the state to all of the offender's relatives, even those very distant? This law was stricter than any others.
XVI. XVII. and XVIII. What has been said respecting the punishment of children for the offences of their fathers or forefathers, may be applied to the relation subsisting between sovereigns and subjects. For it is a relation springing from the contract of society, which makes the sovereign the essential head, life and soul of that body, in which his people form the members. As the civil community therefore with its sovereign or head forms but one body, there can be no separation of interests, but what affects one part must be prejudicial or serviceable to the whole.
XVI. XVII. and XVIII. What has been said about punishing children for their fathers' or ancestors' wrongdoings can also be applied to the relationship between rulers and their citizens. This relationship arises from the social contract, which makes the ruler the essential leader, life, and spirit of the group, where the people are the members. Since the civil community and its leader form one body, there can't be a separation of interests; what affects one part must either harm or benefit the whole.
XIX. Why should an heir, it has been sometimes asked, be bound by other debts of his ancestor, and not feel the effects of his punishment for misconduct? to which answer may be given, that the heir represents the person of the deceased not in his merits or demerits, which are purely personal, but in his property; an artificial mode of preserving unbroken the chain of succession and descent.
XIX. Why should an heir, it has been asked at times, be responsible for their ancestor's debts and not face consequences for their wrongdoing? The answer is that the heir represents the deceased person not in their virtues or faults, which are entirely personal, but in their property; it's a way to maintain the continuity of succession and inheritance.
XX. And hence it follows, that if in addition to the demerit of an offence, any new grounds of obligation should arise connected with the punishment, they must be discharged not properly as a punishment, but as a debt. Thus the heir will be liable to pay the costs awarded by a judgment after a contested suit, which is considered in the light of a contract.
XX. Therefore, it follows that if, along with the wrong of an offense, any new obligations arise related to the punishment, they must be fulfilled not as a punishment, but as a debt. Thus, the heir will have to pay the costs awarded by a judgment after a contested lawsuit, which is viewed as a contract.
CHAPTER XXII.
On the Unjust Causes of War.
Differences between real and colourable motives—War atrocious without either of these motives—Wars of plunder, under the most plausible pretexts, not justifiable—Causes apparently, but not really just—Unnecessary advantage—Desire of a better soil—Discovery of things belonging to others—Incapacity of the original owners—War not always justifiable under the pretext of asserting liberty—Or of imposing a beneficial government upon a people against their will—Emperor's pretensions to universal empire refuted—Pretensions of the Church—Imperfect obligations—Difference between wars originally unjust and those afterwards becoming so.
Differences between true and superficial motives—War is brutal regardless of these motives—Wars fought for gain, even with persuasive excuses, aren't justifiable—Causes that seem fair but aren't really—Unnecessary advantages—A desire for better land—Taking what belongs to others—The inability of the original owners to defend it—War isn't always justifiable just because it claims to be about freedom—Or when trying to impose a supposedly beneficial government on people against their will—The Emperor's claims to world domination are proven false—Claims made by the Church—Imperfect obligations—The distinction between initially unjust wars and those that later become unjust.
I. In a former part of this work, where the justice of war was discussed, it was observed that some wars were founded upon real motives and others only upon colourable pretexts. This distinction was first noticed by Polybius, who calls the pretexts, προφασεις {prophaseis}, and the real causes, αἰτιας {aitias}. Thus Alexander made war upon Darius, under the pretence of avenging the former wrongs done by the Persians to the Greeks. But the real motive of that bold and enterprising hero, was the easy acquisition of wealth and dominion, which the expeditions of Xenophon and Agesilaus had opened to his view.
I. In an earlier section of this work, where the justice of war was discussed, it was noted that some wars are based on genuine motives while others are just smoke and mirrors. This distinction was first pointed out by Polybius, who refers to the pretexts as excuses {prophaseis} and the real causes as αἰτιας {aitias}. For instance, Alexander waged war against Darius, claiming it was to avenge the wrongs the Persians inflicted on the Greeks. However, the true motivation of that bold and ambitious hero was the easy gain of wealth and power that the campaigns of Xenophon and Agesilaus had revealed to him.
In the same manner, a dispute about Saguntum furnished the Carthaginians with COLOURABLE MOTIVES for the second Punic war, but, in REALITY, they could not brook the indignity of having consented to a treaty, which the Romans had extorted from them at an unfavourable moment; and more especially as their spirits were revived by their recent successes in Spain. The real causes assigned by Thucydides for the Peloponnesian war, were the jealousies entertained by the Lacedaemonians of the then growing power of the Athenians, though the quarrels of the Corcyreans, Potidaens, and other secondary states were made the ostensible reasons.
In a similar way, a conflict over Saguntum gave the Carthaginians some PLAUSIBLE REASONS for the second Punic War, but, in TRUTH, they couldn't handle the embarrassment of having agreed to a treaty that the Romans forced on them at a bad time; especially since their morale was lifted by their recent victories in Spain. The real reasons Thucydides gave for the Peloponnesian War were the jealousy the Lacedaemonians felt toward the rising power of the Athenians, despite the fact that the disputes among the Corcyreans, Potidaens, and other smaller states were used as the official justifications.
II. There are some who have neither ostensible reasons, nor just causes to plead for their hostilities, in which, as Tacitus says, they engage from the pure love of enterprise and danger. A disposition to which Aristotle268 gives the name of ferocity. And in the last book of his Nicomachean Ethics, he calls it a bloody cruelty to convert friends into enemies, whom you may slaughter.
II. There are some who have no clear reasons or valid justifications for their conflicts; they simply fight out of a love for adventure and danger, as Tacitus points out. Aristotle refers to this attitude as ferocity268. In the final book of his Nicomachean Ethics, he describes it as a brutal cruelty to turn friends into enemies whom you can then harm.
III. Though most powers, when engaging in war, are desirous to colour over their real motives with justifiable pretexts, yet some, totally disregarding such methods of vindication, seem able to give no better reason for their conduct, than what is told by the Roman Lawyers of a robber, who being asked, what right he had to a thing, which he had seized, replied, it was his own, because he had taken it into his possession? Aristotle in the third book of his Rhetoric, speaking of the promoters of war, asks, if it is not unjust for a neighbouring people to be enslaved, and if those promoters have no regard to the rights of unoffending nations? Cicero, in the first book of his Offices, speaks in the same strain, and calls "the courage, which is conspicuous in danger and enterprise, if devoid of justice, absolutely undeserving of the name of valour. It should rather be considered as a brutal fierceness outraging every principle of humanity."
III. While most powers, when going to war, try to cover up their true motives with justifiable reasons, there are some that completely ignore such attempts at justification and can only offer the same excuse as a robber cited by Roman lawyers, who, when asked about his right to something he had stolen, simply said it was his because he had taken it. Aristotle, in the third book of his Rhetoric, questions whether it's not unjust for a neighboring people to be enslaved and whether those who advocate for war give any thought to the rights of innocent nations. Cicero, in the first book of his Offices, expresses a similar sentiment, stating that "the courage displayed in danger and bold ventures, if lacking justice, is entirely unworthy of being called valor. Instead, it should be viewed as a brutal savagery that violates every principle of humanity."
IV. Others make use of pretexts, which though plausible at first sight, will not bear the examination and test of moral rectitude, and, when stripped of their disguise, such pretexts will be found fraught with injustice. In such hostilities, says Livy, it is not a trial of right, but some object of secret and unruly ambition, which acts as the chief spring. Most powers, it is said by Plutarch, employ the relative situations of peace and war, as a current specie, for the purchase of whatever they deem expedient.
IV. Some people use excuses that seem convincing at first, but don’t hold up under moral scrutiny. When you look closely, these excuses reveal their underlying injustice. In such conflicts, Livy says, it’s not really about what’s right, but rather driven by hidden and uncontrollable ambitions. Plutarch notes that most powers treat peace and war like currency, using them to obtain whatever they find convenient.
By having before examined and established the principles of just and necessary war, we may form a better idea of what goes to constitute the injustice of the same. As the nature of things is best seen by contrast, and we judge of what is crooked by comparing it with what is straight. But for the sake of perspicuity, it will be necessary to treat upon the leading points.
By first examining and establishing the principles of just and necessary war, we can better understand what makes a war unjust. Since we understand things best by comparing them, we judge what is wrong by looking at what is right. However, to make it clear, we need to focus on the main points.
It was shewn above that apprehensions from a neighbouring power are not a sufficient ground for war. For to authorize hostilities as a defensive measure, they must arise from the necessity, which just apprehensions create; apprehensions not only of the power, but of the intentions of a formidable state, and such apprehensions as amount to a moral certainty. For which reason the opinion of those is by no means to be approved of, who lay down as a269 just ground of war, the construction of fortifications in a neighbouring country, with whom there is no existing treaty to prohibit such constructions, or the securing of a strong hold, which may at some future period prove a means of annoyance. For as a guard against such apprehensions, every power may construct, in its own territory, strong works, and other military securities of the same kind, without having recourse to actual war. One cannot but admire the character, which Tacitus has drawn of the Chauci, a noble and high-spirited people of Germany, "who, he says, were desirous of maintaining their greatness by justice, rather than by acts of ungovernable rapacity and ambition—provoking no wars, invading no countries, spoiling no neighbours to aggrandize themselves,—yet, when necessity prompted, able to raise men with arms in their hands at a moment's warning—a great population with a numerous breed of horses to form a well mounted cavalry—and, with all these advantages, upholding their reputation in the midst of peace."
It was shown above that fears from a neighboring power are not a valid reason for war. To justify military action as a defensive measure, these fears must stem from a necessity that genuine concerns create; concerns not only about the power itself but also about the intentions of a formidable state, and such concerns must amount to a moral certainty. For this reason, we should not approve of those who argue that the construction of fortifications in a neighboring country, with which there is no existing treaty to prohibit such constructions, or the securing of a stronghold that might at some point become a source of trouble, is a just cause for war. As a protection against such fears, every power can build strong defenses and other military protections in its own territory without resorting to actual warfare. One cannot help but admire the portrayal of the Chauci by Tacitus, a noble and spirited people of Germany, "who, he says, wanted to maintain their greatness through justice rather than through uncontrollable greed and ambition—provoking no wars, invading no lands, plundering no neighbors to enrich themselves—yet, when necessary, able to rally men with weapons at a moment’s notice—a large population with a plentiful supply of horses to form a well-mounted cavalry—and, with all these advantages, maintaining their reputation in times of peace."
VI.55 Nor can the advantage to be gained by a war be ever pleaded as a motive of equal weight and justice with necessity.
VI.55 The benefits of war can never be argued as a reason that holds the same weight and fairness as necessity.
VII. and VIII. Neither can the desire of emigrating to a more favourable soil and climate justify an attack upon a neighbouring power. This, as we are informed by Tacitus, was a frequent cause of war among the ancient Germans.
VII. and VIII. Nor can the desire to move to a better land and climate justify an attack on a neighboring power. This, as we learn from Tacitus, was a common reason for war among the ancient Germans.
IX. There is no less injustice in setting up claims, under the pretence of newly discovered titles, to what belongs to another.
IX. There's just as much injustice in making claims, under the guise of newly discovered titles, to what belongs to someone else.
Neither can the wickedness, and impiety, nor any other incapacity of the original owner justify such a claim. For the title and right by discovery can apply only to countries and places, that have no owner.
Neither the wickedness and impiety nor any other failure of the original owner can justify such a claim. The title and right by discovery can only apply to countries and places that have no owner.
X. Neither moral nor religious virtue, nor any intellectual excellence is requisite to form a good title to property. Only where a race of men is so destitute of reason as to be incapable of exercising any act of ownership, they can hold no property, nor will the law of charity require that they should have more than the necessaries of life. For the rules of the law of nations can only be applied to those, who are capable of political or commercial intercourse: but not to a people entirely destitute of reason, though it is a matter of just doubt, whether any such is to be found.
X. You don’t need moral or religious virtue or any intellectual excellence to have a legitimate claim to property. Only if a group of people is so lacking in reason that they can’t exercise any ownership rights can they be considered to have no property. The law of charity won’t require that they have more than what’s necessary to live. The principles of international law apply only to those who can engage in political or business interactions, not to a people completely lacking reason, although it’s truly debatable whether such a group even exists.
270 It was an absurdity therefore in the Greeks to suppose, that difference of manners, or inferiority of intellect made those, whom they were pleased to call barbarians, their natural enemies. But as to atrocious crimes striking at the very root and existence of society, the forfeiture of property ensuing from thence is a question of a different nature, belonging to punishments, under the head of which it was discussed.
270 It was ridiculous for the Greeks to think that differences in customs or lower intelligence made those they labeled as barbarians their natural enemies. However, when it comes to serious crimes that threaten the very foundation and existence of society, the loss of property that follows is a different issue, which relates to punishments and was addressed under that topic.
XI. But neither the independence of individuals, nor that of states, is a motive that can at all times justify recourse to arms, as if all persons INDISCRIMINATELY had a natural right to do so. For where liberty is said to be a natural right belonging to all men and states, by that expression is understood a right of nature, antecedent to every human obligation or contract. But in that case, liberty is spoken of in a negative sense, and not by way of contrast to independence, the meaning of which is, that no one is by the law of nature doomed to servitude, though he is not forbidden by that law to enter into such a condition. For in this sense no one can be called free, if nature leaves him not the privilege of chusing his own condition: as Albutius pertinently remarks, "the terms, freedom and servitude are not founded in the principles of nature, but are names subsequently applied to men according to the dispositions of fortune." And Aristotle defines the relations of master and servant to be the result of political and not of natural appointment. Whenever therefore the condition of servitude, either personal or political, subsists, from lawful causes, men should be contented with that state, according to the injunction of the Apostle, "Art thou called, being a servant, let not that be an anxious concern?"
XI. However, neither the independence of individuals nor that of states is a reason that can always justify taking up arms, as if everyone Indiscriminately had a natural right to do so. When we say that liberty is a natural right belonging to all people and states, we mean a right that exists before any human obligation or contract. In this context, liberty is understood in a negative sense, not in contrast to independence, meaning that no one is naturally condemned to servitude, even though the law of nature doesn’t prevent someone from entering that condition. In this sense, no one can be considered free if nature does not allow them the privilege of choosing their own state: as Albutius wisely points out, "the terms freedom and servitude are not based on natural principles, but are names later given to people based on their circumstances." Aristotle also defines the relationships of master and servant as the result of political, not natural, arrangements. Therefore, whenever servitude exists, whether personal or political, for lawful reasons, people should accept that state, following the Apostle's instruction: "If you are called while a servant, don't let it worry you."
XII. And there is equal injustice in the desire of reducing, by force of arms, any people to a state of servitude, under the pretext of its being the condition for which they are best qualified by nature. It does not follow that, because any one is fitted for a particular condition, another has a right to impose it upon him. For every reasonable creature ought to be left free in the choice of what may be deemed useful or prejudicial to him, provided another has no just right to a controul over him.
XII. There is just as much injustice in trying to force any group of people into a state of servitude, claiming it’s what they’re naturally suited for. Just because someone is capable of a certain position doesn’t mean someone else has the right to impose it on them. Every rational being should be free to choose what they find beneficial or harmful, as long as no one else has a legitimate claim to control them.
The case of children has no connection with the question, as they are necessarily under the discipline of others.
The situation with children is unrelated to the issue, as they are always under the control of others.
271 XIII. It would scarce have been necessary to refute the foolish opinion of some, who have ascribed to the Roman Emperors dominion over the most remote and unknown nations, if Bartolus, deemed a lawyer of the first eminence, had not pronounced it heresy to deny those pretensions. This opinion has been built upon the Roman Emperor's some times having styled himself Sovereign of the whole world; a term which it was not unusual for many people to apply to their own country. Thus in the scriptures we find Judea frequently called the whole inhabited earth; therefore when the Jews, in their proverbial expression, called Jerusalem the centre of the world, nothing more is to be implied than that it was situated in the middle of Judea.
271 XIII. It would hardly have been necessary to counter the foolish belief of some who claim that the Roman Emperors had power over the most distant and unknown nations if Bartolus, recognized as a top lawyer, hadn't deemed it heresy to reject those claims. This belief is based on instances where the Roman Emperor referred to himself as the Sovereign of the whole world; a title that many people often used to describe their own country. Similarly, in the scriptures, we see Judea frequently referred to as the entire inhabited earth; thus, when the Jews mentioned Jerusalem as the center of the world, it simply meant that it was located in the middle of Judea.
As to the argument in favor of universal dominion from its being so beneficial to mankind, it may be observed that all its advantages are counterbalanced by still greater disadvantages. For as a ship may be built too large to be conveniently managed, so an empire may be too extensive in population and territory to be directed and governed by one head. But granting the expediency of universal empire, that expediency cannot give such a right, as can be acquired only by treaty or conquest. There were many places formerly belonging to the Roman Empire, over which the Emperor has at present no controul. For war, treaty, or cession have made many changes, by which the rights of territory have passed to other states or sovereign princes, and the standards of different communities, whether kingdoms or commonwealths, now wave in places, which the Roman Eagle once overshadowed with his wings. These are losses and changes, that have been experienced by other powers no less than that, which was once mistress of the world.
Regarding the argument for universal rule based on its benefits to humanity, it should be noted that all its advantages are outweighed by even greater disadvantages. Just as a ship can be too large to manage efficiently, an empire can be too vast in population and territory to be effectively directed and governed by a single leader. However, even if we accept the idea of a universal empire as practical, that practicality cannot create the right to it, which can only be established through treaties or conquests. There were many regions that once belonged to the Roman Empire that the Emperor no longer controls. Wars, treaties, and cessions have led to numerous changes, transferring territorial rights to other states or sovereign rulers, and the flags of different communities, whether kingdoms or republics, now fly in places once dominated by the Roman Eagle. These are losses and changes that have affected other powers just as much as those that impacted the one that was once the ruler of the world.
XIV. But there have been some, who have asserted the rights of the church over unknown parts of the world, though the Apostle Paul himself has expressly said that Christians were not to judge those who were without the pale of their own community. And though the right of judging, which belonged to the Apostles, might in some cases apply to worldly concerns, yet in its general nature it was of a celestial rather than an earthly kind—a judgment not exercised by fire and sword, but by the word of God, proposed to all men and adapted to their peculiar circumstances—a judgment exercised by displaying or withholding the seals of divine grace, as it272 might be most expedient—lastly, it was a judgment exercised in supernatural punishments; in punishments proceeding from God, like the punishments of Ananias, Elymas, Hymenaeus, and others.
XIV. However, some people have claimed the church's authority over parts of the world that are unknown, even though the Apostle Paul clearly stated that Christians shouldn’t judge those outside their own community. While the Apostles had the right to judge, and this might sometimes apply to worldly matters, in general, it was of a spiritual nature rather than a worldly one—a judgment not carried out by violence or force, but by the word of God, offered to everyone and suited to their specific situations—a judgment made by either granting or withholding the signs of divine grace, according to what was most appropriate—finally, it was a judgment that involved supernatural punishments; punishments coming from God, like those experienced by Ananias, Elymas, Hymenaeus, and others.
Christ himself, the spring, from whence all the power of the church was derived, and whose life is the model for the church to follow, said, his kingdom was not of this world, that is, was not of the same nature, with other kingdoms, otherwise, like the rest of sovereigns, he would have maintained his authority by the power of the sword. For if he had pleased to call up the aid of Legions; he would have called up hosts of Angels and not of men. And every exercise of his right was performed by the influence of divine, and not of human power; even when he drove the sellers out of the temple. For the ROD was the EMBLEM and not the INSTRUMENT of divine wrath, as UNCTION was once a SIGN of healing, and not the HEALING POWER ITSELF. St. Augustin on the xviii Chapter of St. John, and 36 ver. invites Sovereign Princes into this kingdom, in these terms, "Hear, O Jews, and Gentiles, hear, O earthly Sovereigns, I will not obstruct your authority, for my kingdom is not of this world. Be not alarmed, like Herod, who trembled, when he heard that Christ was born, and slew so many innocent children, hoping to include the Saviour in that calamity. His fear shewed itself in cruel wrath. But my kingdom, says Christ, is not of this world. Therefore enter this kingdom without fear. Come with faith, and provoke not the king to anger by your delay."
Christ himself, the source of all the church's power and whose life serves as the example for the church to follow, said that his kingdom was not of this world. This means it was different in nature from other kingdoms; otherwise, like other rulers, he would have maintained his authority through the use of force. If he had wanted to, he could have summoned legions of angels instead of men. Every act of his authority was carried out through divine influence, not human power, even when he drove the sellers out of the temple. The rod was a symbol, not the tool of divine wrath, just as anointing was once a sign of healing, not the healing power itself. St. Augustine, in the 18th chapter of St. John, verse 36, invites earthly rulers into this kingdom, stating, "Listen, O Jews and Gentiles, listen, O earthly rulers, I will not hinder your authority, for my kingdom is not of this world. Do not be alarmed like Herod, who trembled when he heard that Christ was born and killed many innocent children, hoping to include the Savior in that tragedy. His fear was evident in his cruel anger. But my kingdom, says Christ, is not of this world. So enter this kingdom without fear. Come with faith, and do not provoke the king to anger by delaying."
XV. There is a caution too necessary to be given, against drawing too close a parallel between ancient and modern times. For it is but seldom that any one can adduce a case exactly conformable to his own circumstances. To draw such pretexts from the interpretation of prophecy is the highest presumption. For no prophecy that is yet to be fulfilled can be unfolded without the aid of a prophetic spirit. The times even of events, that are certain, may escape our notice. Nor is it every prediction, unless it be accompanied with an express command from God, that can justify recourse to arms: sometimes indeed God brings his predicted designs to their issue by the means of wicked instruments.
XV. There's a crucial warning to consider: we shouldn't draw too close a comparison between ancient and modern times. It's rare for anyone to find a situation that exactly matches their own circumstances. Using such reasons based on interpreting prophecy is quite presumptuous. No prophecy that is yet to be fulfilled can be understood without the guidance of a prophetic spirit. Even the timing of events that are certain can slip by unnoticed. Not every prediction, unless it comes with a clear command from God, can justify taking up arms; sometimes God accomplishes His foretold plans through wicked means.
XVI. As the imperfect obligations of charity, and other virtues of the same kind are not cognizable in a court of justice, so neither can the performance of them be compelled273 by force of arms. For it is not the moral nature of a duty that can enforce its fulfillment, but there must be some legal right in one of the parties to exact the obligation. For the moral obligation receives an additional weight from such a right. This obligation therefore must be united to the former to give a war the character of a just war. Thus a person who has conferred a favour, has not, strictly speaking, a RIGHT to demand a return, for that would be converting an act of kindness into a contract.
XVI. Just as the imperfect obligations of charity and other similar virtues can’t be enforced in a court of law, their performance also can’t be compelled by the use of force. It’s not the moral nature of a duty that ensures it gets fulfilled; there needs to be some legal right for one party to insist on the obligation. The moral obligation gains extra significance from such a right. Therefore, this obligation must be linked to the previous one to give a war the status of a just war. So, a person who has done someone a favor doesn’t strictly have a OK to ask for something in return, as that would turn an act of kindness into a contract.273
XVII. It is necessary to observe that a war may be just in its origin, and yet the intentions of its authors may become unjust in the course of its prosecution. For some other motive, not unlawful IN ITSELF, may actuate them more powerfully than the original right, for the attainment of which the war was begun. It is laudable, for instance, to maintain national honour; it is laudable to pursue a public or a private interest, and yet those objects may not form the justifiable grounds of the war in question.
XVII. It’s important to note that a war can start with just intentions, but as it continues, the reasons behind it may become unjust. A different motive, which isn’t illegal in itself, could drive the leaders more strongly than the original right that led to the war. For example, defending national honor is admirable; pursuing a public or private interest is commendable too, but those goals might not be valid reasons for the war in question.
A war may gradually change its nature and its object from the prosecution of a right to the desire of seconding or supporting the aggrandizement of some other power. But such motives, though blamable, when even connected with a just war, do not render the war ITSELF unjust, nor invalidate its conquests.
A war can slowly shift in its purpose and goals from fighting for a right to trying to help another power grow stronger. But while these motivations may be questionable, even if related to a just war, they do not make the war ITSELF unjust or nullify its victories.
CHAPTER XXIII.
On Questionable Causes.
Origin of moral doubts—The dictates of conscience, though erroneous, not to be violated—Opposite opinions supported by argument, or by authority—In doubtful and important matters the safer side of the question to be followed—In such cases it is right to abstain from war—Disputes settled by conference or arbitration—Christian duties—Whether single combat is allowable in order to avoid war—In cases of equal doubt the claims of the present possessor to be preferred—Where neither party is in possession, claims to be divided—Whether a war can be just on both sides, explained by a distinction.
The source of moral doubts—We shouldn’t ignore the demands of our conscience, even if they’re misguided—Conflicting perspectives can be supported by logic or authority—In uncertain and important matters, it’s better to lean toward the safer option—In these cases, it’s best to avoid war—Conflicts should be settled through dialogue or mediation—Christian obligations—Is personal combat acceptable to prevent war?—In situations where uncertainty is equal, the rights of the current possessor should take priority—When neither side has possession, claims should be divided equally—The question of whether war can be justified by both sides is clarified by making a distinction.
I. There is much truth in Aristotle's observation that moral reasonings can never amount to the certainty of mathematical demonstration. Because in mathematical reasoning, all the figures are considered in the abstract, purely by themselves, and without relation to the circumstances of time or place, so that there is nothing to warp the judgment from the object immediately under consideration. Besides the figures in general form a direct contrast to each other. Thus, for instance, there is no intermediate line between a straight line and a curve.
I. There is a lot of truth in Aristotle's observation that moral reasoning can never reach the certainty of mathematical proof. In mathematical reasoning, all the shapes are looked at in an abstract way, purely on their own, and without considering the specific time or place, ensuring that nothing distorts the judgment of the object being analyzed. Additionally, the shapes in general stand in direct contrast to one another. For example, there is no in-between line between a straight line and a curve.
But it is not so in morals, where the least circumstances vary the subject, and admit a latitude of interpretation, settling the points of truth and justice between two extremes. So that between what is right and what is unlawful there is a middle space, where it is easy to incline to the one side, or to the other. This occasions an ambiguity somewhat like the difficulty of deciding the precise moment, where the twilight begins, and where it ends. From hence Aristotle concludes that it is sometimes difficult to determine, between two extremes, what line of conduct ought to be chosen or rejected.
But it's different with morals, where even the smallest details change the subject and allow for a range of interpretations, determining the points of truth and justice between two extremes. So, there's a middle ground between what is right and what is unlawful, making it easy to lean towards one side or the other. This creates ambiguity similar to the challenge of pinpointing the exact moment when twilight starts and when it ends. From this, Aristotle concludes that it can be difficult to decide which course of action should be chosen or avoided between two extremes.
II. But it must be laid down as a necessary principle, that although an action may in reality be just, yet if the party doing it, after weighing every circumstance, cannot reconcile the act to his conscience, he incurs some degree of guilt. "For whatever is not of faith, says the Apostle, is sin;" where, by the term faith he means a deliberate judgment of the mind. For God has given conscience a275 judicial power to be the sovereign guide of human actions, by despising whose admonitions the mind is stupified into brutal hardness. For it often happens that judgment can point out nothing certain, but hesitates; and when such doubts and hesitations cannot satisfactorily be cleared up, the rule of Cicero is a safe one to follow, who says, that it is an excellent injunction, which forbids us to do a thing of the rectitude or impropriety of which we entertain a doubt.
II. But it must be established as an essential principle that even if an action is truly just, if the person carrying it out, after considering all the circumstances, cannot align the act with their conscience, they bear some level of guilt. "For whatever is not of faith," says the Apostle, "is sin;" where the term faith refers to a deliberate judgment of the mind. God has endowed conscience with a275 judicial authority to be the ultimate guide for human actions, and ignoring its warnings leads the mind to become callous and unfeeling. It often happens that judgment reveals nothing definitive but instead leaves us in doubt; and when such uncertainties cannot be satisfactorily resolved, it's wise to follow Cicero's rule, which states that it is a sound principle to refrain from doing something if we have doubts about its rightness or wrongness.
But this rule cannot be applied, where of two things, in the choice of which there is equal doubt, the one must be done, in which case that must be selected, which seems to be the least unjust. For on all occasions, where a choice cannot be avoided, the less of two evils assumes the appearance of a virtue.
But this rule doesn't work when there's equal uncertainty between two options; in that case, you should choose the one that seems the least unfair. Whenever a choice is unavoidable, picking the lesser of two evils starts to look like a good thing.
III. But in doubtful cases, after examination, the mind seldom remains neuter, but inclines to one side, or the other, persuaded either by the merits of the case, or by respect for the judgment of those, who have delivered an opinion upon the question. Now the merits of the case are derived either from the causes, the effects, or other concomitant circumstances.
III. But in uncertain situations, after consideration, the mind rarely stays neutral; it tends to lean toward one side or the other, influenced either by the strengths of the case or by respect for the opinions of those who have weighed in on the matter. The strengths of the case come from either the causes, the effects, or other related factors.
IV. To apprehend such distinctions properly, practice and penetration are necessary, and where men have not in themselves a capacity for the active exercise of judgment it behoves them to follow the maxims of others, who are distinguished by their wisdom and experience. For, in the opinion of Aristotle, those things are probably just, or true, which seem so to all, or to the greater part of men of worth. And this is the method of judging pursued by Sovereign Princes, whose engagements in the affairs of life allow them but little leisure for study and deliberation. Thus the ancient Romans never undertook wars, till they had consulted the sacred college, established for that purpose, and the Christian Emperors scarcely ever did so without advising with the Bishops, in order to be apprized of any thing therein that might affect religion.
IV. To really understand these distinctions, practice and insight are essential. If people lack the ability to actively use their judgment, they should rely on the principles of those who are recognized for their wisdom and experience. According to Aristotle, things that seem just or true to most people or to those of high character are likely correct. This is the approach taken by Sovereign Princes, whose responsibilities leave them little time for study and careful consideration. For instance, the ancient Romans wouldn't go to war until they had consulted the sacred council set up for that purpose, and Christian Emperors rarely did so without consulting the Bishops to ensure they were aware of anything that might impact religion.
V. It may happen in many disputed points, that the intrinsic merits of the case, or the opinions of the learned, are equal on both sides. When that happens, if the matters in discussion are of no great importance, there is nothing to blame in the person, that makes his choice either way. But in matters of moment, where the lives of men are at stake, the decision should incline to the safer side, according to the proverbial maxim, which pronounces276 it better to acquit the guilty than to condemn the innocent.
V. In many debated issues, the strengths of the arguments or the views of respected experts are often about equal on both sides. When this occurs, if the topics being discussed aren't very important, there's no fault in the person choosing either way. However, in serious matters where people's lives are on the line, the decision should lean towards the safer option, following the well-known saying that it's better to let a guilty person go free than to wrongfully convict an innocent one.
VI. War then being an object of such weighty magnitude, in which the innocent must often be involved in the sufferings of the guilty, between wavering opinions the balance should incline in favour of peace.
VI. War is such an important issue, often dragging innocent people into the suffering caused by the guilty. Given the conflicting opinions, the scale should tip in favor of peace.
There are three methods, by which independent nations may settle their disputed rights without coming to the decision of the sword.
There are three ways for independent nations to resolve their conflicting rights without resorting to armed conflict.
VII. The first method is that of conference. For, in the words of Cicero, "there being two methods of deciding quarrels, the one by discussion and the other by force, the former, a peculiar characteristic of man, and the latter, of the brute creation: when the first of these methods fails, men are obliged to have recourse to the latter." Mardonius, in the Polyhymnia of Herodotus, blames the Grecians, who, being united in one language, might settle their quarrels by messengers of peace, by heralds, and negotiations, rather than by war.
VII. The first method is discussion. As Cicero said, "there are two ways to resolve disputes: one through conversation and the other through force. The first, a unique trait of humans, and the second, a trait of animals. When the first method fails, people are forced to resort to the second." Mardonius, in Herodotus' Polyhymnia, criticizes the Greeks, who, sharing a common language, could resolve their conflicts through messengers of peace, heralds, and negotiations instead of going to war.
VIII. The other method is that of compromise, which takes place between those, who have no common judge. Among innumerable instances of this kind in ancient history, we may select that given by Xenophon in his account of Cyrus, where that prince takes the king of the Indians for arbitrator between himself and the king of Assyria. The Carthaginians in their disputes with Masinissa prefer a settlement of this kind before a decision of war. Livy too informs us that the Romans themselves, in a dispute with the Samnites, made an appeal to the common allies of both.
VIII. The other method is compromise, which happens when there’s no common judge. There are countless examples of this in ancient history, like the one by Xenophon in his account of Cyrus, where Cyrus chooses the king of the Indians as the arbitrator between himself and the king of Assyria. The Carthaginians, when disputing with Masinissa, prefer this kind of settlement over going to war. Livy also tells us that the Romans, in a disagreement with the Samnites, turned to the common allies of both for a resolution.
The office of deciding wars and putting an end to the contentions of armies was assigned, according to Strabo, to the Druids of the Gauls, and upon the testimony of the same writer, it formed a part of the priestly functions among the Iberians.
The responsibility for deciding wars and resolving conflicts between armies was given, according to Strabo, to the Druids of the Gauls, and based on the same author’s testimony, it was also part of the priestly duties among the Iberians.
Surely then it is a mode of terminating their disputes, balancing their powers, and settling their pretensions worthy to be adopted by Christian Kings and States. For if, in order to avoid trials before judges who were strangers to the true religion, the Jews and Christians appointed arbitrators of their own, and it was a practice recommended and enjoined by St. Paul, how much more ought such a practice to be recommended and enforced, to gain the still nobler end of preventing the calamities of war.
Surely, this is a way to resolve their disputes, balance their powers, and settle their claims that Christian kings and states should adopt. If, to avoid trials in front of judges who didn't follow the true religion, the Jews and Christians chose their own arbitrators, and this was a practice encouraged by St. Paul, then how much more should we promote and enforce this practice to achieve the even greater goal of preventing the disasters of war.
277 These and many other reasons of no less importance might be advanced for recommending to Christian powers general congresses for the adjustment of their various interests, and for compelling the refractory to submit to equitable terms of peace.
277 These and many other equally important reasons could be put forward to suggest that Christian nations hold general congresses to sort out their different interests and to pressure those who resist to agree to fair peace terms.
IX. A third method of terminating disputes, without hostilities, was by lot, a practice commended by Dion Chrysostom in his speech on the interposition of fortune in directing affairs, and it was commended long before him by Solomon in the xviii. chapter of his Proverbs.
IX. A third way to resolve disputes without conflict was by drawing lots, a practice praised by Dion Chrysostom in his speech about the role of chance in guiding events, and it was recommended long before him by Solomon in the 18th chapter of his Proverbs.
X. Nearly related to the last named method is that of single combat, a practice recommended under the idea that by the risque of two lives a quarrel might be decided, which would otherwise have cost the blood of thousands. In Livy we find Metius addressing Tullus in the following terms, "let us try some method of determining to whom the pre-eminence shall belong, without wasting the blood of each people." Strabo says it was the practice of the ancient Greeks, and Aeneas proposed it to Turnus, as the most equitable way of settling their pretensions. It is described too as the custom of the ancient Franks.
X. Closely related to the last method is that of single combat, a practice suggested with the belief that by risking two lives, a dispute could be resolved that might otherwise result in the deaths of many. In Livy, we find Metius speaking to Tullus with the following words, "let's find a way to determine who should have the superiority, without spilling the blood of our people." Strabo notes that this was common among the ancient Greeks, and Aeneas offered it to Turnus as the fairest way to settle their claims. It is also described as the custom of the ancient Franks.
XI. Although in doubtful cases, both sides are bound to devise every means of avoiding hostilities, yet it is a duty more incumbent upon the claimant than upon the immediate possessor of whatever may be the subject of dispute. For it is a rule not only of civil, but of natural law, that, where the pretensions are equal, those of the possessor are to be preferred.
XI. Even in uncertain situations, both parties are required to try everything possible to avoid conflict, but it's a greater responsibility for the claimant than for the current holder of whatever is in question. It's a principle of both civil and natural law that when claims are equal, the holder's claims take precedence.
To the foregoing remarks an additional observation may be made, that if any one, knowing his pretensions to be just, cannot produce sufficient proofs to convict the intruder of injustice, he cannot lawfully have recourse to arms, because he has no OSTENSIBLE RIGHT, by which he can compel the intruder to relinquish the possession.
To add to what has already been said, it's worth noting that if someone, believing they are right, cannot provide enough evidence to prove the intruder is acting unjustly, they cannot legally resort to violence, because they have no APPARENT RIGHT to force the intruder to give up their hold.
XII. But where the right is ambiguous, and neither party has possession, the pretender, who refuses to divide the claims, may reasonably be charged with injustice.
XII. But when the rights are unclear, and neither party has possession, the one claiming the right, who refuses to share the claims, can reasonably be seen as acting unjustly.
XIII. From what has been said it will not be difficult to settle a much agitated question, whether, with respect to those, who are the principal movers of a war, there can be justice on both sides. For there are distinctions proper to be made in the various acceptations of the word JUST.
XIII. Based on what has been discussed, it shouldn't be hard to resolve a highly debated question about whether there can be justice on both sides in a war, particularly regarding those who are the main instigators. It's important to recognize the different meanings of the word JUST.
278 A thing is said to be just, either as to its causes, or its effects. The causes too may be confined either to justice in a PARTICULAR acceptation, or they may be extended so as to include under that name every kind of rectitude. Again, a particular acceptation may be divided into two kinds, one relating to the ACTION, and the other to the agent.56 An agent may be said to act justly, when, in what he does, he commits no breach of STRICT LAW, though his conduct may not be conformable to equity.
278 A thing is considered just based on its causes or its effects. The causes can be narrowed down to justice in a SPECIFIC sense, or they can be broadened to include all types of correctness. Moreover, a particular sense can be split into two types: one related to the ACTION and the other to the agent.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ An agent is said to act justly when, in their actions, they don't violate STRICT LAW, even if their behavior may not align with fairness.
In a PARTICULAR acceptation of the word justice, with regard to a matter in dispute, it cannot in war, any more than in legal proceedings, apply to both sides. For there can be no moral principle, commanding us, under the same circumstances, both to DO, and to ABSTAIN from a particular action. It may happen indeed that neither of two belligerent powers may act unjustly. For no one can be charged with acting unjustly unless he knows that he is doing so; but there are many, who are not aware of the nature, extent, and consequences of their measures. Thus in a law-suit, both parties may sincerely believe that they have justice on their side. For many things both in law and fact, which would establish a right, may escape the notice of men.
In a SPECIFIC sense of the word justice, when it comes to a dispute, it cannot apply to both sides in war any more than in a legal case. There can't be a moral principle that tells us to both DO and to ABSTAIN from the same action under the same circumstances. It's possible that neither of the two fighting sides is acting unjustly. No one can be considered unjust unless they know they're acting that way; however, many people are unaware of the nature, scope, and consequences of their actions. Similarly, in a lawsuit, both parties might genuinely believe they have justice on their side. Numerous legal and factual aspects that could establish a right might go unnoticed by individuals.
In a GENERAL acceptation, an action may be called just, where the agent is free from every kind of blame. Yet in many cases an agent may deviate from the strict rules of legal justice, and be liable to no blame, when that deviation is owing to unavoidable ignorance, there having been neither time nor opportunity sufficient for him to know the substance, or perhaps existence of the law. So it may happen in law-suits, that both parties are free not only from the imputation of injustice, but from all blame, especially where either of them is litigating a matter not on his own, but on another's account; as for instance where a guardian is acting for his ward, he would not be authorized in abandoning even a doubted right. Aristotle says that in matters of disputed right neither side can be charged with injustice; conformably to which opinion Quintilian observes that an upright279 pleader may be engaged on either side of the question. Aristotle further observes that passing a just judgment is an ambiguous term, signifying that a judge determines either according to the strict letter of the law, or according to the dictates of his own conscience. And, in another place, he has said that giving a wrong judgment through ignorance is no act of injustice.
In a GENERAL sense, an action can be considered just when the person acting is free from all blame. However, there are many situations where someone may stray from the strict rules of legal fairness and still not be blamed, especially if that straying is due to unavoidable ignorance, where there wasn't enough time or opportunity to understand the substance or even the existence of the law. In lawsuits, it can occur that both parties are not only free from accusations of injustice but also from all blame, particularly when one party is litigating on behalf of someone else. For example, if a guardian is acting for their ward, they aren’t allowed to abandon even a questionable right. Aristotle argues that in cases of disputed rights, neither party can be held responsible for injustice; in line with this, Quintilian notes that a fair 279 advocate might represent either side of the issue. Aristotle also points out that delivering a just judgment is an unclear term, meaning that a judge can make decisions based on the exact wording of the law or according to their own moral judgment. Additionally, he has mentioned elsewhere that making an incorrect judgment out of ignorance is not an act of injustice.
But in matters of war and peace, where such weighty and varied interests on all sides are concerned, it would be difficult to obtain a judgment purely impartial, and abstracted from all personal motives, unless there be the most clear and undeniable evidence on the points in question.
But in matters of war and peace, where such important and diverse interests on all sides are involved, it would be hard to get a judgment that is completely unbiased and free from personal motives, unless there is clear and undeniable evidence regarding the issues in question.
If we denominate a thing to be just, from its effect in conferring certain rights, in this sense it is plain that in war there may be justice on both sides. In the same manner, a sentence not strictly legal, or a possession not perfectly just may nevertheless confer certain rights.
If we call something just based on its ability to grant certain rights, then it's clear that in war, both sides can have justice. Similarly, a judgment that's not entirely legal or a possession that's not perfectly just can still grant certain rights.
CHAPTER XXIV.
Precautions Against Recklessly Going to War, Even for Just Reasons.
Relaxation of right in order to avoid war—particularly penalties—Self-preservation motive for forbearing hostilities—Prudential rules in the choice of advantages—Peace preferable to the extermination of hostile powers—Forbearance prudent in inferior powers—War not to be undertaken, but from necessity.
It's important to ease tensions to prevent war—especially through avoiding penalties. Self-preservation is the main reason to avoid conflict. We should be careful when choosing benefits. Peace is better than wiping out enemy nations. Being restrained is smart for weaker powers. War should only be fought if absolutely necessary.
I. Although it seems not to fall within the immediate province of a treatise, entitled the RIGHTS OF WAR, to enter into an investigation of other moral duties, which the relations of war and peace prescribe, yet it may not be improper slightly to touch upon certain errors, which it is necessary to obviate, in order to prevent any one from supposing, that, after establishing the right of war, he is authorized, INSTANTLY or at ALL TIMES, to carry his principles into action, and to reduce his theory to practice. So far from this, it frequently happens that it is an act of greater piety and rectitude to yield a right than to enforce it.
I. Even though it might not directly relate to a discussion titled the War Rights, it's still relevant to briefly mention some misconceptions that need to be addressed to prevent anyone from thinking that once they establish the right to go to war, they can RIGHT AWAY or at ALL TIMES act on those principles and put their theory into practice. In fact, it's often more virtuous and morally correct to give up a right than to insist on it.
It was before shewn, in its proper place how honourable it is to be regardless of our own lives, where we can preserve the lives, and promote the lasting welfare of others. A duty that should operate with greater force upon Christians, who have before their eyes continually the example of him, who died to save us, while we were enemies and ungodly. An example which calls upon us, in the most affecting manner, not to insist upon the rigorous prosecution of our justest rights, where it cannot be done but by the calamities, which war occasions. If arguments and motives like these wanted authorities, abundance of authorities might be adduced for their support.
It has been shown before, in its proper place, how honorable it is to disregard our own lives when we can save the lives of others and enhance their long-term well-being. This is a responsibility that should weigh even more on Christians, who constantly have before them the example of the one who died to save us while we were still enemies and ungodly. This example urges us, in the most poignant way, not to demand the strict enforcement of our rights when doing so would only lead to the suffering that war brings. If arguments and motivations like these needed support, there are plenty of authorities that could be cited to back them up.
II. Many reasons might be brought to dissuade us from urging the full infliction of a punishment. There is an obvious instance in the conduct of fathers, who connive at many faults in their children. But whoever, is authorized to punish another, assumes the character of a sovereign ruler, that is, of a father; in allusion to which St. Augustin, addressing Count Marcellinus, says, "O Christian Judge, fulfil the office of a pious father."
II. There are many reasons that could be used to convince us not to enforce a punishment fully. A clear example is how fathers often overlook many faults in their children. But anyone who has the authority to punish someone else takes on the role of a sovereign ruler, much like a father; to which St. Augustine, speaking to Count Marcellinus, says, "O Christian Judge, fulfill the role of a caring father."
281 Sometimes indeed men are so circumstanced, that to relinquish a right becomes not only a laudable act, but a debt of respect to that law, which commands us to love our enemies: a law to be respected and obeyed not only for its intrinsic value, but as being a precept of the gospel. By the same law, and for the same reasons, we are commanded to pray for and to promote the welfare and safety of Christian Princes and Kings, because their welfare and safety are so essential to the order, peace, and happiness of society.
281 Sometimes, people find themselves in situations where giving up a right is not just a noble act, but a way to show respect for the law that tells us to love our enemies. This law deserves our respect and obedience not only for its own worth but also because it is a principle of the gospel. Following the same law and for the same reasons, we are instructed to pray for and support the well-being and safety of Christian leaders and kings, as their well-being and safety are crucial for the order, peace, and happiness of society.
III. With respect to the pardon of offences committed against ourselves, little need be said, as it is known to be a leading clause in the code of a Christian's duty, to which he readily and freely submits, knowing that God for Christ's sake has forgiven him. Thus revealed law adds a sanction to what was known by heathens to be an amiable precept. Cicero has drawn a fine character of Caesar, in which he commends the excellence of his memory that could recollect every thing but injuries. We find many noble examples of this excellent virtue in the writings of Moses and in various other parts of scripture. These, and these motives ALONE, when they can safely be complied with are sufficient to keep the sword within its scabbard. For the debt of love and forbearance to our enemies is an obligation, which it is honourable to discharge.
III. When it comes to forgiving offenses committed against us, there’s not much to say, as it’s well-known that it's a key part of what it means to be a Christian. A Christian willingly accepts this, knowing that God has forgiven him for Christ’s sake. This revealed law reinforces what even non-believers recognized as a noble teaching. Cicero wrote an impressive description of Caesar, highlighting his remarkable ability to remember everything except for slights against him. We see many great examples of this admirable virtue in the writings of Moses and in various other parts of the scriptures. These, and these reasons SINGLE, when they can be followed without danger, are enough to keep the sword sheathed. The obligation to love and show patience to our enemies is an honorable duty to fulfill.
IV. It is often a duty, which we owe to our country and ourselves, to forbear having recourse to arms. After the college of heralds had pronounced a war to be just we are informed by Plutarch in the life of Numa, that the Senate further deliberated, whether it was expedient to undertake it. According to our Saviour's beautiful and instructive parable, a king, when he is obliged to go to war with another king, should first sit down, an expression implying an act of deliberation, and consider within himself, whether, with ten thousand men he is able to encounter one who is coming against him with twenty times that number: and if he finds himself unequal to the contest, before the enemy has entered his territories he will send an embassy to him offering terms of peace.
IV. Sometimes, it’s our responsibility to our country and ourselves to avoid resorting to violence. After the heralds declared a war to be justified, Plutarch tells us in the life of Numa that the Senate debated whether it was wise to pursue it. In a beautiful and insightful parable from our Savior, a king who must go to war with another king should first sit down, which means he should think carefully, and consider whether he can fight against an enemy who has twenty times his own number of soldiers. If he realizes he can’t win, before the enemy crosses into his land, he should send a message offering terms for peace.
V. In all cases of deliberation, not only the ultimate but the intermediate objects leading to the principal ends are to be considered. The final object is always some good, or at least the evasion of some evil, which282 amounts to the same. The means are never to be considered by THEMSELVES, but only as they have a tendency to the proposed end. Wherefore in all cases of deliberation, the proportion, which the means and the end bear to each other, is to be duly weighed, by comparing them together: a mode of comparison, in which there are three rules necessary to be observed.
V. In every situation where decisions are being made, it's important to consider not just the final goal but also the intermediate steps that lead to that main objective. The ultimate aim is usually some form of good, or at least avoiding some kind of harm, which282 is essentially the same thing. The means should never be viewed in isolation, but only in terms of how they relate to the intended end. Therefore, in any decision-making process, the relationship between the means and the end needs to be carefully evaluated by comparing them with each other: this comparison involves three essential rules that must be followed.
The first thing, in a moral point of view, to be considered is, what tendency the desired object has to produce good or evil; and, if the former has the preponderancy, we are then at liberty to chuse it.—In the second place, if it appears difficult to decide, whether the good or the evil predominates, we may chuse the object, if, in the choice and use of our means, we can give a turn to affairs, that may throw the preponderance into the scale of advantage—or lastly if the good and the evil bear no proportion to each other, nor the means, AT THE FIRST VIEW, appear adequate to the end, if, in pursuing an object, the tendency to good, compared with the tendency to evil be greater than the evil itself when compared with the good; or if the good, in comparison of the evil, be greater than the tendency to evil, in comparison of the tendency to good,57 we may decide in favour of it.
The first thing to consider from a moral standpoint is the potential of the desired object to create either good or evil; if good outweighs evil, we are free to choose it. Secondly, if it's hard to determine whether good or evil prevails, we can choose the object if we can influence the situation in a way that tips the balance toward a positive outcome. Lastly, if good and evil don't compare to each other and the means don’t seem sufficient for the goal, we can pursue the object if the tendency toward good is greater than the tendency toward evil when compared to the evil itself, or if the good, in comparison to the evil, is greater than the tendency to evil when compared to the tendency to good. In that case, we can favor the good.
283 Cicero has treated these abstruse points in a more popular and pleasing manner than abstract reasoning would allow. Applying all the beauties of eloquence to elucidate moral truth, he says, "it is the height of folly and presumption UNNECESSARILY to expose ourselves to dangers. In encountering calamities we must imitate the conduct of physicians who use gentle remedies with weakly constitutions. But in constitutions of a stronger cast, especially, in virulent disorders, they must have recourse to more powerful, though more dangerous expedients. In the same manner, a skilful pilot would not attempt to face the wind directly, but would tack about in order to avoid its fury."
283 Cicero has explored these complex ideas in a way that's more accessible and enjoyable than pure abstract reasoning allows. He uses all the beauty of language to clarify moral truths, saying, "it's foolish and arrogant UNNECESSARY to put ourselves in danger. When facing hardships, we should act like doctors who use gentle treatments for weak patients. But for stronger patients, especially with serious illnesses, they need to use more potent, though riskier, methods. Likewise, a skilled pilot wouldn’t try to sail directly into the wind, but would navigate around it to avoid its wrath."
VI. An example of evils, that ought by all possible means to be avoided, is furnished by the consultations among the states of Gaul, who, according to the account of Tacitus, deliberated, whether they should make choice of liberty or peace. By liberty is here meant civil liberty, that is, the right of governing themselves, and remaining independent states; and by peace is meant such a peace as would prevent the whole people from being exterminated, a calamity like that which befel the Jews, when their city was besieged by Titus.
VI. An example of evils that should be avoided at all costs comes from the discussions among the states of Gaul, who, according to Tacitus, debated whether they should choose freedom or peace. By freedom, we mean civil liberty, which is the right to govern themselves and stay independent states; and by peace, we refer to a peace that would prevent the entire population from being wiped out, a disaster similar to what happened to the Jews when their city was besieged by Titus.
In such cases reason itself dictates the choice of peace, as the only means of preserving life, which is the immediate gift of God, and the foundation of every blessing. So that the Almighty, as we read in his sacred volume, deems it a kindness, when instead of destroying a people, he permits them to be reduced to slavery. Therefore he admonishes the Hebrews, by the mouth of his prophet, to surrender to the Babylonians, rather than to die by pestilence and famine.
In these situations, logic tells us that choosing peace is the only way to preserve life, which is a direct gift from God and the source of all blessings. That's why the Almighty, as noted in his holy book, sees it as a mercy when, instead of annihilating a people, he allows them to be taken into slavery. He warns the Hebrews, through his prophet, to submit to the Babylonians rather than face death from disease and hunger.
What has been said of submitting to disadvantages, and some calamities for the preservation of life or liberty, may be applied to every object of dear value. As Aristides says, it is a moral duty in a storm, to save the ship by casting overboard the goods, but not the crew.
What has been said about facing challenges and hardships to protect life or freedom can be applied to everything we hold dear. As Aristides points out, it’s our moral responsibility during a crisis to save the ship by throwing the cargo overboard, but not the crew.
VII. In exacting punishment it is necessary to use the precaution of avoiding hostilities with a power of equal strength. For to avenge a wrong, or to assert a right by force of arms requires a superiority of strength. So that not only prudence, but a regard for their subjects will at all times deter rulers from involving their people in the calamities of war. A principle of justice too, the sole directress of human affairs, binding sovereigns and284 subjects to each other by their mutual interests, will teach this lesson of precaution. For reparation must be looked for at the hands of those, who bring on the calamities of wanton and unnecessary war. Livy calls that a just, which is a necessary war, and it is a pious cause, when no hope is left, but in recourse to arms.
VII. When exacting punishment, it's important to be cautious and avoid conflict with a power of equal strength. To avenge a wrong or uphold a right by using force requires being stronger. Therefore, both wisdom and concern for their people will always prevent leaders from dragging their citizens into the disasters of war. A principle of justice, which is the guiding force in human affairs and connects rulers and subjects through their shared interests, will reinforce this lesson of caution. After all, those who cause the suffering of unnecessary conflicts should be the ones to make amends. Livy calls a necessary war just, and it becomes a righteous cause when there is no hope left except to resort to arms.
VIII. It is but now and then a cause of such imperious necessity occurs, as to demand the decision of the sword, and that is, when, as Florus says, the desertion of a right will be followed by calamities far more cruel, than the fiercest wars. Seneca says, "that it is right to meet danger, when equal harm would result from acquiescing in an injury," and in this, he is supported by Tacitus, who calls "war a happy exchange for a miserable and insecure peace," and the same animated writer in another place observes, that "an oppressed people may recover their liberty by daring enterprize, and, if defeated they cannot be reduced to greater subjection than before;" a sentiment, with which Livy accords, in naming "peace, when coupled with servitude, a far more grievous calamity, than all the horrors of war." But it is not so, as Cicero says, where defeat will be attended with proscription, and victory with bondage.
VIII. Every now and then, a situation arises that demands a decision through conflict, especially when, as Florus notes, ignoring a right leads to suffering that's worse than the harshest wars. Seneca argues that it’s just to face danger when the same level of harm would result from accepting an injury. Tacitus backs this up by describing war as a better option than a miserable and uncertain peace. In another instance, he points out that an oppressed people can regain their freedom through daring actions, and if they're defeated, they can't be subjected to anything worse than they were before. Livy also agrees, stating that "peace accompanied by servitude is a far greater disaster than all the horrors of war." However, Cicero counters this, claiming that defeat can lead to exile while victory can result in servitude.
IX. Another necessary precaution relates to the TIME, when it is proper to undertake a war, which depends upon a due calculation, whether there are resources and strength sufficient to support our just pretensions. This is conformable to what was said by Augustus, that no war should be undertaken, but where the hopes of advantage could be shewn to overbalance the apprehensions of ruin. Scipio Africanus, and Lucius Aemilius Paulus used to speak in terms not inapplicable to this subject, for they said "it was never right to try the event of battle, but under extreme necessity, or favourable circumstances."
IX. Another important precaution involves the TIME when it’s appropriate to start a war, which relies on a careful assessment of whether we have enough resources and strength to support our rightful claims. This aligns with what Augustus said, that no war should be initiated unless the potential benefits clearly outweigh the risks of defeat. Scipio Africanus and Lucius Aemilius Paulus often expressed similar thoughts, stating that "it’s never wise to test the outcome of battle except in cases of dire necessity or under favorable circumstances."
The above precautions are of great use, where we hope by the dread and fame of our preparations to accomplish our object with little or no danger.
The precautions mentioned above are really helpful, as we aim to achieve our goal with minimal risk, thanks to the fear and reputation of our preparations.
CHAPTER XXV.
The Reasons for Waging War on Behalf of Others.
Sovereigns may engage in war to support the rights of their subjects—Whether an innocent subject can be delivered up to an enemy to avoid danger—Wars justly undertaken in support of confederates upon equal, or unequal terms—For friends—For any men—Omission of this duty not blamable, from motives of self-preservation—Whether war may be justly undertaken in defence of another's subjects, explained by distinctions.
Leaders can go to war to defend the rights of their people—Is it acceptable to hand over an innocent person to an enemy to prevent danger?—Wars fought properly in support of allies, whether on equal or unequal terms—For friends—For anyone—Not fulfilling this responsibility isn't blameworthy if it's for self-preservation—The question of whether a war can be justly fought in defense of someone else's people is explained by certain distinctions.
I. In speaking of belligerent powers, it was shewn that the law of nature authorises the assertion not only of our own rights, but of those also belonging to others. The causes therefore, which justify the principals engaged in war, will justify those also, who afford assistance to others. But whether any one presides over an household, or a state, the first and most necessary care is the support of his dependents or subjects. For the household forms but one body with the master, and the people with the sovereign. So the people of Israel under the command of Joshua took up arms in support of the Gibeonites, whom they had subdued. Our forefathers, said Cicero to the Romans, often engaged in war to support the rights of merchants, whose vessels had been plundered. The same Romans who would refuse to take arms for a people who were only allies, did not hesitate to assert by force of arms the injured rights of the same, when they became their subjects.
I. When discussing warring nations, it was shown that natural law allows us to assert not only our own rights but also those of others. Therefore, the reasons that justify the main parties involved in a war will also justify those who provide assistance to them. Whether someone leads a household or a state, their primary responsibility is to support their dependents or subjects. The household functions as one entity with the head, just as the people do with their ruler. For example, the people of Israel, under Joshua's leadership, took up arms to support the Gibeonites, whom they had conquered. Cicero told the Romans that their ancestors often went to war to defend the rights of merchants whose ships had been attacked. The same Romans who would refuse to fight for an allied nation did not hesitate to use force to defend the rights of those allies once they became their subjects.
II. Yet the cause of any subject, although it may be a just cause, does not always bind sovereigns or rulers to take arms: but only when it can be done without inconvenience to all, or the greater part of their subjects. For the interests of the whole community, rather than those of particular parts, are the principal objects of a sovereign's care; and the greater any part is, the nearer its claims and pretensions approximate to those of the whole.
II. However, just because a cause is just doesn't mean that leaders or rulers are always obligated to fight for it. They should only do so if it doesn't cause significant issues for all or most of their subjects. The well-being of the entire community is the main concern for a sovereign, rather than the interests of specific groups. The larger any specific group is, the more its claims and demands resemble those of the whole community.
III. Some have maintained the position, that if an enemy requires the surrender of a citizen, however innocent, the demand must unquestionably be complied with, if the state is too feeble to resist it. This opinion is strongly286 controverted by Vasquez, but if we attend to his meaning more than his words, we shall find it to be the drift of his argument, that such a citizen ought not to be rashly abandoned, while there remains any possible hope of protecting him. For as a case in point, he alleges the conduct of the Italian Infantry, who, upon receiving assurances of protection from Caesar, deserted Pompey, even before he was reduced to absolute despair: a conduct which he deservedly reprobates in the strongest terms.
III. Some people argue that if an enemy demands the surrender of a citizen, no matter how innocent, the demand must be met if the state is too weak to resist. Vasquez strongly disagrees with this view, but if we focus on what he means rather than just his words, we can see that his main point is that such a citizen should not be carelessly abandoned as long as there is any hope of saving him. As an example, he points to the behavior of the Italian Infantry, who, after receiving promises of protection from Caesar, deserted Pompey even before he was left completely hopeless: a behavior he rightly condemns in the strongest terms.
But whether an innocent citizen may be given up into the hands of an enemy to avoid imminent destruction, which would otherwise fall upon the state, is a point that HAS BEEN formerly, and IS still disputed by the learned, according to the beautiful fable, which Demosthenes told of the wolves, who demanded of the sheep the surrender of the dogs, as the only terms of peace. The lawfulness of this is denied not only by Vasquez, but by one, whose opinions that writer condemns, as bearing a near approach to perfidy. Sotus holds it as an established maxim, that such a citizen is bound to deliver himself up: this Vasquez denies, because the nature of civil society, which every one has entered into for his own advantage, requires no such thing.
But whether an innocent citizen can be handed over to an enemy to avoid imminent destruction to the state is a topic that has been previously and is still debated by scholars, according to the well-known fable shared by Demosthenes about the wolves who demanded that the sheep surrender the dogs as the only terms for peace. This idea is rejected not only by Vasquez but also by someone whose views that writer criticizes for being close to betrayal. Sotus claims it is an established principle that such a citizen is obligated to turn himself in: Vasquez disagrees, arguing that the nature of civil society, which everyone joins for their own benefit, does not require this.
No conclusion can be drawn from hence, except that a citizen is not bound to this by any RIGHT STRICTLY SO CALLED, while at the same time the law of charity will not suffer him to act otherwise. For there are many duties not properly included in the idea of strict justice. These are regarded as acts of good will, the performance of which is not only crowned with praise, but the omission of them cannot escape censure.
No conclusion can be drawn from this, except that a citizen is not obligated to this by any RIGHT STRICTLY SO CALLED, while at the same time, the law of charity doesn’t allow him to behave otherwise. There are many responsibilities that aren’t really part of the concept of strict justice. These are seen as acts of goodwill; doing them earns praise, but failing to do them cannot avoid criticism.
Such is the complexion of the following maxim, that every one should prefer the lives of an innumerable and innocent multitude to his own personal and private welfare. Cicero, in defending Publius Sextius, says, "If I were taking a voyage with my friends, and happening to meet with a fleet of pirates, they threatened to sink our little bark, unless the crew surrendered me as the victim to appease their fury, I would sooner throw myself into the deep, than suffer my companions out of their affection to me to encounter sure death, or even imminent danger."
Such is the essence of the following saying, that everyone should value the lives of countless innocent people over their own private well-being. Cicero, while defending Publius Sextius, states, "If I were on a trip with my friends and we encountered a fleet of pirates who threatened to sink our small boat unless they got me as their sacrifice to calm their wrath, I would rather jump into the sea than let my friends face certain death or even serious danger because of my safety."
But after establishing this point, there remains a doubt, whether any one can be COMPELLED to do what he is BOUND to do. Sotus denies this, and in support of his287 argument quotes the case of a rich man, who, though bound from motives of charity to supply the wants of the needy, cannot be compelled to do so. But the transactions of equals with each other, must be regulated upon principles very different from those that regulate the mutual relations of sovereigns and subjects. For an equal cannot compel an equal to the performance of any thing, but what he is strictly bound by law to perform. But a superior may compel an inferior to the performance of OTHER duties besides those of PERFECT OBLIGATIONS; for that is a right peculiarly and essentially belonging to the nature of superiority. Therefore certain legislative provisions may be made, enacting the performance of such duties, as seem to partake of the nature of benevolence. Phocion, as it is mentioned in Plutarch's lives, said that the persons, whom Alexander demanded, had reduced the commonwealth to such distress, that if he demanded even his dearest friend Nicocles, he should vote for delivering him up.
But after making this point, there’s still a question of whether anyone can be FORCED to do what they are BOUND to do. Sotus disagrees with this, and to support his287 argument, he cites the example of a wealthy man who, although obligated by charity to help those in need, cannot be forced to do so. However, the interactions between equals must be governed by rules that are very different from those that govern the relationship between rulers and their subjects. An equal cannot compel another equal to perform any action except what they are legally required to do. But a superior can compel an inferior to fulfill OTHER duties beyond just Ideal responsibilities; this is a right that is inherently part of superiority. Therefore, certain laws can be established that require the fulfillment of duties that have a benevolent nature. Phocion, as mentioned in Plutarch's lives, stated that the individuals Alexander requested had put the state in such dire straits that if he demanded even his closest friend Nicocles, he would have to vote to hand him over.
IV. Next to subjects, and even upon an equal footing with them, as to claims of protection, are allies, a name including, in its consequences and effects, both those, who have formed a subordinate connection with another power, and those who have entered into engagements of mutual assistance. Yet no such compacts can bind either of the parties to the support or prosecution of unjust wars. And this is the reason, why the Lacedaemonians, before they went to war with the Athenians, left all their allies at liberty to decide for themselves upon the justice of the quarrel. To which an additional observation may be made, that no ally is bound to assist in the prosecution of schemes, which afford no possible prospect of a happy termination. For this would be defeating the very end of alliances, which are contracted from motives of public advantage, and not for a participation in ruin. But any power is obliged to defend an ally even against those, with whom it is already connected by subsisting treaties, provided those treaties contain no express condition prohibiting such defence. Thus the Athenians might have defended the Corcyraeans, IN A JUST CAUSE, even against the Corinthians, their more ancient allies.
IV. Allies, who stand on equal ground regarding claims for protection, include both those who have formed a subordinate connection with another power and those who have entered into mutual support agreements. However, no agreements can force either party to back or engage in unjust wars. This is why the Spartans, before going to war with the Athenians, allowed all their allies to independently decide on the justice of the conflict. Additionally, it's worth noting that no ally is obligated to help pursue plans that offer no chance of a positive outcome. Doing so would contradict the very purpose of alliances, which are formed for mutual benefit and not for sharing in destruction. However, any power is required to defend an ally, even against those it has existing treaties with, as long as those treaties don’t explicitly prohibit such defense. Therefore, the Athenians could have defended the Corcyraeans, FOR A GOOD REASON, even against the Corinthians, their older allies.
V. A third case is that, where assistance has not been expressly promised to a friendly power, and yet is due on the score of friendship, if it can be given without inconvenience.
V. A third case is when assistance hasn't been explicitly promised to a friendly country, yet is owed out of friendship, as long as it can be given without causing any trouble.
288 Upon this principle Abraham took arms in defence of his kinsman Lot: and the Romans charged the Antiates to commit no acts of piracy upon the Greeks, as being a people of the same kindred with the Italians. It was no unusual thing with the Romans to begin, or at least to threaten to begin wars not only in support of allies, to whom they were bound by treaty, but in support of any friendly powers.
288 Based on this principle, Abraham took up arms to defend his relative Lot: and the Romans instructed the Antiates not to commit any acts of piracy against the Greeks, as they were of the same heritage as the Italians. It was common for the Romans to initiate, or at least to threaten to initiate, wars not only in support of allies they had treaties with, but also in support of any friendly nations.
VI. The last and most extensive motive is the common tie of one COMMON NATURE, which alone is sufficient to oblige men to assist each other.
VI. The final and most significant reason is the shared bond of one COMMON NATURE, which is enough to compel people to help one another.
VII. It is a question, whether one man is bound to protect another, or one people another people from injury and aggression. Plato thinks that the individual or state not defending another from intended violence is deserving of punishment. A case for which provision was made by the laws of the Egyptians.
VII. The question is whether one person has a duty to protect another, or whether one nation should defend another from harm and aggression. Plato believes that an individual or state that fails to defend another from intended violence deserves to be punished. This is a situation that was addressed by the laws of the Egyptians.
But in the first place it is certain that no one is bound to give assistance or protection, when it will be attended with evident danger. For a man's own life and property, and a state's own existence and preservation are either to the individual, or the state, objects of greater value and prior consideration than the welfare and security of other individuals or states.
But first of all, it’s clear that no one is obligated to provide help or protection if it poses obvious danger. The safety of one's own life and property, as well as the survival and well-being of a state, is more important and takes precedence over the welfare and security of other individuals or states.
Nor will states or individuals be bound to risk their own safety, even when the aggrieved or oppressed party cannot be relieved but by the destruction of the invader or oppressor. For under some circumstances it is impossible successfully to oppose cruelty and oppression, the punishment of which must be left to the eternal judge of mankind.
Nor will states or individuals be obligated to risk their own safety, even when the injured or oppressed party can only be saved by defeating the invader or oppressor. Because in some situations, it's impossible to effectively fight against cruelty and oppression, and the consequences of that must be left to the ultimate judge of humanity.
VIII. Though it is a rule established by the laws of nature and of social order, and a rule confirmed by all the records of history, that every sovereign is supreme judge in his own kingdom and over his own subjects, in whose disputes no foreign power can justly interfere. Yet where a Busiris, a Phalaris or a Thracian Diomede provoke their people to despair and resistance by unheard of cruelties, having themselves abandoned all the laws of nature, they lose the rights of independent sovereigns, and can no longer claim the privilege of the law of nations. Thus Constantine took up arms against Maxentius and Licinius, and other Roman emperors either took, or threatened to take them against the Persians, if they did not desist from persecuting the Christians.
VIII. Although it's a rule set by the laws of nature and society, and confirmed by all of history, that every ruler is the ultimate judge in their own kingdom and over their own people, with no foreign power justifiably intervening in their disputes. However, when a ruler like Busiris, Phalaris, or Thracian Diomede drives their people to despair and rebellion through unimaginable cruelty, having forsaken all natural laws, they forfeit their rights as independent sovereigns and can no longer claim the protections of international law. This is demonstrated by Constantine, who took up arms against Maxentius and Licinius, and other Roman emperors who either engaged or threatened to engage in conflict with the Persians if they did not stop persecuting Christians.
289 Admitting that it would be fraught with the greatest dangers if subjects were allowed to redress grievances by force of arms, it does not necessarily follow that other powers are prohibited from giving them assistance when labouring under grievous oppressions. For whenever the impediment to any action is of a personal nature, and not inherent in the action itself, one person may perform for another, what he cannot do for himself, provided it is an action by which some kind service may be rendered. Thus a guardian or any other friend may undertake an action for a ward, which he is incapacitated from doing for himself.
289 While it acknowledges that allowing people to address their grievances with force could lead to serious dangers, it doesn't mean that other powers cannot help them when they are suffering from severe oppression. Whenever the obstacle to taking action is personal and not due to the nature of the action itself, one person can do for another what they can't do for themselves, as long as the action provides some kind of service. For example, a guardian or a friend can take action on behalf of someone who is unable to do it for themselves.
The impediment, which prohibits a SUBJECT from making resistance, does not depend upon the nature of the OCCASION, which would operate equally upon the feelings of men, whether they were subjects or not, but upon the character of the persons, who cannot transfer their natural allegiance from their own sovereign to another. But this principle does not bind those, who are not the liege-subjects of that sovereign or power. Their opposition to him or the state may sometimes be connected with the defence of the oppressed, and can never be construed into an act of treason. But pretexts of that kind cannot always be allowed, they may often be used as the cover of ambitious designs. But right does not necessarily lose its nature from being in the hands of wicked men. The sea still continues a channel of lawful intercourse, though sometimes navigated by pirates, and swords are still instruments of defence, though sometimes wielded by robbers or assassins.
The obstacle that prevents a SUBJECT from resisting isn’t based on the nature of the EVENT; it affects everyone’s feelings equally, whether they are subjects or not. Instead, it relies on the character of the individuals who can’t shift their natural loyalty from their own ruler to someone else. However, this principle doesn’t apply to those who aren’t the loyal subjects of that ruler or authority. Their opposition to him or the state may sometimes relate to defending the oppressed and can never be seen as treason. However, reasons like that can’t always be accepted; they may often serve as a façade for selfish ambitions. But just because a right is held by immoral people doesn’t change its nature. The sea remains a pathway for legal trade, even if it’s sometimes navigated by pirates, and swords are still tools for defense, even if they’re sometimes used by thieves or killers.
BOOK III.
CHAPTER I.
What's Legal in War.
What is lawful in war—General Rules derived from the law of nature—Stratagems and lies—Arrangement of the following parts—First rule, all things necessary to the end lawful—Right resulting not only from the origin of a war, but from causes growing out of the same—Certain consequences justifiable, though not originally lawful—What measures are lawful against those who furnish an enemy with supplies—Stratagems—Negative—Positive—Sometimes allowable to use words in a sense different from the general acceptation—A lie according to the true notion of it injurious to the rights of others—Falsehood allowable in order to deceive children or madmen—Any one addressing another without intentions to deceive, not answerable for the misconceptions of a third person—A person not answerable for the wilful mistakes of those to whom he speaks—The fictitious threats of a person in authority—Fiction allowable in order to save the lives of the innocent, or to promote other equally important purposes—Deception lawful against an enemy, but not including promises, or oaths—To forbear using this privilege an act of generosity and Christian simplicity—Not allowable to urge others to what is unlawful for them, but not for us to do—Allowable to use the services of deserters.
What is allowed in war—General Rules based on natural law—Deception and lies—Overview of the following sections—First rule: anything necessary to achieve a legitimate goal is allowed—Rights that apply not only from the start of a war but also from its ongoing circumstances—Certain outcomes can be justified, even if they weren't originally legal—What actions are allowed against those who supply resources to an enemy—Deception—Negative—Positive—Sometimes it's acceptable to use words in a way that differs from their usual meaning—A lie, in the truest sense, harms the rights of others—Falsehoods are acceptable to mislead children or those who are mentally unstable—Anyone speaking to another without the intention to mislead isn't responsible for misunderstandings by a third party—A person isn't liable for the deliberate mistakes of those they are talking to—The imagined threats from someone in a position of authority—Fiction is acceptable to protect innocent lives or pursue other important goals—Deception is allowed against an enemy, but this doesn't include promises or oaths—Choosing not to use this privilege is an act of generosity and Christian integrity—It’s not acceptable to encourage others to do what is unlawful for them, but we can act in ways that aren't prohibited for us—Using the services of deserters is allowed.
I. Having, in the preceding books, considered by what persons, and for what causes, war may be justly declared and undertaken, the subject necessarily leads to an inquiry into the circumstances, under which war may be undertaken, into the extent, to which it may be carried, and into the manner, in which its rights may be enforced. Now all these matters may be viewed in the light of privileges resulting simply from the law of nature and of nations, or as the effects of some prior treaty or promise. But the actions, which are authorised by the law of nature, are those that are first entitled to attention.
I. In the previous books, we've looked at who can justly declare and initiate war, and for what reasons. This naturally leads us to explore the situations in which war can be started, the limits to which it can be taken, and how its rights can be upheld. All these topics can be examined through the lens of rights that arise simply from natural law and international law, or as consequences of prior treaties or agreements. However, the actions sanctioned by natural law should be the first ones we focus on.
II. In the first place, as it has occasionally been observed, the means employed in the pursuit of any object must, in a great degree, derive the complexion of their moral character from the nature of the end to which291 they lead. It is evident therefore that we may justly avail ourselves of those means, provided they be lawful, which are necessary to the attainment of any right. Right in this place means what is strictly so called, signifying the moral power of action, which any one as a member of society possesses. On which account, a person, if he has no other means of saving his life, is justified in using any forcible means of repelling an attack, though he who makes it, as for instance, a soldier in battle, in doing so, is guilty of no crime. For this is a right resulting not properly from the crime of another, but from the privilege of self-defence, which nature grants to every one. Besides, if any one has SURE and UNDOUBTED grounds to apprehend imminent danger from any thing belonging to another, he may seize it without any regard to the guilt or innocence of that owner. Yet he does not by that seizure become the proprietor of it. For that is not necessary to the end he has in view. He may DETAIN it as a precautionary measure, till he can obtain satisfactory assurance of security.
II. First of all, as has been noted from time to time, the methods used to pursue any goal must largely reflect the moral character based on the nature of that goal to which291 they lead. Therefore, it’s clear that we can rightfully use any lawful means necessary to achieve what is considered a right. In this context, “Right” refers to the moral power of action that each person has as a member of society. For this reason, an individual is justified in using any forceful means to defend themselves from an attack if they have no other options to save their life, even if the attacker, like a soldier in battle, is not committing a crime by doing so. This right doesn't stem from someone else's wrongdoing, but rather from the inherent right to self-defense that nature grants to everyone. Additionally, if someone has clear and undeniable reasons to fear immediate danger from someone else's belongings, they can take possession of those without considering the owner's guilt or innocence. However, taking something in this manner does not make them the owner. That is not necessary for achieving their goal. They can hold onto it as a precaution until they can secure assurance of safety.
Upon the same principle any one has a natural right to seize what belongs to him, and is unlawfully detained by another: or, if that is impracticable, he may seize something of equal value, which is nearly the same as recovering a debt. Recoveries of this kind establish a property in the things so reclaimed; which is the only method of restoring the equality and repairing the breaches of violated justice. So too when punishment is lawful and just, all the means absolutely necessary to enforce its execution are also lawful and just, and every act that forms a part of the punishment, such as destroying an enemy's property and country by fire or any other way, falls within the limits of justice proportionable to the offence.
Based on the same idea, everyone has a natural right to take back what belongs to them and is being wrongly held by someone else. If that’s not possible, they can take something of equal value, which is similar to recovering a debt. Taking back what’s rightfully theirs creates ownership over those reclaimed items, which is the only way to restore balance and fix the harm done to justice. Similarly, when punishment is lawful and just, all necessary means to enforce it are also lawful and just. Every action that is part of the punishment, like destroying an enemy’s property or land by fire or other means, is considered just as long as it is proportional to the offense.
III. In the second place, it is generally known that it is not the ORIGIN only of a just war which is to be viewed as the principal source of many of our rights, but there may be causes growing out of that war which may give birth to additional rights. As in proceedings at law, the sentence of the court may give to the successful litigant other rights besides those belonging to the original matter of dispute. So those who join our enemies, either as allies or subjects, give us a right of defending ourselves against THEM also. So too a nation engaging in an unjust war, the injustice of which she292 knows and ought to know, becomes liable to make good all the expences and losses incurred, because she has been guilty of occasioning them. In the same manner those powers, who become auxiliaries in wars undertaken without any reasonable grounds, contract a degree of guilt and render themselves liable to punishment in proportion to the injustice of their measures. Plato approves of war conducted so far, as to compel the aggressor to indemnify the injured and the innocent.
III. Secondly, it’s widely understood that it’s not just the SOURCE of a just war that serves as the main source of many of our rights, but there can also be issues arising from that war that create additional rights. Just like in legal proceedings, a court's ruling can grant the winning party rights beyond those related to the original dispute. Similarly, those who ally with our enemies, whether as partners or subjects, give us the right to defend ourselves against THEM as well. Additionally, a nation engaging in an unjust war, of which it is aware or should be aware, becomes responsible for covering all expenses and losses incurred due to its actions. Likewise, those nations that support wars without reasonable justification take on a level of guilt and make themselves liable to punishment according to the unfairness of their actions. Plato endorses war conducted to the extent that it forces the aggressor to compensate the harmed and innocent.
IV. In the third place, an individual or belligerent power may, in the prosecution of a lawful object, do many things, which were not in the contemplation of the original design, and which in THEMSELVES it would not be lawful to do. Thus in order to obtain what belongs to us, when it is impossible to recover the specific thing, we may take more than our due, under condition of repaying whatever is above the real value. For the same reason it is lawful to attack a ship manned by pirates, or a house occupied by robbers, although in that ship, or that house there may be many innocent persons, whose lives are endangered by such attack.
IV. Third, an individual or warring power may, while pursuing a legitimate goal, take actions that weren't part of the original plan and that wouldn't be legal by themselves. For example, to reclaim what is rightfully ours when we can't retrieve the specific item, we might take more than what is owed to us, as long as we agree to pay back whatever exceeds the actual value. Similarly, it's justifiable to attack a ship crewed by pirates or a house occupied by thieves, even if there are innocent people on that ship or in that house whose lives might be at risk from such an attack.
But we have had frequent occasion to remark, that what is conformable to right taken in its strictest sense is not always lawful in a moral point of view. For there are many instances, in which the law of charity will not allow us to insist upon our right with the utmost rigour. A reason for which it will be necessary to guard against things, which fall not within the original purpose of an action, and the happening of which might be foreseen: unless indeed the action has a tendency to produce advantages, that will far outweigh the consequences of any accidental calamity, and the apprehensions of evil are by no means to be put in competition with the sure hopes of a successful issue. But to determine in such cases requires no ordinary penetration and discretion. But wherever there is any doubt, it is always the safer way to decide in favour of another's interest, than to follow the bent of our own inclination. "Suffer the tares to grow, says our divine teacher, least in rooting up the tares you root up the wheat also."
But we've often noticed that what's legally right in the strictest sense isn't always morally acceptable. There are many situations where the law of kindness doesn't allow us to insist on our rights too harshly. This is why we need to be cautious about things that don't align with the original purpose of an action, especially if we can see they might happen. Unless, of course, the action is likely to bring benefits that far outweigh any unintended negative outcomes, and we shouldn't let worries about possible problems compete with the clear hopes for a successful result. But figuring this out takes a good deal of insight and judgment. Where there’s uncertainty, it's always safer to choose what's best for someone else rather than just following our own desires. "Let the weeds grow," says our divine teacher, "for if you pull up the weeds, you might pull up the wheat too."
The general destruction, which the Almighty, in right of his supreme Majesty, has sometimes decreed and executed, is not a rule, which we can presume to follow. He has not invested men, in the exercise of power, with those transcendent sovereign rights. Yet he himself,293 notwithstanding the unchangeable nature of his sovereign will, was inclined to spare the most wicked cities, if ten righteous persons could be found therein. Examples like these may furnish us with rules to decide, how far the rights of war against an enemy may be exercised or relaxed.
The overall destruction that the Almighty has sometimes ordered and carried out, due to His supreme authority, is not something we can take as a guideline for our actions. He hasn’t given humans the same absolute rights in wielding power. Still, He, 293 despite the fixed nature of His sovereign will, was willing to spare the most corrupt cities if even ten righteous people could be found there. Examples like these can help us understand how far the rights of war against an enemy can be applied or modified.
V. It frequently occurs as a matter of inquiry, how far we are authorised to act against those, who are neither enemies, nor wish to be thought so, but who supply our enemies with certain articles. For we know that it is a point, which on former and recent occasions has been contested with the greatest animosity; some wishing to enforce with all imaginary rigour the rights of war, and others standing up for the freedom of commerce.
V. It often raises the question of how far we are allowed to act against those who are neither our enemies nor want to be seen as such, but who provide our enemies with certain goods. We know this is an issue that has been fiercely debated in the past and recently; some want to strictly enforce the rights of war, while others argue for the freedom of trade.
In the first place, a distinction must be made between the commodities themselves. For there are some, such as arms for instance, which are only of use in war; there are others again, which are of no use in war, but only administer to luxury; but there are some articles, such as money, provisions, ships and naval stores, which are of use at all times both in peace and war.
In the first place, we need to distinguish between the commodities themselves. Some, like weapons for example, are only useful in war; others are not useful in war and are only for luxury; but some items, like money, food, ships, and naval supplies, are useful at all times, whether in peace or in war.
As to conveying articles of the first kind, it is evident that any one must be ranked as an enemy, who supplies an enemy with the means of prosecuting hostilities. Against the conveyance of commodities of the second kind, no just complaint can be made.—And as to articles of the third class, from their being of a doubtful kind, a distinction must be made between the times of war and peace. For if a power cannot defend itself, but by intercepting the supplies sent to an enemy, necessity will justify such a step, but upon condition of making restoration, unless there be some additional reasons to the contrary. But if the conveyance of goods to an enemy tends to obstruct any belligerent power in the prosecution of a lawful right, and the person so conveying them possesses the means of knowing it; if that power, for instance, is besieging a town, or blockading a port, in expectation of a speedy surrender and a peace, the person, who furnishes the enemy with supplies, and the means of prolonged resistance, will be guilty of an aggression and injury towards that power. He will incur the same guilt, as a person would do by assisting a debtor to escape from prison, and thereby to defraud his creditor. His goods may be taken by way of indemnity, and in discharge of the debt. If the person has294 not yet committed the injury, but only intended to do so, the aggrieved power will have a right to detain his goods, in order to compel him to give future security, either by putting into his hands hostages, or pledges; or indeed in any other way. But if there are evident proofs of injustice in an enemy's conduct the person who supports him in such a case, by furnishing him with succours, will be guilty not barely of a civil injury, but his giving assistance will amount to a crime as enormous, as it would be to rescue a criminal in the very face of the judge. And on that account the injured power may proceed against him as a criminal, and punish him by a confiscation of his goods.
When it comes to delivering items of the first type, it's clear that anyone who provides an enemy with the means to continue fighting should be considered an enemy themselves. There can be no valid complaint against the delivery of items of the second type. For items of the third type, which are ambiguous, we need to differentiate between wartime and peacetime. If a power can only defend itself by cutting off supplies to an enemy, necessity can justify this action, as long as they agree to restore what was taken, unless there are additional reasons not to do so. However, if delivering goods to an enemy disrupts a belligerent power that is rightfully pursuing a goal, and the person delivering those goods is aware of it—such as when that power is besieging a town or blockading a port in anticipation of a quick surrender—then the person supplying the enemy with resources that enable prolonged resistance is committing an act of aggression and harm against that power. Their actions would be akin to helping a debtor escape from prison and thereby defrauding the creditor. The goods could be confiscated as compensation for the debt. If the person has not yet caused harm but only plans to, the aggrieved power has the right to hold their goods to ensure future security, whether through hostages or pledges, or in other ways. If there is clear evidence of wrongdoing in the enemy's actions, then a person who aids them by providing support will be guilty not just of a civil wrong, but their assistance will constitute a serious crime, just like helping a criminal escape right in front of the judge. For this reason, the injured power may treat them as a criminal and impose penalties, including confiscating their goods.
These are the reasons, which induce belligerent powers to issue manifestoes, as an appeal to other states, upon the justice of their cause, and their probable hopes of ultimate success. This question has been introduced under the article, which refers to the law of nature, as history supplies us with no precedent to deduce its establishment from the voluntary law of nations.
These are the reasons that lead nations at war to issue manifestos as a way to appeal to other countries about the fairness of their cause and their chances of eventual victory. This topic has been brought up under the article that discusses the law of nature, since history provides no precedent to derive its establishment from the voluntary law of nations.
We are informed by Polybius, in his first book, that the Carthaginians seized some of the Romans, who were carrying supplies to their enemies, though they afterwards gave them up, upon the demand of the Romans. Plutarch says that when Demetrius had invested Attica, and taken the neighbouring towns of Eleusis and Rhamnus, he ordered the master and pilot of a ship, attempting to convey provisions into Athens, to be hanged, as he designed to reduce that city by famine: this act of rigour deterred others from doing the same, and by that means he made himself master of the City.
We learn from Polybius in his first book that the Carthaginians captured some Romans who were delivering supplies to their enemies, but they later released them at the Romans' request. Plutarch writes that when Demetrius had surrounded Attica and taken the nearby towns of Eleusis and Rhamnus, he ordered the captain and crew of a ship trying to deliver food to Athens to be hanged, as he intended to starve the city into submission. This harsh action discouraged others from attempting the same, which allowed him to take control of the City.
VI. Wars, for the attainment of their objects, it cannot be denied, must employ force and terror as their most proper agents. But a doubt is sometimes entertained, whether stratagem may be lawfully used in war. The general sense of mankind seems to have approved of such a mode of warfare. For Homer commends his hero, Ulysses, no less for his ability in military stratagem, than for his wisdom. Xenophon, who was a philosopher as well as a soldier and historian, has said, that nothing can be more useful in war than a well-timed stratagem, with whom Brasidas, in Thucydides agrees, declaring it to be the method from which many great generals have derived the most brilliant reputation. And in Plutarch, Agesilaus maintains, that deceiving an enemy is both295 just and lawful. The authority of Polybius may be added to those already named; for he thinks, that it shews greater talent in a general to avail himself of some favourable opportunity to employ a stratagem, than to gain an open battle. This opinion of poets, historians, and philosophers is supported by that of Theologians. For Augustin has said that, in the prosecution of a just war, the justice of the cause is no way affected by the attainment of the end, whether the object be accomplished by stratagem or open force, and Chrysostom, in his beautiful little treatise on the priestly office, observes, that the highest praises are bestowed on those generals, who have practised successful stratagems. Yet there is one circumstance, upon which the decision of this question turns more than upon any opinion even of the highest authority, and that is, whether stratagem ought to be ranked as one of those evils, which are prohibited under the maxim OF NOT DOING EVIL, THAT GOOD MAY ENSUE, or to be reckoned as one of those actions, which, though evil IN THEMSELVES, may be so modified by particular occasions, as to lose their criminality in consideration of the good, to which they lead.
VI. Wars, in order to achieve their goals, undoubtedly have to use force and fear as their primary tools. However, there is sometimes a question about whether it’s acceptable to use tricks in warfare. The general opinion seems to support this approach. Homer praises his hero, Ulysses, not just for his wisdom but also for his skill in military tactics. Xenophon, who was both a philosopher and a soldier, stated that nothing is more useful in war than a well-timed tactic, a view shared by Brasidas in Thucydides, who claimed that many great generals have earned their greatest reputations this way. In Plutarch, Agesilaus argues that deceiving an enemy is both just and lawful. Polybius also adds to the voices in support, believing that it shows greater skill in a general to seize a favorable opportunity to use strategy than to win an open battle. The views of poets, historians, and philosophers are further backed by theologians. Augustine noted that, in pursuing a just war, the righteousness of the cause is not affected by how the end is achieved, whether through trickery or brute force. Chrysostom, in his elegant treatise on the priestly role, points out that the highest commendations are given to generals who have successfully employed strategies. Still, one important factor that influences this debate more than any esteemed opinions is whether trickery should be classified as one of those wrongs that are prohibited under the principle BY NOT DOING WRONG, GOOD THINGS MAY FOLLOW, or to be viewed as one of those actions that, while inherently Malevolent, can be adjusted by specific circumstances to mitigate their wrongdoing in light of the good they may achieve.
VII. There is one kind of stratagem, it is proper to remark, of a negative, and another of a positive kind. The word stratagem, upon the authority of Labeo, taken in a negative sense, includes such actions, as have nothing criminal in them, though calculated to deceive, where any one, for instance, uses a degree of dissimulation or concealment, in order to defend his own property or that of others.58 So that undoubtedly there is something of harshness in the opinion of Cicero, who says there is no scene of life, that will allow either simulation, or dissimulation to be practised. For as you are not bound to disclose to others all that you either know or intend; it follows that, on certain occasions, some acts of dissimulation, that is, of concealment may be lawful. This is a talent, which Cicero, in many parts of his writings, acknowledges that it is absolutely necessary for statesmen to possess. The history of Jeremiah, in the xxxviiith chapter of his prophecy, furnishes a remarkable instance of this kind. For when that prophet was interrogated296 by the king, respecting the event of the siege, he prudently, in compliance with the king's orders, concealed the real matter from the nobles, assigning a different, though not a false reason for the conference, which he had had. In the same manner, Abraham called Sarah, his sister, an appellation used familiarly at that time to denote a near relation by blood, concealing the circumstance of her being his wife.
VII. There are two types of strategies to note: one negative and one positive. The term strategy, according to Labeo, in a negative sense, refers to actions that aren’t criminal but are meant to deceive. For example, someone might use a level of deceit or secrecy to protect their own or someone else's property. Cicero's view that there is no situation in life where either simulation or dissimulation is acceptable seems a bit harsh. Since you’re not required to share everything you know or plan, it follows that in certain situations, some acts of dissimulation, or concealment, can be lawful. Cicero acknowledges in several of his writings that this skill is essential for statesmen. The history of Jeremiah in the 38th chapter of his prophecy provides a notable example. When that prophet was questioned by the king about the siege's outcome, he wisely followed the king's orders and hid the truth from the nobles, offering a different—and not false—reason for his meeting. Similarly, Abraham referred to Sarah as his sister, a common term at the time to describe a close blood relation, while concealing that she was his wife.
VIII. A stratagem of a positive kind, when practised in actions, is called a feint, and when used in conversation it receives the name of a lie or falsehood. A distinction is made by some, between these two kinds of stratagems, who say, that words are signs of our ideas, but actions are not so. But there is more of truth in the opposite opinion, that words of themselves unaccompanied by the intention of the speaker, signify nothing more than the inarticulate cries would do of any one labouring under grief, or any other passion: which sounds come under the denomination of actions, rather than of speech. But should it be said that being able to convey to others the conceptions of his mind, by words adapted to the purpose, is a peculiar gift of nature, by which man is distinguished from other parts of the animated creation, the truth of this cannot be denied.
VIII. A positive strategy, when carried out in actions, is called a feint, and when used in conversation, it’s referred to as a lie or falsehood. Some people make a distinction between these two types of strategies, claiming that words represent our ideas, while actions do not. However, the opposing view holds more truth: that words alone, without the speaker's intention, signify nothing more than the inarticulate cries of someone in distress or experiencing another strong emotion; these sounds are more like actions than speech. Yet, if it’s suggested that the ability to express one’s thoughts through appropriate words is a unique gift of nature that sets humans apart from other living beings, this cannot be denied.
To which we may add that such communication may be made not only by words, but by signs or gestures, like those used to the dumb; it makes no difference, whether those signs or gestures have any natural connection with the thing they are intended to signify, or whether such a connection is only assigned to them by custom. Equivalent to such signs or gestures is handwriting, which may be considered, as a dumb language, deriving its force not merely from the words used, and the particular form of the letters, but from the real intention of the writer, to be gathered from thence:—to be gathered either from the resemblance between the characters and the intentions, as in the Egyptian hieroglyphics, or from pure fancy, as among the Chinese.
We can also say that communication can happen not just through words, but also through signs or gestures, like those used with the deaf. It doesn’t matter if those signs or gestures have a natural connection to what they represent or if that connection is established purely by convention. Writing is similar to these signs or gestures; it can be viewed as a form of silent language, gaining its meaning not just from the words and the style of the letters, but from the true intention of the writer, which we can interpret:—either from the similarity between the characters and the meanings, as seen in Egyptian hieroglyphics, or from pure imagination, like in Chinese.
Here likewise another distinction is necessary to be applied in the same manner, as was done before, in order to remove all ambiguity in using the term of the Law of Nations. For it was there said, that the laws established by independent and separate states, whether or no those laws implied any mutual obligations, were denominated297 the Law of Nations.59 So that words, gestures, and signs, made use of to convey a meaning, imply an obligation, in all the persons concerned, to receive and employ them in their common acceptation. But the employment of OTHER MEANS, coming under NONE OF THOSE DESCRIPTIONS, cannot be construed into a violation of any social contract, although some may be deceived thereby. It is the REAL NATURE of the actions that is here spoken of, and not the ACCIDENTAL circumstances attending them: such actions for instance, as occasion no mischief; or if they do so, there is no guilt, where there is no treacherous design.
Here, another distinction needs to be made in the same way as before to clarify the use of the term international law. It was previously stated that the laws set by independent and separate states, regardless of whether those laws imply any mutual obligations, are referred to as the International Law. 297 This means that words, gestures, and signs used to convey meaning create an obligation for all parties involved to understand and use them in their common meaning. However, the use of OTHER METHODS that do not fit into NONE OF THOSE DESCRIPTIONS cannot be seen as a violation of any social contract, even if some people are misled by them. It is the REAL NATURE of the actions being discussed, not the UNINTENTIONAL circumstances surrounding them: actions that do not cause harm; or if they do, there is no wrongdoing if there is no malicious intent.
We have an instance of the former kind in the conduct of our Saviour, who, on the way to Emmaus, pretended to the disciples, that he was going further; here was a harmless stratagem, unless we interpret the words, as expressive of his intention to have gone further, if he had not been prevented by their efforts and entreaties to detain him. And in another part of the sacred history it is said, that he intended to have passed by the Apostles on the sea, that is, he intended to have done it, had he not been so earnestly importuned by them to go into the ship. There is another instance too in the conduct of Paul, who circumcised Timothy, though he knew the Jews would conclude from thence, that the ordinance of circumcision, which in reality had been abolished, was still binding upon the descendants of Israel, and that Paul and Timothy were of the same opinion. Whereas Paul had no such intention, but only hoped, by that means, to open for himself and Timothy a way to more familiar intercourse with the Jews. Neither could an ordinance of that kind, when the divine obligation was repealed, any longer be deemed of such importance, nor could the evil of a temporary error, resulting from thence, and afterwards to be corrected, be regarded as equivalent to the opportunity, which Paul thought to gain, of making it conducive to the introduction of Christian truth.
We have an example of the first type in the behavior of our Savior, who, on the road to Emmaus, pretended to the disciples that he was going to go further; this was a harmless trick unless we interpret the words as showing his intention to go farther if he hadn’t been stopped by their efforts and pleas to stay with them. In another part of the sacred narrative, it says that he planned to pass by the Apostles on the sea, meaning he would have done so had they not urged him so strongly to get into the boat. There’s also an instance involving Paul, who circumcised Timothy, although he knew the Jews would think that the practice of circumcision, which had actually been abolished, was still required for the descendants of Israel, and that both Paul and Timothy shared that belief. However, Paul had no such intention; he was merely hoping to create an opportunity for more open interaction with the Jews. An ordinance like that, when the divine obligation was lifted, could no longer be seen as crucial, nor could the temporary misunderstanding that arose from it, which would later be corrected, be considered as significant as the chance Paul thought he could gain to help introduce Christian truth.
298 The Greek Fathers have given the name of ECONOMY, or MANAGEMENT to stratagems of this kind. On this subject there is an admirable sentiment in Clement of Alexandria, who, in speaking of a good man, says that "he will do many things for the benefit of his neighbour alone, which he would not otherwise have undertaken."
298 The Greek Fathers used the term ECONOMY or Management to refer to strategies like this. Clement of Alexandria has a great quote on this topic, mentioning that "a good person will do many things solely for the benefit of their neighbor that they wouldn’t have done otherwise."
One of these stratagems was practised by the Romans, who, during the time that they were besieged in the Capitol, threw some loaves of bread into the enemy's camp, that it might not be supposed they were pressed by famine. The feigned flight, which Joshua ordered his people to make, to assist him in his designs upon Ai, affords an instance of a stratagem of the second kind; the ensuing mischiefs of which may be considered, as some of the effects of lawful war. The ORIGINAL DESIGN of that pretended flight does not at all affect the question. The enemy took it for a proof of fear; and he was at liberty to do so, without debarring the other of his right to march this way, or that, with an accelerated or retarded motion, with a shew of courage, or an appearance of fear, as he might judge it most expedient.
One of these strategies was used by the Romans, who, while they were under siege in the Capitol, threw some loaves of bread into the enemy's camp to create the impression that they weren't suffering from hunger. The fake retreat that Joshua instructed his people to carry out to support his plans against Ai is another example of a strategy of the second type; the resulting troubles from this can be seen as some consequences of legitimate warfare. The ORIGINAL DESIGN of that pretend retreat doesn't affect the issue at all. The enemy interpreted it as a sign of fear, and he had the right to do so, without preventing the other side from maneuvering this way or that, at a quicker or slower pace, with an appearance of bravery or a look of fear, depending on what he thought was best.
History furnishes us with innumerable examples of deceptions practised with success upon an enemy, by assuming his arms, ensigns, colours, or uniforms; all which may be justified upon the same principle. For all these are actions, which any one may avail himself of at his pleasure, by departing from the usual course of his military system. For such points of discipline and system depend upon the will and fancy of the military commanders in each state, rather than upon any invariable custom, equally binding upon all nations.
History provides us with countless examples of successful deceptions against an enemy, by taking on their weapons, banners, colors, or uniforms; all of which can be justified on the same grounds. These are actions that anyone can use at their discretion by stepping away from the usual practices of their military strategy. This is because these aspects of discipline and strategy are based more on the desires and decisions of military leaders in each country, rather than on any fixed tradition that is equally applicable to all nations.
IX. Those signs, by which the daily intercourse of life is maintained, form a subject of more weighty discussion, with which the consideration of lies or falsehood is necessarily interwoven.
IX. The signs that keep our daily interactions going are a topic of much deeper discussion, which inevitably intertwines with the consideration of lies or falsehoods.
All stratagems of this kind are so direct a violation of all moral principle, both in their nature and consequences, that almost every page of the revealed will of God declares their condemnation. Solomon describes a righteous, that is, a good man, as one, who holds every false word in detestation, deprecating the least appearance of deception: and the Apostle's injunction accords with these sentiments, instructing his disciples not to lie to one another.
All strategies like this are such a direct violation of all moral principles, both in their nature and consequences, that almost every page of the revealed will of God condemns them. Solomon describes a righteous, or good, person as someone who detests every false word and shuns even the slightest hint of deception. The Apostle's advice aligns with these beliefs, instructing his followers not to lie to each other.
299 Nor is it in the high standard of perfection alone, which the divine records present, that such a recommendation of fair, open, and sincere dealing is to be found. It is the theme of praise with poets and philosophers, and the angry hero of the Grecian poet declares, that he detests the man, as an infernal being, who utters one thing with his tongue, while he conceals another in his heart. But making some allowance for poetic fiction—we find even the grave, sober, and discerning, Stagirite describing falsehood, as a vile, and abominable refuge, and painting truth as a lovely object, that must extort the warmest praise.
299 It's not just the high standard of perfection found in divine records that advocates for fair, open, and sincere dealing. This idea is celebrated by poets and philosophers alike. The angry hero of the Greek poet expresses his hatred for anyone who says one thing while hiding another in their heart. While we might consider some of this poetic exaggeration, even the serious and thoughtful Aristotle describes falsehood as a terrible refuge and portrays truth as a beautiful concept that deserves the highest praise.
These are all great and high authorities in favour of open dealing. Yet there are names of no less weight, both among sacred and profane writers, whose opinions are a vindication of stratagems, when used upon PROPER occasions. One writer speaks of a case, where stratagem may be used, even for the benefit of the person, on whom it is practised, and adduces the instances of a physician, who, by means of a deception, overcame the perverseness of a patient, and wrought a salutary cure.
These are all respected and powerful figures supporting transparency. However, there are equally significant names among both religious and secular authors whose views defend the use of strategies when applied in the right situations. One author mentions a scenario where a strategy can be beneficial even for the person it's directed at, citing the example of a doctor who, through a deception, managed to overcome a patient's stubbornness and achieved a beneficial cure.
X. To reconcile such a variety of discordant opinions, it may be necessary to devise some way of examining falsehood both in its more extensive, and more confined acceptation. Nor is speaking an untruth, UNAWARES, to be considered in the nature of a lie, but the falsehood, which comes within the limits here defined, is the KNOWN and DELIBERATE UTTERANCE of any thing contrary to our real conviction, intention, and understanding.
X. To bring together such a variety of conflicting opinions, we may need to find a way to examine falsehood in both its broader and narrower meanings. Also, speaking an untruth UNAWARER shouldn't be seen as a lie, but the falsehood that fits within the limits defined here is the Known and Intentional statement of anything that contradicts our true beliefs, intentions, and understanding.
Words, or signs, importing the same meaning as words, are generally taken for conceptions of the mind, yet it is no lie for any man to utter a falsehood, which he believes to be true; but the propagation of a truth, which any one believes to be false, IN HIM amounts to a lie. There must be in the use of the words therefore an INTENTION to deceive, in order to constitute a falsehood in the proper and common acceptation. Consequently, when any one single word, or the whole tenour of a discourse, admits of more significations than one, either by the use of some popular phrase, some term of art, or intelligible figure of speech, in that case if the speaker's intention correspond with any one of those meanings, he cannot be charged with using falsehood, although it is possible that a hearer may take his words in a very different sense. It is true that using such an ambiguous method of speaking on ALL OCCASIONS300 is not to be approved of, though there are particular circumstances under which it may be reconciled with honour and justice. In communicating knowledge, for instance, there is no harm in using a metaphor, an irony, or an hyperbole, figures of speech, tending either to adorn or to elucidate a subject. There are cases too, where by this doubtful mode of expression it may be proper to avoid an urgent and impertinent question. There is an instance of the former kind in our Saviour's saying, that "our friend Lazarus sleepeth," where the disciples understood him, as if he were speaking of the refreshing rest of an ordinary sleep: and when he spoke of restoring the temple, which he meant his own body, he knew that the Jews applied what he said to the MATERIAL EDIFICE of the Temple. In the same manner he frequently addressed the multitudes in parables, which they could not understand by barely hearing, without that docility of mind, and attention, which the subject required. Profane history too furnishes us with an example of the second kind, in the conduct of Vitellius, who, as Tacitus informs us, gave Narcissus doubtful and ambiguous answers, in order to avoid his urgent questions; as any explicit declaration might have been attended with danger.
Words or signs that convey the same meaning as words are generally seen as ideas in the mind. However, it’s not a lie for someone to say something false if they believe it to be true; but if someone spreads a truth they believe to be false, IN HIM it counts as a lie. Therefore, to constitute a falsehood in the proper and common sense, there must be an PURPOSE to deceive involved in the use of the words. Consequently, if a single word or the overall message of a conversation has multiple meanings, whether through a popular phrase, a specialized term, or a clear figure of speech, the speaker cannot be accused of falsehood as long as their intention aligns with one of those meanings, even if a listener interprets it differently. It’s true that using such ambiguous language on ALL OCCASIONS300 is not advisable, although there are specific situations where it can be justified in terms of honor and justice. For example, there’s nothing wrong with using a metaphor, irony, or hyperbole—figures of speech that either enhance or clarify a subject—when sharing knowledge. There are also instances where this kind of ambiguous expression is appropriate to dodge an urgent and irrelevant question. One such example is when our Savior said, "our friend Lazarus sleepeth," which the disciples took to mean he was referring to typical rest. And when he mentioned restoring the temple, he meant his own body, but the Jews understood it in terms of the MATERIAL BUILDING of the Temple. Similarly, he often spoke in parables to the crowds, which they could not fully grasp just by hearing, without the open-mindedness and focus the subject required. Profane history also provides an example of the second type, with Vitellius, who, according to Tacitus, gave Narcissus vague and ambiguous answers to avoid his pressing questions, as a clear response could have posed a risk.
On the other hand, it may happen to be not only censurable, but even wicked to use such a manner of speaking, where either the honour of God or the welfare of mankind is concerned, or indeed any matter, which demands explicit avowals, and open dealing. Thus in contracts every thing necessary to their fulfillment ought to be fully disclosed to those concerned. There is an apposite expression of Cicero, who says, that every degree of deception ought to be banished from all contracts, and there is in the old Athenian Laws a proverb, conformable to this, which says, there must be nothing, but open dealing in markets.
On the other hand, it can be not only wrong but even evil to speak this way when it comes to either the honor of God or the well-being of people, or really any issue that requires clear statements and honesty. In contracts, everything necessary for their completion should be fully revealed to everyone involved. Cicero famously said that all forms of deception should be eliminated from contracts, and there’s an old saying from Athenian laws that emphasizes this: there should be nothing but honesty in marketplaces.
XI. In strictness of speech such ambiguity is excluded from the notion of a lie. The common notion of a lie therefore is something spoken, written, marked, or intimated, which cannot be understood, but in a sense different from the real meaning of the speaker. But a lie, in this stricter acceptation, having some thing unlawful in its very nature, necessarily requires that a distinction should be made between it and that latitude of expression already explained. And if this acceptation be properly considered, at least according to the opinion301 prevailing in all nations, it seems, that no other explanation of it is necessary to be given, except that it is a violation of the existing and permanent rights of the person, to whom a discourse, or particular signs, are directed. It is a violation of the rights of ANOTHER; for it is evident, that no one can utter a falsehood with a view to impose upon himself. The rights here spoken of are peculiarly connected with this subject. They imply that liberty of judgment, which men are understood, by a kind of tacit agreement, to owe to each other in their mutual intercourse. For this, and this alone is that mutual obligation, which men intended to introduce, as soon as they began to use speech, or other signs of equal import. For without such an obligation the invention of those signs would have been perfectly nugatory. It is requisite too, that at the time a discourse is made, such a right or obligation should remain in full force.
XI. In strict terms, such ambiguity is not considered a lie. The common understanding of a lie is something spoken, written, marked, or hinted at that can't be understood except in a way that differs from the speaker's actual meaning. However, a lie, in this stricter sense, which inherently involves something unlawful, requires a clear distinction from the broader use of expression already discussed. If this understanding is properly considered, at least according to the prevailing opinion in all nations, it seems that no further explanation is necessary beyond the fact that it violates the existing and permanent rights of the person to whom a statement or specific signs are directed. It violates the rights of ANOTHER; because it's clear that no one can tell a falsehood intending to deceive themselves. The rights referred to here are specifically tied to this topic. They imply the freedom of judgment that people are understood, by a sort of unspoken agreement, to owe one another in their interactions. This is the mutual obligation that people intended to establish as soon as they began to use speech or other equivalent signs. Without such an obligation, the creation of those signs would have been completely pointless. It is also necessary that at the time a statement is made, such a right or obligation remains fully intact.
A right may indeed have existed and afterwards have become obsolete, owing to the rise or occurrence of some new right: which is the case with a debt, that may be released by acquittance, or non-performance of a condition. It is farther requisite, to constitute a VIOLATION OF THIS RIGHT, that the ensuing injury should immediately affect the PERSON ADDRESSED: as in contracts, there can be no injustice, but what affects one of the parties, or persons concerned.
A right may have existed in the past and then become outdated due to the emergence of a new right: this happens with a debt, which can be canceled by a receipt or by failing to meet a condition. Additionally, to constitute a Breach of this right, the resulting harm must directly impact the Recipient: in contracts, there can be no injustice unless it affects one of the parties or individuals involved.
And perhaps under the head of this right, it may not be improper to assign a place to that TRUE SPEAKING, which Plato, following Simonides, classes with justice, in order to form a more striking contrast with that falsehood, so often prohibited in Scripture, by the name of false witness to, or against, our neighbour, and which Augustin, in defining a lie, calls an intention to deceive. Cicero also in his offices lays down truth, as the basis of justice.
And maybe under this right, it wouldn't be out of place to include Truth Telling, which Plato, following Simonides, associates with justice to create a sharper contrast with that falsehood, frequently condemned in Scripture by the term of false witness to or against our neighbor, and which Augustine defines as an intention to deceive. Cicero also establishes truth as the foundation of justice in his writings.
The right to a discovery of the whole truth may be relinquished by the express consent of the persons, who are engaged in a treaty: the one may declare his intention not to disclose certain points, and the other may allow of this reserve. There may be also a tacit presumption, that there are just reasons for such reserve which may perhaps be necessary out of regard to the rights of a third person: rights which, in the common judgment of all sober men, may be sufficient to counterbalance any obligation in either of the persons engaged in the treaty302 to make a full disclosure of his views and sentiments.—These principles, duly considered, will supply many inferences to reconcile any seeming contradiction in the opinions, that have been advanced.
The right to know the whole truth can be given up if both parties involved in a contract agree to it: one party can express their intention not to share certain information, and the other party can accept this limitation. There may also be a silent assumption that there are valid reasons for such withholding that could be necessary to protect the rights of a third party; rights that, in the common view of rational individuals, may be enough to outweigh any obligation for either party in the agreement to fully disclose their thoughts and feelings.302—These principles, when thoughtfully considered, will lead to many conclusions that can help resolve any apparent contradictions in the opinions that have been put forward.
XII. In the first place, many things may be said to madmen, or children, the LITERAL MEANING of which may not be true, without incurring the guilt of wilful falsehood. A practice which seems to be allowed by the common sense of all mankind. Quintilian, speaking of the age of puerility, says, it is a period of life, when many useful truths may be taught in the dress of fiction.—Another reason given is, that as children and madmen possess no perfect power of judging, impositions of that kind can do no injury to their rights, in such respects.
XII. First of all, there are many things that can be said to madmen or children, the Literal meaning of which may not be true, without being guilty of intentional falsehood. This practice seems to be accepted by common sense across humanity. Quintilian, when talking about childhood, mentions that it's a stage of life during which many useful truths can be taught through fiction. Another reason given is that since children and madmen lack the ability to judge fully, such deceptions cannot harm their rights in those situations.
XIII. Secondly, when a conversation is addressed to any one, who is not thereby deceived, although a third person, not immediately addressed, may misconceive the matter, there is no wilful falsehood in the case. No WILFUL FALSEHOOD towards the person addressed: because he feels no greater injury from thence, than an intelligent hearer would do from the recital of a fable, or the use of a metaphor, irony, or hyperbole in speech. It cannot be said that an injury is done to the person, who accidentally and cursorily hears a matter, and misconceives it: for being no way concerned, there is no obligation due to him. As he misconceives a thing addressed to ANOTHER, and not to HIMSELF, he must take upon his own head all the consequences of the mistake. For, properly speaking, the discourse, WITH RESPECT TO HIM, is no discourse, but an inexpressive sound that may signify one thing as well as another. So that there was nothing wrong in the conduct of Cato the Censor, who made a false promise of assistance to his confederates, nor in that of Flaccus, who informed others that Aemilius had taken the enemy's city by storm, although the enemy were deceived by it. Plutarch mentions an instance of the same kind in the life of Agesilaus. Here no communication was made to the enemy, and the prejudice he sustained was an accidental thing no way unlawful in itself, either to be wished for or procured.
XIII. Secondly, when a conversation is directed at someone who is not deceived by it, even if a third person, who isn’t directly addressed, misunderstands the situation, there is no intentional falsehood involved. There’s no Deliberate deceit towards the person being spoken to because they are not harmed any more than an informed listener would be from hearing a fable or from the use of metaphor, irony, or hyperbole in conversation. It can’t be said that harm is done to someone who accidentally hears something and misunderstands it, as they are not involved in the matter; thus, there is no obligation to them. Since they misunderstand something meant for ANOTHER, and not for THEM, they must take responsibility for their own error. Properly speaking, the discourse, ABOUT THEM, is not really discourse at all, but rather mere sounds that could mean one thing or another. Therefore, Cato the Censor's act of falsely promising help to his allies was not wrong, nor was Flaccus wrong in telling others that Aemilius had captured the enemy city by storm, even if the enemy was misled by it. Plutarch mentions a similar case in the life of Agesilaus. Here, there was no communication made to the enemy, and any harm they suffered was incidental and not unlawful in itself, nor was it something to be sought after or caused.
XIV. In the third place, whenever it is certain that the person, on whom a deception is practised, discovers that the intent of it was to do him a service; he will not feel it as a grievance, nor can it come under the strict denomination of a lie or falsehood. It will be303 no more an INJURY, than it would be a THEFT in any one, presuming upon an owner's consent, to take something belonging to that owner, in order to convert it to his use in a very beneficial way. For in cases of notorious certainty, a PRESUMPTION may be taken for express consent. But it is evident that no man would CONSENT to receive an INJURY.
XIV. Third, whenever it’s clear that the person being deceived realizes the intent was to help him, he won't see it as a grievance, and it can’t really be classified as a lie or falsehood. It won't be any more an 303 Injury than it would be a Theft if someone assumes an owner's permission to take something belonging to them for their own beneficial use. In cases where the certainty is obvious, a ASSUMPTION can be treated as explicit consent. But it’s clear that no one would Consent to receive an Injury.
From hence it appears, that a person is guilty of no treachery, who uses unfounded or fictitious motives to console a friend in distress, as Arria did to Paetus upon the death of his son, of which there is an account in Pliny's Epistles, or in a general, who in a perilous situation should avail himself of false intelligence, to encourage his troops, by which perhaps a victory might be gained.
From this, it seems that a person isn't being treacherous if they use imaginary or made-up reasons to comfort a friend in distress, like Arria did for Paetus after the death of his son, as mentioned in Pliny's Letters. Similarly, a general facing a dangerous situation might use false information to motivate his troops, potentially leading to a victory.
It may be observed likewise, that the injury done to the freedom of judgment is, in such a case, of less consequence, because it is but momentary, and the real fact is soon discovered.
It can also be noted that the harm done to freedom of judgment in such a case is not as significant, because it is only temporary, and the truth is quickly revealed.
XV. There is a fourth case, which bears a near affinity to those above mentioned, and that is, when any one, possessing pre-eminent authority, orders another, in a subordinate capacity, to execute some device or stratagem, conducive either to his individual, or to the public welfare. Which Plato seems to have had particularly in view, in allowing those in authority to avail themselves of pretexts, or stratagems. The same writer is very correct in his notion of not making such a device a characteristic of that authority, which belongs to the supreme being. For all such devices, however justifiable they may be in CERTAIN CASES, strongly betray that imperfection, which is inseparable from all human systems.
XV. There's a fourth situation that's quite similar to the ones mentioned above, and that's when someone with significant authority instructs another person in a lower position to carry out a plan or strategy that benefits either themselves or the public good. Plato seems to have specifically considered this when he said that those in power could use excuses or strategies. He’s also right in pointing out that such tactics should not define the authority that belongs to the supreme being. Because while such tactics might be justified in SOME CASES, they clearly reveal the imperfections that are an inherent part of all human systems.
The stratagem, which Joseph employed to obtain further discoveries without making himself known to his brethren, is much commended by Philo, as a mark of great policy, when, contrary to the convictions and feelings of his own mind, he accused them of being spies, and afterwards charged them with theft. It was by a stratagem of the same kind, that Solomon gave proof of his inspired wisdom, when he used the FICTITIOUS threat of dividing the living child in order to discover the real mother.
The plan that Joseph used to gather more information without revealing himself to his brothers is highly praised by Philo as a sign of cleverness. He went against his own beliefs and feelings by accusing them of being spies and later accused them of theft. Solomon employed a similar tactic to showcase his wise insight when he falsely threatened to divide the living child to identify the true mother.
XVI. The fifth case, which allows a stratagem to be practised, is that, where it may be the ONLY means of saving the life of an innocent person, of obtaining some304 object of equal importance, or of diverting another from the perpetration of some horrid design. The heathen poet has given a beautiful illustration of this in his praises of Hypermnestra, whose conduct he calls "a splendid stratagem, ennobling the virgin to all posterity."
XVI. The fifth case, which permits the use of a clever trick, is when it might be the ONLY way to save the life of an innocent person, achieve some304 equally important goal, or stop someone from carrying out a terrible plan. The pagan poet has illustrated this beautifully in his praises of Hypermnestra, whose actions he describes as "a brilliant stratagem, glorifying the virgin for all time."
XVII. It is evident that many writers of acknowledged wisdom, and sober judgment, have carried the point farther than has been done in this treatise, in allowing the use of false representations to an enemy. In cases, where public enemies are concerned, they maintain, that it is lawful to deviate from those strict rules of avowing and disclosing all our intentions, which they prescribe, on all other occasions. Such is the opinion of Plato and Xenophon among the Greeks, of Philo among the Jews, and Chrysostom among Christians. It may not perhaps be amiss to cite, in this place, the message sent by the men of Jabesh Gilead to the Ammonites, by whom they were besieged, and also that of the prophet Elisha, and at the same time to mention the conduct of Valerius Laevinus, who boasted of having killed Pyrrhus.
XVII. It’s clear that many respected writers, known for their wisdom and good judgment, have taken the argument further than this treatise does by endorsing the use of deception against an enemy. They argue that when it comes to public enemies, it’s acceptable to stray from the strict guidelines of being open and honest about our intentions, which they advocate for in all other situations. This view is held by Plato and Xenophon among the Greeks, Philo among the Jews, and Chrysostom among Christians. It might be useful to mention here the message sent by the people of Jabesh Gilead to the Ammonites, who were besieging them, as well as the one from the prophet Elisha, and to also note the actions of Valerius Laevinus, who claimed to have killed Pyrrhus.
The third, the fourth and fifth observations above made, may be illustrated from what is said by Eustratus, Archbishop of Nice, "An able and upright counsellor is not obliged to disclose the whole truth: for there may be occasions, when it may be necessary for him to recommend the means of deceiving an enemy, or to employ some stratagem towards a friend, where it may turn to his advantage."
The third, fourth, and fifth observations mentioned above can be illustrated by what Eustratus, Archbishop of Nice, said: "A skilled and honest advisor doesn’t have to reveal the entire truth. There may be times when it’s necessary for him to suggest ways to deceive an enemy or to use some tactics with a friend if it benefits him."
XVIII. What has been said of false speaking must be understood as applied to affirmative declarations, which can be prejudicial to no persons, but public enemies: it can by no means be taken to include promises. For promises confer upon the person, to whom they are made, a peculiar right to claim their full performance. And this is a rule, which must take place, even between public enemies; a rule to which existing hostilities are not allowed to form an exception. It is a maxim proper to be enforced in TACIT, as well as in EXPRESS agreements: as when a parley or conference is demanded, there is always an IMPLIED promise, that both sides shall attend it with perfect safety. But these are points reserved for the discussion of another part of this treatise.
XVIII. What was said about false statements should be understood to apply to affirmative declarations, which can harm no one except public enemies; it should definitely not include promises. Promises give the person to whom they are made a specific right to demand their full fulfillment. And this is a rule that must apply even among public enemies; existing hostilities cannot be an exception to it. It is a principle that should be upheld in TACIT as well as in EXPRESS agreements: for instance, when a discussion or meeting is requested, there is always an SUGGESTED promise that both sides will attend with complete safety. However, these matters are reserved for further discussion in another part of this treatise.
XIX. It will be necessary to repeat an observation made before, with respect to oaths, both of the affirmative and promissory kind, where it was maintained that305 they exclude all exceptions, all mental reservations towards the person, to whom they are made, being regarded not merely as a solemn transaction with that individual, but as a stedfast appeal to God. Such an appeal to the supreme being demands the performance of an oath, even if it gave the individual no right to the same.
XIX. It’s important to repeat a point made earlier about oaths, both affirmations and promises, where it was argued that305 they rule out any exceptions or mental reservations regarding the person to whom they are made. These oaths are seen not just as a serious commitment to that individual but also as a firm appeal to God. Such an appeal to the supreme being requires the fulfillment of the oath, even if the individual has no entitlement to it.
At the same time it was observed, that a sworn declaration is not like one of any other kind, where an application of terms different from their usual meaning may supply the speaker with an excuse for evading their import. But truth requires every declaration and promise to be made in terms, which it is supposed that every man of integrity and clear judgment will understand, spurning at the impious thought, that men may be deceived by oaths, as children are by toys and trifles.
At the same time, it was noted that a sworn statement isn’t like any other kind, where using terms differently from their usual meaning might give the speaker a reason to dodge their real meaning. Instead, truth demands that every declaration and promise be made in terms that every honest person with sound judgment will understand, rejecting the idea that people can be misled by oaths, just as children are by toys and trivial matters.
XX. Some nations and individuals indeed have rejected the use of those stratagems, which even the law of nature allows to be employed as a means of self-defence against an enemy. But they did so, not from any opinion of their unlawfulness, but from a noble loftiness of mind, and from a confidence in their own strength. Aelian has preserved a saying of Pythagoras, "that there are two things, in which man approaches nearest to God, in always speaking the truth, and doing good to others." Aristotle, somewhere in his Ethics, calls speaking truth, the freedom of a great soul, and Plutarch says, that falsehood is the qualification of a slave. But an adherence to truth, in simplicity of heart, is not the only duty required of Christians, in this respect, they are commanded to abstain from all vain discourse, as having for their example him, in whose mouth there was found no guile.
XX. Some countries and people have indeed rejected the use of those tactics, which even natural law permits for self-defense against an enemy. But they did this not because they believed it was wrong, but out of noble ideals and confidence in their own strength. Aelian has recorded a saying from Pythagoras: "There are two things that bring man closest to God: always speaking the truth and doing good for others." Aristotle, in his Ethics, describes truth-telling as the freedom of a great soul, and Plutarch states that lying is a mark of a slave. However, staying true in a simple-hearted way is not the only obligation of Christians; they are also instructed to steer clear of all empty talk, following the example of Him who had no deceit in His words.
XXI. With respect to the actions of men, there is another rule which may properly come under this head, and that is, the unlawfulness of urging or persuading any one to do an unlawful act. For instance, no subject has a right to lift his hand against his sovereign, to deliver up a town without public authority, or to despoil his neighbour of his goods. It would be unlawful then to encourage the subject of an enemy, as long as he continues his subject, to do any of these acts. For the person, who urges another to do a wicked act, makes himself a partner in his guilt. Nor can it be received as a just answer, that urging a subject to the perpetration of such a deed is nothing more than employing the lawful means of destroying an enemy. For though it306 may be necessary and just to destroy him, if possible, yet that is not the way, in which it should be done. Augustin has well observed, that it makes no difference whether any one should commit a crime himself, or employ another as his instrument.
XXI. When it comes to people's actions, there's another important principle to consider: it's illegal to encourage or persuade anyone to commit an unlawful act. For example, no person has the right to attack their ruler, surrender a town without proper authority, or take their neighbor's possessions. Therefore, it would be unlawful to encourage a subject of an enemy, as long as they remain a subject, to carry out any of these actions. The person who encourages someone to commit a wrongful act becomes complicit in their wrongdoing. It's also not a valid excuse to say that urging a subject to commit such an act is simply using lawful means to defeat an enemy. While it may be necessary and just to eliminate the enemy, that is not the appropriate way to go about it. Augustine rightly pointed out that it doesn't matter whether someone commits a crime themselves or uses another person as a tool to do so.
But employing the spontaneous offers of a deserter is not contrary to the laws of war, and is a very different action from that of seducing a subject from his allegiance.
But using the spontaneous offers of a deserter isn’t against the laws of war, and it’s a very different action from trying to lure someone away from their loyalty.

WAR AND PEACE
War and Peace
This is a frontispiece to a Latin edition of Grotius' De Jure Belli ac Pacis, published at Amsterdam in 1670. It is intended to be symbolical of War and Peace acting under the direction Justice, these three figures forming the central group.
This is a frontispiece to a Latin edition of Grotius' De Jure Belli ac Pacis, published in Amsterdam in 1670. It represents War and Peace guided by Justice, with these three figures making up the central group.
CHAPTER II.
How International Law Holds the Property of Individuals Liable for the Debts of Governments. The Nature of Reprisals.
No one but an heir bound by the act of another—Property of subjects answerable for the debts of sovereigns, according to the law of Nations—Capture of persons and property after satisfaction refused by the aggressor—Reprisals—Personal safety of subjects—Distinction made by the law of Nations in this respect.
No one but an heir bound by someone else's actions—Property of individuals responsible for the rulers' debts, as per international law—Seizure of people and property when the aggressor refuses to pay—Retaliation—Personal safety of individuals—The distinction outlined by international law on this matter.
I. The rights accruing from the law of Nations are the points next to be considered, which may be referred either to wars in GENERAL, or to those of a PARTICULAR description.
I. The rights that come from international law are the next points to discuss, which can be related either to wars in GENERAL or to those of a SPECIFIC description.
Wars in GENERAL are those, which properly first come under notice.
Wars in GENERAL are those that are typically the first to be recognized.
By the LITERAL law of nature, no one is bound by the actions of another, except the person, who succeeds to his property. For the introduction and establishment of property introduced and established also the power of transferring it with all its incumbrances. The Emperor Zeno however pronounces it repugnant to natural justice for one man to be molested for the debts of another. A principle, which gave rise to the distinctions in the Roman law, that the wife could not be sued for her husband, nor the husband for his wife, nor a son for his father, nor a father or mother for their son. Nor, as Ulpian clearly states it, could individuals be answerable for the debts of the community, and more especially if that community be possessed of property. Indeed if that were not the case individuals could only be obliged to contribute their due proportion, as members of that community.
By the LITERAL law of nature, no one is responsible for the actions of another, except for the person who inherits their property. The introduction and establishment of property also brought the ability to transfer it along with any debts or obligations attached to it. However, Emperor Zeno declared it unjust for one person to be punished for the debts of another. This principle led to distinctions in Roman law, stating that a wife could not be sued for her husband, nor a husband for his wife, nor a son for his father, nor a father or mother for their son. As Ulpian clearly stated, individuals could not be held responsible for the debts of the community, especially if that community owns property. In fact, if that weren't the case, individuals would only be required to contribute their fair share as members of that community.
Seneca says, "if any one lends money to my country, I am not to be considered as his debtor, nor to take the debt upon myself, though I am bound to pay my due proportion of it." There was a special provision made in the Roman law, that one peasant should not be bound for the debts of another, and it is laid down as a rule,308 that the goods of one person shall not be distrained for the debts of another, even if they be public debts; and in Justinian's Novels, pledges for others are forbidden, and the cause assigned for it is, because it is unreasonable that one person should incur the debt, and another be bound to the payment of it, an exaction to which the name of ODIOUS is given. King Theodoric Cassiodor, calls it a shocking licence for one man to be detained as a pledge for another.
Seneca says, "if someone lends money to my country, I'm not considered their debtor, nor do I take on the debt, even though I need to pay my fair share." There was a specific rule in Roman law that one peasant should not be responsible for another's debts, and it is stated as a principle,308 that one person's property cannot be seized for another's debts, even if they are public debts; in Justinian's Novels, pledges for others are not allowed, and the reason given is that it’s unreasonable for one person to incur a debt while another has to pay it, a practice referred to as DISGUSTING. King Theodoric Cassiodor calls it a terrible abuse for one person to be held as a guarantee for another.
II. Although in the preceding observations there may be a great deal of truth, yet it is possible, and indeed appears actually to be the case, that the voluntary law of nations introduced the practice of rendering all the corporeal, and incorporeal property, belonging to the subjects of any state or sovereign, liable to the debts, which that state or sovereign may have incurred, either personally, or by refusing to make such reparation, as may be due for the injuries and aggressions, which they have committed.
II. While the previous statements hold a lot of truth, it seems that the voluntary law of nations has established the practice of making all physical and intangible property belonging to the citizens of any state or ruler liable for the debts incurred by that state or ruler, whether personally or by failing to provide necessary reparations for the wrongs and attacks they have committed.
Yet this is a practice, which nothing but necessity could justify; for, on any other ground, it would be opening a door to innumerable acts of wanton aggression and injustice against individuals. As the property of states and sovereigns cannot often so easily fall into an enemy's hand, as that belonging to individuals, who are more numerous, and whose property is consequently more exposed. So that rights of this kind are to be reckoned among those, which Justinian says, are the offspring of stern necessity, the calamities of men driving them to the use of such means.
Yet this is a practice that only necessity can justify; on any other basis, it would just open the door to countless acts of reckless aggression and injustice against individuals. Since the property of states and sovereigns doesn’t easily fall into enemy hands as that of individuals, who are more numerous and whose property is therefore more at risk. So, these kinds of rights should be considered among those that Justinian described as arising from harsh necessity, driven by the misfortunes of people compelling them to resort to such measures.
But though a practice like this owes its introduction to NECESSITY, it is not so far at variance with the law of nature, as to exclude CUSTOM and TACIT agreement from having some share in its establishment. For we find that sureties are bound by no other tie, but that alone of having given their consent. Besides, it might easily be supposed, that it was the best method of redress against the subjects of another state, where the aggrieved persons could not so easily prosecute their rights, or obtain indemnities, the claims or injuries of strangers being but little understood, and perhaps still less regarded in a foreign land.
But while a practice like this comes about out of NEED, it doesn’t completely contradict the law of nature, allowing CUSTOM and TACIT agreement to play a role in its development. We see that sureties are only bound by the agreement that comes from having given their consent. Additionally, it’s reasonable to think that this was the best way to address issues with subjects from another state, where those affected might find it difficult to assert their rights or get compensation, as claims or grievances involving outsiders are often not well understood and possibly even less valued in a foreign country.
Subjects, being thus liable to the loss of their property, by the conduct of their fellow subjects, or by that of the state, might sometimes feel it a hardship, while on other309 occasions, it would prove their greatest security against aggressions from the subjects of another power.
Subjects, being at risk of losing their property due to the actions of their fellow subjects or the state, might occasionally see it as a burden. However, at other309 times, it could serve as their strongest protection against attacks from subjects of another power.
That this was a received custom appears not only from the regular wars, carried on by one state against another, the rules observed in which are often named in the manifestoes issued on such occasions: the form of which may be seen in the first book of Livy, where it is said, "I declare war against the ancient nations of the Latins, and likewise against the respective individuals"; and the same writer, in his thirty first book, informs us, that, upon the question being put to the people, they were asked, whether it was their pleasure that war should be declared against Philip, and against the Macedonians, his subjects.—But the same custom also prevailed, even before the commencement of actual and open hostilities between two states, when mutual acts of aggression by the subjects of each power could be regarded as nothing but the eve, and prelude to a declaration of war. The words used by Agesilaus to Pharnabazus will serve to elucidate this point: he said; "While we were friends to the king of Persia, we treated him and his subjects in a friendly manner: now we are enemies, you can expect nothing from us but hostilities. Therefore, Pharnabazus, while you chuse to continue a vassal to the King, we wound him through your sides."
That this was an established practice is shown not only by the regular wars fought by one state against another, with rules often mentioned in the declarations made in such situations: an example can be found in the first book of Livy, where it states, "I declare war against the ancient nations of the Latins, and also against the individual leaders." In his thirty-first book, the same author tells us that, when the question was posed to the people, they were asked whether they wanted to declare war against Philip and the Macedonians, his subjects. However, this same practice also existed even before open hostilities began between two states, when reciprocal acts of aggression by the subjects of each power could only be seen as the prelude to a declaration of war. The words spoken by Agesilaus to Pharnabazus illustrate this point: he said, "While we were allies of the king of Persia, we treated him and his subjects with respect: now that we are enemies, you can expect nothing from us but conflict. Therefore, Pharnabazus, as long as you choose to remain a servant to the King, we will attack him through you."
III. The Athenians had a method somewhat like this of seeking redress, which they called ἀνδροληψια {androlêpsia}, a seizure of men's persons, which was laid down in the Attic law in the following terms, "if any one has been murdered in a foreign country, the nearest relatives of the deceased are authorized to seize any three subjects of that country, but not more than three, till the perpetrators of the deed be punished, or at least delivered up to the hands of justice for that purpose."
III. The Athenians had a method somewhat similar to this for seeking justice, which they referred to as man catching {androlêpsia}, meaning a seizure of individuals. This was established in Attic law as follows: "If someone has been murdered in a foreign country, the nearest relatives of the deceased are allowed to seize any three subjects of that country, but no more than three, until the perpetrators are punished or at least handed over to the authorities for that purpose."
In this case we find that the personal liberty of subjects, which may be considered as a kind of incorporeal right, including the right of residing where they please, or doing whatever they may think proper, is made answerable for the debt of the state, who is bound to punish the criminal acts of her subjects: so that the subject suffers constraint, till the state has discharged the debt, which it is bound to pay; and by the payment of this debt is meant the punishment of the guilty. For although the Egyptians, as we learn from Diodorus Siculus, maintained that neither the person, nor liberty of any one ought to be310 bound or constrained for a debt, there is nothing in it repugnant to the law of nature, and by the practice not only of the Greeks, but of other nations, the opposite opinion seems to have been established.
In this situation, we see that the personal freedom of individuals, which can be viewed as a type of intangible right, includes the ability to live wherever they want or do whatever they think is right. However, this freedom can be held accountable for the state’s debts, as the state must punish the criminal actions of its citizens. This means that individuals face restrictions until the state has settled the debt it is obligated to pay, and settling this debt refers to punishing the guilty. Even though the Egyptians, according to Diodorus Siculus, believed that no one's person or freedom should be restricted for a debt, there is nothing in this view that contradicts the law of nature. In fact, based on the practices of not only the Greeks but also other nations, it seems that the opposite view has been accepted.
Aristocrates, who was contemporary with Demosthenes had made a motion for a decree, that if any one killed Charidemus, it might be lawful to seize him, wherever he was to be found, and that any one, who attempted to rescue that person, should be deemed an enemy. Demosthenes finds fault with many parts of this decree. For in the first place, Aristocrates had omitted making a proper distinction between murder and a lawful putting to death, the latter of which is an act of justice: in the next place, he has said nothing of bringing the person to a regular trial: besides, it was not the persons, among whom the murder had been committed, but those who afterwards received the murderer, that were to be declared enemies. Demosthenes says, that "the regular law prescribes, that if the persons in whose district a murder has been committed, neither punish, nor deliver up the perpetrator of the crime, three of their people shall be liable to be seized. But this decree, allowing the persons in whose district it has been committed to escape with impunity, not even naming THEM, passes sentence upon those, who in conformity to the common laws of humanity have received the fugitive, if they do not deliver him up, which would be a breach of the protection due to a suppliant."
Aristocrates, who was a contemporary of Demosthenes, proposed a decree stating that if anyone killed Charidemus, it would be legal to seize that person wherever they were found, and anyone who tried to rescue that individual would be considered an enemy. Demosthenes criticizes several aspects of this decree. First, Aristocrates failed to clearly differentiate between murder and a lawful execution, the latter being an act of justice. Second, he didn’t mention bringing the person to a proper trial. Furthermore, it was not the individuals in whose area the murder occurred but those who later sheltered the murderer who were to be declared enemies. Demosthenes argues that "the regular law states that if the people in whose district a murder happens neither punish nor surrender the perpetrator, three of their members can be seized. However, this decree allows those in whose district the murder was committed to go unpunished, not even naming THEM, and instead punishes those who, in line with the common laws of humanity, have taken in the fugitive if they do not turn them over, which would violate the protection owed to a supplicant."
The fourth point, in which he blames Aristocrates, is for having carried matters to the extremities of open and actual war, in a case, where the law only authorized the seizure and detention of particular persons. Of these arguments, the first, the second, and the fourth, are by no means destitute of weight. But the third argument, unless it be confined entirely to the circumstance of accidental death, or that necessarily occasioned by defending one's self, may be regarded more as an oratorical flourish than a just and solid reason. For the law of nations extends the privileges, and character of suppliants to those only, who have left their country on account of misfortune, and not owing to crimes. Indeed if the law of nations made no such distinction, the persons, among whom a crime has been committed, and who may be suspected of having countenanced the deed, and those who barely refuse to punish or deliver311 up the guilty fugitive, would be upon an equal footing as to right. So that it was either USAGE, which GRADUALLY introduced the above interpretation of that law, to which Demosthenes appeals, or it was afterwards more EXPRESSLY ESTABLISHED, in order to avoid such cavils. For no one can deny the truth of one of these positions who has attended to the observation of Julius Pollux, that "the seizure and detainder of persons can be enforced, whenever a power cannot obtain the surrender of fugitive murderers, which they demand. In this case the aggrieved power or individual may seize and detain any three of the people belonging to the state, which refuses to make that surrender."
The fourth point, where he blames Aristocrates, is for escalating things to outright war in a situation where the law only allowed for the seizure and detention of specific individuals. Among these arguments, the first, second, and fourth are definitely significant. However, the third argument, unless it only refers to accidental death or that which arises from self-defense, seems more like a rhetorical flourish than a valid and solid reason. The law of nations grants the privileges and status of supplicants only to those who have left their country due to misfortune, not because of crimes. In fact, if the law of nations didn’t make such a distinction, then those involved in a crime, who may be suspected of fostering the act, and those who simply refuse to punish or hand over the guilty fugitive, would have the same rights. Thus, it was either USE, which GRADUALLY led to this interpretation of that law, as Demosthenes argues, or it was later more clearly stated to avoid such arguments. No one can deny the truth of one of these positions if they have taken note of Julius Pollux's observation that "the seizure and detention of individuals can be enforced whenever a power cannot obtain the surrender of fugitive murderers, which they demand. In this case, the aggrieved power or individual may seize and detain any three people from the state that refuses to make that surrender."
It is upon the same principle that any power may detain the subjects of another state, in order to procure the release of any subjects of her own, unjustly seized, and imprisoned by that state.
It’s based on the same principle that one country can hold the citizens of another country to secure the release of its own citizens who have been wrongfully taken and imprisoned by that country.
IV. Another method of obtaining redress for any violation of persons, or property is by having recourse to what, in modern language, are called REPRISALS, which the Saxons and Angles denominated WITHERNAM, and to which the French gave the name of Letters of Marque, and those were usually obtained from the crown.
IV. Another way to get compensation for any violation of a person's rights or property is by using what we now call Retaliation, which the Saxons and Angles referred to as WITHERNAM, and the French named Letters of Marque. These were typically issued by the crown.
V. It is generally understood that recourse may be had to this method of redress not only against a foreign aggressor, but also against a debtor, if justice cannot be obtained in due time: but in NOTORIOUS cases, which admit of no doubt, this right may be enforced even beyond the strict letter of the law. For even in DOUBTFUL matters, the presumption will always be in favour of judges appointed by public authority. For it is unlikely that they should GREATLY, or WANTONLY exceed their power; especially when, if so inclined, they have not the same means of enforcing their decrees against foreigners, as against their fellow subjects. Indeed even in disputes between subjects of the same country, they cannot annul a just debt. Paulus, the Lawyer, says that a REAL DEBTOR, though discharged, owing to some informality or inability of the law to enforce payment, still remains a debtor according to the law of nature.
V. It's generally accepted that you can use this method of redress not only against a foreign aggressor, but also against a debtor if you can't get justice in a timely manner: but in Famous for bad reasons cases that leave no doubt, this right can be enforced even beyond the strict letter of the law. Even in UNCERTAIN matters, the assumption will always favor judges appointed by public authority. It's unlikely that they would GREATLY or Willy-nilly exceed their power; especially since, if they wanted to, they don’t have the same means to enforce their decisions against foreigners as they do against their fellow citizens. In fact, even in disputes between subjects of the same country, they cannot invalidate a just debt. Paulus, the Lawyer, states that a REAL DEBTOR, even if discharged due to some formality or the law's inability to enforce payment, still remains a debtor under the law of nature.
And when, in consequence of a judicial sentence, a creditor, under pretext of seizing his own property, had taken from a debtor something which did not belong to him though it was in his possession: upon the discharge of the debt, a doubt arising whether the thing should be312 restored to the debtor, Scaevola maintained that it certainly ought to be restored.
And when, as a result of a court ruling, a creditor, claiming to seize his own property, took something from a debtor that didn't actually belong to him, even though it was in his possession: once the debt was paid off, a question came up about whether the item should be312returned to the debtor. Scaevola argued that it definitely should be returned.
There is a difference between the two cases. For subjects, AS SUCH, cannot make any violent resistance to the execution of a sentence, which they may not deem satisfactory, nor can they prosecute any right in opposition to the law. Foreigners may use violent means to enforce a right: tho' they are not justified in using such means, while there is any possibility of obtaining redress in a legal, and peaceable manner.
There is a difference between the two cases. For subjects, As a result, cannot violently resist the execution of a sentence they may not find acceptable, nor can they pursue any rights against the law. International visitors may resort to force to enforce a right; however, they are not justified in doing so while there is any chance of getting a resolution in a legal and peaceful way.
It is on such grounds that reprisals are made upon the persons and property of the subjects, belonging to a power, who refuses to grant redress and reparation for injuries and aggressions. It is a practice not literally enacted by the law of nature, but generally received through custom. It is a practice too of the greatest antiquity: for in the eleventh book of the Iliad, we find Nestor giving an account of the reprisals, which he had made upon the Epeian nation, from whom he took a great number of cattle, as a satisfaction for a prize which his father Neleus had won at the Elian games; and for debts due to many private subjects of the Pylian kingdom. Out of this booty the king having selected his own due, equitably divided the rest among the other creditors.
It is based on this principle that reprisals are carried out against the people and property of a nation that refuses to provide redress and compensation for injuries and aggressions. This is not something that is strictly defined by the law of nature, but rather is generally accepted through custom. This practice has ancient roots; in the eleventh book of the Iliad, we see Nestor recounting the reprisals he took against the Epeian nation, from whom he seized a large number of cattle as compensation for a prize his father Neleus had won at the Elian games, as well as for debts owed to various private individuals from the Pylian kingdom. After selecting his own share from this loot, the king fairly divided the remainder among the other creditors.
VI. It has been a received opinion with many nations, that reprisals might be made even upon the LIVES of innocent subjects, owing to the right, which it was supposed that every one had over his own life, and which might be transferred from the individual to the state. A doctrine, which, as it was proved in the first book of this treatise, can never be reconciled either to sound religion or morality. Indeed a person may ACCIDENTALLY, though not INTENTIONALLY be killed by us in attempting to prevent him from violently obstructing us in the prosecution of a lawful right. Yet if such an accidental calamity could be foreseen, the law of charity, setting so pre-eminent a value upon the life of man, would in such a case prescribe the forbearance of our right.
VI. Many nations have long believed that reprisals could even be taken against the LIVES of innocent people, based on the idea that everyone has a right to their own life, which could be passed from the individual to the state. This belief, as demonstrated in the first book of this treatise, can never be justified by sound religion or morality. In fact, a person might ACCIDENTALLY be killed by us while we are trying to prevent them from violently obstructing us in pursuing a lawful right, even if we did not mean to harm them. However, if such an accidental tragedy could be anticipated, the law of charity, which places a high value on human life, would suggest that we should refrain from exercising that right.
VII. But on this, as well as other points, we must take care not to confound the natural and fundamental law of nations, with the civil and conventional law of particular states.
VII. But on this, as well as other points, we must be careful not to confuse the natural and fundamental law of nations with the civil and conventional law of specific states.
By the law of nations all the permanent subjects, both natives and settlers, of an offending state or sovereign are liable to suffer reprisals: but the same rule does not bind313 those, who are passing through a country, or only residing in it for a time. For such reprisals are a kind of pledges, like public burdens, made answerable for the public debts, from which foreigners, being temporary residents, though owing obedience to the laws, are totally exempt.
By international law, all permanent residents, both locals and settlers, of a state or ruler that has committed an offense are at risk of facing reprisals. However, this rule does not apply to those who are just passing through a country or only staying temporarily. Reprisals are similar to pledges, like public obligations, that are held accountable for public debts, from which foreigners, as temporary residents, are completely exempt, even though they must obey the laws.
In the same manner, Ambassadors, but not those sent from an enemy to our enemies, and their property, are exempt from such conditions by the law of nations. By the CIVIL LAW too of many countries an exception is made in favour of women and children, of men of letters, and those who are travelling for the purposes of trade. But by the law of NATIONS the goods of all are liable to reprisals, as was the case at Athens, respecting the seizure of persons. In many places, by the civil law, the right of making reprisals is obtained of the sovereign, and in others, of the judges.
In the same way, ambassadors—except for those sent from an enemy to our enemies—and their belongings are protected from such conditions by international law. According to the Civil Law of many countries, there are exceptions made for women and children, intellectuals, and those traveling for trade. However, under COUNTRIES law, the property of everyone can be subjected to reprisals, as was the case in Athens regarding the seizure of individuals. In many jurisdictions, civil law grants the right to execute reprisals from the sovereign, while in others, it is granted by the judges.
By the law of nations the property of all captures is devoted to discharge the debt, and defray the expenses incurred, the remainder of which, after due satisfaction obtained, and peace concluded, should be restored. By the civil law the persons interested are summoned to appear, the property is sold by public authority, and the money, accruing from thence, divided among all who are entitled to a share of the same. But these and other points of the same kind are to be learned from civilians, who are conversant in such matters, and particularly from Bartolus, who has written upon reprisals. This subject may be closed with one observation, that will in some measure tend to soften the rigour of this stern, but necessary right, and that observation is, that such as by not discharging a debt, or granting redress, have occasioned reprisals to be made, are bound, in justice and honour, to make good the losses of those, who have thereby suffered.
According to international law, the property from all captures is meant to pay off debts and cover incurred expenses. Any remaining assets, after all debts are settled and peace is achieved, should be returned. Under civil law, interested parties are called to appear, the property is sold by public authority, and the proceeds are distributed among those entitled to a share. These and similar points should be learned from legal experts, especially from Bartolus, who has written about reprisals. This topic can be concluded with one thought, which helps soften the strictness of this tough but necessary right: those who cause reprisals by failing to pay a debt or provide redress are obligated, in fairness and honor, to compensate those who have suffered as a result.
CHAPTER III.
On Just or Solemn War According to International Law on Declarations of War.
Solemn war, according to the Law of Nations between different states—A people, though engaged in unjust war, to be distinguished from pirates and robbers—Change in the condition of belligerents—Formal war can be made by the Sovereign power alone—Declaration of war—The Law of Nature, Law of Nations, respecting the same—Declaration, conditional, absolute—Forms of declaration introduced by the civil law—War declared against a Sovereign includes his subjects, and allies—The reason why allies are included—Declarations, why necessary to establish certain effects—Whether actual warfare immediately follows a declaration, considered—Whether the violation of an Ambassador's rights to be a just ground of war.
Solemn war, as defined by international law between nations—A people, even if engaged in an unfair war, should still be distinguished from pirates and criminals—Changes in the status of those taking part in the conflict—Only the sovereign authority can officially declare war—War declaration—The principles of nature and international law concerning this—Declarations can be either conditional or absolute—Forms of declaration as set out by civil law—A war declared against a sovereign also affects their subjects and allies—The reason allies are included—Declarations are essential to create specific effects—Whether actual fighting starts immediately after a declaration is taken into account—Whether breaching an ambassador's rights justifies going to war.
I. In the first book of this treatise it was observed, that according to the best writers, a war is defined to be just, not on account of the CAUSES solely, in which it originates, nor on account of the MAGNITUDE of its objects, but from certain, peculiar, effects of right, with which it is attended.
I. In the first book of this treatise, it was noted that according to the best writers, a war is considered just not just because of the CAUSES that start it, or the Magnitude of its aims, but because of specific, unique effects of right that accompany it.
But to what kind of war such an appellation most duly belongs will be best understood by considering the definition, which the Roman Lawyers have given of a PUBLIC or NATIONAL enemy. "Those, says Pomponius, are PUBLIC and LAWFUL ENEMIES, with whose STATE our own is engaged in war: but enemies of every other description, come under the denomination of pirates and robbers." With that opinion Ulpian entirely accords, making an additional observation, that "if any one be taken by robbers, as he is not a lawful prisoner of war, he cannot claim of his own state the right of postliminium. But if he be taken prisoner by a public enemy of the state, being considered as a prisoner of war, he is entitled by the right of postliminium to be restored to his former condition."
But to understand what kind of war truly deserves this name, it’s best to look at the definition provided by the Roman lawyers of a PUBLIC or NATIONAL enemy. "Those," says Pomponius, "are the PUBLIC and LEGAL ENEMIES, with whom our STATE is at war: but enemies of any other kind are classified as pirates and robbers." Ulpian fully agrees with this view, adding that "if someone is captured by robbers, since they are not a lawful prisoner of war, they cannot claim the right of postliminium from their own state. However, if they are captured by a public enemy of the state, being regarded as a prisoner of war, they are entitled to be restored to their former status under the right of postliminium."
These opinions are supported by that of Paulus, who maintains, that persons captured by pirates still continue free, that is, are not to be considered as prisoners, for whom an exchange may be demanded. So that by the opinion of the Roman Lawyers it is evident, that no war315 is considered to be lawful, regular, and formal, except that which is begun and carried on by the sovereign power of each country. Cicero, in his fourth Philippic, describes "a public and authorised enemy to be the person, who possesses the civil and military powers of the state, who can command the treasury, and the services of the people in support of his measures, and who, as occasions offer, has power to conclude treaties of peace and amity."
These views are backed by Paulus, who argues that people taken by pirates remain free and should not be viewed as prisoners, for whom a ransom might be sought. According to Roman lawyers, it is clear that no war315 is seen as lawful, proper, and formal unless it is started and conducted by the sovereign authority of each nation. In his fourth Philippic, Cicero describes "a public and authorized enemy as someone who holds the civil and military powers of the state, who can control the treasury and enlist the support of the people for his initiatives, and who, when opportunities arise, has the authority to make peace treaties and alliances."
II. A state, though it may commit some act of aggression, or injustice, does not thereby lose its political capacity, nor can a band of pirates or robbers ever become a state, although they may preserve among themselves that degree of subordination, which is absolutely necessary to the subsistence of all society. For with the latter, the commission of crime is the SOLE bond of union, whereas the former, though not always free from blame, but occasionally deviating from the laws of nature, which in many cases have been in a great measure obliterated, still regulate their conduct by the treaties, which they have made, and certain customs that have been established, being united among themselves for the mutual support of lawful rights, and connected with foreign states by known rules of standing polity.
II. A state, even if it sometimes acts aggressively or unjustly, doesn’t lose its political authority. On the other hand, a group of pirates or robbers can't ever become a state, even if they maintain a certain level of subordination that's essential for any society to function. In the case of the latter, committing crimes is the only thing that holds them together, while a state, despite not always being blameless and occasionally straying from natural laws—which have often been largely disregarded—still guides its actions by the treaties it has signed and established customs. They unite for the protection of lawful rights and are connected to foreign states through well-defined political rules.
The Scholiast, upon Thucydides, remarks that the Greeks, at the time when piracy was reckoned lawful, forebore committing massacres, or nightly depredations, and carrying off the oxen that were necessary for the plough. We are informed by Strabo, that other nations too, who lived by plunder, after they had returned home from their predatory voyages, sent messages to the owners, whom they had plundered, to know if they would redeem the captures at a fair price.
The Scholiast, commenting on Thucydides, notes that the Greeks, when piracy was considered legal, refrained from committing massacres, nightly raids, and stealing cattle needed for farming. Strabo tells us that other nations who also relied on plunder, after returning home from their raiding trips, would message their victims to see if they wanted to buy back their stolen goods at a reasonable price.
In morals, the whole system often derives its name from some one of the principal parts, as Cicero remarks, in the fifth book of his Bounds of Good and Evil, and Galen observes that a mixture is often called by the name of its chief ingredient. So that Cicero is not altogether correct in saying, that a state is not merely diseased, but entirely destroyed, by the injustice of its component and leading members. For a morbid body is still a body, and a state, though dreadfully diseased, is still a political being, as long as its laws and tribunals and other necessary parts of its constitution remain, to administer justice and give redress to foreigners, no less316 than to private subjects in their actions against each other.
In morality, a whole system often gets its name from one of its main components, as Cicero notes in the fifth book of his Limits of Good and Evil, and Galen points out that a mixture is often named after its primary ingredient. So, Cicero is not entirely right in saying that a state is not just unhealthy but completely destroyed by the wrongdoing of its key members. A sick body is still a body, and a state, even if seriously ailing, is still a political entity as long as its laws, courts, and other essential parts of its structure are there to administer justice and provide recourse for foreigners just as they do for private citizens in their disputes with one another.
There is a beautiful observation in Dion Chrysostom, who compares the law of a state, particularly that branch of it relating to the law of nations, to the body animated by the soul, upon the departure of which the corporeal frame becomes a mass of lifeless clay: in the same manner political society cannot subsist without the guiding and controuling principle of law. Aristides, encouraging the Rhodians to harmony, observes, that even under a tyrannical government many good laws may be found.
There’s a lovely observation by Dion Chrysostom, who compares the laws of a state, especially the ones related to international law, to a body that’s alive because of the soul; when the soul leaves, the body turns into a lump of lifeless clay. Similarly, a political society can’t survive without the guiding and controlling principle of law. Aristides, while encouraging the Rhodians to work together, notes that even in a tyrannical government, there can still be good laws.
These are points, which may be cleared up by examples. Thus Ulpian maintains that those who are captured by pirates cannot be considered as prisoners of war: but if captured by the Germans, for instance, or any national enemy, they lose their liberty for a time. But the Germans, as we are informed by Caesar, thought acts of plunder, if committed in a foreign territory, no disgrace. Tacitus says that the Cattians, a noble race of people in Germany, and the Garamantians were addicted to the same habits of plunder, yet still retained their rank among states.—Such is the difference between a national and political body, and a band of men uniting together SOLELY FOR THE COMMISSION OF CRIMES.
These are points that can be clarified with examples. For instance, Ulpian argues that those who are captured by pirates shouldn’t be considered prisoners of war. However, if they're captured by the Germans, or any national enemy, they lose their freedom for a while. According to Caesar, the Germans saw acts of plunder committed in foreign lands as no shame. Tacitus mentions that the Cattians, a noble group from Germany, and the Garamantians had similar plundering habits, yet they still maintained their status among nations. This highlights the difference between a national and political entity and a group of individuals coming together ONLY FOR THE COMMISSION OF CRIMES.
III. A change may occur not only in the situations of individuals, as in those of Jephthah, Arsaces, and Viriatus, who, from being leaders of voluntary bands, became lawful commanders; but the same has also happened with respect to whole communities, which being originally composed of nothing but freebooters have, by the gradual course and changes of time, risen to the rank and dignity of states.
III. A change can happen not just in the situations of individuals, like Jephthah, Arsaces, and Viriatus, who went from being leaders of informal groups to recognized commanders; it has also occurred with entire communities that, initially made up entirely of bandits, have over time evolved into legitimate states with rank and dignity.
IV. What has been said with respect to the right of making formal and lawful war, being vested in the sovereign power alone, includes those who have any share in the sovereign power, as the different communities forming the States General of many commonwealths. The same rule will hold good of those, who are not SUBJECTS of a superior state, but joined to it in confederacy by an unequal treaty: innumerable instances of which are to be found in history. This was the case between the Romans and their allies, the Volscians, the Latins, and the Spaniards: and all whom we read of being engaged in wars, which were considered as lawful and just.
IV. What has been said about the right to wage formal and lawful war, which is held exclusively by the sovereign power, also applies to those who share in that power, such as the various communities that make up the States General of many commonwealths. The same principle applies to those who are not Topics of a superior state but are connected to it through an unequal treaty: countless examples of this can be found in history. This was true for the Romans and their allies, including the Volscians, the Latins, and the Spaniards, and for all those we read about who were involved in wars that were considered lawful and just.
317 V. But to make a war just, according to this meaning, it must not only be carried on by the sovereign authority on both sides, but it must also be duly and formally declared, and declared in such a manner, as to be known to each of the belligerent powers. Cicero, in the first book of his offices, points out "the equity of the rules prescribed by the Roman Law for the declaration of war, from whence it may be concluded that no war is regular or just, but such as is undertaken to compel restitution, and to procure indemnity for injuries, and that too accompanied with a formal declaration." Livy also in the same manner deems an observance of these rules requisite to form the characteristic of a just war. And describing an incursion of the Acarnanians into Attica, and their ravaging the country, he says that "those acts of irritation ended in a declaration of JUST and REGULAR war on both sides."
317 V. To make a war just, it must not only be waged by the official authority of both sides, but it also needs to be properly and formally declared in a way that is known to each of the warring parties. Cicero, in the first book of his offices, highlights the fairness of the rules set by Roman Law for declaring war, which leads to the conclusion that no war is legitimate or just unless it aims to enforce restitution and secure compensation for wrongs, and is accompanied by a formal declaration. Livy similarly believes that following these rules is essential for defining a just war. When describing an invasion of the Acarnanians into Attica and their devastation of the land, he remarks that "those acts of aggression led to a declaration of JUST and NORMAL war on both sides."
VI. In order to understand all these points clearly respecting the declaration of war, an accurate distinction must be made between the principles, which are founded on the law of nature itself, and those, which, though not derived immediately from that source, are still found to be just: it will be necessary also to examine, what is required by the law of nations towards obtaining, IN WAR, all the consequences, privileges and effects of that law, and, at the same time, to investigate the consequences and rights arising from the peculiar laws and customs of particular nations.
VI. To clearly understand all these points regarding the declaration of war, we need to make a clear distinction between the principles based on the law of nature itself and those that, while not directly sourced from it, are still considered just. It is also important to examine what international law requires to achieve, In battle, all the consequences, privileges, and effects of that law, while simultaneously investigating the consequences and rights that arise from the specific laws and customs of individual nations.
To repel force, or to punish a delinquent, the law of nature requires no declaration. And, as Thucydides relates, Sthenelaidas, one of the Ephori, maintains that "where we have been injured, not by WORDS, but by ACTIONS, the matter cannot be decided by WORDS and FORMS." And Aelian, after Plato, observes that it is not the declaration of the Herald, but the voice and law of nature, which proclaim war, undertaken to repel force. Hence Dion Chrysostom, in addressing the Nicomedians, says that many wars are begun without any declaration.
To defend against force or to punish a wrongdoer, natural law doesn't need a formal announcement. As Thucydides recounts, Sthenelaidas, one of the Ephori, argues that "when we've been harmed, not by WORDS, but by ACTIONS, the issue can't be resolved by WORDS and FORMS." Aelian, following Plato, points out that it's not the announcement of the Herald, but the voice and law of nature that declare war meant to defend against force. Therefore, Dion Chrysostom, while speaking to the Nicomedians, notes that many wars start without any declaration.
Upon the same ground Livy condemns the conduct of Menippus, a general belonging to Antiochus for having killed some Roman citizens before any declaration of war had been made, or even before a sword had been drawn, or a drop of blood spilt, to shew that hostilities were intended. By this objection he proves that either a318 formal declaration, or some act indicative of hostilities was deemed requisite to justify actual warfare.
Upon the same point, Livy criticizes the actions of Menippus, a general under Antiochus, for killing some Roman citizens before any war was declared, or even before a sword was drawn or a drop of blood was shed to indicate that hostilities were intended. By raising this issue, he demonstrates that either a formal declaration or some act showing intent to fight was considered necessary to justify actual warfare.
Neither, if we follow the law of nature, is there any more occasion for notice or declaration, where an owner intends to lay hands upon HIS OWN PROPERTY. But whenever one thing is taken in return for another, or the property of a debtor is seized for the recovery of a debt, and, especially, if any one intends seizing the property of those, who are subjects to the debtor, a formal demand must be made, as a proof that recourse to such security is the only means left of obtaining redress and satisfaction. Such a demand is necessary because that is not a PRIMARY and ORIGINAL right, but a SECONDARY right, SUBSTITUTED in the place of the primary and original, by the artificial rules of civil law.
Neither, if we follow the law of nature, is there any need for notification or declaration when an owner plans to take action regarding HIS OWN PROPERTY. However, when one thing is exchanged for another, or a debtor's property is seized to recover a debt, and especially if someone intends to take the property of those who are connected to the debtor, a formal demand must be made as proof that turning to such security is the only way left to seek remedy and satisfaction. Such a demand is necessary because this is not a PRIMARY and Please provide the text you would like me to modernize. right, but a SECONDARY right, Replaced in place of the primary and original, by the artificial rules of civil law.
In the same manner to justify an attack upon a sovereign power for the aggressions and debts of its subjects, a previous remonstrance, and a proper demand of justice must be made to that power. For it is only by refusing to punish the guilty, or to grant indemnity to the injured, that states or sovereigns can be implicated in the misconduct of their subjects.60 But even where the law of nature does not directly prescribe that such a remonstrance or demand should be made, yet the common principles of humanity and equity will recommend the61 use of any means, that may prevent recourse to the calamities of war. The commandment given by God to the Hebrews, to send a message of peace to any state or city, before they began an intended attack, was designed as a special command to that people, yet some have confounded it with the general law of nations. For it was not ANY kind of peace that was meant by that injunction, but only such a peace as imposed terms of SUBJECTION and TRIBUTE. We are informed by Xenophon, that when Cyrus went into the country of the Armenians, he sent messengers to the king, to demand the tribute and number of troops, which had been stipulated by treaty.
In the same way to justify an attack on a sovereign power for the actions and debts of its citizens, a prior protest and a proper request for justice must be made to that power. It’s only by refusing to punish the guilty or to compensate the injured that states or sovereigns can be held responsible for the misconduct of their subjects.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ However, even when the law of nature doesn't explicitly require such a protest or request, the common principles of humanity and fairness will suggest the__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ use of any means that may prevent the horrors of war. The command given by God to the Hebrews to send a message of peace to any state or city before launching an attack was intended as a specific command for that people, yet some have mistakenly associated it with the general law of nations. For it was not ANY kind of peace that was meant by that command, but only a peace that imposed terms of DOMINATION and Tribute. We learn from Xenophon that when Cyrus went into the lands of the Armenians, he sent messengers to the king to demand the tribute and number of troops that had been agreed upon in treaty.
But to obtain the peculiar rights and consequences resulting from the law of nations, a declaration of war by one of the parties, at least, if not by both, is absolutely requisite in all cases.
But to gain the specific rights and outcomes that come from international law, a declaration of war by at least one of the parties, if not both, is absolutely necessary in all situations.
VII. Those declarations are either conditional or absolute. A conditional declaration is that which is coupled319 with a demand of restitution or redress. Under the name of restitution, the Fecial Law of Rome, that is the Law respecting declarations of war, comprehended not only the claims, which OWNERSHIP established, but the prosecution of EVERY right arising from criminal or civil causes.
VII. Those statements are either conditional or absolute. A conditional statement is one that is linked319 to a request for compensation or justice. Under the term restitution, the Ritual Law of Rome, which pertains to the War declaration laws, included not just the claims established by OWNERSHIP, but also the pursuit of EVERY right arising from criminal or civil cases.
Hence the declarations were couched in terms, requiring restoration, satisfaction, or surrender. Here, by the term, surrender, the party appealed to is understood to have the option either of punishing the offender, himself, or delivering him up to the aggrieved person. This manner of demanding restitution is, according to the testimony of Pliny, called CLARIGATION, that is, a LOUD and FORMAL DEMAND. Livy gives us an example of a conditional and qualified declaration, wherein the aggrieved power denounces "a determined resolution to prosecute her rights with the utmost violence, if the aggressor will not make reparation and atonement for the injury he has done." Tacitus also relates the substance of a dispatch sent to Caecina by Germanicus, wherein he declares, that "if the ringleaders of the mutinous and rebellious legions are not immediately punished, he will advance with his army, and put the whole to the sword."
Hence the declarations were phrased in terms that required restoration, compensation, or surrender. Here, by the term surrender, the party being addressed is understood to have the option of either punishing the offender themselves or handing them over to the aggrieved party. This way of demanding restitution is, according to Pliny's testimony, called Clarification, which means a LOUD and Formal Request. Livy provides an example of a conditional and qualified declaration, where the aggrieved power announces "a firm intention to pursue her rights with the utmost force if the aggressor does not make amends and atone for the harm caused." Tacitus also recounts a message sent to Caecina by Germanicus, where he states that "if the leaders of the mutinous and rebellious legions are not punished immediately, he will march with his army and put them all to the sword."
An ABSOLUTE declaration of war is issued, where any power has already begun hostilities, or committed acts which call for exemplary punishment. Sometimes indeed a conditional, is followed by an absolute war, though in such a case the latter is not actually necessary, but only a confirmation of the former. This gave rise to the form, which says, "an appeal is hereby made against such a people, as unjust and refusing to grant redress." There is another form also purporting, that "the principal herald of the Roman citizens has made known to the principal herald of the ancient Latins, and to the Latin people, that redress is demanded of them by just and lawful war, on account of all the disputes which they have refused to settle, and the indemnities which they have been bound to grant, and have refused; and that this is the only means remaining to recover all that has been unjustly detained." There is also a third mode of declaration, which runs in the following tenour; "Since the ancient people of the Latins have committed aggressions against the people of Rome, the people of Rome, with the advice and consent of the senate, declare war against them, and in the name of the senate and people of Rome their purpose is thus published."
An ABSOLUTE declaration of war is issued when any power has already started hostilities or committed acts that demand serious punishment. Sometimes a conditional declaration is followed by an absolute war, although in such cases the latter is mostly just a confirmation of the former. This led to a form stating, "an appeal is hereby made against such a people, as unjust and refusing to provide remedies." There’s another form that states, "the chief herald of the Roman citizens has informed the chief herald of the ancient Latins, and the Latin people, that redress is demanded from them through just and lawful war, due to all the disputes they have refused to resolve and the compensations they were obligated to provide but did not; and that this is the only way left to recover everything that has been unjustly withheld." There’s also a third way of declaring war, which goes as follows; "Since the ancient Latins have attacked the people of Rome, the people of Rome, with the advice and consent of the senate, declare war against them, and in the name of the senate and people of Rome, their intent is hereby announced."
320 But that in case of RENEWED wars such a declaration is not absolutely necessary, appears from the circumstance of its being made in due form at the nearest garrison, and not PERSONALLY to the offender himself, according to the answer given by the heralds, when they were consulted in the case of Philip of Macedon, and afterwards respecting Antiochus. Whereas a declaration for the FIRST time should be made to the enemy himself. Indeed in the war against Pyrrhus the declaration was made to one of his soldiers, in the Flaminian Circus, where, as Servius observes in his notes on the sixth book of the Aeneid, he was commanded to purchase a piece of ground, as a handle for dispute. A proof also that IN SOME CASES a declaration is superfluous may be taken from the circumstance that war is frequently declared by BOTH SIDES, which was done by the Corcyraeans and Corinthians in the Peloponnesian war, though a declaration by one of the parties would have been sufficient.
320 However, in the case of RENEWED conflicts, such a declaration isn't strictly necessary, as seen from the fact that it’s made formally at the nearest military base, rather than For me to the wrongdoer, according to the response given by the heralds when they were consulted about Philip of Macedon and later regarding Antiochus. In contrast, a declaration for the FIRST time should be communicated directly to the enemy. In the war against Pyrrhus, for example, the declaration was made to one of his soldiers in the Flaminian Circus, where, as Servius points out in his notes on the sixth book of the Aeneid, he was instructed to buy a piece of land, which became a point of contention. Additionally, the fact that In some situations a declaration is unnecessary can be illustrated by the occurrence that war is often declared by BOTH SIDES, as was the case with the Corcyraeans and Corinthians during the Peloponnesian war, even though a declaration from just one side would have sufficed.
VIII. As to the use of the caduceum, or staff with the figure of two snakes twisted around it, which ambassadors carried, when they sued for peace, it was a ceremony peculiar to the Greeks, and not derived from the GENERAL law of nations. The Romans in the same manner had particular customs, such as using vervain in forming alliances, throwing a bloody spear, as a declaration of war, renouncing all former friendship and alliance at the expiration of thirty days, after satisfaction had been demanded and refused, and again throwing another spear. None of these PECULIAR customs ought to be confounded with the GENERAL law of nations. For Arnobius informs us, that in his time many of them had fallen into disuse, and even in the time of Varro some of them were omitted. The third Punic war indeed was not declared till the moment of its actual commencement.
VIII. The use of the caduceum, or the staff with two snakes wrapped around it, which ambassadors carried when seeking peace, was a ceremony unique to the Greeks, and not based on the GENERAL law of nations. The Romans also had specific customs, like using vervain to form alliances, throwing a bloody spear to declare war, and ending all prior friendships and alliances after thirty days if satisfaction was asked for and refused, followed by throwing another spear. None of these WEIRD customs should be confused with the GENERAL law of nations. Arnobius tells us that many of these customs had fallen out of use by his time, and even in Varro's time, some were neglected. The third Punic War, in fact, was only declared at the moment it actually began.
IX. A declaration of war, made against a sovereign, includes not only his own subjects, but all who are likely to become his associates, as thereby they make themselves accessories in the war. And this is what the modern lawyers mean, when they say that, in bidding defiance to a Prince, we bid defiance to all his associates. For they give the name of defiance to a declaration of war. By which is understood the war carried on with the power against whom it has been declared. Thus upon war being declared against Antiochus, there was no occasion for a separate declaration against the Aetolians,321 who had openly joined Antiochus. For, as the heralds in their answer justly observed, the Aetolians had, by that act, voluntarily brought war upon themselves.
IX. A declaration of war against a ruler affects not only their own people but also anyone likely to join them, as these individuals become participants in the conflict. This is what modern lawyers mean when they say that by defying a Prince, we are defying all his allies. They consider a declaration of war to be an act of defiance. This refers to the war being fought against the power that has been challenged. For example, when war was declared against Antiochus, there was no need for a separate declaration against the Aetolians, who had openly sided with Antiochus. As the heralds rightly noted in their response, the Aetolians had, by their actions, voluntarily brought war upon themselves.321
X. But if after the conclusion of such a war it should be deemed expedient to attack any other nation or king for having furnished supplies and assistance towards that war, a new declaration of war will be necessary. For that nation or king is then to be considered, not as an accessory, but as a principal enemy. And therefore it was with reason said, that the war of Manlius against the Galatians, and that of Caesar against Ariovistus, were not just wars according to the law of nations. For war was made upon them not as accessories, but as principals. So that for this purpose, as the law of nations would have required a declaration, in the same manner the Roman law would have required a new order of the Senate.
X. But if, after the end of such a war, it is deemed necessary to attack any other nation or ruler for providing supplies and support during that war, a new declaration of war will be required. That nation or ruler would then be seen not as a supporter, but as a main enemy. Thus, it was rightly stated that the war of Manlius against the Galatians and Caesar's war against Ariovistus were not justified wars according to international law. Those wars were waged against them not as supporters, but as main enemies. Therefore, for this reason, just as international law would have required a declaration, Roman law would also have required a new order from the Senate.
For on the motion being made for the war with Antiochus, the question was also put, whether it should not at the same time be made with his adherents. The same rule also being observed against King Perseus, it must be understood, as including the adherents during all the time that war with those princes continued; and implicating all, who in reality gave them support.
For the motion to declare war against Antiochus, the question was also raised about whether it should include his supporters at the same time. The same rule applied to King Perseus, meaning it included his supporters for the entire duration of the war with those kings, and concerned everyone who actually provided them assistance.
XI. The reason why a declaration is necessary to constitute what is deemed, according to the law of nations, a just war, is not that which some writers assign. For they allege that it is to prevent every appearance of clandestine and treacherous dealing: an openness, which may be dignified with the name of magnanimity, rather than entitled a matter of right. On this point, we are informed that some nations have gone so far, as to settle and make known the very time and place of a general engagement.
XI. The reason a declaration is necessary to establish what is considered, according to international law, a just war is not the one some writers suggest. They claim it’s to avoid any appearance of secretive and deceitful actions; this openness can be seen as noble rather than a matter of entitlement. In this regard, we learn that some nations have even specified the exact time and location of a major battle.
But waving all conjecture, a more satisfactory reason may be found in the necessity that it should be known for CERTAIN, that a war is not the PRIVATE undertaking of bold ADVENTURERS, but made and sanctioned by the PUBLIC and SOVEREIGN authority on both sides; so that it is attended with the effects of binding all the subjects of the respective states;—and it is accompanied also with other consequences and rights, which do not belong to wars against pirates, and to civil wars.
But putting aside all speculation, a better reason might be that it needs to be made clear that a war isn’t just a personal venture of daring individuals, but rather one that is created and approved by the public and sovereign authority on both sides. This means it has impacts that bind all members of the respective states, and it also leads to other consequences and rights that don’t apply to wars against pirates or civil wars.
XII. There is much truth indeed in the observations, which some have made, and which they have produced322 examples to confirm, that even in wars of this kind all captures become the lawful prize of the captors.
XII. There is a lot of truth in the remarks that some people have made, and which they have provided322 examples to support, that even in wars of this nature, all captures become the legal prize of the captors.
Yet this is only partially true, and that too, according to the law of nature, and not according to the voluntary law of nations. For the latter only makes provision to secure the rights of nations, as WHOLE communities, and not of those, who, as in civil wars, form but ONE PART of a nation.
Yet this is only partially true, and that too, according to the law of nature, and not according to the voluntary law of nations. For the latter only makes provisions to secure the rights of nations, as ENTIRE communities, and not of those who, as in civil wars, form only ONE PART of a nation.
The same writers are mistaken too in the supposition that defensive wars require no declaration. For it is no less necessary to shew by way of vindication that it is a defensive war, and at the same time by public declaration to give it the character of a national and lawful war, in order to establish those rights and consequences, that have been already mentioned, and which will hereafter be more fully explained.
The same writers are wrong in thinking that defensive wars don’t need a declaration. It's just as important to prove that it's a defensive war and at the same time to publicly declare it to classify it as a national and lawful war. This is necessary to establish the rights and consequences that have already been mentioned and will be explained in more detail later.
XIII. They maintain another position also, which is by no means true, and that is, that a power ought not IMMEDIATELY to follow up a declaration of war with actual hostilities, as Cyrus did to the Armenians, and the Romans to the Carthaginians. For the law of nations requires the intervention of no DEFINITE time between the declaration and the commencement of war.
XIII. They also hold another view that is definitely untrue, which is that a power shouldn't immediately follow a declaration of war with actual fighting, like Cyrus did with the Armenians and the Romans did with the Carthaginians. The law of nations doesn't specify any definite period that must pass between the declaration and the start of war.
There may indeed be some cases, where natural justice will render such a delay proper. Thus, for instance, where reparation for injury, or the punishment of aggressors is demanded, it is but reasonable to wait till it can be known, whether the just demand will be complied with or rejected.
There might be some situations where natural justice makes a delay appropriate. For example, when seeking compensation for harm or punishing wrongdoers, it makes sense to wait until we know whether the fair request will be accepted or denied.
XIV. In order to establish the same consequences, a declaration will be equally necessary too, where the rights of Ambassadors have been violated. Yet it will be sufficient for it to be made in the manner, in which it may be done with the greatest safety. As in many other matters, in places which afford no security, satisfaction is demanded by denunciation or summons.
XIV. To achieve the same results, a declaration will also be required when the rights of Ambassadors have been violated. However, it should be made in the way that ensures the greatest safety. As with many other issues, in places that offer no security, satisfaction is sought through a formal complaint or summons.
CHAPTER IV.
On the Right to Kill an Enemy in Justified War and Carry Out Other Acts of Aggression.
General explanation of the effects of formal war—Distinction between lawful and innocent impunity—Merit of the latter—Examples added to explain it—General effects of former war considered with respect to lawful impunity—The reason of their introduction—Historical testimonies—By this right all persons, found within an enemy's territory, objects of hostility—Also all going thither before the war—The subjects of an enemy liable to be seized everywhere, except protected by the laws of a neutral territory—Case of women and children—Case of prisoners—Of those whose voluntary offer of surrender is rejected—Unconditional surrender—Retaliation—Obstinate defence—Hostages.
A general overview of the impact of formal warfare—The difference between lawful and innocent impunity—The importance of the latter—Examples given for clarification—The overall impact of previous wars regarding lawful impunity—The reasons for their establishment—Historical evidence—Under this principle, anyone found in enemy territory is viewed as a legitimate target—As well as anyone who enters that territory before the onset of war—Enemies can be captured anywhere, unless protected by neutral territory laws—The situation for women and children—The status of prisoners—Those whose attempts to surrender are rejected—Unconditional surrender—Retaliation—Persistent defense—Hostages.
I. Servius in his comment on the passage of Virgil, where that poet says that war "will authorise mutual acts of destruction and rapine," in tracing the fecial or herald's law to Ancus Martius, and even beyond him to a still more remote period, remarks that, "if ever the persons or property of subjects, belonging to the Roman state, were seized and carried off by any other nation, the principal Herald, or King at arms went out with the sacred ministers, who presided at the making of solemn treaties, and proceeding to the verge of the territories of the offending nation, declared with a loud voice the cause of the war, and the refusal of that nation either to restore what had been seized, or to deliver up the aggressors to justice. After this he threw a spear to indicate that war and all its consequences were from that moment begun."
I. Servius, in his commentary on the passage from Virgil where the poet states that war "will justify mutual acts of destruction and looting," traces the tradition of the fecial or herald's law back to Ancus Martius and even further back to an even more ancient period. He notes that "if the people or property of individuals belonging to the Roman state were ever taken and carried off by another nation, the Chief Herald or King at arms would go out with the sacred officials who oversaw the making of formal treaties. They would approach the borders of the offending nation and loudly declare the reason for the war, along with that nation’s refusal to either return what was taken or hand over the wrongdoers for justice. After this, he would throw a spear to symbolize that war and all its consequences had officially begun."
The commentator had previously observed that the ancients gave the name of rapine to every act of hostility even where there was no act of plunder committed; and they likewise called every kind of restitution a satisfaction.
The commentator had previously noted that the ancients referred to any act of hostility as rapine, even when no plunder occurred; they also termed all forms of restitution as satisfaction.
By this explanation we learn that whenever war is proclaimed between two states or sovereigns, it is accompanied with certain rights or consequences, which do not NECESSARILY belong to war itself. And this is perfectly324 conformable to the examples from the Roman Lawyers, which have been before produced.
By this explanation, we understand that whenever war is declared between two states or rulers, it is associated with specific rights or consequences that do not NEEDED belong to war itself. This aligns perfectly with the examples provided by the Roman Lawyers, which have been mentioned earlier. 324
II. But it will be proper to consider how far the lawfulness, which Virgil speaks of, extends. For the term lawful sometimes implies whatever is just and pious in all respects, although the pursuit of a different course may perhaps be more laudable: according to the expression of St. Paul, who says, "all things are lawful to me, but all things are not expedient." Ulpian is speaking of a seller, who, at the expiration of a certain period, is not answerable for the safety of goods, which a buyer has neglected to take away, says he, will yet think himself bound in EQUITY to preserve them with all imaginable care. On some occasions when it is said, that men may LAWFULLY do a thing, the expression only means that doing such act will not subject them to human and legal penalties, but it by no means indicates that the action is strictly conformable to the rule of religion and morality. Thus among the Lacedaemonians and Egyptians stealing was allowed: an indulgence that by no means took away the GUILT of theft.
II. However, it’s important to consider the extent of the lawfulness that Virgil refers to. The term lawful sometimes means whatever is fair and virtuous in every way, even though choosing a different path might be more commendable. As St. Paul says, "everything is lawful for me, but not everything is beneficial." Ulpian talks about a seller who, after a specific period, is no longer responsible for the safety of goods that the buyer failed to collect, yet he feels morally obligated to take care of them as best as he can. Sometimes when people say that men can lawfully do something, it means that their actions won’t expose them to human and legal consequences, but it certainly doesn’t mean that the action aligns perfectly with religious and moral standards. For example, among the Spartans and Egyptians, stealing was permitted—a leniency that didn’t erase the guilt of theft.
Cicero in the fifth of his Tusculan questions, speaking of Cinna, beautifully and justly points out this abuse of the word, LAWFUL. "He seems to me, says he, a wretched man indeed for having done those acts, and for having been in a situation, where they might be thought lawful. It can never be lawful for any man to do wrong: but we fall into a great mistake in the use of that word: for we consider a thing to be lawful, which any one may do with impunity." This is the meaning, in which the term is generally understood, as the same orator, in addressing the judges in behalf of Rabirius Posthumus, observes, "it behoves you to consider, what is becoming your character, and not what the rigour of the law allows you to inflict. For if you consult the full extent of your authority, you may make away with any citizen you please."
Cicero, in the fifth of his Tusculan Questions, talks about Cinna and accurately highlights the misuse of the word 合法. "He appears to me," he says, "to be a truly miserable man for having committed those acts and for being in a position where they could be considered lawful. It can never be lawful for anyone to do wrong, but we often make a big mistake in how we use that word. We think something is lawful just because someone can do it without facing consequences." This is the meaning in which the term is generally understood, as the same orator, while addressing the judges on behalf of Rabirius Posthumus, notes, "It’s important for you to consider what reflects your character, not just what the strictness of the law permits you to do. Because if you only think about your full power, you could eliminate any citizen you want."
In the same manner legislators, as it was proved in a former book of this treatise, are not accountable, in their legislative capacity, to any human tribunal, for the laws, which they make, yet they cannot, in a moral point of view, avail themselves of this transcendent power to enact a thing that is evidently unjust. In this sense we often meet with a distinction made between what is proper or right, and what is lawful. Thus Cicero, in his speech for Milo, makes the LAW OF NATURE the standard of what is325 RIGHT, and LEGAL AUTHORITY, the standard of what is lawful.
In the same way, legislators, as previously demonstrated in an earlier section of this work, are not answerable to any human court for the laws they create in their official roles. However, they cannot, from a moral standpoint, use this supreme power to implement something that is clearly unjust. In this context, we often hear a distinction made between what is right or proper and what is lawful. For example, Cicero, in his speech for Milo, uses the Natural Law as the benchmark for what is325 RIGHT, and Legal Authority as the benchmark for what is lawful.
III. Thus qualified, the annoyance of an enemy, either in his person or property, is lawful. This right extends not only to the power engaged in a just war, and who in her hostilities confines herself within the practice established by the law of nature, but each side without distinction has a right to employ the same means of annoyance. So that any one taken in arms, even in another's territory, cannot be treated as a robber, malefactor, or murderer, nor can even that neutral power, in whose territory he is taken, treat him as an enemy, for being found in arms.
III. With that clarification, bothering an enemy, whether through their person or their property, is allowed. This right applies not just to the party involved in a just war, who conducts their actions in line with natural law, but each side equally has the right to use the same methods of annoyance. Therefore, anyone caught fighting, even in someone else's territory, cannot be seen as a thief, criminal, or murderer, nor can the neutral power in whose territory they are caught label them as an enemy simply for being armed.
IV. This principle was established by nations to prevent others from interfering in their disputes, or giving the law to them respecting the rights of war. Besides, if this were not the case, neutral powers would frequently be involved in the wars of others. A reason which the people of Marseilles urged in the dispute between Caesar and Pompey. They alleged that they had neither sufficient judgment to determine on which side justice lay, nor, if they could determine, had they strength to give effect to their decisions.
IV. This principle was created by nations to stop others from stepping in on their conflicts or dictating the rules about war rights. If this wasn't the case, neutral countries would often find themselves caught up in the wars of others. This was a point raised by the people of Marseilles during the dispute between Caesar and Pompey. They argued that they didn't have enough insight to decide which side was just, and even if they could make a decision, they lacked the power to enforce it.
A spectator indeed is but ill qualified to judge, how far, even in the most just war, self-defence, the attainment of indemnity, or the punishment of an aggressor, may be carried. These are points, which, on many, if not most, occasions must be left to the conscience and discretion of the belligerents themselves: a mode far preferable to that of appealing to the mediation, and decision of disinterested and neutral powers. Livy has given an address of the Achaeans to the senate, in which they ask, "how their availing themselves of the rights of war can ever be fairly called in question, or made a subject of discussion?"
A spectator is really not well-equipped to judge how far, even in the most justified war, self-defense, seeking compensation, or punishing an aggressor can go. These are issues that, in many, if not most, cases, must be left to the conscience and judgment of the parties involved: a much better option than relying on the mediation and decisions of unbiased and neutral powers. Livy included a speech from the Achaeans to the senate, where they ask, "how can their exercise of the rights of war ever be fairly questioned or debated?"
Besides the impunity attending certain actions done in war, the acquisition of territory by the right of conquest is another topic of consideration, which will hereafter be examined.
Besides the lack of consequences for certain actions taken during war, acquiring territory through conquest is another subject to consider, which will be explored later.
V. The lawfulness of injuring or destroying the person of a public enemy is supported by the testimony of many of the best writers, both poets, moralists, and historians. In one of the tragedies of Euripides, there is a proverb, which says, that "to kill a public enemy, or an enemy in war is no murder." Therefore the custom of the326 ancient Greeks, which rendered it unlawful and impious to use the same bath, or to partake of the same festivities and sacred rites with a person who had killed another in time of peace, did not extend to any one who had killed a public enemy in war. Killing an enemy is indeed everywhere called a right of war. "The rights of war, says Marcellus in Livy, support me in all that I have done against the enemy." And the same historian gives the address of Alcon to the Saguntines, where he says, "You ought to bear these hardships, rather than suffer your own bodies to be mangled, and your wives and children to be seized and dragged away before your eyes." Cicero in his speech in defence of Marcellus passes a high encomium upon the clemency of Caesar, who, "by the laws of war and the rights of victory, might have put to death all, whom he had spared and protected." And Caesar observes to the Eduans, that "it was an act of kindness in HIM, to spare those whom the laws of war would have authorised him to put to death."
V. The legality of harming or killing a public enemy is backed by the writings of many esteemed poets, moralists, and historians. In one of Euripides' tragedies, there's a saying that "killing a public enemy or an enemy in war is not considered murder." Consequently, the ancient Greeks' custom, which deemed it unlawful and wrong to share a bath or partake in the same festivals and sacred rituals with someone who had killed another in peacetime, did not apply to anyone who had killed a public enemy in war. Killing an enemy is universally recognized as a right of war. "The rights of war," says Marcellus in Livy, "justify everything I have done against the enemy." The same historian recounts Alcon's address to the Saguntines, where he urges, "You should endure these hardships rather than allow your bodies to be mutilated or your wives and children to be captured and dragged away before your eyes." Cicero, in his defense of Marcellus, praises Caesar's mercy, noting that "by the laws of war and the rights of victory, he could have killed everyone he spared and protected." Caesar also tells the Eduans that "it was a kind act on his part to spare those he could have legally executed."
But the rights of war, for which these writers plead, could not PERFECTLY JUSTIFY the putting prisoners to death, but could only grant IMPUNITY to those who availed themselves of the barbarous custom. There is a wide difference however between actions like these, and destroying an enemy by proper means of hostility. For, as Tacitus says, "in the leisure hours of peace the merits and demerits of every case may be examined and weighed, but, in the tumult and confusion of war, the innocent must fall with the guilty": and the same writer, in another place, observes, that "there are many actions, which the principles of humanity cannot ENTIRELY approve, but which the policy of war requires." And it is in this, and no other sense that Lucan has said, "the complexion of right may be assigned to what is wrong."
But the rights of war that these writers advocate for can't ABSOLUTELY JUSTIFY executing prisoners; they can only offer Immunity to those who take part in that brutal practice. There is a significant difference, however, between actions like these and defeating an enemy through legitimate means of conflict. As Tacitus states, "in the quiet moments of peace, the merits and faults of each case can be examined and evaluated, but in the chaos and disorder of war, the innocent often suffer alongside the guilty." He adds in another context that "there are many actions that the principles of humanity cannot COMPLETELY endorse, but that the demands of war dictate." And it is in this context, and no other, that Lucan remarked, "the appearance of right can be given to what is wrong."
VI. This right of making lawful what is done in war is of great extent. For in the first place it comprises, in the number of enemies, not only those who actually bear arms, or who are immediately subjects of the belligerent power, but even all who are within the hostile territories, as appears from the form given by Livy, who says, that "war is declared against the sovereign, and all within his jurisdiction." For which a very good reason may be assigned; because danger is to be apprehended even from THEM, which, in a continued and regular war, establishes the right now under discussion.
VI. The right to legitimize what happens in war is quite broad. First of all, it includes not just those who are actively fighting or are directly subject to the warring power, but also everyone within enemy territory. This is evident from Livy's statement that "war is declared against the sovereign, and all within his jurisdiction." There’s a solid reason for this: there’s a potential threat from THEM, which, in the context of an ongoing and organized conflict, establishes the right being discussed now.
327 Reprisals do not come exactly under the same rule. For like taxes, they were introduced for the discharge of public debts, for no part of which temporary residents, or foreigners are answerable. Therefore Baldus is right in his observation, that, after war is actually begun, much greater latitude is allowed, than in the bare right of making reprisals. So that what is said of foreigners, who enter into an enemy's country, and reside there, after war is avowedly declared and begun, is undoubtedly true.
327 Reprisals don't follow the same rules. Just like taxes, they were created to cover public debts, which temporary residents or foreigners aren't responsible for. That's why Baldus correctly pointed out that once a war starts, there's a lot more flexibility allowed than just the basic right to make reprisals. This means what is said about foreigners who enter an enemy's country and stay there after a war is openly declared and starts is definitely true.
VII. But persons, who had gone to reside there before the war was begun, seem by the law of nations to be included in the number of enemies, unless within a reasonable time they chuse to withdraw. So that the Corcyraeans, when going to besiege Epidamnus, gave leave to all strangers to withdraw, denouncing that they would otherwise be treated as enemies.
VII. However, people who moved there before the war started are considered enemies by international law, unless they choose to leave within a reasonable time. Therefore, when the Corcyraeans were about to siege Epidamnus, they allowed all foreigners to leave, stating that those who didn't would be treated as enemies.
VIII. But the persons of natural-born subjects, who owe permanent allegiance to a hostile power may, according to the law of nations, be attacked, or seized, wherever they are found. For whenever, as it was said before, war is declared against any power, it is at the same time declared against all the subjects of that power. And the law of nations authorises us to attack an enemy in every place: An opinion supported by most legal authorities: thus Marcian says "that deserters may be killed in the same manner as enemies, wherever they are found." They may be lawfully killed there, or in their own country, in the enemy's country, in a country belonging to no one, or on the sea. But as to the unlawfulness of killing, or violently molesting them in a neutral territory, this protection does not result from any personal privileges of THEIR OWN, but from the rights of the SOVEREIGN of that country. For all civil societies had an undoubted right to establish it as a standing maxim that no violence should be offered to any person within their territories, nor any punishment inflicted but by due process of law. For where tribunals retain their authority in full vigour, to try the merits of every offence, and, after impartial inquiry, to acquit the innocent, or condemn the guilty, the power of the sword must be restrained from inflicting promiscuous death.
VIII. However, individuals who are natural-born subjects and owe ongoing loyalty to an enemy nation can, according to international law, be attacked or captured wherever they are found. Whenever a declaration of war is made against a nation, it also applies to all subjects of that nation. International law permits us to engage an enemy in any location, a view supported by most legal experts. For instance, Marcian states that "deserters can be killed like enemies, wherever they are found." They can be legally killed either in their home country, in the enemy's territory, in areas that belong to no one, or at sea. However, regarding the prohibition of killing or violently confronting them in neutral territories, this protection doesn't come from their individual rights, but from the rights of the sovereign of that area. All civil societies have the undeniable right to establish the principle that no violence should be inflicted on anyone within their borders, and that punishment should only be administered through proper legal processes. Since courts hold the authority to fully examine the merits of any offense and, after fair investigation, either acquit the innocent or condemn the guilty, the power of force must be limited to prevent unjust death.
Livy mentions the circumstance of seven Carthaginian gallies riding at anchor in a port belonging to Syphax, who was then at peace with the Carthaginians and328 Romans. Scipio arrived at that time, with two gallies, which might have been attacked and sunk by the Carthaginians, before they could enter the port: a brisk wind rising carried them in, before the Carthaginians could weigh anchor; but out of respect to the king's authority they durst not attack the Romans in his harbour.
Livy talks about how seven Carthaginian galleys were anchored in a port owned by Syphax, who was at peace with both the Carthaginians and the Romans. At that time, Scipio arrived with two galleys, which the Carthaginians could have attacked and sunk before they entered the port. However, a strong wind picked up, pushing Scipio's ships in before the Carthaginians could set sail. Out of respect for the king's authority, they didn't dare to attack the Romans in his harbor.
IX. But to return to the subject, which is, to decide how far the power of lawfully destroying an enemy, and all that belong to him, extends. An extent of which we may form some conception from the very circumstance, that even women and children are frequently subject to the calamities and disasters of war. There is no occasion to allege in this place, as an example, the conduct of the Hebrews, who slew the women and children of the Heshbonites, and who were commanded to execute vengeance upon the Canaanites, and upon all, who were involved in the same guilt. Those examples, where God MANIFESTLY interposes his commands, are not to be drawn into a precedent for authorising actions of the SAME kind on DIFFERENT occasions. For the supreme and disposing power of God can never properly be compared with that, which men are allowed to exercise over each other. The Psalmist's expression of the Babylonian children being dashed against the stones is a much stronger proof of the custom commonly prevailing among nations, in the use of victory, to which the language of Homer bears a close resemblance, where the poet says, that "in the cruel rage of war, even the bodies of infant-children were dashed against the ground." Thucydides relates, that when Mycalessus was captured by the Thracians, they put all, even women and children to the sword. Arrian relates the same of the Macedonians, when they took the city of Thebes. And Germanicus Caesar, according to the account of Tacitus, laid waste whole cantons of the Marsians, a people of Germany, with fire and sword, to which the historian adds, "without sparing either age or sex." The Jewish women and children too were exposed by Titus, to be torn to pieces by wild beasts at a public spectacle. Yet neither of those generals were thought deficient in humanity, so much had custom reconciled the minds of men to this barbarous usage. So that the massacre of the aged, like that of Priam by Pyrrhus, is no way surprising.
IX. But to get back to the topic at hand, which is to determine how far the power to lawfully destroy an enemy and everything associated with them extends. We can get some idea of this from the fact that even women and children often suffer the consequences of war. There's no need to mention here the actions of the Hebrews, who killed the women and children of the Heshbonites and were commanded to take vengeance on the Canaanites and others who shared in their guilt. Those instances, where God clearly intervenes with commands, shouldn't be used as a precedent to justify similar actions in different situations. The supreme and controlling power of God can never be rightly compared to the power that humans are permitted to exercise over one another. The Psalmist’s mention of Babylonian children being dashed against stones is a much stronger indication of the custom that was common among nations in the exercise of victory, which is closely mirrored in Homer’s writing, where the poet describes how "in the cruel rage of war, even the bodies of infants were thrown to the ground." Thucydides recounts that when Mycalessus was captured by the Thracians, they killed everyone, even women and children. Arrian says the same about the Macedonians when they took the city of Thebes. And according to Tacitus, Germanicus Caesar devastated entire regions of the Marsians, a Germanic people, with fire and sword, and the historian notes, "without sparing either age or sex." The Jewish women and children were also exposed by Titus to be torn apart by wild animals at a public spectacle. Yet neither of those generals was considered lacking in humanity, as customs had so deeply reconciled people to this brutal practice. Therefore, the massacre of the aged, like that of Priam by Pyrrhus, is hardly surprising.
X. The right of putting prisoners of war to death, was so generally received a maxim, that the Roman Satirist329 has founded an adage upon it, and said, "that when you can sell a prisoner for a slave, it would be absurd to kill him." Words which imply the full power of doing so, if the captor thought proper. The commentators indeed assign the act of saving, as the derivation of the Latin word, servus, a slave. Thus Thucydides speaks of the prisoners taken at Epidamnus, and killed by the Corcyraeans, and Hannibal is reported to have massacred five thousand prisoners at once. Nor was this power limited by the law of nations to any particular time, though it was controuled by greater restrictions in some places, than in others.
X. The right to execute prisoners of war was such a widely accepted principle that the Roman satirist329 created an adage from it, saying, "When you can sell a prisoner as a slave, it would be ridiculous to kill him." These words suggest that the captor had the full authority to do so if they chose. Commentators actually trace the origin of the Latin word, servus, meaning slave, to the act of saving. Thucydides mentions the prisoners taken at Epidamnus who were killed by the Corcyraeans, and Hannibal is said to have slaughtered five thousand prisoners at once. This power was not restricted by international law to any specific period, although it was governed by stricter limitations in some places than in others.
XI. Besides many examples occur of suppliants, being killed. Both ancient poets and historians relate such actions, as ordinary practices, authorised by the laws of war. Augustin commends the Goths for sparing suppliants, who had fled to churches for refuge, and adds by way of comment, that "they deemed it unlawful to avail themselves of the power, which had usually been allowed by the laws of war."
XI. There are many instances of people seeking mercy being killed. Both ancient poets and historians describe these acts as common practices, permitted by the laws of war. Augustine praises the Goths for sparing those who sought refuge in churches, noting that "they considered it wrong to use the power that was typically granted by the laws of war."
Nor did those who offered to surrender always experience the lenity and mercy, which they sought thereby. Tacitus relates, that when the city of Uspes was invested, the besieged sent a deputation with offers of an immediate surrender, and of no less than ten thousand slaves, on condition that the free-born should remain unhurt. The terms were rejected—A proof that such a rejection was thought conformable to the rights of war.
Nor did those who offered to surrender always receive the leniency and mercy they were looking for. Tacitus states that when the city of Uspes was under siege, the people inside sent a delegation with offers of an immediate surrender and no fewer than ten thousand slaves, on the condition that the free-born would remain unharmed. The terms were rejected—evidence that such a rejection was considered consistent with the rights of war.
XII. But even after an unconditional surrender, we find that those, who had capitulated were sometimes put to the sword. In this manner the princes of Pometia were treated by the Romans, the Samnites by Sylla, the Numidians and Vercingetorix by Caesar. It was almost a standing practice with the Romans to crown their triumphs with the death of an enemy's generals, whether made prisoners actually in the field, or by capitulation. Cicero notices this custom in his fifth speech against Verres. Livy may be consulted on this point in many parts of his history, particularly in the twenty-eighth book: and Tacitus also in the 12th book of his Annals. The latter writer, in the first book of his History, relates that Galba ordered every tenth man of those, whom he had, upon their earnest supplication, admitted to surrender, to be beheaded: and Caecina, after the capitulation of Aventicum, punished Julius Alpinus, one330 of the leading men, with death, as a chief promoter of the war, leaving the rest to the mercy or cruelty of Vitellius.
XII. But even after a complete surrender, we see that those who had given up were sometimes executed. The Romans treated the princes of Pometia this way, as did Sylla with the Samnites, and Caesar with the Numidians and Vercingetorix. It became almost a standard practice for the Romans to finish their victories with the deaths of their enemies' generals, whether they were captured in battle or surrendered. Cicero mentions this habit in his fifth speech against Verres. You can refer to Livy on this topic in many parts of his history, especially in the twenty-eighth book, and Tacitus also addresses it in the 12th book of his Annals. The latter writer, in the first book of his History, explains that Galba ordered every tenth person among those who had earnestly begged for mercy to be executed: and Caecina, after the surrender of Aventicum, punished Julius Alpinus, one of the main leaders, with death for being a key instigator of the war, leaving the others to the discretion of Vitellius.
XIII. Historians sometimes account for this right of putting enemies to death, especially prisoners, or suppliants, either on the score of retaliation, or for obstinate resistance. These may sometimes be the real, but cannot be the JUSTIFIABLE motives of such proceedings. For the law of retaliation, strictly and properly so called, must be directly enforced upon the person of the delinquent himself. Whereas, in war, what is called retaliation frequently redounds to the ruin of those, who are no way implicated in the blame. The general consequences of war are thus described by Diodorus Siculus, "they could not be ignorant, says he, having learnt from experience, that all being involved in the common fortune of war, they are liable on both sides in defeat, to suffer the same calamities, which they themselves would have inflicted upon the conquered party."
XIII. Historians sometimes justify the right to execute enemies, especially prisoners or those seeking mercy, either as an act of revenge or because of resistance. While these reasons might sometimes be real, they can’t be considered Justifiable motives for such actions. True retaliation, in its strictest sense, must be applied directly to the wrongdoer. However, in war, what is labeled as retaliation often leads to the suffering of those who aren’t involved in the wrongdoing. Diodorus Siculus describes the general consequences of war: "They could not be unaware, he says, having learned from experience, that since everyone is caught up in the shared fate of war, both sides can suffer the same misfortunes that they would have inflicted on the defeated."
But as the Neapolitans reply to Belisarius, in Procopius, no one can be thought deserving of punishment for a resolute adherence to the side on which he is engaged, especially when actuated by natural and just motives in his choice of that side. So far from incurring guilt by such a resolution, it is on the other hand more criminal for any one to desert his post: and so it was judged by the military laws of ancient Rome. Livy says, it was a capital offence, for which no fear of danger could be pleaded as an excuse. So that in the rigid application of this right, OWING TO ITS IMPORTANCE, every one is left to use his own discretion, and there may be times and circumstances, in which the law of nations will justify its full exertion.
But as the Neapolitans respond to Belisarius in Procopius, no one should be considered deserving of punishment for firmly sticking to the side they've chosen, especially when they are motivated by natural and just reasons in their decision. Far from being guilty for such a commitment, it is actually more wrong for anyone to abandon their position: this was the view held by the military laws of ancient Rome. Livy states it was a capital offense, for which no fear of danger could be used as an excuse. Thus, in the strict application of this principle, DUE TO ITS IMPORTANCE, everyone is left to exercise their own judgement, and there may be situations where the law of nations will support its full application.
XIV. The same right was exercised upon hostages also, not only upon those who had bound themselves, as it were, by convention, but even upon those, who had been delivered up by others. Two hundred and fifty hostages were once massacred by the Thessalians, and the Volsci Aurunci to the amount of three hundred by the Romans. It is to be observed that children were sometimes given, as hostages, which we find was done by the Parthians, and by Simon, who was one of the Maccabees. And in the times of Porsena it was usual to deliver women, as hostages: a practice, which, as Tacitus informs us, was followed by the Germans.
XIV. The same right was also applied to hostages, not just to those who had willingly committed themselves by agreement, but even to those who had been handed over by others. The Thessalians once massacred two hundred and fifty hostages, and the Romans did the same with three hundred Volsci Aurunci. It’s noteworthy that sometimes children were given as hostages, as was done by the Parthians and by Simon, one of the Maccabees. In the time of Porsena, it was common to use women as hostages, a practice that was also noted by Tacitus as being followed by the Germans.
331 XV. As the law of nations permits many things, in the manner above explained, which are not permitted by the law of nature, so it prohibits some things which the law of nature allows. Thus spies, if discovered and taken, are usually treated with the utmost severity. Yet there is no doubt, but the law of nations allows any one to send spies, as Moses did to the land of promise, of whom Joshua was one.
331 XV. Just as international law allows for many things that natural law doesn't, it also prohibits some actions that natural law does allow. For example, spies, if caught, are usually treated very harshly. However, it's clear that international law permits anyone to send out spies, just like Moses did when he sent them to the promised land, one of whom was Joshua.
Persons of that description may sometimes be LAWFULLY employed by those, who are engaged in an EVIDENTLY just war. Others too, who have not such evident proofs of the justice of their cause, may plead the rights of war as a vindication for employing such persons.
People fitting that description may sometimes be LEGALLY hired by those involved in an Evidently just war. Others, who don’t have clear evidence of the justice of their cause, might argue that the rights of war justify hiring such individuals.
But if any are to be found, who disdain to avail themselves of such a privilege, or opportunity, no argument either FOR, or AGAINST the LAWFULNESS of employing spies can be drawn from their conduct, which proceeds rather from a nobleness of mind, and a confidence in open strength, than from any decided opinion upon the subject.
But if there are those who refuse to take advantage of such a privilege or opportunity, no argument either FOR or AGAINST the Legality of using spies can be inferred from their behavior, which comes more from a nobility of spirit and confidence in open strength than from any strong opinion on the matter.
CHAPTER V.
On the Right to Devastate an Enemy's Territory and Seize His Property.
An enemy's property may be wasted and plundered—Things deemed sacred, how far exempted—Stratagem, how far permitted.
Can we destroy and steal an enemy's possessions—What is the limit to protecting sacred items—How much deception can be justified?
I. Cicero, in the third book of his offices, has said that there is nothing repugnant to the LAW OF NATURE in spoiling the effects of an enemy, whom by the same law we are authorized to kill. Wherefore it is not surprising that the same things should be allowed by the LAW OF NATIONS. Polybius, for this reason, in the fifth book of his history, maintains, that the laws of war authorise the destruction of an enemy's forts, harbours, and fleets, the seizure of his men, or carrying off the produce of his country, and every thing of that description. And we find from Livy that there are certain rights of war, by which an enemy must expect to suffer the calamities, which he is allowed to inflict, such as the burning of corn, the destruction of houses, and the plunder of men and cattle. Almost every page of history abounds in examples of entire cities being destroyed, walls levelled to the ground, and even whole countries wasted by fire and sword. Even in cases of surrender, towns have sometimes been destroyed, while the inhabitants were spared—an example of which is given by Tacitus, in the taking of Artaxata by the Romans; the inhabitants opened their gates and were spared, but the town was devoted to the flames.
I. Cicero, in the third book of his "On Duties," stated that there is nothing against the Natural Law in destroying the resources of an enemy, whom we are also permitted to kill by that same law. Therefore, it’s not surprising that the International Law allows the same actions. For this reason, Polybius, in the fifth book of his history, argues that the laws of war permit the destruction of an enemy's forts, harbors, and fleets, the capture of their people, or taking goods from their land, and everything similar. Livy shows us that there are certain rights of war, which mean that an enemy should expect to endure the suffering they are allowed to inflict, such as the burning of crops, destruction of houses, and looting of people and livestock. Almost every page of history is filled with examples of entire cities being destroyed, walls being leveled, and whole countries being ravaged by fire and sword. Even in cases of surrender, towns have sometimes been destroyed while the inhabitants were spared—an example of this is given by Tacitus, in the conquest of Artaxata by the Romans; the inhabitants opened their gates and were spared, but the town was set on fire.
II. Nor does the law of nations, in itself, considered apart from other duties, which will be mentioned hereafter, make any exemption in favour of things deemed sacred. For when places are taken by an enemy, all things without exception, whether sacred or not, must fall a sacrifice. For which it is assigned as a reason, that things which are called sacred, are not actually excepted from all human uses, but are a kind of public property, called sacred indeed from the general purposes, to which they are more immediately devoted. And as a proof of this, it is usual, when one nation surrenders to333 another state or sovereign, to surrender, along with other rights, every thing of a sacred kind, as appears by the form cited from Livy in a former part of this treatise.
II. The law of nations doesn't, by itself and apart from other duties that will be discussed later, provide any exemption for things considered sacred. When an enemy captures a place, everything, without exception, whether sacred or not, must be sacrificed. The reason given for this is that things labeled as sacred are not truly exempt from all human use but instead are a kind of public property, referred to as sacred because of the general purposes for which they are primarily dedicated. To illustrate this, it is common for one nation to surrender to another state or ruler not just other rights but also everything considered sacred, as shown by the example cited from Livy in an earlier part of this treatise.
And therefore Ulpian says, that the public have a property in sacred things. Conformably to which Tacitus says, that "in the Italian towns all the temples, the images of the Gods, and every thing connected with religion belonged of right to the Roman people." For this reason a nation, as the Lawyers, Paulus and Venuleius openly maintain, may, under a change of circumstances, convert to secular uses things, that have before been consecrated: and an overruling necessity may justify the hand, which has formerly consecrated the object in employing it as one of the resources and instruments of war. A thing which Pericles once did under a pledge of making restitution: Mago did the same in Spain, and the Romans in the Mithridatic war. We read of the same actions done by Sylla, Pompey, Caesar, and others. Plutarch in his life of Tiberius Gracchus says that nothing is so sacred and inviolable, as divine offerings: yet no one can hinder these from being removed or applied to other purposes at the pleasure of the state. Thus Livy mentions the ornaments of the temples, which Marcellus brought from Syracuse to Rome, as acquisitions made by the right of war.
And so Ulpian says that the public has ownership of sacred things. In line with this, Tacitus states that "in the Italian towns, all the temples, the images of the Gods, and everything connected with religion rightly belonged to the Roman people." For this reason, a nation, as lawyers Paulus and Venuleius openly argue, can repurpose consecrated items for secular uses when circumstances change: and a pressing necessity might justify the hand that originally dedicated the object in using it as a resource and tool for war. This is something Pericles once did, under a promise of restitution: Mago did the same in Spain, and the Romans in the Mithridatic war. We read about similar actions taken by Sylla, Pompey, Caesar, and others. Plutarch, in his life of Tiberius Gracchus, notes that nothing is as sacred and untouchable as divine offerings: still, no one can stop these from being removed or repurposed at the state's discretion. Similarly, Livy mentions the decorations of the temples that Marcellus brought from Syracuse to Rome as gains made by the right of war.
III. What has been said of sacred things and edifices applies also to another kind of solemn fabrics, and those are sepulchral structures, which may be considered not merely as repositories of the dead, but as monuments belonging to the living, whether families or states. For this reason Pomponius has said, that these, like all other sacred places, when taken by an enemy may lose their inviolability, and Paulus is of the same opinion, observing that we are not restrained by any religious scruple from using the sepulchres of an enemy: for the stones, taken from thence, may be applied to any other purpose. But this right does not authorise wanton insult, offered to the ashes of the dead. For that would be a violation of the solemn rights of burial, which, as it was shewn in a preceding part of this work, were introduced and established by the law of nations.
III. What has been said about sacred things and buildings also applies to another type of solemn structure: burial sites. These should be viewed not just as resting places for the dead but also as monuments belonging to the living, whether individuals or nations. For this reason, Pomponius has stated that these, like all other sacred places, can lose their inviolability when taken by an enemy, and Paulus agrees, noting that we are not bound by any religious scruples from using the graves of an enemy since the stones taken from there can be repurposed. However, this right does not permit disrespectful acts towards the remains of the dead, as that would violate the solemn rights of burial, which, as shown earlier in this work, were created and established by international law.
IV. Here it may be briefly observed, that, according to the law of nations any thing, belonging to an enemy, may be taken not only by open force, but by stratagem, provided it be unaccompanied with treachery.
IV. It can be noted here that, according to international law, anything owned by an enemy can be seized not just through direct force, but also through clever tactics, as long as it doesn't involve deceit.
CHAPTER VI.
On Acquiring Land and Property Through Conquest.
Law of nature with respect to the acquisition of things captured in war—Law of nations on the same subject—In what cases the law of nations confirms the capture of things moveable—Lands acquired by conquest—Lawful prize cannot be made of things not belonging to an enemy—Goods found on board an enemy's ships—Law of nations authorises the making prize of what an enemy has taken from others in war—Sovereigns may acquire possession and dominion through those employed by them—Acts of hostility divided into public and private—Territory may be acquired by a sovereign or people—Private and public captures explained—Discretionary power of generals in this respect—Prizes belong either to the treasury, or to those, who take them—Places sometimes given up to be plundered by the soldiery—Different methods of dividing spoils—Peculation, a portion of the spoils sometimes given to allies, who have supported the war—Sometimes given up to subjects—This illustrated by examples—Utility of the above practices—Whether things taken without the territory of either of the belligerent powers can be acquired by the rights of war—In what manner this right peculiarly applies to solemn wars.
Natural law regarding the capture of things during war—International law on the same subject—In which situations international law backs the capture of movable items—Land obtained through conquest—A legitimate prize cannot consist of items that don't belong to an enemy—Goods found on enemy ships—International law permits the capture of what an enemy has taken from others in combat—Rulers can gain possession and control through those they employ—Acts of aggression are categorized into public and private—Territory can be acquired by a sovereign or a community—Private and public captures described—Generals have the discretionary authority in this matter—Prizes either go to the treasury or to the individuals who capture them—Locations are sometimes surrendered for looting by soldiers—Various methods for dividing spoils—A portion of the spoils may be given to allies who supported the war—Sometimes given to subjects—This is illustrated with examples—The value of these practices—Whether items taken outside the territories of either fighting party can be claimed under wartime rights—How this right specifically applies to formal wars.
I. Besides the impunity allowed to men for certain actions, which have been mentioned before, there are other consequences and effects, peculiar to the law of nations, attending solemn and formal war. The law of nature indeed authorises our making such acquisitions in a just war, as may be deemed an equivalent for a debt, which cannot otherwise be obtained, or as may inflict a loss upon the aggressor, provided it be within the bounds of reasonable punishment. According to this right, as we find in the fourteenth chapter of Genesis, Abraham devoted to God a tenth part of the spoils, which he had taken from the five kings: and the inspired writer in the seventh chapter of his Epistle to the Hebrews gives the same interpretation of this passage. In the same manner the Greeks too, the Carthaginians, and the Romans, devoted a tenth portion of the spoils of war to their deities. Jacob, in making a particular bequest to Joseph above his brethren, says, "I have given to thee one portion above thy brethren, which I took out of the hand of the Amorite with my sword, and with my bow." In this335 place, the expression, I TOOK, is used according to the prophetic style, where an event, that will for certain take place, is spoken of in the past time, and an action is here attributed to Jacob, which some of his descendants were to perform, supposing the progenitor and his children to be the same person.
I. Besides the impunity allowed to men for certain actions, which have been mentioned before, there are other consequences and effects, specific to international law, that come with official and formal war. The law of nature indeed allows us to make acquisitions in a just war that can be seen as compensation for a debt that cannot otherwise be settled, or that can inflict a loss on the aggressor, as long as it stays within reasonable punishment. Following this right, as we see in the fourteenth chapter of Genesis, Abraham dedicated a tenth of the spoils he took from the five kings to God; and the inspired writer in the seventh chapter of his Epistle to the Hebrews interprets this passage the same way. Similarly, the Greeks, Carthaginians, and Romans dedicated a tenth of their war spoils to their gods. Jacob, when giving a specific inheritance to Joseph over his brothers, says, "I have given you one portion beyond your brothers, which I took from the Amorites with my sword and my bow." Here, the term "I took" is expressed in a prophetic style, referring to an event that is certain to happen but described as if it has already occurred, attributing an action to Jacob that some of his descendants would later perform, treating the ancestor and his children as if they were the same person.
Nor is it upon conjecture alone that such a right is founded, but the divine law giver himself pronounces sentence against a city that has rejected the offers of peace, and afterwards been taken by storm, that he gives all her spoils to the conqueror.
Nor is it based solely on speculation that this right exists, but the divine lawgiver himself condemns a city that has turned down peace offers, and after it has been captured, grants all its spoils to the conqueror.
II. But according to the law of nations, not only the person, who makes war upon just grounds; but any one whatever, engaged in regular and formal war, becomes absolute proprietor of every thing which he takes from the enemy: so that all nations respect his title, and the title of all, who derive through him their claim to such possessions. Which, as to all foreign relations, constitutes the true idea of dominion. For, as Cyrus, in Xenophon observes, when the city of an enemy is taken, every thing that is taken therein becomes a lawful prize to the conquerors; and Plato, in his treatise on laws asserts the same. Cicero in his speech against Rullus says that Mitylene belonged to the Roman people by the laws of war, and the right of conquest; and, in the first book of his offices, he observes, that some things become the private property of those, who take possession of them, when unoccupied, or of those, who make a conquest of them in war.—Theophilus, in his Greek institutes, calls the one the natural mode of acquisition, and Aristotle denominates the other the natural way of acquisition by the sword, without regarding any other reason, but the bare fact, from which the right arises. Thus Nerva, the son, as Paulus the lawyer relates, said that property arose from natural possession, some traces of which still remain respecting wild animals taken either upon the sea, or upon the land, or birds flying in the air. It is seen also in things taken in war, all which immediately become the property of the first captors. Now things are considered as taken from an enemy, when taken from his subjects.
II. According to international law, not only does someone who goes to war for just reasons, but anyone involved in regular and formal warfare claims ownership of everything they seize from the enemy. Therefore, all nations recognize their claim, along with anyone else who derives their rights through them. This establishes the true idea of ownership in foreign relations. As Cyrus noted in Xenophon, when an enemy city falls, everything taken from it rightfully belongs to the conquerors. Plato also supports this in his work on laws. Cicero mentioned in his speech against Rullus that Mitylene was owned by the Roman people under the laws of war and the right of conquest, and in the first book of his offices, he stated that certain things become the private property of those who occupy them when they are unclaimed, or of those who conquer them in battle. Theophilus, in his Greek institutes, refers to the first as natural acquisition, while Aristotle calls the latter acquisition by the sword, based solely on the fact from which the right arises. Nerva, as noted by the lawyer Paulus, said that property comes from natural possession, with some remnants of this concept remaining regarding wild animals caught at sea or on land, or birds in the air. This principle also applies to items taken in war, which immediately become the property of the first captors. Things are deemed taken from an enemy when seized from their subjects.
Thus Dercyllides argues, in Xenophon, that as Pharnabazus was an enemy to the Lacedaemonians, every thing belonging to Mania, who was his subject, might be seized by the laws of war.
Thus Dercyllides argues, in Xenophon, that since Pharnabazus was an enemy of the Lacedaemonians, everything belonging to Mania, who was his subject, could be taken according to the laws of war.
336 III. But in this question upon the rights of war nations have decided, that a person is understood to have made a capture, when he detains a thing in such a manner, that the owner has abandoned all probable hopes of recovering it, or, as Pomponius, speaking on the same subject, says, when a thing has escaped beyond pursuit. This takes place with respect to moveable things in such a manner, that they are said to be taken, when they are carried within the territories of the enemy, or places belonging to him. For a thing is lost in the same manner as it is recovered by postliminium. It is said to be recovered whenever it returns within the territories of its owner's sovereign, that is, into places, of which he is master. Paulus indeed has expressly said, that a power or state has lost a subject, when he has gone, or been carried out of the territories of that power: and Pomponius defines a prisoner of war to be an enemy, whom the troops of some other belligerent power have taken and carried into one of their own places; for before he is carried into those places, he continues still a subject of the enemy.
336 III. In this discussion about the rights of war, nations agree that a person is considered to have made a capture when they hold something in such a way that the owner has given up all reasonable hope of getting it back, or, as Pomponius puts it, when something is out of reach. This applies to movable items in a way that they are said to be taken when they are brought within the enemy's territory or any places they control. An item is lost the same way it is regained through postliminium. It is regarded as recovered whenever it returns to the territory of its rightful owner, meaning the places under their control. Paulus has specifically stated that a power or state loses a subject when that subject leaves, or is taken out of, that power's territory. Pomponius defines a prisoner of war as an enemy captured and taken into the territory of another warring power; because until he is brought into those places, he remains a subject of the enemy.
The law of nations, in these respects, treated persons and things in the same manner. From whence it is easy to understand, what is meant, when in another place it is said that things taken from an enemy immediately become the lawful prize of the captors, but only upon the condition of those things continuing in their possession for a reasonable and certain time. Consequently it is plain, that ships and other things taken at sea cannot be considered as really the property of the captors, till they have been carried into some of their ports, or to some place where their whole fleet is stationed. For in that case all hope of recovery seems to have vanished. By a late regulation among the European powers, it has been made an established maxim of the law of nations, that captures shall be deemed good and lawful, which have continued in the enemy's possession for the space of twenty-four hours.
The law of nations treats people and property the same way in these matters. This helps us understand what is meant when it says elsewhere that items taken from an enemy immediately become the rightful prize of the captors, but only as long as those items remain in their possession for a reasonable and definite time. Therefore, it’s clear that ships and other items captured at sea cannot truly be considered the property of the captors until they have been brought into one of their ports or to a location where their entire fleet is stationed. In that scenario, all hope of recovery appears to be lost. Recently, a regulation among European powers has established a principle of international law that captures will be considered valid and lawful if they have remained in the enemy's possession for twenty-four hours.
IV. Lands are not understood to become a lawful possession and absolute conquest from the moment they are invaded. For although it is true, that an army takes immediate and violent possession of the country which it has invaded, yet that can only be considered as a temporary possession, unaccompanied with any of the rights and consequences alluded to in this work, till it has been ratified and secured by some durable means, by cession, or treaty. For this reason, the land without the gates of337 Rome, where Hannibal encamped, was so far from being judged entirely lost, that it was sold for the same price that it would have been sold for before that period.
IV. Lands are not understood to automatically become lawful property and complete conquest just because they are invaded. While it’s true that an army takes immediate and forceful control of the country it has invaded, this should only be seen as a temporary control, lacking any of the rights and consequences discussed in this work, until it is officially confirmed and secured through some lasting means, like transfer or treaty. For this reason, the land outside the gates of 337 Rome, where Hannibal camped, was so far from being considered completely lost that it was sold for the same price it would have fetched before that time.
Now land will be considered as completely conquered, when it is inclosed or secured by permanent fortifications, so that no other state or sovereign can have free access to it, without first making themselves masters of those fortifications. On this account Flaccus, the Sicilian, assigns no improbable conjecture for the origin of the word territory, because the enemy is DETERRED from entering it. At least there is as much probability in this conjecture, as in that of Varro, who derives it from the word terendo, treading the soil. Frontinus deduces it from terra, the earth, and Pomponius from the TERROR of judicial authority exercised in each country. Xenophon however in his book on tributes, seems to accord with the first of these opinions: for he says, that in time of war the possession of a country is kept by walls, strong holds, and barriers.
Now land is considered completely conquered when it is enclosed or secured by permanent fortifications, so that no other state or ruler can access it freely without first taking control of those fortifications. For this reason, Flaccus, the Sicilian, offers a reasonable guess for the origin of the word territory, since the enemy is Dissuaded from entering it. At least this guess has as much validity as Varro’s, who traces it back to the word terendo, meaning treading the soil. Frontinus links it to terra, meaning the earth, while Pomponius attributes it to the TERROR of judicial authority in each region. However, Xenophon, in his book on tributes, seems to agree with the first opinion, stating that during wartime, the possession of a land is maintained by walls, strongholds, and barriers.
V. It is a clear point too, that for any thing to become a prize or conquest by the right of war, it must belong to an enemy. For things, within an enemy's territory, for instance, in any of his towns or garrisons, cannot be acquired as property by the laws of war, if the owners of those things are neither subjects nor confederates of the enemy. It is observed in one of the speeches of Aeschines, that Philip, though at war with the Amphipolitans, could not lawfully take possession of Amphipolis, as a conquest, it being a city, which belonged to the Athenians. For as the enemy is likely to derive no assistance in the war, from things which neither belong to himself, nor to a confederate, no just reason can be assigned for taking them, and the right of making things change their owners by force is of too odious a nature to admit of any extension.
V. It’s also clear that for anything to be considered a prize or conquest in war, it must belong to an enemy. For example, things within an enemy's territory, such as in their towns or garrisons, cannot be claimed as property by the laws of war if the owners of those things are not subjects or allies of the enemy. In one of Aeschines' speeches, it's mentioned that Philip, while at war with the Amphipolitans, couldn’t legally take control of Amphipolis as a conquest because it was a city belonging to the Athenians. The enemy is unlikely to gain any advantage in the war from things that don’t belong to them or to an ally, so there’s no valid reason for taking them, and the right to forcibly change ownership of things is too objectionable to be expanded.
VI. The observation usually made, that all things on board an enemy's ships are to be deemed an enemy's goods, ought not to be received as a STANDING and ACKNOWLEDGED rule of the law of nations, but only as a maxim, indicating the strong presumption that both goods and vessel belong to the same owner, unless clear proof to the contrary can be brought. The States General of Holland made such a decision in the year 1338, at a time when the war with the Hanse-towns raged with the338 greatest violence, and the decision consequently passed into a law.
VI. The common observation that everything on an enemy's ship is considered enemy property should not be taken as a Standing and ACKNOWLEDGED rule of international law, but rather as a principle, suggesting the strong assumption that both the goods and the ship belong to the same owner, unless clear evidence to the contrary is presented. The States General of Holland made this decision in 1338, during a time when the war with the Hanse towns was at its most intense, and this decision ultimately became law.
VII. According to the law of nations it is undoubtedly true, that things taken from an enemy which had been captured by him cannot be claimed by those, to whom they belonged before they were in the enemy's possession, and who had lost them in war. Because the law of nations assigned them to the enemy by the first capture, and then to the person, who took them from him by the second.
VII. According to international law, it's definitely true that items taken from an enemy, which were previously captured by them, cannot be claimed by their original owners who lost them in war. This is because international law assigns those items to the enemy upon first capture, and then to whoever takes them from the enemy secondarily.
Upon this principle among others, Jephthah defends himself against the Ammonites, because by the laws of war they had lost the land, which they claimed, in the same manner, as another part had been transferred from the Moabites to the Amorites, and from the Amorites to the Hebrews. Thus David too claims and divides as his own, what he himself had taken from the Amalekites, and the Amalekites, before him, from the Philistines.
Upon this principle among others, Jephthah defends himself against the Ammonites, because according to the laws of war, they had lost the land they were claiming, just like another area had been given up from the Moabites to the Amorites, and from the Amorites to the Hebrews. Similarly, David also claims and divides as his own what he had taken from the Amalekites, who had previously taken it from the Philistines.
Titus Largius, as we are informed by Dionysius of Halicarnassus, when the Volscians laid claim to some possessions, which they had formerly held, delivered it as his opinion in the Roman Senate, that "the Romans were the fair and just owners of what they had gained by the right of conquest, nor ought they to be so weak as to abandon the fruits of their valour. For not only the people of that day, but their posterity also had a right to a share of those possessions: so that to abandon them would be treating themselves like enemies."
Titus Largius, as noted by Dionysius of Halicarnassus, argued in the Roman Senate when the Volscians claimed some lands they once owned, that "the Romans rightfully own what they have won through conquest, and they shouldn't be so weak as to give up the rewards of their bravery. Both the current generation and their future descendants have a right to those lands, so giving them up would be acting against their own interests."
VIII. and IX. One great point, which the law of nations designed to establish, was that the effects or possessions of one enemy should be considered by another, as things having no owner.
VIII. and IX. One significant goal that international law aimed to achieve was that the belongings or possessions of one enemy should be regarded by another as unowned items.
Things, belonging to no one, became the property of those, who find or take them, both of those, who, like sovereign powers, employ others in such service, and of those, who take them with their own hands.
Things that belong to no one become the property of those who find or take them—both those who, like sovereign powers, use others to do so, and those who take them with their own hands.
Thus not only slaves, or the immediate members of a man's household, but all, who engage themselves, any way, in the service of others, may be said to acquire for their employers all the property, which they take or gain, even in those things, which apparently lie in common to all men, such as pearls, fish, or fowl.
Thus, not just slaves or the immediate members of a person's household, but everyone who participates in the service of others can be said to acquire for their employers all the property they take or gain, even when it comes to things that are typically shared by everyone, like pearls, fish, or birds.
Modestinus has justly said, "that whatever is naturally gained, like a possession, we may acquire through the339 means of any one we chuse to employ," and, upon the same principle, Paulus observes, that "in every acquisition, the exertion of mind and body must concur; the former purely our own, and the latter, either our own, or that of another. In the same manner possession may be taken for us by an attorney, guardian, or trustee, provided they do it on our account and in our name." The reason of which is, because one man may naturally be the voluntary instrument of another, with the consent of that other. So that the distinction made between persons in a servile and free condition, as to the acquisition of property, is a distinction only of the civil law, and applicable to its rules of transferring, acquiring, and confirming, property. And yet the emperor Severus afterwards applied these rules to the natural acquisition of things, not only from motives of utility, but, as he avowed himself, from motives of equity and justice. So that, apart from all authority of the civil law, it is an established maxim that what any one can do for himself, he can do through means of another, and doing such acts by another is the same as doing them himself.
Modestinus rightly said, "Whatever we naturally gain, like a possession, can be acquired through anyone we choose to employ," and based on the same idea, Paulus notes that "in every acquisition, the efforts of both mind and body must come together; the former is entirely our own, while the latter can be our own or that of someone else. Similarly, possession can be taken on our behalf by an attorney, guardian, or trustee, as long as they act for us and in our name." The reason is that one person can naturally be the willing instrument of another, with that other person's consent. Thus, the distinction between people in servile and free conditions regarding property acquisition is just a distinction of civil law and is relevant to rules about transferring, acquiring, and confirming property. Nevertheless, Emperor Severus later applied these rules to the natural acquisition of things, not only for practical reasons but, as he admitted, out of fairness and justice. Therefore, independent of any civil law authority, it is a well-established principle that anything someone can do for themselves can also be done through another person, and having another person perform those actions is equivalent to doing them themselves.
X. A distinction must be made between actions in war, that are really of a PUBLIC NATURE, and the acts of INDIVIDUALS, occasioned by public war: by the latter, individuals acquire an absolute and direct property, in the things, which they take, and by the former, the state makes those acquisitions. Upon this principle of the law of nations Scipio treated with Masinissa, stating that as it was under the auspices of the Roman people, that Syphax was conquered and taken prisoner, himself, his wife, his kingdom, his territory, his towns, and subjects inhabiting those towns, in short, every thing belonging to him became a lawful prize to the Roman people. In the same manner, Antiochus the Great maintained that Coelo-Syria belonged to Seleucus, and not to Ptolemy, because Seleucus had been the principal in the war, to which Ptolemy had contributed his assistance. In the fifth book of Polybius, there is an account of the matter.
X. We need to differentiate between actions in war that are genuinely of a Public Space and the acts of PEOPLE that arise from public war. In the latter case, individuals obtain absolute and direct ownership of the things they take, while in the former, the state claims those acquisitions. Following this principle of international law, Scipio negotiated with Masinissa, asserting that since Syphax was conquered and captured under the authority of the Roman people, everything that belonged to him—his possessions, his wife, his kingdom, his territory, his towns, and the people living in those towns—legally became the property of the Roman people. Similarly, Antiochus the Great argued that Coelo-Syria was owned by Seleucus instead of Ptolemy because Seleucus had played a leading role in the war, and Ptolemy had only provided assistance. This is detailed in the fifth book of Polybius.
XI. Things immoveable are generally taken by some public act, such as marching an army into the country, or placing garrisons there. So that, as Pomponius has said, "lands taken from the enemy become the property of the state, and form no part of the booty belonging to the individual captors." Thus among the Hebrews and Lacedaemonians, lands that were made a conquest, were340 divided by lot. The Romans too either retained conquered lands to let them out for rent, sometimes leaving a small portion to the ancient possessor, or divided them among colonists, whom they sent out, or made them tributary; innumerable instances of which we meet with in their histories, their laws, and treaties on the admeasurements of lands.
XI. Immovable things are usually taken through some public act, like marching an army into the area or setting up garrisons there. As Pomponius stated, "lands taken from the enemy become the property of the state and are not considered part of the booty belonging to the individual captors." Similarly, among the Hebrews and Lacedaemonians, lands that were conquered were 340 divided by lot. The Romans also either kept conquered lands to rent them out, sometimes allowing a small portion to the original owner, or divided them among settlers they sent out, or made them pay tribute; there are countless examples of this in their histories, laws, and treaties regarding land measurements.
XII. But things moveable, whether inanimate, or living, are taken either as connected or unconnected with the public service. When unconnected with the public service, they become the property of the individual captors.62
XII. But movable things, whether they're lifeless or living, are considered either linked or not linked to public service. When they're not linked to public service, they become the property of the individual captors. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Reference may here be made to the remark of Celsus, that "enemy's goods found among us do not belong to the state, but to the prior occupant." By which are meant things found among us at the breaking out of a war. For the same was observed of persons, when, under the same circumstances, they were considered as goods taken.
Reference may here be made to the remark of Celsus, that "enemy's goods found among us do not belong to the state, but to the prior occupant." This refers to items found among us at the outbreak of a war. The same principle was observed with people, who, under the same circumstances, were considered as goods taken.
On this subject there is a remarkable passage in Tryphoninus. "Those persons, says he, who have gone into a foreign country in time of peace, upon the sudden breaking out of war, are made slaves by those, among whom it is their misfortune to be found, being considered as enemies."
On this topic, there's a striking quote from Tryphoninus. "Those people," he says, "who have traveled to a foreign country during peacetime, when war suddenly breaks out, are enslaved by those among whom they unfortunate enough to be found, as they are seen as enemies."
XIII. What has been said upon the law of nations, allowing individuals to acquire property by taking it from an enemy, must be understood as meaning the law of nations, prior to the regulations of civil laws upon that point. For the capture of an enemy's goods which at first appear to resemble things in common, which any one may seize, is now, like that of wild birds or beasts, subject to limitation by the laws of every state, being in some cases assigned to the sovereign, and in others, belonging to the captors. It may in some countries, indeed, be introduced as a rule of law for the whole of an enemy's goods found there to be confiscated.
XIII. What has been said about international law, which allows individuals to take property from an enemy, should be understood as referring to international law before civil laws were established on this issue. The act of capturing an enemy's goods, which initially seem to be like common property that anyone can take, is now, similar to catching wild birds or animals, regulated by each state's laws. In some cases, these goods are assigned to the government, while in others, they belong to the captors. In fact, in some countries, there may be a legal rule that all enemy goods found there are to be confiscated.
XIV. The case is very different respecting what any one takes in actual engagements. For there every individual bears the character of his country, acting in her stead, and supporting her rights. Through the exertions of those individuals, the state acquires both property and dominion, with a power, according to the principles of civilized countries, of conferring them on whom she pleases.
XIV. The situation is quite different regarding what someone gains in actual engagements. In those cases, every person represents their country, acting on its behalf and upholding its rights. Because of the efforts of those individuals, the state gains both property and authority, with the right, according to the principles of civilized nations, to distribute them as it sees fit.
341 This is not a practice of modern date, but one prevailing among the most free and independent nations of remote antiquity. The poets, and historians of those days, describe the hero, after the heat, the burden, and dangers of the day, carrying his spoils to the common stock, to be divided by the General among the army, after retaining his proper share to himself.
341 This isn’t a recent practice; instead, it was common among the most free and independent nations in ancient times. The poets and historians from that era describe the hero, after enduring the heat, labor, and dangers of the day, bringing his rewards to the group to be shared by the General among the troops, keeping his rightful portion for himself.
XXIII.63 It is observed by legal authorities to be a custom, which has silently gained ground, for either allies or subjects, who engage in war, without pay, and at their own risque and expence, to be rewarded with the captures that they make.
XXIII.63 Legal authorities note that it has become a common practice, which has quietly taken hold, for either allies or subjects who go to war without pay, at their own risk and expense, to be rewarded with the spoils they capture.
The reason, why allies have such a privilege, is evident. Because one ally is naturally bound to another to repair the losses, which he has sustained by entering into a mutual agreement to support a common cause. Besides it seldom happens, that services are given without some consideration in return.
The reason allies have such a privilege is clear. One ally is naturally obligated to another to make up for the losses incurred by entering into a mutual agreement to support a shared cause. Plus, it’s rare for services to be provided without some form of compensation in return.
Quintilian, applying the same reasoning to another case, alleges that it is but just for orators and advocates, who devote their whole time and talents to the business of others, to be requited for their services: as thereby they preclude themselves from acquiring gain in any other way.
Quintilian, using the same reasoning in another example, argues that it's only fair for speakers and lawyers, who dedicate all their time and skills to helping others, to be compensated for their efforts: as they are blocking themselves from earning a living in any other way.
It is most likely therefore that some advantage gained from the enemy is always expected, as a compensation for the loss and risque incurred, unless there is evidence to the contrary from some antecedent treaty, in which there is an express stipulation for gratuitous assistance and services.
It’s probably expected that some benefit gained from the enemy will always offset the losses and risks taken, unless there’s proof to the contrary from a previous treaty that specifically states there will be free assistance and services.
XXIV. Such claim to a share of the spoils is not equally evident, where SUBJECTS ONLY are concerned. For the state has a RIGHT TO THEIR SERVICES. Still where ALL are not engaged in arms, but only SOME, those, who give up their time to the calling of soldiers, and expose their lives to its hazards, have a right to be rewarded and supported by the body politic:—and as a compensation for this loss of time, and this personal danger, it is but reasonable they should have a share of the spoils.
XXIV. The claim to a share of the spoils isn’t as clear-cut when it comes to SUBJECTS ONLY. The state has a ACCESS TO THEIR SERVICES. However, when NOT EVERYONE is involved in combat, but only SOME, those who dedicate their time to being soldiers and put their lives on the line deserve to be rewarded and supported by society. It’s only fair that, as compensation for their lost time and personal risk, they receive a share of the spoils.
With respect to allies there is an example in the Roman treaty, in which the Latins are admitted to an equal share of the spoil, in those wars, which were carried on under the auspices of the Roman people.
With regard to allies, there's an example in the Roman treaty where the Latins are allowed an equal share of the spoils in the wars conducted under the leadership of the Roman people.
342 Thus in the war, which the Aetolians carried on with the assistance of the Romans, the lands and cities were ceded to the Aetolians, and the prisoners and moveable effects were given to the Romans. After the defeat of king Ptolemy, Demetrius gave part of the spoils to the Athenians. Ambrose, in speaking of the expedition of Abraham, shews the equity of this practice. He asserts that it was but just for those, who had assisted him as partners in the danger, to share in the prizes, which were their due reward.
342 During the war that the Aetolians fought with the help of the Romans, the territories and cities were handed over to the Aetolians, while the prisoners and movable property were given to the Romans. After defeating King Ptolemy, Demetrius allocated part of the spoils to the Athenians. Ambrose, when discussing Abraham's expedition, illustrates the fairness of this practice. He argues that it was only right for those who had helped him as partners in danger to share in the rewards, which were deserving of them.
As to what were the privileges of subjects in these respects, we have a proof in the conduct of the Hebrews, among whom it was usual for half of the spoils to be given to those, who were engaged in battle. In the same manner the soldiers of Alexander were allowed to appropriate to themselves whatever they took from individuals, except that it was usual for a considerable portion to be set apart for the king. So that it was made a subject of accusation against those at Arbela, who were said to have entered into a conspiracy for securing to themselves every thing that was taken, without contributing a due proportion of it to the treasury.
As for the privileges of subjects in these matters, we see evidence in the actions of the Hebrews, who typically gave half of the spoils to those who fought in battle. Similarly, Alexander's soldiers were allowed to take for themselves whatever they seized from individuals, although a significant portion was usually reserved for the king. This became an accusation against those at Arbela, who were said to have conspired to keep everything they took without giving a fair share to the treasury.
But individuals were not allowed in the same manner to appropriate to themselves the public property of an enemy, that is, such as belonged to the state. Thus when the Macedonians made themselves masters of the camp of Darius at the river Piramus, and every thing was given up to plunder, they spared the royal pavilion, in conformity to an ancient custom, "according to which, as Curtius observes, it was always reserved as the properest place, in which the victorious prince could be received."
But individuals were not allowed to take public property from an enemy, meaning property that belonged to the state. So, when the Macedonians took control of Darius's camp at the river Piramus, and everything was up for grabs, they left the royal tent untouched, following an old tradition, "according to which, as Curtius observes, it was always reserved as the most appropriate place for the victorious prince to be received."
There was a custom somewhat like this among the Hebrews who always placed the crown of the vanquished king upon the head of the conqueror, and assigned to him every thing that was taken, belonging to the royal household. We read of the same conduct in Charles the great, who, upon conquering the Hungarians, gave up the private property as plunder to the soldiers, reserving for the royal use all the public treasures.
There was a tradition somewhat like this among the Hebrews, who always put the crown of the defeated king on the head of the conqueror and gave him everything taken from the royal household. We see the same behavior in Charlemagne, who, after defeating the Hungarians, allowed his soldiers to keep the personal property as loot, while keeping all the public treasures for the royal use.
Some things indeed are too inconsiderable to be made public property. It is a generally received maxim for such things to belong to the individual captors.64
Some things are really too insignificant to be public property. It's a commonly accepted belief that such things should belong to the individual captors.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
343 This was the practice in the ancient times of the Roman republic. A privilege not unlike this is sometimes given to seamen, who serve for pay. It is what the French call spoils, or pillage, including all wearing apparel, and all gold and silver under the value of ten crowns.
343 This was common practice in ancient times during the Roman Republic. A similar privilege is sometimes granted to sailors who are paid for their service. The French refer to it as spoils or pillage, which includes all clothing and any gold or silver worth less than ten crowns.
On this point different customs prevail in different countries. In Spain sometimes a fifth, and sometimes a third was allowed to the soldiers, and at others half was reserved for the crown. On some occasions, a seventh or tenth part was allowed to the general, and the rest belonged to the captors, except ships of war, which belong entirely to the crown.—Sometimes a division was made in proportion to the hazard and expence: which was the case among the Italians, where the third part of the prize was assigned to the owner of the victorious vessel, another third to those who had merchandise on board, and the remaining third to the combatants.
On this matter, different customs are followed in different countries. In Spain, soldiers sometimes received a fifth and sometimes a third, while at other times half was set aside for the crown. Occasionally, a seventh or tenth was granted to the general, with the rest going to the captors, except for warships, which belong entirely to the crown. Sometimes, a division was made based on the risk and cost involved: this was the case among the Italians, where a third of the prize was given to the owner of the victorious ship, another third to those with merchandise on board, and the remaining third to the combatants.
In some cases it happens that private adventurers are not allowed the whole of their captures, a certain portion of which must go to the state or to those, who have received a grant of such prizes from the state. Thus in Spain, if in time of war ships are fitted out by private persons, one part of the captures, which they make belongs to the crown, and another to the Lord High Admiral. So likewise in France, and Holland, the tenth part of a prize belonged to the Admiral, a fifth also being previously deducted for the use of the state. But by land it is customary upon the taking of towns, and in battles, for every one to keep the prizes which he takes. But in excursions, every thing taken becomes the common stock of all engaged, being afterwards divided amongst them according to their respective ranks.
In some cases, private adventurers can't keep everything they capture, as a portion has to go to the state or to those who have been granted such prizes by the state. For instance, in Spain, when ships are outfitted by private individuals during wartime, part of what they capture goes to the crown, and another part goes to the Lord High Admiral. Similarly, in France and Holland, one-tenth of a prize goes to the Admiral, with an additional fifth deducted for state use. On land, when towns are captured or in battles, everyone usually keeps what they take. However, during raids, everything collected becomes the shared property of all involved, which is then divided among them based on their ranks.
XXV. As a consequence deducible from the above positions, it may be observed, that if a people not engaged in war be made mediators in a doubtful matter respecting things captured in war, the cause must be adjudged in favour of him, who has on his side the laws and customs of the country, which he has espoused. But if no such right can be proved, the prize must be adjudged to the state, rather than to the individual captor.—The maxim indeed of Quintilian can never be344 admitted, that the laws of war can never be enforced in matters, that may be decided by judicial authority; and that, on the other hand, whatever has been gained by arms can be maintained by force of arms alone.
XXV. Based on the points made above, it can be noted that if a people who are not involved in the war act as mediators in a disputed issue regarding things taken during the war, the outcome should favor the one who has the laws and customs of the country on their side. However, if no such right can be established, the prize must go to the state, not to the individual who captured it. Indeed, Quintilian's principle that the laws of war can’t be enforced in situations that can be resolved by legal authority cannot be accepted, and conversely, whatever is acquired through force can only be held through force.
XXVI. It was observed in a former part of this chapter, that things, NOT BELONGING to an enemy, cannot be taken, although found with him. For this is neither consonant to natural justice, nor introduced by the law of nations. But if in those things the enemy had any right connected with possession, such as the right of pledge, retention or service, that would not obstruct the power of the captors.
XXVI. It was noted earlier in this chapter that items NOT BELONGING to an enemy cannot be taken, even if found with them. This is not in line with natural justice or supported by international law. However, if the enemy had any rights related to possession of those items, such as a right of pledge, retention, or service, that wouldn't stop the captors from exercising their power.
It is a disputed point, both as to persons and things, whether they can be lawfully taken in the territory of a power at war with neither of the belligerents. In regard ONLY to the law of nations, as far as it allows us to kill an enemy wherever he is found, the PLACE has nothing to do with the question. But considering the rights of the sovereign, to whom that territory belongs, he undoubtedly has a right to forbid the seizure of persons, or the capture of things within his own dominions: and may demand satisfaction for the violation of that right. In the same manner, though beasts, that are wild by nature, become the property of those, who take them, still an owner may forbid any one to commit a trespass upon his lands in order to take them.
It’s a debated issue, both regarding people and objects, whether they can be legally taken in the territory of a power at war with neither of the combatants. As for international law, since it allows us to kill an enemy wherever they are found, the location doesn’t matter. However, considering the rights of the sovereign who owns that territory, they definitely have the right to prohibit the seizure of people or the capture of objects within their own lands and can demand compensation for any violation of that right. Similarly, even though wild animals become the property of those who capture them, an owner can prevent anyone from trespassing on their land to catch them.
CHAPTER VII.
On the Rights of Prisoners of War.
By the law of nations, slavery the result of being taken in solemn war—The same condition extends to the descendants of those taken—The power over them—Even incorporeal things may be gained by the rights of war—Reason of this—This right not prevalent to the same extent among Christian powers of the present day—The substitute used in place of this right.
According to international law, slavery is the result of being taken during formal warfare. This also applies to the descendants of those who were captured. They are subject to authority. Even non-physical things can be obtained through the rights of war. The reasoning behind this is clear. However, this right is not as commonly recognized among Christian nations today. Instead, there are other methods used instead of this right.
I. By the law of nature, in its primaeval state; apart from human institutions and customs, no men can be slaves: and it is in this sense that legal writers maintain the opinion that slavery is repugnant to nature. Yet in a former part of this treatise, it was shewn that there is nothing repugnant to natural justice, in deriving the origin of servitude from human actions, whether founded upon compact or crime.
I. According to the law of nature, in its original state; outside of human institutions and customs, no one can be enslaved: this is why legal scholars argue that slavery goes against nature. However, in an earlier section of this work, it was shown that there's nothing against natural justice in the idea that servitude comes from human actions, whether based on agreement or wrongdoing.
But the law of nations now under consideration is of wider extent both in its authority over persons, and its effects. For, as to persons, not only those, who surrender their rights, or engage themselves to servitude, are considered in the light of slaves, but all, who are taken prisoners in public and solemn war, come under the same description from the time that they are carried into the places, of which the enemy is master.
But the current law of nations is broader in both its authority over individuals and its consequences. Because, regarding individuals, not only those who give up their rights or commit themselves to servitude are viewed as slaves, but everyone who is captured in a formal and public war is treated the same way from the moment they are taken to the territory controlled by the enemy.
Nor is the commission of crime requisite to reduce them to this condition, but the fate of all is alike, who are unfortunately taken within the territories of an enemy, upon the breaking out of war.
Nor is committing a crime necessary to bring them to this condition, but the fate of everyone is the same if they are tragically caught in the territories of an enemy when war breaks out.
II. and III. In ancient times, while slavery was permitted to exist, the offspring, born during captivity or servitude, continued in the same condition as the parents.—The consequences of such rules were of wide extent;—there was no cruelty, which masters might not inflict upon their slaves;—there was no service, the performance of which they might not compel;—the power even of life and death was in their hands. However the Roman laws at length set bounds to such wanton power, at least to the exercise of it within the Roman territories.
II. and III. In ancient times, while slavery was allowed to exist, children born into captivity or servitude ended up in the same situation as their parents. The implications of these rules were far-reaching; there was no cruelty that masters could not inflict on their slaves, and there was no task they could not force them to perform. Masters even had the power of life and death over their slaves. However, Roman laws eventually placed limits on such unchecked power, at least in terms of its exercise within Roman territories.
346 Every thing too, found upon the prisoner's person, became a lawful prize to the captor. For as Justinian observes, one who was entirely in the power of another could have no property of his own.
346 Everything found on the prisoner’s person became a legal prize for the captor. As Justinian points out, someone who is completely under another's control cannot have any property of their own.
IV. and V. Incorporeal rights, gained by the enemy, along with the person so captured, cannot be considered in the light of primary and original acquisitions. And there are some rights so purely personal in their nature, that they cannot be lost even by captivity, nor the duties attached thereto ever be relinquished. Of such a nature was the paternal right among the Romans. For rights of this kind cannot exist but immediately with the person to whom they originally belonged.
IV. and V. Incorporeal rights acquired by the enemy, along with the captured person, cannot be seen as primary and original acquisitions. Some rights are so personal that they cannot be lost even through capture, nor can the associated duties ever be surrendered. An example of this is the paternal right among the Romans. Rights like these can only exist directly with the person to whom they originally belonged.
All these rights to prizes, which were introduced by the law of nations, were intended as an inducement to captors to refrain from the cruel rigour of putting prisoners to death; as they might hope to derive some advantage from sparing and saving them. From hence Pomponius deduces the origin of the word, SERVUS, or SLAVE, being one, who might have been put to death, but from motives of interest or humanity had been saved.
All these rights to prizes, established by international law, were meant to encourage captors to avoid the cruel practice of executing prisoners; they could expect to gain something by sparing their lives. From this, Pomponius traces the origin of the word Hey there, or SLAVE, referring to someone who could have been killed but was saved for reasons of self-interest or compassion.
VI. (being the IX. of the original.) It has long been a maxim, universally received among the powers of Christendom, that prisoners of war cannot be made slaves, so as to be sold, or compelled to the hardships and labour attached to slavery. And they have with good reason embraced the latter principle. As it would be inconsistent with every precept of the law of charity, for men to refuse abandoning a cruel right, unless they might be allowed to substitute another, of great, though somewhat inferior rigour, in its place.
VI. (which is IX. of the original.) It has long been a widely accepted principle among the countries of Christendom that prisoners of war cannot be treated as slaves, meaning they cannot be sold or forced into the hardships and labor that come with slavery. They have rightly adopted this principle. It would go against every principle of charity law for people to keep a cruel right unless they could replace it with another one that is harsh, though slightly less so.
And this, as Gregoras informs us, became a traditionary principle among all who professed one common religion; nor was it confined to those, who lived under the authority of the Roman empire, but prevailed among the Thessalians, the Illyrians, the Triballians, and Bulgarians.—Though such an abolition of slavery, and mitigation of captivity may be considered as of trivial import, yet they were effects produced by the introduction of the Christian religion, especially upon recollection that Socrates tried, but without effect, to prevail upon the Greeks to forbear making slaves of each other.
And this, as Gregoras tells us, became a traditional principle among everyone who followed the same religion; it wasn't just limited to those under the authority of the Roman Empire, but also spread among the Thessalians, the Illyrians, the Triballians, and the Bulgarians. While this end to slavery and the easing of captivity might seem minor, these were consequences of the introduction of Christianity, especially considering that Socrates attempted, but failed, to convince the Greeks to stop enslaving one another.
In this respect the Mahometans act towards each other in the same manner as Christians do. Though it347 is still the practice among Christian powers to detain prisoners of war, till their ransom be paid, the amount of which depends upon the will of the Conqueror, unless it has been settled by express treaty. The right of detaining such prisoners has sometimes been allowed to the individuals, who took them, except where the prisoners were personages of extraordinary rank, who were always considered as prisoners of war to the state.
In this regard, Muslims treat each other the same way Christians do. While it's still common for Christian nations to hold prisoners of war until their ransom is paid, the amount is based on the conqueror's discretion unless it’s specified in a treaty. The right to hold these prisoners has occasionally been granted to the individuals who captured them, except when the prisoners are of very high status, who are always seen as prisoners of war for the state.
CHAPTER VIII.
On Empire Over the Conquered.
Civil and sovereign jurisdiction acquired by conquest—Effects of such acquisition—Absolute power or mixed power gained by conquest—Incorporeal rights acquired in the same manner—Thessalian bond considered.
Civil and sovereign authority gained through conquest—Consequences of that acquisition—Total power or a mix of powers obtained through conquest—Intangible rights obtained in the same way—Thessalian bond analyzed.
I. If individuals can reduce each other to subjection, it is not surprising that states can do the same, and by this means acquire a civil, absolute, or mixed, dominion. So that, in the language of Tertullian, victory has often been the foundation of dominion, and it often happens, as Quintilian remarks, that the boundaries of states and kingdoms, of nations and cities, can only be settled by the laws of war.
I. If people can make each other submissive, it's not surprising that governments can do the same and, in doing so, gain control that is civil, absolute, or mixed. In the words of Tertullian, victory has often been the basis of power, and as Quintilian points out, the borders of countries, kingdoms, nations, and cities can often only be established through the rules of war.
Quintus Curtius relates of Alexander, that he said, it was for conquerors to dictate laws, which the conquered were bound to receive. This has always been a general opinion and rule, thus Ariovistus, in Caesar, laid it down as an indubitable right of war, for the conqueror to impose whatever terms he pleased upon the conquered, nor did he suppose the Roman people would allow any one to interpose with them in the discretionary use of this right.
Quintus Curtius tells us about Alexander, who said that it was up to conquerors to set the laws that the conquered had to accept. This has always been a common belief and practice; for example, Ariovistus in Caesar stated it as an unquestionable right of war for the conqueror to impose any terms they wanted on the defeated. He also assumed that the Roman people would not let anyone interfere with their ability to exercise this right.
By conquest, a prince succeeds to all the rights of the conquered sovereign or state; and if it be a commonwealth, he acquires all the rights and privileges, which the people possessed. He gains the same right, which the state had before, to alienate the possessions, or to transmit them if he chuses to his descendants, by which means they will become a patrimonial territory.
By conquering, a prince takes on all the rights of the defeated ruler or state; if it’s a commonwealth, he gains all the rights and privileges that the people had. He inherits the same authority that the state previously had to sell off the holdings or pass them down to his heirs, which will turn them into inherited land.
II. The right of conquest may go even beyond this. A state may hereby lose its political existence, so far as to form an appendage to another power, which was the case with the Roman provinces: or if a king engaged in war against a state, at his own expence, has reduced it to complete subjection, his authority over it becomes an absolute, rather than a limited sovereignty. It can no longer be called an independent state, but, by the right349 of conquest, forms an integral part of the prince's immediate dominions. Xenophon in drawing the character of Agesilaus, commends him for requiring no other services and obedience of the cities he had conquered, than what is usually paid by subjects to their lawful sovereigns.
II. The right of conquest can extend even further. A state can lose its political existence to the point of becoming part of another power, similar to what happened with the Roman provinces. If a king goes to war against a state at his own expense and brings it completely under control, his authority over that state becomes absolute rather than limited. It can no longer be considered an independent state; instead, through the right of conquest, it becomes an integral part of the prince's direct territories. When Xenophon describes Agesilaus, he praises him for not demanding any more services and obedience from the cities he conquered than what is typically expected from subjects to their rightful sovereigns.
III. From hence it will be easy to understand what is meant by a mixed government, composed partly of civil, and partly of absolute power;—it is a government, where subjection is united with some degree of personal liberty.
III. From here, it will be easy to understand what a mixed government means. It consists of both civil power and absolute power; it's a system where control is combined with some level of personal freedom.
We sometimes read of nations, that have been so far subdued, as to be deprived of the use of all warlike arms, being allowed to retain no instruments of iron, but the implements of husbandry; and of others, that have been compelled to change their national customs and language.
We sometimes hear about nations that have been so thoroughly defeated that they are stripped of all weapons, allowed to keep only farming tools and no iron instruments; and about others that have been forced to change their cultural traditions and language.
IV. States as well as individuals may lose their property by the laws of war: and even a voluntary surrender is in reality nothing more than giving up what might have been taken by force. For as Livy says, where all things submit to the power of arms, the conqueror may impose whatever terms, and exact whatever fines he pleases. Thus the Roman people by the victories of Pompey acquired all the territories, which Mithridates had gained by conquest.
IV. Both states and individuals can lose their property according to the laws of war; even a voluntary surrender is really just giving up what could have been taken by force. As Livy says, when everything is under the control of armed power, the conqueror can impose any terms and demand any fines they want. Thus, the Roman people, through Pompey's victories, acquired all the territories that Mithridates had gained through conquest.
The incorporeal rights too, belonging to one state, may pass to another by the rights of conquest. Upon the taking of Alba, the Romans retained all the rights belonging to that city. From hence it follows, that the Thessalians were released from the obligation of paying a sum of money, which they owed to the Thebans; Alexander, upon the taking of Thebes, having, as a conqueror, forgiven the debt. Nor is the argument used by Quintilian in favour of the Thebans, at all convincing: he maintains that nothing but what is of a tangible nature can pass by right of conquest, a class of things to which incorporeal rights can never be reduced: and that there is a material difference between inheritance and victory, the former of which may convey incorporeal rights, but the latter can give nothing except things of a solid and visible substance.
The intangible rights that belong to one state can also be transferred to another through conquest. After the Romans took Alba, they kept all the rights associated with that city. This means that the Thessalians no longer had to pay the money they owed to the Thebans because Alexander, as the conqueror of Thebes, forgave the debt. Quintilian's argument in favor of the Thebans isn’t convincing at all: he claims that only tangible things can be transferred through conquest, meaning that incorporeal rights don’t fit into that category. He also states that there’s a significant difference between inheritance and victory; inheritance can transfer incorporeal rights, while victory only transfers solid and visible items.
But on the other hand it may be justly said, that whoever is master of the persons, is master also of all the rights and things, which are vested in those persons, who are in that case considered as having nothing of their own. Indeed if any one should leave to a conquered350 people their rights, as a state, still there are some things belonging to that state, which he might appropriate to himself. For it is in his own power to determine, to what extent his generosity, or the exertion of his right shall go. Caesar imitated the conduct of Alexander, in forgiving the Dyrrachians a debt, which they owed to some one of the opposite party. But the kind of war, in which Caesar was engaged does not fall within the rules of the law of nations.
But on the other hand, it's fair to say that whoever controls the people also controls all the rights and belongings associated with those people, who are seen as having nothing of their own. In fact, if someone were to leave a conquered350 group their rights as a state, there would still be some assets belonging to that state that they could take for themselves. It is within their own power to decide the extent of their generosity or the exercise of their rights. Caesar followed Alexander's example by forgiving the Dyrrachians a debt they owed to someone from the opposing side. However, the kind of war Caesar was involved in doesn't align with the rules of international law.
CHAPTER IX.
The Right of Postliminium.
Origin of the term, postliminium—Where it takes effect—Certain things recoverable thereby—In what cases the right of postliminium prevails in peace, as well as war—What rights are recoverable, and what rights not recoverable—When a people is not entitled to the right of postliminium—Extent of civil law in these cases—Deserters—Ransomed prisoners—Subjects—Lands recovered by right of postliminium—Distinction formerly observed with respect to movable things—Modern practice.
Origin of the term postliminium—Where it applies—Specific items that can be recovered—In which situations the right of postliminium is valid during both peace and war—What rights can be recovered and what rights cannot be recovered—When a group is not entitled to the right of postliminium—Scope of civil law in these cases—Deserters—Ransomed prisoners—Subjects—Lands regained through the right of postliminium—Distinctions that were previously made regarding movable items—Current practice.
I. The professors of law in former ages have given no more satisfactory account of the rights of postliminium, than they have done of those, respecting things taken from the enemy. The subject has been more accurately handled by the ancient Romans, but often still with a considerable degree of confusion, so that a reader cannot easily distinguish, what part they assign to the province of the law of nations, and what part to the civil law of Rome.
I. The law professors from past eras haven't provided a clearer explanation of the rights of postliminium than they have for the rights pertaining to things taken from the enemy. The ancient Romans addressed this topic more precisely, but still often with significant confusion, making it difficult for readers to tell which aspects belong to the law of nations and which belong to Roman civil law.
Amidst a great variety of opinions, upon the meaning of the word, postliminium, that of Scaevola seems the most natural, who derives it from the word post, signifying a return after captivity, and limen the boundary or entrance of the house, or from limes, a public boundary. Thus the ancients called exile or banishment, eliminium, that is, sending any one out of the boundaries of the country.
Amidst a wide range of opinions about the meaning of the word postliminium, Scaevola's interpretation seems the most straightforward. He derives it from the word post, meaning a return after captivity, and limen, which refers to the boundary or entrance of a house, or from limes, a public boundary. Therefore, the ancients referred to exile or banishment as eliminium, meaning sending someone outside the borders of the country.
II. Postliminium therefore, according to its original signification, means the right, accruing to any one in consequence of his return home from captivity. Pomponius defines the right of postliminium to take place the moment any one enters a town or garrison, of which his sovereign is master; but according to Paulus he must have entered within the territories of his own country before he can be entitled to that right.
II. Postliminium, as its original meaning suggests, refers to the right that someone gains when they return home from captivity. Pomponius states that the right of postliminium takes effect as soon as someone enters a town or military base under the control of their sovereign; however, according to Paulus, they must first have entered the territory of their own country to be entitled to that right.
Upon this principle nations have, in general, gone so far, as to allow the right of postliminium to take place, where any person, or indeed any thing, coming within the privileges of postliminium, have arrived within the territory of a friendly or allied power.
Upon this principle, nations have generally gone so far as to allow the right of postliminium to apply when any person, or even any thing, that falls under the privileges of postliminium enters the territory of a friendly or allied power.
By the term friends, or allies, used in this place, are not simply meant, those who are at peace with another352 power, but those who are engaged in the same war, and in a common cause with that power. So that all, who have come into the territories of such powers, are protected under the pledge of public faith. For it makes no difference with respect to persons or things, whether they are in the territories of those powers, or in their own.
By "friends" or "allies," I don't just mean those who are at peace with another power, but also those who are fighting alongside that power in a shared cause. Therefore, anyone who enters the lands of those powers is protected under the commitment of public trust. It doesn't matter whether people or things are in the territories of those powers or their own.
In the territory of a friendly power, who is not engaged in the same cause with either of two belligerent parties, prisoners of war do not change their condition, unless it has been agreed to the contrary by express treaty; as in the second treaty between the Romans and Carthaginians, it was stipulated that if any prisoners, taken by the Carthaginians from powers friendly to the Romans, should come into ports subject to the Roman people, their liberty might be claimed: and that powers friendly to the Carthaginians should enjoy the same privilege. For this reason, the Roman prisoners taken in the second Punic war, when sent into Greece, had not the right of postliminium there, the Greeks being entirely neutral, consequently they could not be released, till they were ransomed.
In the territory of a friendly nation that isn't involved in the conflict between the two warring parties, prisoners of war don’t change their status unless there’s an explicit agreement in a treaty stating otherwise. For instance, in the second treaty between the Romans and Carthaginians, it was agreed that if any prisoners taken by the Carthaginians from nations friendly to the Romans ended up in ports controlled by the Roman people, their freedom could be claimed; similarly, nations friendly to the Carthaginians would have the same right. Because of this, Roman prisoners captured during the second Punic War, when sent to Greece, didn’t have the right of postliminium there, as the Greeks were totally neutral, meaning they couldn’t be freed until they were ransomed.
III. According to the language of the ancient Romans, even free men might be restored by the right of postliminium.
III. According to the language of the ancient Romans, even free men could be restored by the right of postliminium.
Gallus Ælius, in the first book of his explanation of law-terms, defines a person restored to his original situation by the right of postliminium, to be one, who had gone from his own country, in a free condition, to another, and returned to his own in consequence of such right. By the right of postliminium a slave also who has fallen into the hands of an enemy, upon his release from thence, returns to the service of his former master.
Gallus Ælius, in the first book of his explanation of law terms, defines a person who is restored to their original status by the right of postliminium as someone who has left their own country freely, gone to another place, and then returned home because of that right. By the right of postliminium, a slave who has been captured by an enemy and is then freed returns to the service of their former master.
As to the law of postliminium, horses, mules, and ships are considered in the same light as slaves. And whatever advantage this law gives any one in recovering persons or things from an enemy, the enemy in his turn has equal advantage from the same law.
As for the law of postliminium, horses, mules, and ships are viewed in the same way as slaves. Any benefit this law provides someone in recovering people or things from an enemy, the enemy also has the same benefit from that law.
But modern lawyers have made a distinction between two kinds of postliminium, by one of which, persons returned to their former condition, and by the other, things are recovered.
But modern lawyers have differentiated between two types of postliminium: one in which people return to their previous status, and the other in which things are reclaimed.
IV. The right of postliminium may extend to those, who are seized and detained in an enemy's country upon the breaking out of war. For though during the continuance353 of that war, there may be reason for detaining them, in order to weaken the enemy's strength, yet, upon the conclusion of a peace, no such motive and pretence can be devised for their release being refused or delayed. It is a settled point therefore that upon peace being made, prisoners of the above description always obtain their liberty, their claim to it being universally acknowledged.
IV. The right of postliminium can apply to those who are captured and held in an enemy's country when war breaks out. Even though there may be justification for keeping them during the war to weaken the enemy, once peace is established, there is no reason or excuse for delaying or refusing their release. It is a well-established principle that when peace is made, prisoners in this situation are always granted their freedom, and their right to it is widely recognized.
With respect to other kinds of prisoners, every one used what he wished to be thought his right, except where fixed rules were prescribed by treaty. And for the same reason, neither slaves, nor things taken in war are restored upon a peace, except express stipulations be made to that purpose. A conqueror too, in general, wishes to have it believed that he had a right to make such acquisition; and indeed the departure from such a rule might give rise to wars without end.
In relation to other types of prisoners, everyone acted as if they had the right to do what they wanted, unless specific rules were established by treaty. Likewise, neither slaves nor items taken in war are returned when peace is made, unless there are clear agreements to do so. Generally, a conqueror wants people to believe that he has the right to seize such possessions; in fact, not following this principle could lead to endless wars.
V. and VI. A prisoner of war, upon his release, and return to his own country, is entitled to all his privileges THERE, and indeed to everything either corporeal, or incorporeal, which he might have before possessed in a NEUTRAL STATE, at the time of his captivity. For if such a state, in order to preserve her neutrality, considered his captivity as a matter of right on the part of the enemy, so also, in order to shew her impartiality, she cannot lawfully abridge his right to any thing he may reclaim upon his release. The controul therefore, which the person, to whom the prisoner belonged by the right of war, had over his effects, was not absolutely unconditional: for he might lose it, even against his will, whenever the prisoner came again under the protection, or within the territories, of his own sovereign. Along with the prisoner therefore he would lose everything, which was considered as an appendage to his person.
V. and VI. A prisoner of war, upon being released and returning to his own country, is entitled to all his privileges THERE, and even to everything he may have possessed, whether physical or non-physical, in a Neutral State, at the time he was captured. If such a state, in order to maintain its neutrality, viewed his captivity as a right of the enemy, then to demonstrate its impartiality, it also cannot legally limit his right to reclaim anything upon his release. Therefore, the control that the person, to whom the prisoner belonged by the right of war, had over his belongings was not completely unconditional: he could lose it, even against his will, whenever the prisoner came back under the protection or within the territories of his own sovereign. Thus, along with the prisoner, he would lose everything that was considered an extension of his person.
In cases where effects taken in war have been alienated, a question arises, whether the law of nations confirms the title, and secures the possession of the person, who has derived or purchased them from him, who was master of them by the rights of war, by having the prisoner in his custody at the time of alienation, or whether such things are recoverable; supposing the things to be in a neutral territory.
In situations where war-related possessions have been transferred, a question comes up: does international law recognize the ownership and protect the possession of the person who received or bought them from the original owner, who had rightful control over them during the war, as long as they had the items at the time of the transfer? Or are those items recoverable, assuming they are in a neutral area?
A distinction seems proper to be made between things recoverable by postliminium, and things excepted from that right: so that every alienation of the former must be qualified and conditional, but that of the latter may354 be absolute. By things alienated may be understood even those, of which a gift has been made, or to which the owner has relinquished every claim.
A clear distinction should be made between things that can be reclaimed through postliminium and those that are excluded from that right: so that any transfer of the former must be limited and conditional, while the transfer of the latter can be absolute. By things that are transferred, we can even understand those for which a gift has been given or to which the owner has given up all claim. 354
VII. Upon any one's returning to his former condition by the law of postliminium, all his rights are restored as fully, as if he had never been in the hands and power of the enemy.
VII. When someone returns to their previous state under the law of postliminium, all their rights are completely restored, as if they had never been in the hands or control of the enemy.
VIII. The case of those however, who have been conquered by the arms of an enemy, and have surrendered themselves, forms an exception to this rule; because engagements of that kind must be valid, and honourably adhered to according to the law of postliminium. So that during the time of a truce, the right of postliminium cannot be claimed.
VIII. The situation of those who have been defeated by an enemy and have surrendered themselves is an exception to this rule; because agreements of that kind must be valid and respected according to the law of postliminium. Therefore, during a truce, the right of postliminium cannot be claimed.
But where a surrender has been made without any express or positive convention the right of postliminium exists in all its force.
But when a surrender has been made without any clear or definite agreement, the right of postliminium remains fully in effect.
IX. What has been said of individuals applies to nations: so that a free people, who have been subjugated, upon being delivered from the yoke of the enemy by the power of their allies, will recover their former condition.
IX. What has been said about individuals applies to nations: so a free people who have been oppressed, when freed from their enemy’s control by the strength of their allies, will return to their former state.
But if the whole population that constituted a state has been dispersed, the people can no longer be considered as the same: nor does the law of nations in such a case enforce the right of postliminium for the restoration of all effects formerly belonging to that people. For as the identity of a ship, or any other material object, can only be ascertained by the permanent union of its original parts: so a nation can no longer be regarded as the same, when every peculiar characteristic belonging to it is effaced.
But if the entire population that made up a state has been scattered, the people can no longer be seen as the same. The law of nations doesn't apply the right of postliminium to restore all the assets that used to belong to that people in such cases. Just as the identity of a ship, or any other physical object, can only be determined by the permanent connection of its original parts, a nation can no longer be recognized as the same when all its unique characteristics have been erased.
The state of Saguntum therefore was no longer judged to be the same, when it was restored to its ancient possessors, at the expiration of eight years: nor could Thebes any longer be deemed the original city, as its inhabitants had been sold by Alexander for slaves. From hence it is evident, that the Thebans could not, by the right of postliminium, recover the sum of money, which the Thessalians had owed them: and that for two reasons: because, in the first place, they were a new people; and, secondly, because Alexander at the time that he was absolute master of the city had a right, if he thought proper, to relinquish the claim to that debt, which he had actually done. Besides, a debt is not in355 the number of things recoverable by the right of postliminium.
The state of Saguntum was no longer considered the same when it was returned to its original owners after eight years. Similarly, Thebes could no longer be seen as the original city since its inhabitants had been sold into slavery by Alexander. Thus, it's clear that the Thebans could not reclaim the money owed to them by the Thessalians for two reasons: first, they were now a new people, and second, Alexander, who had full control of the city, had the right to give up that debt, which he actually did. Additionally, a debt isn't something that can be recovered under the right of postliminium.
The rules, respecting a state, are not much unlike those laid down by the ancient Roman law, which made marriage a dissoluble tie, so that it could not be restored by the right of postliminium: but a new consent, and a new contract were necessary.
The rules about a state are pretty similar to those established by ancient Roman law, which treated marriage as a breakable bond, so it couldn't be restored through the right of postliminium: instead, new consent and a new contract were required.
X. By the Roman civil law deserters were excluded from the right of postliminium.
X. According to Roman civil law, deserters were barred from the right of postliminium.
XI. and XII. It is a point of much importance to the subject, and it was before declared in the affirmative, that nations, which have been under a foreign yoke, recover their former condition, even though their deliverance has not been effected by their former sovereign, but by some ally. It is a settled rule, where there is no express treaty to the contrary. At the same time it is but reasonable that such ally be indemnified for the expences incurred in accomplishing that deliverance.
XI. and XII. It’s very important to the topic that it has been stated before that nations previously under foreign control regain their former status, even if their liberation wasn’t achieved by their original ruler, but by an ally. This is a well-established principle, unless there is a specific treaty saying otherwise. At the same time, it makes sense that the ally should be compensated for the expenses incurred in achieving that liberation.
XIII. Among things within the right of postliminium, lands in particular attract our attention. For, as Pomponius observes, upon the expulsion of an enemy lands naturally revert to their former masters. And in this sense expulsion is understood to take place from the time that his free and open access to a territory is entirely cut off.
XIII. Among the elements related to the right of postliminium, lands in particular stand out to us. As Pomponius notes, when an enemy is expelled, the lands naturally return to their original owners. In this context, expulsion is understood to happen from the moment their free and open access to an area is completely blocked.
Thus the Lacedaemonians, after taking Aegina from the Athenians, restored it to its ancient owners. Justinian and other emperors restored to the heirs of the ancient possessors of the lands, which had been recovered from the Goths and Vandals, still reserving against those owners all prescriptive rights, which the Roman laws had introduced.
Thus, the Spartans, after taking Aegina from the Athenians, returned it to its original owners. Justinian and other emperors returned the lands recovered from the Goths and Vandals to the heirs of the original possessors, while still maintaining all the legal rights established by Roman law against those owners.
The privileges belonging to lands attach to every right also connected with the soil. For religious or consecrated places, that had been taken by an enemy, when recovered returned, as Pomponius has said, to their former condition.
The privileges associated with land are tied to every right related to the soil. For religious or consecrated sites that were seized by an enemy, when they are reclaimed, they revert to their original state, as Pomponius noted.
Upon the same principle it was provided by a law in Spain, that provinces, and all other hereditary jurisdictions, particularly supreme jurisdictions, should return to the original possessors by the right of postliminium; and those of an inferior kind, if reclaimed within the space of four years. Except that citadels lost by war always belonged to the crown, in whatever manner they were recovered.
On the same principle, a law in Spain stated that provinces and all other hereditary jurisdictions, especially supreme ones, should go back to the original owners through the right of postliminium; and those of a lower status, if claimed within four years. However, citadels taken during war always belonged to the crown, regardless of how they were regained.
356 XIV. On the contrary a general opinion prevails, that moveable property, which constitutes part of a lawful prize, is not recoverable by the right of postliminium. So that things acquired by purchase, wherever they are found, continue the property of the purchaser. Nor has the original owner a right to claim them, when found in a neutral state, or even carried into his own territory.
356 XIV. On the other hand, there's a common belief that movable property, which is part of a legitimate prize, cannot be recovered by the right of postliminium. This means that things bought, no matter where they are located, remain the property of the buyer. The original owner does not have the right to claim them when they are found in a neutral state, or even if they are taken back to their own territory.
Things useful in war, as we find, were formerly an exception to this rule: an exception, which seems to have been favoured by the law of nations in order to induce men the more readily to provide them, in the hopes of recovering them, if lost. And this indulgence was the more easily granted, as most nations, at that period, in all their customs, seem to have had an eye to a state of warfare.—Among the things, coming under this description, ships of war, and merchant-ships are reckoned, but neither gallies, nor pleasure-boats: mules also are enumerated; but only such as are used to carry baggage: horses and mares too; but only such as are broken in to obey the bridle. And these are things, the bequest of which the Roman law confirmed, and which might come into the division of an inheritance.
Things useful in war, as we see, used to be an exception to this rule: an exception that the law of nations seemed to encourage in order to persuade people to provide them, hoping to recover them if lost. This leniency was more easily granted since most nations at that time seemed to consider a state of warfare in all their customs. Among the items included in this category are warships and merchant ships, but not galleys or pleasure boats; mules are also listed, but only those used for carrying baggage; horses and mares are included too, but only those that are trained to respond to the bridle. These are items that Roman law validated as bequests and could be included in the division of an inheritance.
Arms and cloathing indeed are useful in war, but still they were not recoverable by the right of postliminium; because the laws were by no means inclined to favour those, who lost either in war: and such a loss was deemed a disgrace, as we find from many parts of history. And in this respect, a distinction was made between a soldier's arms and his horse: because the latter might easily break loose, and fall into an enemy's hands without any fault of his rider. This distinction in moveable things seems to have prevailed in the western parts of Europe, under the Goths, even as far down as to the times of Boetius. For in explaining the Topics of Cicero, he speaks of this right, as a general custom of his day.
Arms and clothing are definitely useful in war, but they couldn't be reclaimed through the right of postliminium; because the laws didn't really favor those who lost anything in battle. Losing something in war was considered a disgrace, as we see in many parts of history. In this context, a distinction was made between a soldier's arms and his horse because the horse could easily get loose and end up in enemy hands without any fault of the rider. This distinction concerning movable goods seemed to exist in the western parts of Europe under the Goths, even down to the times of Boetius. When explaining Cicero's Topics, he mentions this right as a common practice of his time.
XV. But in later times, if not before, this distinction seems to have been abolished. For all intelligent writers speak of moveable effects as not recoverable by the right of postliminium, and it has evidently been decided so, in many places, with respect to ships.
XV. However, in later times, if not earlier, this distinction appears to have been eliminated. All knowledgeable writers refer to movable assets as not being recoverable under the right of postliminium, and it has clearly been established this way in many instances concerning ships.
XVI. The right of postliminium is quite unnecessary, before the things taken have been carried into some place of which the enemy is master, although they may be in his possession: for they have not yet changed their owner, by the law of nations. And, according to the357 opinions of Ulpian and Javolenus, the law of postliminium is no less superfluous, where goods have been taken by robbers and pirates, because the law of nations does not allow THEIR possession of the goods to convey any change, or right of property to THEM.
XVI. The right of postliminium is totally unnecessary before the items taken have been moved to a place under the enemy's control, even if they are in his possession: their ownership hasn't changed according to international law. Also, based on the opinions of Ulpian and Javolenus, the law of postliminium is equally unnecessary when goods have been seized by thieves and pirates, as international law does not recognize their possession of the goods as conferring any change or property rights to them.
Upon this ground, the Athenians wished to consider Philip, as RESTORING, and not GIVING them Halonesus, of which they had been robbed by pirates, from whom he had taken it again. For things taken by pirates may be reclaimed, wherever they are found; except that NATURAL JUSTICE requires that the person, who has gained them out of their hands, at his own expence, should be indemnified, in proportion to what the owner himself would willingly have spent for their recovery.
On this basis, the Athenians wanted to view Philip as RESTORE rather than Giving them Halonesus, which had been taken from them by pirates, and from whom he had reclaimed it. Since things taken by pirates can be recovered, no matter where they are found; however, FAIRNESS dictates that the person who, at their own expense, has retrieved them should be compensated based on what the original owner would have been willing to spend to get them back.
XVII. But a different maxim may be established by the CIVIL LAW. Thus by the law of Spain, ships taken from pirates become the lawful prize of the captors: which may seem a hardship upon the original owners; but in some cases individual interest must be sacrificed to the public good: especially where the danger and difficulty of retaking the ships is so great.65 But such a law will not prevent foreigners from asserting their claims.
XVII. However, a different principle may be established by the Civil Law. According to the law in Spain, ships seized from pirates become the legal property of the captors. This may seem unfair to the original owners, but sometimes individual interests must be set aside for the greater good, especially when the danger and challenge of reclaiming the ships is so great.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Nonetheless, this law does not stop foreigners from claiming their rights.
XVIII. It was rather a surprising maxim in the Roman law, which established the right of postliminium, not only between hostile powers, but between all foreign states, and, in some cases, between those, who were members of the Roman empire. But this was only a vestige of the rude and pastoral ages, before society was perfectly formed. So that even between nations, who were not engaged in public war with each other, a kind of licence resembling that of war prevailed.
XVIII. It was quite a surprising principle in Roman law that established the right of postliminium, not just between hostile powers, but also among all foreign nations, and in certain situations, even among those who were part of the Roman Empire. However, this was merely a remnant of the rough and pastoral times, before society was fully developed. Therefore, even among nations that were not in open conflict with one another, a sort of license resembling that of war existed.
In order to prevent such a licence from proceeding to all the calamities and slaughter of war, the laws of captivity were introduced: and, as a consequence of this, postliminium took place, which might be considered as a great step towards the formation of equal treaties, from the rules of which pirates and robbers were excluded, and which indeed they themselves despised.
To stop that kind of license from leading to all the disasters and bloodshed of war, laws around captivity were created. As a result, postliminium emerged, which can be seen as a significant advancement toward establishing fair treaties, from which pirates and robbers were excluded and which, in fact, they themselves looked down upon.
XIX. In our times, the right of making prisoners, except in war, has been abolished not only among Christian states, but even among the greater part of Mahometans,358 those bands of society, which nature designed to establish amongst men, being in some measure restored.
XIX. Nowadays, the right to take prisoners, except during war, has been eliminated not just among Christian nations, but also among most Muslim ones,358 as the social bonds that nature intended to create among people are being somewhat restored.
But the ancient law of nations seems still in force against any rude or barbarous people, who, without any declaration or cause of war, consider all mankind as enemies. A decision has lately been made in the principal chamber of the parliament of Paris, declaring all effects belonging to the subjects of France, and taken by the Algerines, a people always engaged in predatory and maritime warfare with all other countries, if retaken, to belong to the captors.—At the same time it was decided, that, in the present day, ships are not reckoned among things recoverable by the right of postliminium.
But the old laws of nations still seem to apply against any uncivilized or barbaric groups who, without any declaration or reason for war, view all of humanity as their enemies. A recent decision was made in the main chamber of the Paris parliament, stating that any property belonging to French citizens that is taken by the Algerians, a group that is constantly involved in piracy and maritime conflict with other nations, will belong to those who capture it if it is reclaimed. At the same time, it was ruled that, in today's context, ships are not considered recoverable under the right of postliminium.
CHAPTER XI.66
The Right to Kill Enemies in a Just War Should Be Tempered with Moderation and Humanity.
In what cases strict justice allows the destruction of an enemy—Distinction between misfortune and guilt—Between principals and accessories in war—Distinction between unwarrantable and excusable grounds of promoting war—Sometimes right and laudable to forbear punishing an inveterate enemy—Every possible precaution requisite to spare the innocent—Especially children, women, and the aged, except they have committed atrocious acts—Clergymen, men of letters, husbandmen, merchants, prisoners—Conditional surrender not to be rejected—Unconditional surrender—Exceptions to the above rules, some of them considered, and refuted—Delinquents when numerous to be spared—Hostages to be spared—Unnecessary effusion of blood to be avoided.
When is it acceptable under strict justice to eliminate an enemy? The distinction between bad luck and wrongdoing—Between principal offenders and accomplices in war—The difference between unjustifiable and justifiable reasons for waging war—Sometimes it is appropriate and admirable to avoid punishing a long-time enemy—All possible steps should be taken to protect the innocent—Especially children, women, and the elderly, unless they have committed serious crimes—Clergy, scholars, farmers, merchants, and prisoners—Conditional surrender should not be refused—Unconditional surrender—Some exceptions to these rules are examined and addressed—Many offenders should be spared—Hostages should be protected—Unnecessary loss of life should be prevented.
I. and II. Cicero, in the first book of his offices, has finely observed, that "some duties are to be observed even towards those, from whom you have received an injury. For even vengeance and punishment have their due bounds." And at the same time he extols those ancient periods in the Roman government, when the events of war were mild, and marked with no unnecessary cruelty.
I. and II. Cicero, in the first book of his duties, noted that "some responsibilities should still be honored even towards those who have wronged you. Even revenge and punishment have their limits." He also praises the earlier times in Roman governance when the outcomes of war were more humane and lacked excessive cruelty.
The explanations given in the first chapter of this book will point out the cases, where the destruction of an enemy is one of the rights of lawful war, according to the principles of strict and internal justice, and where it is not so. For the death of an enemy may proceed either from an accidental calamity, or from the fixed purpose of his destruction.
The explanations in the first chapter of this book will highlight situations where destroying an enemy is considered a right in a just war, based on the principles of strict and internal justice, and where it is not. The death of an enemy can result from either an accidental disaster or a deliberate intention to kill.
No one can be justly killed by design, except by way of legal punishment, or to defend our lives, and preserve our property, when it cannot be effected without his destruction. For although in sacrificing the life of man to the preservation of perishable possessions, there may be nothing repugnant to strict justice, it is by no means consonant to the law of charity.
No one should be intentionally killed, except as a legal punishment or to protect our lives and safeguard our property, when it can't be done without causing their death. Even though sacrificing a person's life for the sake of material possessions might not conflict with strict justice, it definitely does not align with the law of charity.
But to justify a punishment of that kind, the person put to death must have committed a crime, and such a360 crime too, as every equitable judge would deem worthy of death. Points, which it is unnecessary to discuss any further, as they have been so fully explained in the chapter on punishments.
But to justify that kind of punishment, the person being executed must have committed a crime, and it should be a crime that any fair judge would consider deserving of death. These points don't need further discussion since they have been thoroughly explained in the chapter on punishments.360
III. In speaking of the calamities of war, as a punishment, it is proper to make a distinction between misfortune and injury. For a people may sometimes be engaged in war against their will, where they cannot be justly charged with entertaining hostile intentions.
III. When discussing the disasters of war as a punishment, it's important to differentiate between misfortune and harm. A group of people might find themselves in a war against their will, and they shouldn't be unfairly blamed for having hostile intentions.
Upon this subject, Velleius Paterculus observes that "to blame the Athenians for revolting, at the time they were besieged by Sylla, betrays a total ignorance of history. For the Athenians always continued so steady in their attachment to the Romans, that their fidelity became a proverbial expression. Yet their situation at that time excused their conduct, overpowered by the arms of Mithridates, they were obliged to submit to a foe within, while they had to sustain a siege from their friends without."
Upon this topic, Velleius Paterculus notes that "blaming the Athenians for rebelling while they were under siege by Sylla shows complete ignorance of history. The Athenians remained consistently loyal to the Romans, so much so that their loyalty became a saying. However, their circumstances at that time justified their actions; overwhelmed by the forces of Mithridates, they had to surrender to an enemy within while dealing with a siege from their supposed allies outside."
IV. and V. Between complete injuries and pure misfortunes there may be sometimes a middle kind of actions, partaking of the nature of both, which can neither be said to be done with known and wilful intention, nor yet excused under colour of ignorance and want of inclination. Acts of pure misfortune neither merit punishment, nor oblige the party to make reparation for the loss occasioned. Hence many parts of history supply us with distinctions that are made between those who are the authors of a war, and principals in it, and those who are obliged to follow others, as accessories in the same.
IV. and V. Between complete injuries and pure misfortunes, there are sometimes actions that share traits of both. These actions can't be clearly defined as being done with deliberate intent, nor can they be excused due to ignorance or lack of desire. Acts of pure misfortune don’t deserve punishment, nor do they require the person responsible to compensate for the loss caused. Therefore, many historical examples show us the differences between those who instigate a war and are key figures in it, and those who are forced to follow others, acting as accessories in the same situation.
VI. But respecting the authors of war, a distinction is to be made also, as to the motives and causes of war: some of which though not actually just, wear an appearance of justice, that may impose upon the well meaning. The writer to Herennius lays it down as the most equitable vindication of injury, where the party committing it, has neither been actuated by revenge, nor cruelty; but by the dictates of duty and an upright zeal.
VI. However, regarding the authors of war, it's important to make a distinction between the motives and causes of war: some, even if they're not truly just, can seem just and might deceive those with good intentions. The writer to Herennius states that the fairest justification for an injury occurs when the person responsible for it is not driven by revenge or cruelty, but by a sense of duty and sincere commitment.
Cicero, in the first book of his offices, advises the sparing of those, who have committed no acts of atrocity and cruelty in war, and that wars, undertaken to maintain national honour, should be conducted upon principles of moderation. And, in one of his letters, adverting to the war between Pompey and Caesar, he describes the struggle between those two illustrious men, as involved361 in so much obscurity of motives and causes, that many were perplexed in deciding which side to embrace. In his speech too for Marcellus, he remarks that such uncertainty might be attended with error, but could never be charged with guilt.
Cicero, in the first book of his "Offices," recommends being lenient toward those who haven’t committed terrible acts of violence in war, and he believes that wars fought to uphold national honor should be carried out with moderation. In one of his letters, referring to the conflict between Pompey and Caesar, he describes the struggle between these two notable figures as shrouded in so much uncertainty about motives and reasons that many people were confused about which side to support. In his speech for Marcellus, he also points out that this kind of uncertainty might lead to mistakes, but it can never be considered guilty.
VII. Such forbearance in war is not only a tribute to justice, it is a tribute to humanity, it is a tribute to moderation, it is a tribute to greatness of soul. It was in this moderation, says Sallust, the foundation of Roman greatness was laid. Tacitus describes his countrymen as a people no less remarkable for their courage in the field, than for their humanity to the vanquished and suppliant.
VII. Such restraint in war is not just a mark of justice; it's a mark of humanity, of moderation, and of greatness of spirit. According to Sallust, it was this moderation that formed the foundation of Roman greatness. Tacitus describes his fellow countrymen as a people notable not only for their bravery in battle but also for their compassion toward the defeated and those seeking mercy.
On this subject, there is a brilliant passage in the fourth book to Herennius, where it is said, "It was an admirable resolution of our ancestors, never to deprive a captive prince of his life. For it would be truly a violation of common justice to abuse, by wanton cruelty and rigour, the power over those, whom fortune has put into our hands, by reducing them from the high condition, in which she had placed them before; their former enmity is forgotten. Because it is the characteristic of bravery to esteem opponents as enemies, while contending for victory, and to treat them as men, when conquered, in order to soften the calamities of war, and improve the terms and relations of peace. But it may be asked, if the enemy now treated with this indulgence would have shewn the same lenity himself. To which a reply may be made, that he is not an object of imitation in what he WOULD have done, so much as in what he OUGHT to have done."
On this topic, there’s a great passage in the fourth book to Herennius, where it says, "It was an admirable decision by our ancestors to never take the life of a captured prince. It would truly be a violation of basic justice to abuse, with senseless cruelty and harshness, the power over those whom fortune has put in our hands, reducing them from the high status she had assigned them before; their previous enmity is forgotten. It's a mark of bravery to regard opponents as enemies while fighting for victory, and to treat them as people when they’ve been conquered, in order to ease the burdens of war and improve the terms and relationships of peace. However, one might ask if the enemy, now treated with this kindness, would have shown the same leniency himself. To which it can be replied that he is not a model for what he WOULD have done, but rather for what he SHOULD to have done."
VIII. Though there may be circumstances, in which absolute justice will not condemn the sacrifice of lives in war, yet humanity will require that the greatest precaution should be used against involving the innocent in danger, except in cases of extreme urgency and utility.
VIII. While there may be situations where absolute justice doesn't condemn the loss of lives in war, humanity demands that the utmost precautions be taken to avoid putting innocent people in danger, except in cases of extreme necessity and benefit.
IX. After establishing these general principles, it will not be difficult to decide upon particular cases. Seneca says, that "in the calamities of war children are exempted and spared, on the score of their age, and women from respect to their sex." In the wars of the Hebrews, even after the offers of peace have been rejected, God commands the women and children to be spared.
IX. After laying out these general principles, it won't be hard to make decisions about specific cases. Seneca mentions that "in the disasters of war, children are protected because of their age, and women are spared out of respect for their gender." In the conflicts of the Hebrews, even after peace offers have been turned down, God instructs that women and children should be saved.
Thus when the Ninevites were threatened with utter362 destruction, on account of their grievous crimes, a mitigation of the sentence was allowed, in compassion to the many thousands, who were of an age incapable of making a distinction between right and wrong.
Thus when the people of Nineveh were warned of complete362 destruction because of their serious wrongdoings, a reduction of the punishment was granted, out of compassion for the many thousands who were too young to understand the difference between right and wrong.
If God, from whose supreme gift the life of man proceeds, and on whose supreme disposal it depends, prescribes to himself a rule like this, it is surely incumbent upon men, who have no commission, but for the welfare and preservation of the lives of men, to act by the same rule. Thus age and sex are equally spared, except where the latter have departed from this privilege by taking arms, or performing the part of men.
If God, from whom all human life comes and who ultimately controls it, sets rules for Himself like this, then it’s clearly important for humans, who have no authority except to promote and protect human lives, to follow the same rules. Therefore, both age and gender are treated equally, unless the latter choose to give up this privilege by taking up arms or acting like men.
X. The same rule may be laid down too with respect to males, whose modes of life are entirely remote from the use of arms. And in the first class of this description may be placed the ministers of religion, who, among all nations, from times of the most remote antiquity have been exempted from bearing arms.—Thus, as may be seen in sacred history, the Philistines, being enemies of the Jews, forbore doing harm to the company of prophets, that was at Gaba: and David fled with Samuel to another place, which the presence of a prophetic company protected from all molestation and injury.
X. The same rule applies to men whose lifestyles have nothing to do with using weapons. The first group in this category includes religious leaders, who, across all nations and throughout history, have been excused from bearing arms. For example, in sacred history, the Philistines, who were enemies of the Jews, made sure not to harm the group of prophets at Gaba; and David escaped with Samuel to another location, which was safeguarded from any disturbance or harm by the presence of a prophetic group.
Plutarch relates of the Cretans, that when all order among them was entirely broken by their civil broils, they abstained from offering violence to any member of the priesthood, or to those employed in the sacred rites belonging to the dead. From hence the Greeks came to denote a GENERAL MASSACRE by the proverbial expression of NO ONE BEING LEFT TO CARRY FIRE TO THE ALTAR.
Plutarch tells us that the Cretans, when their social order completely fell apart due to civil wars, refrained from harming anyone in the priesthood or those involved in the sacred rituals for the dead. This is why the Greeks came to use the saying Mass Killing to mean NO ONE LEFT TO CARRY FIRE TO THE ALTAR.
Equally privileged with the holy priesthood are those, who devote their lives to the pursuit of letters, and other studies beneficial to mankind.
Equally privileged with the holy priesthood are those who dedicate their lives to the pursuit of knowledge and other studies that benefit humanity.
XI. Diodorus bestows an encomium upon the Indians, who, in all their wars with each other, forbore destroying or even hurting those employed in husbandry, as being the common benefactors of all. Plutarch relates the same of the ancient Corinthians and Megarensians, and Cyrus sent a message to the king of Assyria to inform him that he was willing to avoid molesting all who were employed in tilling the ground.
XI. Diodorus praises the Indians, who, in all their wars with each other, refrained from destroying or even harming those who worked in agriculture, seeing them as the common providers for everyone. Plutarch tells a similar story about the ancient Corinthians and Megarensians, and Cyrus sent a message to the king of Assyria to let him know that he was ready to avoid bothering anyone who was involved in farming.
XII. To the above catalogue of those exempted from sharing in the calamities of war, may be added merchants, not only those residing for a time in the enemy's country, but even his natural-born, and regular subjects: artisans363 too, and all others are included; whose subsistence depends upon cultivating the arts of peace.
XII. In addition to the list of those who are exempt from the hardships of war, we can include merchants, not just those temporarily living in enemy territory, but also those who are natural-born citizens and regular subjects of the enemy. Artisans363 and everyone else whose livelihood relies on peaceful pursuits are included as well.
XIII. and XIV. More civilized manners having abolished the barbarous practice of putting prisoners to death, for the same reason, the surrender of those, who stipulate for the preservation of their lives either in battle, or in a siege, is not to be rejected.
XIII. and XIV. More civilized behaviors have put an end to the brutal practice of executing prisoners. For the same reason, we shouldn’t reject the surrender of those who ask for their lives to be spared, whether in battle or during a siege.
The Romans, when investing towns, always accepted offers of capitulation, if made before the battering ram had touched the walls. Caesar gave notice to the Atuatici, that he would save their city, if they surrendered, before the battering ram was brought up. And in modern times it is the usual practice, before shells are thrown, or mines sprung, to summon places to surrender, which are thought unable to hold out—and where places are stronger, such summons is generally sent, before the storming is made.
The Romans, when attacking towns, always accepted offers to surrender if they were made before the battering ram hit the walls. Caesar informed the Atuatici that he would spare their city if they surrendered before the battering ram was deployed. Nowadays, it’s common practice to demand surrender from places deemed unable to withstand an attack before bombs are dropped or explosives are triggered—and when places are better fortified, such demands are usually made before the assault occurs.
XV. and XVI. Against these principles of natural law and equity an objection is sometimes derived from the necessity of retaliation, or striking terror, in cases of obstinate resistance. But such an objection is by no means just. For after a place has surrendered, and there is no danger to be apprehended from the prisoners, there is nothing to justify the further effusion of blood.—Such rigour was sometimes practised, where there were any enormous acts of injustice, or any violation of faith; it was practised also upon deserters, if taken.
XV. and XVI. Sometimes, an objection is raised against these principles of natural law and fairness based on the need for retaliation or instilling fear in cases of stubborn resistance. However, this objection is not justified at all. Once a place has surrendered and there’s no threat from the prisoners, there’s no reason to continue the shedding of blood. Such harshness was occasionally applied in response to serious injustices or breaches of trust; it was also enforced on deserters if they were captured.
Sometimes, where very important advantages may attend striking a terror, by preventing the same crimes in future from being committed, it may be proper to exercise the right of rigour in its full extent. But an obstinate resistance, which can be considered as nothing but the faithful discharge of a trust, can never come within the description of such delinquencies, as justify extreme rigour.
Sometimes, when there are significant benefits to instilling fear by stopping the same crimes from happening again, it might be appropriate to fully exercise strict measures. However, stubborn resistance, which can only be seen as faithfully fulfilling a responsibility, should never be categorized as offenses that warrant harsh punishment.
XVII. Where delinquencies indeed are such as deserve death, but the number of offenders is very great, it is usual, from motives of mercy, to depart in some degree from the right of enforcing the whole power of the law: the authority for so doing is founded on the example of God himself, who commanded such offers of peace to be made to the Canaanites, and their neighbours, the most wicked of any people upon the face of the earth, as might spare their lives upon the condition of their becoming tributaries.
XVII. When crimes are serious enough to warrant death but the number of offenders is very high, it’s common, out of compassion, to ease up on fully enforcing the law. The reasoning behind this is based on God's own example, who instructed that offers of peace be made to the Canaanites and their neighbors, the most wicked people on earth, allowing them to live if they agreed to pay tribute.
364 XVIII. From the opinions advanced and maintained above, it will not be difficult to gather the principles of the law of nature respecting hostages.
364 XVIII. From the opinions presented and supported above, it won’t be hard to understand the principles of natural law regarding hostages.
At the time, when it was a general opinion that every one had the same right over his life, as over his property, and that right, either by express or implied consent was transferred from individuals to the state, it is not surprising that we should read of hostages, though harmless and innocent as individuals, being punished for the offences of the state: and, in this case, the consent of the state to such a regulation implies that of individuals, who have originally resigned their own will to that of the public; in whom, after such resignation, it indubitably vested.
At that time, when it was widely believed that everyone had the same rights over their life as they did over their property, and that those rights, whether through explicit or implied consent, were handed over from individuals to the state, it’s not surprising to read about hostages, even if they are harmless and innocent, being punished for the state’s offenses. In this situation, the state’s agreement to such a rule suggests that individuals have also consented, since they initially surrendered their own will to the public, which has undoubtedly taken over those rights.
But when the day-spring rose upon the world, men, obtaining clearer views of the extent of their power, found that God, in giving man dominion over the whole earth, reserved to himself the supreme disposal of his life, so that man cannot resign to any one the right over his own life or that of another.
But when dawn broke over the world, people, gaining a clearer understanding of the limits of their power, discovered that God, in granting humanity control over the entire earth, kept for Himself the ultimate authority over human life. This means that no one can hand over the right to their own life or that of another person.
XIX. By way of conclusion to this subject it may be observed, that all actions no way conducive to obtain a contested right, or to bring the war to a termination, but calculated merely to display the strength of either side are totally repugnant to the duties of a Christian and to the principles of humanity. So that it behoves Christian princes to prohibit all unnecessary effusion of blood, as they must render an account of their sovereign commission to him, by whose authority, and in whose stead, they bear the sword.
XIX. In conclusion to this topic, it should be noted that any actions that do not help in securing a disputed right or end the war, but are only aimed at showcasing the strength of either side, go against the responsibilities of a Christian and the principles of humanity. Therefore, it is the duty of Christian rulers to prevent any unnecessary shedding of blood, as they will have to answer to the authority that they represent and in whose name they wield power.
CHAPTER XII.
On Moderation in Spoiling an Enemy's Territory.
Lawfulness of despoiling an enemy's country—Forbearance of using this right, where things may be useful to ourselves, and out of an enemy's power—Forbearance in the hopes of speedy conquest, or where things are not immediately necessary to support an enemy, and aid him in maintaining the war—Buildings for the purposes of religion not to be wantonly destroyed—Advantages of this moderation.
The legality of taking from an enemy's country—Deciding not to use this right when it could be advantageous for us and is beyond the enemy's control—Opting not to act in hopes of a swift victory, or when resources aren't urgently needed to support an enemy and sustain their war efforts—Religious structures should not be recklessly destroyed—The advantages of this restraint.
I. One of the three following cases is requisite to justify any one in destroying what BELONGS to another: there must be either such a necessity, as at the original institution of property might be supposed to form an exception, as if for instance any one should throw the sword of another into a river, to prevent a madman from using it to his destruction: still according to the true principles maintained in a former part of this work he will be bound to repair the loss:67 or there must be some debt, arising from the non-performance of an engagement, where the waste committed is considered as a satisfaction for that debt: or there must have been some aggressions, for which such destruction is only an adequate punishment.
I. One of the three following situations is necessary to justify anyone in destroying what BELONGS to someone else: there must be either a necessity that could be seen as an exception at the original establishment of property, like if someone threw another person's sword into a river to stop a madman from using it to cause harm; however, according to the true principles discussed earlier in this work, they would still need to compensate for the loss:__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__. Alternatively, there may be a debt from not fulfilling an obligation, where the destruction is seen as satisfaction for that debt; or there may have been some form of aggression, for which this destruction serves as a suitable punishment.
Now, driving off some of our cattle, or burning a few of our houses, can never be pleaded as a sufficient and justifiable motive for laying waste the whole of an enemy's kingdom. Polybius saw this in its proper light, observing, that vengeance in war should not be carried to its extreme, nor extend any further than was necessary to make an aggressor atone justly for his offence. And it is upon these motives, and within these limits alone, that punishment can be inflicted. But except where prompted to it by motives of great utility, it is folly, and worse than folly, wantonly to hurt another.
Now, driving off some of our cattle or burning a few of our houses can never be considered a sufficient and justifiable reason for destroying an entire enemy's kingdom. Polybius recognized this clearly, noting that revenge in war shouldn't go to extremes or extend beyond what’s necessary to make the aggressor pay fairly for their wrongdoing. Punishment can only be imposed based on these reasons and within these limits. However, unless driven by significant practical reasons, it's foolish, and even worse than foolish, to harm others without cause.
But upon duly and impartially weighing the matter, such acts are oftener regarded in an odious light, than considered as the dictates of prudent and necessary366 counsels. For the most urgent and justifiable motives are seldom of long continuance, and are often succeeded by weightier motives of a more humane description.
But after carefully and fairly considering the situation, such actions are more often seen negatively than viewed as wise and necessary advice. The most pressing and reasonable motives usually don't last long and are often followed by stronger, more compassionate motives.
II. It may be possible, under some circumstances, to detain what belongs to an enemy so as to prevent his deriving advantage from it, in which case it would be an unnecessary and wanton act to destroy it. And to such circumstances the divine law has an eye, in ordering wild trees to be made use of for the construction of works in a siege, while fruit-trees, and every thing necessary for the support of man, ought, if possible, to be spared.
II. Under certain circumstances, it might be possible to keep what belongs to an enemy to stop them from benefiting from it, and in that case, it would be unnecessary and reckless to destroy it. The divine law takes these situations into account, allowing for wild trees to be used in building siege works, while fruit trees and anything needed for human survival should, if possible, be preserved.
III. Where there is an expectation also of speedy victory and conquest, prudence will dictate to a general or commander of any kind the necessity of forbearing from all acts of destruction, by authorising and committing which he would only be injuring those possessions, that are likely to come into the hands of his own state or sovereign. Thus, as we are informed by Plutarch, when Philip had overrun Thessaly, destroying and plundering the whole country, Flaminius ordered his troops to march in a regular manner, as through a ceded country which had become their own.
III. When there’s an expectation of quick victory and conquest, common sense will tell a general or any kind of leader that it’s necessary to avoid all acts of destruction. By allowing or doing so, they would only harm the possessions that are likely to belong to their own state or leader. For example, as Plutarch tells us, when Philip invaded Thessaly, destroying and looting the entire region, Flaminius ordered his troops to march in an orderly fashion, as if through a territory that had become their own.
IV. In the next place, it is unnecessary to destroy an enemy's country, when he has other sources, from which he can draw his supplies, as for instance, the sea or any adjoining territory. Archidamus, in Thucydides, attempting to dissuade the Lacedaemonians from a war with the Athenians, asks them, what object they propose to themselves by such a war? he asks them if they suppose that Attica can easily be laid waste owing to the advantage, which their troops have in superiority and numbers? but, says he, they have other dominions to furnish them with supplies, and they can avail themselves also of maritime importations. So that under such circumstances, it is best to leave agriculture unmolested, even on the frontiers of each side: a practice lately followed in the wars of the low countries, where contributions were paid to both parties, in return for such protection.
IV. Next, it’s unnecessary to devastate an enemy’s land when they have other resources for supplies, like the sea or nearby territories. Archidamus, in Thucydides, tries to convince the Lacedaemonians not to go to war with the Athenians. He asks them what they hope to gain from such a war. He questions whether they really think they can easily ruin Attica just because their forces are bigger and stronger. He points out that the Athenians have other territories to provide them with supplies, and they can also rely on imports from the sea. So, under these conditions, it’s better to leave agriculture alone, even on the borders of both sides: a strategy recently used in the wars in the Low Countries, where both sides paid contributions for such protection.
V. There are some things of such a nature, as to contribute, no way, to the support and prolongation of war: things which reason itself requires to be spared even during the heat and continuance of war. Polybius calls it367 brutal rage and madness to destroy things, the destruction of which does not in the least tend to impair an enemy's strength, nor to increase that of the destroyer: Such are Porticos, Temples, statues, and all other elegant works and monuments of art. Cicero commends Marcellus for sparing the public and private edifices of Syracuse, as if he had come with his army to protect THEM, rather than to take the place by storm.
V. There are some things that, in no way, contribute to the support and prolongation of war: things that reason itself suggests should be spared even during the intensity and duration of conflict. Polybius calls it367 brutal rage and madness to destroy things that don't actually weaken an enemy's strength or boost that of the destroyer: things like porticoes, temples, statues, and all other beautiful works and monuments of art. Cicero praises Marcellus for protecting the public and private buildings of Syracuse, as if he had come with his army to safeguard Them, rather than to capture the city by force.
VI. As this rule of moderation is observed towards other ornamental works of art, for the reasons before stated, there is still greater reason, why it should be obeyed in respect to things devoted to the purposes of religion. For although such things, or edifices, being the property of the state may, according to the law of nations, be with impunity demolished, yet as they contribute nothing to aggravate the calamities, or retard the successes of war, it is a mark of reverence to divine things to spare them, and all that is connected therewith: and more especially should this rule be adhered to among nations, worshipping the same God according to the same fundamental laws, although differing from each other by slight shades of variation in their rights and opinions. Thucydides says that it was a law among the Greeks of his time, in all their invasions of each other's territories, to forbear touching the edifices of religion: and Livy likewise observes that, upon the destruction of Alba by the Romans, the temples of the Gods were spared.
VI. Just as this rule of moderation applies to other forms of decorative art for the reasons mentioned earlier, there’s even more reason to follow it when it comes to things associated with religion. Although such items or buildings, being state property, can be destroyed without penalty according to international law, they don’t worsen the suffering or hinder the success of war. It shows respect for the divine to protect them and everything related to them. This principle should be especially upheld among nations that worship the same God based on the same fundamental laws, even if they have slight differences in their rights and beliefs. Thucydides notes that it was a law among the Greeks in his time not to harm religious buildings during their invasions of each other’s lands. Livy also mentions that when the Romans destroyed Alba, they spared the temples of the gods.
VII. What has been said of the sacred edifices of religion applies also to monuments raised in honour of the dead, unnecessarily to disturb whose ashes in their repose bespeaks a total disregard to the laws and ties of our common humanity.
VII. What has been said about the sacred buildings of religion applies to monuments built to honor the dead as well. Unnecessarily disturbing their ashes shows a complete disregard for the laws and bonds of our shared humanity.
VIII. Although it does not fall within the province of this treatise to inquire into the utility of war in all its various branches, but only to regulate its practices by confining them within due and lawful bounds; yet it will not be improper to observe that rules and practices derive much of their merit from the utility, with which they are attended. So that one great quality, to recommend the moderation above alluded to, will be found in its preventing the enemy from being driven to those resources, which men never fail, at last, of finding in despair. It is a just remark made by some Theologians, that all Christian princes and rulers, who wish to be368 found SUCH in the sight of God as well as that of men, will deem it a duty to interpose their authority to prevent or to suppress all UNNECESSARY violence in the taking of towns: for acts of rigour can never be carried to an extreme without involving great numbers of the innocent in ruin. And practices of that kind, besides being no way conducive to the termination of war, are totally repugnant to every principle of Christianity and justice.
VIII. While this treatise won’t delve into the usefulness of war in all its forms, but rather aims to regulate its practices within proper and lawful limits, it’s worth noting that rules and practices gain much of their value from their practicality. One significant aspect that supports the mentioned moderation is its ability to prevent the enemy from resorting to those resources that people inevitably find in moments of despair. It is a valid point made by some theologians that all Christian leaders and rulers who wish to be 368 regarded as LIKE THIS in the eyes of both God and men, should see it as their duty to use their authority to prevent or suppress all UNNECESSARY violence when capturing towns. Acts of cruelty can never reach an extreme without causing great harm to many innocent lives. Moreover, such practices not only fail to contribute to the resolution of conflict but also contradict every principle of Christianity and justice.
CHAPTER XIII.
On Moderation in Taking Captures During War.
Effects belonging to the subjects of an enemy, and taken detained as a pledge or debt—Not to be taken by way of punishment for another's offence—The debt or obligation, arising from a state of war, illustrated by examples—Forbearance in the exercise of such a right from principles of humanity.
Items owned by an enemy that are taken or held as collateral or debt—Not to be used as punishment for someone else's wrongdoing—The debt or obligation that comes from being at war, explained with examples—Caution in using this right based on humane principles.
I. The capture of an enemy's goods, even in JUST WAR, is not, in ALL CASES, perfectly justifiable, nor is the captor always exempt from the ties of restitution. For strictly speaking, according to the rules of pure justice, it is not lawful to seize or detain goods except to the exact amount of the debt which the enemy has incurred. Indeed goods may be detained beyond that, as a necessary pledge of security, but still upon the condition of being restored, as soon as the danger has ceased: RESTORED EITHER LITERALLY, OR BY SOME PROPER COMPENSATION BEING MADE.
I. Taking an enemy's goods, even in Just War, is not always completely justified, nor is the person taking them always free from the obligation to return them. Strictly speaking, according to pure justice, it's not right to seize or hold onto goods except for the exact amount of the debt that the enemy owes. In fact, goods can be held beyond that as a necessary guarantee for safety, but they must still be returned as soon as the threat is over: RESTORED EITHER LITERALLY OR THROUGH SOME FORM OF FAIR COMPENSATION BEING PROVIDED.
Here then is a right of capture, which confers no right of property or acquisition. But when any thing may become due to us, either from a penalty or the non-performance of an engagement, in both cases a right to an enemy's goods, if they can be taken, is acquired. By the latter kind of debt not only the effects of the debtor himself, but those, belonging to his subjects, may according to the principles introduced by the law of nations be taken as a security.
Here is a right of capture that doesn’t grant any property or ownership rights. However, when something is owed to us, either from a penalty or from not fulfilling an obligation, we gain the right to seize an enemy's goods if we can. In the case of this type of debt, not just the debtor's assets but also those belonging to their subjects can, according to international law principles, be seized as security.
This right of the law of nations is very different from that established in impunity alone, or depending upon the external force of judicial authority. For as by our private consent the person with whom we contract acquires not only an external and legal right over our property, but an internal right, proceeding from conscience, so he acquires the same right by a kind of common consent, which virtually comprehends the consent of individuals, in which sense the law is called the common compact or covenant of the state.
This principle of international law is very different from one based solely on impunity or the external power of judicial authority. Just as through our private agreement the person we contract with gains not only an external and legal right over our property but also an internal right based on conscience, they gain a similar right through a kind of collective agreement that essentially includes the consent of individuals. In this sense, the law is referred to as the common compact or covenant of the state.
And in transactions of this kind it is most likely that nations approving of such a rule, introduced a law, which370 might not only prevent greater evils, but also enable every one to attain his own right.
And in transactions like this, it's very likely that nations agreeing with such a rule established a law that370 could not only stop bigger problems but also help everyone get their rights.
II. But in the other kind of debt arising from penalty, or punishment, it does not appear, that nations consented to the establishment of any such right over the effects of subjects. For binding the property of one man for the offence of another is a kind of odious act, and therefore ought not to be extended farther than the law appears to have actually decreed. Nor is the advantage derived from the latter, by any means equal to that attending the former kind of debt. For what is due to us from damage, or the non-performance of a treaty may be considered as a part of our effects, but it is not so with the obligation to punishment, which is purely of a personal nature, therefore no loss is incurred by relinquishing this right.
II. However, in the case of debt that comes from penalties or punishment, it doesn't seem that nations agreed to any rights over the property of individuals. Holding one person's property accountable for the wrongdoing of another is a pretty terrible idea, and it shouldn't be applied any more broadly than the law actually allows. Plus, the benefits we get from this type of situation are definitely not on par with the benefits from the first type of debt. What we're owed for damages or for not fulfilling a treaty can be seen as part of our property, but that's not the case with the obligation to punish, which is purely personal; therefore, there's no real loss if we give up this right.
Nor is the argument in the least weakened by what was said before68 respecting the Athenian law. For there it was maintained that subjects were not bound to suffer, because the state was amenable to punishment, but in order to compel the state to do what she ought to do, in bringing the guilty to punishment: a debt arising from duty, and relating to obligations of the former kind, rather than to those of the latter. For there is a difference between being obliged to punish another and being one's self amenable to punishment: tho' the latter may frequently arise from the neglect of doing the former, but still there is the same distinction between them, as between cause and effect.
The argument isn’t weakened at all by what was said before__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ about Athenian law. It was argued there that individuals aren’t required to endure suffering just because the state can be punished, but to push the state to do the right thing by holding the guilty accountable: a responsibility based on duty, connected to the first kind of obligations, rather than the last. There’s a difference between having to punish someone else and being punishable oneself; although the latter often comes from failing to do the former, the distinction is still clear, just like the difference between cause and effect.
The goods of subjects can only be taken by way of reprisal in return for other goods taken by the enemy; but they can never be taken as a punishment for the neglect of bringing offenders to justice. The delinquents themselves, in the number of whom may be reckoned those, who have neglected to discharge their duty in this respect, must answer for such offences.
The property of individuals can only be seized as retaliation for goods taken by the enemy; however, it can never be taken as a punishment for failing to bring wrongdoers to justice. The wrongdoers themselves, including those who have failed to fulfill their responsibilities in this matter, must be held accountable for such offenses.
III. The goods of subjects may be taken, and a property acquired therein, not only in order to obtain payment of the ORIGINAL debt, which occasioned the war, but of OTHER debts also, to which the same war may have given birth. And in this sense the words of those are to be taken, who maintain, that captures in war are not a perfect compensation for the principal debt, but only used as a means to enforce satisfaction for the371 damages sustained from aggressions. Thus the Romans, in their dispute with Antiochus, as related by Livy, thought it but right for that king to make reparation for all the expenses incurred in the war, which he had occasioned. Indeed any terms, that may be justly imposed upon the conquered may justly be enforced by war.
III. The property of individuals can be seized, and ownership established over it, not just to settle the original debt that caused the war, but also for other debts that may have arisen from the same conflict. In this context, the statements of those who argue that wartime captures do not fully compensate for the main debt, but are only a way to secure payment for the damages caused by aggression, should be understood. For example, during their dispute with Antiochus, as mentioned by Livy, the Romans believed it was fair for that king to compensate for all the costs incurred during the war he started. In fact, any terms that can be justly imposed on the defeated can be rightfully enforced through war.
IV. The right of seizing the goods of the innocent subject of an enemy seems to have been introduced, in order to compel the original aggressor, or debtor to grant redress for the injury he had done: and although his falling on the innocent may be no way repugnant to what is legally right, it is in some measure a departure from the principles of humanity. On the other hand, history, especially the Roman history, abounds in examples of humanity, where lands have been restored to a conquered enemy, upon condition of their belonging to the STATE, and becoming subject to the payment of a tribute.
IV. The right to seize the goods of an innocent enemy seems to have been established to pressure the original aggressor or debtor to provide compensation for the harm they caused. While targeting the innocent may not conflict with legal standards, it does somewhat stray from principles of humanity. On the flip side, history, particularly Roman history, is full of examples of compassion, where land has been returned to a conquered enemy, with the condition that it belongs to the STATE and is subject to the payment of tribute.
CHAPTER XV.69
On Moderation in Gaining Power.
How far internal justice permits us to acquire dominion—Moderation, in the use of this right over the conquered, laudable—Incorporating them with the conquerors—Allowing them to retain their dominions—Placing garrisons therein—Imposing tributes or other burdens—Utility of such moderation—Change in the form of a conquered government—The conquered permitted to retain some part of their former liberties—Especially in matters of religion—Clemency to be shewn.
How much internal justice lets us assert control—Being reasonable in our use of this right over the conquered is admirable—Integrating them with the conquerors—Allowing them to retain their lands—Stationing troops there—Imposing taxes or other duties—The advantages of such moderation—Adjustments in the structure of a conquered government—The conquered allowed to maintain some of their former freedoms—Especially concerning religion—We should show kindness.
I. That equity and moderation towards individuals, which are so highly extolled, are still more deserving of admiration, when exercised towards nations and kingdoms; where injustice would be attended with more signal calamities, and moderation with more beneficial effects.
I. The fairness and moderation shown towards individuals, which are so highly praised, are even more worthy of admiration when applied to nations and kingdoms; where injustice can lead to greater disasters, and moderation brings about more positive outcomes.
In just war the right of dominion over a people, and the sovereign power, which that people possess, may be acquired as well as any other right. But the claims to such a right ought by no means to be prosecuted beyond indemnity for aggression, and security against future evils.
In a just war, the right to govern a people and the authority that people hold can be obtained just like any other right. However, claims to such a right should not go beyond compensation for harm done and protection against future threats.
But this motive, so necessary to be observed, especially in all treaties of peace, as well as in the use of victory, is often confounded with others. In other points a sovereign prince or state may relinquish a claim from a principle of moderation, but where the future security of their subjects is concerned, it is an act of cruelty rather than of moderation to relax too far in favour of a conquered enemy.
But this reason, which is crucial to recognize, especially in all peace treaties and in the use of victory, is often mixed up with others. In other cases, a sovereign prince or state can give up a claim out of a sense of moderation, but when it comes to the future safety of their citizens, being too lenient towards a defeated enemy is more an act of cruelty than of moderation.
II. Aristotle has, more than once, said, that war is undertaken for the sake of peace, and toil endured in order to obtain rest. And in the same manner, Cicero has observed, that men go to war, that they may live in peace without molestation and injury. War too, as we are instructed by the teachers of true religion, may be made, to remove every thing that interrupts, and stands in the way of peace.
II. Aristotle has said more than once that war is fought for the sake of peace, and that we endure hardship to achieve rest. Similarly, Cicero pointed out that people go to war so they can live in peace without harassment or harm. War, as we learn from the teachings of true religion, can also be waged to eliminate everything that disrupts and obstructs peace.
373 In the primitive ages, as we find from history, wars in general were made to preserve territories rather than to extend them. And any deviation from this rule was thought unlawful: thus the prophet Amos reproves the Ammonites for their love of making conquests.
373 In ancient times, as history shows us, wars were usually fought to protect territory rather than to gain more land. Any exception to this practice was seen as wrong: for example, the prophet Amos criticizes the Ammonites for their desire to conquer.
III. The prudent moderation of the ancient Romans approaches nearly to this model of primitive innocence. For although they made conquests, they mitigated the fate of the conquered by incorporating them with themselves.
III. The careful moderation of the ancient Romans comes close to this ideal of basic innocence. Even though they pursued conquests, they eased the plight of the conquered by bringing them into their society.
IV. Another mark of moderation in the use of victory is leaving to conquered kings, or nations the dominions, which they LAWFULLY held before.
IV. Another sign of moderation in how victory is used is allowing defeated kings or nations to keep the territories that they LEGALLY held before.
Polybius highly extols the merit and wisdom of Antigonus, who, having Sparta in his power, allowed the inhabitants to retain their national polity and freedom.
Polybius really praises the value and wisdom of Antigonus, who, having control over Sparta, let the residents keep their national government and freedom.
V. Sometimes indeed a conqueror, though allowing a subjugated people to retain their dominion and sovereignty, must provide for his own security, by placing garrisons in their country.
V. Sometimes, even a conqueror, while letting a conquered people keep their power and independence, must ensure his own safety by stationing troops in their country.
VI. Contributions too are frequently imposed and levied, not so much by way of indemnity for expences incurred, as for a future security between the conqueror, and the conquered country. Upon the same principle, as was before70 observed, in explaining the nature of unequal treaties, conditions may be imposed also requiring a conquered power to deliver up a certain number of her ships and forts, and to reduce her troops to a limited number.
VI. Contributions are often demanded, not just as compensation for expenses incurred, but also for future security between the conqueror and the conquered nation. Following the same principle as was before__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ mentioned, in discussing the nature of unequal treaties, conditions may require a conquered nation to surrender a specific number of its ships and forts, and to limit the size of its military forces.
VII. But leaving to conquered powers a part or the whole of their dominions is not only sometimes an act of justice and humanity, but an act of sound policy also. Among other of Numa's institutions, his manner of celebrating the rites of Terminus, the DEITY OF BOUNDARIES, is much commended; for he prohibited the use of blood in those ceremonies, as an intimation that nothing was more conducive to the peace and harmony of the world, than for every nation to confine herself within her proper bounds.
VII. But allowing conquered nations to keep part or all of their territories is not only sometimes a matter of justice and mercy, but also a wise strategy. Among other institutions of Numa, his way of honoring the rites of End point, the Goddess of Boundaries, is highly praised; he banned the use of blood in those ceremonies as a sign that nothing fosters the peace and harmony of the world better than for each nation to stick to its own borders.
In conformity to which maxim Florus observes, that it is more easy to make conquests than to keep them. To which rule Plato, in his third book of Laws, adapts the proverbial expression of Hesiod, that HALF IS BETTER THAN THE WHOLE.
In line with this principle, Florus notes that it's easier to make conquests than to maintain them. Plato, in the third book of Laws, relates this to Hesiod's proverb that Half is better than the whole..
374 VIII. The Lacedaemonians and the Athenians anciently claimed no farther dominion over conquered cities and states, than purely wishing them to adopt forms of government like their own, the Lacedaemonians living under an aristocratic, and the Athenians under a democratic system. But whether such changes were conducive to a conqueror's security, it is not to our present purpose to examine.
374 VIII. The Spartans and the Athenians historically only wanted the cities and states they conquered to adopt governments similar to theirs—Spartans with their aristocratic system and Athenians with their democratic system. However, whether these changes actually helped ensure a conqueror's safety isn't what we're focusing on right now.
IX. If it is not perfectly safe to forbear exercising ANY dominion over a conquered enemy, the matter may be so regulated as to leave him some portion of his former sovereignty and power. Thus among the Jews the sceptre remained with the Sanhedrim, even after Archelaus was deprived of his kingdom; and Alexander in many cases allowed Darius to remain a sovereign over others, while he required of him submission to himself.
IX. If it's not completely safe to refrain from exercising ANY control over a defeated enemy, it can be arranged to let them keep some of their previous authority and power. For instance, among the Jews, the ruling authority stayed with the Sanhedrim, even after Archelaus lost his kingdom; and Alexander often permitted Darius to still be a leader over others, while demanding his loyalty to himself.
X. Even though a conquered power was deprived of all sovereignty, she might be allowed to retain some of her laws, privileges, and magistracies of inferior importance. Thus, Pliny, in his letters, informs us, that in the proconsular province of Bithynia, the city of Apamaea was allowed to regulate the form of her government at her own pleasure, and, in other places, the Bithynians were permitted to retain their own magistrates, and their own senate.
X. Even though a conquered power lost all sovereignty, it might still be allowed to keep some of its laws, privileges, and less significant offices. For example, Pliny mentions in his letters that in the proconsular province of Bithynia, the city of Apamaea was allowed to decide on the structure of its government as it wished, and in other areas, the Bithynians were allowed to keep their own magistrates and their own senate.
XI. This indulgence ought to be shewn to every people, especially in their attachment to the religion of their forefathers, of which they should never be deprived but with their own consent and conviction. An indulgence, which Agrippa in his address to Caius, as cited by Philo in the account of his embassy, approves of, as highly grateful to the conquered people, and by no means prejudicial to the conqueror. At the same time a conqueror will take care that erroneous opinions do not prevail to the prejudice and overthrow of true religion, as was done by Constantine upon his crushing the party of Licinius, and afterwards by the Franks and other kings.
XI. This tolerance should be shown to every group, especially regarding their commitment to the beliefs of their ancestors, which they should only lose with their own agreement and understanding. Agrippa, in his speech to Caius, which Philo references in his account of the embassy, supports this idea as being very appreciated by the conquered people and not harmful to the conqueror. At the same time, a conqueror will ensure that false beliefs do not take hold in a way that harms and undermines true religion, as demonstrated by Constantine when he defeated Licinius and later by the Franks and other kings.
CHAPTER XVI.
On Moderation Regarding Things Excluded from the Right of Postliminium by the Law of Nations.
Internal justice requires the restitution of things taken from others by an enemy in unjust war—Deductions made—Subjects and countries, if unjustly seized by an enemy, to be restored to their original sovereign—The time, when the obligation to restore them expires, defined—What is to be done in doubtful cases.
Internal justice requires returning things taken from others by an enemy in an unjust war—Deductions made—Subjects and territories, if unjustly taken by an enemy, should be given back to their rightful ruler—The timeframe for the obligation to return them is specified—What to do in uncertain cases.
I. How far things taken in just war become the property of the captors has been explained before. From which a deduction must be made of things recoverable by the right postliminium, those being no captures at all.
I. How far things taken in just war become the property of the captors has been explained before. From which a deduction must be made of things recoverable by the right postliminium, those being no captures at all.
But things, taken in unjust war, are to be restored, not only by those, who have taken them, but by others also into whose hands they may have by any means fallen. For, as the Roman lawyers say, no one can convey to another a greater right than he himself possesses. The original captor had no just title to any property therein, neither can the person, deriving his title through him, establish any better claim.—A SECOND or THIRD possessor may have acquired a property therein, which the law presumes he has a right to, till the contrary be shewn, and for which an action may be maintained. Yet it is a right of which he cannot honestly avail himself against the real owner, from whom it was unjustly taken.
But things taken in an unjust war should be returned, not just by those who took them, but also by anyone who may have come into possession of them through any means. As Roman lawyers say, no one can give another person a greater right than they themselves have. The original captor had no legitimate claim to any property, and neither can someone who got their title from him make a stronger claim. A 2ND or THIRD possessor may have acquired a property, and the law assumes he has a right to it until proven otherwise, for which a legal action can be pursued. However, it's a right that he cannot ethically use against the true owner from whom it was wrongfully taken.
II. and III. Therefore such things are to be restored to those, from whom they were taken, which we find in ancient times was often done. Livy in relating the defeat of the Volscians and Aequi by a Roman Consul, says that the booty was exposed in a public place, for the space of three days, that every one, coming to recognise what belonged to him, might take it away.71
II. and III. Therefore, things should be returned to those from whom they were taken, as was often the case in ancient times. Livy, while recounting the defeat of the Volscians and Aequi by a Roman Consul, mentions that the spoils were displayed in a public area for three days, so that anyone could come and identify their belongings and take them away. away.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
376 But if any one has become possessed of such a thing by purchase, it may be asked, if he can charge the person from whom it was originally taken, with the price which he has paid for it? According to the principles before72 laid down, he certainly may charge as much to the person losing it, as the repossession of a thing, which he despaired of ever recovering, is worth.
376 But if someone has acquired such an item through purchase, one might wonder if they can hold the original owner responsible for the price they paid for it. Based on the principles before __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ established, they can definitely charge the person who lost it for the value of getting back something they thought they would never see again.
The history of Abraham seems applicable to this subject, when he returned from his victory over the five kings. Being a man of noble and exalted piety, he would appropriate nothing to himself, but considering the things retaken, as his own right, in recompence for his labour and danger, he devoted a tenth part to God, after deducting the necessary expences, and divided a certain portion among his companions.
The story of Abraham relates to this topic when he came back from defeating the five kings. As a man of great faith and integrity, he didn't take anything for himself. Instead, viewing the recovered items as rightfully his due to his hard work and the risks he took, he dedicated a tenth of it to God after covering his expenses and shared a portion with his friends.
IV. As THINGS are to be restored to their original owners, so SUBJECTS are to be restored to their former lawful sovereigns.
IV. Just as STUFF are meant to be returned to their original owners, Topics are to be returned to their previous rightful rulers.
V. The period also, when the obligation to restitution expires, is often a subject of inquiry. But this is a question, when arising between subjects of the same kingdom, which must be settled by the municipal laws of that country: but when the contending parties are the subjects of foreign powers, the matter can only be decided upon a conjecture of the time sufficient to constitute a presumed dereliction of property.
V. The timeframe when the obligation to return something ends is often a topic of discussion. However, this is a question that must be resolved by the local laws of the country when it involves individuals from the same nation. But when the parties involved are from different countries, the issue can only be determined based on an estimate of the time that would indicate a presumed abandonment of property.
VI. But where the right of war is doubtful, it will be safest to follow the conduct of Aratus of Sicyon, in advising the new possessors in some measure to prefer taking a sum money in lieu of the possession, and recommending the same maxim to the original owners, to prefer a sum of money, if they could obtain it, equivalent to the recovery of their right.
VI. But when the right to go to war is unclear, it's best to follow the example of Aratus of Sicyon, who advised new owners to consider taking a lump sum of money instead of the property itself. He also recommended that the original owners should prefer a cash settlement, if they could get one, that was equal to reclaiming their rights.
CHAPTER XVII.
Respecting Those Who Stay Neutral in War.
Nothing to be taken belonging to neutrals, but under circumstances of extreme necessity, and with an intention to pay the full price of it—Conduct of neutral powers towards belligerents.
Nothing owned by neutral parties should be seized, except in cases of dire necessity, and only if there is an intention to compensate them fully—Conduct of neutral powers towards belligerents.
I. It may appear superfluous to speak of neutral powers, against whom no rights of war can exist. But as war, under the plea of necessity, occasions many aggressions to be committed against them, especially when bordering upon the seat of its operations, it may be necessary briefly to repeat a former assertion, that nothing short of extreme exigency can give one power a right over what belongs to another no way involved in the war. The case too is equally clear that no emergency can justify any one in taking and applying to his own use what the owner stands in equal need of himself. But even where the emergency can be plainly proved, nothing can justify us in taking or applying the property of another to our use, beyond the IMMEDIATE DEMANDS OF THAT emergency. Where the CUSTODY of a thing, by securing it, is sufficient for the purpose, the USE and CONSUMPTION of it is absolutely unlawful. If the USE of it is necessary, it must not be ABUSED: and if the entire ABUSE of it be requisite, the full value should be paid.
I. It might seem unnecessary to talk about neutral nations, against whom no war rights exist. However, since war often leads to many aggressions against them, especially when they are near the conflict zone, it’s important to reiterate a previous point that nothing less than an extreme emergency can give one nation the right to take what belongs to another nation that isn't involved in the war. It's also clear that no situation can justify someone taking and using what the owner equally needs. Even when an emergency is clearly demonstrated, nothing justifies taking or using another's property beyond what is absolutely necessary for that emergency. When securing an item is enough for the purpose, its use and consumption are completely unlawful. If using it is essential, it must not be abused; and if total abuse of it is unavoidable, then the full value should be compensated.
II. Again, according to what was said in a preceding part of this book, it is the duty of those, who profess neutrality in a war to do nothing towards increasing the strength of a party maintaining an unjust cause, nor to impede the measures of a power engaged in a just and righteous cause. But in doubtful cases, they ought to shew themselves impartial to both sides, and to give no succour to besieged places, but should allow the troops of each to march through the country, and to purchase forage, and other supplies. The Corcyraeans, in Thucydides,378 say that if the Athenians intend to remain neuter, they ought either to prohibit the Corinthians from enlisting men in the territory of Attica, or to give THEM the same privilege. The Romans objected to the conduct of Philip king of Macedon, charging him with a double violation of treaties, both by injuring the allies of the Roman people, and assisting the enemy with supplies of men and money.
II. As mentioned earlier in this book, those who claim neutrality in a war should not do anything to strengthen a party that is fighting an unjust cause or to obstruct the efforts of a power engaged in a just and right cause. In uncertain situations, they should remain impartial to both sides and not provide support to besieged locations. Instead, they should allow the troops from both sides to pass through their territory and to buy forage and other supplies. The Corcyraeans, in Thucydides,378 suggested that if the Athenians truly want to stay neutral, they should either stop the Corinthians from recruiting in Attica or give THEM the same right. The Romans criticized King Philip of Macedon for violating treaties in two ways: by harming the allies of Rome and by aiding the enemy with troops and money.
CHAPTER XIX.73
In Good Faith With Rivals.
Good faith due to enemies of every description—Due even to pirates, and others of the same kind, in all treaties with them—A promise given to them, binding, when not extorted by fear—Oaths to be inviolably observed—The law of nations does not allow fear to be alleged as an exception to the above rules—Good faith to be observed even to a treacherous enemy—This obligation ceases, where one of the parties violates his engagements—Or refuses a just compensation—Even where the obligation arose from a different contract—From loss occasioned—Or from a penalty—Application of these principles to war.
Good faith should be shown to all enemies—even to pirates and similar groups, in all dealings with them. A promise made to them is binding when it isn't made under duress. Oaths must be honored without exception. International law prohibits using fear as an excuse to break these rules. Good faith must be maintained even towards a deceitful enemy. This obligation ends when one party fails to uphold their commitments or refuses fair compensation, even if the obligation arises from a different agreement, from losses suffered, or from a penalty. These principles apply in warfare.
I. It was before said that the number and extent of actions, lawful in war, may be considered either upon their own intrinsic merits, or as rising out of some antecedent engagement. The former point having before been fully explained, this is the proper place for discussing the latter, which comprehends the good faith of enemies towards each other.
I. It was previously mentioned that the number and extent of actions that are permitted in war can be looked at either based on their own inherent value or as stemming from some prior agreement. Since the first point has been thoroughly discussed, this is the right time to address the second, which involves the good faith of enemies toward one another.
Cicero, in his fifth book on the bounds of good and evil, has well observed that every one must approve and commend a disposition to adhere faithfully to our engagements not only from disinterested motives, but in some cases even in opposition to our own interest. And Augustine says that it is right to maintain the pledge of faith given to an enemy, for under the character of enemies men do not lose their right to the fulfilment of a promise, a right which every one possessed of reason is capable of. It is the power of reason and speech from which the obligation of promises springs. Nor is it to be supposed that, because it is lawful to deceive an enemy on some occasions, the same rule will authorise a violation of faith in engagements. For the obligation to speak the truth arises from causes antecedent in their existence to any state of warfare, and they are causes which a state of warfare may render it necessary to change or abridge. But a promise confers a new right of itself. A distinction which did not escape the notice of Aristotle, who,380 in speaking of truth, says that he does not consider truth and sincerity in engagements, with relation to justice or injustice, but as belonging to another class of virtues.
Cicero, in his fifth book on the boundaries of good and evil, noted that everyone must appreciate and support the commitment to stick to our promises not only out of selfless motives but sometimes even against our own interests. Augustine states that we should uphold the promise of faith given to an enemy, because even as enemies, people still have the right to expect a promise to be fulfilled, a right that everyone with reason possesses. The obligation of promises comes from our ability to reason and communicate. It shouldn’t be assumed that just because it's permissible to deceive an enemy at times, it allows for breaking faith in commitments. The duty to tell the truth arises from principles that exist before any state of war, and those principles can be altered or limited by war. However, a promise creates a new right on its own. This distinction was also recognized by Aristotle, who,380 when discussing truth, mentioned that he does not associate truth and sincerity in commitments with justice or injustice, but rather sees them as part of a different category of virtues.
II. As to engagements with pirates, we may observe, that Pompey in a great measure concluded the disputes with them by treaty, sparing their lives, and allowing them places to reside in, on condition of their abandoning their former way of life. The law of nations indeed has not established the same mode of communication with them, as among regular enemies in just and lawful war: but still the very circumstance of their being MEN, entitles them to those privileges which are sanctioned by the law of nature, among which the observance of engagements is one.
II. Regarding interactions with pirates, we can note that Pompey largely resolved conflicts with them through treaties, sparing their lives and giving them places to live, on the condition that they gave up their old way of life. The law of nations does not recognize the same type of communication with them as it does with regular enemies in a just and lawful war. Still, the fact that they are GUYS entitles them to those rights supported by natural law, one of which is the obligation to honor agreements.
III. Let us consider if a more specious argument than Cicero's may not be devised on this subject.—In the first place it may be stated that atrocious malefactors, forming no part of a state, may be punished by any one whatever, according to the law of nature. For those, who may be punished with death, may upon the same principle be deprived of their property and all their rights. And among rights may be enumerated the right of requiring a fulfilment of promises and engagements: the guilty may therefore be deprived of this right by way of penalty. In reply to which it may be said, this will certainly be the case, if the person is treated with, but not as a malefactor: for the very act of treating with him shews that he is not considered any longer in that light, but as one entitled to all the rights of treaty, the criminal part of his character not being taken into the account, all penalties on that score being, as it were remitted. For every act of treaty must be interpreted so as to avoid absurdity.
III. Let's think about whether a more convincing argument than Cicero's can be made on this topic. First, we can say that serious criminals, who aren't part of a state, can be punished by anyone according to natural law. Those who can be punished with death can, for the same reason, also have their property and all their rights taken away. Among those rights is the right to demand that promises and agreements be fulfilled; thus, the guilty can be stripped of this right as a penalty. In response, it's worth noting that this would definitely be true if the person is engaged with, but not treated as a criminal: because treating with him shows that he is no longer seen that way, but as someone entitled to all the rights of negotiation, with his criminal status not taken into account, and all penalties for that are effectively set aside. Every act of negotiation must be interpreted to avoid absurdity.
IV. An objection to treating with pirates upon principles of good faith is deduced from their calling, which is to extort terms by fear. Now where a promise has been extorted, the promisor is released from his engagement, as having unjustly sustained a damage, by an act repugnant to the nature of human liberty, and to the nature of human action, which ought to be free.
IV. An objection to dealing with pirates based on good faith comes from their profession, which is to force terms through intimidation. When a promise is made under threat, the person who made the promise is freed from their commitment because they've been harmed unjustly by an act that goes against the nature of human freedom and the way human actions should be conducted, which is freely.
This, it must be admitted, may sometimes happen, but does not apply to all promises made to pirates. For to make the person, to whom a promise has been given, liable to release the engagement, the promiser himself381 must have been forced to give the promise under impressions of unjust fear. So that if any one has promised a ransom in order to redeem a friend from captivity, he will be bound by his promise. For in this case there was no impression of fear, as he came voluntarily to make the contract.
This might occasionally happen, but it doesn't apply to all promises made to pirates. For someone to be released from a promise, the person who made the promise must have done so under coercion or unjust fear. So if someone has promised a ransom to free a friend from captivity, they are obligated to keep that promise. In this situation, there was no coercion involved since they voluntarily entered into the agreement.
V. A promise too made through the compulsion of fear will be binding, where it has been ratified by the solemn sanction of an oath: for in that case it is not only one man making an engagement to a fellow creature, but binding himself to God by the most solemn appeal: against which neither fear nor any other motive can form an exception. Yet the heir of a promiser is not bound by any such obligation: because inheritances pass according to the rules of human intercourse established at the original institution of property: but the divine right to the fulfilment of oaths, as such, is not included in these. From the above arguments a conclusion may be deduced, that if any one violates a pledge given to such an enemy either upon oath or without oath, he will not on that account be liable to punishment among other nations, because from the general horror which piracy excites, nations have thought proper to pass over without notice the violation of rules of faith towards them.
V. A promise made under the pressure of fear will be binding if it has been confirmed by a solemn oath: in that case, it’s not just one person making a commitment to another, but also binding themselves to God through the most serious appeal. There’s no exception to this obligation from fear or any other motive. However, the heir of someone who made a promise is not bound by that obligation because inheritances transfer according to the rules of human interaction established when property was first created; but the divine right to the fulfillment of oaths does not fall under these rules. From these arguments, we can conclude that if someone breaks a pledge made to such an enemy, whether under oath or not, they won’t be punished by other nations. This is because the general outrage that piracy causes has led countries to overlook violations of faith towards them.
XI.74 Solemn war, signifying such as is proclaimed and begun on both sides by authority of the sovereign or state, among its many other legal rights, includes also that of giving validity to every promise, which may be conducive to its termination, so that if either party, through an ill-grounded fear of further calamities, has, even against his will, made promises unfavourable, or acceded to terms disadvantageous to himself, such an engagement will be binding. For the law of nations allows belligerent powers to alarm each other, if possible, into submission upon the most unequal terms, in the same manner, as it gives a sanction to many things not strictly equitable according to natural and municipal law. For if such a practice had not been established, wars, which are so frequent, could never have been brought to a conclusion, an object so much for the interest of mankind.
XI.74 Serious war, which is declared and started by the authority of the government or state on both sides, among its many legal rights, also includes the right to validate every promise that may help bring it to an end. This means that if either side, out of an unfounded fear of further disaster, has made unfavorable promises or agreed to terms that disadvantage them, such commitments will be binding. The law of nations permits fighting powers to intimidate each other into submission under very unequal conditions, just as it legitimizes many actions that may not be entirely fair according to natural and municipal law. Without this practice, frequent wars could never be resolved, which is an important goal for humanity.
These are the rights of war which Cicero says ought to be inviolably preserved with an enemy: for an enemy382 not only retains his natural rights in war, but certain other rights originating in the consent of nations. Yet it does not follow from hence that any one, who has extorted such a promise in unjust war, can, consistently with piety and the duties of a good man, retain what he has so received, nor can he compel another to stand to such engagements, whether upon oath, or not. For the natural and internal injustice of such a promise always remains the same, nor can the injustice be removed or altered, till it has received a new and free concurrence from the party, by whom it was given.
These are the rights of war that Cicero claims should always be upheld with an enemy: an enemy382 not only keeps his natural rights during war but also has certain rights that come from the agreement of nations. However, this doesn't mean that anyone who has forced such a promise in an unjust war can, in good faith and as a decent person, keep what they received, nor can they force someone else to honor such commitments, whether sworn or not. The inherent unfairness of such a promise never changes, and the injustice cannot be removed or altered until it gets a new and free agreement from the person who made it.
XII. The only impressions of fear, that can be lawfully inspired in regular war, are those which are approved of by the law of nations. Thus no one can avail himself of a promise, extorted from an ambassador under impressions of fear excited by the seizing of his person.
XII. The only fears that can be justifiably instilled in regular warfare are those that are recognized by international law. Therefore, no one can claim a promise that was forced from an ambassador under the threat of fear caused by their capture.
XIII. and XIV. There are two cases, in which a person may not perform his engagement or promise, without being guilty of treachery: and those are, where the conditions have not been fulfilled, or some compensation has been made. For in one and the same treaty all the clauses seem connected with each other, as a kind of condition expressing the intention of one party to fulfil his engagement, if the other shall do the same. Therefore Tullus, in replying to the Albans invokes destruction upon the head of that people who first rejected the just claims of ambassadors demanding restitution, wishing that all the calamities of war might fall upon them. For, says Ulpian, he shall no longer be held as a confederate, who has renounced a treaty, owing to some condition, on which it was made, not being fulfilled. For which reason, wherever it is intended otherwise, it is usually stated in express terms, that the violation of any particular clause shall not annul the whole treaty.
XIII. and XIV. There are two situations where a person can’t fulfill their promise without being seen as deceitful: when the conditions haven't been met, or when some form of compensation has been provided. In any agreement, all the terms are interconnected, reflecting the understanding that one party will uphold their promise if the other does too. Therefore, Tullus, in responding to the Albans, calls down destruction on those who first ignored the legitimate demands of ambassadors seeking compensation, wishing all the horrors of war upon them. For, as Ulpian states, anyone who has abandoned a treaty due to an unmet condition should no longer be considered an ally. That’s why, if something different is intended, it’s usually clearly stated that breaking a specific clause doesn’t invalidate the entire treaty.
XV. The origin of compensation was explained in the second book of this treatise,75 where it was said to be the power and right of receiving an equivalent, for some thing belonging to us, which is in the hands of another, or any thing due to us, which we cannot otherwise obtain: and much more then have we a right on the same account to detain any thing which is ALREADY IN OUR POWER, whether it be of a corporeal or an incorporeal kind. So that we are not obliged to perform a promise, if it be no more than equivalent to a thing of383 ours which the other party detains. Seneca, in his sixth book On Benefits, says that a creditor often becomes under an obligation to his debtor, if he takes more than an equivalent for his debt. For though it may be granted that he has lent money, yet if by such a loan he has obtained the possession of lands, which he never bought, he changes situations with his debtor, and becomes a debtor in his turn.
XV. The origin of compensation was explained in the second book of this article, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ where it stated that it is the power and right to receive an equivalent for something that belongs to us but is in someone else's possession, or anything that is owed to us that we can’t otherwise obtain. Furthermore, we also have the right to hold onto anything that is IN OUR CONTROL NOW, whether it’s physical or intangible. This means we are not obligated to fulfill a promise if it is only equivalent to something of ours that the other party has. Seneca, in his sixth book On Benefits, says that a creditor can sometimes become indebted to the debtor if they take more than what is equivalent for their debt. Although it can be acknowledged that the creditor has lent money, if by lending that money they ended up gaining possession of land that they never purchased, they essentially swap roles with the debtor and become a debtor themselves.
XVI. It will be the same, if one of the contracting parties owes as much, or more, from some other engagement: and the debt cannot otherwise be obtained, than by taking advantage of the present contract, though it has no connection with the former debt. But in a LEGAL point of view, all actions are perfectly distinct, nor can their forms, their grounds, or their substance be confounded; but certain cases are confined to certain laws, to which it is necessary invariably to adhere: one law cannot be mixed with another, but every one in the prosecution of a right must tread upon invariable and beaten ground. But the law of nations does not regard such distinctions, it allows us to transgress them where there is no other means of obtaining our right.
XVI. It will be the same if one of the parties involved owes as much, or more, from a different agreement: and if the debt cannot be collected in any other way than by using the current contract, even if it's unrelated to the previous debt. However, from a LEGAL standpoint, all actions are completely separate, and their forms, grounds, or substance can't be confused; certain cases are restricted to specific laws, which must always be followed. One law cannot be mixed with another, and anyone pursuing a right must stick to established and proven paths. But international law doesn't recognize such distinctions; it allows us to bypass them when there are no other options for obtaining our rights.
XVII. and XVIII. The same may be said too, where the party exacting a promise, has not contracted any debt by engagement, but has done an injury to the promiser. And whatever is due by way of punishment may be balanced against a promise.
XVII. and XVIII. The same can be said where the party demanding a promise has not created any obligation but has caused harm to the person making the promise. And anything owed as a consequence may offset a promise.
XIX. If while a law-suit is depending, the parties enter into an agreement of any kind, either to pay the costs, or to make good other damages, they cannot avail themselves both of this agreement, and claim a further compensation for the original matter in dispute. In the same manner, if during the continuance of a war the belligerents negotiate for a conclusion of the original dispute, they are supposed thereby to settle every cause of hostility, nor can they any further avail themselves of the rights of war, so as to enjoy both the advantages of them, and of negotiation, at the same time. For if this were the case, no treaties could ever be enforced with certainty.
XIX. If, while a lawsuit is ongoing, the parties reach any kind of agreement—whether to cover costs or to compensate for other damages—they can't use both this agreement and seek additional compensation for the original issue in dispute. Similarly, if during a war the opposing sides negotiate to resolve the original conflict, they're assumed to settle all reasons for hostility, and they can't further use their rights of war, enjoying both the benefits of warfare and negotiation at the same time. If that were allowed, no treaties could ever be reliably enforced.
It may be asked, of what nature are the things for which a promise of compensation should be given? In answer to which it may be observed, that such a promise or engagement may be made in lieu of some other obligation incurred during the course of a war: as for384 instance, where the breach of a truce has been committed, the rights of an ambassador violated, or any other action done, repugnant to the principles established by the law of nations among belligerent powers.
It might be asked, what kinds of things should receive a promise of compensation? In response, it's important to note that such a promise or commitment can be made instead of another obligation taken on during a war. For example, in cases where a truce has been broken, an ambassador's rights have been violated, or any other act has occurred that goes against the principles set by international law between warring nations.
Still it must be observed that the parties, in making compensation, should abstain with the utmost caution from infringing upon the rights of a third person, especially where this can be done without abandoning the principles of the law of nations, which makes the effects of subjects answerable for the debts of the state. Besides it is the mark of a dignified mind to adhere to engagements even after receiving an injury. On which account the Indian sage Jarchas commended that king, who on sustaining an injury from a neighbouring and confederate power, said he should not think himself released from his sworn engagements, which were solemn acts, that no injustice on the part of another could repeal.
It should still be noted that when making compensation, the parties must be extremely careful not to violate the rights of a third party, especially when this can be done without compromising the principles of international law, which holds individuals accountable for the debts of the state. Furthermore, a dignified person honors their commitments, even after facing a setback. For this reason, the Indian sage Jarchas praised the king who, after being wronged by a neighboring allied power, stated that he would not consider himself free from his sworn commitments, which were serious obligations that no wrongdoing by others could undo.
Almost all questions relating to pledges of faith given by one belligerent power to another, may be solved upon the principles before laid down, in explaining the nature and force of promises in general; of oaths, treaties, and conventions, and also in explaining the rights of the obligations of kings, and the method of interpreting doubtful points. But in order to remove every doubt and difficulty, perhaps a brief discussion of the most usual and practical topics of negotiation will not be deemed tedious.
Almost all questions about promises made between warring nations can be resolved using the principles we've outlined regarding the nature and significance of commitments in general; such as oaths, treaties, and conventions, as well as the rights and responsibilities of rulers, and how to interpret uncertain issues. However, to eliminate any uncertainty or confusion, it might be helpful to briefly discuss the most common and practical negotiation topics, which hopefully won't be considered boring.
CHAPTER XX.
On Public Trust, through which War is Ended; Including Peace Treaties, the Nature of Arbitration, Surrender of Hostages, and Guarantees.
In monarchies the power of making peace a royal prerogative—In aristocracies and democracies, this right belongs to a greater number of persons—In what manner the public dominions or any part of them may be alienated—How far a peace concluded by the king binds the state, or his successors—Property of individuals ceded for the benefit of the state at the time of making peace—Indemnity to those individuals—Losses sustained in war—No distinction between things acquired according to the law of nations and the civil law—Transactions of the sovereign with foreign nations deemed valid from motives of public utility—General rule of interpreting the terms of peace—In doubtful cases the former state of things supposed to be continued by a treaty of peace—Things restored to the state they were in before the war—Independent states, voluntarily joining one of the belligerent powers cannot claim indemnity of the other—General amnesty—Private debts subsisting before the war not included therein—Restoration of captures—Rules respecting such restorations—Dubious points to be interpreted to the prejudice of the party dictating the terms—Distinction between new causes of war, and the breach of a peace—Rupture by any act contrary to the terms of peace in general—Infraction of a treaty by allies or subjects—Violation of a particular treaty—Heads of treaties—Penalties annexed—Unavoidable impediments to the fulfilment of a treaty—Peace continued at the option of the injured party—Relations of amity—How far receiving subjects and exiles may be considered as a breach thereof—Victory—War concluded by arbitration—Arbitrators bound by rules of strict justice—Absolute, and conditional surrender—Hostages can be detained for no other than the express cause for which they were given—Released by the death of the party for whom they were given—Obligation of pledges—Right of redeeming them lost.
In monarchies, the power to make peace is a royal privilege. In aristocracies and democracies, this right is shared by more individuals. It addresses how public lands or any parts of them can be transferred. The extent to which a peace agreement made by the king binds the state or his successors is evaluated. Individuals may have their property taken for the state's benefit when making peace, and there should be compensation for those individuals. Losses faced during the war are noted, with no distinction made between property acquired under international law and civil law. Agreements made by the sovereign with foreign nations are considered valid for the public good. A general rule for interpreting peace conditions states that in uncertain situations, the previous status quo is assumed to be preserved by the peace treaty. Things should be returned to how they were before the war. Independent states that willingly ally with one of the warring parties cannot seek compensation from the other. A general amnesty should apply, but private debts that existed before the war are excluded. Guidelines for the restoration of captured items are established, with rules for such restorations. Ambiguous points should be interpreted against the party that created the terms. There’s a difference between new causes of conflict and breaches of peace; a break due to any act that violates the peace terms generally constitutes a rupture. Treaty violations by allies or subjects, as well as breaches of specific treaties, are addressed. The main topics of treaties and associated penalties are noted. Unavoidable barriers to fulfilling a treaty are recognized. Peace is maintained at the discretion of the injured party. The nature of friendships and how accepting subjects and exiles may be viewed as a breach of these relationships is discussed. The idea of victory and wars concluded through arbitration is explored, with arbitrators bound by strict justice. Absolute and conditional surrenders are acknowledged. Hostages can only be held for the specific reasons they were given for and must be released upon the death of the person for whom they were held. The obligation of pledges is recognized, as is the lost right to redeem them.
I. Good faith, either expressed or implied, must be the foundation of every treaty between hostile powers. And again the faith that is expressed is either of a public or a private nature, and the pledges given either by the sovereign, or inferior authorities in states constitute the public faith. It is, by such pledges given on the part of the sovereign power alone, that peace can be concluded, or the rights of war enforced. In the termination of386 every war, either the principal, or accessory causes are to be considered. Treaties are in general regarded as the principal instrument, by which wars are ended, and the mediation, or decision of a third person or power is deemed a secondary or accessory means.
I. Good faith, whether spoken or understood, must be the foundation of every treaty between warring nations. Moreover, the good faith that is spoken can be either public or private, and the commitments made by either the sovereign or lower authorities within states form the basis of public faith. It is through these commitments made by the sovereign power alone that peace can be established or the rights of war upheld. When ending386 a war, both the main and secondary causes need to be taken into account. Treaties are generally seen as the primary tool through which wars are concluded, while the mediation or judgment of a third party is considered a secondary support.
II. The person, who has authority to begin a war, is the only one to whom the right of making peace can properly belong, according to the general maxim, that every one is the best judge in the management of his own affairs. From hence it follows, that public war can be made by the sovereign power alone on each side: a right which in every kingly government is very justly vested in the crown.
II. The person with the authority to start a war is the only one who truly has the right to make peace, following the general principle that everyone is the best judge of their own affairs. Therefore, it follows that public war can only be declared by the sovereign power on each side: a right that is rightfully held by the crown in any monarchy.
III. and IV. In popular or aristocratic forms of government, the right of making war, or concluding peace, is generally lodged in some public council or body, where a majority of voices may form treaties, conventions, or resolutions, which will be binding upon the dissentient part of such council. And all who are bound by a peace, whether approving it or not are entitled to its benefits.
III. and IV. In popular or aristocratic forms of government, the power to declare war or make peace is usually given to a public council or body, where a majority can create treaties, agreements, or decisions that will be binding on those who disagree within that council. And everyone bound by a peace agreement, whether they approve it or not, is entitled to its benefits.
V. In examining those objects, which form the most material part of treaties, we may observe, that kingdoms are not so much a patrimony, which may be alienated at pleasure, as a trust, placed in the hands of the sovereign for the benefit of his people. Indeed kings themselves are aware of this, even before the crown descends upon their heads, and they receive it upon condition of adhering to such sacred obligations.
V. In looking at the things that make up the core of treaties, we can see that kingdoms aren’t just an inheritance that can be given away whenever someone wants; they’re a responsibility given to the ruler for the benefit of the people. In fact, kings know this even before they receive the crown, and they accept it with the understanding that they must follow these important duties.
Nor can such alienations ever be made, so as to be attended with consequences like those of private contracts, or to render the goods and effects of subjects answerable for such engagements. For if that were the case, the fundamental laws of the kingdom, prohibiting such alienations, would be of no effect.
Nor can such alienations ever be made in a way that leads to consequences like those of private contracts, or that makes the goods and assets of individuals accountable for such commitments. Because if that were true, the fundamental laws of the kingdom, which prohibit such alienations, would mean nothing.
To render the alienation of the whole public dominion valid, the consent of the constituted authorities of the state is requisite. And indeed to confirm the transfer of any particular portion, the consent of the whole body as well as of that particular member will be necessary: for otherwise such alienation would be like the violent separation of a limb from the natural body.
To make the alienation of the entire public domain legitimate, the approval of the government authorities is required. In fact, to finalize the transfer of any specific area, the agreement of the entire group as well as that specific member will be essential; otherwise, such alienation would be similar to violently removing a limb from the body.
A whole people may in a case of extreme necessity transfer themselves to the dominion of another, a right which undoubtedly was reserved at the original formation of society.
A whole population can, in times of extreme need, move under the rule of another, a right that was definitely set aside at the original formation of society.
387 Neither is there any thing to prevent a king from alienating his patrimonial and private possessions. Yet there may be parts of the royal dominion, which the sovereign cannot alienate from the crown, especially, if he has received it upon condition of making no personal appropriation of any thing belonging thereto.
387 There's nothing stopping a king from selling or giving away his personal and inherited property. However, there may be certain parts of the royal domain that the ruler cannot transfer out of the crown's ownership, especially if he received them with the condition that he wouldn't personally claim any of it as his own.
There are two ways in which the possessions of the crown may become the patrimony of the king, either as separable or inseparable parts of the kingdom. In the latter case they can only be transferred with the kingdom itself, but in the former, they may be alienated by themselves. And where the crown is not patrimonial and hereditary, the restrictions upon the sovereign in this respect are much greater.
There are two ways that the crown's possessions can become the king's inheritance: either as separable or inseparable parts of the kingdom. In the latter case, they can only be handed over along with the kingdom itself, but in the former, they can be sold or given away on their own. And when the crown is not hereditary, the limits on the sovereign in this regard are much stricter.
VI. A nation and a king's successors are bound by his engagements, in proportion to the power, which he derives from the constitution, of making such engagements. For though this power may not be absolutely unlimited, yet it ought not to be clogged with unnecessary restrictions. It should be such as may enable him to exercise his discretion and judgment on proper occasions for the benefit of his people.
VI. A nation and a king's successors are bound by his commitments, based on the authority he has from the constitution to make those commitments. While this authority may not be completely unrestricted, it shouldn't be weighed down by unnecessary limitations. It should allow him to use his discretion and judgment when appropriate for the benefit of his people.
The case will be different, where a king's power over his subjects is like that of a master over his household, more than of a sovereign over his state, as where he has entirely subjugated a people, or where his controul over their property is absolute. Thus Pharaoh purchased all the land in Egypt, and others have admitted strangers into their territories allowing them to hold lands upon such conditions. For here, there is another right in addition to that of a sovereign, and it is a right, which sovereignty alone without conquest could never have conferred.
The situation is different when a king's power over his subjects resembles that of a master over his household, rather than that of a ruler over his state, especially when he has completely dominated a people or has absolute control over their property. For instance, Pharaoh bought all the land in Egypt, and others have allowed outsiders to settle in their territories, granting them land under specific conditions. In this case, there is an additional right beyond that of a ruler, and it’s a right that sovereignty alone, without conquest, could never have offered.
VII. The right of sovereigns to dispose of the effects of individuals, in order to make peace, is often a disputed point, nor can they exercise this right over the property of subjects in any other manner than as sovereigns.76
VII. The right of rulers to manage the belongings of individuals to achieve peace is often a debated issue, and they can only exercise this right over the property of their subjects in the way that sovereigns. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
The property of subjects is so far under the eminent388 controul of the state, that the state or the sovereign who represents it, can use that property, or destroy it, or alienate it, NOT ONLY IN CASES OF EXTREME NECESSITY, which sometimes allow individuals the liberty of infringing upon the property of others, but on all OCCASIONS, where the public good is concerned, to which the original framers of society intended that private interests should give way. But when that is the case, it is to be observed, the state is bound to repair the losses of individuals, at the public expence, in aid of which the sufferers have contributed their due proportion. Nor will the state, though unable to repair the losses for the present, be finally released from the debt, but whenever she possesses the means of repairing the damages, the dormant claim and obligation will be revived.
The ownership of property by individuals is so much under the control of the state that the state, or the sovereign who represents it, can use, destroy, or transfer that property, 388 NOT JUST IN CASES OF EXTREME NEED, which sometimes allows individuals to infringe on the property of others, but in all EVENTS where the public good is at stake, which the original builders of society intended should take precedence over private interests. However, in such cases, it should be noted that the state is required to compensate individuals for their losses at public expense, for which the affected individuals have contributed their fair share. Even if the state is currently unable to compensate for the losses, it won't be completely released from this obligation; whenever the state has the resources to make reparations, the pending claim and responsibility will be activated.
VIII. There must be some hesitation in admitting the opinion of Ferdinand Vasquez, who maintains that the state is not bound to repair the losses, which are occasioned to individuals in the course of war, as those are accidents permitted by the rights of war.
VIII. There should be some doubt in accepting the opinion of Ferdinand Vasquez, who claims that the state is not obligated to compensate individuals for losses incurred during war, as those are accidents allowed under the rules of war.
For those rights regard the relation of foreign states and enemies to each other, but bear no reference to the disputes of subjects among themselves, who, being united in the same cause, ought to share the common losses, which happen to them in supporting the privileges of their society. It is a rule likewise established by the civil law, that no action can be brought against the state for the losses sustained in war, as every one is thereby induced to defend his own property with more earnestness and spirit.77
For those rights concern the relationship between foreign states and enemies, but they don't address the issues between individuals within the same nation, who, united in a common purpose, should share the losses they incur in defending the privileges of their community. It's also a rule established by civil law that no legal action can be taken against the state for losses suffered in war, as this encourages everyone to defend their own property with greater commitment and enthusiasm.spirit.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
389 IX. Some make a distinction between the property which subjects are entitled to from the law of nations and that which they possess by the authority of the civil law, allowing the king a more extensive controul over the latter, even to the power of taking it without cause or compensation, which is not the case with property of the former kind. But this is an improper distinction. For whatever may be the origin of property, it is always attended with peculiar effects according to the law of nature: so that it cannot be taken away for any other reasons than those inherent in the nature of property itself, or derived from some act of the owners.
389 IX. Some people differentiate between the property that individuals have under international law and what they have under civil law, allowing the king more control over the latter, even giving him the power to take it without reason or compensation, which isn’t the case for property under international law. However, this distinction is incorrect. No matter how property is acquired, it always comes with specific rights according to natural law: therefore, it cannot be taken away for reasons other than those inherent to the nature of the property itself or resulting from the actions of the owners.
X. The prohibition respecting the property of individuals being given up, except for some public advantage, is a matter resting entirely between a sovereign and his subjects, and a compensation for losses is an affair between the state and individuals. But in all transactions between a king and foreigners, the act of the king is sufficient to give them NATIONAL validity, not only out of respect to his personal dignity, but according to the law of nations, which renders the effects of subjects responsible for the acts of the sovereign.
X. The rule about individuals' property being given up, except for some public benefit, is entirely a matter between a sovereign and their subjects, and any compensation for losses is an issue between the state and individuals. However, in all dealings between a king and foreigners, the king's actions are enough to provide them NATIONAL validity, not just out of respect for his personal dignity, but also according to international law, which holds the subjects accountable for the monarch's actions.
XI. In interpreting treaties of peace, favourable circumstances are always to be taken in their utmost latitude, and unfavourable circumstances to be limited as strictly as possible.78
XI. When interpreting peace treaties, favorable circumstances should always be considered to their fullest extent, while unfavorable circumstances should be restricted as much as possible.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Regarding purely the law of nature, the most favourable construction is that, whereby every one is restored to his own property and possessions. Therefore where the articles of a treaty are ambiguous, the construction should go so far, as to grant the party, who has evidently justice on his side, the object for which he went to war, and likewise indemnity for the losses which he has sustained.
Concerning the law of nature, the best interpretation is that everyone should be returned to their own property and possessions. So, when the terms of a treaty are unclear, the interpretation should extend to granting the party who clearly has justice on their side what they sought in the conflict, along with compensation for the losses they have suffered.
But it is not allowable that either party should gain more than an indemnity, or demand any thing by way of punishment, which is of an odious nature.
But neither party is allowed to gain more than compensation or to ask for anything that serves as a punishment, especially if it's something unpleasant.
As in making peace, it scarcely ever happens that either party will acknowledge the injustice of his cause, or of his claims, such a construction must be given, as will equalize the pretensions of each side, which may be accomplished, either by restoring the disputed possessions to their former situation, or by leaving them in the state, to which the war has reduced them.
As with making peace, it rarely happens that either side will admit the unfairness of their cause or claims. Instead, a solution is often created that balances the demands of both sides, which can be done either by returning the disputed possessions to their original state or by keeping them as they are after the war.
390 XII. Of these two methods, in a doubtful case, the latter is preferred, as being the more easily adjusted, and occasioning no further change. From hence the right of postliminium belongs to such prisoners, as are expressly included in the treaty. Neither are deserters to be given up, unless it be so agreed. For by the laws of war any power is allowed to receive deserters, and even to enlist them in his own army.
390 XII. In uncertain situations, the second method is usually preferred because it's easier to modify and doesn't cause any additional changes. This establishes that the right of postliminium applies to prisoners specifically mentioned in the treaty. Deserters shouldn't be handed over unless there is a mutual agreement. According to the laws of war, any nation is permitted to take in deserters and even recruit them into its own military.
By such agreement other things remain in the hands of the possessors, by which is not meant a civil, but a natural possession: for in war BARE POSSESSION is sufficient, nor is any other kind looked for. And lands are said to be so possessed, when inclosed or defended by fortifications, for a temporary occupation by an encampment is not regarded in this case. Hence Demosthenes in his speech for Ctesiphon, says that Philip was anxious to make himself master of all the places he could seize, as he knew that upon the conclusion of a peace, he should retain them.
By this agreement, other things stay in the hands of the possessors, which refers to a natural possession rather than a civil one: in war, Bare possession is enough, and no other type is expected. Lands are considered possessed when they are enclosed or protected by fortifications, as a temporary occupation by an encampment doesn’t count in this situation. Therefore, Demosthenes, in his speech for Ctesiphon, states that Philip was eager to take control of all the places he could grab, knowing that when peace was established, he would keep them.
Incorporeal rights cannot be held but by the occupation of the things with which they are connected; as for instance, the services of lands, or through means of the persons, to whom they belong: but the holders of such rights lose them, when an enemy has become master of the country.
Incorporeal rights can only be held through the possession of the things they are associated with; for example, the services of land or through the people to whom they belong. However, the holders of these rights lose them if an enemy takes control of the territory.
XIII. In that other mode of treaty, whereby possession, that has been disturbed in the course of a war, is restored, it is proper to observe that the last possession, immediately before the war began, is that, which is always meant, so that the individuals then unjustly ejected, may have recourse to law, either to obtain possession by a provisional decree, or to make good their claim.
XIII. In that other way of agreement, where the possession that was interrupted during a war is returned, it’s important to note that the last possession just before the war started is what is always intended, so that those who were wrongfully removed can seek legal recourse, either to regain possession through a temporary order or to validate their claim.
XIV. If an independent people VOLUNTARILY and SPONTANEOUSLY place themselves under the controul and protection of one of the belligerent powers, such a people cannot be included among those entitled to restitution, which only belongs to those who have suffered losses by violence, through fear, or any lawful stratagem of war. Thus when peace was made among the Grecian states, the Thebans retained Plataea, observing that they neither owed their possession of it to violence, nor treachery, but to the free surrender of those, to whom it belonged.
XIV. If an independent people Willingly and SPONTANEOUSLY submit themselves to the control and protection of one of the warring powers, that people cannot be considered among those entitled to restitution, which is only for those who have suffered losses due to violence, fear, or any lawful tactic of war. So when peace was established among the Greek states, the Thebans kept Plataea, noting that they did not gain it through violence or betrayal, but through the voluntary surrender of those who owned it.
XV. Unless there is an express stipulation to the contrary, it is understood that, in all treaties of peace, there is an implied assent that no actions are to be brought for391 losses occasioned by the accidental calamities of war, either to states or individuals. For those are natural consequences of a state of hostilities: and it is supposed that in doubtful cases, no belligerent would consent to be convicted of injustice.
XV. Unless there's a clear agreement saying otherwise, it is understood that in all peace treaties, there is an implied agreement that no legal actions can be taken for391 losses caused by the accidental disasters of war, whether for states or individuals. These are natural outcomes of being at war: and it’s assumed that in uncertain situations, no fighting party would agree to be found unjust.
XVI. The debts, owing to individuals, at the beginning of a war, are not to be thought thereby discharged. For they are not things acquired by the laws of war: for war only prevents the claim to them from being prosecuted, but by no means releases the obligation. So that when the impediment of war is removed, such debts retain their original force. For though it ought not to be presumed that any one should easily be deprived of a right subsisting before the war, yet this is to be understood of the rights arising out of the foundation of property, whereby a community and equality of goods was abolished. For states and governments, says Cicero, were originally and principally designed to preserve to every one the possession of his own property.
XVI. Debts owed to individuals at the start of a war are not automatically canceled. They are not things that can be nullified by the laws of war; war merely stops the ability to claim them, but does not erase the obligation. Therefore, once the obstacle of war is removed, these debts remain valid. While it shouldn’t be assumed that anyone can easily be stripped of a right that existed before the war, this applies specifically to rights related to property, which is where the community and equality of goods were disrupted. As Cicero said, states and governments were originally created to protect everyone’s ownership of their property.
XVII. The right to claim lands or goods of any kind, by way of PUNISHMENT, is not of equal force with the above rules. For in transactions and treaties of that kind between kings and sovereign states, all claims of that kind seem and indeed ought to be relinquished, otherwise peace would be no peace, if the old and original causes of the war were allowed to remain and be revived. And the most latent and remote causes are supposed to be included in the most GENERAL TERMS, in treaties of peace, whereby they are sunk in oblivion.
XVII. The right to claim lands or any goods as a form of Consequences isn’t as strong as the rules mentioned above. In dealings and agreements of this kind between kings and sovereign nations, all such claims seem, and should indeed be, given up; otherwise, peace wouldn’t truly be peace if the original reasons for the war were allowed to linger and resurface. The most hidden and distant causes are thought to be covered by the most TERMS AND CONDITIONS in peace treaties, effectively burying them in forgetfulness.
XVIII. The rights of individuals to penalties are not supposed to be abandoned, resting entirely upon different grounds: because they may be decided by legal tribunals without appealing to the sword. Yet as our rights of this sort are not of the same kind with those of absolute property, and as penalties have always something odious in their nature, any faint verbal conjecture will be thought a sufficient presumption of their being remitted.
XVIII. Individuals' rights to penalties are not supposed to be given up, as they depend on different principles: because these can be determined by legal courts without resorting to violence. However, since our rights in this regard are not the same as those of absolute ownership, and since penalties always have an unpleasant nature, any weak verbal suggestion will be seen as a strong enough indication that they are waived.
XIX. The objection made against taking away any rights, that existed before the war, applies chiefly to the rights of INDIVIDUALS. For where the words of a treaty supply any probable conjecture, it is most natural to suppose that KINGS and NATIONS have more readily relinquished certain rights, especially in matters, where those rights are not clearly and fully ascertained. So that, giving the most favourable construction to their conduct,392 they are supposed to have been animated with the noble desire of rooting up and destroying all the seeds of war.
XIX. The argument against taking away any rights that existed before the war mainly concerns the rights of PEOPLE. When a treaty provides any reasonable assumption, it’s most logical to think that Kings and COUNTRIES have more willingly given up certain rights, especially in areas where those rights aren't clearly defined. Therefore, giving the most favorable interpretation to their actions,392 they are believed to have been motivated by a noble intention to eliminate all the causes of war.
XX. All captures, made after a treaty is finished, must evidently be restored. For the treaty puts an end to all the rights of war.
XX. All captures made after a treaty has ended must clearly be returned. The treaty ends all rights to war.
XXI. But in treaties relating to the restoration of things taken in war, a more extensive interpretation must be given, where the advantages are mutual than where they incline only to one side.79
XXI. But in treaties about returning things taken in war, a broader interpretation should be applied when the benefits are mutual rather than when they only favor one side.__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
In the next place all the parts of a treaty relating to persons are to be interpreted more favourably than those relating to things: and among those relating to things, priority is given to lands before moveable effects, and also among these, such as are in the hands of the state are held in more consideration than the possessions of individuals. And again, among things in the possession of individuals, those are more favoured which are held under a beneficial title, than those which are loaded with incumbrances, as things held by money payments, or by dower.
In addition, all the parts of a treaty concerning individuals should be interpreted more favorably than those concerning property. Among those related to property, land takes precedence over movable items, and among those, state-owned property is regarded more highly than that belonging to individuals. Furthermore, among the items owned by individuals, those that are held with a beneficial title are favored more than those that come with burdens, such as those associated with financial payments or dowries.
XXII. The person, to whom any thing is ceded by a treaty of peace, is entitled to the produce and fruits of it, from the time of such cession, and not farther back: a point maintained by Augustus Caesar in opposition to Sextus Pompey, who, upon Peloponnesus being ceded to him, claimed also the tributes and revenues, that were due for former years.
XXII. The person to whom anything is granted by a peace treaty is entitled to the benefits and profits from that thing starting from the time of the grant, and not any earlier. This was a point argued by Augustus Caesar against Sextus Pompey, who, when Peloponnesus was ceded to him, also claimed the taxes and revenue that were owed for previous years.
XXIII. The names of countries are to be taken according to the usage of the present time, not so much according to the popular acceptation, as to that of men of science, by whom those subjects are generally treated of.
XXIII. The names of countries should be used based on current usage, not just according to popular opinion, but according to the terminology used by scientists, who usually discuss these topics.
XXIV. These rules also are of frequent use, whenever there is a reference to an antecedent, or to an ancient treaty. For in that case the qualities and conditions of the latter treaty are considered as a repetition of those expressed in the former.—And the person contracting is to be considered as having really performed his part of the engagement, which he certainly would have done, had he not been prevented by the party with whom he is engaged in dispute.
XXIV. These rules are also commonly used whenever there is a reference to a previous agreement or an old treaty. In that situation, the qualities and conditions of the latter treaty are seen as a repeat of those stated in the former. The person making the contract is regarded as having truly fulfilled their part of the agreement, which they would have done if they hadn't been blocked by the other party they are in dispute with.
393 XXV. What some allege in excuse for a short delay in the execution of a treaty is not to be admitted as true, except some unforeseen necessity has occasioned the impediment. For though some of the canon-laws may favour such a plea, that is not surprising, considering they are framed solely with the view of promoting charity among Christians. But in this question relating to the interpretation of treaties, it is not so much our business to lay down what is best and properest for every one to do, nor even to state what religion and piety require, as to consider what every one may be compelled by legal authority to do.
393 XXV. What some claim as an excuse for a brief delay in carrying out a treaty should not be accepted as valid unless some unexpected necessity has caused the holdup. Although some canon laws might support such a claim, it isn't surprising since they are designed mainly to encourage goodwill among Christians. In this matter concerning the interpretation of treaties, our focus isn't so much on what is best and most appropriate for everyone to do, or even what religion and moral duty demand, but rather on what individuals can be legally required to do.
XXVI. In doubtful matters it is usual for an interpretation to be given more prejudicial to the party who has dictated the terms, than to the other, because in general he is the more powerful: in the same manner, in explaining the terms of a bargain, a construction is generally given against the seller: as he may blame himself for not having spoken more clearly, and openly. Whereas the other, comprehending the terms in more meanings than one, might fairly select that most favourable to himself.
XXVI. In uncertain situations, it's common for an interpretation to work against the party who set the terms, rather than the other party, because they usually hold more power. Similarly, when clarifying the terms of a deal, explanations typically lean against the seller, as they can be held responsible for not being clearer and more straightforward. On the other hand, the buyer, understanding the terms in multiple ways, can reasonably choose the interpretation that benefits them the most.
XXVII. It is a matter of frequent dispute what constitutes the breach of a peace. For it is not the same thing to break a peace, as to furnish new grounds and causes of war. There is a great difference between these things, both as to the penalty incurred by the aggressor, and as to the aggrieved party being, in other respects, released from his engagements.
XXVII. There's often debate about what actually breaks a peace. It’s not the same to break a peace as it is to create new reasons for war. There’s a significant difference between these two, both concerning the penalties faced by the aggressor and the fact that the aggrieved party is, in other ways, freed from their obligations.
There are three ways, in which a peace may be broken,—either by doing something contrary to the very essence of ALL peace,—or something in violation of the EXPRESS terms of a PARTICULAR peace,—or something contrary to the EFFECTS, which are intended to arise from every peace.
There are three ways in which peace can be broken—either by doing something that goes against the very essence of ALL peace— or something that violates the EXPRESS terms of a SPECIFIC peace—or something that contradicts the IMPACTS that are meant to result from any peace.
XXVIII. A thing is done contrary to the very essence of all peace, when hostile aggressions are committed without any new grounds of war. But where any specious pretext can be assigned for taking arms, it is better it should be supposed purely an act of injustice, than an act of injustice accompanied with perfidy. It is hardly necessary to quote the words of Thucydides, who says, "it is not the party, who repels force by arms, but the power who first makes the attack, that violates a peace."
XXVIII. It's a violation of peace when attacks happen without any just reason for war. However, if there's a plausible excuse for going to war, it's better to view it as an unjust act rather than an unjust act filled with deceit. It's almost unnecessary to quote Thucydides, who states, "it is not the party who defends themselves with arms, but the one who initiates the attack, that breaks the peace."
Having laid down these rules, it remains to be considered, who are the AGGRESSORS, and who are the AGGRIEVED PERSONS, in the breaking of a peace.
Having established these rules, we need to consider who the AGGRESSORS are, and who the Affected individuals are, in the violation of peace.
394 XXIX. There are some, who think that a peace is broken, when even those, who have been allies do any of these things. Nor indeed can it be denied, that such an agreement MAY be made, for one ally to become liable to punishment for the actions of another, and for a peace to be deemed ratified and permanent only upon conditions, partly arbitrary, and partly casual.
394 XXIX. Some people believe that a peace is violated when even allies engage in certain actions. It can't be denied that an agreement MAY be established, where one ally can be held accountable for the actions of another, and a peace can only be considered confirmed and lasting based on conditions that are partly arbitrary and partly accidental.
But it is hardly credible, unless there is the clearest evidence of it, that peace is ever concluded upon such terms. For it is contrary to all rule, and repugnant to the common wishes of those, who make peace. Therefore those, who have committed hostile aggressions, without the assistance of others, will be deemed breakers of the peace, against whom alone the injured party will have a right to take arms.
But it's hard to believe, unless there’s clear evidence, that peace is ever made on such terms. It goes against all norms and clashes with the common desires of those who negotiate peace. Therefore, those who initiate hostilities on their own will be seen as violators of the peace, and the injured party will solely have the right to take up arms against them.
XXX. If subjects have committed any act of hostility without authority and commission from the state, it will form a proper subject of inquiry, whether the state can be judged responsible for the acts of individuals: to constitute which responsibility, it is evident that a knowledge of the fact, power to punish it, and having neglected to do so, are requisite.
XXX. If individuals have taken any hostile action without permission from the state, it raises the question of whether the state can be held responsible for the actions of those individuals. To establish this responsibility, it's clear that knowledge of the act, the ability to punish it, and the failure to do so are necessary.
A formal notice given to the sovereign of the offending subjects is supposed to amount to a knowledge of the fact, and it is presumed that every sovereign is able to controul and punish his own subjects, unless there be some defect in his authority: and a lapse of time, beyond what is usually taken for the punishment of civil offences in every country, may be construed into wilful neglect. And such neglect amounts to a sanction of the offence.
A formal notice sent to the ruler about the offending subjects is considered to be knowledge of the situation, and it’s assumed that every ruler can control and punish their own subjects, unless there’s a problem with their authority. If too much time passes, beyond what is typically allowed for punishing civil offenses in any country, it can be seen as willful neglect. This type of neglect is equivalent to approving the offense.
XXXI. It is likewise frequently made a subject of inquiry, whether a state is answerable for the conduct of any of her people, who do not take arms by her authority, but serve in the armies of some other power engaged in war. The Cerites, in Livy, clear themselves upon this principle, that it was not by their authority their people bore arms. And it is a well-founded opinion that no such permission ought to be deemed as given, unless it appear from probable reasons that it was intended it should be granted: a thing sometimes done, according to the example of the ancient Aetolians, who thought they had a right to deprive every plunderer of his spoils. A custom the force of which Polybius expresses in the following words, "when other powers, friends and allies of the Aetolians,395 are at war with each other, the Aetolians may nevertheless serve in the armies on either side, destroying and spoiling their respective countries."
XXXI. It is often questioned whether a state is responsible for the actions of its people who do not fight under its authority but serve in the armies of another power engaged in war. The Cerites, in Livy, clear themselves on the grounds that their people fought without their permission. It's widely accepted that no such permission should be considered granted unless there are clear reasons indicating it was meant to be given. This has been done before, as seen with the ancient Aetolians, who believed they had the right to take back anything stolen by plunderers. Polybius describes this custom with the following words: "when other powers, friends and allies of the Aetolians,395 are at war with each other, the Aetolians may still serve in the armies on either side, destroying and plundering their respective countries."
XXXII. Again, a peace ought to be deemed broken, not only by any act of violence done to the body politic itself, but to any of the subjects, without new grounds of war. For peace is made with a view to the security of every individual subject: as the state in making peace acts for the whole, and for all its parts.
XXXII. Again, peace should be considered broken, not just by any act of violence against the political body itself, but also against any of its citizens, without any new cause for war. Peace is made to ensure the security of every individual citizen: when the state makes peace, it does so on behalf of everyone and all its components.
Indeed even if new grounds of war should arise, every one may, during the continuance of peace, defend himself and his property. For it is a natural right to repel force by force: a right which it cannot easily be supposed that those, who are upon a footing of equality have ever renounced.
Indeed, even if new reasons for war come up, everyone can defend themselves and their property during peacetime. It’s a natural right to respond to force with force; this is a right that it’s hard to believe anyone on equal footing would ever give up.
But to practise revenge, or use violence in recovering things taken away will not be lawful, except where justice is denied. Justice may admit of some delay: but the other method demands prompt execution, and therefore should not be undertaken but in extreme emergency. But if the subjects of any country persist in a course of uniform crime, and aggression, repugnant to all natural and civil law, in defiance of the authority of their own government, so that the hand of justice cannot reach them, it will be lawful for any one to deprive them of their spoils, and to exercise upon them the same rigour, as if they were delivered up to punishment. But to attack other innocent persons on that account is a direct violation of peace.
But seeking revenge or using violence to recover things that have been taken isn’t allowed, except when justice is denied. Justice might take some time, but violence requires immediate action and should only be used in extreme situations. However, if people in any country continue to commit uniform crimes and act aggressively, going against all natural and civil laws, and defying their own government's authority, to the point that justice can't reach them, then anyone is justified in taking back what has been stolen from them and treating those offenders as if they were being punished. But attacking other innocent people because of this is a clear violation of peace.
XXXIII. Any act of violence also offered to allies, constitutes a breach of the peace, but they must be such allies as are comprehended in the treaty.
XXXIII. Any act of violence against allies also breaks the peace, but these allies must be those included in the treaty.
The same rule holds good, even if the allies themselves have not made the treaty, but others have done so on their behalf: since it is evident that those allies regarded the peace as ratified and valid. For they are looked upon as enemies, till it is certain they have consented to the ratification.
The same rule applies, even if the allies themselves didn’t make the treaty, but others did it on their behalf: because it’s clear that those allies considered the peace as confirmed and valid. They are seen as enemies until it’s established that they have agreed to the ratification.
Other allies, or connections, who are neither subjects nor named in the treaty of peace, form a distinct class, to whom any violence done cannot be construed into an act of breaking the peace. Yet it does not follow that war may not be undertaken on such an account, but then it will be a war resting entirely upon new grounds.
Other allies or connections, who are neither subjects nor mentioned in the peace treaty, form a separate category, and any violence against them cannot be seen as breaking the peace. However, this doesn't mean that war can't be waged for such reasons; it would just be a war based entirely on new grounds.
XXXIV. A peace is broken by doing any thing contrary396 to the express terms of it; and by this is likewise meant the non-performance of engagements.
XXXIV. A peace is violated by doing anything against396 the clear terms of it; and this also includes failing to fulfill commitments.
XXXV. Nor can we admit of any distinction between articles of greater or minor importance.
XXXV. We can't make any distinction between items of greater or lesser importance.
For ALL the articles of a treaty are of sufficient magnitude to require observance, though Christian charity may overlook the breach of them upon due acknowledgement. But to provide greater security for the continuance of a peace, proper clauses will be annexed to the minor articles, stating that any thing done against them shall not be deemed an infraction of the treaty: or that mediation shall be adopted in preference to having recourse to arms.
For ALL the articles of a treaty are significant enough to require adherence, although Christian kindness might overlook violations if they are acknowledged. However, to ensure a lasting peace, appropriate clauses will be added to the minor articles, stating that any actions taken against them will not be considered a violation of the treaty: or that mediation should be favored over resorting to military action.
XXXVI. This seems to have been plainly done in treaties, where any special penalty was annexed. A treaty indeed may be made upon, terms allowing the injured party his option either of enacting the penalty, or receding from his engagement: but the nature of the business rather requires the method of mediation. It is evident and proved from the authority of history, that one of the parties, who has not fulfilled his engagement, owing to the neglect of the other to do so, is by no means guilty of breaking the peace: as his obligation was only conditional.
XXXVI. It seems that this has been clearly shown in treaties where any specific penalty was attached. A treaty can indeed be made with terms that let the injured party choose either to enforce the penalty or to back out of their commitment: however, the nature of the situation calls for mediation instead. It's evident and supported by historical evidence that one party who hasn’t honored their commitment, due to the other party’s failure to do so, is not at all guilty of breaking the peace: their obligation was only conditional.
XXXVII. If there is any unavoidable necessity to prevent one party from fulfilling his engagement, as for instance, if a thing has been destroyed, or carried off, by which the restoration of it has become impossible, a peace shall not thereby be deemed broken, the continuance of it not depending upon CASUAL conditions. But the other party may have his option, either to prefer waiting, if there is any reason to hope that the engagement may be fulfilled at some future period, or to receive an equivalent, or to be released, on his side from some corresponding article of the treaty.
XXXVII. If there’s an unavoidable reason that stops one party from fulfilling their commitment, like if something has been destroyed or taken away, making it impossible to restore, the peace shouldn’t be considered broken, as its continuation isn't based on Laid-back conditions. However, the other party can choose either to wait, if there’s any hope that the commitment can be fulfilled later, or to accept an equivalent, or to be released from some corresponding part of the agreement.
XXXVIII. It is honourable, and laudable to maintain a peace, even after it has been violated by the other party: as Scipio did, after the many treacherous acts of the Carthaginians. For no one can release himself from an obligation by acting contrary to his engagements. And though it may be further said that the peace is broken by such an act, yet the breach ought to be taken in favour of the innocent party, if he thinks proper to avail himself of it.
XXXVIII. It is honorable and commendable to uphold peace, even after the other party has violated it, just like Scipio did after the many betrayal acts of the Carthaginians. No one can free themselves from an obligation by acting against their commitments. While it can be argued that such an act breaks the peace, the breach should be recognized in favor of the innocent party if they choose to take advantage of it.
XXXIX. Lastly, a peace is broken by the violation of any special and express clause in the treaty.
XXXIX. Finally, a peace agreement is violated by breaking any specific and explicit terms in the treaty.
397 XL. In the same manner, those powers, who commit unfriendly acts, are guilty of breaking that peace, which was made solely upon condition of amicable relations being preserved. For what, in other cases, the duties of friendship alone would require, must here be performed by the law of treaty.
397 XL. Similarly, those powers that engage in hostile actions violate the peace that was established on the condition of maintaining friendly relations. What would typically be expected of friendship in other situations must, in this case, be fulfilled by the terms of the treaty.
And it is to treaties of this kind that many points may be referred, which are discussed by legal writers, relating to injuries done without force of arms, and to the offences of insults. According to this principle, Tully has observed, that any offence committed after a reconciliation is not to be imputed to neglect, but to wilful violation, not to imprudence, but to treachery.
And it's to treaties like these that many issues can be referred, which legal scholars discuss regarding injuries caused without the use of force and offenses involving insults. Following this principle, Tully noted that any offense committed after a reconciliation shouldn't be seen as neglect, but rather as a willful violation; not as imprudence, but as treachery.
But here it is necessary, if possible, to exclude from the account every charge of an odious kind. So that an injury done to a relation or subject of the person, with whom a treaty of peace has been made, is not to be deemed the same, as one done to himself, unless there are evident proofs that, through them, an attack upon him was intended. And an invasion of another's rights is often to be ascribed to new motives of rapacity, rather than to those of treachery.
But here it's important, if possible, to rule out any charges of a nasty kind. So, an injury done to a relative or a subject of the person with whom a peace treaty has been made shouldn't be considered the same as one done to him personally, unless there’s clear evidence that it was intended as an attack on him. Also, an invasion of someone else's rights is often driven more by fresh motives of greed than by those of betrayal.
Atrocious menaces, without any new grounds of offence, are repugnant to all terms of amity. Any one may assume this threatening posture, by erecting new fortifications in his territory, as a means of annoyance rather than offence, by raising an unusual number of forces: when it is evident that these preparations can be designed against no one, but the power with whom he has concluded peace.
Atrocious threats, without any new reasons for conflict, are unacceptable to all agreements of friendship. Anyone can take this intimidating stance by building new defenses in their territory, using it more to irritate than to attack, by gathering an unusual amount of troops, especially when it's clear that these actions are aimed at no one but the power they’ve made peace with.
XLI. Nor is it contrary to the relations of amity to receive individual subjects, who wish to remove from the dominions of one power to those of another. For that is not only a principle of natural liberty, but favourable to the general intercourse of mankind. On the same grounds a refuge given to exiles may be justified. But it is not lawful to receive whole towns, or great bodies, forming an integral part of the state. Nor is it more allowable to receive those, who are bound to the service of their own state by oath or other engagement.
XLI. It's not against friendly relations to accept individuals who want to move from one country to another. This is not only a natural right, but it also promotes the overall interaction among people. For the same reasons, offering refuge to exiles can be justified. However, it isn't acceptable to accept entire towns or large groups that are an essential part of a state. It's also not acceptable to take in those who are obligated to serve their own state through an oath or other commitment.
The other kind of arbitration is where a matter ought to be left to the decision of a person, in whose integrity confidence may be placed, of which Celsus has given us an example in his answer, where he says, "though a freedman has sworn, that he will do all the services, which his patron may adjudge, the will of the patron ought not to be ratified, unless his determination be just."
The other type of arbitration is where a matter should be left to the decision of someone who is trustworthy, as Celsus provides an example in his response, stating, "even if a freedman has sworn to perform all the services that his patron may require, the patron's wishes shouldn't be approved unless his decision is fair."
This interpretation of an oath, though conformable to the Roman laws, is by no means consistent with the simplicity of language considered by itself. For the justice of the case remains the same, in whatever way an arbiter is chosen, whether it be to reconcile contending parties, a character, in which we find the Athenians acting between the Rhodians and Demetrius, or to make an absolute decree.
This understanding of an oath, while it aligns with Roman laws, doesn’t quite match the straightforwardness of the language when viewed on its own. The fairness of the situation stays the same, regardless of how an arbiter is selected, whether that's to mediate between opposing parties, like the Athenians did between the Rhodians and Demetrius, or to issue a final ruling.
Although the civil law may decide upon the conduct of such arbiters to whom a compromise is referred, so as to allow of an appeal from their decrees, or of complaints against their injustice, this can never take place between kings and nations. For here there is no superior power, that can either rivet or relax the bonds of an engagement. The decree therefore of such arbiters must be final and without appeal.
Although civil law can determine the actions of arbitrators to whom a compromise is referred, allowing for appeals from their decisions or complaints about their unfairness, this doesn't apply between kings and nations. In this case, there is no higher authority that can reinforce or loosen the terms of an agreement. Therefore, the decision of such arbitrators must be final and unappealable.
XLVII. With respect to the office of an arbiter or mediator, it is proper to inquire, whether the person has been appointed in the character of a judge, or with powers more extensive and discretionary than legal powers. Aristotle says that "an equitable and moderate man will have recourse to arbitration rather than to strict law, ADDING AS A REASON, because an arbitrator may consider the equity of the case, whereas a judge is bound by the letter of the law. Therefore arbitration was introduced to give equity its due weight."
XLVII. When it comes to the role of an arbiter or mediator, it’s important to determine whether the person has been appointed as a judge or has been given broader and more flexible powers than the law allows. Aristotle states that "a fair and reasonable person will turn to arbitration instead of strict law, Adding as a reason, because an arbitrator can take the fairness of the situation into account, while a judge is restricted by the exact wording of the law. So, arbitration was created to ensure fairness is appropriately considered."
Equity does not signify in this place, as it does elsewhere, that part of justice, which gives a strict interpretation of the general expressions of the law, according to the intention of the law-giver. For that is left to the judge. But it includes every thing, which it is more proper to do than to omit, even beyond what is required by the express rules of justice.—Such kind of arbitration being common among individuals and subjects of the same empire, it is recommended by St. Paul as a practice peculiarly proper for Christians. Yet in doubtful cases399 it ought not to be presumed that such extensive powers are granted. For where there is any obscurity it abridges this latitude of decision: and especially in contested matters, between independent sovereigns, who, having no common judge, are supposed to bind the mediators, and arbitrators, whom they chuse, by the strictest rules of law.
Equity doesn't mean here, as it does in other places, the part of justice that gives a strict interpretation of the law's general statements according to the intention of the lawmaker. That role is left to the judge. Instead, it includes everything that it's more appropriate to do than to leave undone, even beyond what is required by the specific rules of justice. This kind of arbitration is common among individuals and subjects within the same empire, and St. Paul recommends it as a practice especially suitable for Christians. However, in uncertain situations399, we shouldn't assume that such broad powers are given. Where there is any ambiguity, it limits this flexibility in decision-making, especially in disputed matters between independent sovereigns, who, having no common judge, are assumed to bind the mediators and arbitrators they choose by the strictest rules of law.
XLVIII. It is to be observed that arbitrators chosen by nations or sovereign princes may decide upon the matter in dispute, but not confer a possession, which is a matter that can only be decided by established rules of civil law, for by the law of nations the right of possession follows the right of property. Therefore while a cause is pending, no innovation ought to be made, both to prevent partiality and prejudice, and because, after possession has been given, recovery is difficult. Livy in his account of some disputed points between the people of Carthage and Masinissa says, "the Ambassadors did not change the right of possession."
XLVIII. It's important to note that arbitrators selected by nations or sovereign leaders can resolve the dispute at hand, but they can't grant possession, which can only be determined by established civil law. According to international law, the right to possession follows the right to property. Therefore, while a case is ongoing, no changes should be made to avoid bias and prejudgment, and because once possession is granted, it's hard to reclaim. Livy, in his discussion of some disputed issues between the people of Carthage and Masinissa, states, "the Ambassadors did not change the right of possession."
XLIX. There is another kind of arbitration, which takes place, when any one makes an absolute surrender of himself and all his rights to an enemy or foreign power. But still a distinction ought to be made, even here, between the bounds of right and wrong, limiting the submission of the vanquished, on the one hand, and the authority of the conqueror, on the other, to a certain degree.
XLIX. There’s another type of arbitration that happens when someone completely surrenders themselves and all their rights to an enemy or foreign power. However, even in this case, it’s important to recognize a difference between what’s right and wrong, which limits how much the defeated can submit and how much authority the conqueror has, to some extent.
For there are particular duties, which ought to be observed in the exercise of EVERY right. Taking the right of the conqueror in its literal meaning and full extent, it is true that he is entitled to impose ANY terms upon the conquered, who is now placed, by the external laws of war, in a situation to be deprived of every thing, even personal liberty or life, much more then, of all his property, either of a public or private kind.
For there are specific responsibilities that should be followed when exercising EVERY right. Taking the conqueror's right in its literal and full sense, it is true that they have the authority to impose ANY conditions on the conquered, who is now, due to the external laws of war, in a position where they can be stripped of everything, including personal freedom or life, and even more so, all their property, whether public or private.
L. The first object of a conqueror should be to avoid committing any act of injustice, or using any rigour, except the demerits and atrocity of the enemy require it; to take nothing but by way of lawful punishment. Observing these bounds, as far as security allows, it is always laudable to incline to moderation and clemency. Sometimes even circumstances may require such a line of conduct, and the best conclusion of any war is that, which reconciles all contending claims by a fair adjustment, and a general amnesty. The moderation and clemency to400 which the vanquished appeal, are by no means an abolition but only a mitigation of the conqueror's absolute right.
L. The first goal of a conqueror should be to avoid any acts of injustice or cruelty, unless the enemy's wrongdoings and brutality demand it; to take nothing except through lawful punishment. As much as security allows, it's always commendable to lean toward moderation and mercy. Sometimes circumstances may necessitate this approach, and the best outcome of any war is one that resolves all opposing claims through a fair settlement and a general pardon. The moderation and mercy that the defeated ask for do not eliminate but rather lessen the conqueror's absolute right.
LI. There are conditional surrenders, reserving to the individuals, certain personal privileges, and remains of their property, and to the state, certain parts of its constitution.
LI. There are conditional surrenders that allow individuals to keep certain personal privileges and some of their property, while the state retains certain aspects of its constitution.
LII. Hostages and pledges may be considered as an appendage to treaties. And some of those hostages are a voluntary surrender, and others given by authority of the state as a security. For the sovereign has the same power over the persons and actions of his subjects, as over their property. But the state or its ruler will be bound to recompense individuals or their relatives for any inconveniences they may sustain.
LII. Hostages and pledges can be seen as an addition to treaties. Some of these hostages are voluntarily surrendered, while others are provided by the state as a form of security. The sovereign has the same control over the people and actions of their subjects as they do over their property. However, the state or its ruler is obligated to compensate individuals or their families for any hardships they may experience.
LIII. Though the law of nations may in its literal rigour allow of putting hostages to death, it can never conscientiously be enforced, but where they have committed crimes deserving of capital punishment. Neither can they be made slaves. Indeed the law of nations permits them to leave their property to their heirs, although by the Roman law provision was made for confiscating it to the state.
LIII. Although international law may technically permit the execution of hostages, it should never be applied in practice unless they have committed offenses warranting the death penalty. They also cannot be enslaved. In fact, international law allows them to bequeath their property to their heirs, even though Roman law provided for its confiscation by the state.
LIV. If it should be asked whether hostages may lawfully make their escape: it may be answered in the negative, especially if, at first, or afterwards, they have pledged their faith to remain, upon condition of being prisoners at large. But it does not appear that states so much intended to impose a hardship upon their subjects by forbidding their escape, as to give the enemy security for the performance of their engagements.
LIV. If someone asks whether hostages can legally escape, the answer is no, especially if they have initially promised to stay, on the condition that they would be treated as free prisoners. However, it doesn't seem that countries intended to make life harder for their people by prohibiting their escape; rather, they aimed to provide the enemy with assurance that their agreements would be honored.
LV. The obligation of hostages is of an odious nature, as being unfriendly to personal liberty, and arising from the act of another. Therefore a strict interpretation must be given to such engagements, so that hostages delivered on one account cannot be detained on any other, nor for any contract, where hostages are not required. But if in another case there has been any violation of good faith, or any debt contracted, hostages may be detained, not as hostages, but in the capacity of subjects, whom the law of nations makes liable to be seized and detained for the acts of their sovereigns. To guard against which, provision may be made by additional clauses for the restoration of hostages, whenever the engagement for which they were delivered has been fulfilled.
LV. The duty of hostages is an unpleasant situation since it goes against personal freedom and is caused by someone else's actions. Therefore, these agreements must be understood strictly, meaning that hostages given for one reason cannot be held for any other reason or for any agreements that don't require hostages. However, if there has been a breach of trust or a debt incurred in a different case, hostages can be held, not as hostages, but as individuals that international law allows to be taken and held accountable for their rulers' actions. To prevent this, additional clauses can be included to ensure that hostages are returned as soon as the agreement for which they were given has been honored.
401 LVI. Whoever has been delivered as a hostage for other prisoners, or for the redemption of other hostages, will naturally be released upon the death of those persons. For by death the right of the pledge is extinguished in the same manner as by the ransom of a prisoner. And therefore, according to Ulpian, as a PERSONAL debt is confined to him, who has contracted it, so one person, being substituted for another, cannot be detained any longer than while the obligation of that other continues.
401 LVI. Anyone who has been held as a hostage for other prisoners, or for the release of other hostages, will naturally be set free upon the death of those individuals. This is because, when someone dies, the right to the pledge is canceled just like it is when a prisoner is ransomed. Therefore, according to Ulpian, just as a PERSONAL debt is limited to the person who incurred it, one person standing in for another cannot be held any longer than the obligation of that other person remains.
LVII. The decision, whether hostages can be detained upon the death of the sovereign, by whom they were delivered, must depend upon the nature of the engagements, which he has made. If they are PERSONAL, they continue in force only during his natural life, but if they are what are called REAL or more PERMANENT treaties, they pass with all their consequences to his successors. For ACCESSORY articles cannot authorise any deviation from the GENERAL rule of interpreting the fundamental and principal points of a treaty, but the accessory articles themselves ought rather to be explained in conformity to those general rules.
LVII. The decision about whether hostages can be held after the death of the sovereign who delivered them depends on the type of agreements he made. If they are PERSONAL, they only last during his lifetime, but if they are what are termed REAL or more Lifelong treaties, they transfer with all their consequences to his successors. Accessory articles cannot justify any deviations from the GENERAL rule for interpreting the key points of a treaty; instead, the accessory articles themselves should be explained in line with those general rules.
LVIII. A cursory observation may be made, that hostages are sometimes considered, not as appendages, but as forming the principal part of an engagement, where any one is bound not for himself, but for another, and, in case of non-performance, being obliged to pay damages, his hostages or sureties are answerable in his stead.—There is not only some thing of harshness, but even injustice in the opinion that hostages may be bound for the conduct of another even without their own consent.
LVIII. A quick observation can be made that hostages are sometimes seen, not as accessories, but as the main part of an agreement, where someone is obligated not for themselves, but for another person, and, in case of failure to fulfill the obligation, they must pay damages, with their hostages or guarantors held responsible in their place. — There is not only something harsh, but even unjust in the belief that hostages can be held accountable for another's actions without their own consent.
LIX. Pledges have some characteristics in common with hostages, and some peculiar to themselves. It is a common characteristic of both to be detained for something else that is due, except where public faith is given, and provision made to the contrary. Pledges may be detained with greater latitude than hostages; which is one of their peculiar characteristics, there being less of odium in the former case than in the latter: THINGS being of a nature more proper for detention than PERSONS.
LIX. Pledges share some traits with hostages but also have unique aspects. Both are typically held as security for something else that is owed, unless there's a promise made otherwise. Pledges can be held with more flexibility than hostages; this is one of their unique features, as it's generally less morally questionable to detain items than people: STUFF are more suitable for detention than People.
LX. No time can bar the redemption of a pledge, whenever the engagement for which it was given is fulfilled. For it is never to be presumed that engagements402 proceed from new causes, when old and known causes can be assigned. If a debtor therefore has forborne to redeem a pledge, we may still suppose that he has not abandoned his original engagement, unless there be clear proof to the contrary: as if, for instance, though desirous of redeeming it, he has been prevented, or suffered a space of time to elapse unnoticed, that would be requisite to imply his consent.
LX. No time can prevent the redemption of a pledge as long as the obligation for which it was given is fulfilled. It shouldn't be assumed that obligations402 arise from new reasons when there are existing and recognized reasons that can be identified. Therefore, if a debtor has delayed redeeming a pledge, we can still assume that he hasn't given up on his original obligation unless there's clear proof otherwise: for example, if he genuinely wants to redeem it but has been prevented from doing so, or if he has let a period of time pass without attention, which would imply his consent.
CHAPTER XXI.
On Faith During Ongoing War, on Ceasefires, Safe Conducts, and the Ransom of Prisoners.
Truces of an intermediate denomination between peace and war—Origin of the word—New declaration of war not necessary after a truce—Time from whence a truce and all its correspondent obligations and privileges commence—A retreat may be made, or fortifications repaired during a truce—Distinction respecting the occupying of places—The case of a person prevented from making his retreat, and taken in the enemy's territories at the expiration of a truce, considered—Express terms and consequences of a truce—Breach of a truce by one party justifies a renewal of war by the other—Penalty annexed—Truce broken by the acts of individuals—Rights belonging to safe-conducts without a truce—Persons in a military capacity how far allowed the benefit of a safe-conduct—Privileges of goods arising from thence—Attendants of the person protected by a safe-conduct—Safe-conduct does not expire upon the death of the grantor—Safe-conduct given to continue during the pleasure of the grantor—Protection thereof extending beyond his own territory—Redemption of prisoners favoured, and not to be prohibited by law.
Temporary agreements that exist between peace and war—Origin of the term—No need for a new declaration of war after a temporary agreement—The start time for a temporary agreement and all its related obligations and benefits—A retreat can occur, or defenses can be repaired during a temporary agreement—Disputes about occupying locations—The situation of someone unable to retreat and stuck in enemy land when a temporary agreement ends—Specific terms and outcomes of a temporary agreement—If one side violates the agreement, the other side can rightfully return to war—Consequences involved—A temporary agreement can be broken by individual actions—Rights related to safe passage without a temporary agreement—How individuals in military roles can gain from safe passage—Benefits for goods resulting from this—Supporters of the person receiving safe passage—Safe passage doesn't end with the grantor's death—Safe passages are issued to last as long as the grantor desires—Protections extend beyond their own territory—The redemption of prisoners is encouraged and shouldn't be limited by law.
I. and II. In the midst of war there are certain points generally conceded by the belligerent powers to each other, which Tacitus and Virgil call the intercourse of war, and which comprehend truces, safe-conducts, and the redemption of prisoners.—Truces are conventions, by which, even during the continuance of war, hostilities on each side cease for a time. During the continuance of war; for, as Cicero says, in his eighth Philippic, between peace and war there is no medium. By war is meant a state of affairs, which may exist even while its operations are not continued. Therefore, as Gellius has said, a peace and a truce are not the same, for the war still continues, though fighting may cease. So that any agreement, deemed valid in the time of war, will be valid also during a truce, unless it evidently appears that it is not the state of affairs, which is considered, but the commission of particular acts of hostility. On the other hand, any thing, agreed to, to be done, when peace shall be made, cannot take place in consequence of a truce. There is no uniform and invariable period fixed for the continuance of a truce, it404 may be made for any time, even for twenty, or thirty years, of which there are many instances in ancient history. A truce, though a repose from war, does not amount to a peace, therefore historians are correct in saying that a peace has often been refused, when a truce has been granted.
I. and II. In the middle of war, there are certain points that the warring parties usually agree on, which Tacitus and Virgil refer to as the interactions of war. These include truces, safe-conducts, and the release of prisoners. — Truces are agreements where, even while war is ongoing, fighting on both sides temporarily stops. During the ongoing war; because, as Cicero mentions in his eighth Philippic, there’s no middle ground between peace and war. War refers to a situation that can exist even if fighting isn’t actively taking place. Thus, as Gellius noted, peace and a truce are not the same, since the war continues even if combat stops. Therefore, any agreement considered valid during wartime remains valid during a truce, unless it’s clear that the focus is on specific acts of hostility rather than the overall situation. Conversely, anything agreed upon to take place when peace is established cannot occur due to a truce. There’s no fixed or standard duration for a truce; it404 can last for any length of time, even twenty or thirty years, with many examples from ancient history. A truce, while a break from fighting, does not equate to peace; thus, historians are correct in stating that peace has often been denied even when a truce has been allowed.
III. After a truce a new declaration of war is not necessary.
III. After a truce, a new declaration of war isn't needed.
For upon the removal of a temporary impediment, the state of warfare revives in full force, which has only been lulled asleep, but not extinguished. Yet we read in Livy, that it was the opinion of the heralds' college, that after the expiration of a truce war ought to be declared. But the ancient Romans only meant to shew by those superfluous precautions, how much they loved peace, and upon what just grounds they were dragged into war.
For once a temporary obstacle is removed, the state of war reactivates fully; it was only put to sleep, not completely ended. However, we read in Livy that the heralds' council believed that after a truce ends, war should be declared. The ancient Romans intended to demonstrate through those extra precautions how much they valued peace and the legitimate reasons that forced them into war.
IV. The time, generally assigned for the continuance of a truce, is either some uninterrupted period, of a HUNDRED DAYS, for instance, or a space limited by some artificial boundary of time, as the Calends of March. In the former case, the calculation is to be made according to the natural motion of time: whereas all civil computations depend upon the laws and customs of each country. In the other case it is generally made a matter of doubt, whether in naming any particular day, month or year, for the expiration of a truce, that particular day, month, or year, are comprehended in the term of the truce, or excluded from it.
IV. The duration of a truce is typically set as either a continuous period, like a Hundred Days, or a timeframe defined by a specific date, such as the Calends of March. In the first scenario, the calculation follows the natural passage of time, while all civil measurements rely on the laws and customs of each country. In the second scenario, there's often uncertainty about whether a specific day, month, or year mentioned for the end of a truce is included within that period or not.
In natural things there are two kinds of boundaries, one of which forms an inseparable part of the things themselves, as the skin does of the body, and the other only adjoins them, as a river adjoins the land, which it bounds or washes. In either of these ways voluntary boundaries may be appointed. But it seems more natural for a boundary to be taken as a part of the thing itself. Aristotle defines the extremity of anything to be its boundary: a meaning to which general custom conforms:—thus if any one has said that a thing is to be done before the day of his death, the day on which he actually dies is to be taken into the account as forming part of the term. Spurinna had apprised Caesar of his danger, which could not extend beyond the Ides of March. Being accosted, respecting the matter, on the very day, he said, the Ides of March are come, but not passed. Such an interpretation is the more proper where the prolongation405 of time is of a favourable nature, as it is in truces, which are calculated to suspend the effusion of human blood.
In natural things, there are two types of boundaries. One is an inseparable part of the things themselves, like skin is to the body, and the other just touches them, like a river touches the land it borders or washes. Boundaries can be voluntarily established in either of these ways. However, it seems more natural to consider a boundary as a part of the thing itself. Aristotle defines the boundary of anything as its extremity, which aligns with common understanding: if someone states that something must happen before their death, the actual day they die is included as part of that timeframe. Spurinna warned Caesar about his danger, which could not extend beyond the Ides of March. When asked about it on that very day, he replied, the Ides of March have come, but not yet passed. This kind of interpretation is more appropriate when the extension of time is favorable, as with truces, which are meant to stop the shedding of human blood.
The day, FROM which any measure of time is said to begin, cannot be taken into the account; because the word, FROM, used on that occasion, implies separation and not conjunction.
The day, FROM which any measure of time is said to begin, cannot be counted; because the word, FROM, used in that context, suggests separation and not connection.
V. It is to be observed that truces, and engagements of that kind immediately bind the contracting parties themselves from the very moment they are concluded. But the subjects on either side are only bound from the time that those engagements have received the form of a law, for which public notice and the regular promulgation are necessary. Upon this being done they immediately derive their authority to bind the subjects. But if notice thereof has only been given in one place, the observance of them cannot be enforced through the whole dominions of the respective sovereigns at one moment, but sufficient time must be allowed for the due promulgation of them to be made in every part. Therefore if in the meantime the subjects on either side have committed an infraction of the truce, they shall be exempt from punishment, but the contracting parties themselves shall be obliged to repair the damages.
V. It's important to note that truces and agreements like these immediately commit the parties involved the moment they are finalized. However, individuals on either side are only bound once these agreements are formalized as law, which requires public notice and proper announcement. Once this is done, they gain the authority to hold individuals accountable. If notice has only been given in one location, compliance can't be enforced throughout the entire territories of the respective rulers all at once; a reasonable amount of time must be provided for the proper announcement to reach every area. Therefore, if individuals on either side violate the truce during this period, they will not face punishment, but the parties who made the agreement will be required to compensate for any damages.
VI. The very definition of a truce implies what actions are lawful, and what are unlawful during the continuance of it. All acts of hostility are unlawful either against the persons or goods of an enemy. For every act of violence during a truce is contrary to the law of nations. Even things belonging to an enemy, which by any accident have fallen into our hands, although they had been ours before, must be restored. Because they had become theirs by that external right according to which such things are adjudged. And this is what Paulus the lawyer says, that during the time of a truce the law of postliminium cannot exist, because to constitute the law of postliminium there must be the previous right of making captures in war, which ceases upon the making of a truce.
VI. The definition of a truce clearly outlines what actions are acceptable and unacceptable while it lasts. Any acts of aggression against an enemy's people or property are not allowed. Every violent act during a truce goes against international law. Even items belonging to an enemy that accidentally come into our possession, even if they were once ours, must be returned. This is because they are considered the enemy's property by the rights that apply in such situations. Paulus, the lawyer, notes that during a truce, the law of postliminium does not apply, because for postliminium to be valid, there must be a prior right to capture in war, which is suspended when a truce is in effect.
Either party may go to or return from, any particular place, but without any warlike apparatus or force, that may prove a means of annoyance, or be attended with any danger. This is observed by Servius on that passage of Virgil, where the poet says, "the Latins mingled with their foes with impunity," where he relates also that406 upon a truce being made between Porsenna and the Romans during a siege, when the games of the circus were celebrating, the generals of the enemy entered the city, contented in the lists, and were many of them crowned as conquerors.
Either side can go to or come back from any specific location, but they must not bring any weapons or forces that could cause trouble or pose a threat. Servius comments on this in relation to a line from Virgil, where the poet mentions, "the Latins mixed with their enemies without fear." He also notes that during a truce between Porsenna and the Romans amid a siege, while the circus games were being held, the enemy generals entered the city, happily participating in the competitions, and many of them were crowned as victors.
VII. To withdraw farther into the country with an army, which we find from Livy that Philip did, is no way contrary to the intention and principles of a truce: neither is it any breach of it to repair the walls of a place, or to raise new forces, unless it has been prohibited by special agreement.
VII. To retreat further into the countryside with an army, as we see from Livy that Philip did, is not against the purpose and principles of a truce: nor is it considered a violation to repair the walls of a location or to gather new troops, unless specifically banned by a formal agreement.
VIII. To corrupt an enemy's garrisons, in order to seize upon the places which he holds, is undoubtedly a breach of the spirit and letter of any truce. For no such advantage can justly be gained but by the laws of war. The same rule is to be laid down respecting the revolt of subjects to an enemy. In the fourth book of Thucydides, Brasidas received the city of Menda, that revolted from the Athenians to the Lacedaemonians during a truce, and excused his conduct upon the plea of the Athenians having done the same.
VIII. Corrupting an enemy's garrisons to take control of the places they occupy is definitely a violation of both the spirit and the letter of any truce. Such an advantage can only be rightfully gained through the laws of war. The same principle applies to the defection of subjects to an enemy. In the fourth book of Thucydides, Brasidas captured the city of Menda, which had rebelled from the Athenians to the Lacedaemonians during a truce, justifying his actions by claiming that the Athenians did the same.
Either of the belligerent powers may take possession of places that have been deserted: if they have been REALLY deserted by the former owner with the intention never to occupy them again, but not merely because they have been left unguarded, either BEFORE, or AFTER, the making of a truce. For the former owner's right of dominion therein still remaining renders another's possession of them unjust. Which is a complete refutation of the cavil of Belisarius against the Goths, who seized upon some places during a truce, under pretext of their being left without garrisons.
Either of the warring powers can take control of places that have been abandoned, but only if they have been REALLY abandoned by the previous owner with the intention of never returning, and not just because they were left unguarded, either BEFORE or AFTER a truce was made. This is because the previous owner's rights still apply, making it unfair for someone else to claim those places. This completely disproves Belisarius's argument against the Goths, who took over certain locations during a truce, claiming they were unprotected.
IX. It is made a subject of inquiry, whether any one being prevented by an unforeseen accident from making his retreat, and being taken within the enemy's territories, at the expiration of a truce, has a right to return. Considering the external law of nations he is undoubtedly upon the same footing as one, who, having gone into a foreign country must, upon the sudden breaking out of war, be detained there as an enemy till the return of peace. Nor is there any thing contrary to strict justice in this; as the goods and persons of enemies are bound for the debt of the state, and may be seized for payment. Nor has such a one more reason to complain than innumerable other innocent persons, on whose heads407 the calamities of war have fallen. Nor is there occasion to refer to the case, which Cicero has alleged, in his second book On Invention, of a ship of war driven by the violence of the wind into a port, where by law it was liable to confiscation. For in the former case the unforeseen accident must do away all idea of punishment, and in the latter, the right of confiscation must be suspended for a time. Yet there can be no doubt but there is more of generosity and kindness in releasing such a person than in insisting upon the right of detaining him.
IX. There is a question of whether someone, who is unexpectedly unable to retreat and is captured within enemy territory after a truce has ended, has the right to return. Considering international law, this person is essentially treated the same as someone who, having entered a foreign country, must remain there as an enemy until peace is restored when war suddenly breaks out. There is nothing unjust about this, as the goods and individuals of enemies can be held for the state’s debts and may be seized for payment. This person has no more reason to complain than many other innocent individuals who also suffer the consequences of war. There's no need to refer to the example Cicero mentioned in his second book On Innovation, about a warship blown by the wind into a port where it could be legally confiscated. In the first case, the unforeseen accident should eliminate any notion of punishment, while in the second case, the right to confiscate should be paused for a while. Still, there’s no doubt that it's more generous and compassionate to release such a person than to insist on their detention.
X. The express nature of a convention renders some things unlawful during a truce, as for instance, if it is granted only in order to bury the dead, neither party will have a right to depart from those conditions. Thus if a siege is suspended by a truce, and nothing more than such a suspension is thereby granted; the besieged cannot lawfully avail himself of it, to convey fresh supplies of troops and stores into the place. For such conventions ought not to prove beneficial to one party, to the prejudice of the other, who grants them. Sometimes it is stipulated that no one shall be allowed to pass to and fro. Sometimes the prohibition extends to persons and not to goods. In which case, if any one, in protecting his goods, hurts an enemy, the act will not constitute a breach of the truce. For as it is lawful that either party should defend his property, an accidental circumstance cannot be deemed an infringement of that personal security, which was the principal object provided for by the truce.
X. The clear terms of a truce make some things unlawful during its duration. For example, if a truce is declared solely for the purpose of burying the dead, neither side can deviate from those terms. So, if a siege is paused by a truce and nothing more than that is allowed, the side being besieged cannot legally use it to bring in new troops or supplies. Such agreements should not benefit one side at the expense of the other that grants them. Sometimes it’s agreed that no one can move back and forth. Other times, the ban applies to people but not to goods. In that case, if someone harms an enemy while protecting their goods, it won't be considered a violation of the truce. Since it is permissible for either side to defend their property, an accidental act cannot be seen as a breach of the personal safety that the truce mainly aims to ensure.
XI. If the faith of a truce is broken by one of the parties, the other who is thereby injured, will undoubtedly have a right to renew hostilities without any formal declaration. For every article in a treaty contains an implied condition of mutual observance. Indeed we may find in history instances of those, who have adhered to a truce till its expiration, notwithstanding a breach on the other side. But on the other hand there are numerous instances of hostilities commenced against those, who have broken their conventions: a variation, which proves that it is at the option of the injured party to use or not to use his right of renewing war upon the breach of a truce.
XI. If one side breaks the faith of a truce, the other side that is harmed has the right to resume hostilities without any formal declaration. Every article in a treaty implies a mutual agreement to uphold it. In fact, history shows instances where people have stuck to a truce until it ended, even with a breach from the other party. However, there are also many cases where hostilities were launched against those who violated their agreements: this variation shows that it’s up to the injured party to decide whether or not to use their right to restart the war after a truce has been broken.
XII. It is evident that, if the stipulated penalty is demanded of the aggressor, and paid by him, the other party can no longer maintain his right of renewing the408 war. For the payment of the penalty restores every thing to its original footing. And on the other hand, a renewal of hostilities implies an intention of the injured party to abandon the penalty, since he has had his option.
XII. It’s clear that if the aggressor is required to pay the agreed penalty, the other party can no longer claim the right to restart the408war. Paying the penalty puts everything back to the way it was. On the flip side, resuming hostilities suggests that the injured party wants to give up the penalty, as they have had their choice.
XIII. A truce is not broken by the acts of individuals, unless they are sanctioned by the authority of the sovereign, which is generally supposed to be given, where the delinquents are neither punished nor delivered up, nor restitution is made of goods taken away.
XIII. A truce is not violated by the actions of individuals, unless those actions are approved by the sovereign’s authority, which is typically assumed to be granted when the offenders are neither punished nor handed over, and when no restitution is made for the stolen goods.
XIV. The rights belonging to a safe-conduct are a privilege distinct from the nature of a truce, and our interpretation of them must be guided by the rules laid down respecting privileges.
XIV. The rights that come with a safe-conduct are a privilege separate from the concept of a truce, and our understanding of them must follow the established rules regarding privileges.
Such a privilege, to be perfect, must be neither injurious to a third person, nor prejudicial to the giver. Therefore in explaining the terms, in which it is couched, a greater latitude of interpretation may be allowed, especially where the party suing for it receives no benefit, but rather confers one, and still more so where the advantage, accruing to the individual from thence, redounds also to the public benefit of the state.
Such a privilege, to be perfect, must not harm a third person or be detrimental to the giver. Therefore, when explaining the terms it is expressed in, more flexibility in interpretation can be permitted, especially when the person seeking it gains no benefit but actually provides one, and even more so when the advantage gained by the individual also contributes to the public benefit of the state.
Therefore the literal interpretation, which the words may bear, ought to be rejected, unless otherwise some absurdity would follow, or there is every reason to suppose that such a literal interpretation is most conformable to the will and intention of the parties concerned. In the same manner, on the other hand, a greater latitude of interpretation may be allowed, in order to avoid the same apprehended absurdity, or to comply more fully with the most urgent and forcible conjectures respecting the will of the contracting parties.
Therefore, the literal interpretation of the words should be dismissed unless it leads to an absurd outcome, or there’s a strong reason to believe that this literal interpretation aligns best with the will and intention of the parties involved. Similarly, a broader interpretation can be allowed to prevent the same perceived absurdity, or to better fulfill the most compelling and strong assumptions about the will of the contracting parties.
XV. Hence we may infer that a safe-conduct, granted to SOLDIERS, includes not only those of an INTERMEDIATE RANK, but the HIGHEST COMMANDERS. For that is a signification strictly and properly authorised by the words themselves, although they MAY be taken in a more LIMITED meaning. So the term clergymen includes those of episcopal as well as those of inferior rank, and by those serving on board a fleet, we mean not only sailors, but all persons found there, who have taken the military oath.
XV. Therefore, we can conclude that a safe-conduct granted to MILITARY PERSONNEL includes not just those of an Mid-level rank, but also the TOP COMMANDERS. This meaning is clearly and appropriately supported by the words themselves, even though they MAY be interpreted in a more LIMITED way. Similarly, the term clergymen encompasses both those who are episcopal and those of lower rank, and when we refer to those serving on a fleet, we mean not only sailors but also everyone present who has taken the military oath.
XVI. Where a free passage is granted, liberty to return is evidently implied, not from the literal force of the expressions themselves, but to avoid the absurdity which would follow the grant of a privilege, that could never409 be made use of. And by the liberty of coming and going is meant a safe passage till the person arrives in a place of perfect security. From hence the good faith of Alexander was impeached, who ordered those to be murdered on the way, whom he had allowed to depart.
XVI. When a free passage is given, the right to return is clearly implied, not because of the literal meaning of the words, but to avoid the ridiculous situation that would arise from granting a privilege that could never be used. By the right to come and go, it means a safe passage until the person reaches a place of complete security. Because of this, Alexander's good faith was questioned when he ordered those he had allowed to leave to be murdered on their way.
Any one may be allowed to go away without being allowed to return. But no power can properly refuse admitting any one, to whom he has granted leave to come, and on the other hand, his admission implies such a leave to have been given. Going away and RETURNING are indeed very different, nor can any construction of language give them the same meaning. If there be any mistake, although it may confer no right, it exempts the party from all penalties.—A person permitted to come shall only come ONCE, but not a SECOND TIME, unless the additional mention of some time may supply room to think otherwise.
Anyone can be allowed to leave without being allowed to come back. But no authority can properly refuse entry to someone they’ve granted permission to enter, and on the flip side, their entry means that such permission was given. Departing and RETURNING are clearly different, and no wording can make them mean the same thing. If there’s any mistake, even if it doesn’t grant a right, it protects the person from all penalties.—A person who is allowed to enter may only enter ONCE, but not a SECOND TIME, unless there's a specific mention of time that suggests otherwise.
XVII. A son shares the fate of his father, and a wife of her husband no farther than as to the right of residing, for men reside with their families, but in general undertake public missions without them. Yet one or two servants, though not expressly named, are generally understood to be included in a safe-conduct, especially where it would be improper for the person to go without such attendants. For every necessary consequence is understood to go along with any privilege that is given.
XVII. A son shares the fate of his father, and a wife shares that of her husband only when it comes to where they live, because men typically live with their families but often take on public duties without them. However, one or two servants, even though not specifically mentioned, are usually thought to be included in a safe-conduct, especially when it would be inappropriate for the person to go without those attendants. Every necessary consequence is assumed to accompany any privilege granted.
XVIII. In the same manner no other effects are included in a safe-conduct, but such as are usually taken on a journey.
XVIII. Similarly, no other effects are covered by a safe-conduct, only those that are typically taken on a journey.
XIX. The name of attendants, expressed in a safe-conduct, granted to any one, will not allow him to extend the protection of it to men of atrocious and criminal characters, such as pirates, robbers, and deserters. And the COUNTRY of the attendants being named shews that the protection cannot extend to those of another nation.
XIX. The names of the attendants listed in a safe conduct granted to someone do not allow that person to extend protection to individuals with terrible and criminal backgrounds, such as pirates, thieves, and deserters. Additionally, stating the COUNTRY of the attendants indicates that the protection does not apply to people from another nation.
XX. The privileges of a safe-conduct do not, in doubtful cases, expire upon the demise of the sovereign who granted it, according to what was said in a former part of this treatise on the nature of favours granted by kings and sovereign princes.
XX. The privileges of a safe-conduct do not, in uncertain situations, end with the death of the ruler who issued it, as mentioned earlier in this treatise regarding the nature of favors granted by kings and sovereign princes.
XXI. It has often been a disputed point, what is meant by the expression used in a safe-conduct, that it shall continue during the PLEASURE OF THE GRANTOR. But there seems most reason and truth in the opinion of those, who maintain that the privilege shall continue, till410 the grantor make some new declaration of his will to the contrary. Because, in doubtful cases, a favour is presumed to continue, till the right, which it conveys, is accomplished. But not so, where all possibility of WILL in the grantor has ceased, which happens by his death. For upon the death of the person all presumption of his WILL continuing must cease: as an accident vanishes when the substance is destroyed.
XXI. There's often been debate about what the phrase used in a safe-conduct means when it says it will continue during the GRANTOR'S PLEASURE. However, it makes the most sense to agree with those who argue that the privilege will last until410 the grantor makes a new declaration stating otherwise. In ambiguous situations, it's assumed that a favor will persist until the right it provides is fulfilled. But this doesn’t apply when the grantor can no longer express their WILL, which occurs upon their death. Once the person dies, all assumptions about their WILL continuing must end, just as an effect disappears when the cause is gone.
XXII. The privilege of a safe-conduct protects the person, to whom it is given, even beyond the territories of the grantor: because it is given as a protection against the rights of war, which are not confined to his territory.
XXII. The privilege of a safe-conduct protects the person to whom it is granted, even outside the lands of the grantor: because it is intended as protection against the rights of war, which are not limited to their territory.
XXIII. The redemption of prisoners is much favoured, particularly among Christian states, to whom the divine law peculiarly recommends it as a kind of mercy. Lactantius calls the redemption of prisoners a great and splendid office of justice.
XXIII. The rescue of prisoners is strongly supported, especially among Christian nations, to whom divine law especially endorses it as a form of compassion. Lactantius describes the rescue of prisoners as a significant and commendable act of justice.
CHAPTER XXII.
On the Faith in Those with Subordinate Powers in War.
Commanders—Extent of their engagements in binding the sovereign—Exceeding their commission—The opposite party bound by such engagements—Power of commanders in war, or of magistrates with respect to those under their authority—Generals cannot make peace, but may conclude a truce—Extent of their authority in granting protection to persons and property—Such engagements to be strictly interpreted—Interpretation of capitulations accepted by generals—Precautions necessary till the pleasure of the sovereign be known—Promise to surrender a town.
Commanders—The extent of their obligations to the sovereign—Exceeding their authority—The opposing side is bound by these obligations—The power of commanders in warfare or of magistrates over those they command—Generals cannot sign peace deals but can accept a truce—The limitations of their authority in ensuring safety for people and property—These obligations must be interpreted with precision—Clarification of agreements made by generals—Caution is required until the wishes of the sovereign are clear—Commitment to surrender a town.
I. Ulpian reckons the agreements, entered into between the generals of opposite armies during the course of a war, among public conventions. So that after explaining the nature of the faith pledged by sovereign powers to each other, it will be proper to make a short inquiry into the nature of engagements made by subordinate authorities; whether those authorities bear a near approach to supreme power, as commanders in chief, or are removed to a greater distance from it. Caesar makes the following distinction between them, observing that the offices of commander and deputy are very different; the latter being obliged to act according to prescribed rules, and the former having unqualified discretion in matters of the highest importance.
I. Ulpian considers the agreements made between the generals of opposing armies during a war as public conventions. After explaining the nature of the commitments made by sovereign powers to each other, it’s important to briefly explore the nature of agreements made by subordinate authorities; whether those authorities are close to supreme power, like commanders in chief, or more distanced from it. Caesar makes a clear distinction between the two, noting that the roles of commander and deputy are quite different; the deputy must follow established rules, while the commander has complete discretion in the most important matters.
II. The engagements of those invested with such subordinate powers are to be considered in a double point of view, whether they are binding upon the sovereign, or only upon themselves. The former of these points has been already settled in a former part of this treatise, where it was shewn that a person is bound by the measures of an agent, whom he has appointed to act in his name, whether his intentions have been expressly named, or are only to be gathered from the nature of the employment. For whoever gives another a commission, gives him along with it every thing in his power that is necessary to the execution of it. So that there are two ways, in which persons acting with subordinate powers may bind their principals by their conduct, and412 that is, by doing what is probably thought to be contained in their commission, or apart from that, by acting according to special instructions, generally known, at least to those, with whom they treat.
II. The actions of those given such limited powers should be viewed in two ways: whether they are binding on the sovereign or just on themselves. The first aspect has already been addressed earlier in this treatise, where it was shown that a person is bound by the actions of an agent they’ve appointed to act on their behalf, whether their intentions are explicitly stated or can only be inferred from the nature of the task. Anyone who gives another person a commission also gives them everything necessary to complete it. Therefore, there are two ways in which individuals acting with subordinate powers can bind their principals through their actions: either by doing what is generally understood to be included in their commission, or alternatively, by acting according to specific instructions that are usually known, at least to those they are dealing with.
III. There are other modes too, in which a sovereign may be bound by the previous act of his minister; but not in such a manner as to suppose the obligation owes its EXISTENCE to that action, which only gives occasion to its fulfilment. And there are two ways, in which this may happen, either by the consent of the sovereign, or by the very nature of the thing itself. His consent appears by his ratification of the act, either expressed or implied, and that is, where a sovereign has known and suffered a thing to be done, which can be accounted for upon no other motive but that of approval and consent.
III. There are other ways a ruler can be bound by their minister's previous actions; however, this doesn't mean that the obligation comes from those actions, which merely provide the opportunity for it to be carried out. This can happen in two ways: either through the ruler's consent or by the nature of the situation itself. The ruler's consent can be shown through their ratification of the action, whether it's explicit or implied, meaning that if the ruler has been aware of and allowed something to happen, it can only be explained by their approval and consent.
The very nature and obligation of all contracts imply that one party is not to gain advantage by the loss of another. Or if advantage is expected from a contract, the contract must be fulfilled or the advantage abandoned. And in this sense, and no other, the proverbial expression, that whatever is beneficial is valid, is to be understood.
The fundamental nature and obligation of all contracts suggest that one party shouldn’t benefit at the expense of another. If a benefit is anticipated from a contract, the contract needs to be honored, or the benefit should be given up. In this way, and only in this way, the saying that anything beneficial is valid should be understood.
On the other hand a charge of injustice may fairly be brought against those, who condemn an engagement, yet retain the advantages, which they could not have had without it.
On the other hand, a charge of injustice can rightly be made against those who criticize a commitment while still enjoying the benefits they wouldn't have without it.
IV. It is necessary to repeat an observation made before, that a sovereign, who has given a commission to another, is bound by the conduct of that person, even though he may have acted contrary to his secret instructions, provided he has not gone beyond the limits of his ostensible, and public commission.
IV. It’s important to reiterate a point made earlier: a ruler who has entrusted someone with a commission is held accountable for that person's actions, even if they acted against their private instructions, as long as they didn't exceed the boundaries of their official, public mandate.
This was a principle of equity, which the Roman Praetor observed in actions brought against employers for the conduct of their agents or factors. An employer could not be made answerable for any act or measure of his factor, but such as was immediately connected with the business, in which he employed him. Nor could HE be considered as an appointed agent, with WHOM the public were apprised, by due notice, to make no contract—If such notice was given, without having come to the knowledge of the contracting parties, the employer was bound by the conduct of the agent. If any one chuses to make a contract on certain conditions, or through the intervention of a third person, it is right and necessary413 for that person to observe the particular conditions on which he is employed.
This was a principle of fairness that the Roman Praetor followed in cases against employers for the actions of their agents or representatives. An employer couldn’t be held responsible for any actions taken by their representative, except for those directly related to the business for which they were hired. Additionally, an employer couldn’t be seen as having appointed an agent that the public was informed, by proper notice, not to engage in contracts with. If that notice was given but didn’t reach the knowledge of the parties involved in the contract, the employer would still be liable for the agent’s actions. If someone chooses to enter into a contract under specific conditions, or through a third party, it is right and necessary for that person to adhere to the particular conditions under which they are employed.413
From hence it follows that kings and nations are more or less bound by the conventions of their commanders in proportion as their laws, conditions, and customs, are more or less known. If the meaning of their intentions is not evident, conjecture may supply the place of evidence, as it is natural to suppose that any one employed would be invested with full powers sufficient to execute his commission.
From this, it follows that kings and countries are more or less obligated by the agreements of their leaders based on how well-known their laws, circumstances, and customs are. If the meaning of their intentions isn't clear, guesswork might fill in for proof, as it's reasonable to assume that anyone appointed would have enough authority to carry out their task.
A person acting in a subordinate capacity, if he has exceeded the powers of his commission will be bound to make reparation, if he cannot fulfil his engagement, unless he is prevented from doing so by some well known law.
A person acting in a lower role, if they have gone beyond the limits of their authority, will be required to make compensation if they cannot fulfill their obligations, unless they are stopped from doing so by some widely recognized law.
But if he has been guilty of treachery also, in pretending to greater powers than he really possessed, he will be bound to repair the injury, which he has WILFULLY done, and to suffer punishment corresponding with his offence. For the first of these offences, his property is answerable, and on failure of that, his personal liberty: and in the latter case, his person or property, or both must be answerable according to the magnitude of the crime.
But if he has also been guilty of betrayal by pretending to have greater powers than he actually did, he will be obligated to fix the harm he has Willingly caused and face a punishment that fits the crime. For the first offense, his assets are at stake, and if those are insufficient, then his personal freedom is on the line; in the latter case, his body or property, or both, must be liable based on the seriousness of the crime.
V. As a sovereign or his minister is always bound by every contract, it is certain the other party will also be bound by the engagement: nor can it be deemed imperfect. For in this respect there is a comparative equality between sovereign and subordinate powers.
V. Since a sovereign or their minister is always bound by every contract, it follows that the other party will also be bound by the agreement; it cannot be considered flawed. In this regard, there is a relative equality between sovereign and subordinate powers.
VI. It is necessary to consider too what are the powers of subordinate authorities over those beneath them. Nor is there any doubt that a general may bind the army, and a magistrate, the inhabitants of a place by those actions, which are usually done by commanders, or magistrates, otherwise their consent would be necessary.
VI. It's also important to think about the powers that subordinate authorities have over those below them. There’s no doubt that a general can hold the army accountable, and a magistrate can hold the residents of a place accountable through actions typically taken by commanders or magistrates; otherwise, their consent would be required.
On the other hand, in engagements purely beneficial, the advantage shall be on the side of the inferior: for that is a condition comprehended in the very nature of power.—Where there is any burdensome condition annexed it shall not extend beyond the usual limits in which authority is exercised; or if it does, it shall be at the option of the inferior to accept or refuse that condition.
On the other hand, in purely beneficial activities, the advantage will go to the weaker party: that's just part of the nature of power. If there are any heavy conditions attached, they shouldn’t go beyond the usual limits of authority; if they do, the weaker party can choose to accept or reject those conditions.
VII. As to the causes and consequences of a war, it is not within the province of a general to decide them.414 For concluding and conducting a war are very different things, and rest upon distinct kinds of authority.
VII. When it comes to the reasons and outcomes of a war, it's not the responsibility of a general to make those decisions.414 Ending and managing a war are two different matters and rely on different types of authority.
VIII. and IX. As to granting truces, it is a power which belongs not only to commanders in chief, but also to inferior commanders. And they may grant them for themselves, and the forces immediately under their command, to places which they are besieging or blockading: but they do not thereby bind other parts of the army. Generals have no right to cede nations, dominions, or any kind of conquests made in war. They may relinquish any thing of which a complete conquest has not been made: for towns frequently surrender on condition of the inhabitants being spared, and allowed to retain their liberty and property: cases, in which there is no time for consulting the will and pleasure of the sovereign. In the same manner, and upon the same principle this right is allowed to subordinate commanders, if it falls within the nature of their commission.
VIII. and IX. When it comes to granting truces, this power belongs not just to the top commanders, but also to lower-ranking commanders. They can grant truces for themselves and their directly commanded forces to the locations they are besieging or blockading, but this doesn’t commit other parts of the army. Generals do not have the authority to give away nations, territories, or any conquests made during war. They can give up anything that hasn’t been completely conquered, as towns often surrender under the condition that the residents are spared and allowed to keep their freedom and property—situations where there’s no time to consult the wishes of the sovereign. Similarly, subordinate commanders are allowed this right within the limits of their authority.
X. As commanders, in all such engagements, are acting in the name of others, their resolutions must not be interpreted so strictly as to bind their sovereigns to greater obligations than they intended to incur, nor at the same time to prove prejudicial to the commanders themselves for having done their duty.
X. As commanders in all these situations are acting on behalf of others, their decisions shouldn't be interpreted so rigidly that they place their leaders under more obligations than they intended to take on, nor should those decisions negatively impact the commanders for fulfilling their responsibilities.
XI. An absolute surrender implies that the party so capitulating submits to the pleasure and discretion of the conqueror.
XI. An absolute surrender means that the party giving in submits to the will and judgment of the conqueror.
XII. In ancient conventions a precaution was usually added, that they would be ratified, if approved of by the Roman people. So that if no ratification ensued, the general was bound no further than to be answerable for any advantage that might have accrued to himself.
XII. In ancient practices, a precaution was typically included, stating that they would be validated if approved by the Roman people. Therefore, if no validation occurred, the general was only responsible for any benefits that might have come to him.
XIII. Commanders having promised to surrender a town, may dismiss the garrison.
XIII. Commanders who have promised to surrender a town may send the garrison away.
CHAPTER XXIV.81
On Implicit Faith.
Tacit faith—Example of in desiring to be taken under the protection of a king or nation—Implied in the demand or grant of a conference—Allowable for the party seeking it to promote his own interest thereby provided he uses no treachery—Meaning of mute signs allowed by custom.
Tacit faith—For example, wanting to be under the protection of a king or a nation—This is implied in the request or offer for a meeting—It's fine for the person seeking it to promote their own interests this way as long as they don't use deception—The meaning of silent gestures is understood through tradition.
I. Both public, private, and mixed, conventions admit of tacit consent, which is allowed by custom. For in whatever manner consent is indicated and accepted it has the power of conveying a right. And, as it has been frequently observed in the course of this treatise, there are other signs of consent besides words and letters: some of them indeed naturally rising out of the action itself.
I. Both public, private, and mixed conventions allow for implied consent, which is permitted by custom. Because however consent is expressed and accepted, it has the ability to convey a right. And, as has been noted many times throughout this discussion, there are other indications of consent beyond just words and letters: some of them naturally arising from the action itself.
II. An example of such tacit agreement may be found in the case of a person coming from an enemy, or foreign country, and surrendering himself to the good faith of another king or people. For such a one tacitly binds himself to do nothing injurious or treacherous to that state, where he seeks protection, a point which is beyond all doubt.
II. An example of this kind of unspoken agreement can be seen in the situation of someone arriving from an enemy or foreign nation and placing themselves under the protection of another king or people. In doing so, that person implicitly commits to not doing anything harmful or deceitful toward the state they are seeking protection from, which is indisputable.
III. In the same manner, a person who grants or requests a conference, gives a tacit promise, that he will do nothing prejudicial to the parties, who attend it. Livy pronounces an injury done to an enemy, under the pretext of holding a conference, a violation of the law of nations.
III. Similarly, when someone arranges or asks for a meeting, they implicitly promise not to do anything harmful to the people attending. Livy states that causing harm to an enemy while pretending to hold a meeting is a breach of international law.
IV. But such a tacit promise, to take no advantage of a parley or conference, is not to be carried farther than what has been said. Provided all injury and injustice are avoided, it is reckoned a lawful stratagem, for any one to avail himself of a parley in order to draw off the enemy's attention from his military projects, and to promote his own. The device, by which Asdrubal extricated his army from the Ausetanian forests, was of this kind, and by the same means Scipio Africanus, the elder, gained a perfect416 knowledge of Syphax's camp. Both these circumstances are related by Livy.
IV. However, this unspoken promise to not take advantage of a discussion or meeting should not be taken further than what has been stated. As long as no harm or injustice occurs, it's considered a legitimate tactic for anyone to use a meeting to divert the enemy's focus from their military plans and to advance their own. The strategy that Asdrubal used to get his army out of the Ausetanian forests falls into this category, and the same approach allowed Scipio Africanus the Elder to gain complete416 insight into Syphax's camp. Both of these events are mentioned by Livy.
V. There are certain mute signs, deriving all their force and meaning from custom; such as the fillets, and branches of olive formerly used: among the Macedonians pikes erected, and among the Romans shields placed upon the head, were signs of a suppliant surrender obliging the party to lay down his arms. In the present day a white flag is a sign of suing for a parley. Therefore all these methods have the force of express declarations.
V. There are certain silent signs that derive all their strength and meaning from tradition; like the ribbons and olive branches that were used in the past: the Macedonians raised pikes, and the Romans held shields over their heads as signs of a surrender that required the person to lay down their arms. Today, a white flag is a sign of seeking a truce. Thus, all these methods carry the weight of clear statements.
CHAPTER XXV.
Conclusion.
Admonitions to the observance of good faith—Peace always to be kept in view in the midst of war—Peace beneficial to the conquered—To the conqueror—And to be chosen in cases where the issue is doubtful—To be religiously observed—Prayer—Conclusion of the work.
It's important to maintain good faith—Always remember peace, even in times of war—Peace is beneficial for the defeated—For the winners—And it should be embraced when the outcome is unclear—To be strictly adhered to—Prayer—Conclusion of the task.
I. Here seems to be the proper place to bring this work to a conclusion, without in the least presuming that every thing has been said, which might be said on the subject: but sufficient has been produced to lay a foundation, on which another, if he pleases, may raise a more noble and extensive edifice, an addition and improvement that will provoke no jealousy, but rather be entitled to thanks.
I. It seems like the right moment to wrap up this work, without assuming that everything that could be said on this topic has been said. However, there’s enough here to create a foundation on which someone else might build a more impressive and comprehensive structure, an enhancement that will inspire gratitude rather than envy.
Before entirely dismissing the subject, it may be necessary to observe, that, as in laying down the true motives and causes, that alone will justify war, every possible precaution at the same time was taken to state the reasons for which it should be avoided; so now a few admonitions will not be deemed superfluous, in order to point out the means of preserving good faith in war, and maintaining peace, after war is brought to a termination, and among other reasons for preserving good faith the desire of keeping alive the hope of peace, even in the midst of war, is not the least important. For good faith, in the language of Cicero, is not only the principal hold by which all governments are bound together, but is the key-stone by which the larger society of nations is united. Destroy this, says Aristotle, and you destroy the intercourse of mankind.
Before completely dismissing the topic, it's important to note that, just as we establish the true motives and reasons that justify war, every possible effort was made to outline the reasons for avoiding it. Therefore, a few reminders are necessary to highlight how to uphold integrity in war and maintain peace after it ends. Among the reasons for preserving integrity, the desire to keep the hope of peace alive, even during war, is especially crucial. As Cicero said, integrity is not only the foundational element binding all governments together but also the key that unites the broader community of nations. Destroy this, as Aristotle states, and you undermine human interaction.
In every other branch of justice there is something of obscurity, but the bond of faith is clear in itself, and is used indeed to do away the obscurity of all transactions. The observance of this is a matter of conscience with all lawful kings and sovereign princes, and is the basis of that reputation by which the honour and dignity of their crowns are maintained with foreign nations.
In every other area of justice, there’s some level of confusion, but the bond of trust is straightforward and is actually used to eliminate the confusion in all dealings. Following this principle is a matter of conscience for all legitimate kings and ruling princes, and it serves as the foundation of the reputation that upholds the honor and dignity of their crowns in the eyes of other nations.
II. In the very heat of war the greatest security and expectation of divine support must be in the unabated418 desire, and invariable prospect of peace, as the only end for which hostilities can be lawfully begun. So that in the prosecution of war we must never carry the rage of it so far, as to unlearn the nature and dispositions of men.
II. In the midst of war, the strongest assurance of safety and hope for divine help should come from our constant desire and unwavering hope for peace, which is the only legitimate goal for starting hostilities. Therefore, in our conduct of war, we must never let our anger lead us to forget the true nature and feelings of people.
III. These and these alone would be sufficient motives for the termination of war, and the cultivation of peace. But apart from all considerations of humanity, the INTERESTS of mankind would inevitably lead us to the same point. In the first place it is dangerous to prolong a contest with a more powerful enemy. In such a case some sacrifices should be made for the sake of peace, as in a storm goods are sometimes thrown overboard to prevent a greater calamity, and to save the vessel and the crew.
III. These and only these would be enough reasons for ending the war and promoting peace. But aside from all humanitarian concerns, the INTERESTS of humanity would inevitably drive us to the same conclusion. First, it's risky to drag out a fight with a stronger enemy. In such situations, some sacrifices are necessary for the sake of peace, just like during a storm when goods are sometimes discarded to avoid a bigger disaster and to protect the ship and its crew.
IV. Even for the stronger party, when flushed with victory, peace is a safer expedient, than the most extensive successes. For there is the boldness of despair to be apprehended from a vanquished enemy, dangerous as the bite of a ferocious animal in the pangs of death.
IV. Even for the stronger side, when riding high on victory, peace is a safer option than even the greatest successes. For there is the recklessness of desperation to be feared from a defeated opponent, as dangerous as the bite of a wild animal in its death throes.
V. If indeed both parties are upon an equal footing, it is the opinion of Caesar, that it is the most favourable moment for making peace, when each party has confidence in itself.
V. If both parties are truly on equal ground, Caesar believes that the best time to make peace is when each side has confidence in itself.
VI. On whatever terms peace is made, it must be absolutely kept. From the sacredness of the faith pledged in the engagement, and every thing must be cautiously avoided, not only savouring of treachery, but that may tend to awaken and inflame animosity. For what Cicero has said of private friendships may with equal propriety be applied to public engagements of this kind, which are all to be religiously and faithfully observed, especially where war and enmity have ended in peace and reconciliation.
VI. No matter how peace is established, it must be strictly upheld. Due to the sacredness of the commitment made in this agreement, everything must be carefully avoided that not only hints at betrayal but could also stir up and intensify hostility. Just as Cicero remarked about personal friendships, the same can be said about public agreements like this one, which should be honored and respected, especially when war and conflict have transitioned into peace and reconciliation.
VII. And may God, to whom alone it belongs to dispose the affections and desires of sovereign princes and kings, inscribe these principles upon their hearts and minds, that they may always remember that the noblest office, in which man can be engaged, is the government of men, who are the principal objects of the divine care.
VII. And may God, who alone has the authority to influence the feelings and desires of rulers and kings, write these principles on their hearts and minds, so they always remember that the highest duty a person can have is to govern others, who are the main focus of divine care.
INDEX
- Abandoned property, title to, 107, 111.
- Acceptance: Necessity of, in promise to convey a right, 139.
- Acceptilation, 111.
- Accessories to crimes, 197, 257.
- Accomplices, punishment of, 256.
- Acquisitions: Of property in war, 334 et seq., 346.
- Of dominion, 379.
- Actions at law: Stipulations as to, in treaties, 390.
- Admiralty, 146.
- Affirmations, 164, 165.
- Agency, 339, 412.
- Agents: Acts of, binding on principal, 138, 139, 412.
- Agreements: Special and exclusive, 101.
- Between citizens of different countries, 136.
- Alexandrinus, Clemens, 52.
- Alienation: Of things by right of war, 353, 389.
- Of public dominion, 386.
- Alliances: Between states, partnerships, 146.
- Allies: Aid to, 173.
- Ambassadors: Promises of, binding, 139.
- Ratification of treaties made by, 167.
- Inviolability of, 202, 204.
- Must be duly accredited, 202.
- Sovereign states may send, 203.
- Refusal to receive, 204.
- Exemptions, 205, 209, 210, 211, 313.
- Punishment of, for crimes, 208.
- Passage through foreign states, 209.
- Suite and personal effects of, 211.
- House of, as asylum, 211.
- Debts contracted by, 212.
- Ambrose, 54.
- Andronicus, 24.
- Antoninus, Marcus, 66.
- Antoninus, Pius, 112.
- Aptitude, 19.
- Arbiter, office of, 398.
- Arbitration, 84, 276, 397.
- Arcifinium, 106.
- Aristotle, 19, 20, 22, 24, 61, 62, 64, 76, 118, 120, 190, 218, 251, 268.
- Asylum, right of, 260.
- Augustine, 58, 74.
- Aurelius, Marcus, 52, 68.
- Barbeyrac, 173, 392.
- Blackstone's Commentaries, 29, 61, 86, 100, 136, 154, 155, 156, 177, 182—notes.
- Bodies politic, privileges of, 262.
- Boundary, rivers as, 107.
- Breach of peace, 395.
- Burial, right of, 213 et seq.
- Burke, Edmund, 282 note.
- Caduceum, use of, 320.
- Caesar, Julius, 59.
- Captures in war, 334, 369.
- Cargo, in enemy's ships, title to, 337.
- Cassius, 60, 74.
- Cato, 59, 77.
- Causes of war, justifiable, 85.
- Chirographarii, 173.
- Chrysostom, Dio, 25.
- Cicero, 18, 23, 24, 31, 34, 35, 60, 68, 78, 86, 89, 92, 137, 191, 208, 214, 215, 268, 283, 317, 379.
- Civil law: Relation of, to law of nature, 91.
- Clarigation, 319.
- Commerce, treaties of, 169, 170.
- Commissions: Special, of ambassador, 167.
- Variations from, 188.
- Common right to actions, 99.
- Common right to things, 99.
- Community of goods, 86.
- Of lands, 88.
- Compensation, defined, 382.
- Compromise: As method of settling national disputes, 276.
- Conditional surrender, 400.
- Conference: To settle disputes of nations, 276.
- Conqueror, rights of, 399.
- Conquest, rights resulting from, 348, 399.
- Consent to conventions, 415.
- Consideration of contracts, 136, 138.
- Constantine, 53, 54.
- Contracts: Expressed and implied, 100, 145.
- Contributions levied for future security, 373.
- Conventions: Public and private, 166.420
- Corporeal rights, 85.
- Countries, names of, 392.
- Creditors, personal, 173.
- Crimes: Principals and accessories, 197, 198, 257.
- And misdemeanors, 241.
- Damages, 196, 197, 199, 200, 388.
- Debts, individual, effect of war upon, 391.
- Deception, innocent, 302.
- Declaration of war, 318, 321.
- After truce, not necessary, 404.
- Defense: A justifiable cause of war, 75.
- Right of, 395.
- Demand of restitution, 319.
- Demosthenes, 74, 81, 170, 240, 310.
- Deserters: Not entitled to right of postliminium, 355, 390.
- Dictator, sovereign power of, 72.
- Dionysius, 61, 74, 98, 163.
- Disputes of nations, methods of settlement, 276.
- Divided and assigned land, 106.
- Dominion, acquisition of, 372.
- Duration of truces, 404.
- Duties: Right to impose, on goods in transit, 97.
- Duty of citizen to prevent war, 286.
- Eliminium, 351.
- Enemies: Furnishing aid to, 293-321.
- Engagements, 167.
- Of sovereigns or states, 387.
- Epictetus, 22.
- Equity: A species of justice, 190.
- Euripides, 22, 78.
- Exchange, contracts of, 145.
- Extradition, 258, 259.
- Factors: Acts of, bind merchants, when, 139, 412.
- Faculty, definition of, 19.
- Falsehood, discussed, 299 et seq.
- Fecial law of Rome, 319.
- Federal Union, 62, 121.
- Ferae naturae, 86.
- Rights of sovereign as to, 91.
- Fishing, a common right, 101.
- Florentinus, 19, 35.
- Foreign residents, rights of, 98, 327.
- Free passage through countries, right of, 95, 97.
- Permission first asked, 96.
- Funeral rites, 214.
- Galen, 33, 62.
- Good faith, foundation of all treaties, 385, 417.
- Goods in enemy's ships, title to, 337.
- Government: Change of form of, effect upon debts, 121.
- Governments, established for what, 68.
- Gregory of Tours, 69.
- Guaranty of performance by another, 143.
- Heraclitus, 24.
- Hermogenianus, 36.
- Herodotus, 66, 68.
- Hesiod, 23, 24, 68.
- Hiring, 153.
- Homicide, excusable, 29.
- Hostages: Right to kill, 330, 364.
- Appendages to treaties, 400.
- Immunity of Ambassadors, 202.
- Incorporeal rights, 85, 309, 346.
- Of a state lost by conquest, 349.
- Indemnity: A justifiable cause for war, 75.
- Injunctions, 170.
- Injuries to property: Robbery, 81.
- Insurance, contract of, 156, 157.
- Interest, lawfulness of, 154, 156.
- Interpretation: Of laws, 136.
- Of promises, 137.
- Of treaties, 176 et seq.
- Words, taken in common acceptation, 177.
- Words of art, 177, 181.
- Obscure words, 178.
- Probable consequences, 179.
- Context, 179.
- Motive, 180.
- Allies, construed, 183.
- Absurd conditions, 188.
- And law of nations, 194.
- Of peace, 389, 392, 401.
- Names of countries, 392.
- Josephus, 35, 50.
- Justifiable causes of war, 73, 75, 85, 247, 285.
- Justinian, 58.
- Kings, accountability of, 69.
- Not all made by the people, 67.
- Lactantius, 23, 74.
- Lakes, when property, 90.
- Lands: Three-fold division of, 106.
- Law: Basis of, 136.
- Fecial, of Rome, 319.
- Lawful war, 18, 31, 278, 324.
- Law of Nations, 23.
- Law of nature, 22, 79,421
- Laws: Interpretation of, 136.
- Power to repeal, 238.
- Letters of marque and reprisal, 278, 311.
- Letting and hiring, 153.
- Lie, what is a, 299.
- Livy, 64, 73, 78, 114, 167, 170, 206, 317, 332.
- Losses of individuals in war, 388.
- Lot, as method of settling national disputes, 277.
- Marque and reprisal, letters of, 278, 311.
- Mediation, 84.
- Mediator, office of, 398.
- Money, variations in value, 153.
- Monopoly, 101, 152.
- Moral distinctions, as to acts, 274 et seq.
- Mosaic Law, 26-28.
- Not binding upon Christians, 29.
- Mutius, Quintius, 36.
- Nations, law of, 23.
- Natural Right, 21.
- Nature, law of, unalterable, 22.
- Proof of existence of, 24.
- Naval associations: Apportionment of losses, 158.
- Necessity, appropriation of property under, 92, 93.
- Negotiation of treaties, true basis for, 385.
- Neutral soil: Right of belligerent to, 93.
- Neutrals, rights and duties, 377.
- Oaths: Sanctity of, 160 et seq.
- Obligations: Arising from property, 123.
- Occupancy, title by, 90.
- Occupatory lands, 106.
- Offenses against society, punishment of, 258.
- Origen, 49.
- Ovid, 32.
- Pardons, lawfulness of, 236, 238.
- Parley, sign of, 416.
- Partnerships, 146.
- Trading—proportion of profits and losses, 157.
- Paulus, 21.
- Peace: The object of wars, 379.
- Penal statutes, construction of, 181.
- Penalties: Remitted, 391.
- Performance of contract, guaranty for, 143.
- Piracy, sovereign answerable for, 200.
- Pirates, treatment of, 380.
- Plato, 75, 93, 224, 226, 229.
- Pledges: Appendages to treaties, 400.
- Redemption of, 401.
- Pliny, 36, 254.
- Plutarch, 23, 24, 66, 93, 221, 226, 227, 235.
- Polybius, 23, 73, 208.
- Pomponius, 159.
- Ponds, when property, 90.
- Porphyry, 24.
- Possession: Uninterrupted, transfers property, 114.
- Posthumous rights to property, 114.
- Postliminium: Definition of, 169, 331.
- Premium of insurance, 156.
- Prescription, law of, as applied to a sovereign, 115.
- Price, governed by demand, 151.
- Prisoners: Surrender of, 258, 259.
- Privateers, 200.
- Private right, 20.
- Privileges of bodies politic, 262.
- Prizes: By right of war, 337, 343, 346.
- Taken from pirates, 357.
- Prohibitions in treaties, 193.
- Promises: Obligation of, 131, 135, 379, 381.
- Property: Means of acquiring, 103.
- Obligations arising from possession of, 123 et seq.
- Alienated by rights of war, 353, 389.
- Restoration of, taken in unjust war, 375.
- Possession of, for long time may not give right of, 109,—but see 114.
- Redress of injuries to, 311, 318.
- Of enemy, right to destroy, 332, 365, 366.
- Title to, 335, 90.
- Possession of, after war, 390.
- Appropriation of, on ground of necessity, 91, 92.
- Of subjects, liability of for debts of states, 308, 370, 387.
- Title to, as between enemies, 338.
- Use of, 94.
- Acquisition of, in war, 340.
- Captured, 369.
- Idea of how established, 89.
- When right of, ceases to exist, 117.
- Movable and immovable, 88, 356.
- Things not reducible to, 89.
- In lakes, ponds, and rivers, 90.
- Abandoned, 107, 111.
- Puffendorf, 193.422
- Punishment: A justifiable cause of war, 75.
- Defined, 221.
- Who may inflict, 223, 226, 228.
- Object of, 224, 226, 229, 232, 240, 247, 370.
- Under the Gospel, 230.
- Capital, 233.
- Wicked acts not subject to, 235.
- Proportioned to offense, 243 et seq.
- Of offenses against God, 249 et seq.
- Communication of, upon accomplices, 256.
- Offenses affecting society, 258.
- Of non-participants, 262.
- Of surety, 264.
- Of children for parents' sins, 266.
- Classes exempt from, 362.
- Of hostages, 364.
- Right to claim property as, 391.
- Quintilian, 24, 89.
- Ratification of treaties and conventions, 167, 175, 414.
- Recovery of things alienated by rights of war, 353.
- Redemption of pledges, 401.
- Redress, method of obtaining, 311, 318.
- Religion, based on four truths, 250.
- Remedial statutes, construction of, 181.
- Reprisal: Letters of Marque and, 278.
- Residents, foreign, rights of, 97.
- Restoration: Of subjugated people, 354, 355.
- Right: To movables by occupancy, 104.
- To impose duties on goods in transit, 97.
- Common-passage through countries, 95, 97, 99.
- Of burial, 213.
- Violation of, 301.
- Of dominion, acquisition of, 379.
- Of governors and governed, 19.
- Of prisoners, 353.
- Definition and signification of, 18, 19, 20.
- To actions, 99.
- Private, 20.
- Superior, 20.
- Of asylum, 260.
- Voluntary, 25.
- Of making war, 386.
- Of possession, 399.
- Rights: Human and Divine, 25.
- River: Effect of change in course of, 106.
- Robbery, right to kill robber, 81.
- Romanus, Clemens, 52.
- Sacred things not exempt from destruction by enemy, 332.
- Safe conduct, a, 408.
- Expiration of, 409.
- Sales and purchases: Right of restricting, 100.
- When contract complete, 151.
- Sallust, 206.
- Salvian, 51.
- Sea: Open, not property, 90.
- Portions of, may become property, 104.
- Self-defense, 77.
- Seneca, 19, 24, 74, 75, 80, 92, 108, 118, 135, 192.
- Services, gratuitous, 144.
- Settlement of national disputes, methods of, 276.
- Ships. Owners bound by acts of masters of, when, 139.
- Silanian, Decree, 53.
- Slavery, 345.
- Slaves: Prisoners of war, 345.
- Right of postliminium, 352.
- Smith, Adam, 101 n.
- Soldiers, compensation to, 341, 343.
- Sovereign power: Not in the people in every case, 63 et seq., 120.
- Sovereigns: Elective and hereditary, 71.
- Sovereignty: Its nature and where it resides, 60, 62, 70, 71, 103.
- Not forfeitable by act of delinquency, 80.
- Spies, treatment of, when captured, 331.
- Sponsio, 167.
- State: Definition of, 25.
- States: When immortal, 117.
- States General: Three divisions of, 70, 71.
- Statutes: Penal construed strictly; remedial liberally, 181.
- Strabo, 62, 98.
- Stratagem, use of, in war, 294 et seq.
- Subjects: Of sovereign, detention of, 311.
- Liability to attack, in time of war, anywhere, 327.
- Superior right, 20.
- Supply of a thing affects its price, 151.
- Surety: Punishment of, 264.
- Bound by consent, 308.
- Surrender: Of a people, in war, 390.
- Conditional, 400.
- Sylla, Lucius Cornelius, 57.
- Tacitus, 64, 68, 87, 106, 110, 213.
- Taxes on goods in transit, 97.
- Terminus, rites of, 373.
- Territory long possessed, title to, 110.
- Tertullian, 49, 51, 52.
- Thucydides, 60, 174.
- Time: As an element of right of property, 109.
- Immemorial, 113.
- Transit, goods in, 97.
- Treaties: Public and private, 166.423
- Equal, 170.
- Unequal, 158, 170, 171, 184.
- Definition of, 167.
- Requiring ratification, 167.
- Power to make in monarchies, 168.
- Resting in law of nature, 168.
- Of commerce and amity, 169, 170, 185.
- Of peace, 170, 386, 389, 391.
- Renewal of, 173.
- Effect of violation of, 174.
- Interpretation of, 176 et seq. (See Interpretation of Treaties.)
- Personal and real, 184.
- Where governments change form, 184, 185.
- Of peace, material part of, 386.
- Stipulations as to actions at law, 390.
- Hostages and pledges under, 400.
- Truces: Definition, 403.
- Ulpian, 21, 34, 36, 129, 162, 166, 263, 333.
- Unlawful acts, 305.
- Usucaption, law of, as applied to sovereigns, 115.
- Usufruct, 155.
- Usufructuary property, 86.
- Usury, 155.
- Valentinian, 67.
- Value of a thing governed by what? 150.
- Of money, 153.
- Vasquez, 80, 239, 286, 388.
- Vattel, 101, 158, 167, 169, 177, 203, 297, 387, 388—notes.
- War: Definition of, 18, 403.
- Derivation of word, 18.
- Division of, public, private, and mixed, 55.
- All, not repugnant to law of nature, 34, 36.
- Private, 55, 56, 83.
- Justifiable causes, pretexts, and beginning of, 73, 75, 247, 285.
- Defense, indemnity and punishment, 75, 245.
- Time of beginning, 284.
- Object of, 379.
- Effect upon debts, 391.
- Lawfulness of, 18, 31, 278, 324.
- Under divine voluntary law, 36, 40.
- Aid to parties to, 173.
- Causes, justifying participation of allies, 285.
- Lawful means used in, 290, 363.
- Use of stratagem, 294.
- Suspicion of hostile intentions, 83.
- Injury to property, 85.
- Demand of surrender of citizen, 285.
- Precautions against, 280 et seq.
- Right of belligerents to neutral soil, 93.
- Unjust, causes of, 267 et seq.
- Avoidance of, 280 et seq., 418.
- Declaration of, 318, 321, 404, and forms, 319.
- Right to make, 386.
- Losses of individuals by, 388.
- Public, formal and informal, declared by sovereign, 57, 316, 317, 386.
- Right to avert, and to punish wrongs, 83, 200, 247, 280.
- "Wealth of Nations," 101n.
- Withernam, 311.
- Wrongs: Division of, private and public, 61.
- Sovereign power may avert and punish, 83.
- Xenophon, 32, 93.
FOOTNOTES
1 The eighth Section is omitted, the greater part of it consisting of verbal criticism upon Aristotle's notions of geometrical and arithmetical justice; a discussion no way conducive to that clearness and simplicity, so necessary to every didactic treatise.—Translator.
1 The eighth section is left out because most of it is just a critique of Aristotle's ideas on geometric and arithmetic justice; this discussion doesn't help with the clarity and simplicity that are essential for any instructional work.—Translator.
2 The law, by its silence, permits those acts, which it does not prohibit. Thus many acts, if they are not evil in themselves, are no offence, till the law has made them such. Of this kind are many acts, such as exporting gold, or importing certain articles of trade; doing certain actions, or following certain callings, without the requisite qualifications, which are made punishable offences by the Statute-Law. Those actions, before the prohibition was enjoined by the law, came under the class of what Grotius calls permissions.
2 The law, by remaining silent, allows those actions that it doesn't explicitly ban. So, many actions, unless they are harmful in themselves, aren't considered offenses until the law defines them as such. This includes things like exporting gold or importing certain trade items, as well as taking specific actions or pursuing certain jobs without the necessary qualifications, which the law then makes punishable. Before the law imposed these restrictions, those actions were seen as permissible, as Grotius refers to them.
4 To explain the meaning of Grotius in this place, recourse must be had to first principles. Thus the law of nature authorizing self-defence in its fullest extent, the laws of nations, which authorize war for the same purpose, cannot be repugnant to it.
4 To understand Grotius's meaning here, we need to refer to fundamental principles. Therefore, the law of nature that allows for self-defense in its broadest sense, along with the laws of nations that permit war for the same reason, cannot contradict it.
5 The Law of England on homicide excusable by self-defence, will throw light on the sentiments of Grotius in this place. "The law requires, that the person who kills another in his own defence, should have retreated as far as he conveniently or safely can, to avoid the violence of the assault, before he turns upon his assailant; and that, not fictitiously, or in order to watch his opportunity, but from a real tenderness of shedding his brother's blood. And though it may be cowardice, in time of war, between two independent nations, to flee from our enemy; yet between two fellow subjects the law countenances no such point of honour; because the king and his courts are the vindices injuriarum, and will give to the party wronged all the satisfaction he deserves. And this is the doctrine of universal justice, as well as of the municipal law."—Blackstone's Com. vol. 4, chap. 14.
5 The Law of England regarding homicide justified by self-defense will shed light on Grotius’s views here. "The law states that a person who kills another in self-defense should retreat as far as they can, safely and conveniently, to avoid the violence of the attack, before confronting their attacker. This should be done not in a fake manner or just to find an opportunity, but out of a genuine concern for shedding another's blood. While it might be considered cowardice to flee from an enemy during war between independent nations, the law does not support such notions of honor among fellow subjects. This is because the king and his courts are the vindices injuriarum, and will provide the injured party with the satisfaction they deserve. This represents the principles of universal justice as well as municipal law."—Blackstone's Com. vol. 4, chap. 14.
6 The author here alludes to the defilement or uncleanness which the ancients thought was contracted by touching a man, who had killed another, even innocently and lawfully.—Barbeyrac.
6 The author refers to the impurity or uncleanliness that ancient people believed was gained by touching someone who had killed another person, even if it was done innocently and legally.—Barbeyrac.
7 The remainder of this section is omitted, Grotius himself stating it to be only a repetition and enlargement of his arguments immediately preceding it. (Translator.)
7 The rest of this section is skipped, as Grotius himself says it is just a repetition and expansion of his arguments right before this. (Translator.)
9 By the Silanian decree of the Senate, it was ordered that if a master happened to be murdered in his own house, all the slaves under the same roof should be put to death; even though no proof appeared of their being concerned in the murder. We have an example of the case in Tacitus. Annal. v. xiv. ch. xlii. The Emperor Adrian softened the rigour of that decree, by ordering that only they should be exposed to the rack, who were near enough to have heard some noise. Spartian, Life of Adrian, ch. xviii.
9 By the Silanian decree of the Senate, it was declared that if a master was murdered in his own home, all the slaves living under the same roof should be executed, even if there was no evidence that they were involved in the murder. We see an example of this in Tacitus. Annal. v. xiv. ch. xlii. The Emperor Adrian eased the harshness of that decree by ruling that only those who were close enough to hear something should be tortured. Spartian, Life of Adrian, ch. xviii.
11 As the topics of the third section have been so fully stated in the second chapter, that section has been omitted, and the translation goes on from the second of the original to the fourth. (Translator.)
11 Since the subjects of the third section are thoroughly covered in the second chapter, that section has been left out, and the translation continues from the second of the original to the fourth. (Translator.)
13 "Wrongs are divisible into two sorts or species, PRIVATE WRONGS, and PUBLIC WRONGS. The former are an infringement or privation of the private or civil rights belonging to individuals, considered as individuals, and are therefore frequently termed civil injuries; the latter are a breach and violation of public rights and duties which affect the whole community considered as a community, and are distinguished by the harsher appellation of crimes and misdemeanors."—Blackst. Com. b. iii. c. i.
13 "Wrongs fall into two categories: PRIVATE WRONGS, and Public offenses. Private wrongs involve violations of the individual civil rights of people as individuals, and are often called civil injuries. Public wrongs, on the other hand, are breaches of public rights and duties that impact the community as a whole, and they are known by the harsher terms of crimes and misdemeanors."—Blackst. Com. b. iii. c. i.
14 The translation proceeds from hence to the second book of the original, which seems to follow this part without any material break in the chain of argument: the intermediate sections relating to instances in the Roman Republic, which do not directly apply to the practice of modern governments.—Translator.
14 The translation continues on to the second book of the original, which seems to follow this section without any significant interruption in the flow of discussion: the intermediate parts discussing examples from the Roman Republic, which aren't directly relevant to the operations of modern governments.—Translating service.
15 The tenth section is omitted in the translation; as the subject of Christian forbearance of which it treats, has already been discussed in the preceeding book.—Translator.
15 The tenth section is left out in the translation because the topic of Christian patience, which it covers, has already been talked about in the previous book.—Translator.
17 Actus aliquos, which literally signifies certain acts, may be rendered by the term incorporeal rights, which imply the right of ways, dignities, franchises, and many other personal privileges arising out of certain corporeal kinds of property.
17 Actus aliquos, which literally means certain acts, can be translated as incorporeal rights, referring to rights of way, honors, privileges, and various other personal benefits that come from specific types of tangible property.
18 The words of Judge Blackstone will elucidate the meaning of Grotius in this place. The learned Commentator says, "There are some few things, which, notwithstanding the general introduction and continuance of property, must still unavoidably remain in common; being such wherein nothing but an usufructuary property is capable of being had: and therefore they still belong to the first occupant, during the time he holds possession of them, and no longer. Such (among others) are the elements of light, air, and water; which a man may occupy by means of his windows, his gardens, his mills, and other conveniences: such also are the generality of those animals which are said to be ferae naturae, or of a wild and untameable disposition: which any man may seise upon and keep for his own use or pleasure. All these things, so long as they remain in possession, every man has a right to enjoy without disturbance; but if once they escape from his custody, or he voluntarily abandons the use of them, they return to the common stock, and any man else has a right to seise and enjoy them afterwards."
18 The words of Judge Blackstone will clarify Grotius's meaning here. The learned commentator says, "There are a few things that, despite the general establishment and persistence of property, must still remain common; these are things where only a usufructuary property can exist: and therefore they still belong to the first occupant, as long as he holds possession of them, and no longer. Such (among others) are light, air, and water; which a person can utilize through their windows, gardens, mills, and other conveniences: similarly, this includes many animals deemed ferae naturae, or wild and untameable: which anyone may catch and keep for their own use or pleasure. As long as these things are in possession, everyone has the right to enjoy them without interference; but if they escape from someone's custody or if he voluntarily gives them up, they return to the common pool, and anyone else has the right to seize and enjoy them afterward."
19 The meaning of Grotius in this Section will be more clearly understood by a brief explanation of the nature of Contracts. "Now contracts are of two kinds, either express or implied. Express contracts are openly uttered and avowed at the time of making, as to deliver an ox, or ten load of timber, or to pay a stated price for certain goods. Implied are such as reason and justice dictate, and which therefore the law presumes, that every man undertakes to perform. As, if I employ a person to do any business for me, or perform any work; the law implies that I undertook, or contracted, to pay him as much as his labor deserves. If I take up wares from a tradesman, without any agreement of price, the law concludes, that I contracted to pay their real value. And there is also one species of implied contracts, which runs through and is annexed to all other contracts, conditions, and covenants, viz. that if I fail in my part of the agreement, I shall pay the other party such damages as he has sustained by such my neglect or refusal." Blackst. Com. b. ii. c. 30. p. 442.
19 The meaning of Grotius in this section will be clearer with a brief explanation of what contracts are. "Contracts are of two types: express and implied. Express contracts are clearly stated at the time they are made, such as agreeing to deliver an ox, ten loads of timber, or pay a set price for certain goods. Implied contracts are those that reason and justice suggest, which the law assumes everyone agrees to perform. For example, if I hire someone to do a job for me, the law assumes I agreed to pay them fairly for their work. If I pick up goods from a vendor without discussing a price, the law presumes I agreed to pay their actual value. There is also one type of implied contract that applies to all other contracts, conditions, and agreements, which states that if I fail to meet my part of the agreement, I must compensate the other party for any damages they incur due to my neglect or refusal." Blackst. Com. b. ii. c. 30. p. 442.
20 There are cases in which monopolies, and the exclusive privileges of trading companies are not only allowable but absolutely necessary. "For there are, says Vattel, commercial enterprizes that cannot be carried on without an energy that requires considerable funds, which surpass the ability of individuals. There are others that would soon become ruinous, were they not conducted with great prudence, with one regular spirit, and according to well supported maxims and rules. These branches of trade cannot be indiscriminately carried on by individuals: companies are therefore formed, under the authority of the government; and these companies cannot subsist without an exclusive privilege. It is therefore advantageous to the nation to grant them: hence have arisen in different countries, those powerful companies that carry on commerce with the East."—Law of Nat. b. i. c. viii. sect. 97. p. 42.
20 There are situations where monopolies and the exclusive rights of trading companies are not only acceptable but absolutely necessary. "For there are, says Vattel, commercial ventures that cannot operate without a level of energy that requires significant funding, which exceeds what individuals can provide. There are other ventures that would quickly fail if they weren't managed with great care, with a consistent approach, and according to established principles and guidelines. These sectors of trade cannot be conducted randomly by individuals: companies are therefore established under government authority; and these companies cannot survive without exclusive rights. It is therefore beneficial for the nation to grant them: thus, powerful companies that engage in trade with the East have emerged in different countries."—Law of Nat. b. i. c. viii. sect. 97. p. 42.
21 Adam Smith in his Wealth of Nations, speaking of treaties of commerce, observes, that "when a nation binds itself by treaty, either to permit the entry of certain goods from one foreign country which it prohibits from all others, or to exempt the goods of one country from duties to which it subjects those of all others, the country, or at least the merchants and manufacturers of the country, whose commerce is so favoured, must necessarily derive great advantages from the treaty. Those merchants and manufacturers enjoy a sort of monopoly in the country, which is so indulgent to them. That country becomes a market both more extensive and more advantageous for their goods: more extensive, because the goods of other nations being either excluded or subjected to heavier duties, it takes off a great quantity of theirs: more advantageous, because the merchants of the favoured country, enjoying a sort of monopoly there, will often sell their goods for a better price, than if exposed to the free competition of all other nations."—Vol. 2. b. iv. ch. vi.
21 Adam Smith, in his Wealth of Nations, discusses trade treaties, noting that "when a nation commits to a treaty, either allowing certain goods from one foreign country while banning them from others, or exempting the goods of one country from taxes that others have to pay, the nation—or at least the merchants and manufacturers who benefit from this arrangement—will gain significant advantages from the treaty. Those merchants and manufacturers have a sort of monopoly in the nation that is so favorable to them. As a result, that nation becomes a market that is both broader and more profitable for their goods: broader, because the goods from other nations are either banned or face heavier taxes, leading to a higher demand for theirs; more profitable, because the merchants from the favored country, holding a sort of monopoly there, can often sell their goods at a higher price than if they had to compete freely with all other nations."—Vol. 2. b. iv. ch. vi.
22 The translation proceeds from the fourth to the ninth Chapter of the Second book of the original. The intermediate chapters, being chiefly a repetition of the author's former arguments, respecting the rights of seas and rivers, and other kinds of dominions; and that relating to the rights of persons, being so fully treated in the first volume of Judge Blackstone's Commentaries, it seemed unnecessary to give them in the present work.—Translator.
22 The translation goes from the fourth to the ninth chapter of the second book of the original. The chapters in between mostly repeat the author's earlier points about the rights to seas and rivers, along with other types of dominion; that concerning personal rights is covered in detail in the first volume of Judge Blackstone's Commentaries, so it seemed unnecessary to include them in this work.—Translator.
24 The following extracts from Blackstone's Com. b. ii. ch. xxx. will elucidate the meaning of our author in this place. "Sale or EXCHANGE is a transmutation of property from one man to another, in consideration of some price or recompense; for there is no sale without a recompence." P. 446.
24 The following excerpts from Blackstone's Com. b. ii. ch. xxx. will clarify the meaning of our author here. "A sale or SWAP is a transfer of property from one person to another in exchange for some price or compensation; there is no sale without compensation." P. 446.
"Where the vendor HATH in himself the property of the goods sold, he hath the liberty of disposing of them to whom ever he pleases, at any time, and in any manner." Ibid. 446.
"Where the vendor HAS ownership of the goods sold, he has the freedom to sell them to whoever he wants, whenever he wants, and however he wants." Ibid. 446.
"And notwithstanding any number of intervening sales, if the original vendor, who sold without having the property, comes again into possession of the goods, the original owner may take them, when found in his hands who was guilty of the first breach of justice." Ibid. p. 450.
"And even with any number of sales in between, if the original seller, who sold the item without actually owning it, gets the goods back, the original owner can reclaim them when they are found in the hands of the person who committed the initial wrongdoing." Ibid. p. 450.
25 "A promise is in the nature of a verbal covenant, and wants nothing but the solemnity of writing and sealing to make it absolutely the same. If therefore it be to do any explicit act, it is an express contract, as much as any covenant; and the breach of it is an equal injury."—Blackst. Com. b. iii. ch. ix. sect. 3.
25 "A promise is essentially a verbal agreement and only needs the formality of being written and sealed to be equally binding. If it requires a specific action, it is an explicit contract, just like any agreement; and breaking it causes the same level of harm."—Blackst. Com. b. iii. ch. ix. sect. 3.
26 All the reasonings of Grotius, on this, and on every other point, are intended to apply not only to the transactions of individuals, but to the conduct and affairs of nations.
26 All of Grotius's arguments on this and every other issue are meant to apply not just to individual actions, but also to the behavior and dealings of nations.
27 "The most universal and effectual way of discovering the true meaning of a law, when the words are dubious, is by considering the REASON and SPIRIT of it, or the cause which moved the legislator to enact it. For when the reason ceases, the law itself ought likewise to cease with it."—Blackst. Introd. Com. ch. 2. p. 16.
27 "The best and most effective way to understand the true meaning of a law when its wording is unclear is to look at its REASON and SPIRIT, or the motivation behind the legislator's decision to make it. Because when the reason is no longer valid, the law should also no longer be valid."—Blackst. Introd. Com. ch. 2. p. 16.
29 From this simple origin of barter, and exchange of things have arisen all the various transactions of commerce. And what was at first an act of necessity between individuals, has proved an inexhaustible source of wealth and prosperity to nations.
29 From this basic idea of bartering and exchanging goods, all the different types of commercial transactions have developed. What started as a simple necessity between individuals has turned into a never-ending source of wealth and prosperity for nations.
31 The Dutch in order to secure to themselves the monopoly of the spice-trade have frequently destroyed all the productions of the spice islands beyond what was necessary for their own supply. By the just policy of the laws of England, "combinations among victuallers or artificers, to raise the price of provisions, or any commodities, or the rate of labour, are in many cases severely punished by particular statutes; and, in general, by statute 2 and 3 Edwd. VI. c. 15, with the forfeiture of 10 l., or twenty days imprisonment with an allowance of only bread and water, for the first offence; 20 l. or the pillory for the second; and 40 l. for the third, or else the pillory, loss of one ear, and perpetual infamy. In the same manner, by a constitution of the Emperor Zeno, all monopolies and combinations to keep up the price of merchandise, provisions, or workmanship, were prohibited, upon pain of forfeiture of goods and perpetual banishment."—Blackst. Com. b. iv. c. 12. p. 159.—Also the 39 Geo. III. c. 81, enacted, that every person combining with others to advance their wages, or decrease the quantity of work, or any way to affect or controul those who carried on any manufacture or trade in the conduct and management thereof, might be convicted before one justice of the peace, and might be committed to the common gaol for any time not exceeding three calendar months, or be kept to hard labour in the house of correction for two months.—Christian's notes to Blackstone on the same place.
31 The Dutch, in order to maintain control over the spice trade, have often destroyed all the production from the spice islands beyond what they needed for their own use. According to the fair policies of English law, "collusions among food suppliers or craftsmen to raise prices of food, goods, or labor rates are often severely punished under specific statutes; and, generally, under statute 2 and 3 Edward VI, chapter 15, with a fine of £10 or twenty days in jail with only bread and water for the first offense; £20 or the pillory for the second; and £40 for the third, or the pillory, loss of one ear, and lasting disgrace. Similarly, by a rule from Emperor Zeno, all monopolies and agreements to keep prices of goods, provisions, or services high were banned, with the risk of losing goods and permanent exile."—Blackst. Com. b. iv. c. 12. p. 159.—Also, the 39 Geo. III. c. 81 states that anyone who joins with others to raise their wages, reduce the amount of work, or otherwise influence or control those engaged in any manufacture or trade, can be prosecuted before a single magistrate and may be sentenced to jail for up to three months, or made to perform hard labor in a correctional facility for two months.—Christian's notes to Blackstone on the same place.
32 "It is possible that an estate or a house may, during the term of a lease, be so increased or diminished in its value, as to become worth much more, or much less, than the rent agreed to be paid for it. In some of which cases it may be doubted, to whom, of natural right, the advantage or disadvantage belongs. The rule of justice seems to be this: If the alteration might be EXPECTED by the parties, the hirer must take the consequence; if it could not, the owner. An orchard, or a vineyard, or a mine, or a fishery, or a decoy, may this year yield nothing or next to nothing, yet the tenant shall pay his rent; and if they next year produce tenfold the usual profit, no more shall be demanded; because the produce is in its nature precarious, and this variation might be expected."—Paley's, Mor. Phil. vol. 1. p. 155, 156.
32 "It's possible for a property or a house to increase or decrease in value during the lease period, so it could end up being worth a lot more or a lot less than the agreed-upon rent. In some cases, it might be unclear who naturally benefits or suffers from this change. The principle of fairness seems to be this: if the change was something the parties could have anticipated, then the tenant has to deal with the consequences; if it wasn’t foreseeable, then the property owner does. An orchard, vineyard, mine, fishery, or similar property might produce little or nothing this year, yet the tenant still has to pay rent; and if next year they yield ten times the usual profit, the rent won't increase because the income is inherently uncertain, and this fluctuation was something that could have been expected."—Paley's, Mor. Phil. vol. 1. p. 155, 156.
33 The following passage from Judge Blackstone will both elucidate the meaning and support the reasoning of our author. "Though money was originally used only for the purposes of exchange, yet the laws of any state may be well justified in permitting it to be turned to the purposes of profit, if the convenience of society (the great end for which money was invented) shall require it. And that the allowance of moderate interest tends greatly to the benefit of the public, especially in a trading country, will appear from that generally acknowledged principle, that commerce cannot subsist without mutual and extensive credit. Unless money therefore can be borrowed, trade cannot be carried on: and if no premium were allowed for the hire of money, few persons would care to lend it; or at least the ease of borrowing at short warning (which is the life of commerce) would be entirely at an end."—B. ii. ch. 30. p. 454, 455.
33 The following passage from Judge Blackstone will clarify the meaning and support the reasoning of our author. "Although money was originally used just for exchanging goods, the laws of any state can justifiably allow it to be used for profit if the convenience of society (the primary purpose for which money was created) requires it. Furthermore, allowing moderate interest significantly benefits the public, especially in a trading nation, as is widely accepted that commerce cannot thrive without mutual and extensive credit. If money cannot be borrowed, trade cannot continue; and if no interest were permitted for borrowing money, few people would be willing to lend it; or at the very least, the ability to borrow quickly (which is essential for commerce) would be completely gone."—B. ii. ch. 30. p. 454, 455.
34 "The Mosaic law indeed prohibited the lending of money upon usury. But this was a political and not a moral precept. It only prohibited the Jews from taking usury of their brethren the Jews, but in express words permitted them to take it of a stranger: which proves that the taking of moderate usury, or a reward for the use, is not an evil in itself, since it was allowed where any but an Israelite was concerned."—Blackst. Com. b. ii. ch. 30. p. 454. The objections made to it by Cicero and others, our author observes, are founded more upon the consequences of usury than upon usury itself. Because it deters men from borrowing. But, on the other hand, if there were no advantage attached to the lending of money, none would be found willing to lend; consequently the benefits arising from a facility of borrowing money to carry on trade would be defeated.
34 "The Mosaic law did forbid lending money with interest. However, this was a political guideline rather than a moral one. It only stopped Jews from charging interest to other Jews but explicitly allowed them to charge it to outsiders. This indicates that charging moderate interest, or receiving compensation for the use of money, isn't inherently wrong, since it was allowed when dealing with anyone other than an Israelite."—Blackst. Com. b. ii. ch. 30. p. 454. The objections raised by Cicero and others, our author notes, focus more on the effects of usury than on usury itself. It discourages people from borrowing. On the flip side, if there were no benefits to lending money, no one would be willing to lend; therefore, the advantages of being able to borrow money for trade would be lost.
35 "Insurances being contracts, the very essence of which consists in observing the purest good faith and integrity, they are vacated by any the least shadow of fraud or undue concealment; and, on the other hand, being much for the benefit and extension of trade, by distributing the loss or gain among a number of adventurers, they are greatly encouraged and protected both by common law and acts of parliament."—Blackst. Com. b. ii. ch. 30. p. 460.
35 "Since insurance contracts rely on complete honesty and integrity, they become invalid if there's even a hint of fraud or concealment. At the same time, insurance is beneficial for promoting trade by spreading risk among many participants, so it receives strong support and protection from both common law and legislation."—Blackst. Com. b. ii. ch. 30. p. 460.
"The contract of insurance is founded upon the purest principles of morality and abstract justice. Hence it is necessary that the contracting parties should have perfectly equal knowledge or ignorance of every material circumstance respecting the thing insured. If on either side there is any misrepresentation or allegatio falsi, or concealment, or suppressio veri, which would in any degree affect the premium, or the terms of the engagement, the contract is fraudulent and absolutely void."—Christian's note on the same passage.
"The insurance contract is based on the highest principles of morality and fairness. Therefore, it’s essential that both parties involved have equal knowledge or lack of knowledge about every important detail concerning the insured item. If either party makes any false statements, hides information, or withholds the truth in a way that could influence the premium or the terms of the agreement, the contract is considered fraudulent and completely invalid."—Christian's note on the same passage.
36 There is a distinction to be observed between the NECESSARY, and the VOLUNTARY law of nations. Vattel defines the NECESSARY law to be "that which is always obligatory on the conscience, and of which a nation ought never to lose sight in the line of conduct she is to pursue in order to fulfil her duty, but when there is a question of examining what she may demand of other states, she must consult the Voluntary law, whose maxims are devoted to the safety and advantage of the universal society of mankind."—Prelim. sect. 28.
36 There is a difference to recognize between the Essential and the Optional laws of nations. Vattel defines the Essential law as "that which is always mandatory on the conscience and which a nation should never ignore in determining how to act in order to fulfill its duty. However, when considering what it can demand from other states, it must refer to the Optional law, whose principles are focused on the safety and benefit of the global society of humanity."—Prelim. sect. 28.
37 The writer quoted in the preceding note defines that obligation "to be INTERNAL, which binds the conscience, and is deduced from the rules of duty; and that to be EXTERNAL, which is considered relatively to other men, and produces some right between them."—Ibid. sect. 17.
37 The writer quoted in the previous note describes that obligation "to be INTERNAL, which binds the conscience, and is deduced from the rules of duty; and that to be EXTERNAL, which is considered in relation to other people, and creates some rights between them."—Ibid. sect. 17.
38 A treaty may be more advantageous to one of the contracting parties than to the other, and yet contain nothing unjust. "Frequently a great monarch, wishing to engage a weaker state in his interest, offers her advantageous conditions, promises her gratuitous succours, or greater than he stipulates for himself; but at the same time he claims a superiority of dignity, and requires respect from his ally. It is this last particular which renders THE ALLIANCE UNEQUAL: and to this circumstance we must attentively advert; for with alliances of this nature we are not to confound those in which the parties treat on a footing of equality, though the more powerful of the allies, for particular reasons, gives more than he receives, promises his assistance gratis, without requiring gratuitous assistance in his turn, or promises more considerable succours or even the assistance of all his forces: here the alliance is equal, but the treaty is unequal, unless indeed we may be allowed to say, that, as the party who makes the greater concessions has a greater interest in concluding the treaty, this consideration restores the equality. Thus, at a time when France found herself embarrassed in a momentous war with the house of Austria, and the cardinal de Richelieu wished to humble that formidable power, he, like an able minister, concluded a treaty with Gustavus Adolphus, in which all the advantage appeared to be on the side of Sweden. From a bare consideration of the stipulations of that treaty, it would have been pronounced an unequal one; but the advantages which France derived from it, amply compensated for that inequality."—Vattel, b. ii. ch. 12. sect. 175. p. 200, 201.
38 A treaty might benefit one of the parties involved more than the other, yet still be fair. "Often, a powerful monarch, seeking to involve a weaker state in his interests, offers favorable terms, promises assistance for free, or grants more than he’s asking for himself; but he also asserts his superiority in status and demands respect from his ally. This aspect is what makes THE UNEQUAL ALLIANCE: and we should pay close attention to this, as we should not confuse these types of alliances with those where both parties engage on equal footing, even if the stronger ally, for specific reasons, gives more than he gets, offers help without expecting anything in return, or promises significant support or even all his forces. In this case, the alliance is equal, but the treaty is unequal, unless we think that since the party making more concessions has more motivation to finalize the treaty, this consideration brings back some balance. For example, at a time when France was in a difficult war with the House of Austria, and Cardinal de Richelieu wanted to weaken that powerful enemy, he, as a skilled leader, formed a treaty with Gustavus Adolphus that seemed to benefit Sweden more. Just by looking at the terms of that treaty, one would deem it unequal; however, the advantages France gained from it made up for that imbalance."—Vattel, b. ii. ch. 12. sect. 175. p. 200, 201.
39 The nature of oaths, contracts and promises having been so fully discussed in the preceding chapters, the translation proceeds from the thirteenth to the fifteenth chapter of the original, the fourteenth being in a great measure only a repetition of our author's former arguments upon the subject.—Translator.
39 Since we've thoroughly covered the nature of oaths, contracts, and promises in the previous chapters, we'll now move from the thirteenth to the fifteenth chapter of the original text. The fourteenth chapter mainly repeats our author's previous arguments on the topic.—Translator.
40 On this subject the opinions of our author, and those of Vattel will reflect light upon each other. From the latter of whom, the following extracts will place the matter in a clear point of view. "If a public person, an ambassador, or a general of an army, exceeding the bounds of his commission, concludes a treaty or a convention without orders from the sovereign or without being authorised to do it by virtue of his office, the treaty is null, as being made without sufficient powers: it cannot become valid without the express or tacit ratification of the sovereign. The express ratification is a written deed by which the sovereign approves the treaty, and engages to observe it. The tacit ratification is implied by certain steps which the sovereign is justly presumed to take only in pursuance of the treaty, and which he could not be supposed to take without considering it as concluded and agreed upon. Thus, on a treaty of peace being signed by public ministers who have even exceeded the orders of their sovereigns, if one of the sovereigns causes troops to pass on the footing of friends through the territories of his reconciled enemy, he tacitly ratifies the treaty of peace. But if, by a reservatory clause of the treaty, the ratification of the sovereign be required—as such reservation is usually understood to imply an express ratification, it is absolutely requisite that the treaty be thus expressly ratified before it can acquire its full force. By the Latin term sponsio, we express an agreement relating to affairs of state, made by a public person, who exceeds the bounds of his commission, and acts without the orders or command of the sovereign. The person who treats for the state in this manner without being commissioned for the purpose, promises of course to use his endeavours for prevailing on the state or sovereign to ratify the articles he has agreed to: otherwise his engagements would be nugatory and illusive. The foundation of this agreement can be no other, on either side, than the hope of such ratification."—Vattel, b. ii. ch. xiv. sect. 208, 209, p. 219. "The general of an army, he proceeds, has indeed by virtue of his commission, a power to enter, as circumstances may require, into a private convention,—a compact relative to himself, to his troops, or to the occurrences of war: but he has no power to conclude a treaty of peace. He may bind himself, and the troops under his command, on all occasions where his functions require that he should have the power of treating; but he cannot bind the state beyond the extent of his commission."—Ibid. sect. 210. p. 220.
40 In this regard, the perspectives of our author and Vattel will illuminate one another. The following quotes from Vattel will clarify the issue. "If a public official, such as an ambassador or a general, goes beyond the limits of their authority and concludes a treaty or agreement without the sovereign's orders or without the power to do so by virtue of their position, the treaty is void because it was made without the necessary authority: it cannot be valid without the explicit or implied ratification of the sovereign. The explicit ratification is a written document in which the sovereign approves the treaty and agrees to uphold it. The implied ratification occurs through certain actions that the sovereign is reasonably presumed to take solely in alignment with the treaty, which they could not be assumed to take without considering it as finalized and accepted. For instance, if a peace treaty is signed by public officials who have even overstepped their sovereigns' instructions, and one of the sovereigns allows troops to pass through the territories of their reconciled enemy as friends, they tacitly ratify the peace treaty. However, if the treaty includes a clause that requires the sovereign's ratification, as such a clause is typically understood to require explicit ratification, it is absolutely necessary for the treaty to be explicitly ratified before it can have its full effect. The Latin term sponsio refers to an agreement regarding state matters made by a public person who exceeds their authority and acts without the orders or commands of the sovereign. A person negotiating for the state in this way, without being authorized, naturally promises to strive for the state or sovereign to ratify the articles they have agreed to; otherwise, their commitments would be ineffective and misleading. The basis of this agreement can only be the expectation of such ratification."—Vattel, b. ii. ch. xiv. sect. 208, 209, p. 219. "The general of an army, he continues, does have the authority by virtue of his commission to enter into a private agreement—an arrangement related to himself, his troops, or the circumstances of war: but he does not have the power to finalize a peace treaty. He can commit himself and the troops under his command whenever his duties require that he has the authority to negotiate; but he cannot bind the state beyond the limits of his commission."—Ibid. sect. 210. p. 220.
41 "The right of postliminium is that, in virtue of which, persons and things taken by the enemy are restored to their former state, on coming again into the power of the nation to which they belonged." Vattel, b. iii. ch. xiv. sect. 204.
41 "The right of postliminium means that individuals and items taken by the enemy are returned to their original status once they come back under the control of the nation they belonged to." Vattel, b. iii. ch. xiv. sect. 204.
42 "Personal creditors are in the Roman law called Chirographarii, because they commonly have some bond or note of hand for the debt. And where there are several such creditors, if the debtor's estate is not sufficient to satisfy them all, each has his share assigned in proportion to the largeness of the debt, without any regard to the time, when it was contracted. But in mortgages it was different, the debt of longest standing was to be first satisfied."—Barbeyrac.
42 "In Roman law, personal creditors are referred to as Chirographarii because they usually have some form of bond or promissory note for the debt. If there are several such creditors and the debtor's assets aren't enough to pay them all, each creditor gets a share based on the size of their debt, regardless of when it was incurred. However, in the case of mortgages, it was different; the oldest debt was to be paid first."—Barbeyrac.
43 When the Roman army had passed under the yoke at Caudium, upon their return, when the matter was referred to the senate, it was said that as the convention was made without the consent of the senate or people, the Roman people were not bound by it, and a proposal was made that those who had signed the treaty should again be given up to the enemy, thus the people would be released from the engagement. This proposal was agreed to, and a decree to that purpose passed.
43 When the Roman army submitted to the yoke at Caudium, upon their return and after the matter was brought before the senate, it was stated that since the agreement was made without the approval of the senate or the people, the Roman citizens were not obligated to it. A suggestion was made to hand over those who had signed the treaty back to the enemy, which would free the people from the commitment. This suggestion was accepted, and a decree to that effect was enacted.
44 Luctatius had inserted this clause that the agreement should be good and valid, only in case it was approved by the Roman people.—Liv. lib. xxi. c. xix. See likewise Polybius, lib. iii. c. xxi.
44 Luctatius added this clause stating that the agreement would only be valid if it was approved by the Roman people.—Liv. lib. xxi. c. xix. See also Polybius, lib. iii. c. xxi.
45 "In all human affairs, where absolute certainty is not at hand to point out the way, we must take probability for our guide. In most cases it is extremely probable that the parties have expressed themselves conformably to the established usage: and such probability ever affords a strong presumption, which cannot be overruled but by a still stronger presumption to the contrary. Camden, in his history of Queen Elizabeth, gives us a treaty, in which it is expressly said that the treaty shall be precisely understood according to the force and appropriate signification of the terms."—Vattel, b. ii. ch. xvii. sect. 271. On the same subject, Judge Blackstone says, that "words are generally to be understood in their usual and most known signification; not so much regarding the propriety of grammar, as their general and popular use."—Introduct. to Com. ch. ii. p. 59.
45 "In all human matters, when absolute certainty isn't available to show us the way, we have to rely on probability as our guide. In most situations, it's highly likely that the parties have expressed themselves in line with established usage: and this likelihood provides a strong presumption that can't be overturned unless there's an even stronger presumption against it. Camden, in his history of Queen Elizabeth, includes a treaty that explicitly states the treaty should be understood according to the true meaning and significance of the terms."—Vattel, b. ii. ch. xvii. sect. 271. Regarding the same topic, Judge Blackstone notes that "words are usually understood in their common and most recognized meaning; not so much focusing on grammatical correctness, but on their general and popular use."—Introduct. to Com. ch. ii. p. 59.
46 "The word DAY is understood of the NATURAL DAY, or of the time during which the sun affords us his light, and of the CIVIL DAY, or the space of twenty-four hours. When it is used in a convention to point out a space of time, the subject itself manifestly shews that the parties mean the civil day, or the term of twenty-four hours."—Vattel, b. ii. ch. xvii. sect. 280.
46 "The term DAY refers to the NATURAL DAY, or the period when the sun provides light, and to the Civic Day, which is a span of twenty-four hours. When used in an agreement to indicate a period of time, it's clear that the parties intend to mean the civil day, or a duration of twenty-four hours."—Vattel, b. ii. ch. xvii. sect. 280.
47 "It is a fundamental rule of construction, that penal statutes shall be construed strictly, and remedial statutes shall be construed liberally. It was one of the laws of the twelve tables of Rome, that whenever there was a question between liberty and slavery, the presumption should be on the side of liberty. This excellent principle our law has adopted in the construction of penal statutes: for whenever any ambiguity arises in a statute introducing a new penalty or punishment, the decision shall be on the side of lenity and mercy; or in favour of natural right and liberty: or, in other words, the decision shall be according to the strict letter in favour of the subject. And though the judges in such cases may frequently raise and solve difficulties contrary to the intention or the legislature, yet no further inconvenience can result, than that the law remains as it was before the statute, and it is more consonant to principles of liberty, that the judge should acquit whom the legislator intended to punish, than that he should punish whom the legislator intended to discharge with impunity. But remedial statutes must be construed according to the spirit: for in giving relief against fraud, or in the furtherance and extension of natural right and justice, the judge may safely go even beyond that which existed in the minds of those who framed the law."—Christian's Notes on Blackst. Comm. Introd. p. 87.
47 "It’s a basic rule of law that criminal statutes should be interpreted strictly, while laws meant to help should be interpreted generously. One of the Twelve Tables of Roman law stated that when there’s a conflict between freedom and slavery, the assumption should favor freedom. Our legal system has adopted this great principle for interpreting criminal laws: whenever there’s any uncertainty in a law that introduces a new penalty or punishment, the ruling should lean towards leniency and mercy, or in favor of natural rights and freedom. In simpler terms, the decision should be made according to the strict wording that benefits the individual. Even though judges may sometimes create and resolve issues that go against what the lawmakers intended, the only issue that comes from this is that the law holds as it was before the statute. It’s more aligned with the principles of freedom for a judge to clear someone the lawmakers wanted to punish than to punish someone the lawmakers intended to let go without penalty. However, laws meant to provide relief should be interpreted with their purpose in mind; when addressing fraud or promoting and expanding natural rights and justice, judges can safely go even further than what the law's creators may have envisioned."—Christian's Notes on Blackst. Comm. Introd. p. 87.
48 The case of a promise made on the supposition of a posthumous child's dying, instanced by our author in this place, bears so near a resemblance to that of a father's bequeathing his property to another, believing his son to be dead, that it is omitted in this chapter having been already given under the head of erroneous promises in the xi. chapter and 6th section of this book.—(Translator.)
48 The situation involving a promise made under the assumption that a child will die after birth, as mentioned by our author here, is so similar to a father's decision to leave his belongings to someone else because he thinks his son has died, that we’ve left it out of this chapter since it was already addressed in the section on mistaken promises in chapter xi, section 6 of this book.—(Translator.)
49 "The variety of human transactions cannot be comprised within general rules. Occasional decrees therefore become requisite; which vary with each variation of circumstances, for the measure of what is indefinite must be indefinite itself, like the leaden ruler in the Lesbian architecture, which changes its own shape according to that of the stones to which it is applied. It is manifest, therefore, that equity is a species of justice, and contrasted with another species to which it is preferable. A man of equity is he who deliberately and habitually exercises this virtue; who prefers it in all his dealings to the rigour of justice; and who, even when the law is on his side, will not avail himself of this advantage to treat others injuriously or unhandsomely."—Aristot. Eth. b. v. ch. x.
49 "The variety of human interactions can't be limited to general rules. That's why occasional decisions are necessary; they change with each new circumstance, because something that is indefinite must itself be indefinite, like the lead ruler in Lesbian architecture, which changes its shape based on the stones it's applied to. It's clear, then, that equity is a type of justice and is contrasted with another type that is preferable. A person of equity is someone who consistently and intentionally practices this virtue; who prioritizes it in all their dealings over strict justice; and who, even when the law is on their side, will not use that advantage to treat others unfairly or unkindly."—Aristot. Eth. b. v. ch. x.
50 Owing to circumstances there may be a variation in the conduct, and yet no change in the principles of a state. This must frequently happen in the commercial regulations between different countries, who are obliged to vary their means to secure the unity of their end. Or if in a treaty between two nations, it is declared there shall be PERPETUAL amity, and a subsequent declaration of war by one of the parties pronounces such amicable relations to be at an end, here there is no variation in PRINCIPLE but in CIRCUMSTANCES, which render such a dissolution of the amity, that was originally intended to be perpetual, necessary to the welfare and preservation of that power, the sole object of all treaties.
50 Due to circumstances, there may be differences in behavior, but the principles of a state remain unchanged. This often occurs in the trade regulations between different countries, which must adjust their methods to achieve the same goal. For example, if a treaty between two nations states there shall be Eternal friendship, and later one of the parties declares war, this ends the friendly relations. Here, the principles remain the same, but the SITUATION have changed, making it necessary to dissolve the friendship that was meant to be everlasting for the sake of the power’s welfare and preservation, which is the main aim of all treaties.
51 To illustrate the nature of GENERAL AND PARTICULAR cases, the following example is taken from the Puffendorf:—"One law forbids us to appear in public with arms on holidays: another law commands us to turn out under arms and repair to our posts, as soon as we hear the sound of the alarm bell. The alarm is rung on a holiday. In such case we must obey the latter of the two laws, which creates an exception to the former."—Jur. Gent, lib. v. c. xii. sect. 23.
51 To illustrate the nature of GENERAL AND PARTICULAR cases, the following example is taken from Puffendorf:—"One law prohibits us from appearing in public with weapons on holidays: another law requires us to arm ourselves and go to our posts as soon as we hear the sound of the alarm bell. The alarm rings on a holiday. In this situation, we must follow the second law, which creates an exception to the first."—Jur. Gent, lib. v. c. xii. sect. 23.
52 "The deputies sent to the assembly of the states of a kingdom, or a commonwealth are not public ministers like ambassadors, as they are not sent to foreign powers; but they are public persons, and, in that respect, are possessed of every exemption and immunity, that are necessary to the discharge of their functions."—Vatt. b. iv. ch. vii. sect. 109. Of this nature are the privileges enjoyed by the representatives of the British people, and denominated the PRIVILEGES OF PARLIAMENT.
52 "The representatives sent to the assembly of the states of a kingdom or a commonwealth are not public ministers like ambassadors because they are not sent to foreign powers; however, they are public figures and, in that sense, have every exemption and immunity that are necessary to carry out their duties."—Vatt. b. iv. ch. vii. sect. 109. This includes the privileges enjoyed by the representatives of the British people, known as the Parliamentary Privileges.
53 Nothing forms a more striking contrast between ancient and modern war, then the personal animosities, which seemed to operate upon the combatants in the former, and the public and national objects, WITHOUT ANY PERSONAL CONCERN, upon which the latter are undertaken. Peruse any ancient historian, or the battles in Homer and Virgil, WHICH THOUGH FICTIONS, DESCRIBE THE MANNERS OF THE AGE, and you see combatants engaged, on whom the laws of nature and of nations seem to have lost their force. Read the accounts of modern warfare and you find hostilities commenced, not from private animosity, but from some great and national object, in the prosecution of which the feelings of the individuals appointed to conduct them are not the only springs of action.
53 Nothing creates a more striking contrast between ancient and modern warfare than the personal grudges that influenced the fighters in the past, compared to the public and national goals, WITHOUT ANY PERSONAL AGENDAS, that drive the latter. If you look at any ancient historian or the battles described in Homer and Virgil, WHICH, ALTHOUGH FICTIONS, REFLECT THE CUSTOMS OF THE TIME, you'll see fighters who seem to be beyond the reach of the laws of nature and of nations. In modern warfare, however, hostilities begin not from personal hatred, but from significant national objectives, where the feelings of the individuals leading the efforts are not the only motivations.
54 Sections XVI and XVII of the original, relating only to the refutation of certain abstruse opinions, are omitted in the translation.—(Translator.)
54 Sections XVI and XVII of the original, which only address the disagreement with some complex opinions, are left out of the translation.—(Translator.)
56 Thus letters of marque and reprisal, by which individuals are enabled to redress their own wrongs, must issue from the sovereign power, otherwise the hostilities of such individuals would be unlawful. So that here the ACTION would be unlawful, that is unjust, unless performed by an AGENT, who had a commission from public authority.
56 So, letters of marque and reprisal, which allow individuals to seek justice for their own grievances, must come from the sovereign power; otherwise, the actions of those individuals would be illegal. Therefore, here the Action would be illegal, meaning unjust, unless carried out by an REPRESENTATIVE who has authorization from public authority.
57 The three rules above laid down by our author may be illustrated by the three following propositions.—
57 The three rules mentioned above by our author can be explained by the three propositions below.—
In the first place, it cannot be denied, that war, in the ABSTRACT, is an evil, but then it is necessary to consider, whether it is not an evil that must, in many cases, be submitted to in order to avoid still greater calamities.
In the first place, it can't be denied that war, in the ABSTRACT, is a bad thing, but we also need to consider whether it’s an evil that must, in many cases, be tolerated to avoid even greater disasters.
Secondly, in the prosecution of a war, where the advantages, or evils are doubtful, it is necessary to endeavour after the attainment of new confederacies or alliances, that may compensate for the losses sustained, or may open out new channels of trade and commerce, which may supply the place of those that have been closed by the immediate war.
Secondly, in the pursuit of a war, where the benefits or harms are unclear, it’s important to seek out new alliances or partnerships that can make up for the losses suffered, or that can create new avenues for trade and commerce, which can replace those that have been shut down due to the ongoing conflict.
As an illustration of the third point, we may adduce the conduct of King William, after the British Cabinet that met at Tunbridge Wells, August 28, 1698, represented to him how inadequate the spirit of the nation was to enter into a new war, and to bear additional burdens, concluding, "this is the truth of the fact upon which your Majesty will determine what resolution ought to be taken." His Majesty did determine upon war, as the least of all the evils which faced his people, notwithstanding the APPARENT inadequacy of his means. And "in that great war, says Mr. Burke, carried on against Louis the XIV, for near eighteen years, government spared no pains to satisfy the nation, that though they were to be animated by a desire of glory, glory was not their ultimate object: but that every thing dear to them, in religion, in law, in liberty, every thing, which as freemen, as Englishmen, and as citizens of the great commonwealth of Christendom, they had at heart, was then at stake."—Lett. on Regic Peace, p. 90.
As an example of the third point, we can mention the actions of King William after the British Cabinet met at Tunbridge Wells on August 28, 1698, and informed him how unprepared the nation was to engage in a new war and take on more burdens, concluding, "this is the truth of the fact upon which your Majesty will determine what resolution ought to be taken." His Majesty decided on war, seeing it as the least harmful option for his people, despite the EVIDENT lack of resources. And "in that great war, Mr. Burke states, which lasted nearly eighteen years against Louis XIV, the government made every effort to assure the nation that although they should be driven by a desire for glory, glory was not their ultimate goal: but that everything precious to them, in religion, in law, in liberty, everything they cared about as free people, as English people, and as citizens of the great commonwealth of Christendom, was at stake."—Lett. on Regic Peace, p. 90.
58 Thus when a ship makes an appearance of mounting more guns than she really carries, in order to deter an enemy from attacking her, this may be considered as one of those negative stratagems, or stratagems of dissimulation, to which our author alludes.
58 So, when a ship looks like it has more guns than it actually does to scare off an enemy from attacking, this can be seen as one of those deceptive tactics, or tactics of disguise, that our author refers to.
59 Besides the NECESSARY law of nations, which is EQUALLY, and at ALL TIMES binding upon ALL states, there is a POSITIVE law of nations, consisting of THE VOLUNTARY, THE CONVENTIONAL and THE CUSTOMARY law. All of which "proceed from the will of nations,—the VOLUNTARY from their presumed consent, the CONVENTIONAL from an express consent, and the CUSTOMARY from tacit consent: and as there can be no other mode of deducing any law from the will of nations, there are only these three kinds of POSITIVE LAW OF NATIONS."—Vattel, Prelim. Sect. 27.
59 Besides the N/A laws of nations, which are SAME and at ALL TIMES binding on ALL states, there is a POSITIVE law of nations, consisting of VOLUNTEER, THE TRADITIONAL, and THE NORM laws. All of these "come from the will of nations—the Voluntary from their presumed consent, the TRADITIONAL from express consent, and the TRADITIONAL from tacit consent: and since there is no other way to derive any law from the will of nations, there are only these three types of International Law."—Vattel, Prelim. Sect. 27.
60 See b. ii. ch. xxi. sect. 2. of this treatise.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Check out __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__ of this doc.
61 See b. ii. ch. xxiii. sect. 7. ibid.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__ ibid.
63 The translation proceeds from the XV. to the XXIII. Section of the original, the intermediate Sections being only a confirmation of the preceding arguments by examples from ancient history.—Translator.
63 The translation goes from Section XV to Section XXIII of the original, with the sections in between just confirming the previous arguments with examples from ancient history.—Translator.
64 Our author here speaks of things taken in battle. For upon the surrender of towns, in almost all articles of capitulation it is stipulated, that the General and other superior officers, and the officers of regiments shall preserve their swords and their private baggage, and the noncommissioned officers and soldiers shall preserve their knapsacks.
64 Our author here discusses items taken in battle. Because when towns surrender, it is usually stated in the terms of surrender that the General and other high-ranking officers, along with the officers of regiments, are allowed to keep their swords and personal belongings, while noncommissioned officers and soldiers can keep their backpacks.
65 "The end of such a law is to animate soldiers and privateers to pursue robbers and pirates, by the hopes of possessing things taken even from the subjects of the state."—Barbeyrac.
65 "The purpose of this law is to encourage soldiers and privateers to chase down robbers and pirates, fueled by the hope of seizing goods even from the citizens of the state."—Barbeyrac.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Check out __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__
68 See b. iii. ch. ii. of this work.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Check out __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__ of this project.
71 "The difficulty of recognising things of this nature, and the endless disputes, which would arise from the prosecution of the owner's claims to them, have been deemed motives of sufficient weight for the establishment of a contrary practice. It is therefore with reason, that moveables or booty are excepted from the right of postliminium, unless retaken from the enemy immediately after his capture of them; in which case the proprietor neither finds a difficulty in recognising his effects, nor is presumed to have relinquished them."—Vattel b. iii. ch. xiv. sect. 209.
71 "The challenge of identifying things like this, along with the ongoing arguments that would come from enforcing the owner's claims to them, have been considered strong enough reasons to create a different practice. Therefore, it makes sense that movable items or loot are excluded from the right of postliminium, unless they are recaptured from the enemy right after being taken; in that situation, the owner has no trouble identifying their belongings and is not assumed to have given them up."—Vattel b. iii. ch. xiv. sect. 209.
76 "The necessity of making peace authorises the Sovereign to dispose of the property of individuals; and the eminent dominion gives him a right to do it. Every thing in the political society ought to tend to the good of the community; and since even the powers of the citizens are subject to this rule, their property cannot be excepted. The state could not subsist, or constantly administer the public affairs in the most advantageous manner, if it had not a power to dispose occasionally of all kinds of property."—Vattel, b. iv. ch. ii. sect. 12. ibid. b. i. ch. xx. sect. 244.
76 "The need to establish peace allows the Sovereign to manage individual property, and the ultimate authority gives them the right to do so. Everything within the political society should contribute to the welfare of the community; and since even the powers of the citizens are subject to this principle, their property cannot be excluded. The state wouldn't be able to survive or effectively manage public affairs in the best possible way if it didn't have the authority to occasionally deal with all types of property."—Vattel, b. iv. ch. ii. sect. 12. ibid. b. i. ch. xx. sect. 244.
77 "Some damages are done deliberately and by way of precaution, as when a field, a house, or a garden, belonging to a private person, is taken for the purpose of erecting on the spot a tower, rampart, or any other piece of fortification,—or when his standing corn, or his storehouses are destroyed, to prevent their being of use to the enemy. Such damages are to be made good to the individual, who should bear only his quota of the loss. But there are other damages, caused by inevitable necessity, as for instance, the destruction caused by the artillery in retaking a town from the enemy. These are merely accidents, they are misfortunes, which chance deals out to the proprietors on whom they happen to fall. The sovereign ought indeed to shew an equitable regard for the sufferers, if the situation of his affairs will admit of it: but no action lies against the state for misfortunes of this nature,—for losses, which she has occasioned, not wilfully, but through necessity and mere accident, in the exertion of her rights. The same may be said of damages caused by the enemy." Vat. b. iii. ch. xv. sect. 232.
77 "Some damages are done on purpose and as a precaution, like when a field, house, or garden owned by someone is taken to build a tower, wall, or any other type of fortification—or when their standing crops or storage buildings are destroyed to keep them from benefiting the enemy. These damages should be compensated to the individual, who should only be responsible for their fair share of the loss. However, there are other damages caused by unavoidable necessity, such as the destruction from artillery when reclaiming a town from the enemy. These are simply accidents, misfortunes that happen to the owners who encounter them. The sovereign should show fair consideration for the affected, if their circumstances allow it: but no legal action can be taken against the state for these kinds of misfortunes—because of losses it caused, not intentionally, but out of necessity and accident, in the exercise of its rights. The same applies to damages inflicted by the enemy." Vat. b. iii. ch. xv. sect. 232.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Check out __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__
79 "Because then the condition of the contracting parties being unequal, there is great reason to believe, that he, to whose disadvantage the inequality is, has pretended to engage himself as little as possible: and it was the other's business who was to have the benefit of it, to have the thing explained in as clear a manner as possible."—Barbeyrac.
79 "Because when the parties in a contract are not equal, there's good reason to think that the person at a disadvantage has tried to limit their commitment as much as possible: and it was the responsibility of the other person who would benefit from the agreement to explain things as clearly as possible."—Barbeyrac.
Transcribers' Notes
Punctuation and hyphenation were made consistent when a predominant preference was found in this book; otherwise they were not changed. In particular, inconsistent punctuation in Biblical citations and omitted commas or periods in several places have not been remedied.
Punctuation and hyphenation were made consistent when a clear preference was identified in this book; otherwise, they were left unchanged. Specifically, inconsistent punctuation in Biblical citations and missing commas or periods in several instances have not been corrected.
Ambiguous hyphens at the ends of lines were retained.
Ambiguous hyphens at the ends of lines were kept.
Spelling was made consistent when a predominant preference was found in this book, or when some occurrences of a word matched modern usage while other occurrences did not; otherwise, all variations were retained. Words spelled differently in quoted material than in the primary author's text were not changed.
Spelling was made consistent when a main preference was identified in this book, or when some instances of a word matched modern usage while others did not; otherwise, all variations were kept. Words that were spelled differently in quoted material compared to the primary author's text were not altered.
Simple typographical errors were corrected; occasional unbalanced quotation marks remedied when unambiguous, and otherwise retained. These are noted below.
Simple typographical errors were fixed; occasional unbalanced quotation marks were corrected when it was clear what was meant, and otherwise kept as is. These are noted below.
Several chapters were omitted from the English translation of which this is a transcription. The reasons for this are given in the footnotes.
Several chapters were left out of the English translation from which this is a transcription. The reasons for this are provided in the footnotes.
The Index was not checked for proper alphabetization or correct page references.
The Index wasn't checked for proper alphabetical order or accurate page references.
Within the Index, links to notes were added based on the assumption that the references were to footnotes on the pages identified just before the word "notes."
Within the Index, links to notes were added with the assumption that the references pointed to footnotes on the pages mentioned right before the word "notes."
"Controul" is always spelled that way in the original book.
"Controul" is always spelled that way in the original book.
"Commit" sometimes is used where modern practice would use "commits".
"Commit" is sometimes used where modern practice would use "commits."
Text uses both "sometimes" and "some times", "anything" and "any thing".
Text uses both "sometimes" and "some times," "anything" and "any thing."
Some footnotes reference Chapters that were omitted from this translation.
Some footnotes refer to chapters that were left out of this translation.
Page 3: "Jugemens d' Oléron" likely is a misprint for "Jugements d' Oléron"; "Saurez" may be a misprint for "Suarez".
Page 3: "Jugemens d' Oléron" is probably a typo for "Jugements d' Oléron"; "Saurez" might be a typo for "Suarez".
Page 21: "δικαιώματα" {dikaiômata} was misprinted as "δικαὠματα" {dikaômata} and has been changed here.
Page 21: "rights" {dikaiômata} was incorrectly printed as "δικαὠματα" {dikaômata} and has been corrected here.
Page 43: No matching closing quotation mark found for sentence beginning '"How can kings serve the Lord'.
Page 43: No matching closing quotation mark found for sentence beginning '"How can kings serve the Lord'.
Page 55: No matching closing quotation mark found for clause beginning '"what can be done by a magistrate'.
Page 55: No matching closing quotation mark found for the clause starting with '"what can be done by a magistrate'.
Page 59: No matching closing quotation mark found for sentence beginning '"For though UNDER SOME'.
Page 59: No matching closing quotation mark found for the sentence that starts with '"For though UNDER CERTAIN'.
Page 73: "ἀρχας πολεμων" {archas polemôn} was misprinted as "ἀρχασπολεμων" {archaspolemôn}; changed here.
Page 73: "Beginning of wars" {archas polemôn} was incorrectly printed as "war chief" {archaspolemôn}; corrected here.
Page 78: No matching opening quotation mark found for sentence ending 'whom he himself apprehended injury or destruction."'
Page 78: No matching opening quotation mark found for the sentence ending 'whom he himself feared harm or destruction.'
Page 107: "will not continue to be same river" likely is missing "the".
Page 107: "will not continue to be the same river" likely is missing "the".
Page 110: No matching closing quotation mark found for clause beginning '"that he would restore'.
Page 110: No matching closing quotation mark found for clause beginning '"that he would restore'.
Page 193: "what is required to be done at a" was printed as "to be one at"; changed here.
Page 193: "what needs to be done at a" was printed as "to be one at"; changed here.
Page 249: "uninjured or endangered" may be a misprint for "injured".
Page 249: "uninjured or endangered" might be a typo for "injured".
Page 267: "αἰτιας" {aitias} was misprinted as "ὰιτιας" {aitias}; changed here.
Page 267: "κατηγόρια" {aitias} was incorrectly printed as "ὰιτιας" {aitias}; updated here.
Page 286: Transcriber added closing quotation mark at the end of the paragraph ending with 'or even imminent danger.'
Page 286: The transcriber added a closing quotation mark at the end of the paragraph that ends with 'or even imminent danger.'
Page 310: the colon in "which is an act of justice: in the next place" was poorly printed, and may be either a different punctuation mark or just a space.
Page 310: the colon in "which is an act of justice: in the next place" was poorly printed and might be a different punctuation mark or just a space.
Page 314: the closing quotation mark in 'denomination of pirates and robbers." With' was added by the Transcriber.
Page 314: the closing quotation mark in 'denomination of pirates and robbers.' With' was added by the Transcriber.
Page 321: Transcriber added a comma in "by that act, voluntarily" because there was excess space between the words, which suggested a misprint.
Page 321: The transcriber added a comma in "by that act, voluntarily" because there was extra space between the words, which indicated a potential misprint.
Footnote 18: Transcriber added a closing quotation mark at the end of the footnote.
Footnote 18: The transcriber added a closing quotation mark at the end of the footnote.
Footnote 19: Transcriber added a closing quotation mark after 'my neglect or refusal.'
Footnote 19: The transcriber added a closing quotation mark after 'my neglect or refusal.'
Download ePUB
If you like this ebook, consider a donation!