This is a modern-English version of A Treatise of Human Nature, originally written by Hume, David.
It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling,
and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If
you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.
Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.
A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE
By David Hume
CONTENTS
TABLE OF CONTENTS
ADVERTISEMENT.
My design in the present work is sufficiently explained in the Introduction. The reader must only observe, that all the subjects I have there planned out to myself, are not treated of in these two volumes. The subjects of the Understanding and Passions make a compleat chain of reasoning by themselves; and I was willing to take advantage of this natural division, in order to try the taste of the public. If I have the good fortune to meet with success, I shall proceed to the examination of Morals, Politics, and Criticism; which will compleat this Treatise of Human Nature. The approbation of the public I consider as the greatest reward of my labours; but am determined to regard its judgment, whatever it be, as my best instruction.
My design in this work is clearly explained in the Introduction. The reader should note that I haven’t covered all the topics I planned for these two volumes. The subjects of Understanding and Passions create a complete chain of reasoning on their own, and I wanted to take advantage of this natural separation to gauge the public's interest. If I’m fortunate enough to be successful, I will move on to examine Morals, Politics, and Criticism, which will complete this Treatise of Human Nature. I see public approval as the greatest reward for my efforts, but I’m committed to viewing its judgment, whatever it may be, as my best guide.
INTRODUCTION.
Nothing is more usual and more natural for those, who pretend to discover anything new to the world in philosophy and the sciences, than to insinuate the praises of their own systems, by decrying all those, which have been advanced before them. And indeed were they content with lamenting that ignorance, which we still lie under in the most important questions, that can come before the tribunal of human reason, there are few, who have an acquaintance with the sciences, that would not readily agree with them. It is easy for one of judgment and learning, to perceive the weak foundation even of those systems, which have obtained the greatest credit, and have carried their pretensions highest to accurate and profound reasoning. Principles taken upon trust, consequences lamely deduced from them, want of coherence in the parts, and of evidence in the whole, these are every where to be met with in the systems of the most eminent philosophers, and seem to have drawn disgrace upon philosophy itself.
Nothing is more common and natural for those who claim to discover something new in philosophy and the sciences than to promote their own ideas by criticizing all those that came before them. And honestly, if they were just focused on pointing out the ignorance we still face regarding the most important questions that human reason can address, most people familiar with the sciences would likely agree with them. It’s easy for someone who is knowledgeable and learned to see the shaky foundations of even the most respected systems, which claim to provide accurate and deep reasoning. Principles taken on faith, poorly drawn conclusions, and a lack of coherence in the parts and evidence in the whole can be found everywhere in the works of the most prominent philosophers, and this seems to have brought shame upon philosophy itself.
Nor is there required such profound knowledge to discover the present imperfect condition of the sciences, but even the rabble without doors may, judge from the noise and clamour, which they hear, that all goes not well within. There is nothing which is not the subject of debate, and in which men of learning are not of contrary opinions. The most trivial question escapes not our controversy, and in the most momentous we are not able to give any certain decision. Disputes are multiplied, as if every thing was uncertain; and these disputes are managed with the greatest warmth, as if every thing was certain. Amidst all this bustle it is not reason, which carries the prize, but eloquence; and no man needs ever despair of gaining proselytes to the most extravagant hypothesis, who has art enough to represent it in any favourable colours. The victory is not gained by the men at arms, who manage the pike and the sword; but by the trumpeters, drummers, and musicians of the army.
You don’t need deep knowledge to see that the sciences are currently in an imperfect state; even the average person outside can tell from the noise and commotion that things aren’t going well. Everything is up for debate, and experts often have opposing views. Even the most trivial questions spark controversy, and we struggle to come to a clear conclusion on the most important issues. Disputes multiply, as if nothing is certain, yet these arguments are heated, as if everything is definite. In all this chaos, it’s not reason that wins out, but eloquence; anyone can attract followers to the wildest ideas if they’re skilled enough to present them positively. Victory doesn’t go to the soldiers wielding pikes and swords, but to the trumpeters, drummers, and musicians of the army.
From hence in my opinion arises that common prejudice against metaphysical reasonings of all kinds, even amongst those, who profess themselves scholars, and have a just value for every other part of literature. By metaphysical reasonings, they do not understand those on any particular branch of science, but every kind of argument, which is any way abstruse, and requires some attention to be comprehended. We have so often lost our labour in such researches, that we commonly reject them without hesitation, and resolve, if we must for ever be a prey to errors and delusions, that they shall at least be natural and entertaining. And indeed nothing but the most determined scepticism, along with a great degree of indolence, can justify this aversion to metaphysics. For if truth be at all within the reach of human capacity, it is certain it must lie very deep and abstruse: and to hope we shall arrive at it without pains, while the greatest geniuses have failed with the utmost pains, must certainly be esteemed sufficiently vain and presumptuous. I pretend to no such advantage in the philosophy I am going to unfold, and would esteem it a strong presumption against it, were it so very easy and obvious.
In my opinion, this is where the common bias against metaphysical reasoning comes from, even among people who consider themselves scholars and appreciate every other area of literature. When they talk about metaphysical reasoning, they don’t mean discussions on specific branches of science but any arguments that are somewhat obscure and require effort to understand. We’ve often found our efforts in these areas fruitless, so we usually dismiss them without second thought and decide that if we must be misled and confused, at least it should be entertaining and relatable. In fact, only a strong sense of skepticism, combined with a fair amount of laziness, can justify this dislike for metaphysics. If truth is indeed accessible to human understanding, it surely exists at a deep and complex level: thinking we can reach it effortlessly, while the greatest minds have struggled with great effort, is clearly arrogant and unrealistic. I don’t claim any special advantage in the philosophy I’m about to present and would consider it a significant flaw if it were so simple and straightforward.
It is evident, that all the sciences have a relation, greater or less, to human nature: and that however wide any of them may seem to run from it, they still return back by one passage or another. Even. Mathematics, Natural Philosophy, and Natural Religion, are in some measure dependent on the science of MAN; since they lie under the cognizance of men, and are judged of by their powers and faculties. It is impossible to tell what changes and improvements we might make in these sciences were we thoroughly acquainted with the extent and force of human understanding, and could explain the nature of the ideas we employ, and of the operations we perform in our reasonings. And these improvements are the more to be hoped for in natural religion, as it is not content with instructing us in the nature of superior powers, but carries its views farther, to their disposition towards us, and our duties towards them; and consequently we ourselves are not only the beings, that reason, but also one of the objects, concerning which we reason.
It's clear that all sciences have some connection, big or small, to human nature. No matter how far they seem to stray from it, they eventually circle back in some way. Even mathematics, natural philosophy, and natural religion are somewhat reliant on the study of humans since they fall within human understanding and are evaluated based on our abilities and faculties. We can't know what changes and improvements we could make in these fields if we fully understood the limits and capabilities of human knowledge, or if we could clarify the nature of the ideas we use and the processes we follow in our reasoning. These advancements are especially promising in natural religion, as it not only teaches us about higher powers but also looks further into their attitudes toward us and our responsibilities to them; thus, we are not just beings that reason, but also one of the subjects we reason about.
If therefore the sciences of Mathematics, Natural Philosophy, and Natural Religion, have such a dependence on the knowledge of man, what may be expected in the other sciences, whose connexion with human nature is more close and intimate? The sole end of logic is to explain the principles and operations of our reasoning faculty, and the nature of our ideas: morals and criticism regard our tastes and sentiments: and politics consider men as united in society, and dependent on each other. In these four sciences of Logic, Morals, Criticism, and Politics, is comprehended almost everything, which it can any way import us to be acquainted with, or which can tend either to the improvement or ornament of the human mind.
If the fields of Mathematics, Natural Philosophy, and Natural Religion rely heavily on human knowledge, what can we expect from other fields that are even more closely connected to human nature? The main purpose of logic is to clarify how our reasoning works and the nature of our ideas; ethics and criticism deal with our tastes and feelings; and politics looks at people as members of society who depend on one another. Together, these four fields—Logic, Ethics, Criticism, and Politics—cover almost everything we need to understand or that can enhance or enrich the human mind.
Here then is the only expedient, from which we can hope for success in our philosophical researches, to leave the tedious lingering method, which we have hitherto followed, and instead of taking now and then a castle or village on the frontier, to march up directly to the capital or center of these sciences, to human nature itself; which being once masters of, we may every where else hope for an easy victory. From this station we may extend our conquests over all those sciences, which more intimately concern human life, and may afterwards proceed at leisure to discover more fully those, which are the objects of pore curiosity. There is no question of importance, whose decision is not comprised in the science of man; and there is none, which can be decided with any certainty, before we become acquainted with that science. In pretending, therefore, to explain the principles of human nature, we in effect propose a compleat system of the sciences, built on a foundation almost entirely new, and the only one upon which they can stand with any security.
Here is the only solution we can count on for success in our philosophical research: we need to move away from the slow and tedious method we’ve been using and instead of occasionally exploring a small part of the frontier, we should directly tackle the core of these sciences—human nature itself. Once we master that, we can expect easy victories in every other area. From this position, we can expand our understanding of all the sciences that are closely related to human life and later take our time to delve deeper into those that pique our curiosity. There’s no important question that isn’t related to the science of man, and there’s no question we can answer with any certainty until we understand that science. So, by aiming to explain the principles of human nature, we’re effectively proposing a complete system of sciences based on a new foundation—the only one that can provide solid support.
And as the science of man is the-only solid foundation for the other sciences, so the only solid foundation we can give to this science itself must be laid on experience and observation. It is no astonishing reflection to consider, that the application of experimental philosophy to moral subjects should come after that to natural at the distance of above a whole century; since we find in fact, that there was about the same interval betwixt the origins of these sciences; and that reckoning from THALES to SOCRATES, the space of time is nearly equal to that betwixt, my Lord Bacon and some late philosophers in England,[1] who have begun to put the science of man on a new footing, and have engaged the attention, and excited the curiosity of the public. So true it is, that however other nations may rival us in poetry, and excel us in some other agreeable arts, the improvements in reason and philosophy can only be owing to a land of toleration and of liberty.
And just as the science of humanity is the only solid foundation for the other sciences, the only solid foundation we can provide for this science itself must be based on experience and observation. It's not surprising to think that the application of experimental philosophy to moral topics came more than a century after its application to natural subjects; we actually see that there was about the same gap between the beginnings of these sciences. If we count from THALES to SOCRATES, the time span is nearly equal to that between my Lord Bacon and some recent philosophers in England, [1] who have started to establish the science of humanity in a new way and have captured the attention and stirred the curiosity of the public. It's true that while other nations may compete with us in poetry and excel in various pleasing arts, advancements in reason and philosophy can only be attributed to a land of tolerance and freedom.
[1] Mr. Locke, my Lord Shaftesbury, Dr. Mandeville, Mr. Hutchinson, Dr. Butler, etc.
[1] Mr. Locke, Lord Shaftesbury, Dr. Mandeville, Mr. Hutchinson, Dr. Butler, etc.
Nor ought we to think, that this latter improvement in the science of man will do less honour to our native country than the former in natural philosophy, but ought rather to esteem it a greater glory, upon account of the greater importance of that science, as well as the necessity it lay under of such a reformation. For to me it seems evident, that the essence of the mind being equally unknown to us with that of external bodies, it must be equally impossible to form any notion of its powers and qualities otherwise than from careful and exact experiments, and the observation of those particular effects, which result from its different circumstances and situations. And though we must endeavour to render all our principles as universal as possible, by tracing up our experiments to the utmost, and explaining all effects from the simplest and fewest causes, it is still certain we cannot go beyond experience; and any hypothesis, that pretends to discover the ultimate original qualities of human nature, ought at first to be rejected as presumptuous and chimerical.
We shouldn't think that this recent advancement in understanding human nature will bring less honor to our country than the previous achievements in natural philosophy. In fact, we should consider it an even greater accomplishment because of the greater significance of this field and the urgent need for such a transformation. It seems clear to me that just as we don't fully understand the essence of the mind, we also don't grasp the essence of external objects. Therefore, it's equally impossible to form any ideas about its abilities and characteristics without careful and precise experiments, as well as observing the specific effects that arise from different conditions and situations. Although we should try to make all our principles as universal as possible by tracing our experiments to their origins and explaining all effects with the simplest and fewest causes, it remains true that we can't go beyond experience. Any theory that claims to reveal the fundamental qualities of human nature should initially be dismissed as arrogant and unrealistic.
I do not think a philosopher, who would apply himself so earnestly to the explaining the ultimate principles of the soul, would show himself a great master in that very science of human nature, which he pretends to explain, or very knowing in what is naturally satisfactory to the mind of man. For nothing is more certain, than that despair has almost the same effect upon us with enjoyment, and that we are no sooner acquainted with the impossibility of satisfying any desire, than the desire itself vanishes. When we see, that we have arrived at the utmost extent of human reason, we sit down contented, though we be perfectly satisfied in the main of our ignorance, and perceive that we can give no reason for our most general and most refined principles, beside our experience of their reality; which is the reason of the mere vulgar, and what it required no study at first to have discovered for the most particular and most extraordinary phænomenon. And as this impossibility of making any farther progress is enough to satisfy the reader, so the writer may derive a more delicate satisfaction from the free confession of his ignorance, and from his prudence in avoiding that error, into which so many have fallen, of imposing their conjectures and hypotheses on the world for the most certain principles. When this mutual contentment and satisfaction can be obtained betwixt the master and scholar, I know not what more we can require of our philosophy.
I don't think a philosopher who dedicates himself seriously to explaining the ultimate principles of the soul can truly claim to master the very field of human nature that he attempts to clarify or to understand what genuinely satisfies the human mind. It's clear that despair affects us almost as much as joy, and as soon as we realize that satisfying any desire is impossible, the desire itself tends to disappear. When we understand that we've reached the limits of human reason, we find contentment, even if we're fully aware of our ignorance, and recognize that we can't justify our most basic and refined principles beyond our direct experience of their reality. This is the same reasoning as the average person, which doesn’t require extensive study to uncover, especially in the case of unique and extraordinary phenomena. The fact that we can't make any further progress is enough to satisfy the reader, while the writer can take a deeper satisfaction in openly admitting his ignorance and being wise enough to avoid the mistake that so many have made—passing off their guesses and theories as certain principles. When this mutual satisfaction can be achieved between teacher and student, I can't think of anything more we could ask from our philosophy.
But if this impossibility of explaining ultimate principles should be esteemed a defect in the science of man, I will venture to affirm, that it is a defect common to it with all the sciences, and all the arts, in which we can employ ourselves, whether they be such as are cultivated in the schools of the philosophers, or practised in the shops of the meanest artizans. None of them can go beyond experience, or establish any principles which are not founded on that authority. Moral philosophy has, indeed, this peculiar disadvantage, which is not found in natural, that in collecting its experiments, it cannot make them purposely, with premeditation, and after such a manner as to satisfy itself concerning every particular difficulty which may be. When I am at a loss to know the effects of one body upon another in any situation, I need only put them in that situation, and observe what results from it. But should I endeavour to clear up after the same manner any doubt in moral philosophy, by placing myself in the same case with that which I consider, it is evident this reflection and premeditation would so disturb the operation of my natural principles, as must render it impossible to form any just conclusion from the phenomenon. We must therefore glean up our experiments in this science from a cautious observation of human life, and take them as they appear in the common course of the world, by men's behaviour in company, in affairs, and in their pleasures. Where experiments of this kind are judiciously collected and compared, we may hope to establish on them a science which will not be inferior in certainty, and will be much superior in utility to any other of human comprehension.
But if the inability to explain ultimate principles is seen as a flaw in the science of humanity, I’ll boldly say that it’s a flaw shared with all sciences and arts we engage in, whether they’re studied in philosophy classrooms or practiced in the workshops of the most basic craftsmen. None of them can go beyond experience or establish any principles that aren’t based on that authority. Moral philosophy has a unique disadvantage that isn’t found in natural sciences; when collecting its experiments, it cannot do so deliberately, with premeditation, or in a way that addresses every specific challenge it might face. When I’m unsure about how one body affects another in any given situation, I just need to put them in that situation and see the results. However, if I try to resolve a moral philosophy question in the same way by putting myself in the same scenario I’m considering, it’s clear that this reflection and premeditation would disrupt my natural instincts so much that it would make it impossible to draw any accurate conclusions from the phenomenon. Therefore, we have to gather our experiments in this field from careful observations of human life, taking them as they present themselves in everyday interactions, in business, and in leisure. When such experiments are wisely collected and compared, we can hope to create a science that is no less certain and much more useful than any other human endeavor.
SECT. I. OF THE ORIGIN OF OUR IDEAS.
All the perceptions of the human mind resolve themselves into two distinct kinds, which I shall call IMPRESSIONS and IDEAS. The difference betwixt these consists in the degrees of force and liveliness, with which they strike upon the mind, and make their way into our thought or consciousness. Those perceptions, which enter with most force and violence, we may name impressions: and under this name I comprehend all our sensations, passions and emotions, as they make their first appearance in the soul. By ideas I mean the faint images of these in thinking and reasoning; such as, for instance, are all the perceptions excited by the present discourse, excepting only those which arise from the sight and touch, and excepting the immediate pleasure or uneasiness it may occasion. I believe it will not be very necessary to employ many words in explaining this distinction. Every one of himself will readily perceive the difference betwixt feeling and thinking. The common degrees of these are easily distinguished; though it is not impossible but in particular instances they may very nearly approach to each other. Thus in sleep, in a fever, in madness, or in any very violent emotions of soul, our ideas may approach to our impressions, As on the other hand it sometimes happens, that our impressions are so faint and low, that we cannot distinguish them from our ideas. But notwithstanding this near resemblance in a few instances, they are in general so very different, that no-one can make a scruple to rank them under distinct heads, and assign to each a peculiar name to mark the difference.[1]
All the perceptions of the human mind can be divided into two distinct types, which I’ll call IMPRESSIONS and IDEAS. The difference between them lies in the levels of intensity and clarity with which they impact our mind and enter our thoughts or consciousness. The perceptions that strike us with the most intensity we can call impressions; this category includes all our sensations, passions, and emotions as they first appear in the mind. By ideas, I mean the faint images of these during thinking and reasoning, such as all the perceptions triggered by the current discussion, except for those that come from sight and touch, and excluding any immediate pleasure or discomfort it may cause. I don't think it’s necessary to use many words to explain this distinction. Everyone can easily recognize the difference between feeling and thinking. The common levels of these are easy to tell apart, although in some cases they can become quite similar. For example, during sleep, fever, madness, or intense emotions, our ideas can come close to our impressions. On the flip side, there are times when our impressions are so weak and subtle that we can't tell them apart from our ideas. However, despite this close resemblance in some cases, they are generally so different that no one should hesitate to categorize them separately and give each a specific name to highlight the difference.
[1] I here make use of these terms, impression and idea, in a sense different from what is usual, and I hope this liberty will be allowed me. Perhaps I rather restore the word, idea, to its original sense, from which Mr Locke had perverted it, in making it stand for all our perceptions. By the terms of impression I would not be understood to express the manner, in which our lively perceptions are produced in the soul, but merely the perceptions themselves; for which there is no particular name either in the English or any other language, that I know of.
[1] I'm using the terms impression and idea in a way that's different from the usual meaning, and I hope that's acceptable. I might actually be returning the word "idea" to its original meaning, which Mr. Locke changed when he used it to refer to all our perceptions. By "impression," I don’t mean to describe how our vivid perceptions are created in the mind, but just the perceptions themselves; there’s no specific term for that in English or any other language that I know of.
There is another division of our perceptions, which it will be convenient to observe, and which extends itself both to our impressions and ideas. This division is into SIMPLE and COMPLEX. Simple perceptions or impressions and ideas are such as admit of no distinction nor separation. The complex are the contrary to these, and may be distinguished into parts. Though a particular colour, taste, and smell, are qualities all united together in this apple, it is easy to perceive they are not the same, but are at least distinguishable from each other.
There’s another way to categorize our perceptions that’s useful to note, and it applies to both our impressions and ideas. This categorization is into SIMPLE and COMPLEX. Simple perceptions or impressions and ideas can't be broken down or separated. Complex perceptions, on the other hand, can be divided into parts. While a specific color, taste, and smell are all combined in this apple, it's clear that they are different and can be distinguished from one another.
Having by these divisions given an order and arrangement to our objects, we may now apply ourselves to consider with the more accuracy their qualities and relations. The first circumstance, that strikes my eye, is the great resemblance betwixt our impressions and ideas in every other particular, except their degree of force and vivacity. The one seem to be in a manner the reflexion of the other; so that all the perceptions of the mind are double, and appear both as impressions and ideas. When I shut my eyes and think of my chamber, the ideas I form are exact representations of the impressions I felt; nor is there any circumstance of the one, which is not to be found in the other. In running over my other perceptions, I find still the same resemblance and representation. Ideas and impressions appear always to correspond to each other. This circumstance seems to me remarkable, and engages my attention for a moment.
Having organized our subjects into these divisions, we can now focus on examining their qualities and relationships more closely. The first thing that catches my attention is the strong similarity between our impressions and ideas in every way, except for their intensity and vividness. One seems to be a reflection of the other; all the perceptions of the mind are basically dual, appearing as both impressions and ideas. When I close my eyes and think about my room, the ideas I create are accurate representations of the impressions I experienced, and there’s no aspect of one that isn’t also found in the other. As I review my other perceptions, I still find the same similarity and representation. Ideas and impressions always seem to correspond with one another. This fact strikes me as noteworthy and holds my attention for a moment.
Upon a more accurate survey I find I have been carried away too far by the first appearance, and that I must make use of the distinction of perceptions into simple and complex, to limit this general decision, that all our ideas and impressions are resembling. I observe, that many of our complex ideas never had impressions, that corresponded to them, and that many of our complex impressions never are exactly copied in ideas. I can imagine to myself such a city as the New Jerusalem, whose pavement is gold and walls are rubies, though I never saw any such. I have seen Paris; but shall I affirm I can form such an idea of that city, as will perfectly represent all its streets and houses in their real and just proportions?
After a closer look, I've realized that I've been misled by initial appearances, and I need to recognize the difference between simple and complex perceptions to refine my overall conclusion that all our ideas and impressions are similar. I've noticed that many of our complex ideas don't actually correspond to any real impressions, and many of our complex impressions aren't perfectly captured in our ideas. I can envision a city like the New Jerusalem, with streets made of gold and walls of rubies, even though I've never seen anything like it. I've been to Paris, but can I really say that I have a clear picture of the city that accurately reflects all its streets and buildings in their true proportions?
I perceive, therefore, that though there is in general a great, resemblance betwixt our complex impressions and ideas, yet the rule is not universally true, that they are exact copies of each other. We may next consider how the case stands with our simple, perceptions. After the most accurate examination, of which I am capable, I venture to affirm, that the rule here holds without any exception, and that every simple idea has a simple impression, which resembles it, and every simple impression a correspondent idea. That idea of red, which we form in the dark, and that impression which strikes our eyes in sun-shine, differ only in degree, not in nature. That the case is the same with all our simple impressions and ideas, it is impossible to prove by a particular enumeration of them. Every one may satisfy himself in this point by running over as many as he pleases. But if any one should deny this universal resemblance, I know no way of convincing him, but by desiring him to shew a simple impression, that has not a correspondent idea, or a simple idea, that has not a correspondent impression. If he does not answer this challenge, as it is certain he cannot, we may from his silence and our own observation establish our conclusion.
I see, therefore, that while there is generally a strong similarity between our complex impressions and ideas, it’s not always true that they are exact copies of one another. Next, let’s examine how things stand with our simple perceptions. After the closest examination I can manage, I feel confident in saying that the rule holds true without exception, and that every simple idea has a simple impression that resembles it, and every simple impression has a corresponding idea. The idea of red that we form in the dark and the impression that hits our eyes in sunlight differ only in degree, not in nature. It’s impossible to prove that this is the case for all our simple impressions and ideas by listing them out one by one. Anyone can confirm this by going through as many examples as they like. However, if someone were to deny this universal resemblance, I wouldn’t know how to convince them other than to ask them to show a simple impression that lacks a corresponding idea or a simple idea that lacks a corresponding impression. If they can’t answer this challenge—which they certainly can’t—we can establish our conclusion from their silence and our own observations.
Thus we find, that all simple ideas and impressions resemble each other; and as the complex are formed from them, we may affirm in general, that these two species of perception are exactly correspondent. Having discovered this relation, which requires no farther examination, I am curious to find some other of their qualities. Let us consider how they stand with regard to their existence, and which of the impressions and ideas are causes, and which effects.
So, we see that all basic ideas and impressions are similar to each other; and since complex ideas are formed from them, we can generally say that these two types of perception correspond exactly. Having identified this relationship, which doesn't need any further investigation, I'm interested in exploring some other qualities they have. Let’s look at how they relate to their existence and determine which impressions and ideas are causes and which are effects.
The full examination of this question is the subject of the present treatise; and therefore we shall here content ourselves with establishing one general proposition, THAT ALL OUR SIMPLE IDEAS IN THEIR FIRST APPEARANCE ARE DERIVED FROM SIMPLE IMPRESSIONS, WHICH ARE CORRESPONDENT TO THEM, AND WHICH THEY EXACTLY REPRESENT.
The complete exploration of this question is the focus of this paper; therefore, we will simply establish one main point: THAT ALL OUR SIMPLE IDEAS, IN THEIR INITIAL FORM, COME FROM SIMPLE IMPRESSIONS THAT CORRESPOND TO THEM AND THAT THEY ACCURATELY REFLECT.
In seeking for phenomena to prove this proposition, I find only those of two kinds; but in each kind the phenomena are obvious, numerous, and conclusive. I first make myself certain, by a new, review, of what I have already asserted, that every simple impression is attended with a correspondent idea, and every simple idea with a correspondent impression. From this constant conjunction of resembling perceptions I immediately conclude, that there is a great connexion betwixt our correspondent impressions and ideas, and that the existence of the one has a considerable influence upon that of the other. Such a constant conjunction, in such an infinite number of instances, can never arise from chance; but clearly proves a dependence of the impressions on the ideas, or of the ideas on the impressions. That I may know on which side this dependence lies, I consider the order of their first appearance; and find by constant experience, that the simple impressions always take the precedence of their correspondent ideas, but never appear in the contrary order. To give a child an idea of scarlet or orange, of sweet or bitter, I present the objects, or in other words, convey to him these impressions; but proceed not so absurdly, as to endeavour to produce the impressions by exciting the ideas. Our ideas upon their appearance produce not their correspondent impressions, nor do we perceive any colour, or feel any sensation merely upon thinking of them. On the other hand we find, that any impression either of the mind or body is constantly followed by an idea, which resembles it, and is only different in the degrees of force and liveliness. The constant conjunction of our resembling perceptions, is a convincing proof, that the one are the causes of the other; and this priority of the impressions is an equal proof, that our impressions are the causes of our ideas, not our ideas of our impressions.
In looking for evidence to support this idea, I find two main types of phenomena; in each category, the evidence is clear, abundant, and convincing. First, I confirm through a new review of what I’ve already claimed that every simple impression comes with a corresponding idea, and every simple idea comes with a corresponding impression. From this consistent connection of similar perceptions, I immediately conclude that there is a strong link between our corresponding impressions and ideas, and that the presence of one significantly affects the other. Such a consistent relationship, witnessed in countless instances, cannot be random; it clearly shows a dependency of impressions on ideas, or ideas on impressions. To determine which side this dependency leans toward, I look at the order in which they first appear and find, through consistent experience, that simple impressions always come before their corresponding ideas and never in the opposite order. To teach a child the concept of scarlet or orange, sweet or bitter, I present the objects, or in other words, provide these impressions; I certainly do not make the foolish attempt to create impressions by stimulating the ideas. Our ideas, when they appear, do not produce their corresponding impressions, nor do we see any color or feel any sensation simply by thinking about them. On the other hand, we observe that any impression, whether of the mind or body, is always followed by a similar idea, differing only in terms of intensity and vividness. The consistent connection of our similar perceptions is clear evidence that one causes the other; and this precedence of impressions further proves that our impressions cause our ideas, not the other way around.
To confirm this I consider Another plain and convincing phænomenon; which is, that, where-ever by any accident the faculties, which give rise to any impressions, are obstructed in their operations, as when one is born blind or deaf; not only the impressions are lost, but also their correspondent ideas; so that there never appear in the mind the least traces of either of them. Nor is this only true, where the organs of sensation are entirely destroyed, but likewise where they have never been put in action to produce a particular impression. We cannot form to ourselves a just idea of the taste of a pine apple, without having actually tasted it.
To confirm this, I think about another clear and convincing phenomenon: whenever the senses that create impressions are blocked, like when someone is born blind or deaf, not only are those impressions lost, but also the ideas that go with them. As a result, there are never any traces of either in the mind. This is true not only when the sensory organs are completely gone but also when they have never been used to create a particular impression. We can't really understand what a pineapple tastes like without having actually tasted it.
There is however one contradictory phænomenon, which may prove, that it is not absolutely impossible for ideas to go before their correspondent impressions. I believe it will readily be allowed that the several distinct ideas of colours, which enter by the eyes, or those of sounds, which are conveyed by the hearing, are really different from each other, though at the same time resembling. Now if this be true of different colours, it must be no less so of the different shades of the same colour, that each of them produces a distinct idea, independent of the rest. For if this should be denied, it is possible, by the continual gradation of shades, to run a colour insensibly into what is most remote from it; and if you will not allow any of the means to be different, you cannot without absurdity deny the extremes to be the same. Suppose therefore a person to have enjoyed his sight for thirty years, and to have become perfectly well acquainted with colours of all kinds, excepting one particular shade of blue, for instance, which it never has been his fortune to meet with. Let all the different shades of that colour, except that single one, be placed before him, descending gradually from the deepest to the lightest; it is plain, that he will perceive a blank, where that shade is wanting, said will be sensible, that there is a greater distance in that place betwixt the contiguous colours, than in any other. Now I ask, whether it is possible for him, from his own imagination, to supply this deficiency, and raise up to himself the idea of that particular shade, though it had never been conveyed to him by his senses? I believe there are few but will be of opinion that he can; and this may serve as a proof, that the simple ideas are not always derived from the correspondent impressions; though the instance is so particular and singular, that it is scarce worth our observing, and does not merit that for it alone we should alter our general maxim.
There is, however, one contradictory phenomenon that may show it’s not entirely impossible for ideas to come before their corresponding impressions. I think it’s generally accepted that the various distinct ideas of colors that enter through the eyes, or those of sounds that we hear, are truly different from one another, even though they have some similarities. Now, if this is true for different colors, it must also be true for the different shades of the same color, as each produces a distinct idea, independent of the others. If this were denied, it would be possible to blend colors gradually into something completely different, and if you won’t accept that any of the means are different, you cannot logically deny that the extremes are the same. Let’s suppose a person has enjoyed their sight for thirty years and is perfectly familiar with all kinds of colors except for one specific shade of blue, which they have never encountered. If all the different shades of that color, except for that single one, are placed before them, ranging from the deepest to the lightest, it’s clear that they will notice a gap where that shade is missing and will sense that there’s a greater distance between the adjacent colors at that spot than anywhere else. Now I ask, is it possible for them to imagine and create the idea of that specific shade even though it has never been conveyed to them through their senses? I believe few would disagree that they can; and this may serve as proof that simple ideas are not always derived from corresponding impressions, though this example is so particular and unique that it is hardly worth noting, and it doesn’t merit altering our general principle just for this case.
But besides this exception, it may not be amiss to remark on this head, that the principle of the priority of impressions to ideas must be understood with another limitation, viz., that as our ideas are images of our impressions, so we can form secondary ideas, which are images of the primary; as appears from this very reasoning concerning them. This is not, properly speaking, an exception to the rule so much as an explanation of it. Ideas produce the images of themselves in new ideas; but as the first ideas are supposed to be derived from impressions, it still remains true, that all our simple ideas proceed either mediately or immediately, from their correspondent impressions.
But aside from this exception, it’s worth noting that the principle of the priority of impressions over ideas must be understood with another limitation: just as our ideas are images of our impressions, we can create secondary ideas, which are images of the primary ones, as this reasoning shows. This isn't really an exception to the rule but more of an explanation of it. Ideas create images of themselves in new ideas; however, since the initial ideas are thought to come from impressions, it remains true that all our simple ideas come, either directly or indirectly, from their corresponding impressions.
This then is the first principle I establish in the science of human nature; nor ought we to despise it because of the simplicity of its appearance. For it is remarkable, that the present question concerning the precedency of our impressions or ideas, is the same with what has made so much noise in other terms, when it has been disputed whether there be any INNATE IDEAS, or whether all ideas be derived from sensation and reflexion. We may observe, that in order to prove the ideas of extension and colour not to be innate, philosophers do nothing but shew that they are conveyed by our senses. To prove the ideas of passion and desire not to be innate, they observe that we have a preceding experience of these emotions in ourselves. Now if we carefully examine these arguments, we shall find that they prove nothing but that ideas are preceded by other more lively perceptions, from which the are derived, and which they represent. I hope this clear stating of the question will remove all disputes concerning it, and win render this principle of more use in our reasonings, than it seems hitherto to have been.
This is the first principle I establish in the study of human nature, and we shouldn’t underestimate it because of its simple appearance. It's interesting that the current debate about whether our impressions or ideas come first is similar to the longstanding argument over whether there are any INNATE IDEAS or if all ideas come from sensation and reflection. We can see that to argue against the ideas of extension and color being innate, philosophers simply show that they come from our senses. To argue against the ideas of passion and desire being innate, they point out that we have prior experiences of these emotions within ourselves. If we closely examine these arguments, we’ll find they only demonstrate that ideas are preceded by other, stronger perceptions from which they come and which they represent. I hope this clear explanation of the issue will settle any disputes about it and make this principle more useful in our reasoning than it has been so far.
SECT. II. DIVISION OF THE SUBJECT.
Since it appears, that our simple impressions are prior to their correspondent ideas, and that the exceptions are very rare, method seems to require we should examine our impressions, before we consider our ideas. Impressions may be divided into two kinds, those Of SENSATION and those of REFLEXION. The first kind arises in the soul originally, from unknown causes. The second is derived in a great measure from our ideas, and that in the following order. An impression first strikes upon the senses, and makes us perceive heat or cold, thirst or hunger, pleasure or pain of some kind or other. Of this impression there is a copy taken by the mind, which remains after the impression ceases; and this we call an idea. This idea of pleasure or pain, when it returns upon the soul, produces the new impressions of desire and aversion, hope and fear, which may properly be called impressions of reflexion, because derived from it. These again are copied by the memory and imagination, and become ideas; which perhaps in their turn give rise to other impressions and ideas. So that the impressions of reflexion are only antecedent to their correspondent ideas; but posterior to those of sensation, and derived from them. The examination of our sensations belongs more to anatomists and natural philosophers than to moral; and therefore shall not at present be entered upon. And as the impressions of reflexion, viz. passions, desires, and emotions, which principally deserve our attention, arise mostly from ideas, it will be necessary to reverse that method, which at first sight seems most natural; and in order to explain the nature and principles of the human mind, give a particular account of ideas, before we proceed to impressions. For this reason I have here chosen to begin with ideas.
Since it seems that our simple impressions come before their related ideas, and that exceptions are quite rare, it makes sense that we should examine our impressions before we think about our ideas. Impressions can be divided into two types: those of SENSATION and those of REFLEXION. The first type originates in the mind from unknown causes. The second type mostly comes from our ideas, and follows this order. An impression first affects the senses, making us feel heat or cold, thirst or hunger, some type of pleasure, or pain. The mind then takes a copy of this impression, which remains even after the impression fades; we call this an idea. When this idea of pleasure or pain comes back to the mind, it produces new impressions of desire and aversion, hope and fear, which we can call impressions of reflexion because they derive from the first type. These are then remembered and imagined, becoming ideas again, which may in turn lead to more impressions and ideas. So, impressions of reflexion come before their related ideas but after those of sensation, and depend on them. Examining our sensations is more suited for anatomists and natural philosophers than for moral philosophers, so we won’t focus on that right now. Since the impressions of reflexion—like passions, desires, and emotions—that truly deserve our attention mostly arise from ideas, we need to reverse the method that initially seems more natural. To explain the nature and principles of the human mind, we should provide a detailed account of ideas before moving on to impressions. For this reason, I have chosen to start with ideas.
SECT. III. OF THE IDEAS OF THE MEMORY AND IMAGINATION.
We find by experience, that when any impression has been present with the mind, it again makes its appearance there as an idea; and this it may do after two different ways: either when in its new appearance it retains a considerable degree of its first vivacity, and is somewhat intermediate betwixt an impression and an idea: or when it entirely loses that vivacity, and is a perfect idea. The faculty, by which we repeat our impressions in the first manner, is called the MEMORY, and the other the IMAGINATION. It is evident at first sight, that the ideas of the memory are much more lively and strong than those of the imagination, and that the former faculty paints its objects in more distinct colours, than any which are employed by the latter. When we remember any past event, the idea of it flows in upon the mind in a forcible manner; whereas in the imagination the perception is faint and languid, and cannot without difficulty be preserved by the mind steddy and uniform for any considerable time. Here then is a sensible difference betwixt one species of ideas and another. But of this more fully hereafter.[2]
We learn from experience that when a thought has been in our mind, it can return as an idea. This can happen in two ways: either when it reappears with a strong sense of its original intensity, being somewhat of a mix between an impression and an idea, or when it completely loses that intensity and becomes just a plain idea. The ability to recall impressions in the first way is called MEMORY, while the other is referred to as IMAGINATION. It's clear at first glance that the ideas from memory are much more vivid and powerful than those from imagination, and that memory paints its images in more vivid colors compared to imagination. When we recall a past event, that idea comes to mind forcefully; on the other hand, with imagination, the perception is weak and faint, making it hard to keep it steady and consistent in our mind for a significant amount of time. Here’s a noticeable difference between these types of ideas. But we’ll discuss this in more detail later. [2]
[2] Part III, Sect. 5.
There is another difference betwixt these two kinds of ideas, which is no less evident, namely that though neither the ideas, of the memory nor imagination, neither the lively nor faint ideas can make their appearance in the mind, unless their correspondent impressions have gone before to prepare the way for them, yet the imagination is not restrained to the same order and form with the original impressions; while the memory is in a manner tied down in that respect, without any power of variation.
There’s another clear difference between these two types of ideas: although neither the ideas of memory nor imagination—neither the vivid nor faint ideas—can arise in the mind without previous corresponding impressions to prepare for them, the imagination isn’t restricted to the same order and form as the original impressions. In contrast, memory is somewhat bound by that requirement and lacks any power of variation.
It is evident, that the memory preserves the original form, in which its objects were presented, and that where-ever we depart from it in recollecting any thing, it proceeds from some defect or imperfection in that faculty. An historian may, perhaps, for the more convenient Carrying on of his narration, relate an event before another, to which it was in fact posterior; but then he takes notice of this disorder, if he be exact; and by that means replaces the idea in its due position. It is the same case in our recollection of those places and persons, with which we were formerly acquainted. The chief exercise of the memory is not to preserve the simple ideas, but their order and position. In short, this principle is supported by such a number of common and vulgar phaenomena, that we may spare ourselves the trouble of insisting on it any farther.
It’s clear that memory keeps the original form of the things we experienced, and that whenever we deviate from it while recalling something, it's due to a flaw or limitation in that ability. A historian might, for the sake of telling a story more conveniently, mention an event before another that actually happened later; however, if he’s accurate, he acknowledges this misplacement and then corrects the order in his narrative. The same applies to how we remember places and people we once knew. The main function of memory isn’t just to hold onto simple ideas but to maintain their sequence and position. In short, this principle is backed by so many common and ordinary observations that we don’t need to discuss it any further.
The same evidence follows us in our second principle, OF THE LIBERTY OF THE IMAGINATION TO TRANSPOSE AND CHANGE ITS IDEAS. The fables we meet with in poems and romances put this entirely out of the question. Nature there is totally confounded, and nothing mentioned but winged horses, fiery dragons, and monstrous giants. Nor will this liberty of the fancy appear strange, when we consider, that all our ideas are copyed from our impressions, and that there are not any two impressions which are perfectly inseparable. Not to mention, that this is an evident consequence of the division of ideas into simple and complex. Where-ever the imagination perceives a difference among ideas, it can easily produce a separation.
The same evidence supports our second principle, ABOUT THE FREEDOM OF THE IMAGINATION TO TRANSFORM AND CHANGE ITS IDEAS. The fables we find in poems and stories completely illustrate this. Nature is completely mixed up, and we only see things like winged horses, fire-breathing dragons, and giant monsters. This freedom of imagination won't seem odd when we realize that all our ideas are based on our experiences, and there are no two experiences that are perfectly connected. Not to mention, this is a clear result of how we categorize ideas into simple and complex. Whenever the imagination notices a difference among ideas, it can easily create a separation.
SECT. IV. OF THE CONNEXION OR ASSOCIATION OF IDEAS.
As all simple ideas may be separated by the imagination, and may be united again in what form it pleases, nothing would be more unaccountable than the operations of that faculty, were it not guided by some universal principles, which render it, in some measure, uniform with itself in all times and places. Were ideas entirely loose and unconnected, chance alone would join them; and it is impossible the same simple ideas should fall regularly into complex ones (as they Commonly do) without some bond of union among them, some associating quality, by which one idea naturally introduces another. This uniting principle among ideas is not to be considered as an inseparable connexion; for that has been already excluded from the imagination: Nor yet are we to conclude, that without it the mind cannot join two ideas; for nothing is more free than that faculty: but we are only to regard it as a gentle force, which commonly prevails, and is the cause why, among other things, languages so nearly correspond to each other; nature in a manner pointing out to every one those simple ideas, which are most proper to be united in a complex one. The qualities, from which this association arises, and by which the mind is after this manner conveyed from one idea to another, are three, viz. RESEMBLANCE, CONTIGUITY in time or place, and CAUSE and EFFECT.
As all simple ideas can be separated by our imagination and can be combined again in any way we choose, it would be completely puzzling how that process works if it weren't guided by some universal principles that keep it somewhat consistent across all times and places. If ideas were totally random and disconnected, they would come together purely by chance; and it would be impossible for the same simple ideas to form complex ones (as they often do) without some connection between them—some quality that naturally leads one idea to introduce another. This connecting principle among ideas shouldn't be seen as a strict, unbreakable link; that has already been ruled out by our imagination. Nor should we assume that without it, the mind can't connect two ideas, as that faculty is quite free. Instead, we should see it as a gentle influence that typically takes over, explaining why, among other reasons, languages closely resemble each other. Nature seems to indicate to everyone which simple ideas are most suited to be combined into a complex one. The qualities that lead to this association, which help the mind transition from one idea to another, are three: RESEMBLANCE, CONTIGUITY in time or place, and CAUSE and EFFECT.
I believe it will not be very necessary to prove, that these qualities produce an association among ideas, and upon the appearance of one idea naturally introduce another. It is plain, that in the course of our thinking, and in the constant revolution of our ideas, our imagination runs easily from one idea to any other that resembles it, and that this quality alone is to the fancy a sufficient bond and association. It is likewise evident that as the senses, in changing their objects, are necessitated to change them regularly, and take them as they lie CONTIGUOUS to each other, the imagination must by long custom acquire the same method of thinking, and run along the parts of space and time in conceiving its objects. As to the connexion, that is made by the relation of cause and effect, we shall have occasion afterwards to examine it to the bottom, and therefore shall not at present insist upon it. It is sufficient to observe, that there is no relation, which produces a stronger connexion in the fancy, and makes one idea more readily recall another, than the relation of cause and effect betwixt their objects.
I don’t think it’s necessary to prove that these qualities create a connection between ideas and naturally lead to the introduction of another idea when one appears. It’s clear that as we think and our ideas constantly shift, our imagination easily jumps from one idea to any similar one. This quality alone is enough to serve as a bond and connection for our imagination. It’s also obvious that just as our senses must regularly change their focus and take objects as they are placed next to each other, our imagination, through long practice, must develop the same way of thinking and move along the aspects of space and time when forming its ideas. Regarding the connection made by the relationship of cause and effect, we will deal with that in more detail later, so we won't focus on it right now. It’s important to note, though, that no relationship creates a stronger connection in our imagination or makes one idea recall another more easily than the relationship of cause and effect between their objects.
That we may understand the full extent of these relations, we must consider, that two objects are connected together in the imagination, not only when the one is immediately resembling, contiguous to, or the cause of the other, but also when there is interposed betwixt them a third object, which bears to both of them any of these relations. This may be carried on to a great length; though at the same time we may observe, that each remove considerably weakens the relation. Cousins in the fourth degree are connected by causation, if I may be allowed to use that term; but not so closely as brothers, much less as child and parent. In general we may observe, that all the relations of blood depend upon cause and effect, and are esteemed near or remote, according to the number of connecting causes interposed betwixt the persons.
To fully grasp these relationships, we need to recognize that two things are linked in our minds not only when one directly resembles, is next to, or causes the other, but also when a third object sits between them and shares any of these connections. This can extend quite far; however, we should note that each step away significantly weakens the connection. Cousins who are related in the fourth degree are linked by cause, if I can use that term, but not as closely as siblings, and certainly not as closely as a parent and child. Overall, we can see that all family relationships depend on cause and effect, and they are considered close or distant based on how many connecting causes are present between the individuals.
Of the three relations above-mentioned this of causation is the most extensive. Two objects may be considered as placed in this relation, as well when one is the cause of any of the actions or motions of the other, as when the former is the cause of the existence of the latter. For as that action or motion is nothing but the object itself, considered in a certain light, and as the object continues the same in all its different situations, it is easy to imagine how such an influence of objects upon one another may connect them in the imagination.
Of the three relationships mentioned earlier, causation is the most extensive. Two objects can be seen as connected in this way whether one causes the actions or movements of the other, or whether the first causes the existence of the second. Since action or motion is simply the object itself viewed in a certain light, and because the object remains the same in all its different situations, it’s easy to see how the influence of objects on each other can link them in our minds.
We may carry this farther, and remark, not only that two objects are connected by the relation of cause and effect, when the one produces a motion or any action in the other, but also when it has a power of producing it. And this we may observe to be the source of all the relation, of interest and duty, by which men influence each other in society, and are placed in the ties of government and subordination. A master is such-a-one as by his situation, arising either from force or agreement, has a power of directing in certain particulars the actions of another, whom we call servant. A judge is one, who in all disputed cases can fix by his opinion the possession or property of any thing betwixt any members of the society. When a person is possessed of any power, there is no more required to convert it into action, but the exertion of the will; and that in every case is considered as possible, and in many as probable; especially in the case of authority, where the obedience of the subject is a pleasure and advantage to the superior.
We can take this further and point out that two things are connected by cause and effect not just when one causes a motion or action in the other, but also when it has the power to do so. This is the foundation of all the relationships of interest and duty through which people influence one another in society and are bound by government and hierarchy. A master is someone who, by virtue of their position—whether through force or agreement—has the power to direct the actions of another person, whom we call a servant. A judge is someone who can determine ownership or property in any disputes between members of society. When someone has power, all that’s needed to turn that power into action is the exercise of their will; and this is generally seen as possible, and in many cases likely, especially when it comes to authority, where the compliance of the subject brings pleasure and benefits to the superior.
These are therefore the principles of union or cohesion among our simple ideas, and in the imagination supply the place of that inseparable connexion, by which they are united in our memory. Here is a kind of ATTRACTION, which in the mental world will be found to have as extraordinary effects as in the natural, and to shew itself in as many and as various forms. Its effects are every where conspicuous; but as to its causes, they are mostly unknown, and must be resolved into original qualities of human nature, which I pretend not to explain. Nothing is more requisite for a true philosopher, than to restrain the intemperate desire of searching into causes, and having established any doctrine upon a sufficient number of experiments, rest contented with that, when he sees a farther examination would lead him into obscure and uncertain speculations. In that case his enquiry would be much better employed in examining the effects than the causes of his principle.
These are the principles of connection or cohesion among our simple ideas, which in our imagination take the place of the inseparable links that unite them in our memory. This represents a kind of ATTRACTION that, in the mental world, has effects as remarkable as those in the natural world and appears in many different forms. Its effects are evident everywhere, but the causes are mostly unknown and can be traced back to the original qualities of human nature, which I don't intend to explain. Nothing is more essential for a true philosopher than to control the excessive urge to explore causes, and once a doctrine is established based on a sufficient number of experiments, to be content with that when further inquiry would lead to obscure and uncertain speculation. In such cases, it would be much better to focus on examining the effects rather than the causes of his principle.
Amongst the effects of this union or association of ideas, there are none more remarkable, than those complex ideas, which are the common subjects of our thoughts and reasoning, and generally arise from some principle of union among our simple ideas. These complex ideas may be divided into Relations, Modes, and Substances. We shall briefly examine each of these in order, and shall subjoin some considerations concerning our general and particular ideas, before we leave the present subject, which may be considered as the elements of this philosophy.
Among the effects of this connection or association of ideas, none are more notable than those complex ideas that are the main topics of our thoughts and reasoning, typically arising from some principle of connection among our simple ideas. These complex ideas can be categorized into Relations, Modes, and Substances. We will briefly explore each of these in order and will include some thoughts about our general and specific ideas before we finish this topic, which can be seen as the foundation of this philosophy.
SECT. V. OF RELATIONS.
The word RELATION is commonly used in two senses considerably different from each other. Either for that quality, by which two ideas are connected together in the imagination, and the one naturally introduces the other, after the manner above-explained: or for that particular circumstance, in which, even upon the arbitrary union of two ideas in the fancy, we may think proper to compare them. In common language the former is always the sense, in which we use the word, relation; and it is only in philosophy, that we extend it to mean any particular subject of comparison, without a connecting principle. Thus distance will be allowed by philosophers to be a true relation, because we acquire an idea of it by the comparing of objects: But in a common way we say, THAT NOTHING CAN BE MORE DISTANT THAN SUCH OR SUCH THINGS FROM EACH OTHER, NOTHING CAN HAVE LESS RELATION: as if distance and relation were incompatible.
The word RELATION is often used in two very different ways. One refers to the quality that connects two ideas in our minds, where one idea naturally leads to the other, as explained earlier. The other refers to a specific situation where we choose to compare two ideas, even if they are just randomly connected in our imagination. In everyday language, we usually refer to the first meaning when we say "relation." It’s only in philosophy that we broaden it to refer to any specific subject of comparison, without a linking principle. For instance, philosophers agree that distance is a true relation because we understand it by comparing objects. But in everyday conversation, we might say, "NOTHING CAN BE MORE DISTANT THAN SUCH OR SUCH THINGS FROM EACH OTHER, NOTHING CAN HAVE LESS RELATION," as if distance and relation cannot coexist.
It may perhaps be esteemed an endless task to enumerate all those qualities, which make objects admit of comparison, and by which the ideas of philosophical relation are produced. But if we diligently consider them, we shall find that without difficulty they may be comprised under seven general heads, which may be considered as the sources of all philosophical relation.
It might seem like an endless job to list all the qualities that allow us to compare objects and create the ideas of philosophical relationships. However, if we look closely at them, we’ll see that they can easily be grouped into seven main categories, which can be seen as the foundations of all philosophical relationships.
(1) The first is RESEMBLANCE: And this is a relation, without which no philosophical relation can exist; since no objects will admit of comparison, but what have some degree of resemblance. But though resemblance be necessary to all philosophical relation, it does not follow, that it always produces a connexion or association of ideas. When a quality becomes very general, and is common to a great many individuals, it leads not the mind directly to any one of them; but by presenting at once too great a choice, does thereby prevent the imagination from fixing on any single object.
(1) The first is RESEMBLANCE: This is a relationship without which no philosophical relation can exist because no objects can be compared unless they have some degree of resemblance. However, while resemblance is necessary for all philosophical relations, it doesn't necessarily create a connection or association of ideas. When a quality becomes very general and is shared by many individuals, it doesn't lead the mind directly to any one of them; instead, by offering too many options at once, it prevents the imagination from focusing on any single object.
(2) IDENTITY may be esteemed a second species of relation. This relation I here consider as applied in its strictest sense to constant and unchangeable objects; without examining the nature and foundation of personal identity, which shall find its place afterwards. Of all relations the most universal is that of identity, being common to every being whose existence has any duration.
(2) IDENTITY can be regarded as a second type of relation. I’m looking at this relation in its strictest sense as it applies to constant and unchanging objects, without exploring the nature and foundation of personal identity, which will be addressed later. Of all relations, the most universal is identity, as it is common to every being whose existence lasts for any period.
(3) After identity the most universal and comprehensive relations are those of SPACE and TIME, which are the sources of an infinite number of comparisons, such as distant, contiguous, above, below, before, after, etc.
(3) After identity, the most universal and comprehensive relationships are those of SPACE and TIME, which are the sources of countless comparisons, like distant, adjacent, above, below, before, after, etc.
(4) All those objects, which admit of QUANTITY, or NUMBER, may be compared in that particular; which is another very fertile source of relation.
(4) All objects that can be measured in QUANTITY or NUMBER can be compared in that way, which is another very rich source of relationships.
(5) When any two objects possess the same QUALITY in common, the DEGREES, in which they possess it, form a fifth species of relation. Thus of two objects, which are both heavy, the one may be either of greater, or less weight than the other. Two colours, that are of the same kind, may yet be of different shades, and in that respect admit of comparison.
(5) When two objects share the same QUALITY, the DIFFERENCES in how much they possess it create a fifth type of relationship. For example, if two objects are both heavy, one might weigh more or less than the other. Two colors that are of the same type can still have different shades, allowing for comparison in that aspect.
(6) The relation of CONTRARIETY may at first sight be regarded as an exception to the rule, THAT NO RELATION OF ANY KIND CAN SUBSIST WITHOUT SOME DEGREE OF RESEMBLANCE. But let us consider, that no two ideas are in themselves contrary, except those of existence and non-existence, which are plainly resembling, as implying both of them an idea of the object; though the latter excludes the object from all times and places, in which it is supposed not to exist.
(6) The relationship of CONTRARIETY might initially seem like an exception to the rule that NO RELATION OF ANY KIND CAN EXIST WITHOUT SOME DEGREE OF RESEMBLANCE. However, if we think about it, no two ideas are truly contrary except for those of existence and non-existence, which clearly resemble each other since they both imply some idea of the object; although the latter removes the object from all times and places where it’s presumed not to exist.
(7) All other objects, such as fire and water, heat and cold, are only found to be contrary from experience, and from the contrariety of their causes or effects; which relation of cause and effect is a seventh philosophical relation, as well as a natural one. The resemblance implied in this relation, shall be explained afterwards.
(7) All other things, like fire and water, heat and cold, are seen to be opposites based on experience and the differences in their causes or effects. This connection between cause and effect is a seventh philosophical relationship, as well as a natural one. The similarity involved in this relationship will be explained later.
It might naturally be expected, that I should join DIFFERENCE to the other relations. But that I consider rather as a negation of relation, than as anything real or positive. Difference is of two kinds as opposed either to identity or resemblance. The first is called a difference of number; the other of KIND.
It might be expected that I should connect DIFFERENCE to the other relations. However, I see it more as a negation of relation than as something real or positive. There are two kinds of difference: one is in contrast to identity, and the other to resemblance. The first is called a difference of number; the second, a difference of KIND.
SECT. VI. OF MODES AND SUBSTANCES
I would fain ask those philosophers, who found so much of their reasonings on the distinction of substance and accident, and imagine we have clear ideas of each, whether the idea of substance be derived from the impressions of sensation or of reflection? If it be conveyed to us by our senses, I ask, which of them; and after what manner? If it be perceived by the eyes, it must be a colour; if by the ears, a sound; if by the palate, a taste; and so of the other senses. But I believe none will assert, that substance is either a colour, or sound, or a taste. The idea, of substance must therefore be derived from an impression of reflection, if it really exist. But the impressions of reflection resolve themselves into our passions and emotions: none of which can possibly represent a substance. We have therefore no idea of substance, distinct from that of a collection of particular qualities, nor have we any other meaning when we either talk or reason concerning it.
I would like to ask those philosophers who base so much of their reasoning on the difference between substance and accident, and who think we have clear ideas of both, whether the idea of substance comes from our sensory experiences or from reflection. If it comes to us through our senses, I wonder which sense it is and in what way. If it's perceived by the eyes, it must be a color; if by the ears, a sound; if by the mouth, a taste; and the same goes for the other senses. But I doubt anyone would claim that substance is just a color, a sound, or a taste. Therefore, the idea of substance must come from an impression of reflection, if it actually exists. However, the impressions of reflection boil down to our feelings and emotions, none of which can truly represent a substance. So, we have no idea of substance that is separate from a collection of specific qualities, nor do we have any other understanding when we talk or think about it.
The idea of a substance as well as that of a mode, is nothing but a collection of Simple ideas, that are united by the imagination, and have a particular name assigned them, by which we are able to recall, either to ourselves or others, that collection. But the difference betwixt these ideas consists in this, that the particular qualities, which form a substance, are commonly referred to an unknown something, in which they are supposed to inhere; or granting this fiction should not take place, are at least supposed to be closely and inseparably connected by the relations of contiguity and causation. The effect of this is, that whatever new simple quality we discover to have the same connexion with the rest, we immediately comprehend it among them, even though it did not enter into the first conception of the substance. Thus our idea of gold may at first be a yellow colour, weight, malleableness, fusibility; but upon the discovery of its dissolubility in aqua regia, we join that to the other qualities, and suppose it to belong to the substance as much as if its idea had from the beginning made a part of the compound one. The principal of union being regarded as the chief part of the complex idea, gives entrance to whatever quality afterwards occurs, and is equally comprehended by it, as are the others, which first presented themselves.
The concept of a substance and a mode is essentially just a collection of simple ideas that our imagination links together and gives a specific name, allowing us to remember that collection for ourselves or for others. The key difference between these ideas is that the specific qualities defining a substance are usually associated with an unknown something in which they are believed to reside. Even if we don’t accept this assumption, they are still thought to be closely and inseparably connected through their relationships in terms of proximity and cause-and-effect. As a result, whenever we discover a new simple quality that has the same connection to the rest, we immediately include it in the group, even if it wasn’t part of our initial understanding of the substance. For example, our idea of gold might start with its yellow color, weight, malleability, and ability to melt; but once we find out that it dissolves in aqua regia, we add that quality to the others, assuming it is just as much a part of the substance as if it had been included from the start. The principle of unity is seen as the most important aspect of the complex idea, allowing any new quality that arises to be accepted just like the initial qualities were.
That this cannot take place in modes, is evident from considering their nature. The simple ideas of which modes are formed, either represent qualities, which are not united by contiguity and causation, but are dispersed in different subjects; or if they be all united together, the uniting principle is not regarded as the foundation of the complex idea. The idea of a dance is an instance of the first kind of modes; that of beauty of the second. The reason is obvious, why such complex ideas cannot receive any new idea, without changing the name, which distinguishes the mode.
That this cannot happen in different forms is clear when we think about their nature. The simple ideas that make up modes either represent qualities that aren't connected by proximity or cause, but instead are spread across various subjects; or if they are all grouped together, the principle that combines them isn’t seen as the base of the complex idea. The idea of a dance is an example of the first type of modes; the idea of beauty is an example of the second. It's clear why such complex ideas can’t take on any new ideas without changing the name that identifies the mode.
SECT. VII. OF ABSTRACT IDEAS.
A very material question has been started concerning ABSTRACT or GENERAL ideas, WHETHER THEY BE GENERAL OR PARTICULAR IN THE MIND'S CONCEPTION OF THEM. A great philosopher[3] has disputed the received opinion in this particular, and has asserted, that all general ideas are nothing but particular ones, annexed to a certain term, which gives them a more extensive signification, and makes them recall upon occasion other individuals, which are similar to them. As I look upon this to be one of the greatest and most valuable discoveries that has been made of late years in the republic of letters, I shall here endeavour to confirm it by some arguments, which I hope will put it beyond all doubt and controversy.
A significant question has come up regarding ABSTRACT or GENERAL ideas, whether they are GENERAL or PARTICULAR in how we conceive them. A great philosopher[3] has challenged the accepted view on this issue and has claimed that all general ideas are simply particular ones linked to a specific term, which gives them broader meaning and allows them to evoke similar individuals when needed. Since I believe this to be one of the most important and valuable discoveries made in recent years in the world of literature, I will attempt to support it with some arguments that I hope will make it indisputable and free from controversy.
[3] Dr. Berkeley. [Introd.: to ‘Principles of Human Knowledge,’ secs. 18 &c. Cf. also Introd. to this volume paragraphs 183 and ff.—Ed.]
[3] Dr. Berkeley. [Intro: to ‘Principles of Human Knowledge,’ secs. 18 & etc. See also Intro to this volume paragraphs 183 and following.—Ed.]
It is evident, that in forming most of our general ideas, if not all of them, we abstract from every particular degree of quantity and quality, and that an object ceases not to be of any particular species on account of every small alteration in its extension, duration and other properties. It may therefore be thought, that here is a plain dilemma, that decides concerning the nature of those abstract ideas, which have afforded so much speculation to philosophers. The abstract idea of a man represents men of all sizes and all qualities; which it is concluded it cannot do, but either by representing at once all possible sizes and all possible qualities, or by, representing no particular one at all. Now it having been esteemed absurd to defend the former proposition, as implying an infinite capacity in the mind, it has been commonly inferred in favour of the latter: and our abstract ideas have been supposed to represent no particular degree either of quantity or quality. But that this inference is erroneous, I shall endeavour to make appear, first, by proving, that it is utterly impossible to conceive any quantity or quality, without forming a precise notion of its degrees: And secondly by showing, that though the capacity of the mind be not infinite, yet we can at once form a notion of all possible degrees of quantity and quality, in such a manner at least, as, however imperfect, may serve all the purposes of reflection and conversation.
It’s clear that when we create most of our general ideas, if not all of them, we remove every specific degree of quantity and quality, and an object doesn’t stop being part of a particular category just because of minor changes in its size, duration, and other characteristics. This presents a straightforward dilemma that addresses the nature of those abstract ideas, which have sparked so much debate among philosophers. The abstract idea of a man represents men of all sizes and qualities; it’s concluded that it can’t do this unless it represents all possible sizes and qualities at once, or represents no specific one at all. Since it’s considered absurd to support the first idea, as it suggests that the mind has infinite capacity, people generally lean towards the second: our abstract ideas are thought to represent no specific degree of quantity or quality. However, I aim to show that this reasoning is incorrect. First, I will prove that it’s completely impossible to conceive of any quantity or quality without forming a clear idea of its degrees. Second, I’ll demonstrate that while the capacity of the mind isn’t infinite, we can still form a notion of all possible degrees of quantity and quality at once, in a way that, though imperfect, can still meet the needs of reflection and conversation.
To begin with the first proposition, THAT THE MIND CANNOT FORM ANY NOTION OF QUANTITY OR QUALITY WITHOUT FORMING A PRECISE NOTION OF DEGREES OF EACH; we may prove this by the three following arguments. First, We have observed, that whatever objects are different are distinguishable, and that whatever objects are distinguishable are separable by the thought and imagination. And we may here add, that these propositions are equally true in the inverse, and that whatever objects are separable are also distinguishable, and that whatever objects are distinguishable, are also different. For how is it possible we can separate what is not distinguishable, or distinguish what is not different? In order therefore to know, whether abstraction implies a separation, we need only consider it in this view, and examine, whether all the circumstances, which we abstract from in our general ideas, be such as are distinguishable and different from those, which we retain as essential parts of them. But it is evident at first sight, that the precise length of a line is not different nor distinguishable from the line itself nor the precise degree of any quality from the quality. These ideas, therefore, admit no more of separation than they do of distinction and difference. They are consequently conjoined with each other in the conception; and the general idea of a line, notwithstanding all our abstractions and refinements, has in its appearance in the mind a precise degree of quantity and quality; however it may be made to represent others, which have different degrees of both.
To start with the first idea, THAT THE MIND CANNOT FORM ANY NOTION OF QUANTITY OR QUALITY WITHOUT FORMING A PRECISE NOTION OF DEGREES OF EACH; we can support this with three arguments. First, we've noticed that any objects that are different can be distinguished, and anything that can be distinguished can be separated in thought and imagination. Additionally, these statements are just as true in reverse: anything that can be separated is also distinguishable, and anything distinguishable is also different. After all, how can we separate things that aren’t distinguishable, or distinguish things that aren’t different? Therefore, to understand whether abstraction implies separation, we only need to look at it this way and check if all the features we abstract from our general ideas are distinguishable and different from those we keep as essential elements. It’s clear at first glance that the specific length of a line is not different or distinguishable from the line itself, nor is the exact degree of any quality different from the quality. These concepts therefore allow no more separation than they do distinction and difference. They are thus interconnected in our understanding; the general idea of a line, despite all our abstractions and refinements, carries within it a precise degree of quantity and quality, even if it can represent others that have different degrees of both.
Secondly, it is contest, that no object can appear to the senses; or in other words, that no impression can become present to the mind, without being determined in its degrees both of quantity and quality. The confusion, in which impressions are sometimes involved, proceeds only from their faintness and unsteadiness, not from any capacity in the mind to receive any impression, which in its real existence has no particular degree nor proportion. That is a contradiction in terms; and even implies the flattest of all contradictions, viz. that it is possible for the same thing both to be and not to be.
Secondly, it's clear that no object can be perceived by the senses; in other words, no impression can come to the mind without being defined in its levels of both quantity and quality. The confusion that sometimes surrounds impressions comes only from their faintness and instability, not from any ability of the mind to accept an impression that, in reality, has no specific degree or proportion. That would be a contradiction in itself and even suggests the most fundamental contradiction of all, which is that it's possible for the same thing to both exist and not exist.
Now since all ideas are derived from impressions, and are nothing but copies and representations of them, whatever is true of the one must be acknowledged concerning the other. Impressions and ideas differ only in their strength and vivacity. The foregoing conclusion is not founded on any particular degree of vivacity. It cannot therefore be affected by any variation in that particular. An idea is a weaker impression; and as a strong impression must necessarily have a determinate quantity and quality, the case must be the same with its copy or representative.
Now that all ideas come from impressions and are just copies and representations of them, whatever is true for one must also be true for the other. Impressions and ideas differ only in their intensity and vividness. This conclusion isn’t based on any specific level of vividness, so it can’t be influenced by changes in that area. An idea is a less intense impression, and since a strong impression must have a specific quantity and quality, the same must apply to its copy or representation.
Thirdly, it is a principle generally received in philosophy that everything in nature is individual, and that it is utterly absurd to suppose a triangle really existent, which has no precise proportion of sides and angles. If this therefore be absurd in fact and reality, it must also be absurd in idea; since nothing of which we can form a clear and distinct idea is absurd and impossible. But to form the idea of an object, and to form an idea simply, is the same thing; the reference of the idea to an object being an extraneous denomination, of which in itself it bears no mark or character. Now as it is impossible to form an idea of an object, that is possest of quantity and quality, and yet is possest of no precise degree of either; it follows that there is an equal impossibility of forming an idea, that is not limited and confined in both these particulars. Abstract ideas are therefore in themselves individual, however they may become general in their representation. The image in the mind is only that of a particular object, though the application of it in our reasoning be the same, as if it were universal.
Thirdly, it's a widely accepted principle in philosophy that everything in nature is individual and that it's completely ridiculous to think of a triangle that exists without specific proportions of sides and angles. If this is absurd in reality, it must also be absurd in concept since nothing we can clearly understand is absurd or impossible. However, forming an idea of an object and simply forming an idea is the same thing; the connection of the idea to an object is an external label that doesn't inherently define it. Since it's impossible to have an idea of an object that has quantity and quality but lacks a specific degree of either, it follows that it's equally impossible to have an idea that isn't limited and defined in these respects. Abstract ideas are therefore individual in nature, even though they may be represented generally. The image in our minds is only of a specific object, even if we use it in reasoning as if it were universal.
This application of ideas beyond their nature proceeds from our collecting all their possible degrees of quantity and quality in such an imperfect manner as may serve the purposes of life, which is the second proposition I proposed to explain. When we have found a resemblance[4] among several objects, that often occur to us, we apply the same name to all of them, whatever differences we may observe in the degrees of their quantity and quality, and whatever other differences may appear among them. After we have acquired a custom of this kind, the hearing of that name revives the idea of one of these objects, and makes the imagination conceive it with all its particular circumstances and proportions. But as the same word is supposed to have been frequently applied to other individuals, that are different in many respects from that idea, which is immediately present to the mind; the word not being able to revive the idea of all these individuals, but only touches the soul, if I may be allowed so to speak, and revives that custom, which we have acquired by surveying them. They are not really and in fact present to the mind, but only in power; nor do we draw them all out distinctly in the imagination, but keep ourselves in a readiness to survey any of them, as we may be prompted by a present design or necessity. The word raises up an individual idea, along with a certain custom; and that custom produces any other individual one, for which we may have occasion. But as the production of all the ideas, to which the name may be applied, is in most eases impossible, we abridge that work by a more partial consideration, and find but few inconveniences to arise in our reasoning from that abridgment.
This application of ideas beyond their natural scope comes from our attempt to gather all their possible degrees of quantity and quality in a way that serves the purposes of life, which is the second point I wanted to explain. When we find a similarity among several objects that we frequently encounter, we use the same name for all of them, despite any differences we might notice in their quantity and quality, as well as any other differences that may exist. Once we develop this habit, hearing that name brings to mind the idea of one of these objects and allows our imagination to picture it with all its specific details and proportions. However, since the same word has been used for other individuals that are quite different from the idea currently in our minds, the word can't bring to mind all those individuals but only triggers the custom we've developed from observing them. They aren't actually present in our minds—only in potential; we don't distinctly recall all of them in our imagination but are ready to consider any of them as needed based on our current goals or necessities. The word evokes an individual idea along with a certain custom, and that custom can lead to any other specific one we might need. But since recalling every idea the name could apply to is often impossible, we simplify that task with a more focused consideration, leading to few issues in our reasoning from that simplification.
[4] It is evident, that even different simple ideas may have a similarity or resemblance to each other; nor is it necessary, that the point or circumstance of resemblance shoud be distinct or separable from that in which they differ. BLUE and GREEN are different simple ideas, but are more resembling than BLUE and SCARLET; tho their perfect simplicity excludes all possibility of separation or distinction. It is the same case with particular sounds, and tastes and smells. These admit of infinite resemblances upon the general appearance and comparison, without having any common circumstance the same. And of this we may be certain, even from the very abstract terms SIMPLE IDEA. They comprehend all simple ideas under them. These resemble each other in their simplicity. And yet from their very nature, which excludes all composition, this circumstance, In which they resemble, Is not distinguishable nor separable from the rest. It is the same case with all the degrees In any quality. They are all resembling and yet the quality, In any individual, Is not distinct from the degree.
[4] It's clear that even different simple ideas can share similarities or resemblances; it's not necessary for the aspect in which they resemble each other to be distinct or separate from what makes them different. BLUE and GREEN are different simple ideas, but they resemble each other more than BLUE and SCARLET do, even though their complete simplicity means there's no chance for separation or distinction. The same applies to specific sounds, tastes, and smells. These can have countless similarities based on their general appearance and comparison, without having any shared characteristics. We can be sure of this just from the very abstract terms SIMPLE IDEA, which include all simple ideas under them. They resemble each other in their simplicity. Yet, because of their nature, which prevents any composition, the aspect in which they resemble each other isn't distinguishable or separable from the rest. This also applies to all degrees of any quality. They all resemble each other, yet the quality in any individual case isn't distinct from the degree.
For this is one of the most extraordinary circumstances in the present affair, that after the mind has produced an individual idea, upon which we reason, the attendant custom, revived by the general or abstract term, readily suggests any other individual, if by chance we form any reasoning, that agrees not with it. Thus should we mention the word triangle, and form the idea of a particular equilateral one to correspond to it, and should we afterwards assert, that the three angles of a triangle are equal to each other, the other individuals of a scalenum and isosceles, which we overlooked at first, immediately crowd in upon us, and make us perceive the falshood of this proposition, though it be true with relation to that idea, which we had formed. If the mind suggests not always these ideas upon occasion, it proceeds from some imperfection in its faculties; and such a one as is often the source of false reasoning and sophistry. But this is principally the case with those ideas which are abstruse and compounded. On other occasions the custom is more entire, and it is seldom we run into such errors.
For this is one of the most remarkable situations in this matter, that once the mind has created an individual idea, which we then reason about, the related custom, triggered by the general or abstract term, quickly brings to mind another individual idea if we happen to make any reasoning that doesn’t align with it. For example, if we mention the word triangle and visualize a specific equilateral triangle to match it, then later state that the three angles of a triangle are equal to one another, the other types, like scalene and isosceles, which we initially ignored, instantly come to mind and show us the falsehood of this claim, even though it is true in relation to the idea we had formed. If the mind doesn't always recall these ideas when needed, it results from some deficiency in its abilities, leading to false reasoning and trickery. However, this primarily happens with ideas that are complex and obscure. In other instances, the custom is more complete, and it's rare for us to make such mistakes.
Nay so entire is the custom, that the very same idea may be annext to several different words, and may be employed in different reasonings, without any danger of mistake. Thus the idea of an equilateral triangle of an inch perpendicular may serve us in talking of a figure, of a rectilinear figure, of a regular figure, of a triangle, and of an equilateral triangle. All these terms, therefore, are in this case attended with the same idea; but as they are wont to be applied in a greater or lesser compass, they excite their particular habits, and thereby keep the mind in a readiness to observe, that no conclusion be formed contrary to any ideas, which are usually comprized under them.
The custom is so complete that the same idea can be linked to several different words and can be used in various arguments without any risk of confusion. For example, the concept of an equilateral triangle with a one-inch height can be used when discussing a figure, a straight-sided figure, a regular figure, a triangle, and an equilateral triangle. Therefore, all these terms carry the same idea in this context; however, since they are often applied in broader or narrower contexts, they invoke their specific associations, which helps the mind stay alert to ensure that no conclusions are drawn that contradict any ideas typically included under them.
Before those habits have become entirely perfect, perhaps the mind may not be content with forming the idea of only one individual, but may run over several, in order to make itself comprehend its own meaning, and the compass of that collection, which it intends to express by the general term. That we may fix the meaning of the word, figure, we may revolve in our mind the ideas of circles, squares, parallelograms, triangles of different sizes and proportions, and may not rest on one image or idea. However this may be, it is certain that we form the idea of individuals, whenever we use any general term; that we seldom or never can exhaust these individuals; and that those, which remain, are only represented by means of that habit, by which we recall them, whenever any present occasion requires it. This then is the nature of our abstract ideas and general terms; and it is after this manner we account for the foregoing paradox, THAT SOME IDEAS ARE PARTICULAR IN THEIR NATURE, BUT GENERAL IN THEIR REPRESENTATION. A particular idea becomes general by being annexed to a general term; that is, to a term, which from a customary conjunction has a relation to many other particular ideas, and readily recalls them in the imagination.
Before those habits become completely perfected, the mind might not be satisfied with just forming the idea of a single individual. Instead, it may consider several individuals to better understand its own meaning and the range of that collection that it wants to express with a general term. To clarify the meaning of the word "figure," we can mentally go through the concepts of circles, squares, parallelograms, and triangles of various sizes and shapes, without settling on just one image or idea. Regardless of this, it’s clear that we form the idea of individuals whenever we use any general term; we can hardly ever capture all of these individuals, and those that remain are represented only through the habit by which we recall them whenever a current situation calls for it. This is the nature of our abstract ideas and general terms, and this is how we explain the earlier paradox: SOME IDEAS ARE PARTICULAR IN THEIR NATURE, BUT GENERAL IN THEIR REPRESENTATION. A particular idea becomes general when it is attached to a general term; that is, a term that, due to common usage, relates to many other particular ideas and easily brings them to mind.
The only difficulty, that can remain on this subject, must be with regard to that custom, which so readily recalls every particular idea, for which we may have occasion, and is excited by any word or sound, to which we commonly annex it. The most proper method, in my opinion, of giving a satisfactory explication of this act of the mind, is by producing other instances, which are analogous to it, and other principles, which facilitate its operation. To explain the ultimate causes of our mental actions is impossible. It is sufficient, if we can give any satisfactory account of them from experience and analogy.
The only challenge that remains on this topic has to do with that habit which easily brings to mind every specific idea we might need, triggered by any word or sound that we usually associate with it. In my view, the best way to provide a clear explanation of this mental process is by offering other examples that are similar to it and other principles that help make it work. It's impossible to explain the ultimate causes of our mental actions. It’s enough if we can provide a satisfactory account of them based on experience and analogy.
First then I observe, that when we mention any great number, such as a thousand, the mind has generally no adequate idea of it, but only a power of producing such an idea, by its adequate idea of the decimals, under which the number is comprehended. This imperfection, however, in our ideas, is never felt in our reasonings; which seems to be an instance parallel to the present one of universal ideas.
First, I notice that when we talk about a large number, like a thousand, our minds usually don’t have a clear understanding of it. Instead, we can only form some idea of it based on our understanding of the smaller parts, like decimals, that make up that number. However, this limitation in our understanding doesn't affect our reasoning, which seems similar to the current example of universal ideas.
Secondly, we have several instances of habits, which may be revived by one single word; as when a person, who has by rote any periods of a discourse, or any number of verses, will be put in remembrance of the whole, which he is at a loss to recollect, by that single word or expression, with which they begin.
Secondly, we have several examples of habits that can be triggered by just one word; for instance, when someone who has memorized parts of a speech or lines of poetry finds themselves unable to recall the entire thing, a single word or phrase that starts it can jog their memory.
Thirdly, I believe every one, who examines the situation of his mind in reasoning will agree with me, that we do not annex distinct and compleat ideas to every term we make use of, and that in talking of government, church, negotiation, conquest, we seldom spread out in our minds all the simple ideas, of which these complex ones are composed. It is however observable, that notwithstanding this imperfection we may avoid talking nonsense on these subjects, and may perceive any repugnance among the ideas, as well as if we had a fall comprehension of them. Thus if instead of saying, that in war the weaker have always recourse to negotiation, we should say, that they have always recourse to conquest, the custom, which we have acquired of attributing certain relations to ideas, still follows the words, and makes us immediately perceive the absurdity of that proposition; in the same manner as one particular idea may serve us in reasoning concerning other ideas, however different from it in several circumstances.
Thirdly, I think anyone who reflects on their thought process will agree with me that we don’t attach clear and complete meanings to every term we use. When discussing topics like government, church, negotiation, or conquest, we rarely consider all the basic ideas that make up these complex concepts. However, it’s noteworthy that despite this limitation, we can still avoid saying nonsense about these subjects and recognize contradictions among the ideas, just as if we fully understood them. For example, if instead of saying that the weaker side in war often turns to negotiation, we claimed they always resort to conquest, our familiarity with the relationships between ideas still influences our understanding of the words and quickly highlights the absurdity of that statement. Similarly, one specific idea can help us reason about other ideas, even if they differ in various ways.
Fourthly, As the individuals are collected together, said placed under a general term with a view to that resemblance, which they bear to each other, this relation must facilitate their entrance in the imagination, and make them be suggested more readily upon occasion. And indeed if we consider the common progress of the thought, either in reflection or conversation, we shall find great reason to be satisfyed in this particular. Nothing is more admirable, than the readiness, with which the imagination suggests its ideas, and presents them at the very instant, in which they become necessary or useful. The fancy runs from one end of the universe to the other in collecting those ideas, which belong to any subject. One would think the whole intellectual world of ideas was at once subjected to our view, and that we did nothing but pick out such as were most proper for our purpose. There may not, however, be any present, beside those very ideas, that are thus collected by a kind of magical faculty in the soul, which, though it be always most perfect in the greatest geniuses, and is properly what we call a genius, is however inexplicable by the utmost efforts of human understanding.
Fourthly, as people come together, they are grouped under a general term based on the similarities they share. This connection makes it easier for them to pop into our minds and for us to bring them up when needed. If we look at how thoughts flow, whether in deep thought or conversation, we'll see plenty of reasons to feel satisfied about this. Nothing is more impressive than how quickly our imagination brings forth ideas right when we need them. It effortlessly moves across the entire universe to gather ideas related to any topic. It feels like the entire world of ideas is laid out before us, and all we have to do is choose the ones that fit our needs best. However, it’s possible that only those specific ideas are present, collected through a kind of magical ability in the soul, which is most pronounced in the greatest minds and is what we call genius, yet it remains beyond full explanation despite our best efforts to understand it.
Perhaps these four reflections may help to remove an difficulties to the hypothesis I have proposed concerning abstract ideas, so contrary to that, which has hitherto prevailed in philosophy, But, to tell the truth I place my chief confidence in what I have already proved concerning the impossibility of general ideas, according to the common method of explaining them. We must certainly seek some new system on this head, and there plainly is none beside what I have proposed. If ideas be particular in their nature, and at the same time finite in their number, it is only by custom they can become general in their representation, and contain an infinite number of other ideas under them.
Maybe these four reflections can help eliminate some difficulties with the hypothesis I’ve proposed about abstract ideas, which is so different from what has been accepted in philosophy until now. But honestly, I rely mostly on what I’ve already demonstrated about the impossibility of general ideas, based on the common way of explaining them. We definitely need to look for a new system on this topic, and clearly, there isn’t one other than what I’ve suggested. If ideas are specific by nature and at the same time limited in number, they can only become general in their representation through habit and encompass an infinite number of other ideas beneath them.
Before I leave this subject I shall employ the same principles to explain that distinction of reason, which is so much talked of, and is so little understood, in the schools. Of this kind is the distinction betwixt figure and the body figured; motion and the body moved. The difficulty of explaining this distinction arises from the principle above explained, that all ideas, which are different, are separable. For it follows from thence, that if the figure be different from the body, their ideas must be separable as well as distinguishable: if they be not different, their ideas can neither be separable nor distinguishable. What then is meant by a distinction of reason, since it implies neither a difference nor separation.
Before I wrap up this topic, I want to use the same principles to clarify that concept of reason, which gets talked about a lot but is hardly understood in schools. This includes the distinction between a figure and the body it represents, as well as motion and the body that is moving. The challenge in explaining this distinction comes from the principle mentioned earlier, that all different ideas are separable. This means that if the figure is different from the body, their ideas must be both separable and distinguishable; if they aren’t different, then their ideas can’t be separable or distinguishable either. So what does a distinction of reason really mean, since it suggests neither a difference nor a separation?
To remove this difficulty we must have recourse to the foregoing explication of abstract ideas. It is certain that the mind would never have dreamed of distinguishing a figure from the body figured, as being in reality neither distinguishable, nor different, nor separable; did it not observe, that even in this simplicity there might be contained many different resemblances and relations. Thus when a globe of white marble is presented, we receive only the impression of a white colour disposed in a certain form, nor are we able to separate and distinguish the colour from the form. But observing afterwards a globe of black marble and a cube of white, and comparing them with our former object, we find two separate resemblances, in what formerly seemed, and really is, perfectly inseparable. After a little more practice of this kind, we begin to distinguish the figure from the colour by a distinction of reason; that is, we consider the figure and colour together, since they are in effect the same and undistinguishable; but still view them in different aspects, according to the resemblances, of which they are susceptible. When we would consider only the figure of the globe of white marble, we form in reality an idea both of the figure and colour, but tacitly carry our eye to its resemblance with the globe of black marble: And in the same manner, when we would consider its colour only, we turn our view to its resemblance with the cube of white marble. By this means we accompany our ideas with a kind of reflection, of which custom renders us, in a great measure, insensible. A person, who desires us to consider the figure of a globe of white marble without thinking on its colour, desires an impossibility but his meaning is, that we should consider the figure and colour together, but still keep in our eye the resemblance to the globe of black marble, or that to any other globe of whatever colour or substance.
To address this difficulty, we need to refer back to the earlier explanation of abstract ideas. It’s clear that the mind wouldn’t have thought to separate a figure from the object it represents, since they are actually inseparable and not different from each other. However, it notices that even in this simplicity, there can be different resemblances and relationships. For example, when we see a globe made of white marble, we only get the impression of a white color shaped in a certain way, and we can’t separate the color from the shape. But when we later see a globe made of black marble and a cube of white, and compare them to the first object, we identify two distinct resemblances, in what seemed, and indeed is, completely inseparable. With a bit more practice like this, we start to differentiate between the shape and the color by a mental distinction; that is, we consider both shape and color together, since they are essentially the same and indistinguishable, but we still view them from different perspectives based on their resemblances. When we focus only on the shape of the white marble globe, we actually form an idea that includes both the shape and the color, while silently connecting it to its resemblance to the black marble globe. Similarly, when we want to focus solely on its color, we reference its similarity to the white marble cube. This way, we attach a kind of reflection to our ideas, which, due to habit, we often overlook. If someone asks us to consider the shape of a white marble globe without thinking about its color, they’re asking for the impossible. What they mean is that we should consider both shape and color together while keeping in mind the similarity to the black marble globe or any other globe, regardless of color or material.
SECT. I. OF THE INFINITE DIVISIBILITY OF OUR IDEAS OF SPACE AND TIME.
Whatever has the air of a paradox, and is contrary to the first and most unprejudiced notions of mankind, is often greedily embraced by philosophers, as shewing the superiority of their science, which could discover opinions so remote from vulgar conception. On the other hand, anything proposed to us, which causes surprize and admiration, gives such a satisfaction to the mind, that it indulges itself in those agreeable emotions, and will never be persuaded that its pleasure is entirely without foundation. From these dispositions in philosophers and their disciples arises that mutual complaisance betwixt them; while the former furnish such plenty of strange and unaccountable opinions, and the latter so readily believe them. Of this mutual complaisance I cannot give a more evident instance than in the doctrine of infinite divisibility, with the examination of which I shall begin this subject of the ideas of space and time.
Anything that seems paradoxical and goes against the basic and most unbiased ideas of people is often eagerly accepted by philosophers, as it shows how advanced their knowledge is, since they can reveal concepts so far removed from common understanding. Conversely, anything presented to us that surprises and fascinates us brings such satisfaction to the mind that it revels in those pleasant feelings, convinced that its enjoyment has some basis. This dynamic between philosophers and their followers creates a mutual agreement; the former offer a wealth of strange and puzzling ideas, while the latter readily accept them. A clear example of this mutual agreement is found in the idea of infinite divisibility, which is where I will start my discussion on the concepts of space and time.
It is universally allowed, that the capacity of the mind is limited, and can never attain a full and adequate conception of infinity: And though it were not allowed, it would be sufficiently evident from the plainest observation and experience. It is also obvious, that whatever is capable of being divided in infinitum, must consist of an infinite number of parts, and that it is impossible to set any bounds to the number of parts, without setting bounds at the same time to the division. It requires scarce any, induction to conclude from hence, that the idea, which we form of any finite quality, is not infinitely divisible, but that by proper distinctions and separations we may run up this idea to inferior ones, which will be perfectly simple and indivisible. In rejecting the infinite capacity of the mind, we suppose it may arrive at an end in the division of its ideas; nor are there any possible means of evading the evidence of this conclusion.
It's generally accepted that the mind has limits and can never fully grasp the concept of infinity. Even if it weren't accepted, it would be evident from basic observation and experience. It's clear that anything that can be divided infinitely must consist of an infinite number of parts, and it's impossible to limit the number of parts without also limiting the division itself. It hardly requires any reasoning to conclude from this that the idea we form of any finite quality is not infinitely divisible, but that with proper distinctions and separations, we can trace this idea back to simpler, indivisible ones. By rejecting the infinite capacity of the mind, we assume it can reach a conclusion in the division of its ideas; and there are no ways to escape this conclusion.
It is therefore certain, that the imagination reaches a minimum, and may raise up to itself an idea, of which it cannot conceive any sub-division, and which cannot be diminished without a total annihilation. When you tell me of the thousandth and ten thousandth part of a grain of sand, I have a distinct idea of these numbers and of their different proportions; but the images, which I form in my mind to represent the things themselves, are nothing different from each other, nor inferior to that image, by which I represent the grain of sand itself, which is supposed so vastly to exceed them. What consists of parts is distinguishable into them, and what is distinguishable is separable. But whatever we may imagine of the thing, the idea of a grain of sand is not distinguishable, nor separable into twenty, much less into a thousand, ten thousand, or an infinite number of different ideas.
It’s clear that the imagination has a limit and can create an idea that it can’t break down any further, and which can’t be reduced without completely destroying it. When you mention a thousandth or a ten thousandth of a grain of sand, I have a clear understanding of those numbers and their different ratios; however, the images I create in my mind to represent the actual things are no different from each other or less than the image I use to represent the grain of sand itself, which is thought to be so much larger than them. Things that have parts can be divided into those parts, and things that can be divided are separable. But no matter how we think about it, the idea of a grain of sand cannot be divided or separated into twenty, let alone a thousand, ten thousand, or an infinite number of different ideas.
It is the same case with the impressions of the senses as with the ideas of the imagination. Put a spot of ink upon paper, fix your eye upon that spot, and retire to such a distance, that, at last you lose sight of it; it is plain, that the moment before it vanished the image or impression was perfectly indivisible. It is not for want of rays of light striking on our eyes, that the minute parts of distant bodies convey not any sensible impression; but because they are removed beyond that distance, at which their impressions were reduced to a minimum, and were incapable of any farther diminution. A microscope or telescope, which renders them visible, produces not any new rays of light, but only spreads those, which always flowed from them; and by that means both gives parts to impressions, which to the naked eye appear simple and uncompounded, and advances to a minimum, what was formerly imperceptible.
It's the same with sensory impressions as it is with imaginative ideas. Imagine a spot of ink on paper; if you focus on that spot and then move back far enough until you can no longer see it, it's clear that just before it disappeared, the image or impression was completely indivisible. It's not that there aren’t enough light rays hitting our eyes that prevent the tiny parts of distant objects from making any noticeable impression; it’s because those objects are too far away, beyond the point where their impressions are reduced to the smallest size and can’t be reduced any further. A microscope or telescope, which makes them visible, doesn't create new rays of light; it simply spreads out the light that has always come from them. In doing so, it breaks down the impressions that appear simple and undivided to the naked eye and reveals details that were previously invisible.
We may hence discover the error of the common opinion, that the capacity of the mind is limited on both sides, and that it is impossible for the imagination to form an adequate idea, of what goes beyond a certain degree of minuteness as well as of greatness. Nothing can be more minute, than some ideas, which we form in the fancy; and images, which appear to the senses; since there are ideas and images perfectly simple and indivisible. The only defect of our senses is, that they give us disproportioned images of things, and represent as minute and uncompounded what is really great and composed of a vast number of parts. This mistake we are not sensible of: but taking the impressions of those minute objects, which appear to the senses, to be equal or nearly equal to the objects, and finding by reason, that there are other objects vastly more minute, we too hastily conclude, that these are inferior to any idea of our imagination or impression of our senses. This however is certain, that we can form ideas, which shall be no greater than the smallest atom of the animal spirits of an insect a thousand times less than a mite: And we ought rather to conclude, that the difficulty lies in enlarging our conceptions so much as to form a just notion of a mite, or even of an insect a thousand times less than a mite. For in order to form a just notion of these animals, we must have a distinct idea representing every part of them, which, according to the system of infinite divisibility, is utterly impossible, and, recording to that of indivisible parts or atoms, is extremely difficult, by reason of the vast number and multiplicity of these parts.
We can therefore see the fallacy in the common belief that the mind's capacity is limited on both ends, making it impossible for our imagination to grasp ideas that exceed a certain level of smallness or vastness. Some concepts we create in our minds, as well as images we perceive through our senses, can be incredibly tiny. There are ideas and images that are perfectly simple and indivisible. The only limitation of our senses is that they provide us with distorted images of things, representing something small and simple when it's actually large and made up of many parts. We are often unaware of this error; we assume that the impressions from these tiny objects that we perceive are equal to or nearly equal to the real thing. Discovering, through reason, that there are objects far smaller, we too quickly conclude that these are less than any idea from our imagination or our sensory impressions. However, it's clear that we can create ideas that are no larger than the smallest particle of an insect's spirit that is a thousand times smaller than a mite. We should rather conclude that the challenge lies in expanding our understanding enough to accurately picture a mite or even an insect that is a thousand times smaller than a mite. To form an accurate idea of these creatures, we need to distinctly represent each part of them, which, based on the concept of infinite divisibility, is completely impossible, and according to the concept of indivisible parts or atoms, is extremely difficult due to the sheer number and complexity of these parts.
SECT. II. OF THE INFINITE DIVISIBILITY OF SPACE AND TIME.
Wherever ideas are adequate representations of objects, the relations, contradictions and agreements of the ideas are all applicable to the objects; and this we may in general observe to be the foundation of all human knowledge. But our ideas are adequate representations of the most minute parts of extension; and through whatever divisions and subdivisions we may suppose these parts to be arrived at, they can never become inferior to some ideas, which we form. The plain consequence is, that whatever appears impossible and contradictory upon the comparison of these ideas, must be really impossible and contradictory, without any farther excuse or evasion.
Wherever ideas accurately reflect objects, the relationships, contradictions, and agreements between those ideas apply to the objects as well; this is generally the basis of all human knowledge. However, our ideas are accurate representations of even the tiniest parts of space; no matter how we divide these parts, they can never be lesser than some ideas we create. The straightforward conclusion is that anything that seems impossible and contradictory when we compare these ideas must genuinely be impossible and contradictory, without any further justification or excuses.
Every thing capable of being infinitely divided contains an infinite number of parts; otherwise the division would be stopt short by the indivisible parts, which we should immediately arrive at. If therefore any finite extension be infinitely divisible, it can be no contradiction to suppose, that a finite extension contains an infinite number of parts: And vice versa, if it be a contradiction to suppose, that a finite extension contains an infinite number of parts, no finite extension can be infinitely divisible. But that this latter supposition is absurd, I easily convince myself by the consideration of my clear ideas. I first take the least idea I can form of a part of extension, and being certain that there is nothing more minute than this idea, I conclude, that whatever I discover by its means must be a real quality of extension. I then repeat this idea once, twice, thrice, &c., and find the compound idea of extension, arising from its repetition, always to augment, and become double, triple, quadruple, &c., till at last it swells up to a considerable bulk, greater or smaller, in proportion as I repeat more or less the same idea. When I stop in the addition of parts, the idea of extension ceases to augment; and were I to carry on the addition in infinitum, I clearly perceive, that the idea of extension must also become infinite. Upon the whole, I conclude, that the idea of all infinite number of parts is individually the same idea with that of an infinite extension; that no finite extension is capable of containing an infinite number of parts; and consequently that no finite extension is infinitely divisible.[1]
Everything that can be divided infinitely contains an infinite number of parts; otherwise, the division would stop at indivisible parts, which we would encounter immediately. So, if a finite extension can be divided infinitely, it’s not a contradiction to assume that a finite extension has an infinite number of parts. On the other hand, if it would be a contradiction to think that a finite extension has an infinite number of parts, then no finite extension can be infinitely divisible. However, I easily convince myself that this second assumption is absurd by reflecting on my clear ideas. I first consider the smallest idea I can form of a part of extension, and since I'm sure there's nothing smaller than this idea, I conclude that whatever I discover through it must be a real quality of extension. I then repeat this idea once, twice, three times, etc., and find that the combined idea of extension increases, doubling, tripling, quadrupling, etc., until it ultimately grows into a substantial size, larger or smaller depending on how many times I repeat the same idea. When I stop adding parts, the idea of extension no longer increases; and if I were to continue adding parts indefinitely, I clearly see that the idea of extension would also become infinite. Overall, I conclude that the idea of an infinite number of parts is essentially the same as that of an infinite extension; that no finite extension can contain an infinite number of parts; and therefore, no finite extension is infinitely divisible.[1]
[1] It has been objected to me, that infinite divisibility supposes only an infinite number of PROPORTIONAL not of ALIQIOT parts, and that an infinite number of proportional parts does not form an infinite extension. But this distinction is entirely frivolous. Whether these parts be calld ALIQUOT or PROPORTIONAL, they cannot be inferior to those minute parts we conceive; and therefore cannot form a less extension by their conjunction.
[1] I've been challenged on the idea that infinite divisibility only implies an infinite number of PROPORTIONAL parts, not ALIQUID parts, and that an infinite number of proportional parts doesn't create an infinite extension. But this distinction is completely pointless. Whether we call these parts ALIQUOT or PROPORTIONAL, they cannot be smaller than the tiny parts we imagine; therefore, their combination cannot result in a smaller extension.
I may subjoin another argument proposed by a noted author,[2] which seems to me very strong and beautiful. It is evident, that existence in itself belongs only to unity, and is never applicable to number, but on account of the unites, of which the number is composed. Twenty men may be said to exist; but it is only because one, two, three, four, &c. are existent, and if you deny the existence of the latter, that of the former falls of course. It is therefore utterly absurd to suppose any number to exist, and yet deny the existence of unites; and as extension is always a number, according to the common sentiment of metaphysicians, and never resolves itself into any unite or indivisible quantity, it follows, that extension can never at all exist. It is in vain to reply, that any determinate quantity of extension is an unite; but such-a-one as admits of an infinite number of fractions, and is inexhaustible in its sub-divisions. For by the same rule these twenty men may be considered as a unit. The whole globe of the earth, nay the whole universe, may be considered as a unit. That term of unity is merely a fictitious denomination, which the mind may apply to any quantity of objects it collects together; nor can such an unity any more exist alone than number can, as being in reality a true number. But the unity, which can exist alone, and whose existence is necessary to that of all number, is of another kind, and must be perfectly indivisible, and incapable of being resolved into any lesser unity.
I might add another argument put forward by a well-known author, [2] which I find quite compelling and elegant. It's clear that existence itself only belongs to unity and is never applicable to numbers, except in relation to the units that make up those numbers. We can say that twenty men exist; however, that’s only because one, two, three, four, etc., exist, and if you deny the existence of those units, the existence of the twenty men follows suit. Therefore, it's completely nonsensical to think that a number can exist while denying the existence of its units; and since extension is always a number, according to common metaphysical beliefs, and never breaks down into any unit or indivisible quantity, it follows that extension can never truly exist. It's pointless to argue that any specific amount of extension is a unit; it is one that allows for an infinite number of fractions and is endlessly divisible. By the same logic, these twenty men can be seen as a unit. The entire globe, or even the whole universe, can be considered as a unit. That idea of unity is just a fictional label that the mind can apply to any collection of objects; nor can such a unity exist on its own any more than a number can, as it is essentially a true number. But the unity that can exist independently, and whose existence is necessary for all numbers, is of a different nature—it must be completely indivisible and incapable of being broken down into any smaller unity.
[2] Mons. MALEZIEU
All this reasoning takes place with regard to time; along with an additional argument, which it may be proper to take notice of. It is a property inseparable from time, and which in a manner constitutes its essence, that each of its parts succeeds another, and that none of them, however contiguous, can ever be co-existent. For the same reason, that the year 1737 cannot concur with the present year 1738 every moment must be distinct from, and posterior or antecedent to another. It is certain then, that time, as it exists, must be composed of indivisible moments. For if in time we could never arrive at an end of division, and if each moment, as it succeeds another, were not perfectly single and indivisible, there would be an infinite number of co-existent moments, or parts of time; which I believe will be allowed to be an arrant contradiction.
All this reasoning relates to time, along with an additional point that deserves attention. It's an inherent property of time, which essentially defines it, that every part follows another, and that none of them, no matter how close together, can ever exist at the same time. For the same reason, the year 1737 cannot overlap with the current year 1738; every moment must be different from, and either before or after, another moment. Therefore, it’s clear that time, as we perceive it, must consist of indivisible moments. If time could never be fully divided, and if each moment, as it follows another, wasn't completely single and indivisible, there would be an infinite number of moments existing at the same time, which is evidently a contradiction.
The infinite divisibility of space implies that of time, as is evident from the nature of motion. If the latter, therefore, be impossible, the former must be equally so.
The infinite ability to divide space suggests the same for time, which is clear from how motion works. If motion is impossible, then space must be equally impossible.
I doubt not but, it will readily be allowed by the most obstinate defender of the doctrine of infinite divisibility, that these arguments are difficulties, and that it is impossible to give any answer to them which will be perfectly clear and satisfactory. But here we may observe, that nothing can be more absurd, than this custom of calling a difficulty what pretends to be a demonstration, and endeavouring by that means to elude its force and evidence. It is not in demonstrations as in probabilities, that difficulties can take place, and one argument counter-ballance another, and diminish its authority. A demonstration, if just, admits of no opposite difficulty; and if not just, it is a mere sophism, and consequently can never be a difficulty. It is either irresistible, or has no manner of force. To talk therefore of objections and replies, and ballancing of arguments in such a question as this, is to confess, either that human reason is nothing but a play of words, or that the person himself, who talks so, has not a Capacity equal to such subjects. Demonstrations may be difficult to be comprehended, because of abstractedness of the subject; but can never have such difficulties as will weaken their authority, when once they are comprehended.
I have no doubt that even the most stubborn supporter of the idea of infinite divisibility will agree that these arguments present challenges, and that no answer can be given that is completely clear and satisfying. However, we should note that nothing is more absurd than the habit of calling a challenge something that pretends to be a proof, and trying to escape its impact and clarity by doing so. Demonstrations are not like probabilities, where difficulties can arise and one argument can cancel out another, reducing its authority. A valid demonstration does not allow for opposing difficulties; if it's not valid, it's just a fallacy and thus cannot be considered a difficulty. It is either undeniable or has no real strength. Therefore, discussing objections and responses or weighing arguments in a matter like this implies either that human reasoning is merely a play of words, or that the person making such claims lacks the capacity to understand such topics. Demonstrations may be hard to grasp due to the abstract nature of the subject, but they can never have difficulties that undermine their authority once they are understood.
It is true, mathematicians are wont to say, that there are here equally strong arguments on the other side of the question, and that the doctrine of indivisible points is also liable to unanswerable objections. Before I examine these arguments and objections in detail, I will here take them in a body, and endeavour by a short and decisive reason to prove at once, that it is utterly impossible they can have any just foundation.
It’s true, mathematicians often say, that there are equally strong arguments against this point of view, and that the idea of indivisible points is also subject to compelling objections. Before I dive into these arguments and objections in detail, I will address them all at once and try to provide a concise and clear reason to demonstrate that there’s no valid basis for them.
It is an established maxim in metaphysics, That whatever the mind clearly conceives, includes the idea of possible existence, or in other words, that nothing we imagine is absolutely impossible. We can form the idea of a golden mountain, and from thence conclude that such a mountain may actually exist. We can form no idea of a mountain without a valley, and therefore regard it as impossible.
It's a well-known principle in metaphysics that whatever the mind clearly imagines includes the idea of possible existence. In simpler terms, nothing we think of is absolutely impossible. We can picture a golden mountain and conclude that such a mountain might actually exist. However, we can't imagine a mountain without a valley, so we see that as impossible.
Now it is certain we have an idea of extension; for otherwise why do we talk and reason concerning it? It is likewise certain that this idea, as conceived by the imagination, though divisible into parts or inferior ideas, is not infinitely divisible, nor consists of an infinite number of parts: For that exceeds the comprehension of our limited capacities. Here then is an idea of extension, which consists of parts or inferior ideas, that are perfectly, indivisible: consequently this idea implies no contradiction: consequently it is possible for extension really to exist conformable to it: and consequently all the arguments employed against the possibility of mathematical points are mere scholastick quibbles, and unworthy of our attention.
Now it's clear that we have a concept of extension; otherwise, why would we discuss and think about it? It's also clear that this concept, as imagined, while it can be divided into smaller parts or ideas, is not infinitely divisible, nor does it consist of an infinite number of parts: that goes beyond what we can understand. So, here we have a concept of extension made up of parts or smaller ideas that are perfectly indivisible: therefore, this idea doesn't contradict itself: thus, it's possible for extension to truly exist in accordance with it: and therefore, all the arguments made against the possibility of mathematical points are just academic nonsense and not worth our attention.
These consequences we may carry one step farther, and conclude that all the pretended demonstrations for the infinite divisibility of extension are equally sophistical; since it is certain these demonstrations cannot be just without proving the impossibility of mathematical points; which it is an evident absurdity to pretend to.
These consequences can lead us to further conclude that all the so-called proofs for the infinite divisibility of space are equally misleading; since it’s clear that these proofs cannot be valid without also proving the impossibility of mathematical points, which is obviously absurd to claim.
SECT. III. OF THE OTHER QUALITIES OF OUR IDEA OF SPACE AND TIME.
No discovery could have been made more happily for deciding all controversies concerning ideas, than that abovementioned, that impressions always take the precedency of them, and that every idea, with which the imagination is furnished, first makes its appearance in a correspondent impression. These latter perceptions are all so clear and evident, that they admit of no controversy; though many of our ideas are so obscure, that it is almost impossible even for the mind, which forms them, to tell exactly their nature and composition. Let us apply this principle, in order to discover farther the nature of our ideas of space and time.
No discovery could have been happier for settling all debates about ideas than the one mentioned above, which states that impressions always come before ideas, and that every idea the imagination creates first appears as a related impression. These impressions are so clear and obvious that there's no room for debate; however, many of our ideas are so unclear that even the mind that creates them finds it nearly impossible to define their true nature and structure. Let's use this principle to further explore the nature of our ideas of space and time.
Upon opening my eyes, and turning them to the surrounding objects, I perceive many visible bodies; and upon shutting them again, and considering the distance betwixt these bodies, I acquire the idea of extension. As every idea is derived from some impression, which is exactly similar to it, the impressions similar to this idea of extension, must either be some sensations derived from the sight, or some internal impressions arising from these sensations.
When I open my eyes and look at the things around me, I see many objects; and when I close them again and think about the space between these objects, I get the idea of extension. Since every idea comes from some impression that is similar to it, the impressions related to this idea of extension must come from either sensations from sight or some internal impressions that arise from these sensations.
Our internal impressions are our passions, emotions, desires and aversions; none of which, I believe, will ever be asserted to be the model, from which the idea of space is derived. There remains therefore nothing but the senses, which can convey to us this original impression. Now what impression do oar senses here convey to us? This is the principal question, and decides without appeal concerning the nature of the idea.
Our internal feelings are our passions, emotions, desires, and dislikes; none of which, I believe, will ever be claimed as the standard from which the idea of space is formed. So, we are left with the senses, which can communicate to us this original impression. Now, what impression do our senses convey here? This is the main question and it ultimately determines the nature of the idea.
The table before me is alone sufficient by its view to give me the idea of extension. This idea, then, is borrowed from, and represents some impression, which this moment appears to the senses. But my senses convey to me only the impressions of coloured points, disposed in a certain manner. If the eye is sensible of any thing farther, I desire it may be pointed out to me. But if it be impossible to shew any thing farther, we may conclude with certainty, that the idea of extension is nothing but a copy of these coloured points, and of the manner of their appearance.
The table in front of me is enough on its own to give me the idea of extension. This idea is borrowed from, and represents, some impression that this moment provides to my senses. However, my senses only give me the impressions of colored points arranged in a certain way. If the eye perceives anything beyond that, I would like it to be pointed out to me. But if it's impossible to show anything more, we can confidently conclude that the idea of extension is just a copy of these colored points and how they appear.
Suppose that in the extended object, or composition of coloured points, from which we first received the idea of extension, the points were of a purple colour; it follows, that in every repetition of that idea we would not only place the points in the same order with respect to each other, but also bestow on them that precise colour, with which alone we are acquainted. But afterwards having experience of the other colours of violet, green, red, white, black, and of all the different compositions of these, and finding a resemblance in the disposition of coloured points, of which they are composed, we omit the peculiarities of colour, as far as possible, and found an abstract idea merely on that disposition of points, or manner of appearance, in which they agree. Nay even when the resemblance is carryed beyond the objects of one sense, and the impressions of touch are found to be Similar to those of sight in the disposition of their parts; this does not hinder the abstract idea from representing both, upon account of their resemblance. All abstract ideas are really nothing but particular ones, considered in a certain light; but being annexed to general terms, they are able to represent a vast variety, and to comprehend objects, which, as they are alike in some particulars, are in others vastly wide of each other.
Imagine that in an extended object, or a collection of colored points, from which we first got the idea of extension, the points were purple. It follows that in every time we repeat that idea, we wouldn’t just arrange the points in the same order relative to each other, but we’d also give them that exact color we recognize. But later, after experiencing other colors like violet, green, red, white, and black, along with all the combinations of these, and noticing similarities in the arrangement of the colored points they consist of, we start to overlook the specific colors as much as we can and form an abstract idea based solely on the arrangement of the points, or the way they appear together. Even when the similarities extend beyond just one sense, and we find that touch impressions are similar to visual impressions in how their parts are arranged, this doesn’t stop the abstract idea from representing both because of their resemblance. All abstract ideas are really just specific ones viewed in a certain way; however, when linked to general terms, they can represent a wide range and encompass objects that, while similar in some aspects, can be very different in others.
The idea of time, being derived from the succession of our perceptions of every kind, ideas as well as impressions, and impressions of reflection as well as of sensations will afford us an instance of an abstract idea, which comprehends a still greater variety than that of space, and yet is represented in the fancy by some particular individual idea of a determinate quantity and quality.
The concept of time, arising from the sequence of all our perceptions—both ideas and impressions, including reflections as well as sensations—provides an example of an abstract idea. This idea encompasses a wider range than that of space but is still illustrated in our minds by some specific individual idea of a defined quantity and quality.
As it is from the disposition of visible and tangible objects we receive the idea of space, so from the succession of ideas and impressions we form the idea of time, nor is it possible for time alone ever to make its appearance, or be taken notice of by the mind. A man in a sound sleep, or strongly occupyed with one thought, is insensible of time; and according as his perceptions succeed each other with greater or less rapidity, the same duration appears longer or shorter to his imagination. It has been remarked by a great philosopher, that our perceptions have certain bounds in this particular, which are fixed by the original nature and constitution of the mind, and beyond which no influence of external objects on the senses is ever able to hasten or retard our thought. If you wheel about a burning coal with rapidity, it will present to the senses an image of a circle of fire; nor will there seem to be any interval of time betwixt its revolutions; meerly because it is impossible for our perceptions to succeed each other with the same rapidity, that motion may be communicated to external objects. Wherever we have no successive perceptions, we have no notion of time, even though there be a real succession in the objects. From these phenomena, as well as from many others, we may conclude, that time cannot make its appearance to the mind, either alone, or attended with a steady unchangeable object, but is always discovered some PERCEIVABLE succession of changeable objects.
Just as we understand space through the arrangement of visible and tangible objects, we grasp the concept of time through the flow of ideas and impressions. Time cannot exist on its own or be noticed by the mind. When a person is in deep sleep or fully absorbed in a single thought, they lose track of time. Depending on how quickly or slowly their thoughts come to them, the same amount of time can feel longer or shorter. A great philosopher noted that our perceptions have certain limits defined by the nature and makeup of our minds, and nothing outside can speed up or slow down our thoughts beyond those limits. If you spin a burning coal quickly, it will create the illusion of a circle of fire, and it won’t seem like there's any gap of time between its spins, simply because our perceptions can’t keep pace with the speed of external motion. Where we lack successive perceptions, we have no sense of time, even if there is a real succession of events happening. From these observations, as well as many others, we can conclude that time cannot be perceived by the mind either on its own or alongside a steady, unchanging object; it is always recognized through some observable sequence of changing objects.
To confirm this we may add the following argument, which to me seems perfectly decisive and convincing. It is evident, that time or duration consists of different parts: For otherwise we could not conceive a longer or shorter duration. It is also evident, that these parts are not co-existent: For that quality of the co-existence of parts belongs to extension, and is what distinguishes it from duration. Now as time is composed of parts, that are not coexistent: an unchangeable object, since it produces none but coexistent impressions, produces none that can give us the idea of time; and consequently that idea must be derived from a succession of changeable objects, and time in its first appearance can never be severed from such a succession.
To confirm this, we can add the following argument, which I believe is completely convincing. It's clear that time or duration is made up of different parts; otherwise, we wouldn't be able to think of a longer or shorter duration. It's also clear that these parts don't exist at the same time; that characteristic of parts existing together is something that applies to space, and it's what sets it apart from duration. Since time is made up of parts that don't coexist, an unchanging object, which only creates impressions that exist at the same time, can't give us the idea of time. Therefore, that idea must come from a series of changing objects, and time, as we first experience it, can never be separated from that series.
Having therefore found, that time in its first appearance to the mind is always conjoined with a succession of changeable objects, and that otherwise it can never fall under our notice, we must now examine whether it can be conceived without our conceiving any succession of objects, and whether it can alone form a distinct idea in the imagination.
Having found that time, when it first appears in our minds, is always linked to a series of changing objects, and that it can never be noticed otherwise, we now need to explore whether it can be understood without imagining any sequence of objects, and whether it can create a clear idea in our imagination on its own.
In order to know whether any objects, which are joined in impression, be inseparable in idea, we need only consider, if they be different from each other; in which case, it is plain they may be conceived apart. Every thing, that is different is distinguishable: and everything, that is distinguishable, may be separated, according to the maxims above-explained. If on the contrary they be not different, they are not distinguishable: and if they be not distinguishable, they cannot be separated. But this is precisely the case with respect to time, compared with our successive perceptions. The idea of time is not derived from a particular impression mixed up with others, and plainly distinguishable from them; but arises altogether from the manner, in which impressions appear to the mind, without making one of the number. Five notes played on a flute give us the impression and idea of time; though time be not a sixth impression, which presents itself to the hearing or any other of the senses. Nor is it a sixth impression, which the mind by reflection finds in itself. These five sounds making their appearance in this particular manner, excite no emotion in the mind, nor produce an affection of any kind, which being observed by it can give rise to a new idea. For that is necessary to produce a new idea of reflection, nor can the mind, by revolving over a thousand times all its ideas of sensation, ever extract from them any new original idea, unless nature has so framed its faculties, that it feels some new original impression arise from such a contemplation. But here it only takes notice of the manner, in which the different sounds make their appearance; and that it may afterwards consider without considering these particular sounds, but may conjoin it with any other objects. The ideas of some objects it certainly must have, nor is it possible for it without these ideas ever to arrive at any conception of time; which since it, appears not as any primary distinct impression, can plainly be nothing but different ideas, or impressions, or objects disposed in a certain manner, that is, succeeding each other.
To determine if objects that are linked in perception are inseparable in thought, we just need to think about whether they are different from each other. If they are different, it’s clear they can be imagined separately. Anything that is different can be distinguished, and everything that can be distinguished can be separated, based on the principles explained earlier. However, if they are not different, they cannot be distinguished, and if they cannot be distinguished, they cannot be separated. This applies specifically to time in relation to our successive perceptions. The concept of time doesn’t come from a specific impression mixed with others that is clearly distinguishable; rather, it arises entirely from the way impressions appear to the mind, without being one of those impressions. When five notes are played on a flute, they give us the impression and idea of time, even though time is not a sixth impression that is presented to our hearing or any other senses. Nor is it a sixth impression that the mind finds through reflection. These five sounds appearing in this specific way do not stir any emotions in the mind, nor do they create any feelings that could lead to a new idea. For a new idea to arise through reflection is necessary, and the mind cannot, no matter how many times it revisits its sensory ideas, draw out any new original idea unless nature has designed its faculties to evoke a new original impression from that contemplation. Instead, the mind simply notes how these different sounds present themselves, so it can later consider this without focusing on those particular sounds, but rather combine it with other objects. It certainly must have ideas of some objects, and without those ideas, it cannot form any concept of time, which, since it doesn’t appear as any primary distinct impression, is clearly just different ideas, impressions, or objects arranged in a certain way, that is, occurring in succession.
I know there are some who pretend, that the idea of duration is applicable in a proper sense to objects, which are perfectly unchangeable; and this I take to be the common opinion of philosophers as well as of the vulgar. But to be convinced of its falsehood we need but reflect on the foregoing conclusion, that the idea of duration is always derived from a succession of changeable objects, and can never be conveyed to the mind by any thing stedfast and unchangeable. For it inevitably follows from thence, that since the idea of duration cannot be derived from such an object, it can never-in any propriety or exactness be applied to it, nor can any thing unchangeable be ever said to have duration. Ideas always represent the Objects or impressions, from which they are derived, and can never without a fiction represent or be applied to any other. By what fiction we apply the idea of time, even to what is unchangeable, and suppose, as is common, that duration is a measure of rest as well as of motion, we shall consider afterwards.[3]
I know there are some who pretend that the concept of duration applies in a true sense to objects that are completely unchangeable; I believe this is the common view of both philosophers and the general public. However, to understand why this is false, we just need to reflect on the previous conclusion that the idea of duration is always based on a series of changing objects, and cannot be conveyed to the mind by anything steady and unchangeable. It follows that since the idea of duration cannot come from such an object, it can never be properly or accurately applied to it, nor can anything unchangeable truly be said to have duration. Ideas always represent the objects or impressions from which they come and can never, without some fiction, represent or be applied to anything else. The fiction by which we apply the idea of time to what is unchangeable and assume, as is common, that duration measures both rest and motion will be discussed later. [3]
[3] Sect 5.
There is another very decisive argument, which establishes the present doctrine concerning our ideas of space and time, and is founded only on that simple principle, that our ideas of them are compounded of parts, which are indivisible. This argument may be worth the examining.
There’s another strong argument that supports the current understanding of our concepts of space and time, based solely on the simple principle that our ideas about them are made up of parts that cannot be divided. This argument is worth looking into.
Every idea, that is distinguishable, being also separable, let us take one of those simple indivisible ideas, of which the compound one of extension is formed, and separating it from all others, and considering it apart, let us form a judgment of its nature and qualities.
Every distinct idea can be separated, so let's take one of those simple, indivisible ideas that make up the complex idea of extension. By isolating it from all others and examining it on its own, we can make a judgment about its nature and qualities.
It is plain it is not the idea of extension. For the idea of extension consists of parts; and this idea, according to the supposition, is perfectly simple and indivisible. Is it therefore nothing? That is absolutely impossible. For as the compound idea of extension, which is real, is composed of such ideas; were these so many non-entities, there would be a real existence composed of non-entities; which is absurd. Here therefore I must ask, What is our idea of a simple and indivisible point? No wonder if my answer appear somewhat new, since the question itself has scarce ever yet been thought of. We are wont to dispute concerning the nature of mathematical points, but seldom concerning the nature of their ideas.
It's clear that the concept of extension isn't about that. The idea of extension is made up of parts, yet this idea, as assumed, is completely simple and indivisible. So, is it nothing? That’s definitely impossible. Because the real concept of extension, which is compound, is made up of such ideas; if these were merely non-entities, then we would have a real existence made up of non-entities, which is ridiculous. So, I must ask, what do we mean by a simple and indivisible point? It's no surprise if my answer seems a bit new since the question itself has rarely been considered. We often argue about the nature of mathematical points but seldom about the nature of their ideas.
The idea of space is conveyed to the mind by two senses, the sight and touch; nor does anything ever appear extended, that is not either visible or tangible. That compound impression, which represents extension, consists of several lesser impressions, that are indivisible to the eye or feeling, and may be called impressions of atoms or corpuscles endowed with colour and solidity. But this is not all. It is not only requisite, that these atoms should be coloured or tangible, in order to discover themselves to our senses; it is also necessary we should preserve the idea of their colour or tangibility in order to comprehend them by our imagination. There is nothing but the idea of their colour or tangibility, which can render them conceivable by the mind. Upon the removal of the ideas of these sensible qualities, they are utterly annihilated to the thought or imagination.
The concept of space is communicated to us through two senses: sight and touch. Nothing appears to be extended unless it is either visible or tangible. This combined impression that represents extension is made up of several smaller impressions that can't be divided further by our eyes or touch, which we can think of as impressions of small particles or atoms that have color and solidity. But that’s not all. It's not enough for these atoms to simply have color or be tangible for us to detect them with our senses; we also need to keep in mind their color or tangibility to understand them in our imagination. The only thing that makes them understandable to the mind is the idea of their color or tangibility. If we remove these ideas of sensory qualities, they become completely nonexistent in thought or imagination.
Now such as the parts are, such is the whole. If a point be not considered as coloured or tangible, it can convey to us no idea; and consequently the idea of extension, which is composed of the ideas of these points, can never possibly exist. But if the idea of extension really can exist, as we are conscious it does, its parts must also exist; and in order to that, must be considered as coloured or tangible. We have therefore no idea of space or extension, but when we regard it as an object either of our sight or feeling.
Now, just as the individual parts are, so is the whole. If a point isn’t seen as colored or tangible, it doesn't give us any idea; and therefore, the idea of extension, which comes from these points, can't possibly exist. However, if the idea of extension can really exist, as we are aware it does, its parts must also exist and must be considered as colored or tangible. So, we only have a concept of space or extension when we view it as something we can see or feel.
The same reasoning will prove, that the indivisible moments of time must be filled with some real object or existence, whose succession forms the duration, and makes it be conceivable by the mind.
The same reasoning will show that the indivisible moments of time must be occupied by some real object or existence, whose sequence creates duration and makes it understandable to the mind.
SECT. IV. OBJECTIONS ANSWERED.
Our system concerning space and time consists of two parts, which are intimately connected together. The first depends on this chain of reasoning. The capacity of the mind is not infinite; consequently no idea of extension or duration consists of an infinite number of parts or inferior ideas, but of a finite number, and these simple and indivisible: It is therefore possible for space and time to exist conformable to this idea: And if it be possible, it is certain they actually do exist conformable to it; since their infinite divisibility is utterly impossible and contradictory.
Our understanding of space and time is made up of two parts that are closely linked. The first part rests on this line of reasoning. The capacity of the mind isn’t limitless; therefore, no idea of space or duration is made up of an infinite number of pieces or smaller ideas, but rather a finite number, and these are simple and indivisible. It is possible for space and time to exist in line with this idea: and if it’s possible, then it’s certain they actually do exist in this way; because their infinite divisibility is completely impossible and contradictory.
The other part of our system is a consequence of this. The parts, into which the ideas of space and time resolve themselves, become at last indivisible; and these indivisible parts, being nothing in themselves, are inconceivable when not filled with something real and existent. The ideas of space and time are therefore no separate or distinct ideas, but merely those of the manner or order, in which objects exist: Or in other words, it is impossible to conceive either a vacuum and extension without matter, or a time, when there was no succession or change in any real existence. The intimate connexion betwixt these parts of our system is the reason why we shall examine together the objections, which have been urged against both of them, beginning with those against the finite divisibility of extension.
The other part of our system is a result of this. The components, into which the concepts of space and time break down, ultimately become indivisible; and these indivisible components, being nothing on their own, are unimaginable without something real and existent to fill them. Thus, the concepts of space and time are not separate or distinct ideas but simply represent the way or order in which objects exist. In other words, it's impossible to imagine a vacuum and extension without matter, or a time when there was no succession or change in any real existence. The close connection between these parts of our system is why we will look at the objections raised against both of them together, starting with those against the finite divisibility of extension.
I. The first of these objections, which I shall take notice of, is more proper to prove this connexion and dependence of the one part upon the other, than to destroy either of them. It has often been maintained in the schools, that extension must be divisible, in infinitum, because the system of mathematical points is absurd; and that system is absurd, because a mathematical point is a non-entity, and consequently can never by its conjunction with others form a real existence. This would be perfectly decisive, were there no medium betwixt the infinite divisibility of matter, and the non-entity of mathematical points. But there is evidently a medium, viz. the bestowing a colour or solidity on these points; and the absurdity of both the extremes is a demonstration of the truth and reality of this medium. The system of physical points, which is another medium, is too absurd to need a refutation. A real extension, such as a physical point is supposed to be, can never exist without parts, different from each other; and wherever objects are different, they are distinguishable and separable by the imagination.
I. The first objection I want to address actually supports the idea that one part depends on the other instead of disproving them. It's often claimed in academic circles that extension must be infinitely divisible because the idea of mathematical points is nonsense. This idea is nonsensical because a mathematical point is not real and therefore can't combine with others to create something that truly exists. This would be completely convincing if there wasn't something in between the infinite divisibility of matter and the non-existence of mathematical points. But there clearly is something in between, namely, giving these points color or solidity; the absurdity of both extremes proves the truth and reality of this middle ground. The concept of physical points, which represents another middle ground, is too absurd to even require an argument against it. A real extension, like a physical point is thought to be, can never exist without parts that are different from one another; and whenever objects are different, they can be distinguished and separated in our imagination.
II. The second objection is derived from the necessity there would be of PENETRATION, if extension consisted of mathematical points. A simple and indivisible atom, that touches another, must necessarily penetrate it; for it is impossible it can touch it by its external parts, from the very supposition of its perfect simplicity, which excludes all parts. It must therefore touch it intimately, and in its whole essence, SECUNDUM SE, TOTA, ET TOTALITER; which is the very definition of penetration. But penetration is impossible: Mathematical points are of consequence equally impossible.
II. The second objection is based on the necessity of PENETRATION if extension were made up of mathematical points. A simple and indivisible atom that touches another must necessarily penetrate it; it’s impossible for it to touch through its outer parts, given the assumption of its perfect simplicity, which excludes any parts. Therefore, it must touch it intimately and completely, SECUNDUM SE, TOTA, ET TOTALITER; which is the very definition of penetration. But penetration is impossible; therefore, mathematical points are equally impossible.
I answer this objection by substituting a juster idea of penetration. Suppose two bodies containing no void within their circumference, to approach each other, and to unite in such a manner that the body, which results from their union, is no more extended than either of them; it is this we must mean when we talk of penetration. But it is evident this penetration is nothing but the annihilation of one of these bodies, and the preservation of the other, without our being able to distinguish particularly which is preserved and which annihilated. Before the approach we have the idea of two bodies. After it we have the idea only of one. It is impossible for the mind to preserve any notion of difference betwixt two bodies of the same nature existing in the same place at the same time.
I respond to this objection by offering a more accurate idea of penetration. Imagine two bodies that have no empty space within their boundaries, coming close to each other and merging in such a way that the resulting body is no larger than either of them. This is what we mean when we refer to penetration. However, it's clear that this kind of penetration is simply the destruction of one of these bodies and the continuation of the other, without us being able to specifically identify which one is preserved and which one is destroyed. Before they come together, we have the idea of two bodies. After they unite, we only have the idea of one. It's impossible for the mind to maintain any notion of difference between two bodies of the same kind existing in the same place at the same time.
Taking then penetration in this sense, for the annihilation of one body upon its approach to another, I ask any one, if he sees a necessity, that a coloured or tangible point should be annihilated upon the approach of another coloured or tangible point? On the contrary, does he not evidently perceive, that from the union of these points there results an object, which is compounded and divisible, and may be distinguished into two parts, of which each preserves its existence distinct and separate, notwithstanding its contiguity to the other? Let him aid his fancy by conceiving these points to be of different colours, the better to prevent their coalition and confusion. A blue and a red point may surely lie contiguous without any penetration or annihilation. For if they cannot, what possibly can become of them? Whether shall the red or the blue be annihilated? Or if these colours unite into one, what new colour will they produce by their union?
Taking penetration in this way, as the destruction of one object when it comes close to another, I ask anyone if they see any reason that a colored or tangible point should be destroyed when approaching another colored or tangible point? On the contrary, don't they clearly see that when these points come together, they form an object that is complex and can be divided, with each part maintaining its own existence distinct and separate, despite being next to the other? Let’s use our imagination and think of these points as different colors to better illustrate their separation and avoid confusion. A blue point and a red point can certainly sit next to each other without any penetration or destruction. Because if they can’t, what can possibly happen to them? Will the red or the blue be destroyed? Or if these colors merge into one, what new color will result from their union?
What chiefly gives rise to these objections, and at the same time renders it so difficult to give a satisfactory answer to them, is the natural infirmity and unsteadiness both of our imagination and senses, when employed on such minute objects. Put a spot of ink upon paper, and retire to such a distance, that the spot becomes altogether invisible; you will find, that upon your return and nearer approach the spot first becomes visible by short intervals; and afterwards becomes always visible; and afterwards acquires only a new force in its colouring without augmenting its bulk; and afterwards, when it has encreased to such a degree as to be really extended, it is still difficult for the imagination to break it into its component parts, because of the uneasiness it finds in the conception of such a minute object as a single point. This infirmity affects most of our reasonings on the present subject, and makes it almost impossible to answer in an intelligible manner, and in proper expressions, many questions which may arise concerning it.
What mainly causes these objections, and at the same time makes it hard to provide a clear answer, is the natural weakness and inconsistency of both our imagination and senses when dealing with such tiny details. If you put a spot of ink on paper and step back until the spot is completely invisible, you’ll notice that when you come back closer, the spot first appears in brief flashes; then it becomes continuously visible, gaining intensity in its color without getting bigger; and later, once it has expanded enough to be clearly seen, it's still challenging for the imagination to break it down into its smaller parts because it's hard to conceive something as tiny as a single point. This weakness impacts much of our reasoning on this topic and makes it nearly impossible to respond clearly and appropriately to many questions that may come up about it.
III. There have been many objections drawn from the mathematics against the indivisibility of the parts of extension: though at first sight that science seems rather favourable to the present doctrine; and if it be contrary in its DEMONSTRATIONS, it is perfectly conformable in its definitions. My present business then must be to defend the definitions, and refute the demonstrations.
III. There have been many objections raised from mathematics against the idea that parts of extension are indivisible: although at first glance, that field seems somewhat supportive of the current theory; and if it contradicts in its PROOFS, it aligns perfectly in its definitions. My current task, then, is to defend the definitions and counter the proofs.
A surface is DEFINed to be length and breadth without depth: A line to be length without breadth or depth: A point to be what has neither length, breadth nor depth. It is evident that all this is perfectly unintelligible upon any other supposition than that of the composition of extension by indivisible points or atoms. How else could any thing exist without length, without breadth, or without depth?
A surface is defined as having length and width but no depth; a line is length without width or depth; a point is something that has no length, width, or depth. It’s clear that all of this is completely incomprehensible under any assumption other than that extension is made up of indivisible points or atoms. How else could anything exist without length, width, or depth?
Two different answers, I find, have been made to this argument; neither of which is in my opinion satisfactory. The first is, that the objects of geometry, those surfaces, lines and points, whose proportions and positions it examines, are mere ideas in the mind; and not only never did, but never can exist in nature. They never did exist; for no one will pretend to draw a line or make a surface entirely conformable to the definition: They never can exist; for we may produce demonstrations from these very ideas to prove, that they are impossible.
I find that there are two different answers to this argument, and neither of them is satisfactory, in my opinion. The first answer is that the objects of geometry—those surfaces, lines, and points whose proportions and positions it studies—are just ideas in the mind and never actually existed in nature. They never did exist because no one can claim to draw a line or create a surface that completely matches the definition. They also can’t exist because we can use these very ideas to demonstrate that they are impossible.
But can anything be imagined more absurd and contradictory than this reasoning? Whatever can be conceived by a clear and distinct idea necessarily implies the possibility of existence; and he who pretends to prove the impossibility of its existence by any argument derived from the clear idea, in reality asserts, that we have no clear idea of it, because we have a clear idea. It is in vain to search for a contradiction in any thing that is distinctly conceived by the mind. Did it imply any contradiction, it is impossible it could ever be conceived.
But can anything be more absurd and contradictory than this reasoning? Anything that can be understood through a clear and distinct idea necessarily suggests the possibility of its existence; and anyone who claims to prove that it cannot exist using an argument based on that clear idea is actually saying that we don't have a clear idea of it, precisely because we do have a clear idea. It's pointless to look for a contradiction in anything that is clearly conceived by the mind. If it did imply some contradiction, it could never be conceived at all.
There is therefore no medium betwixt allowing at least the possibility of indivisible points, and denying their idea; and it is on this latter principle, that the second answer to the foregoing argument is founded. It has been[4] pretended, that though it be impossible to conceive a length without any breadth, yet by an abstraction without a separation, we can consider the one without regarding the other; in the same manner as we may think of the length of the way betwixt two towns, and overlook its breadth. The length is inseparable from the breadth both in nature and in our minds; but this excludes not a partial consideration, and a distinction of reason, after the manner above explained.
There is no middle ground between accepting the possibility of indivisible points and denying their concept; and it is on this latter principle that the second response to the previous argument is based. It has been pretended that although it's impossible to imagine a length without any width, we can abstractly consider one without focusing on the other. This is similar to how we might think about the distance between two towns while ignoring its width. Length is inseparable from width in both nature and in our thoughts; however, this doesn't prevent us from considering them separately or distinguishing between them in a reasoned way, as explained above.
[4] L'Art de penser.
The Art of Thinking.
In refuting this answer I shall not insist on the argument, which I have already sufficiently explained, that if it be impossible for the mind to arrive at a minimum in its ideas, its capacity must be infinite, in order to comprehend the infinite number of parts, of which its idea of any extension would be composed. I shall here endeavour to find some new absurdities in this reasoning.
In arguing against this answer, I won't repeat the point I've already made that if the mind can't reach a minimum in its ideas, then its capacity has to be infinite to understand the endless number of parts that make up its idea of any extension. Instead, I'll try to identify some new flaws in this reasoning.
A surface terminates a solid; a line terminates a surface; a point terminates a line; but I assert, that if the ideas of a point, line or surface were not indivisible, it is impossible we should ever conceive these terminations: For let these ideas be supposed infinitely divisible; and then let the fancy endeavour to fix itself on the idea of the last surface, line or point; it immediately finds this idea to break into parts; and upon its seizing the last of these parts, it loses its hold by a new division, and so on in infinitum, without any possibility of its arriving at a concluding idea. The number of fractions bring it no nearer the last division, than the first idea it formed. Every particle eludes the grasp by a new fraction; like quicksilver, when we endeavour to seize it. But as in fact there must be something, which terminates the idea of every finite quantity; and as this terminating idea cannot itself consist of parts or inferior ideas; otherwise it would be the last of its parts, which finished the idea, and so on; this is a clear proof, that the ideas of surfaces, lines and points admit not of any division; those of surfaces in depth; of lines in breadth and depth; and of points in any dimension.
A surface defines a solid; a line defines a surface; a point defines a line; but I argue that if the concepts of a point, line, or surface were not indivisible, we would never be able to grasp these definitions. Imagine these concepts were infinitely divisible; then when trying to focus on the idea of the final surface, line, or point, you'd quickly find that this idea breaks into parts. As soon as you try to hold onto the last part, it slips away due to further division, and this goes on infinitely, making it impossible to reach a final idea. The number of fractions doesn’t bring you any closer to that last division than the first idea you formed. Every piece escapes your grasp with another division, just like trying to catch mercury. But since there must be something that defines the idea of every finite quantity, and this defining idea can't consist of parts or lesser ideas—otherwise, it would simply be the last of its parts that completes the idea, and so on—this clearly shows that the concepts of surfaces, lines, and points cannot be divided. Surfaces have depth; lines have breadth and depth; and points have no dimension.
The school were so sensible of the force of this argument, that some of them maintained, that nature has mixed among those particles of matter, which are divisible in infinitum, a number of mathematical points, in order to give a termination to bodies; and others eluded the force of this reasoning by a heap of unintelligible cavils and distinctions. Both these adversaries equally yield the victory. A man who hides himself, confesses as evidently the superiority of his enemy, as another, who fairly delivers his arms.
The school recognized the strength of this argument so much that some argued that nature has mixed in a number of mathematical points among those particles of matter, which can be divided endlessly, to give bodies a limit. Others tried to counter this reasoning with a bunch of confusing objections and distinctions. Both sides ultimately lose the debate. A person who hides concedes just as clearly to their opponent's superiority as someone who openly surrenders their weapons.
Thus it appears, that the definitions of mathematics destroy the pretended demonstrations; and that if we have the idea of indivisible points, lines and surfaces conformable to the definition, their existence is certainly possible: but if we have no such idea, it is impossible we can ever conceive the termination of any figure; without which conception there can be no geometrical demonstration.
It seems that the definitions of mathematics undermine the supposed proofs; and if we have a clear idea of indivisible points, lines, and surfaces that match the definition, their existence is indeed possible. However, if we lack such an idea, we can never truly grasp the end of any shape; without this understanding, there can be no geometric proof.
But I go farther, and maintain, that none of these demonstrations can have sufficient weight to establish such a principle, as this of infinite divisibility; and that because with regard to such minute objects, they are not properly demonstrations, being built on ideas, which are not exact, and maxims, which are not precisely true. When geometry decides anything concerning the proportions of quantity, we ought not to look for the utmost precision and exactness. None of its proofs extend so far. It takes the dimensions and proportions of figures justly; but roughly, and with some liberty. Its errors are never considerable; nor would it err at all, did it not aspire to such an absolute perfection.
But I go further and argue that none of these arguments can provide enough support to establish the principle of infinite divisibility. This is because, when it comes to such tiny objects, they aren't really arguments at all; they're based on ideas that aren't precise and assumptions that aren't completely true. When geometry makes decisions about the proportions of quantities, we shouldn't expect the highest level of precision and accuracy. None of its proofs reach that level. Geometry accurately considers the dimensions and proportions of shapes, but does so in a general way and with some flexibility. Its mistakes are never significant, nor would it make any mistakes at all if it didn't aim for such absolute perfection.
I first ask mathematicians, what they mean when they say one line or surface is EQUAL to, or GREATER or LESS than another? Let any of them give an answer, to whatever sect he belongs, and whether he maintains the composition of extension by indivisible points, or by quantities divisible in infinitum. This question will embarrass both of them.
I first ask mathematicians what they mean when they say one line or surface is EQUAL to, GREATER than, or LESS than another. Let any of them provide an answer, regardless of their school of thought, whether they believe that extension is made up of indivisible points or of quantities that can be divided infinitely. This question will confuse both sides.
There are few or no mathematicians, who defend the hypothesis of indivisible points; and yet these have the readiest and justest answer to the present question. They need only reply, that lines or surfaces are equal, when the numbers of points in each are equal; and that as the proportion of the numbers varies, the proportion of the lines and surfaces is also varyed. But though this answer be just, as well as obvious; yet I may affirm, that this standard of equality is entirely useless, and that it never is from such a comparison we determine objects to be equal or unequal with respect to each other. For as the points, which enter into the composition of any line or surface, whether perceived by the sight or touch, are so minute and so confounded with each other, that it is utterly impossible for the mind to compute their number, such a computation will Never afford us a standard by which we may judge of proportions. No one will ever be able to determine by an exact numeration, that an inch has fewer points than a foot, or a foot fewer than an ell or any greater measure: for which reason we seldom or never consider this as the standard of equality or inequality.
There are very few, if any, mathematicians who support the idea of indivisible points; yet they have the simplest and most accurate answer to the current question. They just need to say that lines or surfaces are considered equal when the number of points in each is the same, and that as the ratio of the numbers changes, so does the ratio of the lines and surfaces. But even though this answer is correct and straightforward, I can confidently say that this measure of equality is completely useless, and we never determine objects to be equal or unequal based on this comparison. Since the points that make up any line or surface, whether seen or felt, are so tiny and so intertwined with each other, it’s completely impossible for the mind to count them. This kind of counting will never give us a standard to judge proportions. No one can ever accurately count that an inch has fewer points than a foot, or that a foot has fewer points than an ell or any larger measure, which is why we rarely, if ever, consider this as the measure of equality or inequality.
As to those, who imagine, that extension is divisible in infinitum, it is impossible they can make use of this answer, or fix the equality of any line or surface by a numeration of its component parts. For since, according to their hypothesis, the least as well as greatest figures contain an infinite number of parts; and since infinite numbers, properly speaking, can neither be equal nor unequal with respect to each other; the equality or inequality of any portions of space can never depend on any proportion in the number of their parts. It is true, it may be said, that the inequality of an ell and a yard consists in the different numbers of the feet, of which they are composed; and that of a foot and a yard in the number of the inches. But as that quantity we call an inch in the one is supposed equal to what we call an inch in the other, and as it is impossible for the mind to find this equality by proceeding in infinitum with these references to inferior quantities: it is evident, that at last we must fix some standard of equality different from an enumeration of the parts.
For those who think that extension can be divided infinitely, it's impossible for them to use this explanation or determine the equality of any line or surface by counting its parts. According to their idea, both the smallest and largest shapes contain an infinite number of parts; and since infinite numbers can't be equal or unequal to each other, the equality or inequality of any sections of space can never depend on how many parts they have. It's true that one could argue that the difference between an ell and a yard lies in the number of feet that make them up, and that the difference between a foot and a yard lies in the number of inches. But since the quantity we call an inch in one measurement is assumed to be equal to an inch in the other, and since it’s impossible to establish this equality by endlessly referring to smaller quantities, it's clear that ultimately, we need to establish some standard of equality that isn't just about counting the parts.
There are some[5], who pretend, that equality is best defined by congruity, and that any two figures are equal, when upon the placing of one upon the other, all their parts correspond to and touch each other. In order to judge of this definition let us consider, that since equality is a relation, it is not, strictly speaking, a property in the figures themselves, but arises merely from the comparison, which the mind makes betwixt them. If it consists, therefore, in this imaginary application and mutual contact of parts, we must at least have a distinct notion of these parts, and must conceive their contact. Now it is plain, that in this conception we would run up these parts to the greatest minuteness, which can possibly be conceived; since the contact of large parts would never render the figures equal. But the minutest parts we can conceive are mathematical points; and consequently this standard of equality is the same with that derived from the equality of the number of points; which we have already determined to be a just but an useless standard. We must therefore look to some other quarter for a solution of the present difficulty.
There are some[5], who pretend that equality is best defined by how closely two shapes match, claiming that two figures are equal when, if one is placed on top of the other, all their parts align and touch each other. To evaluate this definition, we should consider that since equality is a relationship, it isn’t strictly a characteristic of the figures themselves, but arises simply from the comparison our minds make between them. If equality relies on this imagined application and mutual contact of parts, we must at least have a clear idea of what these parts are and envision their contact. It’s clear that in this mental picture, we would break down these parts to their tiniest detail, because just having large parts in contact would never make the figures equal. However, the smallest parts we can think of are mathematical points; therefore, this standard of equality is the same as the one based on having the same number of points, which we have already determined to be accurate yet impractical. We must seek another approach to solve the current problem.
There are many philosophers, who refuse to assign any standard of equality, but assert, that it is sufficient to present two objects, that are equal, in order to give us a just notion of this proportion. All definitions, say they, are fruitless, without the perception of such objects; and where we perceive such objects, we no longer stand in need of any definition. To this reasoning, I entirely agree; and assert, that the only useful notion of equality, or inequality, is derived from the whole united appearance and the comparison of particular objects.
Many philosophers refuse to establish any standard of equality and claim that it's enough to show two equal objects to give us a clear understanding of this concept. They argue that all definitions are pointless without the experience of such objects; and where we can observe these objects, we don't need any definitions at all. I completely agree with this reasoning and believe that the only meaningful understanding of equality or inequality comes from the overall comparison and collective appearance of specific objects.
It is evident, that the eye, or rather the mind is often able at one view to determine the proportions of bodies, and pronounce them equal to, or greater or less than each other, without examining or comparing the number of their minute parts. Such judgments are not only common, but in many cases certain and infallible. When the measure of a yard and that of a foot are presented, the mind can no more question, that the first is longer than the second, than it can doubt of those principles, which are the most clear and self-evident.
It's clear that our eyes, or more accurately our minds, can often quickly assess the sizes of objects and determine if they are equal, larger, or smaller than one another without needing to analyze or compare their tiny components. These kinds of judgments are not only frequent but, in many situations, accurate and unquestionable. When faced with a yard and a foot, the mind has no reason to doubt that the yard is longer than the foot, just as it wouldn't question those principles that are most obvious and self-evident.
There are therefore three proportions, which the mind distinguishes in the general appearance of its objects, and calls by the names of greater, less and equal. But though its decisions concerning these proportions be sometimes infallible, they are not always so; nor are our judgments of this kind more exempt from doubt and error than those on any other subject. We frequently correct our first opinion by a review and reflection; and pronounce those objects to be equal, which at first we esteemed unequal; and regard an object as less, though before it appeared greater than another. Nor is this the only correction, which these judgments of our senses undergo; but we often discover our error by a juxtaposition of the objects; or where that is impracticable, by the use of some common and invariable measure, which being successively applied to each, informs us of their different proportions. And even this correction is susceptible of a new correction, and of different degrees of exactness, according to the nature of the instrument, by which we measure the bodies, and the care which we employ in the comparison.
There are three proportions that the mind recognizes in the overall appearance of objects, referring to them as greater, less, and equal. While our judgments about these proportions are sometimes spot-on, they're not always reliable; our assessments in this area can be just as prone to doubt and error as in any other field. We often revise our initial opinions through review and reflection, declaring objects to be equal that we first thought were unequal, and considering an object to be less, even if we previously viewed it as greater than another. This isn't the only way our sensory judgments are corrected; we frequently notice our mistakes by comparing the objects side by side, or when that's not possible, by using a common standard measure that we apply to each object to reveal their different proportions. Even this type of correction can be further refined and vary in accuracy, depending on the nature of the measuring tool we use and the care we take in making the comparison.
When therefore the mind is accustomed to these judgments and their corrections, and finds that the same proportion which makes two figures have in the eye that appearance, which we call equality, makes them also correspond to each other, and to any common measure, with which they are compared, we form a mixed notion of equality derived both from the looser and stricter methods of comparison. But we are not content with this. For as sound reason convinces us that there are bodies vastly more minute than those, which appear to the senses; and as a false reason would perswade us, that there are bodies infinitely more minute; we clearly perceive, that we are not possessed of any instrument or art of measuring, which can secure us from ill error and uncertainty. We are sensible, that the addition or removal of one of these minute parts, is not discernible either in the appearance or measuring; and as we imagine, that two figures, which were equal before, cannot be equal after this removal or addition, we therefore suppose some imaginary standard of equality, by which the appearances and measuring are exactly corrected, and the figures reduced entirely to that proportion. This standard is plainly imaginary. For as the very idea of equality is that of such a particular appearance corrected by juxtaposition or a common measure. The notion of any correction beyond what we have instruments and art to make, is a mere fiction of the mind, and useless as well as incomprehensible. But though this standard be only imaginary, the fiction however is very natural; nor is anything more usual, than for the mind to proceed after this manner with any action, even after the reason has ceased, which first determined it to begin. This appears very conspicuously with regard to time; where though it is evident we have no exact method of determining the proportions of parts, not even so exact as in extension, yet the various corrections of our measures, and their different degrees of exactness, have given as an obscure and implicit notion of a perfect and entire equality. The case is the same in many other subjects. A musician finding his ear becoming every day more delicate, and correcting himself by reflection and attention, proceeds with the same act of the mind, even when the subject fails him, and entertains a notion of a compleat TIERCE or OCTAVE, without being able to tell whence he derives his standard. A painter forms the same fiction with regard to colours. A mechanic with regard to motion. To the one light and shade; to the other swift and slow are imagined to be capable of an exact comparison and equality beyond the judgments of the senses.
When the mind gets used to these judgments and their corrections, and sees that the same proportion that makes two shapes appear equal also makes them correspond to each other and to any common measure they're compared against, we create a mixed idea of equality based on both loose and strict methods of comparison. But we're not satisfied with this. For just as sound reasoning shows us that there are objects much smaller than what we can perceive, a false rationale might convince us that there are objects infinitely smaller. We clearly see that we don't have any tools or methods of measurement that can protect us from significant errors and uncertainties. We realize that adding or removing one of these tiny parts isn’t noticeable either in appearance or measurement; and when we think that two shapes, which were equal before, can no longer be equal after this addition or removal, we then assume some imaginary standard of equality by which the appearances and measurements are perfectly corrected, bringing the shapes entirely into that proportion. This standard is obviously imaginary. The very idea of equality relies on such a specific appearance corrected by side-by-side comparison or a common measure. The notion of any correction beyond what our tools and methods can achieve is merely a mental fiction and is both useless and incomprehensible. However, even though this standard is purely imaginary, the fiction is quite natural; it's common for the mind to function this way concerning any action, even after the reasoning that initially prompted it has ceased. This is especially evident with time; although it's clear we have no precise way of determining proportions of parts, not even as precise as with extension, the various corrections to our measurements and their different levels of precision have given us an unclear and implicit notion of perfect and complete equality. The same goes for many other areas. A musician finds his ear becoming increasingly refined, correcting himself through reflection and attention, continues the same mental process even when he loses the subject, and holds onto an idea of a complete TIERCE or OCTAVE without being able to pinpoint where his standard comes from. A painter creates a similar fiction regarding colors, while a mechanic does the same regarding motion. For one, light and shade; for the other, fast and slow are imagined to allow for an exact comparison and equality beyond sensory judgments.
We may apply the same reasoning to CURVE and RIGHT lines. Nothing is more apparent to the senses, than the distinction betwixt a curve and a right line; nor are there any ideas we more easily form than the ideas of these objects. But however easily we may form these ideas, it is impossible to produce any definition of them, which will fix the precise boundaries betwixt them. When we draw lines upon paper, or any continued surface, there is a certain order, by which the lines run along from one point to another, that they may produce the entire impression of a curve or right line; but this order is perfectly unknown, and nothing is observed but the united appearance. Thus even upon the system of indivisible points, we can only form a distant notion of some unknown standard to these objects. Upon that of infinite divisibility we cannot go even this length; but are reduced meerly to the general appearance, as the rule by which we determine lines to be either curve or right ones. But though we can give no perfect definition of these lines, nor produce any very exact method of distinguishing the one from the other; yet this hinders us not from correcting the first appearance by a more accurate consideration, and by a comparison with some rule, of whose rectitude from repeated trials we have a greater assurance. And it is from these corrections, and by carrying on the same action of the mind, even when its reason fails us, that we form the loose idea of a perfect standard to these figures, without being able to explain or comprehend it.
We can use the same reasoning for CURVES and STRAIGHT lines. Nothing is clearer to our senses than the difference between a curve and a straight line; nor are there any concepts we find easier to understand than these. However, even though we can easily form these ideas, it's impossible to come up with a definition that clearly defines the exact boundaries between them. When we draw lines on paper or any continuous surface, there's a specific way in which the lines connect one point to another, creating the complete impression of either a curve or a straight line; but this method remains entirely unknown, and all we observe is the combined appearance. Thus, even with the concept of indivisible points, we can only form a vague idea of some unknown standard for these objects. With the concept of infinite divisibility, we can’t even go that far; we can only rely on their general appearance as the basis for determining whether lines are curved or straight. Even though we can't provide a perfect definition for these lines, nor establish a precise way to distinguish one from the other, this doesn’t stop us from refining our initial impressions through more careful analysis and by comparing them to a standard that we have more confidence in due to repeated testing. It is through these refinements, and by continuing to engage our minds even when our reasoning fails, that we develop a vague idea of a perfect standard for these figures, even if we can't fully explain or understand it.
It is true, mathematicians pretend they give an exact definition of a right line, when they say, it is the shortest way betwixt two points. But in the first place I observe, that this is more properly the discovery of one of the properties of a right line, than a just deflation of it. For I ask any one, if upon mention of a right line he thinks not immediately on such a particular appearance, and if it is not by accident only that he considers this property? A right line can be comprehended alone; but this definition is unintelligible without a comparison with other lines, which we conceive to be more extended. In common life it is established as a maxim, that the straightest way is always the shortest; which would be as absurd as to say, the shortest way is always the shortest, if our idea of a right line was not different from that of the shortest way betwixt two points.
It's true that mathematicians claim they provide an exact definition of a straight line when they say it's the shortest distance between two points. However, I think this is more accurately a statement about one of the properties of a straight line rather than a proper definition. I ask anyone if, when they hear "straight line," they don't immediately think of a specific appearance, and whether it's merely by coincidence that they consider this property. A straight line can be understood on its own, but this definition is meaningless without comparing it to other lines that we imagine as being more extended. In everyday life, it's commonly accepted that the straightest path is always the shortest; saying the shortest path is always the shortest would be just as absurd, if our concept of a straight line wasn't distinct from that of the shortest distance between two points.
Secondly, I repeat what I have already established, that we have no precise idea of equality and inequality, shorter and longer, more than of a right line or a curve; and consequently that the one can never afford us a perfect standard for the other. An exact idea can never be built on such as are loose and undetermined.
Secondly, I’ll say again what I’ve already pointed out: we don’t have a clear concept of equality and inequality, shorter and longer, any more than we do of a straight line or a curve; therefore, one can never give us a perfect standard for the other. A precise idea can never be formed from things that are vague and undefined.
The idea of a plain surface is as little susceptible of a precise standard as that of a right line; nor have we any other means of distinguishing such a surface, than its general appearance. It is in vain, that mathematicians represent a plain surface as produced by the flowing of a right line. It will immediately be objected, that our idea of a surface is as independent of this method of forming a surface, as our idea of an ellipse is of that of a cone; that the idea of a right line is no more precise than that of a plain surface; that a right line may flow irregularly, and by that means form a figure quite different from a plane; and that therefore we must suppose it to flow along two right lines, parallel to each other, and on the same plane; which is a description, that explains a thing by itself, and returns in a circle.
The concept of a flat surface is just as hard to define precisely as that of a straight line; we only have its overall appearance to differentiate such a surface. Mathematicians may suggest that a flat surface is created by the movement of a straight line, but it can easily be argued that our understanding of a surface is as separate from this construction method as our understanding of an ellipse is from that of a cone. The notion of a straight line isn't any clearer than that of a flat surface; a straight line can curve irregularly and create a shape completely different from a plane. Therefore, we must assume it flows along two straight lines that are parallel to each other and on the same plane, which is a description that simply reiterates itself and goes in circles.
It appears, then, that the ideas which are most essential to geometry, viz. those of equality and inequality, of a right line and a plain surface, are far from being exact and determinate, according to our common method of conceiving them. Not only we are incapable of telling, if the case be in any degree doubtful, when such particular figures are equal; when such a line is a right one, and such a surface a plain one; but we can form no idea of that proportion, or of these figures, which is firm and invariable. Our appeal is still to the weak and fallible judgment, which we make from the appearance of the objects, and correct by a compass or common measure; and if we join the supposition of any farther correction, it is of such-a-one as is either useless or imaginary. In vain should we have recourse to the common topic, and employ the supposition of a deity, whose omnipotence may enable him to form a perfect geometrical figure, and describe a right line without any curve or inflexion. As the ultimate standard of these figures is derived from nothing but the senses and imagination, it is absurd to talk of any perfection beyond what these faculties can judge of; since the true perfection of any thing consists in its conformity to its standard.
It seems, then, that the ideas that are most important to geometry, specifically those of equality and inequality, a straight line, and a flat surface, are far from being exact and clear, according to how we commonly perceive them. Not only are we unable to determine, if there's any doubt, when certain figures are equal; when a line is straight; and when a surface is flat; but we also cannot form a solid and consistent idea of that proportion or of these figures. We still rely on our weak and fallible judgment based on how things appear, correcting it with a compass or standard measure; and if we assume there’s any further correction needed, it’s one that’s either useless or imaginary. It would be pointless to turn to the common argument and suggest the idea of a deity whose omnipotence allows for the creation of a perfect geometrical figure, defining a straight line without any curve or bend. Since the ultimate standard of these figures comes from nothing but our senses and imagination, it’s pointless to talk about any perfection beyond what these faculties can assess; true perfection consists in how well something matches its standard.
Now since these ideas are so loose and uncertain, I would fain ask any mathematician what infallible assurance he has, not only of the more intricate, and obscure propositions of his science, but of the most vulgar and obvious principles? How can he prove to me, for instance, that two right lines cannot have one common segment? Or that it is impossible to draw more than one right line betwixt any two points? should he tell me, that these opinions are obviously absurd, and repugnant to our clear ideas; I would answer, that I do not deny, where two right lines incline upon each other with a sensible angle, but it is absurd to imagine them to have a common segment. But supposing these two lines to approach at the rate of an inch in twenty leagues, I perceive no absurdity in asserting, that upon their contact they become one. For, I beseech you, by what rule or standard do you judge, when you assert, that the line, in which I have supposed them to concur, cannot make the same right line with those two, that form so small an angle betwixt them? You must surely have some idea of a right line, to which this line does not agree. Do you therefore mean that it takes not the points in the same order and by the same rule, as is peculiar and essential to a right line? If so, I must inform you, that besides that in judging after this manner you allow, that extension is composed of indivisible points (which, perhaps, is more than you intend) besides this, I say, I must inform you, that neither is this the standard from which we form the idea of a right line; nor, if it were, is there any such firmness in our senses or imagination, as to determine when such an order is violated or preserved. The original standard of a right line is in reality nothing but a certain general appearance; and it is evident right lines may be made to concur with each other, and yet correspond to this standard, though corrected by all the means either practicable or imaginable.
Since these ideas are so vague and uncertain, I would like to ask any mathematician what absolute certainty he has, not just about the more complex and obscure propositions of his field, but also about the simplest and most obvious principles. How can he prove to me, for example, that two straight lines can’t have a common segment? Or that it’s impossible to draw more than one straight line between any two points? If he tells me that these beliefs are clearly absurd and contradict our clear ideas, I would respond that I don’t deny that when two straight lines intersect at a noticeable angle, it’s absurd to think they can have a common segment. But if we assume these two lines get closer at the rate of an inch over twenty leagues, I see no absurdity in claiming that upon contact they become one. So I ask you, by what rule or standard do you judge when you claim that the line I’m assuming they form cannot be the same straight line as those two, which create such a small angle between them? You must have some conception of a straight line that this line doesn’t match. Do you mean it doesn’t take the points in the same order and by the same rule that is essential to a straight line? If that’s the case, I must inform you that by judging this way, you imply that extension consists of indivisible points (which might be more than you intend). Furthermore, I must tell you that this is not the standard from which we form the idea of a straight line; and even if it were, there’s no certainty in our senses or imagination to determine when such an order is violated or maintained. The original standard of a straight line is really just a general appearance; and it’s clear that straight lines can be made to coincide with each other while still adhering to this standard, even if corrected by all possible means.
To whatever side mathematicians turn, this dilemma still meets them. If they judge of equality, or any other proportion, by the accurate and exact standard, viz. the enumeration of the minute indivisible parts, they both employ a standard, which is useless in practice, and actually establish the indivisibility of extension, which they endeavour to explode. Or if they employ, as is usual, the inaccurate standard, derived from a comparison of objects, upon their general appearance, corrected by measuring and juxtaposition; their first principles, though certain and infallible, are too coarse to afford any such subtile inferences as they commonly draw from them. The first principles are founded on the imagination and senses: The conclusion, therefore, can never go beyond, much less contradict these faculties.
No matter where mathematicians look, they still face this dilemma. If they assess equality or any other proportion using the precise standard of counting tiny, indivisible parts, they end up relying on a standard that is impractical and unintentionally affirm the indivisibility of extension, which they aim to reject. On the other hand, if they use the usual imprecise standard based on comparing objects by their general appearance, adjusted through measuring and positioning them next to each other, their fundamental principles, while certain and reliable, are too rough to support the subtle conclusions they usually draw. These fundamental principles are based on imagination and sensory perception; therefore, the conclusions can never exceed or contradict these faculties.
This may open our eyes a little, and let us see, that no geometrical demonstration for the infinite divisibility of extension can have so much force as what we naturally attribute to every argument, which is supported by such magnificent pretensions. At the same time we may learn the reason, why geometry falls of evidence in this single point, while all its other reasonings command our fullest assent and approbation. And indeed it seems more requisite to give the reason of this exception, than to shew, that we really must make such an exception, and regard all the mathematical arguments for infinite divisibility as utterly sophistical. For it is evident, that as no idea of quantity is infinitely divisible, there cannot be imagined a more glaring absurdity, than to endeavour to prove, that quantity itself admits of such a division; and to prove this by means of ideas, which are directly opposite in that particular. And as this absurdity is very glaring in itself, so there is no argument founded on it which is not attended with a new absurdity, and involves not an evident contradiction.
This might open our eyes a bit and help us see that no geometric proof for the infinite divisibility of space can be as compelling as the significance we naturally give to any argument that boasts such grand claims. At the same time, we can understand why geometry lacks clarity on this one point while all its other reasoning earns our complete agreement and approval. In fact, it seems more important to explain why this exception exists rather than just show that we really need to make this exception and view all the mathematical arguments for infinite divisibility as completely fallacious. It's clear that since no notion of quantity is infinitely divisible, there's no greater absurdity than trying to prove that quantity itself can be divided in such a way, especially when we use ideas that are directly opposed to that concept. And since this absurdity is quite obvious, any argument based on it is bound to lead to another absurdity and involves a clear contradiction.
I might give as instances those arguments for infinite divisibility, which are derived from the point of contact. I know there is no mathematician, who will not refuse to be judged by the diagrams he describes upon paper, these being loose draughts, as he will tell us, and serving only to convey with greater facility certain ideas, which are the true foundation of all our reasoning. This I am satisfyed with, and am willing to rest the controversy merely upon these ideas. I desire therefore our mathematician to form, as accurately as possible, the ideas of a circle and a right line; and I then ask, if upon the conception of their contact he can conceive them as touching in a mathematical point, or if he must necessarily imagine them to concur for some space. Whichever side he chuses, he runs himself into equal difficulties. If he affirms, that in tracing these figures in his imagination, he can imagine them to touch only in a point, he allows the possibility of that idea, and consequently of the thing. If he says, that in his conception of the contact of those lines he must make them concur, he thereby acknowledges the fallacy of geometrical demonstrations, when carryed beyond a certain degree of minuteness; since it is certain he has such demonstrations against the concurrence of a circle and a right line; that is, in other words, he can prove an idea, viz. that of concurrence, to be INCOMPATIBLE with two other ideas, those of a circle and right line; though at the same time he acknowledges these ideas to be inseparable.
I could point to those arguments for infinite divisibility that come from the point of contact. I know there isn't a mathematician who would accept being judged by the diagrams they sketch on paper, as they are just rough drafts, as they would say, and serve only to convey certain ideas more easily, which are the true foundation of all our reasoning. I'm satisfied with this and am willing to base the discussion solely on these ideas. Therefore, I ask our mathematician to form, as accurately as possible, the ideas of a circle and a straight line; then I ask if, when considering their contact, he can imagine them touching at a mathematical point, or if he must necessarily think of them intersecting over some area. No matter which choice he makes, he faces the same challenges. If he claims that when imagining these figures, he can see them touch only at a point, he acknowledges the possibility of that concept, and consequently, the existence of the thing. If he says that in his understanding of the contact of those lines he must think of them intersecting, he admits the flaw in geometric proofs when taken beyond a certain level of detail; since it is clear he has such proofs against the intersection of a circle and a straight line; in other words, he can prove the concept of intersection to be INCOMPATIBLE with the concepts of a circle and straight line; while at the same time, he acknowledges these concepts to be inseparable.
SECT. V. THE SAME SUBJECT CONTINUED.
If the second part of my system be true, that the idea of space or extension is nothing but the idea of visible or tangible points distributed in a certain order; it follows, that we can form no idea of a vacuum, or space, where there is nothing visible or tangible. This gives rise to three objections, which I shall examine together, because the answer I shall give to one is a consequence of that which I shall make use of for the others.
If the second part of my theory is correct, and that the concept of space or extension is just the idea of visible or touchable points arranged in a specific order, then it follows that we cannot truly imagine a vacuum or space where there is nothing visible or tangible. This leads to three objections, which I'll address together, since the response I provide for one will apply to the others as well.
First, It may be said, that men have disputed for many ages concerning a vacuum and a plenum, without being able to bring the affair to a final decision; and philosophers, even at this day, think themselves at liberty to take part on either side, as their fancy leads them. But whatever foundation there may be for a controversy concerning the things themselves, it may be pretended, that the very dispute is decisive concerning the idea, and that it is impossible men could so long reason about a vacuum, and either refute or defend it, without having a notion of what they refuted or defended.
First, it can be said that people have debated for many ages about a vacuum and a plenum, without being able to reach a final conclusion; and philosophers, even today, feel free to take sides based on their preferences. However, no matter the basis for the debate over these concepts, one could argue that the very argument itself is telling regarding the idea, and that it’s impossible for people to discuss a vacuum for so long, either arguing against it or in favor of it, without having some understanding of what they are arguing about.
Secondly, If this argument should be contested, the reality or at least the possibility of the idea of a vacuum may be proved by the following reasoning. Every idea is possible, which is a necessary and infallible consequence of such as are possible. Now though we allow the world to be at present a plenum, we may easily conceive it to be deprived of motion; and this idea will certainly be allowed possible. It must also be allowed possible, to conceive the annihilation of any part of matter by the omnipotence of the deity, while the other parts remain at rest. For as every idea, that is distinguishable, is separable by the imagination; and as every idea, that is separable by the imagination, may be conceived to be separately existent; it is evident, that the existence of one particle of matter, no more implies the existence of another, than a square figure in one body implies a square figure in every one. This being granted, I now demand what results from the concurrence of these two possible ideas of rest and annihilation, and what must we conceive to follow upon the annihilation of all the air and subtile matter in the chamber, supposing the walls to remain the same, without any motion or alteration? There are some metaphysicians, who answer, that since matter and extension are the same, the annihilation of one necessarily implies that of the other; and there being now no distance betwixt the walls of the chamber, they touch each other; in the same manner as my hand touches the paper, which is immediately before me. But though this answer be very common, I defy these metaphysicians to conceive the matter according to their hypothesis, or imagine the floor and roof, with all the opposite sides of the chamber, to touch each other, while they continue in rest, and preserve the same position. For how can the two walls, that run from south to north, touch each other, while they touch the opposite ends of two walls, that run from east to west? And how can the floor and roof ever meet, while they are separated by the four walls, that lie in a contrary position? If you change their position, you suppose a motion. If you conceive any thing betwixt them, you suppose a new creation. But keeping strictly to the two ideas of rest and annihilation, it is evident, that the idea, which results from them, is not that of a contact of parts, but something else; which is concluded to be the idea of a vacuum.
Secondly, if this argument is challenged, the existence or at least the possibility of a vacuum can be demonstrated by the following reasoning. Every idea is possible if it necessarily follows from other possible ideas. Although we currently consider the world to be full, we can easily imagine it being motionless; and this idea is certainly possible. It must also be possible to envision the complete destruction of any part of matter by the power of a deity, while the other parts remain still. Since every distinguishable idea can be separated in our imagination, and any idea that can be separated in our imagination can also be imagined as existing separately, it becomes clear that the existence of one particle of matter does not imply the existence of another, just as having one square object does not mean every object must also be square. With this understanding, I now ask what follows from combining these two possible ideas of rest and destruction, and what we should conceive of when all the air and fine matter in a room is annihilated while the walls stay the same, without any movement or change? Some metaphysicians claim that since matter and space are the same, destroying one means destroying the other; and with no distance between the walls of the room, they touch each other, just like my hand touches the paper right in front of me. But while this answer is common, I challenge these metaphysicians to truly conceive of the situation according to their theory, or to imagine the floor and ceiling, along with the opposite walls of the room, touching each other while remaining still and in the same position. How can two walls running from south to north touch each other if they also touch the opposite ends of two walls running from east to west? And how can the floor and ceiling ever meet when they are separated by four walls that are positioned oppositely? If you change their position, you are assuming movement. If you imagine anything between them, you are assuming a new creation. But if we strictly stick to the two ideas of rest and destruction, it is evident that the resulting idea is not one of contact between parts, but rather something else; which is concluded to be the idea of a vacuum.
The third objection carries the matter still farther, and not only asserts, that the idea of a vacuum is real and possible, but also necessary and unavoidable. This assertion is founded on the motion we observe in bodies, which, it is maintained, would be impossible and inconceivable without a vacuum, into which one body must move in order to make way for another.. I shall not enlarge upon this objection, because it principally belongs to natural philosophy, which lies without our present sphere.
The third objection takes the discussion further, arguing not only that the idea of a vacuum is real and possible but also necessary and unavoidable. This claim is based on the movement we observe in objects, which it is argued would be impossible and unimaginable without a vacuum, into which one object must move to make space for another. I won’t elaborate on this objection, as it mainly pertains to natural philosophy, which is outside our current focus.
In order to answer these objections, we must take the matter pretty deep, and consider the nature and origin of several ideas, lest we dispute without understanding perfectly the subject of the controversy. It is evident the idea of darkness is no positive idea, but merely the negation of light, or more properly speaking, of coloured and visible objects. A man, who enjoys his sight, receives no other perception from turning his eyes on every side, when entirely deprived of light, than what is common to him with one born blind; and it is certain such-a-one has no idea either of light or darkness. The consequence of this is, that it is not from the mere removal of visible objects we receive the impression of extension without matter; and that the idea of utter darkness can never be the same with that of vacuum.
To address these objections, we need to dig deeper and examine the nature and origin of various ideas, so we don’t argue without fully understanding the topic at hand. It’s clear that the idea of darkness is not a positive concept; it’s just the absence of light, or more accurately, the absence of colored and visible objects. A person with normal vision receives no different perception from looking around when completely deprived of light than someone who was born blind. And it's true that such a person has no concept of either light or darkness. The implication of this is that it’s not simply the absence of visible objects that gives us the impression of extension without matter, and that the idea of complete darkness can never be the same as that of a vacuum.
Suppose again a man to be supported in the air, and to be softly conveyed along by some invisible power; it is evident he is sensible of nothing, and never receives the idea of extension, nor indeed any idea, from this invariable motion. Even supposing he moves his limbs to and fro, this cannot convey to him that idea. He feels in that case a certain sensation or impression, the parts of which are successive to each other, and may give him the idea of time: But certainly are not disposed in such a manner, as is necessary to convey the idea of space or the idea of space or extension.
Imagine a man being held up in the air, gently moved along by some unseen force; it's clear that he doesn't feel anything and doesn't gain the concept of extension, or really any concept, from this constant motion. Even if he moves his limbs back and forth, that won't give him that understanding. In that scenario, he would experience a certain feeling or impression that comes one after the other, which might give him a sense of time. But those sensations are definitely not arranged in a way that would allow him to grasp the idea of space or extension.
Since then it appears, that darkness and motion, with the utter removal of every thing visible and tangible, can never give us the idea of extension without matter, or of a vacuum; the next question is, whether they can convey this idea, when mixed with something visible and tangible?
Since then, it seems that darkness and motion, along with the complete absence of everything we can see or touch, can never make us think of extension without matter or of a vacuum. The next question is whether they can convey this idea when mixed with something we can see and touch.
It is commonly allowed by philosophers, that all bodies, which discover themselves to the eye, appear as if painted on a plain surface, and that their different degrees of remoteness from ourselves are discovered more by reason than by the senses. When I hold up my hand before me, and spread my fingers, they are separated as perfectly by the blue colour of the firmament, as they could be by any visible object, which I could place betwixt them. In order, therefore, to know whether the sight can convey the impression and idea of a vacuum, we must suppose, that amidst an entire darkness, there are luminous bodies presented to us, whose light discovers only these bodies themselves, without giving us any impression of the surrounding objects.
Philosophers generally agree that all objects we see appear as if they're painted on a flat surface, and it's through reasoning rather than our senses that we understand how far away they are from us. When I hold up my hand and spread my fingers, they are as clearly separated by the blue sky as they would be by any visible object I could put between them. Therefore, to determine if our sight can convey the idea of a vacuum, we must imagine a complete darkness where there are bright objects visible to us, whose light only reveals those objects without providing any impression of the surrounding space.
We must form a parallel supposition concerning the objects of our feeling. It is not proper to suppose a perfect removal of all tangible objects: we must allow something to be perceived by the feeling; and after an interval and motion of the hand or other organ of sensation, another object of the touch to be met with; and upon leaving that, another; and so on, as often as we please. The question is, whether these intervals do not afford us the idea of extension without body?
We need to create a similar assumption about the things we feel. It isn't right to think that we can completely eliminate all physical objects: we have to allow for something to be sensed through feeling; and after a moment and a movement of the hand or another sensory part, we encounter another object to touch; and upon leaving that one, we find another; and this can continue as often as we like. The question is, do these gaps give us the concept of space without a physical body?
To begin with the first case; it is evident, that when only two luminous bodies appear to the eye, we can perceive, whether they be conjoined or separate: whether they be separated by a great or small distance; and if this distance varies, we can perceive its increase or diminution, with the motion of the bodies. But as the distance is not in this case any thing coloured or visible, it may be thought that there is here a vacuum or pure extension, not only intelligible to the mind, but obvious to the very senses.
To start with the first case, it's clear that when we see just two light sources, we can tell if they are together or apart, and if they are separated by a large or small distance. If this distance changes, we can notice whether it's getting bigger or smaller as the objects move. However, since the distance itself isn’t colored or visible, it might seem like there is just empty space or pure extension that is not only understandable to the mind but also apparent to our senses.
This is our natural and most familiar way of thinking; but which we shall learn to correct by a little reflection. We may observe, that when two bodies present themselves, where there was formerly an entire darkness, the only change, that is discoverable, is in the appearance of these two objects, and that all the rest continues to be as before, a perfect negation of light, and of every coloured or visible object. This is not only true of what may be said to be remote from these bodies, but also of the very distance; which is interposed betwixt them; that being nothing but darkness, or the negation of light; without parts, without composition, invariable and indivisible. Now since this distance causes no perception different from what a blind man receives from his eyes, or what is conveyed to us in the darkest night, it must partake of the same properties: And as blindness and darkness afford us no ideas of extension, it is impossible that the dark and undistinguishable distance betwixt two bodies can ever produce that idea.
This is our natural and most familiar way of thinking, but we will learn to correct it with a little reflection. We can notice that when two objects appear in what was previously complete darkness, the only change we can see is the appearance of those two objects, while everything else remains as it was—a complete absence of light and any colored or visible objects. This is true not only for what might be far from these objects but also for the very distance between them, which is nothing more than darkness, or the absence of light; it has no parts, no composition, is unchanging, and indivisible. Since this distance causes no perception different from what a blind person experiences through their eyes, or what we perceive in the darkest night, it must have the same properties. And just as blindness and darkness give us no ideas of extension, it's impossible for the dark and indistinguishable distance between two objects to ever create that idea.
The sole difference betwixt an absolute darkness and the appearance of two or more visible luminous objects consists, as I said, in the objects themselves, and in the manner they affect our senses. The angles, which the rays of light flowing from them, form with each other; the motion that is required in the eye, in its passage from one to the other; and the different parts of the organs, which are affected by them; these produce the only perceptions, from which we can judge of the distance. But as these perceptions are each of them simple and indivisible, they can never give us the idea of extension.
The only difference between complete darkness and the visibility of two or more light sources is, as I mentioned, in the objects themselves and how they affect our senses. The angles created by the rays of light they emit and the movement required by the eye to switch from one to the other, along with the different parts of our sensory organs that are engaged; these create the only perceptions we use to estimate distance. However, since these perceptions are each simple and indivisible, they can never provide us with the concept of extension.
We may illustrate this by considering the sense of feeling, and the imaginary distance or interval interposed betwixt tangible or solid objects. I suppose two cases, viz. that of a man supported in the air, and moving his limbs to and fro, without meeting any thing tangible; and that of a man, who feeling something tangible, leaves it, and after a motion, of which he is sensible, perceives another tangible object; and I then ask, wherein consists the difference betwixt these two cases? No one will make any scruple to affirm, that it consists meerly in the perceiving those objects, and that the sensation, which arises from the motion, is in both cases the same: And as that sensation is not capable of conveying to us an idea of extension, when unaccompanyed with some other perception, it can no more give us that idea, when mixed with the impressions of tangible objects; since that mixture produces no alteration upon it.
We can illustrate this by looking at our sense of touch and the imaginary space that exists between solid objects. Let’s consider two situations: one where a person is suspended in the air, moving their limbs without touching anything solid, and another where a person touches something solid, lets go, and after a noticeable movement, feels another solid object. My question is, what’s the difference between these two situations? Nobody would hesitate to say that the distinction lies purely in the perception of those objects, and that the sensation from the movement is the same in both cases. And since that sensation doesn’t give us a sense of space when it’s not accompanied by another type of perception, it can’t provide that sense even when mixed with the feelings from tangible objects, because that mixture doesn’t change anything about it.
But though motion and darkness, either alone, or attended with tangible and visible objects, convey no idea of a vacuum or extension without matter, yet they are the causes why we falsly imagine we can form such an idea. For there is a close relation betwixt that motion and darkness, and a real extension, or composition of visible and tangible objects.
But even though motion and darkness, either by themselves or along with solid and visible objects, don't give us any idea of a vacuum or space without matter, they lead us to mistakenly think we can create such an idea. This is because there is a strong connection between that motion and darkness and the actual space, or arrangement of visible and tangible objects.
First, We may observe, that two visible objects appearing in the midst of utter darkness, affect the senses in the same manner, and form the same angle by the rays, which flow from them, and meet in the eye, as if the distance betwixt them were find with visible objects, that give us a true idea of extension. The sensation of motion is likewise the same, when there is nothing tangible interposed betwixt two bodies, as when we feel a compounded body, whose different parts are placed beyond each other.
First, we can note that two visible objects appearing in complete darkness affect our senses in the same way and create the same angle by the rays that come from them and meet in the eye, as if the space between them were filled with visible objects that provide a clear idea of distance. The feeling of motion is also the same when there’s nothing solid between two bodies, just as when we experience a combined object with its different parts positioned next to each other.
Secondly, We find by experience, that two bodies, which are so placed as to affect the senses in the same manner with two others, that have a certain extent of visible objects interposed betwixt them, are capable of receiving the same extent, without any sensible impulse or penetration, and without any change on that angle, under which they appear to the senses. In like manner, where there is one object, which we cannot feel after another without an interval, and the perceiving of that sensation we call motion in our hand or organ of sensation; experience shews us, that it is possible the same object may be felt with the same sensation of motion, along with the interposed impression of solid and tangible objects, attending the sensation. That is, in other words, an invisible and intangible distance may be converted into a visible and tangible one, without any change on the distant objects.
Secondly, we find from experience that two objects, positioned in a way that they affect our senses like two others, which have a certain range of visible objects in between them, can receive the same extent of sensation without any noticeable impact or penetration, and without any change in the angle at which they appear to our senses. Similarly, when there is one object that we can't feel after another without a gap in between, the sensation we perceive is what we refer to as motion in our hand or sensory organ. Experience shows us that it’s possible for the same object to be felt with the same sensation of motion, even when solid and tangible objects are interposed during that sensation. In other words, an invisible and intangible distance can be turned into a visible and tangible one, without any change to the distant objects.
Thirdly, We may observe, as another relation betwixt these two kinds of distance, that they have nearly the same effects on every natural phænomenon. For as all qualities, such as heat, cold, light, attraction, &c. diminish in proportion to the distance; there is but little difference observed, whether this distance be marled out by compounded and sensible objects, or be known only by the manner, in which the distant objects affect the senses.
Thirdly, we can see that there’s a similar relationship between these two types of distance, as they have nearly the same effects on every natural phenomenon. Just as all qualities, like heat, cold, light, and attraction, decrease in intensity as the distance increases, there's very little difference observed whether this distance is marked by complex and obvious objects, or understood simply by how the distant objects impact our senses.
Here then are three relations betwixt that distance, which conveys the idea of extension, and that other, which is not filled with any coloured or solid object. The distant objects affect the senses in the same manner, whether separated by the one distance or the other; the second species of distance is found capable of receiving the first; and they both equally diminish the force of every quality.
Here are three relationships between that distance, which suggests space, and the other, which isn't filled with any colored or solid object. Distant objects affect the senses in the same way, whether they are separated by one type of distance or another; the second type of distance is able to encompass the first; and both similarly lessen the impact of every quality.
These relations betwixt the two kinds of distance will afford us an easy reason, why the one has so often been taken for the other, and why we imagine we have an idea of extension without the idea of any object either of the sight or feeling. For we may establish it as a general maxim in this science of human nature, that wherever there is a close relation betwixt two ideas, the mind is very apt to mistake them, and in all its discourses and reasonings to use the one for the other. This phænomenon occurs on so many occasions, and is of such consequence, that I cannot forbear stopping a moment to examine its causes. I shall only premise, that we must distinguish exactly betwixt the phænomenon itself, and the causes, which I shall assign for it; and must not imagine from any uncertainty in the latter, that the former is also uncertain. The phænomenon may be real, though my explication be chimerical. The falshood of the one is no consequence of that of the other; though at the same time we may observe, that it is very natural for us to draw such a consequence; which is an evident instance of that very principle, which I endeavour to explain.
These relationships between the two types of distance give us a clear reason why one is often mistaken for the other and why we believe we have an idea of extension without actually having a reference to any object we can see or touch. It’s a general rule in the study of human nature that whenever there’s a close connection between two ideas, our minds tend to confuse them and often use one in place of the other in our thoughts and arguments. This phenomenon happens in so many situations and is so significant that I can’t help but take a moment to look into its causes. I want to clarify that we need to differentiate between the phenomenon itself and the causes I’ll suggest; we shouldn’t think that any lack of clarity in the latter means the former is also unclear. The phenomenon can still be real, even if my explanation is off-base. The falsehood of one doesn’t imply the falsehood of the other; however, it’s natural for us to make that assumption, which clearly illustrates the very principle I’m trying to explain.
When I received the relations of resemblance, contiguity and causation, as principles of union among ideas, without examining into their causes, it was more in prosecution of my first maxim, that we must in the end rest contented with experience, than for want of something specious and plausible, which I might have displayed on that subject. It would have been easy to have made an imaginary dissection of the brain, and have shewn, why upon our conception of any idea, the animal spirits run into all the contiguous traces, and rouze up the other ideas, that are related to it. But though I have neglected any advantage, which I might have drawn from this topic in explaining the relations of ideas, I am afraid I must here have recourse to it, in order to account for the mistakes that arise from these relations. I shall therefore observe, that as the mind is endowed with a power of exciting any idea it pleases; whenever it dispatches the spirits into that region of the brain, in which the idea is placed; these spirits always excite the idea, when they run precisely into the proper traces, and rummage that cell, which belongs to the idea. But as their motion is seldom direct, and naturally turns a little to the one side or the other; for this reason the animal spirits, falling into the contiguous traces, present other related ideas in lieu of that, which the mind desired at first to survey. This change we are not always sensible of; but continuing still the same train of thought, make use of the related idea, which is presented to us, and employ it in our reasoning, as if it were the same with what we demanded. This is the cause of many mistakes and sophisms in philosophy; as will naturally be imagined, and as it would be easy to show, if there was occasion.
When I learned about the relationships of similarity, proximity, and causation as principles connecting ideas, without looking into their origins, I was more focused on my primary principle that we should ultimately rely on experience than out of a lack of something convincing and plausible to present on the topic. It would have been easy to create an imaginary breakdown of the brain and explain why, when we conceive an idea, the mental forces jump to all the nearby connections and activate other ideas related to it. But although I passed on any advantages I could have gained from this topic in explaining the relationships of ideas, I’m afraid I must refer back to it to explain the mistakes that arise from these connections. So, I'll point out that since the mind has the ability to trigger any idea it wants, whenever it sends the mental forces to the part of the brain where the idea is located, these forces will always activate that idea when they move precisely along the right connections and rummage through the area that belongs to the idea. However, since their movement is rarely straightforward and often veers slightly to one side or the other, this causes the mental forces, ending up in the nearby connections, to present other related ideas instead of the one the mind initially wanted to explore. We don’t always notice this change; instead, we continue along the same train of thought and use the related idea that comes up, treating it as if it were the one we intended to examine. This is the reason for many errors and fallacies in philosophy, as one might naturally conclude, and it would be easy to demonstrate this if needed.
Of the three relations above-mentioned that of resemblance is the most fertile source of error; and indeed there are few mistakes in reasoning, which do not borrow largely from that origin. Resembling ideas are not only related together, but the actions of the mind, which we employ in considering them, are so little different, that we are not able to distinguish them. This last circumstance is of great consequence, and we may in general observe, that wherever the actions of the mind in forming any two ideas are the same or resembling, we are very apt to confound these ideas, and take the one for the other. Of this we shall see many instances in the progress of this treatise. But though resemblance be the relation, which most readily produces a mistake in ideas, yet the others of causation and contiguity may also concur in the same influence. We might produce the figures of poets and orators, as sufficient proofs of this, were it as usual, as it is reasonable, in metaphysical subjects to draw our arguments from that quarter. But lest metaphysicians should esteem this below their dignity, I shall borrow a proof from an observation, which may be made on most of their own discourses, viz. that it is usual for men to use words for ideas, and to talk instead of thinking in their reasonings. We use words for ideas, because they are commonly so closely connected that the mind easily mistakes them. And this likewise is the reason, why we substitute the idea of a distance, which is not considered either as visible or tangible, in the room of extension, which is nothing but a composition of visible or tangible points disposed in a certain order. In causing this mistake there concur both the relations of causation and resemblance. As the first species of distance is found to be convertible into the second, it is in this respect a kind of cause; and the similarity of their manner of affecting the senses, and diminishing every quality, forms the relation of resemblance.
Of the three relationships mentioned, resemblance is the most common source of error; in fact, few reasoning mistakes don’t stem from this. Resembling ideas not only connect to each other, but the mental processes we use to think about them are so similar that we often can’t tell them apart. This is crucial, and we can generally observe that whenever the mental actions involved in forming two ideas are the same or similar, we tend to confuse these ideas and mistake one for the other. We'll see many examples of this as we move through this discussion. Although resemblance is the relationship that most easily leads to confusion in ideas, causation and contiguity can also play a part. We could cite examples from poets and orators as proof of this, but since it’s not common—though reasonable—to base our arguments on that in metaphysical subjects, I’ll draw evidence from a common observation about many of their discussions: people often use words to represent ideas and end up talking instead of thinking through their reasoning. We use words for ideas because they’re usually so closely linked that our minds easily mix them up. This is also why we replace the idea of a distance, which isn’t perceived as visible or tangible, with the concept of extension, which is merely a collection of visible or tangible points arranged in a certain way. Both causation and resemblance are involved in creating this confusion. Since the first type of distance can be transformed into the second, it acts as a kind of cause; and the similarity in how they affect the senses and lessen every quality creates the resemblance relationship.
After this chain of reasoning and explication of my principles, I am now prepared to answer all the objections that have been offered, whether derived from metaphysics or mechanics. The frequent disputes concerning a vacuum, or extension without matter prove not the reality of the idea, upon which the dispute turns; there being nothing more common, than to see men deceive themselves in this particular; especially when by means of any close relation, there is another idea presented, which may be the occasion of their mistake.
After this line of reasoning and explanation of my principles, I'm now ready to address all the objections that have been raised, whether they come from metaphysics or mechanics. The ongoing arguments about a vacuum or extension without matter don't prove the reality of the idea at the center of the debate; it's quite common to see people fool themselves in this area, especially when there's another related idea presented that can lead to confusion.
We may make almost the same answer to the second objection, derived from the conjunction of the ideas of rest and annihilation. When every thing is annihilated in the chamber, and the walls continue immoveable, the chamber must be conceived much in the same manner as at present, when the air that fills it, is not an object of the senses. This annihilation leaves to the eye, that fictitious distance, which is discovered by the different parts of the organ, that are affected, and by the degrees of light and shade;—and to the feeling, that which consists in a sensation of motion in the hand, or other member of the body. In vain should we. search any farther. On whichever side we turn this subject, we shall find that these are the only impressions such an object can produce after the supposed annihilation; and it has already been remarked, that impressions can give rise to no ideas, but to such as resemble them.
We can respond to the second objection, which comes from the combination of the ideas of rest and annihilation, in a similar way. When everything is gone from the chamber and the walls remain still, we should imagine the chamber much like it is now, even when the air inside it isn’t something we can sense. This annihilation leaves a perceived distance to the eye, which is noticed through the different parts of the eye that are stimulated and by varying degrees of light and shade; and to the sense of touch, it creates a feeling of movement in the hand or other parts of the body. There's no point in searching for more. No matter how we look at this topic, we’ll find that these are the only impressions such an object can create after this supposed annihilation; and it’s already been pointed out that impressions can only lead to ideas that resemble them.
Since a body interposed betwixt two others may be supposed to be annihilated, without producing any change upon such as lie on each hand of it, it is easily conceived, how it may be created anew, and yet produce as little alteration. Now the motion of a body has much the same effect as its creation. The distant bodies are no more affected in the one case, than in the other. This suffices to satisfy the imagination, and proves there is no repugnance in such a motion. Afterwards experience comes in play to persuade us that two bodies, situated in the manner above-described, have really such a capacity of receiving body betwixt them, and that there is no obstacle to the conversion of the invisible and intangible distance into one that is visible and tangible. However natural that conversion may seem, we cannot be sure it is practicable, before we have had experience of it.
Since a body placed between two others can be thought of as disappearing without affecting those on either side, it's easy to understand how it can be created again with minimal impact. The movement of a body acts similarly to its creation. The distant objects aren't influenced in either case. This is enough to satisfy our imagination and shows that there's no conflict in such movement. Later, experience helps convince us that two bodies, positioned as described, really have the ability to accommodate another body between them, and that there’s no barrier to turning the invisible and intangible space into something visible and tangible. However natural that change might seem, we can't be sure it's possible until we've experienced it.
Thus I seem to have answered the three objections above-mentioned; though at the same time I am sensible, that few will be satisfyed with these answers, but will immediately propose new objections and difficulties. It will probably be said, that my reasoning makes nothing to the matter in hands and that I explain only the manner in which objects affect the senses, without endeavouring to account for their real nature and operations. Though there be nothing visible or tangible interposed betwixt two bodies, yet we find BY EXPERIENCE, that the bodies may be placed in the same manner, with regard to the eye, and require the same motion of the hand in passing from one to the other, as if divided by something visible and tangible. This invisible and intangible distance is also found by experience to contain a capacity of receiving body, or of becoming visible and tangible. Here is the whole of my system; and in no part of it have I endeavoured to explain the cause, which separates bodies after this manner, and gives them a capacity of receiving others betwixt them, without any impulse or penetration.
So, I believe I've addressed the three objections mentioned earlier; however, I realize that few will be satisfied with these responses and will quickly raise new objections and challenges. It will likely be argued that my reasoning doesn’t contribute anything relevant to the issue at hand, and that I’m only explaining how objects affect the senses, without trying to account for their actual nature and functions. Even though there’s nothing visible or tangible between two bodies, we know from experience that they can be positioned in the same way relative to the eye and require the same hand movement to switch from one to the other, as if they were separated by something visible and tangible. This invisible and intangible gap is also shown through experience to have the capacity to hold something or to become visible and tangible. This represents the entirety of my system; and at no point have I tried to explain the reason that separates bodies in this way and allows them to have the capacity to receive others between them, without any push or penetration.
I answer this objection, by pleading guilty, and by confessing that my intention never was to penetrate into the nature of bodies, or explain the secret causes of their operations. For besides that this belongs not to my present purpose, I am afraid, that such an enterprise is beyond the reach of human understanding, and that we can never pretend to know body otherwise than by those external properties, which discover themselves to the senses. As to those who attempt any thing farther, I cannot approve of their ambition, till I see, in some one instance at least, that they have met with success. But at present I content myself with knowing perfectly the manner in which objects affect my senses, and their connections with each other, as far as experience informs me of them. This suffices for the conduct of life; and this also suffices for my philosophy, which pretends only to explain the nature and causes of our perceptions, or impressions and ideas.[6]
I address this objection by admitting that I fully agree; my goal was never to delve into the nature of physical objects or to explain the hidden causes behind their actions. Aside from the fact that this isn't my current aim, I worry that such a task is beyond what humans can truly understand, and we can only claim to know about objects through the external properties that reveal themselves to our senses. As for those who try to go further, I cannot support their aspirations unless I see at least one successful example. For now, I am satisfied with understanding how objects impact my senses and how they relate to each other, as far as my experiences show me. This is enough for everyday life, and it is also sufficient for my philosophy, which aims only to clarify the nature and causes of our perceptions, impressions, and ideas.[6]
[6]
As long as we confine our speculations to the appearances of objects to our
senses, without entering into disquisitions concerning their real nature and
operations, we are safe from all difficulties, and can never be embarrassed by
any question. Thus, if it be asked, if the invisible and intangible distance,
interposed betwixt two objects, be something or nothing: It is easy to answer,
that it is SOMETHING, VIZ. a property of the objects, which affect the SENSES
after such a particular manner. If it be asked whether two objects, having such
a distance betwixt them, touch or not: it may be answered, that this depends
upon the definition of the word, TOUCH. If objects be said to touch, when there
is nothing SENSIBLE interposed betwixt them, these objects touch: it objects be
said to touch, when their IMAGES strike contiguous parts of the eye, and when
the hand FEELS both objects successively, without any interposed motion, these
objects do not touch. The appearances of objects to our senses are all
consistent; and no difficulties can ever arise, but from the obscurity of the
terms we make use of.
If we carry our enquiry beyond the appearances of objects to the senses, I
am afraid, that most of our conclusions will be full of scepticism and
uncertainty. Thus if it be asked, whether or not the invisible and intangible
distance be always full of body, or of something that by an improvement of our
organs might become visible or tangible, I must acknowledge, that I find no
very decisive arguments on either side; though I am inclined to the contrary
opinion, as being more suitable to vulgar and popular notions. If THE NEWTONIAN
philosophy be rightly understood, it will be found to mean no more. A vacuum is
asserted: That is, bodies are said to be placed after such a manner, is to
receive bodies betwixt them, without impulsion or penetration. The real nature
of this position of bodies is unknown. We are only acquainted with its effects
on the senses, and its power of receiving body. Nothing is more suitable to
that philosophy, than a modest scepticism to a certain degree, and a fair
confession of ignorance in subjects, that exceed all human capacity.
[6]
As long as we stick to discussing how objects appear to our senses, without delving into their true nature and functions, we avoid all complications and will never face difficult questions. For instance, if someone asks whether the invisible and intangible space between two objects is something or nothing, the answer is straightforward: it is SOMETHING, specifically a property of the objects that affects our SENSES in a certain way. If it's questioned whether two objects with such a space between them touch or not, the answer depends on how we define the word "TOUCH." If we say that objects touch when there is nothing SENSIBLE between them, then these objects touch. However, if we say they touch when their IMAGES stimulate adjacent parts of the eye and the hand FEELS both objects one after the other, without any intervening movement, then these objects do not touch. The appearances of objects to our senses are always consistent; any difficulties that arise come from unclear terminology.
If we take our inquiry beyond how objects appear to our senses, I'm afraid most of our conclusions will be filled with doubt and uncertainty. For instance, if someone asks whether the invisible and intangible space is always filled with matter, or with something that could become visible or tangible if we improved our senses, I have to admit that I don't find strong arguments on either side; although I tend to lean towards the latter view, as it aligns better with common beliefs. If THE NEWTONIAN philosophy is properly understood, it suggests no more than that. A vacuum is claimed: that is, bodies are said to be arranged in such a way as to allow other bodies to fit between them, without pushing or penetrating. The true nature of this arrangement of bodies is unknown. We're only familiar with its effects on our senses and its ability to hold matter. Nothing fits that philosophy better than a reasonable level of skepticism and a honest acknowledgment of our ignorance about topics that are beyond human understanding.
I shall conclude this subject of extension with a paradox, which will easily be explained from the foregoing reasoning. This paradox is, that if you are pleased to give to the in-visible and intangible distance, or in other words, to the capacity of becoming a visible and tangible distance, the name of a vacuum, extension and matter are the same, and yet there is a vacuum. If you will not give it that name, motion is possible in a plenum, without any impulse in infinitum, without returning in a circle, and without penetration. But however we may express ourselves, we must always confess, that we have no idea of any real extension without filling it with sensible objects, and conceiving its parts as visible or tangible.
I'll wrap up this topic of extension with a paradox that can be easily explained based on the reasoning we've just discussed. The paradox is this: if you choose to call the invisible and intangible distance, or in other words, the potential to become a visible and tangible distance, a vacuum, then extension and matter are the same, and yet a vacuum still exists. If you don't call it that, motion is possible in a full space without any continuous push, without looping back around, and without penetrating. But however we phrase it, we must always admit that we have no real understanding of extension without filling it with tangible objects and imagining its parts as visible or touchable.
As to the doctrine, that time is nothing but the manner, in which some real objects exist; we may observe, that it is liable to the same objections as the similar doctrine with regard to extension. If it be a sufficient proof, that we have the idea of a vacuum, because we dispute and reason concerning it; we must for the same reason have the idea of time without any changeable existence; since there is no subject of dispute more frequent and common. But that we really have no such idea, is certain. For whence should it be derived? Does it arise from an impression of sensation or of reflection? Point it out distinctly to us, that we may know its nature and qualities. But if you cannot point out any such impression, you may be certain you are mistaken, when you imagine you have any such idea.
Regarding the idea that time is just the way some real objects exist, we can see that it faces the same issues as the similar idea about space. If having the concept of a vacuum is enough proof because we argue and think about it, then by the same logic, we must also have a concept of time that isn't tied to any changing existence, since it's a topic we often debate. However, it's clear that we really don't have such a concept. Where would it come from? Does it stem from a sensation or from reflection? Clearly identify it for us, so we can understand its nature and qualities. But if you can't pinpoint any such sensation, you can be sure you're mistaken if you think you have such a concept.
But though it be impossible to shew the impression, from which the idea of time without a changeable existence is derived; yet we can easily point out those appearances, which make us fancy we have that idea. For we may observe, that there is a continual succession of perceptions in our mind; so that the idea of time being for ever present with us; when we consider a stedfast object at five-a-clock, and regard the same at six; we are apt to apply to it that idea in the same manner as if every moment were distinguished by a different position, or an alteration of the object. The first and second appearances of the object, being compared with the succession of our perceptions, seem equally removed as if the object had really changed. To which we may add, what experience shews us, that the object was susceptible of such a number of changes betwixt these appearances; as also that the unchangeable or rather fictitious duration has the same effect upon every quality, by encreasing or diminishing it, as that succession, which is obvious to the senses. From these three relations we are apt to confound our ideas, and imagine we can form the idea of a time and duration, without any change or succession.
But even though it's impossible to show the impression that gives rise to the idea of time without a changeable existence, we can easily identify the appearances that lead us to think we have that idea. We can observe a constant flow of perceptions in our minds, so the idea of time feels always present with us. When we look at a stationary object at five o'clock and then again at six, we tend to apply that idea to it as if every moment were marked by a different position or a change in the object. The first and second appearances of the object, when compared to the flow of our perceptions, seem equally distant as if the object had truly changed. We can also add that experience shows us the object could have gone through many changes between these appearances, and that the unchanging or more accurately, fictional duration affects every quality by increasing or decreasing it, just like the succession that is apparent to our senses. From these three relationships, we tend to confuse our ideas and think we can create the idea of time and duration without any change or succession.
SECT. VI. OF THE IDEA OF EXISTENCE, AND OF EXTERNAL EXISTENCE.
It may not be amiss, before we leave this subject, to explain the ideas of existence and of external existence; which have their difficulties, as well as the ideas of space and time. By this means we shall be the better prepared for the examination of knowledge and probability, when we understand perfectly all those particular ideas, which may enter into our reasoning.
It might be helpful, before we wrap up this topic, to clarify the concepts of existence and external existence, as they come with their own challenges, just like the ideas of space and time. Doing this will better prepare us to examine knowledge and probability when we fully grasp all these specific ideas that can influence our reasoning.
There is no impression nor idea of any kind, of which we have any consciousness or memory, that is not conceived as existent; and it is evident, that from this consciousness the most perfect idea and assurance of being is derived. From hence we may form a dilemma, the most clear and conclusive that can be imagined, viz. that since we never remember any idea or impression without attributing existence to it, the idea of existence must either be derived from a distinct impression, conjoined with every perception or object of our thought, or must be the very same with the idea of the perception or object.
There is no impression or idea that we are aware of or remember that doesn’t seem real; it’s clear that from this awareness, we gain the most complete idea and assurance of existence. From this, we can create a very clear and convincing dilemma: since we never recall an idea or impression without attributing existence to it, the idea of existence must either come from a separate impression linked with every perception or object of our thought, or it must be identical to the idea of that perception or object.
As this dilemma is an evident consequence of the principle, that every idea arises from a similar impression, so our decision betwixt the propositions of the dilemma is no more doubtful. So far from there being any distinct impression, attending every impression and every idea, that I do not think there are any two distinct impressions, which are inseparably conjoined. Though certain sensations may at one time be united, we quickly find they admit of a separation, and may be presented apart. And thus, though every impression and idea we remember be considered as existent, the idea of existence is not derived from any particular impression.
This problem clearly comes from the idea that every thought comes from a similar experience, so choosing between the options in this dilemma is not uncertain. There's no specific experience that goes along with every experience and every thought; in fact, I don’t believe there are two separate experiences that are always linked together. While some sensations may be connected at one moment, we soon realize they can be separated and presented individually. Therefore, even though we see every experience and thought as real, the concept of existence doesn’t come from any specific experience.
The idea of existence, then, is the very same with the idea of what we conceive to be existent. To reflect on any thing simply, and to reflect on it as existent, are nothing different from each other. That idea, when conjoined with the idea of any object, makes no addition to it. Whatever we conceive, we conceive to be existent. Any idea we please to form is the idea of a being; and the idea of a being is any idea we please to form.
The concept of existence is the same as what we think of as existing. Thinking about something in general and thinking about it as existing are essentially the same. That idea, when paired with the idea of any object, doesn't change anything. Whatever we imagine, we imagine to be existing. Any idea we want to create is the idea of something that exists; and the idea of something that exists is any idea we want to create.
Whoever opposes this, must necessarily point out that distinct impression, from which the idea of entity is derived, and must prove, that this impression is inseparable from every perception we believe to be existent. This we may without hesitation conclude to be impossible.
Whoever disagrees with this must clearly identify that unique impression from which the concept of an entity comes, and they must show that this impression is inseparable from any perception we consider to be real. We can confidently conclude that this is impossible.
Our foregoing reasoning[7] concerning the distinction of ideas without any real difference will not here serve us in any stead. That kind of distinction is founded on the different resemblances, which the same simple idea may have to several different ideas. But no object can be presented resembling some object with respect to its existence, and different from others in the same particular; since every object, that is presented, must necessarily be existent.
Our earlier reasoning[7] about the difference between ideas that don’t actually differ won’t help us here. That type of distinction is based on how the same simple idea can look similar to several different ideas. But no object can be shown to resemble one object in terms of its existence while differing from others in the same way; since every object that is presented must necessarily exist.
[7] Part I. Sect. 7.
A like reasoning will account for the idea of external existence. We may observe, that it is universally allowed by philosophers, and is besides pretty obvious of itself, that nothing is ever really present with the mind but its perceptions or impressions and ideas, and that external objects become known to us only by those perceptions they occasion. To hate, to love, to think, to feel, to see; all this is nothing but to perceive.
A similar reasoning explains the idea of external existence. It’s widely accepted among philosophers, and it’s quite clear on its own, that nothing is actually present to the mind except for its perceptions, impressions, and ideas, and that we learn about external objects solely through the perceptions they produce. To hate, to love, to think, to feel, to see; all of this is simply a matter of perception.
Now since nothing is ever present to the mind but perceptions, and since all ideas are derived from something antecedently present to the mind; it follows, that it is impossible for us so much as to conceive or form an idea of any thing specifically different from ideas and impressions. Let us fix our attention out of ourselves as much as possible: Let us chase our imagination to the heavens, or to the utmost limits of the universe; we never really advance a step beyond ourselves, nor can conceive any kind of existence, but those perceptions, which have appeared in that narrow compass. This is the universe of the imagination, nor have we any idea but what is there produced.
Now, since we can only be aware of our perceptions, and since all ideas come from something that was already in our minds, it follows that it's impossible for us to even imagine or form an idea of anything that is truly different from ideas and impressions. Let’s try to focus our attention away from ourselves as much as we can: Let’s allow our imagination to reach the heavens or the farthest edges of the universe; we never actually move beyond ourselves, nor can we conceive of any kind of existence other than those perceptions that have appeared within that limited scope. This is the universe of our imagination, and we don’t have any ideas except those that are produced there.
The farthest we can go towards a conception of external objects, when supposed SPECIFICALLY different from our perceptions, is to form a relative idea of them, without pretending to comprehend the related objects. Generally speaking we do not suppose them specifically different; but only attribute to them different relations, connections and durations. But of this more fully hereafter.[8]
The farthest we can get in understanding external objects, when we assume they are specifically different from our perceptions, is to create a relative idea of them, without claiming to fully understand the actual objects. Generally, we don't think of them as specifically different; we just attribute different relationships, connections, and durations to them. But we'll cover this in more detail later.[8]
[8] Part IV, Sect. 2.
SECT. I. OF KNOWLEDGE.
There are seven[1] different kinds of philosophical relation, viz. RESEMBLANCE, IDENTITY, RELATIONS OF TIME AND PLACE, PROPORTION IN QUANTITY OR NUMBER, DEGREES IN ANY QUALITY, CONTRARIETY and CAUSATION. These relations may be divided into two classes; into such as depend entirely on the ideas, which we compare together, and such as may be changed without any change in the ideas. It is from the idea of a triangle, that we discover the relation of equality, which its three angles bear to two right ones; and this relation is invariable, as long as our idea remains the same. On the contrary, the relations of contiguity and distance betwixt two objects may be changed merely by an alteration of their place, without any change on the objects themselves or on their ideas; and the place depends on a hundred different accidents, which cannot be foreseen by the mind. It is the same case with identity and causation. Two objects, though perfectly resembling each other, and even appearing in the same place at different times, may be numerically different: And as the power, by which one object produces another, is never discoverable merely from their idea, it is evident cause and effect are relations, of which we receive information from experience, and not from any abstract reasoning or reflection. There is no single phænomenon, even the most simple, which can be accounted for from the qualities of the objects, as they appear to us; or which we could foresee without the help of our memory and experience.
There are seven[1] different types of philosophical relationships: RESEMBLANCE, IDENTITY, RELATIONS OF TIME AND PLACE, PROPORTION IN QUANTITY OR NUMBER, DEGREES IN ANY QUALITY, CONTRADICTION, and CAUSATION. These relationships can be divided into two categories: those that rely entirely on the ideas we compare and those that can change without altering the ideas themselves. From the concept of a triangle, we find the relationship of equality that its three angles have to two right angles; this relationship stays the same as long as our concept doesn't change. In contrast, the relationships of proximity and distance between two objects can change simply by moving their position, without any change to the objects themselves or their ideas; and the position depends on many different factors that the mind cannot predict. The same is true for identity and causation. Two objects, even if they look exactly alike and appear in the same place at different times, can still be numerically different. And since the power by which one object produces another cannot be figured out just from their idea, it's clear that cause and effect are relationships we learn about through experience, not from abstract reasoning or reflection. There is no single phenomenon, even the simplest one, that can be explained by the qualities of the objects as they appear to us, or that we could predict without the help of our memory and experience.
[1] Part I. Sect. 5.
It appears, therefore, that of these seven philosophical relations, there remain only four, which depending solely upon ideas, can be the objects of knowledge and certainty. These four are RESEMBLANCE, CONTRARIETY, DEGREES IN QUALITY, and PROPORTIONS IN QUANTITY OR NUMBER. Three of these relations are discoverable at first sight, and fall more properly under the province of intuition than demonstration. When any objects resemble each other, the resemblance will at first strike the eye, or rather the mind; and seldom requires a second examination. The case is the same with contrariety, and with the degrees of any quality. No one can once doubt but existence and non-existence destroy each other, and are perfectly incompatible and contrary. And though it be impossible to judge exactly of the degrees of any quality, such as colour, taste, heat, cold, when the difference betwixt them is very small: yet it is easy to decide, that any of them is superior or inferior to another, when their difference is considerable. And this decision we always pronounce at first sight, without any enquiry or reasoning.
It seems, then, that of these seven philosophical relationships, only four remain that are purely based on ideas and can be the objects of knowledge and certainty. These four are RESEMBLANCE, CONTRARIETY, DEGREES IN QUALITY, and PROPORTIONS IN QUANTITY OR NUMBER. Three of these relationships are immediately noticeable and are better understood through intuition rather than demonstration. When objects resemble each other, the similarity is usually apparent at first glance, or rather in the mind; it rarely needs a second look. The same goes for contrariety and the degrees of any quality. No one can doubt that existence and non-existence conflict with each other and are completely incompatible and opposed. Although it’s impossible to judge precisely the degrees of qualities like color, taste, heat, or cold when the differences are minimal, it’s easy to determine when one is superior or inferior to another when their differences are significant. We make this judgment immediately, without any need for further inquiry or reasoning.
We might proceed, after the same manner, in fixing the proportions of quantity or number, and might at one view observe a superiority or inferiority betwixt any numbers, or figures; especially where the difference is very great and remarkable. As to equality or any exact proportion, we can only guess at it from a single consideration; except in very short numbers, or very limited portions of extension; which are comprehended in an instant, and where we perceive an impossibility of falling into any considerable error. In all other cases we must settle the proportions with some liberty, or proceed in a more artificial manner.
We can also determine the proportions of quantity or number in the same way, allowing us to see a superiority or inferiority between any numbers or figures, especially when the difference is significant and noticeable. When it comes to equality or any precise proportion, we can only estimate it based on a single factor, except in very short numbers or very limited measures, which we can grasp instantly and where it’s clear we can't make a major error. In all other situations, we have to adjust the proportions more freely or follow a more complicated process.
I have already observed, that geometry, or the art, by which we fix the proportions of figures; though it much excels both in universality and exactness, the loose judgments of the senses and imagination; yet never attains a perfect precision and exactness. It's first principles are still drawn from the general appearance of the objects; and that appearance can never afford us any security, when we examine, the prodigious minuteness of which nature is susceptible. Our ideas seem to give a perfect assurance, that no two right lines can have a common segment; but if we consider these ideas, we shall find, that they always suppose a sensible inclination of the two lines, and that where the angle they form is extremely small, we have no standard of a I @ right line so precise as to assure us of the truth of this proposition. It is the same case with most of the primary decisions of the mathematics.
I've noticed that geometry, or the art of defining the proportions of shapes, although it significantly surpasses the loose judgments of our senses and imagination in both universality and precision, still doesn't achieve perfect accuracy. Its fundamental principles are derived from the general appearance of objects, and that appearance can never guarantee us certainty when we examine the incredible detail that nature can possess. Our ideas seem to confidently assert that no two straight lines can share a common segment; however, upon examining these ideas, we find that they always assume a noticeable angle between the two lines, and when that angle is very small, we lack a precise standard for a straight line that can guarantee the truth of this statement. The same applies to most of the basic conclusions in mathematics.
There remain, therefore, algebra and arithmetic as the only sciences, in which we can carry on a chain of reasoning to any degree of intricacy, and yet preserve a perfect exactness and certainty. We are possest of a precise standard, by which we can judge of the equality and proportion of numbers; and according as they correspond or not to that standard, we determine their relations, without any possibility of error. When two numbers are so combined, as that the one has always an unite answering to every unite of the other, we pronounce them equal; and it is for want of such a standard of equality in extension, that geometry can scarce be esteemed a perfect and infallible science.
There are still only two sciences, algebra and arithmetic, where we can follow a line of reasoning to any level of complexity while maintaining perfect accuracy and certainty. We have a clear standard that allows us to assess the equality and proportion of numbers. Based on whether they meet that standard, we determine their relationships without the risk of making a mistake. When two numbers are combined in such a way that one has a unit corresponding to every unit of the other, we say they are equal. It is the absence of such a standard for equality in extension that prevents geometry from being considered a flawless and completely reliable science.
But here it may not be amiss to obviate a difficulty, which may arise from my asserting, that though geometry falls short of that perfect precision and certainty, which are peculiar to arithmetic and algebra, yet it excels the imperfect judgments of our senses and imagination. The reason why I impute any defect to geometry, is, because its original and fundamental principles are derived merely from appearances; and it may perhaps be imagined, that this defect must always attend it, and keep it from ever reaching a greater exactness in the comparison of objects or ideas, than what our eye or imagination alone is able to attain. I own that this defect so far attends it, as to keep it from ever aspiring to a full certainty: But since these fundamental principles depend on the easiest and least deceitful appearances, they bestow on their consequences a degree of exactness, of which these consequences are singly incapable. It is impossible for the eye to determine the angles of a chiliagon to be equal to 1996 right angles, or make any conjecture, that approaches this proportion; but when it determines, that right lines cannot concur; that we cannot draw more than one right line between two given points; it's mistakes can never be of any consequence. And this is the nature and use of geometry, to run us up to such appearances, as, by reason of their simplicity, cannot lead us into any considerable error.
But it might be helpful to address a challenge that comes up when I claim that, even though geometry doesn’t achieve the perfect precision and certainty that arithmetic and algebra do, it is still better than the flawed judgments of our senses and imagination. The reason I point out any shortcomings in geometry is that its basic principles come solely from appearances. Some might think that this limitation will always affect geometry and prevent it from achieving more accuracy in comparing objects or ideas than what our eyes or imagination can achieve on their own. I admit that this flaw does limit geometry from ever reaching complete certainty. However, since these fundamental principles are based on the simplest and least misleading appearances, they give a degree of precision to their outcomes that those outcomes could never achieve alone. The eye cannot determine that the angles of a chiliagon equal 1996 right angles or even guess close to that ratio. But when it observes that straight lines can’t meet or that there can only be one straight line between two points, any mistakes made can never be significant. This is the essence and purpose of geometry: to guide us to such appearances that, because of their simplicity, won’t lead us into major errors.
I shall here take occasion to propose a second observation concerning our demonstrative reasonings, which is suggested by the same subject of the mathematics. It is usual with mathematicians, to pretend, that those ideas, which are their objects, are of so refined and spiritual a nature, that they fall not under the conception of the fancy, but must be comprehended by a pure and intellectual view, of which the superior faculties of the soul are alone capable. The same notion runs through most parts of philosophy, and is principally made use of to explain oar abstract ideas, and to shew how we can form an idea of a triangle, for instance, which shall neither be an isoceles nor scalenum, nor be confined to any particular length and proportion of sides. It is easy to see, why philosophers are so fond of this notion of some spiritual and refined perceptions; since by that means they cover many of their absurdities, and may refuse to submit to the decisions of clear ideas, by appealing to such as are obscure and uncertain. But to destroy this artifice, we need but reflect on that principle so oft insisted on, that all our ideas are copyed from our impressions. For from thence we may immediately conclude, that since all impressions are clear and precise, the ideas, which are copyed from them, must be of the same nature, and can never, but from our fault, contain any thing so dark and intricate. An idea is by its very nature weaker and fainter than an impression; but being in every other respect the same, cannot imply any very great mystery. If its weakness render it obscure, it is our business to remedy that defect, as much as possible, by keeping the idea steady and precise; and till we have done so, it is in vain to pretend to reasoning and philosophy.
I want to take this opportunity to make a second observation about our logical reasoning, inspired by the same topic in mathematics. Mathematicians often claim that the concepts they work with are so refined and abstract that they cannot be understood through imagination but must be grasped through a clear and intellectual perspective, which only the higher faculties of the mind can achieve. This idea is prevalent throughout much of philosophy and is mainly used to explain our abstract concepts, demonstrating how we can form an idea of a triangle, for example, that isn’t specifically an isosceles or scalene triangle, nor limited to any particular size or proportion of sides. It’s easy to understand why philosophers are drawn to this idea of spiritual and refined perceptions; it allows them to mask many of their inconsistencies and avoid clear conclusions by referring to ideas that are vague and uncertain. However, to debunk this tactic, we just need to remember the principle that all our ideas come from our impressions. From this, we can directly conclude that since all impressions are clear and specific, the ideas derived from them must be of the same nature and should never, except through our own shortcomings, contain anything overly confusing or intricate. By nature, an idea is weaker and less vivid than an impression, but since they are essentially the same, there can't be any significant mystery involved. If its weakness makes it unclear, it's our responsibility to improve that issue as much as possible by keeping the idea steady and specific; until we do that, it’s pointless to claim we are engaging in reasoning and philosophy.
SECT. II. OF PROBABILITY, AND OF THE IDEA OF CAUSE AND EFFECT.
This is all I think necessary to observe concerning those four relations, which are the foundation of science; but as to the other three, which depend not upon the idea, and may be absent or present even while that remains the same, it will be proper to explain them more particularly. These three relations are identity, the situations in time and place, and causation.
This is all I believe is important to note about those four relationships, which are the basis of science; however, regarding the other three, which do not rely on the idea and can exist or not exist even if the idea stays the same, it makes sense to explain them in more detail. These three relationships are identity, the locations in time and space, and causation.
All kinds of reasoning consist in nothing but a comparison, and a discovery of those relations, either constant or inconstant, which two or more objects bear to each other. This comparison we may make, either when both the objects are present to the senses, or when neither of them is present, or when only one. When both the objects are present to the senses along with the relation, we call this perception rather than reasoning; nor is there in this case any exercise of the thought, or any action, properly speaking, but a mere passive admission of the impressions through the organs of sensation. According to this way of thinking, we ought not to receive as reasoning any of the observations we may make concerning identity, and the relations of time and place; since in none of them the mind can go beyond what is immediately present to the senses, either to discover the real existence or the relations of objects. It is only causation, which produces such a connexion, as to give us assurance from the existence or action of one object, that it was followed or preceded by any other existence or action; nor can the other two relations be ever made use of in reasoning, except so far as they either affect or are affected by it. There is nothing in any objects to perswade us, that they are either always remote or always contiguous; and when from experience and observation we discover, that their relation in this particular is invariable, we, always conclude there is some secret cause, which separates or unites them. The same reasoning extends to identity. We readily suppose an object may continue individually the same, though several times absent from and present to the senses; and ascribe to it an identity, notwithstanding the interruption of the perception, whenever we conclude, that if we had kept our eye or hand constantly upon it, it would have conveyed an invariable and uninterrupted perception. But this conclusion beyond the impressions of our senses can be founded only on the connexion of cause and effect; nor can we otherwise have any security, that the object is not changed upon us, however much the new object may resemble that which was formerly present to the senses. Whenever we discover such a perfect resemblance, we consider, whether it be common in that species of objects; whether possibly or probably any cause could operate in producing the change and resemblance; and according as we determine concerning these causes and effects, we form our judgment concerning the identity of the object.
All types of reasoning are basically about comparing and discovering the relationships, whether constant or variable, between two or more objects. We can make this comparison when both objects are present to our senses, when neither is present, or when only one is. When both objects and the relationship between them are perceived directly, we call it perception instead of reasoning; in this case, there’s no real thought or action involved, just a passive reception of impressions through our senses. According to this way of thinking, we shouldn't consider any observations about identity and the relationships of time and place as reasoning, since the mind can't go beyond what’s immediately perceptible through the senses to uncover the actual existence or relationships of objects. Only causation creates a connection that assures us that one object's existence or action was followed or preceded by another. The other two types of relationships can only be used in reasoning if they impact or are impacted by causation. There’s nothing inherent in any objects to convince us that they are either always separate or always together; when we notice through experience and observation that their relationship is consistent, we assume there’s some hidden cause that separates or connects them. The same logic applies to identity. We typically assume an object can remain the same individual entity, even if it’s sometimes absent from and present to our senses, and we attribute an identity to it, despite gaps in our perception, whenever we conclude that if we had kept constant watch over it, the perception would have been steady and uninterrupted. But this conclusion, stretching beyond our sensory impressions, can only be supported by the connection of cause and effect; otherwise, we can’t be sure that the object hasn’t changed, no matter how much the new object resembles the one we previously perceived. Whenever we find such a perfect resemblance, we consider whether it’s common among that type of objects, or whether there could be a cause that might have led to both the change and the resemblance; based on our assessment of these causes and effects, we form our judgment about the object’s identity.
Here then it appears, that of those three relations, which depend not upon the mere ideas, the only one, that can be traced beyond our senses and informs us of existences and objects, which we do not see or feel, is causation. This relation, therefore, we shall endeavour to explain fully before we leave the subject of the understanding.
Here it seems that out of those three relationships, which are not just based on our ideas, the only one that goes beyond our senses and tells us about existences and objects that we cannot see or feel is causation. Therefore, we will try to explain this relationship thoroughly before we finish discussing understanding.
To begin regularly, we must consider the idea of causation, and see from what origin it is derived. It is impossible to reason justly, without understanding perfectly the idea concerning which we reason; and it is impossible perfectly to understand any idea, without tracing it up to its origin, and examining that primary impression, from which it arises. The examination of the impression bestows a clearness on the idea; and the examination of the idea bestows a like clearness on all our reasoning.
To start regularly, we need to think about the concept of causation and determine where it comes from. It's impossible to reason correctly without fully understanding the concept we're reasoning about, and we can't fully understand any idea without tracing it back to its origin and examining that initial impression from which it comes. Looking into the impression gives clarity to the idea, and examining the idea adds clarity to all our reasoning.
Let us therefore cast our eye on any two objects, which we call cause and effect, and turn them on all sides, in order to find that impression, which produces an idea, of such prodigious consequence. At first sight I perceive, that I must not search for it in any of the particular qualities of the objects; since which-ever of these qualities I pitch on, I find some object, that is not possessed of it, and yet falls under the denomination of cause or effect. And indeed there is nothing existent, either externally or internally, which is not to be considered either as a cause or an effect; though it is plain there is no one quality, which universally belongs to all beings, and gives them a title to that denomination.
Let's take a look at any two things we label as cause and effect, and examine them from all angles to find the impression that leads to such a significant idea. At first glance, I see that I shouldn't look for it in the specific qualities of the objects; no matter which quality I focus on, I find another object that lacks it but is still considered a cause or an effect. In fact, there’s nothing that exists, whether outside or inside, that isn’t seen as either a cause or an effect, yet it’s clear there’s no single quality that universally applies to all things, giving them that label.
The idea, then, of causation must be derived from some relation among objects; and that relation we must now endeavour to discover. I find in the first place, that whatever objects are considered as causes or effects, are contiguous; and that nothing can operate in a time or place, which is ever so little removed from those of its existence. Though distant objects may sometimes seem productive of each other, they are commonly found upon examination to be linked by a chain of causes, which are contiguous among themselves, and to the distant objects; and when in any particular instance we cannot discover this connexion, we still presume it to exist. We may therefore consider the relation of CONTIGUITY as essential to that of causation; at least may suppose it such, according to the general opinion, till we can find a more[2] proper occasion to clear up this matter, by examining what objects are or are not susceptible of juxtaposition and conjunction.
The concept of causation must come from some relationship between objects, and now we need to figure that relationship out. First, I've noticed that whatever objects are seen as causes or effects are adjacent to each other, and nothing can have an effect in a time or place that is even slightly separate from where it exists. Although distant objects might sometimes appear to cause one another, they usually end up being connected by a chain of causes that are close to each other and to the distant objects. When we can't find this connection in a specific case, we still assume it exists. Therefore, we can view the relationship of CONTIGUITY as crucial to causation; at least we can assume it is, according to general belief, until we get a better chance to clarify this issue by looking at which objects can or cannot be next to each other and combined.
[2] Part IV. Sect. 5.
The second relation I shall observe as essential to causes and effects, is not so universally acknowledged, but is liable to some controversy. It is that of PRIORITY Of time in the cause before the effect. Some pretend that it is not absolutely necessary a cause should precede its effect; but that any object or action, in the very first moment of its existence, may exert its productive quality, and give rise to another object or action, perfectly co-temporary with itself. But beside that experience in most instances seems to contradict this opinion, we may establish the relation of priority by a kind of inference or reasoning. It is an established maxim both in natural and moral philosophy, that an object, which exists for any time in its full perfection without producing another, is not its sole cause; but is assisted by some other principle, which pushes it from its state of inactivity, and makes it exert that energy, of which it was secretly possest. Now if any cause may be perfectly co-temporary with its effect, it is certain, according to this maxim, that they must all of them be so; since any one of them, which retards its operation for a single moment, exerts not itself at that very individual time, in which it might have operated; and therefore is no proper cause. The consequence of this would be no less than the destruction of that succession of causes, which we observe in the world; and indeed, the utter annihilation of time. For if one cause were co-temporary with its effect, and this effect with its effect, and so on, it is plain there would be no such thing as succession, and all objects must be co-existent.
The second relationship I’ll discuss that’s essential to causes and effects isn’t as widely accepted and is somewhat controversial. It’s the idea of TIME PRIORITY in which the cause comes before the effect. Some argue that it's not absolutely necessary for a cause to precede its effect; they believe that any object or action, at the very first moment of its existence, can exert its productive quality and create another object or action that exists at the same time as it does. However, aside from the fact that experience often contradicts this view, we can establish the relationship of priority through reasoning. It’s a well-accepted principle in both natural and moral philosophy that an object which exists in its full perfection for some time without producing another is not its sole cause; instead, it’s influenced by another principle that pushes it out of its inactive state and makes it exhibit the energy it possesses. If any cause could exist at the same time as its effect, then, according to this principle, they would all have to; since any one of them that delays its action for even a moment isn’t acting at that specific time when it could have. Therefore, it cannot be a proper cause. The implication of this would be nothing less than the collapse of the chain of causes we see in the world and ultimately, the total destruction of time. If one cause existed simultaneously with its effect, and that effect with its subsequent effect, and so forth, it’s clear there would be no concept of succession, and all objects would have to exist together.
If this argument appear satisfactory, it is well. If not, I beg the reader to allow me the same liberty, which I have used in the preceding case, of supposing it such. For he shall find, that the affair is of no great importance.
If this argument seems satisfactory, that's great. If it doesn't, I ask the reader to give me the same freedom I used earlier, to assume it is. For he will find that the matter is not very important.
Having thus discovered or supposed the two relations of contiguity and succession to be essential to causes and effects, I find I am stopt short, and can proceed no farther in considering any single instance of cause and effect. Motion in one body is regarded upon impulse as the cause of motion in another. When we consider these objects with utmost attention, we find only that the one body approaches the other; and that the motion of it precedes that of the other, but without any, sensible interval. It is in vain to rack ourselves with farther thought and reflection upon this subject. We can go no farther in considering this particular instance.
Having discovered or assumed that the two relationships of closeness and sequence are essential to causes and effects, I find myself at a standstill and unable to explore any single instance of cause and effect further. Motion in one object is seen as the cause of motion in another when there is an impulse. When we look closely at these objects, we find only that one body moves toward the other, and that its motion comes before the other’s, but without any noticeable delay. It's pointless to stress ourselves with more thought and reflection on this topic. We cannot go deeper into this specific instance.
Should any one leave this instance, and pretend to define a cause, by saying it is something productive of another, it is evident he would say nothing. For what does he mean by production? Can he give any definition of it, that will not be the same with that of causation? If he can; I desire it may be produced. If he cannot; he here runs in a circle, and gives a synonimous term instead of a definition.
If anyone tries to walk away from this situation and claims to define a cause by saying it’s something that produces another thing, it’s clear they wouldn’t be saying anything meaningful. What do they even mean by production? Can they provide a definition that isn’t just the same as causation? If they can, I’d like to see it. If they can’t, then they’re just going in circles and offering a synonym instead of a real definition.
Shall we then rest contented with these two relations of contiguity and succession, as affording a complete idea of causation? By, no means. An object may be contiguous and prior to another, without being considered as its cause. There is a NECESSARY CONNEXION to be taken into consideration; and that relation is of much greater importance, than any of the other two above-mentioned.
Should we be satisfied with just these two relationships of proximity and sequence as a complete understanding of causation? Absolutely not. An object can be next to another and come before it without being seen as its cause. There is a NECESSARY CONNECTION that must be considered, and this relationship is much more important than the other two mentioned above.
Here again I turn the object on all sides, in order to discover the nature of this necessary connexion, and find the impression, or impressions, from which its idea may be derived. When I cast my eye on the known Qualities of objects, I immediately discover that the relation of cause and effect depends not in the least on them. When I consider their relations, I can find none but those of contiguity and succession; which I have already regarded as imperfect and unsatisfactory. Shall the despair of success make me assert, that I am here possest of an idea, which is not preceded by any similar impression? This would be too strong a proof of levity and inconstancy; since the contrary principle has been already so firmly established, as to admit of no farther doubt; at least, till we have more fully examined the present difficulty.
Here I am again, turning the object around to figure out the nature of this necessary connection and find the impression, or impressions, that could lead to its idea. When I look at the known qualities of objects, I quickly realize that the relationship of cause and effect doesn’t depend on them at all. When I think about their relationships, the only ones I can find are those of closeness and sequence, which I’ve already considered incomplete and unsatisfactory. Should I let my frustration with not succeeding lead me to claim that I have an idea that doesn’t follow from any similar impression? That would be too strong a sign of thoughtlessness and inconsistency, especially since the opposite principle has already been firmly established, leaving no room for doubt; at least until we have thoroughly examined the current challenge.
We must, therefore, proceed like those, who being in search of any thing, that lies concealed from them, and not finding it in the place they expected, beat about all the neighbouring fields, without any certain view or design, in hopes their good fortune will at last guide them to what they search for. It is necessary for us to leave the direct survey of this question concerning the nature of that necessary connexion, which enters into our idea of cause and effect; and endeavour to find some other questions, the examination of which will perhaps afford a hint, that may serve to clear up the present difficulty. Of these questions there occur two, which I shall proceed to examine, viz.
We should, therefore, approach this like those who are searching for something hidden from them. When they can't find it where they expected, they explore all the nearby areas without a clear plan, hoping that luck will eventually lead them to what they're looking for. We need to set aside the straightforward examination of this question about the essential connection that shapes our understanding of cause and effect, and instead try to find other questions that might provide a clue to help clarify the current issue. Among these questions, there are two that I will examine, namely:
First, For what reason we pronounce it necessary, that every thing whose existence has a beginning, should also have a cause.
First, we believe it's essential that everything that comes into existence must also have a cause.
Secondly, Why we conclude, that such particular causes must necessarily have such particular effects; and what is the nature of that inference we draw from the one to the other, and of the belief we repose in it?
Secondly, why do we conclude that specific causes must lead to specific effects? What is the nature of the inference we make from one to the other, and what do we believe about it?
I shall only observe before I proceed any farther, that though the ideas of cause and effect be derived from the impressions of reflection as well as from those of sensation, yet for brevity's sake, I commonly mention only the latter as the origin of these ideas; though I desire that whatever I say of them may also extend to the former. Passions are connected with their objects and with one another; no less than external bodies are connected together. The same relation, then, of cause and effect, which belongs to one, must be common to all of them.
I just want to note before I go any further that while the concepts of cause and effect come from both reflective impressions and sensory experiences, for the sake of simplicity, I usually refer only to the latter as the source of these concepts; however, I intend for everything I say about them to also apply to the former. Emotions are linked to their objects and to each other, just like external things are connected. Therefore, the same relationship of cause and effect that applies to one should apply to all of them.
SECT. III. WHY A CAUSE IS ALWAYS NECESSARY.
To begin with the first question concerning the necessity of a cause: It is a general maxim in philosophy, that whatever begins to exist, must have a cause of existence. This is commonly taken for granted in all reasonings, without any proof given or demanded. It is supposed to be founded on intuition, and to be one of those maxims, which though they may be denyed with the lips, it is impossible for men in their hearts really to doubt of. But if we examine this maxim by the idea of knowledge above-explained, we shall discover in it no mark of any such intuitive certainty; but on the contrary shall find, that it is of a nature quite foreign to that species of conviction.
To start with the first question about whether a cause is necessary: There’s a common saying in philosophy that anything that begins to exist must have a cause for its existence. This is usually taken for granted in all reasoning, with no proof offered or required. It’s believed to be based on intuition and is one of those principles that, although people might deny it verbally, it's impossible for anyone to truly doubt in their hearts. However, if we look at this principle through the lens of the idea of knowledge mentioned earlier, we won’t find any sign of such intuitive certainty; instead, we’ll see that it’s fundamentally different from that kind of conviction.
All certainty arises from the comparison of ideas, and from the discovery of such relations as are unalterable, so long as the ideas continue the same. These relations are RESEMBLANCE, PROPORTIONS IN QUANTITY AND NUMBER, DEGREES OF ANY QUALITY, and CONTRARIETY; none of which are implyed in this proposition, Whatever has a beginning has also a cause of existence. That proposition therefore is not intuitively certain. At least any one, who would assert it to be intuitively certain, must deny these to be the only infallible relations, and must find some other relation of that kind to be implyed in it; which it will then be time enough to examine.
All certainty comes from comparing ideas and discovering unchangeable relationships, as long as the ideas remain the same. These relationships are RESEMBLANCE, PROPORTIONS IN QUANTITY AND NUMBER, DEGREES OF ANY QUALITY, and CONTRADICTION; none of which are implied in this statement: Whatever has a beginning also has a cause for existing. Therefore, that statement isn’t intuitively certain. Anyone who claims it is intuitively certain would have to deny that these are the only reliable relationships and must identify some other similar relationship implied in it; then we can examine it.
But here is an argument, which proves at once, that the foregoing proposition is neither intuitively nor demonstrably certain. We can never demonstrate the necessity of a cause to every new existence, or new modification of existence, without shewing at the same time the impossibility there is, that any thing can ever begin to exist without some productive principle; and where the latter proposition cannot be proved, we must despair of ever being able to prove the former. Now that the latter proposition is utterly incapable of a demonstrative proof, we may satisfy ourselves by considering that as all distinct ideas are separable from each other, and as the ideas of cause and effect are evidently distinct, it will be easy for us to conceive any object to be non-existent this moment, and existent the next, without conjoining to it the distinct idea of a cause or productive principle. The separation, therefore, of the idea of a cause from that of a beginning of existence, is plainly possible for the imagination; and consequently the actual separation of these objects is so far possible, that it implies no contradiction nor absurdity; and is therefore incapable of being refuted by any reasoning from mere ideas; without which it is impossible to demonstrate the necessity of a cause.
But here's an argument that shows right away that the previous statement is neither intuitively nor demonstrably certain. We can never prove that a cause is necessary for every new existence or new change in existence without simultaneously showing that it’s impossible for anything to begin to exist without some kind of productive principle. And if we can't prove that, we shouldn't expect to prove the first statement. Since the idea that something can begin to exist without a cause is completely unprovable, we can look at it this way: all distinct ideas can be separated from one another, and the ideas of cause and effect are clearly different. So, it's easy for us to imagine that an object does not exist one moment and then does exist the next, without linking it to the distinct idea of a cause or productive principle. Therefore, separating the idea of a cause from that of the beginning of existence is clearly possible in our imagination. As a result, the actual separation of these concepts is possible in a way that doesn’t imply any contradiction or absurdity, and thus cannot be refuted by reasoning based solely on ideas; without which, it is impossible to demonstrate the necessity of a cause.
Accordingly we shall find upon examination, that every demonstration, which has been produced for the necessity of a cause, is fallacious and sophistical. All the points of time and place, say some philosophers,[3] in which we can suppose any object to begin to exist, are in themselves equal; and unless there be some cause, which is peculiar to one time and to one place, and which by that means determines and fixes the existence, it must remain in eternal suspence; and the object can never begin to be, for want of something to fix its beginning. But I ask; Is there any more difficulty in supposing the time and place to be fixed without a cause, than to suppose the existence to be determined in that manner? The first question that occurs on this subject is always, whether the object shall exist or not: The next, when and where it shall begin to exist. If the removal of a cause be intuitively absurd in the one case, it must be so in the other: And if that absurdity be not clear without a proof in the one case, it will equally require one in the other. The absurdity, then, of the one supposition can never be a proof of that of the other; since they are both upon the same footing, and must stand or fall by the same reasoning.
As we examine this, we will find that every argument made for the necessity of a cause is misleading and deceptive. Some philosophers argue that all the points in time and place where we can think of an object starting to exist are equal. Unless there’s a specific cause tied to a particular time and place that determines and fixes its existence, it would remain in a state of eternal uncertainty; the object could never actually begin to exist because there would be nothing to establish its start. But I ask: Is it more challenging to assume that the time and place are set without a cause than it is to assume that existence itself is determined in this way? The first question that comes up is always whether the object will exist or not. The next question is about when and where it will start to exist. If removing a cause seems obviously unreasonable in one case, it must be unreasonable in the other as well. And if that unreasonableness isn’t immediately clear in one case without proof, it will also require proof in the other. Therefore, the ridiculousness of one assumption cannot serve as proof of the ridiculousness of the other since they are on equal grounds and must be supported or rejected by the same reasoning.
[3] Mr. Hobbes.
The second argument,[4] which I find used on this head, labours under an equal difficulty. Every thing, it is said, must have a cause; for if any thing wanted a cause, it would produce ITSELF; that is, exist before it existed; which is impossible. But this reasoning is plainly unconclusive; because it supposes, that in our denial of a cause we still grant what we expressly deny, viz. that there must be a cause; which therefore is taken to be the object itself; and that, no doubt, is an evident contradiction. But to say that any thing is produced, or to express myself more properly, comes into existence, without a cause, is not to affirm, that it is itself its own cause; but on the contrary in excluding all external causes, excludes a fortiori the thing itself, which is created. An object, that exists absolutely without any cause, certainly is not its own cause; and when you assert, that the one follows from the other, you suppose the very point in questions and take it for granted, that it is utterly impossible any thing can ever begin to exist without a cause, but that, upon the exclusion of one productive principle, we must still have recourse to another.
The second argument, [4] which I see used on this topic, has the same issue. It's said that everything must have a cause; because if something didn't have a cause, it would have to create itself, meaning it would exist before it existed, which is impossible. But this reasoning clearly doesn't hold up; it assumes that in denying a cause, we still accept what we’re denying, namely that there must be a cause, which is taken to be the very thing itself; and that, of course, is a clear contradiction. To say that something is produced, or to put it more accurately, comes into existence without a cause, doesn't mean that it is its own cause; rather, by excluding all external causes, it also excludes the created thing itself. An object that exists entirely without any cause certainly isn't its own cause; and when you claim that one follows from the other, you are assuming the very point in question and taking for granted that it is completely impossible for anything to begin to exist without a cause, suggesting that if we rule out one source, we must look to another.
[4] Dr. Clarke and others.
Dr. Clarke and others.
It is exactly the same case with the third argument,[5] which has been employed to demonstrate the necessity of a cause. Whatever is produced without any cause, is produced by nothing; or in other words, has nothing for its cause. But nothing can never be a cause, no more than it can be something, or equal to two right angles. By the same intuition, that we perceive nothing not to be equal to two right angles, or not to be something, we perceive, that it can never be a cause; and consequently must perceive, that every object has a real cause of its existence.
It’s the same with the third argument, [5] which has been used to show the need for a cause. Anything that comes into being without a cause comes from nothing; in other words, it has nothing as its cause. But nothing can’t be a cause, just as it can’t be something, or equal to two right angles. Just as we understand that nothing isn’t equal to two right angles, or isn’t something, we also understand that it can never be a cause; therefore, we must recognize that every object has a real cause for its existence.
[5] Mr. Locke.
Mr. Locke.
I believe it will not be necessary to employ many words in shewing the weakness of this argument, after what I have said of the foregoing. They are all of them founded on the same fallacy, and are derived from the same turn of thought. It is sufficient only to observe, that when we exclude all causes we really do exclude them, and neither suppose nothing nor the object itself to be the causes of the existence; and consequently can draw no argument from the absurdity of these suppositions to prove the absurdity of that exclusion. If every thing must have a cause, it follows, that upon the exclusion of other causes we must accept of the object itself or of nothing as causes. But it is the very point in question, whether every thing must have a cause or not; and therefore, according to all just reasoning, it ought never to be taken for granted.
I think it won't take many words to demonstrate the weakness of this argument, especially after what I’ve already said about the previous points. They all rely on the same fallacy and stem from the same way of thinking. It's enough to note that when we exclude all causes, we really do exclude them—neither assuming nothing nor the object itself to be the cause of its existence. Therefore, we can't use the absurdity of these assumptions to prove the absurdity of that exclusion. If everything must have a cause, then when we rule out other causes, we must accept either the object itself or nothing as the cause. But this is the very issue we're debating: whether everything must have a cause or not; and so, based on sound reasoning, it should never simply be taken for granted.
They are still more frivolous, who say, that every effect must have a cause, because it is implyed in the very idea of effect. Every effect necessarily pre-supposes a cause; effect being a relative term, of which cause is the correlative. But this does not prove, that every being must be preceded by a cause; no more than it follows, because every husband must have a wife, that therefore every man must be marryed. The true state of the question is, whether every object, which begins to exist, must owe its existence to a cause: and this I assert neither to be intuitively nor demonstratively certain, and hope to have proved it sufficiently by the foregoing arguments.
They are even more superficial who claim that every effect must have a cause because it's implied in the very concept of effect. Every effect necessarily assumes a cause; effect is a relative term, with cause being its counterpart. However, this doesn't prove that every being must be preceded by a cause, just as it doesn't follow that because every husband must have a wife, every man must be married. The real issue is whether every object that comes into existence must derive its existence from a cause: and I assert that this is neither intuitively nor demonstratively certain, and I hope to have sufficiently proven it with the arguments I've presented.
Since it is not from knowledge or any scientific reasoning, that we derive the opinion of the necessity of a cause to every new production, that opinion must necessarily arise from observation and experience. The next question, then, should naturally be, how experience gives rise to such a principle? But as I find it will be more convenient to sink this question in the following, Why we conclude, that such particular causes must necessarily have such particular erects, and why we form an inference from one to another? we shall make that the subject of our future enquiry. It will, perhaps, be found in the end, that the same answer will serve for both questions.
Since our belief in the necessity of a cause for every new occurrence doesn't come from knowledge or scientific reasoning, it must stem from observation and experience. The next question should naturally be how experience leads to this principle. However, I think it's more convenient to combine this question with the following one: Why do we conclude that specific causes must have specific effects, and why do we infer one from the other? We will make that the focus of our future inquiry. In the end, it may turn out that the same answer applies to both questions.
SECT. IV. OF THE COMPONENT PARTS OF OUR REASONINGS CONCERNING CAUSE AND EFFECT.
Though the mind in its reasonings from causes or effects carries its view beyond those objects, which it sees or remembers, it must never lose sight of them entirely, nor reason merely upon its own ideas, without some mixture of impressions, or at least of ideas of the memory, which are equivalent to impressions. When we infer effects from causes, we must establish the existence of these causes; which we have only two ways of doing, either by an immediate perception of our memory or senses, or by an inference from other causes; which causes again we must ascertain in the same manner, either by a present impression, or by an inference from their causes, and so on, till we arrive at some object, which we see or remember. It is impossible for us to carry on our inferences IN INFINITUM; and the only thing, that can stop them, is an impression of the memory or senses, beyond which there is no room for doubt or enquiry.
Even though the mind, when reasoning from causes or effects, can extend its perspective beyond what it directly sees or remembers, it must never completely lose sight of those objects. It can't just reflect on its own ideas without incorporating some impressions, or at least memories that act like impressions. When we draw conclusions about effects from causes, we first need to confirm the existence of those causes. We can do this in only two ways: through a direct memory or sensory perception, or by inferring from other causes. For those causes, we then need to verify them in the same way—either by a current impression or by inferring from their causes—continuing this process until we get to something we actually see or remember. We can't keep extending our inferences indefinitely; the only thing that can halt them is a clear impression from memory or the senses, beyond which there’s no room for doubt or further inquiry.
To give an instance of this, we may chuse any point of history, and consider for what reason we either believe or reject it. Thus we believe that Caesar was killed in the senate-house on the ides of March; and that because this fact is established on the unanimous testimony of historians, who agree to assign this precise time and place to that event. Here are certain characters and letters present either to our memory or senses; which characters we likewise remember to have been used as the signs of certain ideas; and these ideas were either in the minds of such as were immediately present at that action, and received the ideas directly from its existence; or they were derived from the testimony of others, and that again from another testimony, by a visible gradation, it will we arrive at those who were eyewitnesses and spectators of the event. It is obvious all this chain of argument or connexion of causes and effects, is at first founded on those characters or letters, which are seen or remembered, and that without the authority either of the memory or senses our whole reasoning would be chimerical and without foundation. Every link of the chain would in that case hang upon another; but there would not be any thing fixed to one end of it, capable of sustaining the whole; and consequently there would be no belief nor evidence. And this actually is the case with all hypothetical arguments, or reasonings upon a supposition; there being in them, neither any present impression, nor belief of a real existence.
To illustrate this, we can choose any moment in history and examine why we either accept or reject it. For example, we believe that Caesar was killed in the Senate on the Ides of March because this fact is backed by the unanimous accounts of historians, who all agree on the specific time and place of that event. There are certain characters and letters that we recall or perceive; these characters are also remembered as symbols of certain ideas. These ideas were either in the minds of those who were directly present at that moment and experienced it firsthand, or they were passed down through others' accounts, creating a visible chain of testimonies that ultimately lead back to eyewitnesses of the event. It’s clear that this entire chain of reasoning or connection of causes and effects is initially based on those characters or letters that we see or remember. Without the authority of our memory or senses, our reasoning would be imaginary and unfounded. Each link in that chain would rely on another, but there would be nothing anchoring one end of it that could support the whole, leaving us with no belief or evidence. This is exactly the issue with all hypothetical arguments or reasoning based on assumptions, which lack both any immediate impression and belief in a real existence.
I need not observe, that it is no just objection to the present doctrine, that we can reason upon our past conclusions or principles, without having recourse to those impressions, from which they first arose. For even supposing these impressions should be entirely effaced from the memory, the conviction they produced may still remain; and it is equally true, that all reasonings concerning causes and effects are originally derived from some impression; in the same manner, as the assurance of a demonstration proceeds always from a comparison of ideas, though it may continue after the comparison is forgot.
I don't need to point out that it's not a valid argument against the current idea that we can think about our past conclusions or principles without relying on the impressions that first led to them. Even if those impressions are completely wiped from our memory, the belief they created may still persist. It's also true that all reasoning about causes and effects originally comes from some impression, just like the certainty of a demonstration always comes from comparing ideas, even if that comparison is forgotten later.
SECT. V. OF THE IMPRESSIONS OF THE SENSES AND MEMORY.
In this kind of reasoning, then, from causation, we employ materials, which are of a mixed and heterogeneous nature, and which, however connected, are yet essentially different from each other. All our arguments concerning causes and effects consist both of an impression of the memory or, senses, and of the idea of that existence, which produces the object of the impression, or is produced by it. Here therefore we have three things to explain, viz. First, The original impression. Secondly, The transition to the idea of the connected cause or effect. Thirdly, The nature and qualities of that idea.
In this type of reasoning, we use materials that are mixed and varied, which, although related, are fundamentally different from one another. All our arguments about causes and effects include both a memory or sensory impression and the idea of the existence that creates the impression or is created by it. So, we need to explain three things: First, the original impression. Second, the shift to the idea of the related cause or effect. Third, the nature and qualities of that idea.
As to those impressions, which arise from the senses, their ultimate cause is, in my opinion, perfectly inexplicable by human reason, and it will always be impossible to decide with certainty, whether they arise immediately from the object, or are produced by the creative power of the mind, or are derived from the author of our being. Nor is such a question any way material to our present purpose. We may draw inferences from the coherence of our perceptions, whether they be true or false; whether they represent nature justly, or be mere illusions of the senses.
Regarding those impressions that come from our senses, I believe that their ultimate cause is completely beyond human understanding, and we will never be able to definitively say whether they come directly from the object, are created by our mind, or originate from our creator. However, this question isn't really relevant to what we're discussing right now. We can make conclusions based on the consistency of our perceptions, regardless of whether they are true or false, or if they accurately reflect reality or are just tricks of the senses.
When we search for the characteristic, which distinguishes the memory from the imagination, we must immediately perceive, that it cannot lie in the simple ideas it presents to us; since both these faculties borrow their simple ideas from the impressions, and can never go beyond these original perceptions. These faculties are as little distinguished from each other by the arrangement of their complex ideas. For though it be a peculiar property of the memory to preserve the original order and position of its ideas, while the imagination transposes and changes them, as it pleases; yet this difference is not sufficient to distinguish them in their operation, or make us know the one from the other; it being impossible to recal the past impressions, in order to compare them with our present ideas, and see whether their arrangement be exactly similar. Since therefore the memory, is known, neither by the order of its complex ideas, nor the nature of its simple ones; it follows, that the difference betwixt it and the imagination lies in its superior force and vivacity. A man may indulge his fancy in feigning any past scene of adventures; nor would there be any possibility of distinguishing this from a remembrance of a like kind, were not the ideas of the imagination fainter and more obscure.
When we look for what sets memory apart from imagination, we quickly realize it can't be found in the simple ideas they present, since both faculties take their simple ideas from impressions and can't go beyond these original perceptions. They're also not differentiated by how they arrange their complex ideas. While memory does have the unique ability to keep the original order and position of its ideas, and imagination can rearrange and change them as it likes, this difference doesn't help us distinguish between the two in how they operate. It's impossible to recall past impressions to compare them with our current ideas and see if their arrangement is exactly the same. Therefore, since memory is not defined by the order of its complex ideas or the nature of its simple ones, the difference between it and imagination lies in its greater strength and vividness. A person can let their imagination run wild in creating any past scene of adventures; there would be no way to tell it apart from an actual memory of a similar event if the ideas of imagination weren't dimmer and less clear.
It frequently happens, that when two men have been engaged in any scene of action, the one shall remember it much better than the other, and shall have all the difficulty in the world to make his companion recollect it. He runs over several circumstances in vain; mentions the time, the place, the company, what was said, what was done on all sides; till at last he hits on some lucky circumstance, that revives the whole, and gives his friend a perfect memory of every thing. Here the person that forgets receives at first all the ideas from the discourse of the other, with the same circumstances of time and place; though he considers them as mere fictions of the imagination. But as soon as the circumstance is mentioned, that touches the memory, the very same ideas now appear in a new light, and have, in a manner, a different feeling from what they had before. Without any other alteration, beside that of the feeling, they become immediately ideas of the memory, and are assented to.
It often happens that when two people are involved in an event, one of them remembers it much better than the other, who struggles to recall it. The one who remembers goes through various details in vain, mentioning the time, place, the people present, what was said, and what happened, until finally, he stumbles upon a key detail that jogs his friend's memory and helps him remember everything clearly. In this case, the person who forgets initially takes in all the ideas from the other person's account, along with the same details of time and place, but sees them as mere fabrications of the mind. However, once the detail that triggers the memory is mentioned, those same ideas suddenly come back in a different light and with a different feeling than before. With no other change except for the feeling, they quickly become memories that are accepted.
Since, therefore, the imagination can represent all the same objects that the memory can offer to us, and since those faculties are only distinguished by the different feeling of the ideas they present, it may be proper to consider what is the nature of that feeling. And here I believe every one will readily agree with me, that the ideas of the memory are more strong and lively than those of the fancy.
Since the imagination can represent all the same objects that memory can provide, and since those abilities are only different due to the varying feelings brought about by the ideas they present, it’s worth considering what that feeling is like. Here, I think everyone will agree with me that the ideas from memory are stronger and more vivid than those from imagination.
A painter, who intended to represent a passion or emotion of any kind, would endeavour to get a sight of a person actuated by a like emotion, in order to enliven his ideas, and give them a force and vivacity superior to what is found in those, which are mere fictions of the imagination. The more recent this memory is, the clearer is the idea; and when after a long interval he would return to the contemplation of his object, he always finds its idea to be much decayed, if not wholly obliterated. We are frequently in doubt concerning the ideas of the memory, as they become very weak and feeble; and are at a loss to determine whether any image proceeds from the fancy or the memory, when it is not drawn in such lively colours as distinguish that latter faculty. I think, I remember such an event, says one; but am not sure. A long tract of time has almost worn it out of my memory, and leaves me uncertain whether or not it be the pure offspring of my fancy.
A painter who wants to express a passion or emotion will try to observe someone experiencing a similar feeling to energize his ideas and make them more impactful and vivid than those that are just products of his imagination. The fresher this memory is, the clearer the idea becomes; and when he returns to reflect on his subject after a long time, he often finds the idea has faded significantly, if not completely disappeared. We often doubt our memories as they can become very weak; it can be hard to tell whether an image comes from memory or imagination when it isn't portrayed in the bright colors that typically characterize the former. "I think I remember such an event," someone might say, "but I'm not sure." A long passage of time has nearly erased it from my memory, leaving me uncertain whether it's a genuine memory or just a creation of my imagination.
And as an idea of the memory, by losing its force and vivacity, may degenerate to such a degree, as to be taken for an idea of the imagination; so on the other hand an idea of the imagination may acquire such a force and vivacity, as to pass for an idea of the memory, and counterfeit its effects on the belief and judgment. This is noted in the case of liars; who by the frequent repetition of their lies, come at last to believe and remember them, as realities; custom and habit having in this case, as in many others, the same influence on the mind as nature, and infixing the idea with equal force and vigour.
And as a memory can lose its strength and clarity to the point that it’s mistaken for a product of imagination, an imaginary idea can also become so vivid and strong that it’s accepted as a memory, mimicking its effects on belief and judgment. This is evident in the behavior of liars, who, through the constant repetition of their lies, eventually come to believe and remember them as truths; in this case, as in many others, habit and repetition have an impact on the mind similar to that of nature, firmly establishing the idea with equal strength and intensity.
Thus it appears, that the belief or assent, which always attends the memory and senses, is nothing but the vivacity of those perceptions they present; and that this alone distinguishes them from the imagination. To believe is in this case to feel an immediate impression of the senses, or a repetition of that impression in the memory. It is merely the force and liveliness of the perception, which constitutes the first act of the judgment, and lays the foundation of that reasoning, which we build upon it, when we trace the relation of cause and effect.
So it seems that the belief or agreement that always comes with memory and the senses is just the intensity of those perceptions they show. This is what sets them apart from imagination. To believe, in this case, means to have a direct sensory impression or to recall that impression from memory. It’s really just the strength and vividness of the perception that forms the initial act of judgment and establishes the basis for the reasoning we build on when we explore cause and effect relationships.
SECT. VI. OF THE INFERENCE FROM THE IMPRESSION TO THE IDEA.
It is easy to observe, that in tracing this relation, the inference we draw from cause to effect, is not derived merely from a survey of these particular objects, and from such a penetration into their essences as may discover the dependance of the one upon the other. There is no object, which implies the existence of any other if we consider these objects in themselves, and never look beyond the ideas which we form of them. Such an inference would amount to knowledge, and would imply the absolute contradiction and impossibility of conceiving any thing different. But as all distinct ideas are separable, it is evident there can be no impossibility of that kind. When we pass from a present impression to the idea of any object, we might possibly have separated the idea from the impression, and have substituted any other idea in its room.
It's easy to see that when we look at this relationship, the conclusion we draw from cause to effect doesn't come just from examining these specific objects or from deeply understanding their essences to reveal how they depend on each other. No object suggests the existence of any other if we consider these objects on their own and don't think beyond the ideas we have about them. Drawing such a conclusion would mean we have knowledge, which would require a complete contradiction and the impossibility of imagining anything different. However, since all distinct ideas can be separated, it's clear that such an impossibility doesn't exist. When we move from a current impression to the idea of any object, we might have separated the idea from the impression and replaced it with some other idea.
It is therefore by EXPERIENCE only, that we can infer the existence of one object from that of another. The nature of experience is this. We remember to have had frequent instances of the existence of one species of objects; and also remember, that the individuals of another species of objects have always attended them, and have existed in a regular order of contiguity and succession with regard to them. Thus we remember, to have seen that species of object we call flame, and to have felt that species of sensation we call heat. We likewise call to mind their constant conjunction in all past instances. Without any farther ceremony, we call the one cause and the other effect, and infer the existence of the one from that of the other. In all those instances, from which we learn the conjunction of particular causes and effects, both the causes and effects have been perceived by the senses, and are remembered. But in all cases, wherein we reason concerning them, there is only one perceived or remembered, and the other is supplyed in conformity to our past experience.
It is only through EXPERIENCE that we can deduce the existence of one thing from another. This is the nature of experience. We remember having many instances of one type of object’s existence, and we also remember that individuals from another type of object have always accompanied them, existing in a consistent order of closeness and following with respect to them. For example, we recall seeing the type of object we call flame and feeling the sensation we call heat. We also remember their constant connection in all past experiences. Without any further fuss, we label one as the cause and the other as the effect, inferring the existence of one from the other. In all cases where we learn about the connection between specific causes and effects, both the causes and effects have been perceived by our senses and are remembered. However, in all situations where we reason about them, only one is perceived or remembered, while the other is provided based on our past experience.
Thus in advancing we have insensibly discovered a new relation betwixt cause and effect, when we least expected it, and were entirely employed upon another subject. This relation is their CONSTANT CONJUNCTION. Contiguity and succession are not sufficient to make us pronounce any two objects to be cause and effect, unless we perceive, that these two relations are preserved in several instances. We may now see the advantage of quitting the direct survey of this relation, in order to discover the nature of that necessary connexion, which makes so essential a part of it. There are hopes, that by this means we may at last arrive at our proposed end; though to tell the truth, this new-discovered relation of a constant conjunction seems to advance us but very little in our way. For it implies no more than this, that like objects have always been placed in like relations of contiguity and succession; and it seems evident, at least at first sight, that by this means we can never discover any new idea, and can only multiply, but not enlarge the objects of our mind. It may be thought, that what we learn not from one object, we can never learn from a hundred, which are all of the same kind, and are perfectly resembling in every circumstance. As our senses shew us in one instance two bodies, or motions, or qualities in certain relations of success and contiguity; so our memory presents us only with a multitude of instances, wherein we always find like bodies, motions, or qualities in like relations. From the mere repetition of any past impression, even to infinity, there never will arise any new original idea, such as that of a necessary connexion; and the number of impressions has in this case no more effect than if we confined ourselves to one only. But though this reasoning seems just and obvious; yet as it would be folly to despair too soon, we shall continue the thread of our discourse; and having found, that after the discovery of the constant conjunction of any objects, we always draw an inference from one object to another, we shall now examine the nature of that inference, and of the transition from the impression to the idea. Perhaps it will appear in the end, that the necessary connexion depends on the inference, instead of the inference's depending on the necessary connexion.
As we move forward, we've unintentionally uncovered a new relationship between cause and effect at a time when we least expected it, focusing on something else entirely. This relationship is their CONSTANT CONJUNCTION. Just being next to each other or happening one after the other isn’t enough for us to decide that two things are cause and effect unless we notice that these two relationships are consistent across different examples. It’s clear now that stepping back from a direct examination of this relationship can help us understand the nature of the necessary connection that is crucial to it. There’s hope that this approach might lead us to our intended goal; however, to be honest, this newly discovered relationship of constant conjunction doesn’t seem to get us very far. It suggests only that similar objects have always been in similar relationships of proximity and succession, and at first glance, it appears that this method doesn’t help us discover new ideas but just allows us to multiply, not expand, the objects in our minds. One might argue that we can’t learn anything new from one object if we also can’t learn from a hundred similar objects that are exactly alike in every detail. Just as our senses show us, in one instance, two bodies, motions, or qualities in certain relationships of succession and proximity, our memory simply presents us with many instances where we find similar bodies, motions, or qualities in similar relationships. From the endless repetition of any past impression, we will never generate a new original idea, like that of a necessary connection; the quantity of impressions doesn’t change this, and it’s as if we were limited to just one impression. Although this line of reasoning seems sound and straightforward, it would be foolish to give up too quickly; so we’ll continue our discussion. Since we’ve observed that after discovering the constant conjunction of any objects, we always infer one object from another, we’ll now look into the nature of that inference and the shift from impression to idea. It may ultimately become clear that the necessary connection relies on the inference rather than the other way around.
Since it appears, that the transition from an impression present to the memory or senses to the idea of an object, which we call cause or effect, is founded on past experience, and on our remembrance of their constant conjunction, the next question is, Whether experience produces the idea by means of the understanding or imagination; whether we are determined by reason to make the transition, or by a certain association and relation of perceptions. If reason determined us, it would proceed upon that principle, that instances, of which we have had no experience, must resemble those, of which we have had experience, and that the course of nature continues always uniformly the same. In order therefore to clear up this matter, let us consider all the arguments, upon which such a proposition may be supposed to be founded; and as these must be derived either from knowledge or probability, let us cast our eye on each of these degrees of evidence, and see whether they afford any just conclusion of this nature.
Since it seems that the shift from a current impression to a memory or sense to the concept of an object, which we refer to as cause or effect, is based on past experience and our recollection of their consistent connection, the next question is whether experience creates the idea through understanding or imagination; whether we are guided by reason to make this shift, or by a certain association and relationship of perceptions. If we were guided by reason, it would follow the principle that instances we've never encountered must be similar to those we've experienced, and that the course of nature always remains consistently the same. To clarify this issue, let’s examine all the arguments that could support such a proposition; and since these must come from either knowledge or probability, let’s look at each of these types of evidence and see whether they provide any valid conclusions of this kind.
Our foregoing method of reasoning will easily convince us, that there can be no demonstrative arguments to prove, that those instances, of which we have, had no experience, resemble those, of which we have had experience. We can at least conceive a change in the course of nature; which sufficiently proves, that such a change is not absolutely impossible. To form a clear idea of any thing, is an undeniable argument for its possibility, and is alone a refutation of any pretended demonstration against it.
Our previous way of thinking will quickly convince us that there can be no clear arguments to prove that the instances we lack experience with are similar to those we do have experience with. We can at least imagine a change in the natural order, which sufficiently shows that such a change is not completely impossible. Forming a clear idea of something is a strong argument for its possibility and is enough to counter any supposed proof against it.
Probability, as it discovers not the relations of ideas, considered as such, but only those of objects, must in some respects be founded on the impressions of our memory and senses, and in some respects on our ideas. Were there no mixture of any impression in our probable reasonings, the conclusion would be entirely chimerical: And were there no mixture of ideas, the action of the mind, in observing the relation, would, properly speaking, be sensation, not reasoning. It is therefore necessary, that in all probable reasonings there be something present to the mind, either seen or remembered; and that from this we infer something connected with it, which is not seen nor remembered.
Probability doesn't just look at the relationships of ideas by themselves, but rather focuses on the relationships of objects. It must be based on both the impressions we have from our memory and senses, as well as our ideas. If there were no element of any impression in our reasoning about probabilities, the conclusions we draw would be entirely imaginary. On the other hand, if there were no component of ideas, our mental activity in observing relationships would be more like sensation than reasoning. Therefore, it's essential that in all our reasoning about probabilities, there is something in our mind that we either see or remember, and from that, we can infer something related that we haven't seen or remembered.
The only connexion or relation of objects, which can lead us beyond the immediate impressions of our memory and senses, is that of cause and effect; and that because it is the only one, on which we can found a just inference from one object to another. The idea of cause and effect is derived from experience, which informs us, that such particular objects, in all past instances, have been constantly conjoined with each other: And as an object similar to one of these is supposed to be immediately present in its impression, we thence presume on the existence of one similar to its usual attendant. According to this account of things, which is, I think, in every point unquestionable, probability is founded on the presumption of a resemblance betwixt those objects, of which we have had experience, and those, of which we have had none; and therefore it is impossible this presumption can arise from probability. The same principle cannot be both the cause and effect of another; and this is, perhaps, the only proposition concerning that relation, which is either intuitively or demonstratively certain.
The only connection or relationship between objects that allows us to go beyond our immediate memories and senses is that of cause and effect; and that’s because it’s the only one we can use to make a valid inference from one object to another. The idea of cause and effect comes from experience, which tells us that certain objects have been consistently linked together in all past instances. And when we encounter an object that resembles one of these, we tend to assume that a similar object usually accompanies it. According to this explanation, which I believe is unquestionable in every aspect, probability is based on the assumption that there is a resemblance between objects we have experienced and those we have not; therefore, this assumption cannot arise from probability. The same principle cannot be both the cause and effect of another, and this is perhaps the only statement about that relationship that is either intuitively or demonstrably certain.
Should any one think to elude this argument; and without determining whether our reasoning on this subject be derived from demonstration or probability, pretend that all conclusions from causes and effects are built on solid reasoning: I can only desire, that this reasoning may be produced, in order to be exposed to our examination. It may, perhaps, be said, that after experience of the constant conjunction of certain objects, we reason in the following manner. Such an object is always found to produce another. It is impossible it could have this effect, if it was not endowed with a power of production. The power necessarily implies the effect; and therefore there is a just foundation for drawing a conclusion from the existence of one object to that of its usual attendant. The past production implies a power: The power implies a new production: And the new production is what we infer from the power and the past production.
If anyone tries to dodge this argument and claims, without deciding if our reasoning is based on proof or likelihood, that all conclusions drawn from causes and effects are solidly reasoned: I can only ask for this reasoning to be provided so we can examine it. It might be argued that after observing the consistent connection between certain objects, we reason like this: Such an object always leads to another. It couldn't have this effect if it didn't have the ability to produce it. The ability necessarily implies the effect, so there's a valid basis for inferring the presence of one object from its usual counterpart. Past production suggests an ability: The ability suggests a new production: And the new production is what we conclude from the ability and the past production.
It were easy for me to shew the weakness of this reasoning, were I willing to make use of those observations, I have already made, that the idea of production is the same with that of causation, and that no existence certainly and demonstratively implies a power in any other object; or were it proper to anticipate what I shall have occasion to remark afterwards concerning the idea we form of power and efficacy. But as such a method of proceeding may seem either to weaken my system, by resting one part of it on another, or to breed a confusion in my reasoning, I shall endeavour to maintain my present assertion without any such assistance.
It would be easy for me to show the flaws in this reasoning if I were willing to use the observations I've already made, that the concept of production is the same as that of causation, and that no existence clearly and demonstrably indicates a power in any other object; or if it were appropriate to anticipate what I will discuss later regarding the idea we have of power and effectiveness. However, since such an approach might either weaken my argument by relying on one part to support another, or create confusion in my reasoning, I will try to uphold my current assertion without such help.
It shall therefore be allowed for a moment, that the production of one object by another in any one instance implies a power; and that this power is connected with its effect. But it having been already proved, that the power lies not in the sensible qualities of the cause; and there being nothing but the sensible qualities present to us; I ask, why in other instances you presume that the same power still exists, merely upon the appearance of these qualities? Your appeal to past experience decides nothing in the present case; and at the utmost can only prove, that that very object, which produced any other, was at that very instant endowed with such a power; but can never prove, that the same power must continue in the same object or collection of sensible qualities; much less, that a like power is always conjoined with like sensible qualities, should it be said, that we have experience, that the same power continues united with the same object, and that like objects are endowed with like powers, I would renew my question, why from this experience we form any conclusion beyond those past instances, of which we have had experience. If you answer this question in, the same manner as the preceding, your answer gives still occasion to a new question of the same kind, even in infinitum; which clearly proves, that the foregoing reasoning had no just foundation.
It should be allowed for a moment to acknowledge that producing one thing from another in any given case implies some kind of power, and this power is connected to its effect. However, since it has already been demonstrated that this power doesn't reside in the observable qualities of the cause, and we only have the observable qualities in front of us, I ask why you assume that the same power still exists in other cases simply based on the presence of these qualities? Your reference to past experiences does not clarify anything in this situation; at most, it can only prove that the specific object that caused another was indeed endowed with such power at that exact moment. But it can never prove that the same power must remain with the same object or collection of observable qualities; even less can it be claimed that a similar power is always linked to similar observable qualities. If it's suggested that we have experienced this continued connection of power with the same object, and that similar objects possess similar powers, I would repeat my question: why do we draw any conclusions from this experience that go beyond the previous cases with which we are familiar? If you answer this question as you did before, your response still leads to yet another question of the same nature, potentially ad infinitum, which clearly shows that the previous reasoning lacked a solid foundation.
Thus not only our reason fails us in the discovery of the ultimate connexion of causes and effects, but even after experience has informed us of their constant conjunction, it is impossible for us to satisfy ourselves by our reason, why we should extend that experience beyond those particular instances, which have fallen under our observation. We suppose, but are never able to prove, that there must be a resemblance betwixt those objects, of which we have had experience, and those which lie beyond the reach of our discovery.
So not only does our reasoning let us down when it comes to figuring out the ultimate connection between causes and effects, but even after we’ve gained experience that shows us their consistent connection, we can’t convince ourselves through reasoning why we should apply that experience to other cases that we haven’t observed. We assume there must be some similarity between the things we’ve experienced and those that are beyond our understanding, but we can never really prove it.
We have already taken notice of certain relations, which make us pass from one object to another, even though there be no reason to determine us to that transition; and this we may establish for a general rule, that wherever the mind constantly and uniformly makes a transition without any reason, it is influenced by these relations. Now this is exactly the present case. Reason can never shew us the connexion of one object with another, though aided by experience, and the observation of their constant conjunction in all past instances. When the mind, therefore, passes from the idea or impression of one object to the idea or belief of another, it is not determined by reason, but by certain principles, which associate together the ideas of these objects, and unite them in the imagination. Had ideas no more union in the fancy than objects seem to have to the understanding, we could never draw any inference from causes to effects, nor repose belief in any matter of fact. The inference, therefore, depends solely on the union of ideas.
We've already noticed certain connections that cause us to move from one idea to another, even when there's no clear reason for that shift. We can state as a general rule that whenever the mind consistently makes a transition without any justification, it's influenced by these connections. This is exactly the case here. Reason can never show us how one object relates to another, even with the help of experience and observing their constant pairing in the past. So, when the mind shifts from the idea or impression of one object to the idea or belief of another, it's not driven by reason but by certain principles that link these ideas and bring them together in our imagination. If ideas had no more connection in our minds than objects appear to have in our understanding, we could never infer causes from effects or trust in any facts. Therefore, inferences rely entirely on the connection of ideas.
The principles of union among ideas, I have reduced to three general ones, and have asserted, that the idea or impression of any object naturally introduces the idea of any other object, that is resembling, contiguous to, or connected with it. These principles I allow to be neither the infallible nor the sole causes of an union among ideas. They are not the infallible causes. For one may fix his attention during Sometime on any one object without looking farther. They are not the sole causes. For the thought has evidently a very irregular motion in running along its objects, and may leap from the heavens to the earth, from one end of the creation to the other, without any certain method or order. But though I allow this weakness in these three relations, and this irregularity in the imagination; yet I assert that the only general principles, which associate ideas, are resemblance, contiguity and causation.
I've narrowed down the principles of how ideas connect to three main ones. I argue that the idea or impression of any object naturally leads to the idea of any other object that is similar, nearby, or connected to it. I recognize that these principles aren't the only or guaranteed causes of the connection between ideas. They're not guaranteed causes because someone can focus on a single object for a while without thinking of anything else. They're also not the only causes because thoughts can jump around unpredictably, moving from the heavens to the earth or anywhere else, without any clear method or order. However, despite acknowledging these limitations in these three relations and the irregularity of imagination, I maintain that the main principles that link ideas are resemblance, proximity, and causation.
There is indeed a principle of union among ideas, which at first sight may be esteemed different from any of these, but will be found at the bottom to depend on the same origin. When every individual of any species of objects is found by experience to be constantly united with an individual of another species, the appearance of any new individual of either species naturally conveys the thought to its usual attendant. Thus because such a particular idea is commonly annexed to such a particular word, nothing is required but the hearing of that word to produce the correspondent idea; and it will scarce be possible for the mind, by its utmost efforts, to prevent that transition. In this case it is not absolutely necessary, that upon hearing such a particular sound we should reflect on any past experience, and consider what idea has been usually connected with the sound. The imagination of itself supplies the place of this reflection, and is so accustomed to pass from the word to the idea, that it interposes not a moment's delay betwixt the hearing of the one, and the conception of the other.
There is definitely a principle of connection between ideas that might initially seem different from the others mentioned, but ultimately it comes from the same source. When we repeatedly observe that every individual of one type of object is consistently linked with an individual of another type, the appearance of any new individual from either type naturally brings to mind its usual counterpart. So, because a certain idea is commonly associated with a certain word, all it takes is hearing that word to trigger the related idea. It's nearly impossible for the mind, even with the greatest effort, to stop that connection from happening. In this situation, it’s not essential that we think back on past experiences or consider which idea has typically been linked to the word when we hear it. Our imagination automatically fills in this gap, and it’s so trained to move from the word to the idea that there’s hardly any delay between hearing one and conceiving the other.
But though I acknowledge this to be a true principle of association among ideas, I assert it to be the very same with that betwixt the ideas of cause and effects and to be an essential part in all our reasonings from that relation. We have no other notion of cause and effect, but that of certain objects, which have been always conjoined together, and which in all past instances have been found inseparable. We cannot penetrate into the reason of the conjunction. We only observe the thing itself, and always find that from the constant conjunction the objects acquire an union in the imagination. When the impression of one becomes present to us, we immediately form an idea of its usual attendant; and consequently we may establish this as one part of the definition of an opinion or belief, that it is an idea related to or associated with a present impression.
But while I recognize this as a true principle of how ideas connect, I argue that it's the same relationship that exists between cause and effect, and it's a crucial part of all our reasoning based on that connection. We have no other understanding of cause and effect except as certain objects that have always been linked together and have always been found inseparable in past instances. We can't really understand the reason behind this connection. We only observe the relationship itself and consistently find that because of the constant connection, the objects gain a bond in our imagination. When we perceive one, we immediately think of its usual counterpart; therefore, we can define an opinion or belief as an idea linked to or associated with a present impression.
Thus though causation be a philosophical relation, as implying contiguity, succession, and constant conjunction, yet it is only so far as it is a natural relation, and produces an union among our ideas, that we are able to reason upon it, or draw any inference from it.
So, even though causation is a philosophical concept that involves closeness, sequence, and consistent association, it's only when it becomes a natural connection and creates a bond between our ideas that we can think about it or make any conclusions based on it.
SECT. VII. OF THE NATURE OF THE IDEA OR BELIEF.
The idea of an object is an essential part of the belief of it, but not the whole. We conceive many things, which we do not believe. In order then to discover more fully the nature of belief, or the qualities of those ideas we assent to, let us weigh the following considerations.
The concept of an object is a key part of believing in it, but it's not the entire picture. We can think about many things without actually believing in them. To better understand the nature of belief and the characteristics of the ideas we agree with, let’s consider the following points.
It is evident, that all reasonings from causes or effects terminate in conclusions, concerning matter of fact; that is, concerning the existence of objects or of their qualities. It is also evident, that the idea, of existence is nothing different from the idea of any object, and that when after the simple conception of any thing we would conceive it as existent, we in reality make no addition to or alteration on our first idea. Thus when we affirm, that God is existent, we simply form the idea of such a being, as he is represented to us; nor is the existence, which we attribute to him, conceived by a particular idea, which we join to the idea of his other qualities, and can again separate and distinguish from them. But I go farther; and not content with asserting, that the conception of the existence of any object is no addition to the simple conception of it, I likewise maintain, that the belief of the existence joins no new ideas to those which compose the idea of the object. When I think of God, when I think of him as existent, and when I believe him to be existent, my idea of him neither encreases nor diminishes. But as it is certain there is a great difference betwixt the simple conception of the existence of an object, and the belief of it, and as this difference lies not in the parts or composition of the idea, which we conceive; it follows, that it must lie in the manner, in which we conceive it.
It’s clear that all reasoning from causes or effects leads to conclusions about facts; that is, about the existence of objects or their qualities. It’s also clear that the idea of existence is no different from the idea of any object, and that when we think of something simply, and then consider it as existing, we aren’t really adding anything new or changing our original idea. So, when we say that God exists, we just form the idea of the being as he is presented to us; the existence we attribute to him isn’t conceived as a separate idea that we can just add to or pull apart from his other qualities. But I go further; I don't just claim that the idea of the existence of any object doesn’t add anything to our simple understanding of it, I also argue that believing in the existence of the object doesn't add new ideas to the ones that make up our idea of that object. When I think of God, when I think of him as existing, and when I believe he exists, my idea of him neither grows nor shrinks. However, there is a significant difference between simply conceiving of the existence of an object and believing in it, and since this difference doesn’t lie in the components or composition of the idea we have, it must be based on how we conceive it.
Suppose a person present with me, who advances propositions, to which I do not assent, that Caesar dyed in his bed, that silver is more fusible, than lead, or mercury heavier than gold; it is evident, that notwithstanding my incredulity, I clearly understand his meaning, and form all the same ideas, which he forms. My imagination is endowed with the same powers as his; nor is it possible for him to conceive any idea, which I cannot conceive; nor conjoin any, which I cannot conjoin. I therefore ask, Wherein consists the difference betwixt believing and disbelieving any proposition? The answer is easy with regard to propositions, that are proved by intuition or demonstration. In that case, the person, who assents, not only conceives the ideas according to the proposition, but is necessarily determined to conceive them in that particular manner, either immediately or by the interposition of other ideas. Whatever is absurd is unintelligible; nor is it possible for the imagination to conceive any thing contrary to a demonstration. But as in reasonings from causation, and concerning matters of fact, this absolute necessity cannot take place, and the imagination is free to conceive both sides of the question, I still ask, Wherein consists the deference betwixt incredulity and belief? since in both cases the conception of the idea is equally possible and requisite.
Imagine someone with me who makes claims that I don't agree with, like saying that Caesar died in his bed, that silver melts easier than lead, or that mercury is heavier than gold. Clearly, even though I doubt these statements, I understand what he's saying and can form the same ideas he has. My imagination has the same abilities as his; he can't come up with any idea that I can't also understand or connect with. So I ask, what is the difference between believing and not believing a statement? It's easy to answer for statements that are proven by direct perception or logical demonstration. In those cases, when someone agrees, they not only understand the ideas in the statement but are also compelled to see them in that specific way, either directly or through other ideas. Anything absurd is incomprehensible; the imagination can't grasp anything that contradicts a logical conclusion. However, when it comes to reasoning about causes and real-life situations, that absolute compulsion doesn't apply, and the imagination can entertain both sides of the argument. So I still ask, what is the difference between disbelief and belief? In both cases, it's equally possible and necessary to conceive the idea.
It will not be a satisfactory answer to say, that a person, who does not assent to a proposition you advance; after having conceived the object in the same manner with you; immediately conceives it in a different manner, and has different ideas of it. This answer is unsatisfactory; not because it contains any falshood, but because it discovers not all the truth. It is contest, that in all cases, wherein we dissent from any person, we conceive both sides of the question; but as we can believe only one, it evidently follows, that the belief must make some difference betwixt that conception to which we assent, and that from which we dissent. We may mingle, and unite, and separate, and confound, and vary our ideas in a hundred different ways; but until there appears some principle, which fixes one of these different situations, we have in reality no opinion: And this principle, as it plainly makes no addition to our precedent ideas, can only change the manner of our conceiving them.
It’s not a satisfactory answer to say that a person who disagrees with a proposition you present, after having understood the object in the same way as you, suddenly sees it differently and has different ideas about it. This response isn’t satisfactory, not because it’s false, but because it doesn't reveal the whole truth. It’s clear that in every case where we disagree with someone, we comprehend both sides of the issue; but since we can only believe one, it follows that our belief must create some difference between the idea we accept and the one we reject. We can mix, combine, separate, confuse, and vary our ideas in countless ways; but until a principle emerges that determines one of these different perspectives, we truly have no opinion. This principle, as it clearly doesn’t add anything to our previous ideas, can only change how we conceive them.
All the perceptions of the mind are of two kinds, viz. impressions and ideas, which differ from each other only in their different degrees of force and vivacity. Our ideas are copyed from our impressions, and represent them in all their parts. When you would any way vary the idea of a particular object, you can only encrease or diminish its force and vivacity. If you make any other change on it, it represents a different object or impression. The case is the same as in colours. A particular shade of any colour may acquire a new degree of liveliness or brightness without any other variation. But when you produce any other variation, it is no longer the same shade or colour. So that as belief does nothing but vary the manner, in which we conceive any object, it can only bestow on our ideas an additional force and vivacity. An opinion, therefore, or belief may be most accurately defined, a lively idea related to or associated with a present impression.[6]
All the thoughts in our mind fall into two categories: impressions and ideas, which differ only in their levels of intensity and vividness. Our ideas are copies of our impressions and reflect them in all their details. If you want to change the idea of a specific object, you can only increase or decrease its intensity and vividness. If you change it in any other way, it represents a different object or impression. This is similar to colors. A specific shade of a color can become more vibrant or brighter without any other changes. But if you make any other change, it’s no longer the same shade or color. So since belief only alters how we perceive an object, it can only add strength and vividness to our ideas. Therefore, an opinion or belief can be defined as a vivid idea connected to or associated with a current impression. [6]
[6] We may here take occasion to observe a very remarkable error, which being frequently inculcated in the schools, has become a kind of establishd maxim, and is universally received by all logicians. This error consists in the vulgar division of the acts of the understanding, into CONCEPTION, JUDGMENT and REASONING, and in the definitions we give of them. Conception is defind to be the simple survey of one or more ideas: Judgment to be the separating or uniting of different ideas: Reasoning to be the separating or uniting of different ideas by the interposition of others, which show the relation they bear to each other. But these distinctions and definitions are faulty in very considerable articles. For FIRST, it is far from being true, that in every judgment, which we form, we unite two different ideas; since in that proposition, GOD IS, or indeed any other, which regards existence, the idea of existence is no distinct idea, which we unite with that of the object, and which is capable of forming a compound idea by the union. SECONDLY, As we can thus form a proposition, which contains only one idea, so we may exert our reason without employing more than two ideas, and without having recourse to a third to serve as a medium betwixt them. We infer a cause immediately from its effect; and this inference is not only a true species of reasoning, but the strongest of all others, and more convincing than when we interpose another idea to connect the two extremes. What we may in general affirm concerning these three acts of the understanding is, that taking them in a proper light, they all resolve themselves into the first, and are nothing but particular ways of conceiving our objects. Whether we consider a single object, or several; whether we dwell on these objects, or run from them to others; and in whatever form or order we survey them, the act of the mind exceeds not a simple conception; and the only remarkable difference, which occurs on this occasion, is, when we join belief to the conception, and are persuaded of the truth of what we conceive. This act of the mind has never yet been explain’d by any philosopher; and therefore I am at liberty to propose my hypothesis concerning it; which is, that it is only a strong and steady conception of any idea, and such as approaches in some measure to an immediate impression.
[6] Here we can take the opportunity to point out a significant mistake that is often taught in schools, has become a sort of established principle, and is widely accepted by all logicians. This mistake lies in the common division of the acts of understanding into CONCEPTION, JUDGMENT, and REASONING, along with the definitions we assign to them. Conception is defined as the simple observation of one or more ideas; Judgment is viewed as the separation or union of different ideas; and Reasoning is considered the separation or union of different ideas through the introduction of others that demonstrate how they relate to each other. However, these distinctions and definitions have notable flaws. First, it is not true that in every judgment we form, we combine two different ideas; for instance, in the proposition "GOD IS," or indeed any other statement about existence, the idea of existence is not a separate idea that we combine with that of the object, nor is it able to form a compound idea through this union. Secondly, just as we can create a proposition containing only one idea, we can also exercise our reasoning using only two ideas without needing a third to connect them. We can directly infer a cause from its effect; and this inference is not only a valid form of reasoning but also the strongest and most convincing, more so than when we introduce another idea to link the two ends. Generally, we can say about these three acts of understanding that, when viewed correctly, they all boil down to the first and are merely specific ways of conceiving our objects. Whether we look at a single object or multiple ones; whether we focus on these objects or move on to others; and in whatever way or order we examine them, the act of the mind does not go beyond a simple conception. The only significant difference that arises is when we add belief to the conception and are convinced of the truth of what we conceive. This mental act has never been clearly explained by any philosopher; therefore, I feel free to present my hypothesis about it, which is that it is simply a strong and steady conception of any idea, one that somewhat resembles an immediate impression.
Here are the heads of those arguments, which lead us to this conclusion. When we infer the existence of an object from that of others, some object must always be present either to the memory or senses, in order to be the foundation of our reasoning; since the mind cannot run up with its inferences IN INFINITUM. Reason can never satisfy us that the existence of any one object does ever imply that of another; so that when we pass from the impression of one to the idea or belief of another, we are not determined by reason, but by custom or a principle of association. But belief is somewhat more than a simple idea. It is a particular manner of forming an idea: And as the same idea can only be varyed by a variation of its degrees of force and vivacity; it follows upon the whole, that belief is a lively idea produced by a relation to a present impression, according to the foregoing definition.
Here are the main points of those arguments that lead us to this conclusion. When we deduce the existence of one object from that of others, there must always be some object currently in our memory or within our senses to serve as the basis for our reasoning; the mind cannot endlessly create inferences. Reason can never convince us that the existence of one object necessarily implies the existence of another; therefore, when we move from the impression of one thing to the idea or belief of another, we are guided not by reason, but by habit or a principle of association. However, belief is more than just a simple idea. It's a specific way of forming an idea: And since the same idea can only change based on differences in its intensity and vividness, it follows that belief is a vivid idea generated by its connection to a current impression, according to the definition above.
This operation of the mind, which forms the belief of any matter of fact, seems hitherto to have been one of the greatest mysteries of philosophy; though no one has so much as suspected, that there was any difficulty in explaining it. For my part I must own, that I find a considerable difficulty in the case; and that even when I think I understand the subject perfectly, I am at a loss for terms to express my meaning. I conclude, by an induction which seems to me very evident, that an opinion or belief is nothing but an idea, that is different from a fiction, not in the nature or the order of its parts, but in the manner of its being conceived. But when I would explain this manner, I scarce find any word that fully answers the case, but am obliged to have recourse to every one's feeling, in order to give him a perfect notion of this operation of the mind. An idea assented to FEELS different from a fictitious idea, that the fancy alone presents to us: And this different feeling I endeavour to explain by calling it a superior force, or vivacity, or solidity, or FIRMNESS, or steadiness. This variety of terms, which may seem so unphilosophical, is intended only to express that act of the mind, which renders realities more present to us than fictions, causes them to weigh more in the thought, and gives them a superior influence on the passions and imagination. Provided we agree about the thing, it is needless to dispute about the terms. The imagination has the command over all its ideas, and can join, and mix, and vary them in all the ways possible. It may conceive objects with all the circumstances of place and time. It may set them, in a manner, before our eyes in their true colours, just as they might have existed. But as it is impossible, that that faculty can ever, of itself, reach belief, it is evident, that belief consists not in the nature and order of our ideas, but in the manner of their conception, and in their feeling to the mind. To confess, that it is impossible to explain perfectly this feeling or manner of conception. We may make use of words, that express something near it. But its true and proper name is belief, which is a term that every one sufficiently understands in common life. And in philosophy we can go no farther, than assert, that it is something felt by the mind, which distinguishes the ideas of the judgment from the fictions of the imagination. It gives them more force and influence; makes them appear of greater importance; infixes them in the mind; and renders them the governing principles of all our actions.
This mental process, which creates the belief in any fact, has so far been one of the greatest mysteries in philosophy; yet no one has even suspected that explaining it might be challenging. I have to admit that I find it quite difficult; and even when I think I've completely grasped the subject, I'm at a loss for the right words to express my thoughts. I conclude, through a very clear line of reasoning, that an opinion or belief is simply an idea that differs from a fictional one—not in the nature or arrangement of its components, but in how it is conceived. However, when I try to explain this way of thinking, I hardly find any term that fully captures it, and I have to reference everyone's personal feelings to give a clear understanding of this mental operation. An idea that we agree with FEELS different from a fictional idea produced purely by the imagination: and this different feeling I try to clarify by referring to it as a greater force, or vividness, or solidity, or FIRMNESS, or stability. This range of terms, which might seem unphilosophical, is meant to reflect that mental act which makes real things feel more immediate to us than fantasies, makes them weigh more heavily in our thoughts, and gives them greater influence over our emotions and imagination. As long as we agree on the concept, there's no need to argue over the terminology. The imagination controls all its ideas and can combine, mix, and alter them in every possible way. It can visualize objects with all the details of time and place. It can present them to us in their true colors, just as they might have existed. But since it’s impossible for that faculty, on its own, to achieve belief, it’s clear that belief doesn't lie in the nature and arrangement of our ideas but in how we conceive them and how they resonate with the mind. It's crucial to acknowledge that it’s impossible to perfectly explain this feeling or way of conception. We can use words that approximate it, but its true name is belief, a term everyone understands in everyday life. In philosophy, we can only go as far as to say that it’s something the mind feels, distinguishing the ideas of judgment from the fictions of imagination. It gives them more power and influence, makes them seem more significant, embeds them in our minds, and turns them into the guiding principles of all our actions.
This definition will also be found to be entirely conformable to every one's feeling and experience. Nothing is more evident, than that those ideas, to which we assent, are more strong, firm and vivid, than the loose reveries of a castle-builder. If one person sits down to read a book as a romance, and another as a true history, they plainly receive the same ideas, and in the same order; nor does the incredulity of the one, and the belief of the other hinder them from putting the very same sense upon their author. His words produce the same ideas in both; though his testimony has not the same influence on them. The latter has a more lively conception of all the incidents. He enters deeper into the concerns of the persons: represents to himself their actions, and characters, and friendships, and enmities: He even goes so far as to form a notion of their features, and air, and person. While the former, who gives no credit to the testimony of the author, has a more faint and languid conception of all these particulars; and except on account of the style and ingenuity of the composition, can receive little entertainment from it.
This definition aligns with everyone’s feelings and experiences. It's clear that the ideas we agree with are stronger, more solid, and more vivid than the scattered daydreams of someone imagining a grand fantasy. If one person reads a book as a fictional story, while another reads it as a factual account, they clearly receive the same ideas in the same order; the disbelief of one and the belief of the other don’t prevent them from interpreting the author’s message in the same way. The author’s words evoke the same ideas in both readers, even though the impact of the author’s credibility differs for them. The believer has a more vivid imagination of all the events. They dive deeper into the characters' lives, envisioning their actions, traits, friendships, and rivalries. They even go as far as picturing their features and demeanor. Meanwhile, the skeptic, who doesn’t trust the author’s claims, has a much weaker and less engaging grasp of these details; aside from the style and cleverness of the writing, they find little enjoyment in it.
SECT. VIII. OF THE CAUSES OF BELIEF.
Having thus explained the nature of belief, and shewn that it consists in a lively idea related to a present impression; let us now proceed to examine from what principles it is derived, and what bestows the vivacity on the idea.
Having explained what belief is and shown that it involves a vivid idea connected to a present impression, let's now look into the principles it comes from and what gives the idea its intensity.
I would willingly establish it as a general maxim in the science of human nature, that when any impression becomes present to us, it not only transports the mind to such ideas as are related to it, but likewise communicates to them a share of its force and vivacity. All the operations of the mind depend in a great measure on its disposition, when it performs them; and according as the spirits are more or less elevated, and the attention more or less fixed, the action will always have more or less vigour and vivacity. When therefore any object is presented, which elevates and enlivens the thought, every action, to which the mind applies itself, will be more strong and vivid, as Tong as that disposition continues, Now it is evident the continuance of the disposition depends entirely on the objects, about which the mind is employed; and that any new object naturally gives a new direction to the spirits, and changes the disposition; as on the contrary, when the mind fixes constantly on the same object, or passes easily and insensibly along related objects, the disposition has a much longer duration. Hence it happens, that when the mind is once inlivened by a present impression, it proceeds to form a more lively idea of the related objects, by a natural transition of the disposition from the one to the other. The change of the objects is so easy, that the mind is scarce sensible of it, but applies itself to the conception of the related idea with all the force and vivacity it acquired from the present impression.
I would gladly establish it as a general principle in understanding human nature that when any impression comes to us, it not only brings to mind ideas related to it but also gives them a share of its strength and liveliness. All mental processes largely depend on our state of mind when we perform them; as the mood is better or worse and the focus is stronger or weaker, the action will always have varying degrees of energy and liveliness. So, when an object is presented that lifts and energizes our thoughts, every action the mind engages in will be stronger and more vivid as long as that state of mind lasts. Now, it’s clear that the duration of that state depends entirely on the objects the mind is focused on, and that any new object naturally shifts our mood and changes our focus. Conversely, when the mind fixates constantly on the same object or smoothly transitions along related objects, that state of mind lasts much longer. This is why, once the mind is energized by an immediate impression, it proceeds to form a more vivid idea of related objects by a natural shift from one to the other. The change between objects is so subtle that the mind hardly notices it, but it engages in the concept of the related idea with all the strength and liveliness gained from the immediate impression.
If in considering the nature of relation, and that facility of transition, which is essential to it, we can satisfy ourselves concerning the reality of this phænomenon, it is well: But I must confess I place my chief confidence in experience to prove so material a principle. We may, therefore, observe, as the first experiment to our present purpose, that upon the appearance of the picture of an absent friend, our idea of him is evidently inlivened by the resemblance, and that every passion, which that idea occasions, whether of joy or sorrow, acquires new force and vigour. In producing this effect there concur both a relation and a present impression. Where the picture bears him no resemblance, or at least was not intended for him, it never so much as conveys our thought to him: And where it is absent, as well as the person; though the mind may pass from the thought of the one to that of the other; it feels its idea to be rather weekend than inlivened by that transition. We take a pleasure in viewing the picture of a friend, when it is set before us; but when it is removed, rather choose to consider him directly, than by reflexion in an image, which is equally distinct and obscure.
If we can understand the nature of connections and the ease of transition that’s essential to them, that’s great. But I have to admit I mainly trust experience to validate such an important idea. So, let’s first look at the example that suits our purpose: when we see a picture of an absent friend, our mental image of them is clearly energized by the likeness, and whatever feelings that image brings up, whether joy or sadness, get stronger and more intense. This effect comes from both a connection and an immediate impression. When the picture doesn’t resemble them, or was not meant for them, it doesn’t even bring our thoughts to them. And when both the picture and the person are absent, even though our mind might shift from thinking about one to the other, it feels like the idea is more diminished than energized by that shift. We enjoy looking at a friend's picture when it’s in front of us, but when it’s gone, we’d rather think of them directly than through a reflection in an image that feels both clear and vague at the same time.
The ceremonies of the Roman Catholic religion may be considered as experiments of the same nature. The devotees of that strange superstition usually plead in excuse of the mummeries, with which they are upbraided, that they feel the good effect of those external motions, and postures, and actions, in enlivening their devotion, and quickening their fervour, which otherwise would decay away, if directed entirely to distant and immaterial objects. We shadow out the objects of our faith, say they, in sensible types and images, and render them more present to us by the immediate presence of these types, than it is possible for us to do, merely by an intellectual view and contemplation. Sensible objects have always a greater influence on the fancy than any other; and this influence they readily convey to those ideas, to which they are related, and which they Resemble. I shall only infer from these practices, and this reasoning, that the effect of resemblance in inlivening the idea is very common; and as in every case a resemblance and a present impression must concur, we are abundantly supplyed with experiments to prove the reality of the foregoing principle.
The ceremonies of the Roman Catholic Church can be seen as experiments of a similar kind. The followers of this peculiar belief often justify the rituals they are criticized for by saying that they feel the positive effects of these physical actions, postures, and movements, which enhance their devotion and energize their passion that would otherwise fade away if focused solely on distant and abstract concepts. They claim, "We express our faith through tangible symbols and images, making their presence more immediate to us than we could achieve through just intellectual understanding and contemplation." Physical objects always have a greater impact on the imagination than anything else; this impact easily transfers to the ideas they are connected to and resemble. I can only conclude from these practices and this reasoning that the effect of resemblance in energizing ideas is quite common; and since resemblance and immediate impressions must always go together in every case, we have plenty of examples to demonstrate the truth of this principle.
We may add force to these experiments by others of a different kind, in considering the effects of contiguity, as well as of resemblance. It is certain, that distance diminishes the force of every idea, and that upon our approach to any object; though it does not discover itself to our senses; it operates upon the mind with an influence that imitates an immediate impression. The thinking on any object readily transports the mind to what is contiguous; but it is only the actual presence of an object, that transports it with a superior vivacity. When I am a few miles from home, whatever relates to it touches me more nearly than when I am two hundred leagues distant; though even at that distance the reflecting on any thing in the neighbourhood of my friends and family naturally produces an idea of them. But as in this latter case, both the objects of the mind are ideas; notwithstanding there is an easy transition betwixt them; that transition alone is not able to give a superior vivacity to any of the ideas, for want of some immediate impression.[7]
We can strengthen these experiments by adding different types, looking at the effects of closeness as well as similarity. It's clear that distance weakens every idea, and when we get closer to something, even if it doesn't actually come into view, it influences our mind like it’s right in front of us. Thinking about something easily brings our mind to what's nearby, but only having the actual presence of something gives it a stronger impact. When I'm a few miles from home, anything related to it affects me more than if I'm two hundred leagues away; even at that distance, just thinking about anything connected to my friends and family naturally brings them to mind. However, in the latter case, both things our mind is focused on are just ideas; even though there's a smooth shift between them, that shift alone doesn't make any of the ideas feel more vivid without some immediate impression.
[7]
NATURANE NOBIS, IN QUIT, DATUM DICAM, AN ERRORE QUODAM, UT, CUM EA LOCA
VIDEAMUS, IN QUIBUS MEMORIA DIGNOS VIROS ACCEPERIMUS MULTURN ESSE VERSATOS,
MAGIS MOVEAMUR, QUAM SIQUANDO EORUM IPSORUM AUT JACTA AUDIAMUS, AUT SCRIPTUM
ALIQUOD LEGAMUS? VELUT EGO NUNC MOVEOR. VENIT ENIM MIHI PLATONIS IN MENTEM:
QUEM ACCIPIMUS PRIMURN HIC DISPUTARE SOLITUM: CUJUS ETIAM ILLI HORTULI
PROPINQUI NON MEMORIAM SOLUM MIHI AFFERUNT, SED IPSUM VIDENTUR IN CONSPECTU MEO
HIC PONERE. HIC SPEUSIPPUS, HIC XENOCRATES, HIC EJUS AUDITOR POLEMO; CUJUS IPSA
ILLA SESSIO FUIT, QUAM VIDEAMUS. EQUIDEM ETIAM CURIAM NOSTRAM, HOSTILIAM DICO,
NON HANC NOVAM, QUAE MIHI MINOR ESSE VIDETUR POST QUAM EST MAJOR, SOLE BARN
INTUENS SCIPIONEM, CATONEM, LACLIUM, NOSTRUM VERO IN PRIMIS AVUM COGITARE.
TANTA VIS ADMONITIONIS INEST IN LOCIS; UT NON SINE CAUSA EX HIS MEMORIAE DUCTA
SIT DISCIPLINA. Cicero de Finibus, lib. 5.
{"Should I, he said, "attribute to instinct or to some kind of illusion the
fact that when we see those places in which we are told notable men spent much
of their time, we are more powerfully affected than when we hear of the
exploits of the men themselves or read something written? This is just what is
happening to me now; for I am reminded of Plato who, we are told, was the first
to make a practice of holding discussions here. Those gardens of his near by do
not merely put me in mind of him; they seem to set the man himself before my
very eyes. Speusippus was here; so was Xenocrates; so was his pupil, Polemo,
and that very seat which we may view was his.
"Then again, when I looked at our Senate-house (I mean the old building of
Hostilius, not this new one; when it was enlarged, it diminished in my
estimation), I used to think of Scipio, Cato, Laelius and in particular of my
own grandfather.
"Such is the power of places to evoke associations; so it is with good
reason that they are used as a basis for memory training."}
[7] Is it instinct or some kind of illusion that when we see the places where great men spent their time, we feel more affected than when we hear about their deeds or read something they've written? That's exactly how I'm feeling right now; I'm reminded of Plato, who we know was the first to hold discussions here. Those nearby gardens don't just remind me of him; they seem to bring him right in front of me. Speusippus was here; so was Xenocrates; and his student, Polemo, too. That very seat we see was his. Then again, when I looked at our Senate-house (the old one built by Hostilius, not this new one; it feels less significant to me now that it's been expanded), I used to think of Scipio, Cato, Laelius, and especially my grandfather. Such is the power of places to bring back memories; it's no wonder they're used as a foundation for improving memory.
No one can doubt but causation has the same influence as the other two relations; of resemblance and contiguity. Superstitious people are fond of the relicks of saints and holy men, for the same reason that they seek after types and images, in order to enliven their devotion, and give them a more intimate and strong conception of those exemplary lives, which they desire to imitate. Now it is evident, one of the best relicks a devotee could procure, would be the handywork of a saint; and if his cloaths and furniture are ever to be considered in this light, it is because they were once at his disposal, and were moved and affected by him; in which respect they are to be considered as imperfect effects, and as connected with him by a shorter chain of consequences than any of those, from which we learn the reality of his existence. This phænomenon clearly proves, that a present impression with a relation of causation may, inliven any idea, and consequently produce belief or assent, according to the precedent definition of it.
No one can deny that causation has the same impact as the other two relationships: resemblance and contiguity. Superstitious people are drawn to relics of saints and holy figures for the same reason they seek out types and images—to enhance their devotion and create a deeper, stronger understanding of the exemplary lives they wish to emulate. Clearly, one of the best relics a devotee could obtain would be the work of a saint; if his clothes and belongings are ever regarded in this way, it’s because they were once in his possession and were used or affected by him. In this sense, they should be seen as imperfect effects, connected to him by a shorter chain of consequences than those we rely on to verify his existence. This phenomenon clearly shows that a present impression linked to causation can enliven any idea, and thus produce belief or agreement, as defined earlier.
But why need we seek for other arguments to prove, that a present impression with a relation or transition of the fancy may inliven any idea, when this very instance of our reasonings from cause and effect will alone suffice to that purpose? It is certain we must have an idea of every matter of fact, which we believe. It is certain, that this idea arises only from a relation to a present impression. It is certain, that the belief super-adds nothing to the idea, but only changes our manner of conceiving it, and renders it more strong and lively. The present conclusion concerning the influence of relation is the immediate consequence of all these steps; and every step appears to me sure end infallible. There enters nothing into this operation of the mind but a present impression, a lively idea, and a relation or association in the fancy betwixt the impression and idea; so that there can be no suspicion of mistake.
But why do we need to look for other reasons to prove that a current impression tied to our imagination can bring any idea to life, when this specific example of our reasoning about cause and effect is enough on its own? It's clear that we must have an idea of every fact we believe in. It's clear that this idea only comes from a connection to a current impression. It's clear that belief adds nothing to the idea itself; it just changes how we think about it and makes it stronger and more vivid. The current conclusion about the influence of connection is a direct result of all these points, and every point seems certain and undeniable to me. In this mental process, only a current impression, a vivid idea, and a connection or association between the impression and idea are involved; so there can be no doubt of any mistake.
In order to put this whole affair in a fuller light, let us consider it as a question in natural philosophy, which we must determine by experience and observation. I suppose there is an object presented, from which I draw a certain conclusion, and form to myself ideas, which I am said to believe or assent to. Here it is evident, that however that object, which is present to my senses, and that other, whose existence I infer by reasoning, may be thought to influence each other by their particular powers or qualities; yet as the phenomenon of belief, which we at present examine, is merely internal, these powers and qualities, being entirely unknown, can have no hand in producing it. It is the present impression, which is to be considered as the true and real cause of the idea, and of the belief which attends it. We must therefore endeavour to discover by experiments the particular qualities, by which it is enabled to produce so extraordinary an effect.
To shed more light on this whole situation, let's look at it as a question in natural philosophy that we need to answer through experience and observation. I assume there's an object in front of me, from which I draw a certain conclusion and form ideas that I’m said to believe or agree with. It’s clear that even though that object, which my senses perceive, and another whose existence I deduce through reasoning might seem to influence each other with their specific powers or qualities, the phenomenon of belief we’re currently examining is purely internal. Since these powers and qualities are completely unknown, they can't play any role in creating it. The immediate impression is what we should consider the true and real cause of the idea and the belief that comes with it. Therefore, we need to try to discover through experiments the specific qualities that allow it to produce such an extraordinary effect.
First then I observe, that the present impression has not this effect by its own proper power and efficacy, and when considered alone, as a single perception, limited to the present moment. I find, that an impression, from which, on its first appearance, I can draw no conclusion, may afterwards become the foundation of belief, when I have had experience of its usual consequences. We must in every case have observed the same impression in past instances, and have found it to be constantly conjoined with some other impression. This is confirmed by such a multitude of experiments, that it admits not of the smallest doubt.
First, I notice that the current impression doesn’t have this effect by its own power and effectiveness when looked at alone, as a single perception limited to the present moment. I see that an impression, from which I can't draw any conclusions initially, can later become the basis of belief after I've experienced its usual outcomes. In every case, we must have noted the same impression in past instances and found it to be consistently associated with another impression. This is backed by so many experiments that there is no doubt about it.
From a second observation I conclude, that the belief, which attends the present impression, and is produced by a number of past impressions and conjunctions; that this belief, I say, arises immediately, without any new operation of the reason or imagination. Of this I can be certain, because I never am conscious of any such operation, and find nothing in the subject, on which it can be founded. Now as we call every thing CUSTOM, which proceeds from a past repetition, without any new reasoning or conclusion, we-may establish it as a certain truth, that all the belief, which follows upon any present impression, is derived solely from that origin. When we are accustomed to see two impressions conjoined together, the appearance or idea of the one immediately carries us to the idea of the other.
From a second observation, I conclude that the belief that comes with the current impression, and is created by many past impressions and connections, arises immediately, without any new reasoning or imagination. I know this for sure because I'm never aware of any such process, and I find nothing in the subject that it could be based on. Since we call everything CUSTOM that comes from a past repetition without any new reasoning or conclusion, we can establish it as a fact that all belief that follows a current impression is derived solely from that source. When we’re used to seeing two impressions linked together, the appearance or idea of one immediately brings to mind the idea of the other.
Being fully satisfyed on this head, I make a third set of experiments, in order to know, whether any thing be requisite, beside the customary transition, towards the production of this phænomenon of belief. I therefore change the first impression into an idea; and observe, that though the customary transition to the correlative idea still remains, yet there is in reality no belief nor perswasion. A present impression, then, is absolutely requisite to this whole operation; and when after this I compare an impression with an idea, and find that their only difference consists in their different degrees of force and vivacity, I conclude upon the whole, that belief is a more vivid and intense conception of an idea, proceeding from its relation to a present impression.
Satisfied with this, I conduct a third set of experiments to find out if anything is needed beyond the usual transition to produce this phenomenon of belief. I then change the initial impression into an idea and notice that, while the usual transition to the related idea still exists, there is actually no belief or persuasion. A current impression is therefore essential to this whole process. When I later compare an impression with an idea and see that their only difference lies in their varying degrees of strength and vividness, I conclude that belief is a more intense and vivid conception of an idea, arising from its connection to a current impression.
Thus all probable reasoning is nothing but a species of sensation. It is not solely in poetry and music, we must follow our taste and sentiment, but likewise in philosophy. When I am convinced of any principle, it is only an idea, which strikes more strongly upon me. When I give the preference to one set of arguments above another, I do nothing but decide from my feeling concerning the superiority of their influence. Objects have no discoverable connexion together; nor is it from any other principle but custom operating upon the imagination, that we can draw any inference from the appearance of one to the existence of another.
So, all reasoning is really just a kind of sensation. It's not just in poetry and music where we need to follow our taste and feelings, but also in philosophy. When I believe in any principle, it's just an idea that resonates with me more strongly. When I prefer one set of arguments over another, I'm really just making a decision based on my feelings about their greater impact. Objects don’t have any obvious connection to each other; it's only through custom affecting our imagination that we can make any inference from one thing's appearance to another's existence.
It will here be worth our observation, that the past experience, on which all our judgments concerning cause and effect depend, may operate on our mind in such an insensible manner as never to be taken notice of, and may even in some measure be unknown to us. A person, who stops short in his journey upon meeting a river in his way, foresees the consequences of his proceeding forward; and his knowledge of these consequences is conveyed to him by past experience, which informs him of such certain conjunctions of causes and effects. But can we think, that on this occasion he reflects on any past experience, and calls to remembrance instances, that he has seen or heard of, in order to discover the effects of water on animal bodies? No surely; this is not the method, in which he proceeds in his reasoning. The idea of sinking is so closely connected with that of water, and the idea of suffocating with that of sinking, that the mind makes the transition without the assistance of the memory. The custom operates before we have time for reflection. The objects seem so inseparable, that we interpose not a moment's delay in passing from the one to the other. But as this transition proceeds from experience, and not from any primary connexion betwixt the ideas, we must necessarily acknowledge, that experience may produce a belief and a judgment of causes and effects by a secret operation, and without being once thought of. This removes all pretext, if there yet remains any, for asserting that the mind is convinced by reasoning of that principle, that instances of which we have no experience, must necessarily resemble those, of which we have. For we here find, that the understanding or imagination can draw inferences from past experience, without reflecting on it; much more without forming any principle concerning it, or reasoning upon that principle.
It’s important to note that our past experiences, which shape all our judgments about cause and effect, can affect our minds in such a subtle way that we may not even notice it, and this information can sometimes even be unknown to us. When someone pauses their journey at the sight of a river, they anticipate the consequences of moving forward. Their understanding of these outcomes comes from past experiences that inform them about the certain connections between causes and effects. But do we really think that at that moment, they consciously recall any past experiences or remember examples they've seen or heard to assess the effects of water on living beings? Definitely not; that’s not how their reasoning works. The thought of sinking is so tightly linked with water, and the thought of suffocating is so tied to sinking, that the mind transitions between these ideas without needing memory. The habit kicks in before we have time to think. The objects seem so connected that we don’t pause even for a moment before moving from one idea to the next. However, since this transition comes from experience and not from any inherent connection between the ideas, we must accept that experience can create belief and judgment about causes and effects through a subtle process without us even thinking about it. This clears any lingering excuse for claiming that the mind is convinced through reasoning that instances we have no experience with must resemble those we do. Here, we see that our understanding or imagination can draw conclusions from past experiences without thinking about them; even more so, without establishing any principles about them or reasoning based on those principles.
In general we may observe, that in all the most established and uniform conjunctions of causes and effects, such as those of gravity, impulse, solidity, &c. the mind never carries its view expressly to consider any past experience: Though in other associations of objects, which are more rare and unusual, it may assist the custom and transition of ideas by this reflection. Nay we find in some cases, that the reflection produces the belief without the custom; or more properly speaking, that the reflection produces the custom in an oblique and artificial manner. I explain myself. It is certain, that not only in philosophy, but even in common life, we may attain the knowledge of a particular cause merely by one experiment, provided it be made with judgment, and after a careful removal of all foreign and superfluous circumstances. Now as after one experiment of this kind, the mind, upon the appearance either of the cause or the effect, can draw an inference concerning the existence of its correlative; and as a habit can never be acquired merely by one instance; it may be thought, that belief cannot in this case be esteemed the effect of custom. But this difficulty will vanish, if we consider, that though we are here supposed to have had only one experiment of a particular effect, yet we have many millions to convince us of this principle; that like objects placed in like circumstances, will always produce like effects; and as this principle has established itself by a sufficient custom, it bestows an evidence and firmness on any opinion, to which it can be applied. The connexion of the ideas is not habitual after one experiment: but this connexion is comprehended under another principle, that is habitual; which brings us back to our hypothesis. In all cases we transfer our experience to instances, of which we have no experience, either expressly or tacitly, either directly or indirectly.
In general, we can see that in all the most established and consistent combinations of causes and effects, like gravity, force, solidity, etc., the mind doesn’t specifically consider any past experience. However, in other associations of objects that are more rare and unusual, it can aid the transition of ideas through this reflection. In fact, we find that in some cases, the reflection creates belief without the need for custom; or more accurately, that reflection creates the custom in an indirect and artificial way. Let me clarify. It’s clear that not only in philosophy but also in everyday life, we can understand a specific cause just from one experiment, as long as it’s done carefully and without outside or unnecessary factors. After such an experiment, when we see either the cause or the effect, the mind can make an inference about the existence of its counterpart; and because a habit can’t be formed from just one example, one might think that belief in this case isn’t a result of custom. But this issue disappears if we remember that, even though we may have just one experiment of a specific effect, we have countless others supporting this principle: that similar objects in similar situations will always yield similar effects. Since this principle has established itself through enough custom, it gives credibility and strength to any opinion it applies to. The connection of the ideas isn’t habitual after just one experiment; instead, this connection is understood under another principle that is habitual, bringing us back to our hypothesis. In all cases, we apply our experience to instances we have no experience with, either explicitly or implicitly, directly or indirectly.
I must not conclude this subject without observing, that it is very difficult to talk of the operations of the mind with perfect propriety and exactness; because common language has seldom made any very nice distinctions among them, but has generally called by the same term all such as nearly resemble each other. And as this is a source almost inevitable of obscurity and confusion in the author; so it may frequently give rise to doubts and objections in the reader, which otherwise he would never have dreamed of. Thus my general position, that an opinion or belief is nothing but a strong and lively idea derived from a present impression related to it, maybe liable to the following objection, by reason of a little ambiguity in those words strong and lively. It may be said, that not only an impression may give rise to reasoning, but that an idea may also have the same influence; especially upon my principle, that all our ideas are derived from correspondent impressions. For suppose I form at present an idea, of which I have forgot the correspondent impression, I am able to conclude from this idea, that such an impression did once exist; and as this conclusion is attended with belief, it may be asked, from whence are the qualities of force and vivacity derived, which constitute this belief? And to this I answer very readily, from the present idea. For as this idea is not here considered, as the representation of any absent object, but as a real perception in the mind, of which we are intimately conscious, it must be able to bestow on whatever is related to it the same quality, call it firmness, or solidity, or force, or vivacity, with which the mind reflects upon it, and is assured of its present existence. The idea here supplies the place of an impression, and is entirely the same, so far as regards our present purpose.
I can’t wrap up this topic without noting that it’s really challenging to discuss the workings of the mind with complete accuracy and clarity. This is mainly because everyday language rarely makes fine distinctions between these processes and typically uses the same term for things that are quite similar. This lack of precision can lead to confusion for the writer, and it can often spark doubts and questions for the reader that they wouldn’t have considered otherwise. So, my general argument—that an opinion or belief is just a strong and vivid idea based on a current impression—might face criticism due to the somewhat vague terms "strong" and "vivid." Someone could argue that not only can an impression lead to reasoning, but an idea can also have the same effect, especially since I believe that all our ideas come from corresponding impressions. For example, if I currently form an idea but have forgotten the related impression, I can still conclude that such an impression once existed. And since this conclusion comes with belief, one might wonder where the qualities of strength and vividness that make up this belief come from. I would answer that they come from the current idea. This idea isn’t viewed as just a representation of some absent object; instead, it’s a real perception in the mind that we are fully aware of, so it can impart the same quality—whether we call it strength, solidity, force, or vividness—to anything related to it, reflecting our conviction of its existence right now. The idea here effectively takes the place of an impression and serves the same purpose for our current discussion.
Upon the same principles we need not be surprized to hear of the remembrance of an idea: that is, of the idea of an idea, and of its force and vivacity superior to the loose conceptions of the imagination. In thinking of our past thoughts we not only delineate out the objects, of which we were thinking, but also conceive the action of the mind in the meditation, that certain JE-NE-SÇAI-QUOI, of which it is impossible to give any definition or description, but which every one sufficiently understands. When the memory offers an idea of this, and represents it as past, it is easily conceived how that idea may have more vigour and firmness, than when we think of a past thought, of which we have no remembrance.
Based on the same principles, we shouldn’t be surprised to hear about the memory of an idea: that is, the idea of an idea, and how its power and liveliness are greater than the vague thoughts of our imagination. When we reflect on our past thoughts, we not only outline the objects we were thinking about, but we also recognize the mind's action in the contemplation of that certain JE-NE-SÇAI-QUOI, which is impossible to define or describe, yet everyone understands it well enough. When memory brings forth an idea of this and presents it as something from the past, it’s easy to see how that idea might be more vigorous and solid than when we think about a past thought we can't recall.
After this any one will understand how we may form the idea of an impression and of an idea, and how we way believe the existence of an impression and of an idea.
After this, anyone will understand how we can form the idea of an impression and of an idea, and how we can believe in the existence of an impression and of an idea.
SECT. IX. OF THE EFFECTS OF OTHER RELATIONS AND OTHER HABITS.
However convincing the foregoing arguments may appear, we must not rest contented with them, but must turn the subject on every side, in order to find some new points of view, from which we may illustrate and confirm such extraordinary, and such fundamental principles. A scrupulous hesitation to receive any new hypothesis is so laudable a disposition in philosophers, and so necessary to the examination of truth, that it deserves to be complyed with, and requires that every argument be produced, which may tend to their satisfaction, and every objection removed, which may stop them in their reasoning.
No matter how convincing the arguments above might seem, we can’t just settle for them. We need to explore the topic from every angle to uncover new perspectives that can help us illustrate and support these extraordinary, fundamental principles. It's a commendable quality in philosophers to carefully consider any new hypothesis, and it's essential for the pursuit of truth. This attitude deserves our adherence and requires that all arguments be presented to satisfy them, as well as addressing any objections that might hinder their reasoning.
I have often observed, that, beside cause and effect, the two relations of resemblance and contiguity, are to be considered as associating principles of thought, and as capable of conveying the imagination from one idea to another. I have also observed, that when of two objects connected to-ether by any of these relations, one is immediately present to the memory or senses, not only the mind is conveyed to its co-relative by means of the associating principle; but likewise conceives it with an additional force and vigour, by the united operation of that principle, and of the present impression. All this I have observed, in order to confirm by analogy, my explication of our judgments concerning cause and effect. But this very argument may, perhaps, be turned against me, and instead of a confirmation of my hypothesis, may become an objection to it. For it may be said, that if all the parts of that hypothesis be true, viz. that these three species of relation are derived from the same principles; that their effects in informing and enlivening our ideas are the same; and that belief is nothing but a more forcible and vivid conception of an idea; it should follow, that that action of the mind may not only be derived from the relation of cause and effect, but also from those of contiguity and resemblance. But as we find by experience, that belief arises only from causation, and that we can draw no inference from one object to another, except they be connected by this relation, we may conclude, that there is some error in that reasoning, which leads us into such difficulties.
I've often noticed that, besides cause and effect, the two relationships of resemblance and contiguity should be seen as principles that link thoughts and can move the imagination from one idea to another. I've also noted that when two objects are connected by any of these relationships, and one is immediately in our memory or senses, the mind not only connects to its counterpart through this associating principle but also understands it with greater strength and intensity due to the combined influence of that principle and the current impression. I have observed all of this to support my explanation of how we judge cause and effect. However, this very argument could also be used against me. It might be said that if all parts of my hypothesis are correct—that these three types of relationships come from the same principles, that their effects in shaping and energizing our ideas are alike, and that belief is simply a stronger and more vivid conception of an idea—it should follow that this mental action could derive not only from the relation of cause and effect but also from those of contiguity and resemblance. Yet, from experience, we see that belief arises solely from causation, and we can't make inferences between objects unless they are connected by this relationship. Therefore, we can conclude that there is some flaw in the reasoning that leads to these complications.
This is the objection; let us now consider its solution. It is evident, that whatever is present to the memory, striking upon the mind with a vivacity, which resembles an immediate impression, must become of considerable moment in all the operations of the mind, and must easily distinguish itself above the mere fictions of the imagination. Of these impressions or ideas of the memory we form a kind of system, comprehending whatever we remember to have been present, either to our internal perception or senses; and every particular of that system, joined to the present impressions, we are pleased to call a reality. But the mind stops not here. For finding, that with this system of perceptions, there is another connected by custom, or if you will, by the relation of cause or effect, it proceeds to the consideration of their ideas; and as it feels that it is in a manner necessarily determined to view these particular ideas, and that the custom or relation, by which it is determined, admits not of the least change, it forms them into a new system, which it likewise dignifies with the title of realities. The first of these systems is the object of the memory and senses; the second of the judgment.
This is the objection; now let's look at the solution. It’s clear that anything that stands out in our memory, impacting our mind with a clarity similar to a direct impression, must play a significant role in all mental activities and must easily stand out from mere imaginary thoughts. From these memories or ideas, we create a sort of system that includes everything we recall having experienced, either through our internal awareness or our senses; and every detail in that system, when combined with our current impressions, we like to call a reality. But the mind doesn't stop there. It finds that this system of perceptions is linked to another one through habit, or you might say, through cause-and-effect relationships, and it then begins to consider these ideas. As it realizes that it’s somewhat compelled to focus on these specific ideas, and that the habits or relationships connecting them are unchanging, it organizes them into a new system, which it also labels as realities. The first of these systems is based on memory and sensory experiences; the second is based on judgment.
It is this latter principle, which peoples the world, and brings us acquainted with such existences, as by their removal in time and place, lie beyond the reach of the senses and memory. By means of it I paint the universe in my imagination, and fix my attention on any part of it I please. I form an idea of ROME, which I neither see nor remember; but which is connected with such impressions as I remember to have received from the conversation and books of travellers and historians. This idea of Rome I place in a certain situation on the idea of an object, which I call the globe. I join to it the conception of a particular government, and religion, and manners. I look backward and consider its first foundation; its several revolutions, successes, and misfortunes. All this, and everything else, which I believe, are nothing but ideas; though by their force and settled order, arising from custom and the relation of cause and effect, they distinguish themselves from the other ideas, which are merely the offspring of the imagination.
It’s this latter principle that populates the world and introduces us to realities that, due to their distance in time or space, are beyond our senses and memory. Through this principle, I can envision the universe in my mind and focus on any part of it that I choose. I create an idea of ROME, which I neither see nor recall, but which is linked to the impressions I remember having gathered from conversations and the works of travelers and historians. I place this idea of Rome in a specific position on the concept of the globe. I add to it thoughts about its particular government, religion, and customs. I reflect on its origins, its many changes, triumphs, and downfalls. All of this, along with everything else I believe, consists solely of ideas; however, due to their intensity and organized structure, shaped by tradition and the connection of cause and effect, they stand out from other ideas that are merely products of the imagination.
As to the influence of contiguity and resemblance, we may observe, that if the contiguous and resembling object be comprehended in this system of realities, there is no doubt but these two relations will assist that of cause and effect, and infix the related idea with more force in the imagination. This I shall enlarge upon presently. Mean while I shall carry my observation a step farther, and assert, that even where the related object is but feigned, the relation will serve to enliven the idea, and encrease its influence. A poet, no doubt, will be the better able to form a strong description of the Elysian fields, that he prompts his imagination by the view of a beautiful meadow or garden; as at another time he may by his fancy place himself in the midst of these fabulous regions, that by the feigned contiguity he may enliven his imagination.
Regarding the influence of proximity and similarity, we can see that if the neighboring and similar object is included in this reality system, there's no doubt these two relationships will strengthen the idea of cause and effect, embedding the related concept more powerfully in our minds. I'll elaborate on this shortly. In the meantime, I want to take my observation a step further and claim that even when the related object is merely imagined, the relationship will help energize the idea and increase its impact. A poet, for instance, can create a vivid description of the Elysian fields better if they stimulate their imagination by looking at a beautiful meadow or garden; at other times, they might use their imagination to place themselves in these mythical lands, where the imagined proximity can enhance their creativity.
But though I cannot altogether exclude the relations of resemblance and contiguity from operating on the fancy in this manner, it is observable that, when single, their influence is very feeble and uncertain. As the relation of cause and effect is requisite to persuade us of any real existence, so is this persuasion requisite to give force to these other relations. For where upon the appearance of an impression we not only feign another object, but likewise arbitrarily, and of our mere good-will and pleasure give it a particular relation to the impression, this can have but a small effect upon the mind; nor is there any reason, why, upon the return of the same impression, we should be determined to place the same object in the same relation to it. There is no manner of necessity for the mind to feign any resembling and contiguous objects; and if it feigns such, there is as little necessity for it always to confine itself to the same, without any difference or variation. And indeed such a fiction is founded on so little reason, that nothing but pure caprice can determine the mind to form it; and that principle being fluctuating and uncertain, it is impossible it can ever operate with any considerable degree of force and constancy. The mind forsees and anticipates the change; and even from the very first instant feels the looseness of its actions, and the weak hold it has of its objects. And as this imperfection is very sensible in every single instance, it still encreases by experience and observation, when we compare the several instances we may remember, and form a general rule against the reposing any assurance in those momentary glimpses of light, which arise in the imagination from a feigned resemblance and contiguity.
But while I can’t completely dismiss the connections of similarity and proximity from influencing the imagination in this way, it’s clear that, when alone, their impact is quite weak and unpredictable. Just as the cause-and-effect relationship is essential for us to believe in any real existence, this belief is also necessary to give strength to these other relationships. When an impression appears, if we not only imagine another object but also randomly and at our own will connect it to that impression, the effect on the mind can only be minimal; there’s no reason why, upon experiencing the same impression again, we should feel compelled to link the same object to it again. The mind is not required to invent any similar or nearby objects; and if it does, there’s equally no obligation for it to always stick to the same ones without any change or variation. In fact, such a creation is based on so little logic that only pure whim can drive the mind to create it; and since that principle is unstable and unpredictable, it can never operate with any significant strength or consistency. The mind anticipates and predicts change; even from the very first moment, it feels the looseness of its actions and the weak grip it has on its objects. Since this imperfection is quite noticeable in each individual case, it grows even clearer through experience and observation when we compare the various instances we remember, forming a general rule against placing any trust in those fleeting moments of insight that arise in the imagination from a fabricated similarity and proximity.
The relation of cause and effect has all the opposite advantages. The objects it presents are fixt and unalterable. The impressions of the memory never change in any considerable degree; and each impression draws along with it a precise idea, which takes its place in the imagination as something solid and real, certain and invariable. The thought is always determined to pass from the impression to the idea, and from that particular impression to that particular idea, without any choice or hesitation.
The relationship between cause and effect has all the opposite benefits. The things it presents are fixed and unchanging. The memories we have don’t change significantly, and each memory brings with it a clear idea, which settles in our imagination as something solid and real, certain and unchanging. Our thoughts are always driven to move from the memory to the idea, and from that specific memory to that specific idea, without any choice or hesitation.
But not content with removing this objection, I shall endeavour to extract from it a proof of the present doctrine. Contiguity and resemblance have an effect much inferior to causation; but still have some effect, and augment the conviction of any opinion, and the vivacity of any conception. If this can be proved in several new instances, beside what we have already observed, it will be allowed no inconsiderable argument, that belief is nothing but a lively idea related to a present impression.
But not satisfied with just dismissing this objection, I will try to draw from it proof of the current theory. Contiguity and resemblance hold much less influence than causation, but they still have some impact and can strengthen the belief in any opinion and enhance the clarity of any idea. If this can be demonstrated in several new examples, in addition to what we have already noted, it will be considered a significant argument that belief is simply a vivid idea connected to a current impression.
To begin with contiguity; it has been remarked among the Mahometans as well as Christians, that those pilgrims, who have seen MECCA or the HOLY LAND, are ever after more faithful and zealous believers, than those who have not had that advantage. A man, whose memory presents him with a lively image of the Red-Sea, and the Desert, and Jerusalem, and Galilee, can never doubt of any miraculous events, which are related either by Moses or the Evangelists. The lively idea of the places passes by an easy transition to the facts, which are supposed to have been related to them by contiguity, and encreases the belief by encreasing the vivacity of the conception. The remembrance of these fields and rivers has the same influence on the vulgar as a new argument; and from the same causes.
To start with, let's talk about contiguity; it's been noted by both Muslims and Christians that those pilgrims who have visited MECCA or the HOLY LAND tend to be more dedicated and passionate believers than those who haven't had that experience. A person who vividly remembers the Red Sea, the Desert, Jerusalem, and Galilee can never doubt the miraculous events described by either Moses or the Evangelists. The strong mental image of these locations easily connects to the events that are believed to have taken place there, increasing belief by intensifying the clarity of the concept. Remembering these fields and rivers has the same effect on the general public as a new argument, for the same reasons.
We may form a like observation concerning resemblance. We have remarked, that the conclusion, which we draw from a present object to its absent cause or effect, is never founded on any qualities, which we observe in that object, considered in itself, or, in other words, that it is impossible to determine, otherwise than by experience, what will result from any phenomenon, or what has preceded it. But though this be so evident in itself, that it seemed not to require any, proof; yet some philosophers have imagined that there is an apparent cause for the communication of motion, and that a reasonable man might immediately infer the motion of one body from the impulse of another, without having recourse to any past observation. That this opinion is false will admit of an easy proof. For if such an inference may be drawn merely from the ideas of body, of motion, and of impulse, it must amount to a demonstration, and must imply the absolute impossibility of any contrary supposition. Every effect, then, beside the communication of motion, implies a formal contradiction; and it is impossible not only that it can exist, but also that it can be conceived. But we may soon satisfy ourselves of the contrary, by forming a clear and consistent idea of one body's moving upon another, and of its rest immediately upon the contact, or of its returning back in the same line in which it came; or of its annihilation; or circular or elliptical motion: and in short, of an infinite number of other changes, which we may suppose it to undergo. These suppositions are all consistent and natural; and the reason, Why we imagine the communication of motion to be more consistent and natural not only than those suppositions, but also than any other natural effect, is founded on the relation of resemblance betwixt the cause and effect, which is here united to experience, and binds the objects in the closest and most intimate manner to each other, so as to make us imagine them to be absolutely inseparable. Resemblance, then, has the same or a parallel influence with experience; and as the only immediate effect of experience is to associate our ideas together, it follows, that all belief arises from the association of ideas, according to my hypothesis.
We can make a similar observation regarding resemblance. We’ve noted that the conclusion we draw from a present object to its absent cause or effect isn’t based on any qualities we observe in that object by itself. In other words, it's impossible to determine, apart from experience, what will result from any phenomenon or what has preceded it. Although this seems so evident that it doesn’t require proof, some philosophers have thought that there’s an obvious reason for the transfer of motion, suggesting that a rational person could immediately deduce the motion of one body from the impact of another without referring to any past observations. This belief is easily proven false. If such an inference could be made solely from our understanding of bodies, motion, and impact, it would be a demonstration and imply that any contrary idea is utterly impossible. Every effect besides the transfer of motion would then imply a formal contradiction; it’s not only impossible for it to exist, but also impossible to even conceive of it. However, we can quickly reassure ourselves of the opposite by imagining a clear, consistent scenario where one body moves against another, comes to rest upon contact, or moves back in the same direction it came from, or is annihilated, or moves in a circular or elliptical path, and countless other changes we might envisage. All these scenarios are consistent and natural. The reason we think the transfer of motion is more consistent and natural than those other scenarios or any other natural effect is based on the resemblance between cause and effect, which is connected to experience and binds the objects together in the closest and most intimate way, making us believe they are absolutely inseparable. Thus, resemblance has the same or similar influence as experience; and since the only immediate effect of experience is to link our ideas together, it follows that all belief originates from the association of ideas, according to my theory.
It is universally allowed by the writers on optics, that the eye at all times sees an equal number of physical points, and that a man on the top of a mountain has no larger an image presented to his senses, than when he is cooped up in the narrowest court or chamber. It is only by experience that he infers the greatness of the object from some peculiar qualities of the image; and this inference of the judgment he confounds with sensation, as is common on other occasions. Now it is evident, that the inference of the judgment is here much more lively than what is usual in our common reasonings, and that a man has a more vivid conception of the vast extent of the ocean from the image he receives by the eye, when he stands on the top of the high promontory, than merely from hearing the roaring of the waters. He feels a more sensible pleasure from its magnificence; which is a proof of a more lively idea: And he confounds his judgment with sensation, which is another proof of it. But as the inference is equally certain and immediate in both cases, this superior vivacity of our conception in one case can proceed from nothing but this, that in drawing an inference from the sight, beside the customary conjunction, there is also a resemblance betwixt the image and the object we infer; which strengthens the relation, and conveys the vivacity of the impression to the related idea with an easier and more natural movement.
It's widely accepted among optics experts that the eye always perceives the same number of physical points, and a person at the top of a mountain does not see a larger image than someone confined in a small courtyard or room. It's only through experience that he deduces the size of the object from certain unique qualities of the image, and this judgment mixes with sensation, similar to how it often happens in other situations. Clearly, the inference of the judgment here is much more vivid than what we usually encounter in everyday reasoning. A person standing on a high cliff has a stronger sense of the vastness of the ocean from what he sees than from simply hearing the crashing waves. He enjoys the spectacle more, which indicates a stronger mental image, and he confuses his judgment with sensation, which further supports this. However, since the inference is equally certain and immediate in both scenarios, the heightened clarity of our understanding in one case must stem from the fact that in drawing an inference from sight, there is not only the usual connection but also a similarity between the image and the object we infer from. This reinforces the relationship and naturally transfers the intensity of the impression to the associated idea.
No weakness of human nature is more universal and conspicuous than what we commonly call CREDULITY, or a too easy faith in the testimony of others; and this weakness is also very naturally accounted for from the influence of resemblance. When we receive any matter of fact upon human testimony, our faith arises from the very same origin as our inferences from causes to effects, and from effects to causes; nor is there anything but our experience of the governing principles of human nature, which can give us any assurance of the veracity of men. But though experience be the true standard of this, as well as of all other judgments, we seldom regulate ourselves entirely by it; but have a remarkable propensity to believe whatever is reported, even concerning apparitions, enchantments, and prodigies, however contrary to daily experience and observation. The words or discourses of others have an intimate connexion with certain ideas in their mind; and these ideas have also a connexion with the facts or objects, which they represent. This latter connexion is generally much over-rated, and commands our assent beyond what experience will justify; which can proceed from nothing beside the resemblance betwixt the ideas and the facts. Other effects only point out their causes in an oblique manner; but the testimony of men does it directly, and is to be considered as an image as well as an effect. No wonder, therefore, we are so rash in drawing our inferences from it, and are less guided by experience in our judgments concerning it, than in those upon any other subject.
No flaw in human nature is more common and obvious than what we usually call CREDULITY, or an overly easy trust in what others say; and this flaw can be easily explained by the influence of similarity. When we accept facts based on human testimony, our belief comes from the same source as our conclusions about causes and effects. There’s nothing except our experience with the fundamental principles of human nature that can assure us of people's honesty. However, although experience is the true benchmark for this, as well as all other judgments, we often don’t rely solely on it; we have a strong tendency to believe whatever is reported, even about ghosts, magic, and wonders, no matter how much they clash with our everyday experiences. The words or statements of others are closely linked to certain ideas in their minds; and these ideas are also connected to the facts or objects they describe. This latter connection is often overestimated and demands our agreement beyond what our experience can support, arising solely from the resemblance between the ideas and the facts. Other effects only indicate their causes indirectly, but human testimony does so directly and should be seen as both an image and an effect. It’s no surprise, then, that we are so quick to draw conclusions from it and are less influenced by experience in our judgments about it than we are with any other topic.
As resemblance, when conjoined with causation, fortifies our reasonings; so the want of it in any very great degree is able almost entirely to destroy them. Of this there is a remarkable instance in the universal carelessness and stupidity of men with regard to a future state, where they show as obstinate an incredulity, as they do a blind credulity on other occasions. There is not indeed a more ample matter of wonder to the studious, and of regret to the pious man, than to observe the negligence of the bulk of mankind concerning their approaching condition; and it is with reason, that many eminent theologians have not scrupled to affirm, that though the vulgar have no formal principles of infidelity, yet they are really infidels in their hearts, and have nothing like what we can call a belief of the eternal duration of their souls. For let us consider on the one hand what divines have displayed with such eloquence concerning the importance of eternity; and at the same time reflect, that though in matters of rhetoric we ought to lay our account with some exaggeration, we must in this case allow, that the strongest figures are infinitely inferior to the subject: And after this let us view on the other hand, the prodigious security of men in this particular: I ask, if these people really believe what is inculcated on them, and what they pretend to affirm; and the answer is obviously in the negative. As belief is an act of the mind arising from custom, it is not strange the want of resemblance should overthrow what custom has established, and diminish the force of the idea, as much as that latter principle encreases it. A future state is so far removed from our comprehension, and we have so obscure an idea of the manner, in which we shall exist after the dissolution of the body, that all the reasons we can invent, however strong in themselves, and however much assisted by education, are never able with slow imaginations to surmount this difficulty, or bestow a sufficient authority and force on the idea. I rather choose to ascribe this incredulity to the faint idea we form of our future condition, derived from its want of resemblance to the present life, than to that derived from its remoteness. For I observe, that men are everywhere concerned about what may happen after their death, provided it regard this world; and that there are few to whom their name, their family, their friends, and their country are in any period of time entirely indifferent.
As similarity, when combined with cause and effect, strengthens our reasoning; the lack of it to a significant degree can almost completely undermine it. A striking example of this is the widespread carelessness and ignorance of people regarding the afterlife, where they display as stubborn disbelief as they do blind belief in other situations. There truly isn’t a more astonishing thing for scholars and a source of regret for the devout than to see how most people neglect their impending fate. It makes sense that many respected theologians have boldly stated that while the general public may not openly reject faith, they are actually disbelievers at heart and lack any real belief in the everlasting nature of their souls. On one hand, let’s examine what theologians have eloquently expressed about the importance of eternity; on the other hand, let's recognize that while some exaggeration is expected in rhetoric, in this case, even the most powerful expressions are woefully inadequate compared to the subject. Then let’s look at how incredibly unconcerned people are about this issue: I ask, do these individuals truly believe what is being taught to them, and what they claim to accept? The clear answer is no. Since belief is a mental act shaped by habit, it’s not surprising that a lack of similarity can dismantle what habit has established, weakening the impact of the idea just as that principle strengthens it. A future state is so far beyond our understanding, and we have such a vague notion of how we will exist after our bodies dissolve, that all the reasons we can come up with, no matter how strong they are and however bolstered by education, are never enough to overcome this challenge or lend sufficient authority and power to the idea. I prefer to attribute this disbelief to the unclear image we have of our future state, stemming from its dissimilarity to our current life, rather than its distance. I notice that people everywhere care about what might happen after death, as long as it pertains to this world; and there are few who find their name, family, friends, and country entirely unimportant across any period of time.
And indeed the want of resemblance in this case so entirely destroys belief, that except those few, who upon cool reflection on the importance of the subject, have taken care by repeated meditation to imprint in their minds the arguments for a future state, there scarce are any, who believe the immortality of the soul with a true and established judgment; such as is derived from the testimony of travellers and historians. This appears very conspicuously wherever men have occasion to compare the pleasures and pains, the rewards and punishments of this life with those of a future; even though the case does not concern themselves, and there is no violent passion to disturb their judgment. The Roman Catholicks are certainly the most zealous of any sect in the Christian world; and yet you'll find few among the more sensible people of that communion who do not blame the Gunpowder-treason, and the massacre of St. Bartholomew, as cruel and barbarous, though projected or executed against those very people, whom without any scruple they condemn to eternal and infinite punishments. All we can say in excuse for this inconsistency is, that they really do not believe what they affirm concerning a future state; nor is there any better proof of it than the very inconsistency.
And indeed, the lack of similarity in this case completely undermines belief, so that aside from a few people who, after thinking carefully about the importance of the topic, have taken the time through repeated meditation to solidify in their minds the arguments for an afterlife, there are hardly any who genuinely believe in the immortality of the soul with a clear and established understanding; such as is based on the accounts of travelers and historians. This is clearly evident whenever people have the chance to weigh the pleasures and pains, and the rewards and punishments of this life against those of the next; even when the situation doesn't directly affect them and there’s no strong emotion clouding their judgment. Roman Catholics are definitely the most passionate of any group in the Christian world; yet you’ll find few among the more thoughtful members of that faith who don’t criticize the Gunpowder Plot and the Massacre of St. Bartholomew as cruel and barbaric, even though those acts were aimed at the very people they unhesitatingly condemn to eternal and infinite punishments. All we can say to excuse this contradiction is that they don’t truly believe what they claim about the afterlife; and the best proof of this is the very inconsistency.
We may add to this a remark; that in matters of religion men take a pleasure in being terrifyed, and that no preachers are so popular, as those who excite the most dismal and gloomy passions. In the common affairs of life, where we feel and are penetrated with the solidity of the subject, nothing can be more disagreeable than fear and terror; and it is only in dramatic performances and in religious discourses, that they ever give pleasure. In these latter cases the imagination reposes itself indolently on the idea; and the passion, being softened by the want of belief in the subject, has no more than the agreeable effect of enlivening the mind, and fixing the attention.
We can add a note that when it comes to religion, people actually enjoy being frightened, and the most popular preachers are those who stir up the darkest and most sorrowful emotions. In everyday life, where we clearly understand the reality of things, nothing is more unpleasant than fear and terror; it's only in plays and religious talks that they bring any enjoyment. In these situations, the imagination lazily dwells on the idea, and because there's a lack of belief in the subject, the emotion becomes just enough to energize the mind and focus our attention.
The present hypothesis will receive additional confirmation, if we examine the effects of other kinds of custom, as well as of other relations. To understand this we must consider, that custom, to which I attribute all belief and reasoning, may operate upon the mind in invigorating an idea after two several ways. For supposing that in all past experience we have found two objects to have been always conjoined together, it is evident, that upon the appearance of one of these objects in an impression, we must from custom make an easy transition to the idea of that object, which usually attends it; and by means of the present impression and easy transition must conceive that idea in a stronger and more lively manner, than we do any loose floating image of the fancy. But let us next suppose, that a mere idea alone, without any of this curious and almost artificial preparation, should frequently make its appearance in the mind, this idea must by degrees acquire a facility and force; and both by its firm hold and easy introduction distinguish itself from any new and unusual idea. This is the only particular, in which these two kinds of custom agree; and if it appear, that their effects on the judgment, are similar and proportionable, we may certainly conclude, that the foregoing explication of that faculty is satisfactory. But can we doubt of this agreement in their influence on the judgment, when we consider the nature and effects Of EDUCATION?
The current hypothesis will gain further support if we look into the effects of different customs and relationships. To understand this, we need to consider that the customs I associate with all belief and reasoning can influence the mind in two main ways to enhance an idea. If we assume that in all past experiences, we have observed that two objects have always appeared together, it's clear that when one of these objects appears, we naturally transition to the idea of the other object that usually accompanies it. Through this impression and smooth transition, we are likely to conceive that idea more strongly and vividly than any random thought that crosses our mind. Now let’s imagine that an idea by itself—without any intricate and almost fabricated setup—appears in our mind frequently; over time, this idea will gain a certain ease and impact, allowing it to stand out from any new or strange ideas due to its strong presence and easy recognition. This is the only way in which these two forms of custom are alike; and if it turns out that their effects on judgment are similar and proportional, we can confidently conclude that the previous explanation of this faculty is satisfying. But can we really doubt this agreement in their influence on judgment when we observe the nature and effects of EDUCATION?
All those opinions and notions of things, to which we have been accustomed from our infancy, take such deep root, that it is impossible for us, by all the powers of reason and experience, to eradicate them; and this habit not only approaches in its influence, but even on many occasions prevails over that which a-rises from the constant and inseparable union of causes and effects. Here we most not be contented with saying, that the vividness of the idea produces the belief: We must maintain that they are individually the same. The frequent repetition of any idea infixes it in the imagination; but could never possibly of itself produce belief, if that act of the mind was, by the original constitution of our natures, annexed only to a reasoning and comparison of ideas. Custom may lead us into some false comparison of ideas. This is the utmost effect we can conceive of it. But it is certain it could never supply the place of that comparison, nor produce any act of the mind, which naturally belonged to that principle.
All those opinions and ideas we've been exposed to since childhood take such deep root that it's impossible for us to eliminate them, no matter how much reason and experience we apply. This habit not only influences us but often prevails over what comes from the constant and inseparable connection of causes and effects. We can't just say that the vividness of an idea leads to belief; we must argue that they are essentially the same. The frequent repetition of any idea embeds it in our minds, but repetition alone could never create belief if that belief were originally tied to reasoning and comparing ideas. Custom might lead us into some flawed comparisons of ideas, but that's the farthest effect we can expect from it. However, it’s clear that it could never replace that comparison or generate any mental activity that naturally belongs to that principle.
A person, that has lost a leg or an arm by amputation, endeavours for a long time afterwards to serve himself with them. After the death of any one, it is a common remark of the whole family, but especially of the servants, that they can scarce believe him to be dead, but still imagine him to be in his chamber or in any other place, where they were accustomed to find him. I have often heard in conversation, after talking of a person, that is any way celebrated, that one, who has no acquaintance with him, will say, I have never seen such-a-one, but almost fancy I have; so often have I heard talk of him. All these are parallel instances.
A person who has lost a leg or arm due to amputation struggles for a long time to adjust to life without it. After someone dies, it's common for the family, especially the staff, to remark that they can hardly believe he is gone and still picture him in his room or wherever they used to find him. I've often heard people say, after discussing a well-known individual, that someone who doesn’t know him will claim, "I’ve never met him, but I almost feel like I have," because they've heard so much talk about him. All of these examples are similar.
If we consider this argument from EDUCATION in a proper light, it will appear very convincing; and the more so, that it is founded on one of the most common phaenomena, that is any where to be met with. I am persuaded, that upon examination we shall find more than one half of those opinions, that prevail among mankind, to be owing to education, and that the principles, which are thus implicitely embraced, overballance those, which are owing either to abstract reasoning or experience. As liars, by the frequent repetition of their lies, come at last to remember them; so the judgment, or rather the imagination, by the like means, may have ideas so strongly imprinted on it, and conceive them in so full a light, that they may operate upon the mind in the same manner with those, which the senses, memory or reason present to us. But as education is an artificial and not a natural cause, and as its maxims are frequently contrary to reason, and even to themselves in different times and places, it is never upon that account recognized by philosophers; though in reality it be built almost on the same foundation of custom and repetition as our reasonings from causes and effects.[8]
If we look at this argument about EDUCATION in the right way, it becomes very convincing, especially since it’s based on one of the most common phenomena found everywhere. I'm convinced that if we examine it closely, we'll see that more than half of the opinions held by people are a result of education. The principles that are implicitly accepted outweigh those that come from abstract reasoning or personal experience. Just as liars end up remembering their lies after telling them repeatedly, our judgment, or rather our imagination, can have ideas so deeply embedded that they can influence our minds just like those presented by our senses, memory, or reason. However, since education is an artificial cause rather than a natural one, and since its principles often contradict reason and even each other across different times and places, philosophers usually don't recognize it. Yet, in reality, it’s built on a similar foundation of custom and repetition as our reasoning from causes and effects.[8]
[8] In general we may observe, that as our assent to all probable reasonings is founded on the vivacity of ideas, It resembles many of those whimsies and prejudices, which are rejected under the opprobrious character of being the offspring of the imagination. By this expression it appears that the word, imagination, is commonly usd in two different senses; and tho nothing be more contrary to true philosophy, than this inaccuracy, yet in the following reasonings I have often been obligd to fall into it. When I oppose the Imagination to the memory, I mean the faculty, by which we form our fainter ideas. When I oppose it to reason, I mean the same faculty, excluding only our demonstrative and probable reasonings. When I oppose it to neither, it is indifferent whether it be taken in the larger or more limited sense, or at least the context will sufficiently explain the meaning.
[8] In general, we can see that our agreement with likely arguments is based on the vividness of ideas. It resembles many of the strange beliefs and biases that are dismissed as mere products of the imagination. This suggests that the word "imagination" is often used in two different ways. Although nothing contradicts true philosophy more than this confusion, I've had to use it in this way in the following discussions. When I contrast imagination with memory, I mean the ability to form our less vivid ideas. When I contrast it with reason, I mean the same ability, but excluding our demonstrative and likely reasoning. When I don't oppose it to either, it doesn't matter whether it's taken in a broader or narrower sense, or at least the context will clarify the meaning.
SECT. X. OF THE INFLUENCE OF BELIEF.
But though education be disclaimed by philosophy, as a fallacious ground of assent to any opinion, it prevails nevertheless in the world, and is the cause why all systems are apt to be rejected at first as new and unusual. This perhaps will be the fate of what I have here advanced concerning belief, and though the proofs I have produced appear to me perfectly conclusive, I expect not to make many proselytes to my opinion. Men will scarce ever be persuaded, that effects of such consequence can flow from principles, which are seemingly so inconsiderable, and that the far greatest part of our reasonings with all our actions and passions, can be derived from nothing but custom and habit. To obviate this objection, I shall here anticipate a little what would more properly fall under our consideration afterwards, when we come to treat of the passions and the sense of beauty.
But even though education is dismissed by philosophy as a misleading basis for believing anything, it still holds power in the world and is why all new and unfamiliar ideas are often initially rejected. This might be the experience of what I’ve presented here about belief, and while the evidence I've provided seems completely convincing to me, I don’t expect to win over many converts to my viewpoint. People are rarely persuaded that such significant effects can come from principles that seem so trivial, and that most of our reasoning, along with all our actions and emotions, can be traced back to nothing more than custom and habit. To address this objection, I will briefly touch on some ideas that would be better suited for later discussion when we delve into the passions and the sense of beauty.
There is implanted in the human mind a perception of pain and pleasure, as the chief spring and moving principle of all its actions. But pain and pleasure have two ways of making their appearance in the mind; of which the one has effects very different from the other. They may either appear in impression to the actual feeling, or only in idea, as at present when I mention them. It is evident the influence of these upon our actions is far from being equal. Impressions always actuate the soul, and that in the highest degree; but it is not every idea which has the same effect. Nature has proceeded with caution in this came, and seems to have carefully avoided the inconveniences of two extremes. Did impressions alone influence the will, we should every moment of our lives be subject to the greatest calamities; because, though we foresaw their approach, we should not be provided by nature with any principle of action, which might impel us to avoid them. On the other hand, did every idea influence our actions, our condition would not be much mended. For such is the unsteadiness and activity of thought, that the images of every thing, especially of goods and evils, are always wandering in the mind; and were it moved by every idle conception of this kind, it would never enjoy a moment's peace and tranquillity.
The human mind has a built-in sense of pain and pleasure, which serves as the main driver behind all its actions. However, pain and pleasure can present themselves in two different ways, each having very different effects. They can either be felt directly or exist only as an idea, like right now when I mention them. It's clear that their impact on our actions is not the same. Actual feelings always stimulate the soul powerfully, but not every idea has that same influence. Nature has been careful in this regard, seemingly avoiding the potential problems of two extremes. If only feelings influenced our will, we would constantly face the worst disasters because, although we might predict them, we wouldn't have any natural instinct pushing us to avoid them. Conversely, if every idea influenced our actions, our situation wouldn't improve much. The mind is so restless and active that thoughts about everything, especially good and bad things, are always drifting around; if it reacted to every fleeting thought, it would never find a moment of peace or calm.
Nature has, therefore, chosen a medium, and has neither bestowed on every idea of good and evil the power of actuating the will, nor yet has entirely excluded them from this influence. Though an idle fiction has no efficacy, yet we find by experience, that the ideas of those objects, which we believe either are or will be existent, produce in a lesser degree the same effect with those impressions, which are immediately present to the senses and perception. The effect, then, of belief is to raise up a simple idea to an equality with our impressions, and bestow on it a like influence on the passions. This effect it can only have by making an idea approach an impression in force and vivacity. For as the different degrees of force make all the original difference betwixt an impression and an idea, they must of consequence be the source of all the differences in the effects of these perceptions, and their removal, in whole or in part, the cause of every new resemblance they acquire. Wherever we can make an idea approach the impressions in force and vivacity, it will likewise imitate them in its influence on the mind; and vice versa, where it imitates them in that influence, as in the present case, this must proceed from its approaching them in force and vivacity. Belief, therefore, since it causes an idea to imitate the effects of the impressions, must make it resemble them in these qualities, and is nothing but A MORE VIVID AND INTENSE CONCEPTION OF ANY IDEA. This, then, may both serve as an additional argument for the present system, and may give us a notion after what manner our reasonings from causation are able to operate on the will and passions.
Nature has, therefore, chosen a medium, and has neither granted every notion of good and evil the ability to motivate the will, nor completely excluded them from this influence. Although an idle fiction lacks power, we find through experience that the ideas of objects we believe actually exist or will exist have a similar, albeit lesser, effect compared to those impressions that are immediately present to our senses and perceptions. The effect of belief is to elevate a simple idea to a level comparable to our impressions, giving it a similar influence on our emotions. It can only achieve this by making an idea resemble an impression in strength and liveliness. Since the different levels of strength create all the original differences between an impression and an idea, they must therefore be the source of all differences in the effects of these perceptions, and their complete or partial removal is the reason for any new similarities they develop. Whenever we can make an idea match the impressions in strength and liveliness, it will also reflect them in its influence on the mind; conversely, when it resembles them in that influence, as in this case, it must be due to its matching them in strength and liveliness. Belief, therefore, since it causes an idea to reflect the effects of the impressions, must make it similar to them in these qualities and is nothing more than A MORE VIVID AND INTENSE CONCEPTION OF ANY IDEA. This can serve both as further justification for the current system and as a basis for understanding how our reasoning about causation can influence the will and emotions.
As belief is almost absolutely requisite to the exciting our passions, so the passions in their turn are very favourable to belief; and not only such facts as convey agreeable emotions, but very often such as give pain, do upon that account become more readily the objects of faith and opinion. A coward, whose fears are easily awakened, readily assents to every account of danger he meets with; as a person of a sorrowful and melancholy disposition is very credulous of every thing, that nourishes his prevailing passion. When any affecting object is presented, it gives the alarm, and excites immediately a degree of its proper passion; especially in persons who are naturally inclined to that passion. This emotion passes by an easy transition to the imagination; and diffusing itself over our idea of the affecting object, makes us form that idea with greater force and vivacity, and consequently assent to it, according to the precedent system. Admiration and surprize have the same effect as the other passions; and accordingly we may observe, that among the vulgar, quacks and projectors meet with a more easy faith upon account of their magnificent pretensions, than if they kept themselves within the bounds of moderation. The first astonishment, which naturally attends their miraculous relations, spreads itself over the whole soul, and so vivifies and enlivens the idea, that it resembles the inferences we draw from experience. This is a mystery, with which we may be already a little acquainted, and which we shall have farther occasion to be let into in the progress of this treatise.
As belief is almost essential for stirring our emotions, emotions, in turn, support belief; not just facts that bring us joy, but often those that cause pain become more easily accepted as true. A coward, whose fears are easily triggered, readily agrees with every report of danger he encounters; similarly, someone who is sad and melancholic is very gullible to anything that feeds into their dominant feelings. When a touching subject is presented, it triggers an alarm and immediately stirs up a degree of the appropriate emotion, especially in those who are naturally inclined towards that emotion. This feeling easily transitions to the imagination; it spreads over our perception of the touching subject, causing us to form a stronger, more vivid idea and, accordingly, accept it based on our previous beliefs. Amazement and surprise have the same effect as other emotions; thus, we can see that among the general public, charlatans and promoters gain a more willing belief due to their grand claims than if they stayed within reasonable limits. The initial shock that naturally accompanies their miraculous stories permeates the whole mind, enlivening the idea so much that it resembles conclusions drawn from experience. This is a mystery we may already be somewhat familiar with and one we will explore further as we progress through this treatise.
After this account of the influence of belief on the passions, we shall find less difficulty in explaining its effects on the imagination, however extraordinary they may appear. It is certain we cannot take pleasure in any discourse, where our judgment gives no assent to those images which are presented to our fancy. The conversation of those who have acquired a habit of lying, though in affairs of no moment, never gives any satisfaction; and that because those ideas they present to us, not being attended with belief, make no impression upon the mind. Poets themselves, though liars by profession, always endeavour to give an air of truth to their fictions; and where that is totally neglected, their performances, however ingenious, will never be able to afford much pleasure. In short, we may observe, that even when ideas have no manner of influence on the will and passions, truth and reality are still requisite, in order to make them entertaining to the imagination.
After discussing how belief influences our emotions, it becomes easier to explain its effects on the imagination, no matter how unusual they might seem. It's clear we can't enjoy any conversation where our judgment doesn't agree with the images presented to us. The chats of those who frequently lie, even about trivial matters, are never satisfying because the ideas they share, lacking belief, leave no mark on our minds. Poets, despite being professional storytellers, always try to add an element of truth to their creations; when that’s completely missing, their work, no matter how clever, won’t provide much enjoyment. In short, we can see that even when ideas don't affect our will and emotions, truth and reality are still necessary to make them interesting to our imagination.
But if we compare together all the phenomena that occur on this head, we shall find, that truth, however necessary it may seem in all works of genius, has no other effect than to procure an easy reception for the ideas, and to make the mind acquiesce in them with satisfaction, or at least without reluctance. But as this is an effect, which may easily be supposed to flow from that solidity and force, which, according to my system, attend those ideas that are established by reasonings from causation; it follows, that all the influence of belief upon the fancy may be explained from that system. Accordingly we may observe, that wherever that influence arises from any other principles beside truth or reality, they supply its place, and give an equal entertainment to the imagination. Poets have formed what they call a poetical system of things, which though it be believed neither by themselves nor readers, is commonly esteemed a sufficient foundation for any fiction. We have been so much accustomed to the names of MARS, JUPITER, VENUS, that in the same manner as education infixes any opinion, the constant repetition of these ideas makes them enter into the mind with facility, and prevail upon the fancy, without influencing the judgment. In like manner tragedians always borrow their fable, or at least the names of their principal actors, from some known passage in history; and that not in order to deceive the spectators; for they will frankly confess, that truth is not in any circumstance inviolably observed: but in order to procure a more easy reception into the imagination for those extraordinary events, which they represent. But this is a precaution, which is not required of comic poets, whose personages and incidents, being of a more familiar kind, enter easily into the conception, and are received without any such formality, even though at first night they be known to be fictitious, and the pure offspring of the fancy.
But if we compare all the phenomena related to this topic, we'll find that truth, no matter how necessary it might seem in works of genius, mainly serves to ensure that ideas are easily accepted, allowing the mind to agree with them comfortably, or at least without hesitation. This effect can easily be seen as stemming from the solidity and strength that, according to my system, come with ideas established through reasoning based on causation, which means that the influence of belief on the imagination can be explained through that system. Therefore, we can observe that wherever this influence comes from principles other than truth or reality, those principles take their place and provide equal engagement for the imagination. Poets have created what they call a poetic system, which, although not believed by themselves or their readers, is still generally considered a fair basis for any fiction. We've become so accustomed to names like MARS, JUPITER, and VENUS that, just as education ingrains opinions, the constant repetition of these ideas allows them to enter the mind easily and capture the imagination without affecting judgment. Similarly, tragic playwrights often draw their stories, or at least the names of their main characters, from well-known historical events, not to trick the audience but to help those extraordinary events resonate more easily with the imagination. However, this caution isn't needed for comic playwrights, whose characters and situations are more relatable and easily understood, being accepted without any formality, even if it's clear from the start that they are fictional and purely products of imagination.
This mixture of truth and falshood in the fables of tragic poets not only serves our present purpose, by shewing, that the imagination can be satisfyed without any absolute belief or assurance; but may in another view be regarded as a very strong confirmation of this system. It is evident, that poets make use of this artifice of borrowing the names of their persons, and the chief events of their poems, from history, in order to procure a more easy reception for the whole, and cause it to make a deeper impression on the fancy and affections. The several incidents of the piece acquire a kind of relation by being united into one poem or representation; and if any of these incidents be an object of belief, it bestows a force and vivacity on the others, which are related to it. The vividness of the first conception diffuses itself along the relations, and is conveyed, as by so many pipes or canals, to every idea that has any communication with the primary one. This, indeed, can never amount to a perfect assurance; and that because the union among the ideas is, in a manner, accidental: But still it approaches so near, in its influence, as may convince us, that they are derived from the same origin. Belief must please the imagination by means of the force and vivacity which attends it; since every idea, which has force and vivacity, is found to be agreeable to that faculty.
This mix of truth and fiction in the stories of tragic poets not only helps our current point by showing that the imagination can be satisfied without complete belief or certainty, but it can also be seen as a strong support for this idea. It's clear that poets use the trick of borrowing names of their characters and key events from history to make their work more easily accepted and have a stronger impact on the imagination and emotions. The various incidents in the work create a connection by being combined into one poem or performance; if any of these incidents are believable, they give strength and vibrancy to the others that are linked to it. The intensity of the initial idea spreads through the connections and is transmitted, like water through pipes or canals, to every concept that relates to the primary one. However, this can never provide complete certainty, as the connection between the ideas is somewhat random. Still, it comes close enough in its effect to convince us that they come from the same source. Belief must engage the imagination through the strength and vibrancy that accompanies it, since every idea that has strength and vibrancy is found to be appealing to that faculty.
To confirm this we may observe, that the assistance is mutual betwixt the judgment and fancy, as well as betwixt the judgment and passion; and that belief not only gives vigour to the imagination, but that a vigorous and strong imagination is of all talents the most proper to procure belief and authority. It is difficult for us to withhold our assent from what is painted out to us in all the colours of eloquence; and the vivacity produced by the fancy is in many cases greater than that which arises from custom and experience. We are hurried away by the lively imagination of our author or companion; and even he himself is often a victim to his own fire and genius.
To confirm this, we can observe that there is a mutual assistance between judgment and imagination, as well as between judgment and emotion; and that belief not only energizes the imagination, but also that a strong and vivid imagination is the best talent for gaining belief and authority. It’s hard for us to withhold our agreement from what is presented to us with all the flair of eloquence; and the excitement created by imagination often surpasses what comes from tradition and experience. We get swept away by the vivid imagination of our author or friend; and even he is often caught up in his own passion and creativity.
Nor will it be amiss to remark, that as a lively imagination very often degenerates into madness or folly, and bears it a great resemblance in its operations; so they influence the judgment after the same manner, and produce belief from the very same principles. When the imagination, from any extraordinary ferment of the blood and spirits, acquires such a vivacity as disorders all its powers and faculties, there is no means of distinguishing betwixt truth and falshood; but every loose fiction or idea, having the same influence as the impressions of the memory, or the conclusions of the judgment, is received on the same footing, and operates with equal force on the passions. A present impression and a customary transition are now no longer necessary to enliven our ideas. Every chimera of the brain is as vivid and intense as any of those inferences, which we formerly dignifyed with the name of conclusions concerning matters of fact, and sometimes as the present impressions of the senses.
It’s worth noting that a vivid imagination often slips into madness or foolishness, resembling it in many ways; similarly, both influence our judgment and create beliefs based on the same core principles. When the imagination, due to some intense disturbance of the blood and spirit, gains such intensity that it disrupts its functions and abilities, there's no way to tell apart truth from falsehood. Every wild idea or fantasy has the same effect as memories or sound judgments, being accepted equally and having a strong impact on our emotions. We no longer need immediate impressions or familiar transitions to animate our thoughts. Every wild notion is as vibrant and powerful as those conclusions we once proudly called facts, and sometimes as immediate as our current sensory experiences.
We may observe the same effect of poetry in a lesser degree; and this is common both to poetry and madness, that the vivacity they bestow on the ideas is not derived from the particular situations or connexions of the objects of these ideas, but from the present temper and disposition of the person. But how great soever the pitch may be, to which this vivacity rises, it is evident, that in poetry it never has the same feeling with that which arises in the mind, when we reason, though even upon the lowest species of probability. The mind can easily distinguish betwixt the one and the other; and whatever emotion the poetical enthusiasm may give to the spirits, it is still the mere phantom of belief or persuasion. The case is the same with the idea, as with the passion it occasions. There is no passion of the human mind but what may arise from poetry; though at the same time the feelings of the passions are very different when excited by poetical fictions, from what they are when they are from belief and reality. A passion, which is disagreeable in real life, may afford the highest entertainment in a tragedy, or epic poem. In the latter case, it lies not with that weight upon us: It feels less firm and solid: And has no other than the agreeable effect of exciting the spirits, and rouzing the attention. The difference in the passions is a clear proof of a like difference in those ideas, from which the passions are derived. Where the vivacity arises from a customary conjunction with a present impression; though the imagination may not, in appearance, be so much moved; yet there is always something more forcible and real in its actions, than in the fervors of poetry and eloquence. The force of our mental actions in this case, no more than in any other, is not to be measured by the apparent agitation of the mind. A poetical description may have a more sensible effect on the fancy, than an historical narration. It may collect more of those circumstances, that form a compleat image or picture. It may seem to set the object before us in more lively colours. But still the ideas it presents are different to the feeling from those, which arise from the memory and the judgment. There is something weak and imperfect amidst all that seeming vehemence of thought and sentiment, which attends the fictions of poetry.
We can see a similar effect of poetry, but to a lesser extent; and this is true for both poetry and madness: the liveliness they give to ideas doesn’t come from the specific situations or connections of those ideas, but from the current mood and mindset of the individual. However intense this liveliness may be, it’s clear that in poetry it doesn’t feel the same as when we think rationally, even about the simplest forms of probability. The mind can easily tell the difference between the two; and whatever emotion the poetic enthusiasm might stir in us, it remains just an illusion of belief or persuasion. The situation is the same with the idea as it is with the emotion it creates. Any passion of the human mind can emerge from poetry; still, the feelings associated with those passions are very different when triggered by poetic fictions than when they come from actual belief and reality. A feeling that is unpleasant in real life can bring great enjoyment in a tragedy or epic poem. In the latter case, it doesn’t weigh as heavily on us: it feels less firm and solid and only has the pleasant effect of lifting our spirits and grabbing our attention. The difference in our feelings is clear proof of a similar difference in the ideas that give rise to those feelings. When vivacity comes from a usual connection with a current impression, even if the imagination doesn’t seem as stirred, there’s always something more powerful and real in its actions than in the excitement of poetry and eloquence. The strength of our mental actions in this case, just like in any other, isn’t measured by how visibly agitated the mind appears. A poetic description may have a more striking effect on the imagination than a historical narrative. It can capture more of those details that create a complete image or picture. It can seem to present the object to us in more vibrant colors. Yet, the ideas it conveys feel different from those that come from memory and judgment. There’s something weak and incomplete within all that apparent intensity of thought and emotion that surrounds the fabrications of poetry.
We shall afterwards have occasion to remark both the resemblance and differences betwixt a poetical enthusiasm, and a serious conviction. In the mean time I cannot forbear observing, that the great difference in their feeling proceeds in some measure from reflection and GENERAL RULES. We observe, that the vigour of conception, which fictions receive from poetry and eloquence, is a circumstance merely accidental, of which every idea is equally susceptible; and that such fictions are connected with nothing that is real. This observation makes us only lend ourselves, so to speak, to the fiction: But causes the idea to feel very different from the eternal established persuasions founded on memory and custom. They are somewhat of the same kind: But the one is much inferior to the other, both in its causes and effects.
We will later discuss both the similarities and differences between poetic enthusiasm and serious conviction. In the meantime, I can't help but point out that the significant difference in their feelings comes partly from reflection and GENERAL RULES. We see that the strength of imagination, which fictional works gain from poetry and eloquence, is just an accidental feature that any idea can embody; these fictions have no real connections. This observation makes us engage with the fiction, so to speak, but it also leads the idea to feel quite different from the deep, established beliefs based on memory and custom. They are somewhat related, but one is clearly inferior to the other in terms of both its causes and effects.
A like reflection on general rules keeps us from augmenting our belief upon every encrease of the force and vivacity of our ideas. Where an opinion admits of no doubt, or opposite probability, we attribute to it a full conviction: though the want of resemblance, or contiguity, may render its force inferior to that of other opinions. It is thus the understanding corrects the appearances of the senses, and makes us imagine, that an object at twenty foot distance seems even to the eye as large as one of the same dimensions at ten.
A similar reflection on general rules prevents us from increasing our belief with every boost in the strength and clarity of our ideas. When an opinion leaves no room for doubt or conflicting chances, we give it our full conviction; however, the lack of similarity or connection can make its influence weaker than that of other opinions. This is how our understanding adjusts what our senses perceive, leading us to think that an object twenty feet away appears just as large to the eye as one of the same size that is ten feet away.
We may observe the same effect of poetry in a lesser degree; only with this difference, that the least reflection dissipates the illusions of poetry, and Places the objects in their proper light. It is however certain, that in the warmth of a poetical enthusiasm, a poet has a counterfeit belief, and even a kind of vision of his objects: And if there be any shadow of argument to support this belief, nothing contributes more to his full conviction than a blaze of poetical figures and images, which have their effect upon the poet himself, as well as upon his readers.
We can see a similar effect in poetry, though it's less intense; the only difference is that just a little thought can break the illusions created by poetry and show things as they really are. However, it’s clear that when a poet feels a surge of creative passion, they experience a kind of false belief and even a sort of vision of their subjects. If there’s any reason to justify this belief, nothing strengthens the poet’s conviction more than a burst of poetic imagery and metaphors, which influence both the poet and their readers.
SECT. XI. OF THE PROBABILITY OF CHANCES.
But in order to bestow on this system its full force and evidence, we must carry our eye from it a moment to consider its consequences, and explain from the same principles some other species of reasoning, which are derived from the same origin.
But to give this system its full strength and clarity, we need to take a moment to look away from it to consider its impacts and explain, using the same principles, some other types of reasoning that come from the same source.
Those philosophers, who have divided human reason into knowledge and probability, and have defined the first to be that evidence, which arises from the comparison of ideas, are obliged to comprehend all our arguments from causes or effects under the general term of probability. But though every one be free to use his terms in what sense he pleases; and accordingly in the precedent part of this discourse, I have followed this method of expression; it is however certain, that in common discourse we readily affirm, that many arguments from causation exceed probability, and may be received as a superior kind of evidence. One would appear ridiculous, who would say, that it is only probable the sun will rise to-morrow, or that all men must dye; though it is plain we have no further assurance of these facts, than what experience affords us. For this reason, it would perhaps be more convenient, in order at once to preserve the common signification of words, and mark the several degrees of evidence, to distinguish human reason into three kinds, viz. THAT FROM KNOWLEDGE, FROM PROOFS, AND FROM PROBABILITIES. By knowledge, I mean the assurance arising from the comparison of ideas. By proofs, those arguments, which are derived from the relation of cause and effect, and which are entirely free from doubt and uncertainty. By probability, that evidence, which is still attended with uncertainty. It is this last species of reasoning, I proceed to examine.
Those philosophers who have split human reason into knowledge and probability, defining knowledge as evidence that comes from comparing ideas, have to categorize all our arguments based on causes or effects under the general term of probability. Even though everyone is free to use terms however they like—like I’ve done in the earlier part of this discussion—it’s clear that in everyday conversation, we often assert that many arguments from causation are more certain than probability and can be accepted as a higher form of evidence. It would seem ridiculous to claim that it's only probable the sun will rise tomorrow, or that everyone must die, even though we clearly have no more assurance of these facts than what experience provides. For this reason, it might be more practical to maintain the common meanings of words while indicating the different levels of evidence by categorizing human reason into three types: THAT FROM KNOWLEDGE, FROM PROOFS, AND FROM PROBABILITIES. By knowledge, I mean the certainty that comes from comparing ideas. By proofs, I’m referring to arguments derived from cause and effect relationships that are completely free from doubt and uncertainty. By probability, I mean the evidence that still carries some uncertainty. It is this last type of reasoning that I will examine next.
Probability or reasoning from conjecture may be divided into two kinds, viz. that which is founded on chance, and that which arises from causes. We shall consider each of these in order.
Probability or reasoning based on guesswork can be categorized into two types: one based on chance and the other based on causes. We will examine each of these in turn.
The idea of cause and effect is derived from experience, which presenting us with certain objects constantly conjoined with each other, produces such a habit of surveying them in that relation, that we cannot without a sensible violence survey them iii any other. On the other hand, as chance is nothing real in itself, and, properly speaking, is merely the negation of a cause, its influence on the mind is contrary to that of causation; and it is essential to it, to leave the imagination perfectly indifferent, either to consider the existence or non-existence of that object, which is regarded as contingent. A cause traces the way to our thought, and in a manner forces us to survey such certain objects, in such certain relations. Chance can only destroy this determination of the thought, and leave the mind in its native situation of indifference; in which, upon the absence of a cause, it is instantly re-instated.
The concept of cause and effect comes from experience, which, by consistently presenting us with certain objects linked together, creates a habit of viewing them in that way. As a result, we find it hard to see them in any other light without feeling a noticeable discomfort. On the flip side, since chance isn’t something real on its own and is really just the absence of a cause, its effect on our mind works differently from causation. It keeps our imagination neutral, making us indifferent to whether an object that is considered contingent exists or not. A cause directs our thoughts and somewhat compels us to view specific objects in specific relationships. Chance, on the other hand, can only disrupt this focus and leave our minds in a natural state of indifference, where, in the absence of a cause, we quickly revert back to that state.
Since therefore an entire indifference is essential to chance, no one chance can possibly be superior to another, otherwise than as it is composed of a superior number of equal chances. For if we affirm that one chance can, after any other manner, be superior to another, we must at the same time affirm, that there is something, which gives it the superiority, and determines the event rather to that side than the other: That is, in other words, we must allow of a cause, and destroy the supposition of chance; which we had before established. A perfect and total indifference is essential to chance, and one total indifference can never in itself be either superior or inferior to another. This truth is not peculiar to my system, but is acknowledged by every one, that forms calculations concerning chances.
Since total indifference is essential to chance, no single chance can be better than another except when it consists of a greater number of equal chances. If we claim that one chance can somehow be better than another, we must also admit that there is something that gives it that advantage and affects the outcome in its favor. In other words, we have to recognize a cause and negate the idea of chance, which we had previously established. A perfect and complete indifference is crucial to chance, and one complete indifference can never be inherently better or worse than another. This truth isn't unique to my theory but is recognized by everyone who makes calculations regarding chances.
And here it is remarkable, that though chance and causation be directly contrary, yet it is impossible for us to conceive this combination of chances, which is requisite to render one hazard superior to another, without supposing a mixture of causes among the chances, and a conjunction of necessity in some particulars, with a total indifference in others. Where nothing limits the chances, every notion, that the most extravagant fancy can form, is upon a footing of equality; nor can there be any circumstance to give one the advantage above another. Thus unless we allow, that there are some causes to make the dice fall, and preserve their form in their fall, and lie upon some one of their sides, we can form no calculation concerning the laws of hazard. But supposing these causes to operate, and supposing likewise all the rest to be indifferent and to be determined by chance, it is easy to arrive at a notion of a superior combination of chances. A dye that has four sides marked with a certain number of spots, and only two with another, affords us an obvious and easy instance of this superiority. The mind is here limited by the causes to such a precise number and quality of the events; and at the same time is undetermined in its choice of any particular event.
It's interesting to note that even though chance and causation are directly opposed, it's hard for us to imagine the combination of chances needed for one risk to be better than another without thinking there’s a mix of causes among those chances, along with some necessary connections in certain situations, while being completely random in others. When nothing restricts the chances, every idea, no matter how outrageous, stands on equal ground; no circumstance can give one an edge over the other. Unless we accept that there are some causes influencing how the dice land and keep their shape while falling, and settle on one of their sides, we can't make any calculations about the laws of chance. But if we assume these causes are at work, and everything else is random, it becomes straightforward to understand a better combination of chances. A die with four sides showing a specific number of spots and only two showing another is a clear and simple example of this superiority. Here, our thinking is limited by the causes to a specific number and type of outcomes, while still being open in our choice of any particular outcome.
Proceeding then in that reasoning, wherein we have advanced three steps; that chance is merely the negation of a cause, and produces a total indifference in the mind; that one negation of a cause and one total indifference can never be superior or inferior to another; and that there must always be a mixture of causes among the chances, in order to be the foundation of any reasoning: We are next to consider what effect a superior combination of chances can have upon the mind, and after what manner it influences our judgment and opinion. Here we may repeat all the same arguments we employed in examining that belief, which arises from causes; and may prove, after the same manner, that a superior number of chances produces our assent neither by demonstration nor probability. It is indeed evident that we can never by the comparison of mere ideas make any discovery, which can be of consequence in this affairs and that it is impossible to prove with certainty, that any event must fall on that side where there is a superior number of chances. To, suppose in this case any certainty, were to overthrow what we have established concerning the opposition of chances, and their perfect equality and indifference.
Following the reasoning we've used, we've made three points: that chance is simply the absence of a cause, leading to complete indifference in the mind; that one absence of a cause and one complete indifference is never greater or lesser than another; and that there always needs to be a mix of causes among chances to form the basis of any reasoning. Next, we should think about what impact a greater combination of chances has on the mind and how it affects our judgment and opinions. Here, we can repeat the same arguments we used when looking at the belief that comes from causes and show, in the same way, that a larger number of chances doesn't lead us to agree through demonstration or probability. It's clear that we can't discover anything meaningful just by comparing mere ideas, and it's impossible to prove for sure that any event will land on the side with more chances. To assume any certainty in this case would contradict what we've established about the opposition of chances, as well as their complete equality and indifference.
Should it be said, that though in an opposition of chances it is impossible to determine with certainty, on which side the event will fall, yet we can pronounce with certainty, that it is more likely and probable, it will be on that side where there is a superior number of chances, than where there is an inferior: should this be said, I would ask, what is here meant by likelihood and probability? The likelihood and probability of chances is a superior number of equal chances; and consequently when we say it is likely the event win fall on the side, which is superior, rather than on the inferior, we do no more than affirm, that where there is a superior number of chances there is actually a superior, and where there is an inferior there is an inferior; which are identical propositions, and of no consequence. The question is, by what means a superior number of equal chances operates upon the mind, and produces belief or assent; since it appears, that it is neither by arguments derived from demonstration, nor from probability.
It's been said that while we can't determine for sure where an event will land in a situation with competing chances, we can confidently state that it’s more likely to be on the side with more chances than on the side with fewer. If that's the case, I’d ask: what do we mean by likelihood and probability here? Likelihood and probability of chances come from having a greater number of equal chances; therefore, when we claim that it is likely the event will favor the side with more chances rather than the side with fewer, we're simply stating that where there are more chances, there are indeed more, and where there are fewer, there are fewer. These are identical statements and hold no real significance. The real question is how a greater number of equal chances influences the mind and creates belief or agreement, since it seems that it’s neither from arguments based on demonstration nor from probability.
In order to clear up this difficulty, we shall suppose a person to take a dye, formed after such a manner as that four of its sides are marked with one figure, or one number of spots, and two with another; and to put this dye into the box with an intention of throwing it: It is plain, he must conclude the one figure to be more probable than the other, and give the preference to that which is inscribed on the greatest number of sides. He in a manner believes, that this will lie uppermost; though still with hesitation and doubt, in proportion to the number of chances, which are contrary: And according as these contrary chances diminish, and the superiority encreases on the other side, his belief acquires new degrees of stability and assurance. This belief arises from an operation of the mind upon the simple and limited object before us; and therefore its nature will be the more easily discovered and explained. We have nothing but one single dye to contemplate, in order to comprehend one of the most curious operations of the understanding.
To resolve this issue, let's imagine a person has a die, where four of its faces show one figure or number of spots and two show another. When they put this die into a box with the intention of rolling it, it's clear that they must consider the first figure to be more likely than the second and prefer the one that appears on the most sides. They essentially believe that this will be the face that lands on top, though they still have some hesitation and doubt based on the number of unfavorable outcomes. As those unfavorable outcomes decrease and the likelihood of the preferred outcome increases, their belief becomes more stable and certain. This belief comes from the way the mind processes the simple and straightforward object in front of us, making its nature easier to identify and explain. We only need to focus on this one die to understand one of the most interesting functions of the mind.
This dye, formed as above, contains three circumstances worthy of our attention. First, Certain causes, such as gravity, solidity, a cubical figure, &c. which determine it to fall, to preserve its form in its fall, and to turn up one of its sides. Secondly, A certain number of sides, which are supposed indifferent. Thirdly, A certain figure inscribed on each side. These three particulars form the whole nature of the dye, so far as relates to our present purpose; and consequently are the only circumstances regarded by the mind in its forming a judgment concerning the result of such a throw. Let us, therefore, consider gradually and carefully what must be the influence of these circumstances on the thought and imagination.
This die, created as mentioned earlier, has three aspects worth noting. First, there are specific factors like gravity, solidity, a cube shape, etc., that cause it to fall, maintain its shape while falling, and land on one of its faces. Second, there’s a certain number of faces that are considered neutral. Third, there’s a specific design on each face. These three elements encompass the entire nature of the die, as it relates to our current focus, and are the only factors the mind considers when judging the outcome of a roll. So, let’s examine gradually and carefully how these factors influence thought and imagination.
First, We have already observed, that the mind is determined by custom to pass from any cause to its effect, and that upon the appearance of the one, it is almost impossible for it not to form an idea of the other. Their constant conjunction in past instances has produced such a habit in the mind, that it always conjoins them in its thought, and infers the existence of the one from that of its usual attendant. When it considers the dye as no longer supported by the box, it can not without violence regard it as suspended in the air; but naturally places it on the table, and views it as turning up one of its sides. This is the effect of the intermingled causes, which are requisite to our forming any calculation concerning chances.
First, we have already noted that the mind tends to connect any cause with its effect, and when one appears, it’s almost impossible not to think of the other. Their repeated association in the past has created a habit in the mind, so it always links them together in thought and assumes one exists because the other does. When it sees the dye no longer in the box, it struggles to imagine it floating in the air; instead, it naturally places it on the table and perceives it as tipping onto one side. This is the result of the intermingled causes that we need for making any predictions about probabilities.
Secondly, It is supposed, that though the dye be necessarily determined to fall, and turn up one of its sides, yet there is nothing to fix the particular side, but that this is determined entirely by chance. The very nature and essence of chance is a negation of causes, and the leaving the mind in a perfect indifference among those events, which are supposed contingent. When therefore the thought is determined by the causes to consider the dye as falling and turning up one of its sides, the chances present all these sides as equal, and make us consider every one of them, one after another, as alike probable and possible. The imagination passes from the cause, viz. the throwing of the dye, to the effect, viz. the turning up one of the six sides; and feels a kind of impossibility both of stopping short in the way, and of forming any other idea. But as all these six sides are incompatible, and the dye cannot turn up above one at once, this principle directs us not to consider all of them at once as lying uppermost; which we look upon as impossible: Neither does it direct us with its entire force to any particular side; for in that case this side would be considered as certain and inevitable; but it directs us to the whole six sides after such a manner as to divide its force equally among them. We conclude in general, that some one of them must result from the throw: We run all of them over in our minds: The determination of the thought is common to all; but no more of its force falls to the share of any one, than what is suitable to its proportion with the rest. It is after this manner the original impulse, and consequently the vivacity of thought, arising from the causes, is divided and split in pieces by the intermingled chances.
Secondly, it is believed that although the die is destined to fall and land on one of its sides, there is no way to determine which side will be facing up; this is entirely left to chance. The very nature of chance ignores causes and leaves the mind indifferent among the supposed random outcomes. When we focus on the die falling and landing on one of its sides, all these sides are presented to us as equal options, making us think of each one as equally likely and possible. Our imagination shifts from the cause, which is throwing the die, to the effect, which is landing on one of the six sides; and we find it hard to stop at any point or come up with a different idea. However, since all six sides cannot appear simultaneously and the die can only show one at a time, this principle tells us not to see all of them as facing up at once, which we think is impossible. It also doesn’t force our attention onto a specific side because that would make it seem certain and unavoidable; instead, it directs our consideration to all six sides in a way that divides our focus evenly among them. We generally conclude that one of them must come up from the roll: we mentally go through all of them. The focus of thought is shared among all sides, but none receives more attention than what’s proportional to the others. This is how the initial impulse, and thus the vividness of thought driven by the causes, is split and scattered by the mixed chances.
We have already seen the influence of the two first qualities of the dye, viz. the causes, and the number and indifference of the sides, and have learned how they give an impulse to the thought, and divide that impulse into as many parts as there are unites in the number of sides. We must now consider the effects of the third particular, viz. the figures inscribed on each side. It is evident that where several sides have the same figure inscribe on them, they must concur in their influence on the mind, and must unite upon one image or idea of a figure all those divided impulses, that were dispersed over the several sides, upon which that figure is inscribed. Were the question only what side will be turned up, these are all perfectly equal, and no one could ever have any advantage above another. But as the question is concerning the figure, and as the same figure is presented by more than one side: it is evident, that the impulses belonging to all these sides must re-unite in that one figure, and become stronger and more forcible by the union. Four sides are supposed in the present case to have the same figure inscribed on them, and two to have another figure. The impulses of the former are, therefore, superior to those of the latter. But as the events are contrary, and it is impossible both these figures can be turned up; the impulses likewise become contrary, and the inferior destroys the superior, as far as its strength goes. The vivacity of the idea is always proportionable to the degrees of the impulse or tendency to the transition; and belief is the same with the vivacity of the idea, according to the precedent doctrine.
We've already looked at how the first two qualities of the dye affect things, which are the causes and the number and indifference of the sides. We’ve learned how they drive thought and split that drive into as many parts as there are units in the number of sides. Now we need to explore the effects of the third aspect, which is the figures drawn on each side. It's clear that when several sides have the same figure on them, they will combine in their effect on the mind and unify all those divided impulses into one image or idea of that figure, which is inscribed on the different sides. If the question were simply which side would show up, all sides would be perfectly equal, and no one would have an advantage over another. However, since the question concerns the figure, and the same figure appears on more than one side, it’s evident that the impulses from all these sides must come together in that one figure and become stronger through their union. In this case, four sides are assumed to have the same figure inscribed on them, while two have a different figure. Therefore, the impulses from the former are greater than those from the latter. But since the outcomes are opposing, and it’s impossible for both figures to appear, the impulses also become opposing, and the weaker one cancels out the stronger one, at least to its extent. The intensity of the idea is always proportional to the strength of the impulse or tendency toward the change, and belief correlates with the intensity of the idea, according to the earlier argument.
SECT. XII. OF THE PROBABILITY OF CAUSES.
What I have said concerning the probability of chances can serve to no other purpose, than to assist us in explaining the probability of causes; since it is commonly allowed by philosophers, that what the vulgar call chance is nothing but a secret and concealed cause. That species of probability, therefore, is what we must chiefly examine.
What I've mentioned about the likelihood of chances can only help us understand the likelihood of causes; because philosophers generally agree that what people commonly refer to as chance is really just a hidden and undisclosed cause. So, that type of probability is what we need to focus on the most.
The probabilities of causes are of several kinds; but are all derived from the same origin, viz. THE ASSOCIATION OF IDEAS TO A PRESENT IMPRESSION. As the habit, which produces the association, arises from the frequent conjunction of objects, it must arrive at its perfection by degrees, and must acquire new force from each instance, that falls under our observation. The first instance has little or no force: The second makes some addition to it: The third becomes still more sensible; and it is by these slow steps, that our judgment arrives at a full assurance. But before it attains this pitch of perfection, it passes through several inferior degrees, and in all of them is only to be esteemed a presumption or probability. The gradation, therefore, from probabilities to proofs is in many cases insensible; and the difference betwixt these kinds of evidence is more easily perceived in the remote degrees, than in the near and contiguous.
The chances of causes come in several forms, but they all stem from the same source: THE ASSOCIATION OF IDEAS TO A PRESENT IMPRESSION. Since the habit that creates the association develops from the repeated linking of objects, it must reach its peak gradually, gaining strength with each instance we observe. The first instance carries little weight: the second adds some strength; the third becomes even more noticeable. It is through these gradual steps that our judgment achieves full confidence. However, before reaching this level of certainty, it goes through several lower degrees, where it should only be viewed as a presumption or probability. Therefore, the transition from probabilities to proofs is often subtle, and the distinction between these types of evidence is easier to notice at more distant stages than at the closer, adjacent ones.
It is worthy of remark on this occasion, that though the species of probability here explained be the first in order, and naturally takes place before any entire proof can exist, yet no one, who is arrived at the age of maturity, can any longer be acquainted with it. It is true, nothing is more common than for people of the most advanced knowledge to have attained only an imperfect experience of many particular events; which naturally produces only an imperfect habit and transition: But then we must consider, that the mind, having formed another observation concerning the connexion of causes and effects, gives new force to its reasoning from that observation; and by means of it can build an argument on one single experiment, when duly prepared and examined. What we have found once to follow from any object, we conclude will for ever follow from it; and if this maxim be not always built upon as certain, it is not for want of a sufficient number of experiments, but because we frequently meet with instances to the contrary; which leads us to the second species of probability, where there is a contrariety in our experience and observation.
It's worth noting that while the type of probability discussed here is the first in order and naturally comes before any complete proof can exist, no one who has reached adulthood can remain unaware of it. It's true that it's common for highly knowledgeable people to only have a limited experience with many specific events, which leads to only a partial understanding and transition. However, we must also recognize that the mind, having formed another observation about the connection between causes and effects, strengthens its reasoning based on that observation; it can then build an argument from a single experiment when it is properly prepared and examined. What we have observed to consistently follow from any object, we assume will always follow from it; and if this principle is not always regarded as certain, it’s not due to a lack of sufficient experiments but because we often encounter contradicting cases, which brings us to the second type of probability, where there is a conflict in our experience and observation.
It would be very happy for men in the conduct of their lives and actions, were the same objects always conjoined together, and, we had nothing to fear but the mistakes of our own judgment, without having any reason to apprehend the uncertainty of nature. But as it is frequently found, that one observation is contrary to another, and that causes and effects follow not in the same order, of which we have I had experience, we are obliged to vary our reasoning on, account of this uncertainty, and take into consideration the contrariety of events. The first question, that occurs on this head, is concerning the nature and causes of the contrariety.
It would be very beneficial for people in how they live and act if the same outcomes were always linked together, and we only had to worry about the errors in our own judgment, without fearing the unpredictability of nature. However, since it's often the case that one observation contradicts another, and causes and effects don't always follow in the same order, which we have experienced firsthand, we have to adjust our reasoning because of this uncertainty and consider the conflicting events. The first question that comes to mind regarding this is about the nature and causes of the contradictions.
The vulgar, who take things according to their first appearance, attribute the uncertainty of events to such an uncertainty in the causes, as makes them often fail of their usual influence, though they meet with no obstacle nor impediment in their operation. But philosophers observing, that almost in every part of nature there is contained a vast variety of springs and principles, which are hid, by reason of their minuteness or remoteness, find that it is at least possible the contrariety of events may not proceed from any contingency in the cause, but from the secret operation of contrary causes. This possibility is converted into certainty by farther observation, when they remark, that upon an exact scrutiny, a contrariety of effects always betrays a contrariety of causes, and proceeds from their mutual hindrance and opposition. A peasant can give no better reason for the stopping of any clock or watch than to say, that commonly it does not go right: But an artizan easily perceives, that the same force in the spring or pendulum has always the same influence on the wheels; but fails of its usual effect, perhaps by reason of a grain of dust, which puts a stop to the whole movement. From the observation of several parallel instances, philosophers form a maxim, that the connexion betwixt all causes and effects is equally necessary, and that its seeming uncertainty in some instances proceeds from the secret opposition of contrary causes.
Those who are overly simplistic and take things at face value attribute the unpredictability of events to a similar uncertainty in their causes, which often fails to have its usual impact, even when there are no visible obstacles in its way. However, philosophers notice that nearly every aspect of nature contains a wide variety of hidden mechanisms and principles, either due to their small size or their distance. They realize that the contradictory nature of events may not arise from random chance in the causes, but rather from the hidden effects of opposing causes. This possibility becomes a certainty upon deeper examination, as they find that a contradiction in effects usually indicates a contradiction in causes, resulting from their interference with each other. A farmer might not be able to explain why a clock or watch has stopped any better than saying it usually doesn’t work properly. In contrast, a craftsman understands that the same force acting on a spring or pendulum consistently affects the gears, but may fail to work correctly due to something as minor as a speck of dust that halts the entire mechanism. From observing several similar cases, philosophers develop a principle that the relationship between all causes and effects is equally essential, and that the seeming unpredictability in some situations stems from hidden conflicts between opposing causes.
But however philosophers and the vulgar may differ in their explication of the contrariety of events, their inferences from it are always of the same kind, and founded on the same principles. A contrariety of events in the past may give us a kind of hesitating belief for the future after two several ways. First, By producing an imperfect habit and transition from the present impression to the related idea. When the conjunction of any two objects is frequent, without being entirely constant, the mind is determined to pass from one object to the other; but not with so entire a habit, as when the union is uninterrupted, and all the instances we have ever met with are uniform and of a piece-.. We find from common experience, in our actions as well as reasonings, that a constant perseverance in any course of life produces a strong inclination and tendency to continue for the future; though there are habits of inferior degrees of force, proportioned to the inferior degrees of steadiness and uniformity in our conduct.
But even though philosophers and regular people might interpret the contradiction of events differently, their conclusions are always similar and based on the same principles. A contradiction of events in the past can lead to a kind of uncertain belief for the future in two ways. First, by creating an imperfect habit that connects the current impression to the related idea. When two objects are frequently associated but not completely constant, the mind tends to move from one object to the other, but not as strongly as when the connection is uninterrupted and all the examples we've encountered are consistent. From common experience, both in our actions and reasoning, we see that consistently pursuing a certain path creates a strong inclination to continue that path in the future, even though there are habits with lesser degrees of strength that correspond to lower levels of consistency in our behavior.
There is no doubt but this principle sometimes takes place, and produces those inferences we draw from contrary phaenomena: though I am perswaded, that upon examination we shall not find it to be the principle, that most commonly influences the mind in this species of reasoning. When we follow only the habitual determination of the mind, we make the transition without any reflection, and interpose not a moment's delay betwixt the view of one object and the belief of that, which is often found to attend it. As the custom depends not upon any deliberation, it operates immediately, without allowing any time for reflection. But this method of proceeding we have but few instances of in our probable reasonings; and even fewer than in those, which are derived from the uninterrupted conjunction of objects. In the former species of reasoning we commonly take knowingly into consideration the contrariety of past events; we compare the different sides of the contrariety, and carefully weigh the experiments, which we have on each side: Whence we may conclude, that our reasonings of this kind arise not directly from the habit, but in an oblique manner; which we must now endeavour to explain.
There's no doubt that this principle sometimes comes into play and leads us to the conclusions we make from opposing phenomena. However, I believe that, upon closer examination, we will find it’s not the principle that usually influences our thinking in this type of reasoning. When we simply follow our usual mental patterns, we make the leap without any thought and don’t take even a moment to pause between seeing one thing and believing in what often follows it. Since habits don’t rely on any deliberation, they act immediately, without giving us time to think. But we have few examples of this in our probable reasoning, and even fewer when it comes to cases involving the continuous connection of objects. In the former type of reasoning, we typically consciously consider the contradictions of past events; we compare different aspects of the opposition and carefully evaluate the evidence on each side. From this, we can conclude that our reasoning in this area doesn’t stem directly from habit, but rather in a roundabout way, which we now need to explain.
It is evident, that when an object is attended with contrary effects, we judge of them only by our past experience, and always consider those as possible, which we have observed to follow from it. And as past experience regulates our judgment concerning the possibility of these effects, so it does that concerning their probability; and that effect, which has been the most common, we always esteem the most likely. Here then are two things to be considered, viz. the reasons which determine us to make the past a standard for the future, and the manner how we extract a single judgment from a contrariety of past events.
It’s clear that when an object brings about opposite effects, we only evaluate them based on our previous experiences, and we always see as possible those that we've seen happen before. Just like our past experiences shape our judgment about the possibility of these effects, they also influence our thoughts on how likely they are; we tend to regard the effect that has occurred most often as the most probable. Therefore, there are two things to consider: the reasons that lead us to use the past as a guide for the future, and how we form a single judgment from conflicting past events.
First we may observe, that the supposition, that the future resembles the past, is not founded on arguments of any kind, but is derived entirely from habit, by which we are determined to expect for the future the same train of objects, to which we have been accustomed. This habit or determination to transfer the past to the future is full and perfect; and consequently the first impulse of the imagination in this species of reasoning is endowed with the same qualities.
First, we can note that the assumption that the future will be like the past is not based on any logical arguments but comes entirely from habit. This habit leads us to expect the same sequence of events in the future that we have become accustomed to in the past. This habit or tendency to project the past onto the future is complete and strong; therefore, the initial instinct of the imagination in this type of reasoning shares the same characteristics.
But, secondly, when in considering past experiments we find them of a contrary nature, this determination, though full and perfect in itself, presents us with no steady object, but offers us a number of disagreeing images in a certain order and proportion. The first impulse, therefore, is here broke into pieces, and diffuses itself over all those images, of which each partakes an equal share of that force and vivacity, that is derived from the impulse. Any of these past events may again happen; and we judge, that when they do happen, they will be mixed in the same proportion as in the past.
But, secondly, when we look back at previous experiments and find that they contradict each other, this conclusion, although complete and thorough on its own, does not give us a clear and consistent perspective. Instead, it presents us with a series of conflicting images arranged in a particular order and ratio. Therefore, the initial drive gets fragmented and spreads out across all those images, with each one receiving an equal amount of the force and liveliness that comes from that drive. Any of these past events could happen again, and we believe that when they do occur, they will be mixed in the same proportions as they were before.
If our intention, therefore, be to consider the proportions of contrary events in a great number of instances, the images presented by our past experience must remain in their FIRST FORM, and preserve their first proportions. Suppose, for instance, I have found by long observation, that of twenty ships, which go to sea, only nineteen return. Suppose I see at present twenty ships that leave the port: I transfer my past experience to the future, and represent to myself nineteen of these ships as returning in safety, and one as perishing. Concerning this there can be no difficulty. But as we frequently run over those several ideas of past events, in order to form a judgment concerning one single event, which appears uncertain; this consideration must change the FIRST FORM of our ideas, and draw together the divided images presented by experience; since it is to it we refer the determination of that particular event, upon which we reason. Many of these images are supposed to concur, and a superior number to concur on one side. These agreeing images unite together, and render the idea more strong and lively, not only than a mere fiction of the imagination, but also than any idea, which is supported by a lesser number of experiments. Each new experiment is as a new stroke of the pencil, which bestows an additional vivacity on the colours without either multiplying or enlarging the figure. This operation of the mind has been so fully explained in treating of the probability of chance, that I need not here endeavour to render it more intelligible. Every past experiment may be considered as a kind of chance; I it being uncertain to us, whether the object will exist conformable to one experiment or another. And for this reason every thing that has been said on the one subject is applicable to both.
If we want to look at the proportions of different outcomes across many situations, the images from our past experiences need to stay in their ORIGINAL FORM and keep their initial proportions. For example, if I've observed over time that out of twenty ships that go to sea, only nineteen come back, and I see another twenty ships leaving the port now, I project my past experience into the future and imagine that nineteen of these ships will return safely, while one will be lost. This idea is straightforward. However, since we often revisit these various ideas from past events to form a judgment about a single event that seems uncertain, this process must change the ORIGINAL FORM of our ideas and bring together the separate images created by experience; as we rely on this to determine that specific event we are thinking about. Many of these images are thought to agree, and a greater number is expected to support one side. These agreeing images come together, making the idea much stronger and more vivid, not just compared to a simple imagination but also against any idea backed by fewer experiments. Each new experiment acts like a new stroke of paint, adding more vibrancy to the colors without multiplying or enlarging the image. This mental process has been thoroughly explained when discussing the probability of chance, so I won't try to make it clearer here. Every past experiment can be seen as a type of chance, since it's uncertain whether the outcome will align with one experiment or another. That’s why everything said about one topic applies to both.
Thus upon the whole, contrary experiments produce an imperfect belief, either by weakening the habit, or by dividing and afterwards joining in different parts, that perfect habit, which makes us conclude in general, that instances, of which we have no experience, must necessarily resemble those of which we have.
Thus, overall, opposing experiments create an incomplete belief, either by weakening the habit or by splitting and then rejoining different parts of that perfect habit, which leads us to generally conclude that instances we have no experience with must necessarily resemble those we do.
To justify still farther this account of the second species of probability, where we reason with knowledge and reflection from a contrariety of past experiments, I shall propose the following considerations, without fearing to give offence by that air of subtilty, which attends them. Just reasoning ought still, perhaps, to retain its force, however subtile; in the same manner as matter preserves its solidity in the air, and fire, and animal spirits, as well as in the grosser and more sensible forms.
To further justify this discussion of the second type of probability, where we draw conclusions based on knowledge and reflection from contrasting past experiments, I will present the following points, not worrying about appearing overly clever. Sound reasoning should still hold its power, no matter how subtle it may be, just as matter maintains its solidity in air, fire, and animal spirits, as well as in more tangible and noticeable forms.
First, We may observe, that there is no probability so great as not to allow of a contrary possibility; because otherwise it would cease to be a probability, and would become a certainty. That probability of causes, which is most extensive, and which we at present examine, depends on a contrariety of experiments: and it is evident an experiment in the past proves at least a possibility for the future.
First, we can see that no probability is so high that it doesn’t allow for a possible opposite outcome; otherwise, it would stop being a probability and become a certainty. The probability of causes that we are currently looking at is based on opposing experiments: and it's clear that an experiment from the past at least shows a possibility for the future.
Secondly, The component parts of this possibility and probability are of the same nature, and differ in number only, but not in kind. It has been observed, that all single chances are entirely equal, and that the only circumstance, which can give any event, that is contingent, a superiority over another is a superior number of chances. In like manner, as the uncertainty of causes is discovery by experience, which presents us with a view of contrary events, it is plain, that when we transfer the past to the future, the known to the unknown, every past experiment has the same weight, and that it is only a superior number of them, which can throw the ballance on any side. The possibility, therefore, which enters into every reasoning of this kind, is composed of parts, which are of the same nature both among themselves, and with those, that compose the opposite probability.
Secondly, the different parts of this possibility and probability are of the same nature and only differ in quantity, not in type. It has been noted that all single chances are completely equal, and the only factor that can give one contingent event an advantage over another is a greater number of chances. Similarly, as uncertainty about causes is revealed through experience, which shows us contrasting events, it is clear that when we apply lessons from the past to the future, the known to the unknown, each past experiment carries the same weight, and it's only a greater number of them that can tip the scales in favor of one side. Therefore, the possibility that plays a role in reasoning like this consists of parts that are of the same nature, both among themselves and with those that make up the opposing probability.
Thirdly, We may establish it as a certain maxim, that in all moral as well as natural phaenomena, wherever any cause consists of a number of parts, and the effect encreases or diminishes, according to the variation of that number, the effects properly speaking, is a compounded one, and arises from the union of the several effects, that proceed from each part of the cause. Thus, because the gravity of a body encreases or diminishes by the encrease or diminution of its parts, we conclude that each part contains this quality and contributes to the gravity of the whole. The absence or presence of a part of the cause is attended with that of a proportionable part of the effect. This connexion or constant conjunction sufficiently proves the one part to be the cause of the other. As the belief which we have of any event, encreases or diminishes according to the number of chances or past experiments, it is to be considered as a compounded effect, of which each part arises from a proportionable number of chances or experiments.
Thirdly, we can establish as a certainty that in all moral and natural phenomena, whenever a cause is made up of multiple parts, and the effect increases or decreases with changes in that number, the effect is a combined one. It comes from the combination of the various effects produced by each part of the cause. For instance, since the weight of an object increases or decreases with the number of its parts, we conclude that each part has this property and adds to the weight of the whole. The absence or presence of a part of the cause corresponds to a proportional change in the effect. This connection or consistent relationship clearly shows that one part is the cause of the other. Similarly, our belief in any event grows or diminishes according to the number of possibilities or past experiences, and it should be viewed as a combined effect, where each part comes from a proportional number of possibilities or experiences.
Let us now join these three observations, and see what conclusion we can draw from them. To every probability there is an opposite possibility. This possibility is composed of parts, that are entirely of the same nature with those of the probability; and consequently have the same influence on the mind and understanding. The belief, which attends the probability, is a compounded effect, and is formed by the concurrence of the several effects, which proceed from each part of the probability. Since therefore each part of the probability contributes to the production of the belief, each part of the possibility must have the same influence on the opposite side; the nature of these parts being entirely the same. The contrary belief, attending the possibility, implies a view of a certain object, as well as the probability does an opposite view. In this particular both these degrees of belief are alike. The only manner then, in which the superior number of similar component parts in the one can exert its influence, and prevail above the inferior in the other, is by producing a stronger and more lively view of its object. Each part presents a particular view; and all these views uniting together produce one general view, which is fuller and more distinct by the greater number of causes or principles, from which it is derived.
Let’s now put these three observations together and see what conclusion we can reach. For every probability, there’s an opposite possibility. This possibility consists of parts that are entirely similar to those making up the probability and thus have the same effect on our thoughts and understanding. The belief linked to the probability is a combined effect created by the agreement of the different effects arising from each part of the probability. Since each part of the probability contributes to forming the belief, each part of the possibility has the same effect on the opposite side, as the nature of these parts is completely the same. The belief that comes with the possibility involves a perception of a specific object, just as the probability involves an opposing perception. In this regard, both levels of belief are similar. The only way in which the larger number of similar parts in one can have more influence and outweigh the fewer in the other is by creating a stronger and clearer perception of its object. Each part presents a specific viewpoint, and when all these viewpoints come together, they create a general view that is richer and more detailed due to the larger number of causes or principles it stems from.
The component parts of the probability and possibility, being alike in their nature, must produce like effects; and the likeness of their effects consists in this, that each of them presents a view of a particular object. But though these parts be alike in their nature, they are very different in their quantity and number; and this difference must appear in the effect as well as the similarity. Now as the view they present is in both cases full and entire, and comprehends the object in all its parts, it is impossible that in this particular there can be any difference; nor is there any thing but a superior vivacity in the probability, arising from the concurrence of a superior number of views, which can distinguish these effects.
The components of probability and possibility are similar in nature and therefore create similar effects; the similarity of these effects lies in the way each one offers a perspective on a specific object. However, while these components share the same nature, they differ significantly in quantity and number, and this variation must be reflected in the effects, as well as their similarities. Since the perspective they provide in both instances is complete and encompasses the object in all its aspects, there can be no difference in that regard. The only distinction arises from the greater intensity in probability, which comes from the combination of a higher number of perspectives, setting these effects apart.
Here is almost the same argument in a different light. All our reasonings concerning the probability of causes are founded on the transferring of past to future. The transferring of any past experiment to the future is sufficient to give us a view of the object; whether that experiment be single or combined with others of the same kind; whether it be entire, or opposed by others of a contrary kind. Suppose, then, it acquires both these qualities of combination and opposition, it loses not upon that account its former power of presenting a view of the object, but only concurs with and opposes other experiments, that have a like influence. A question, therefore, may arise concerning the manner both of the concurrence and opposition. As to the concurrence, there is only the choice left betwixt these two hypotheses. First, That the view of the object, occasioned by the transference of each past experiment, preserves itself entire, and only multiplies the number of views. Or, SECONDLY, That it runs into the other similar and correspondent views, and gives them a superior degree of force and vivacity. But that the first hypothesis is erroneous, is evident from experience, which informs us, that the belief, attending any reasoning, consists in one conclusion, not in a multitude of similar ones, which would only distract the mind, and in many cases would be too numerous to be comprehended distinctly by any finite capacity. It remains, therefore, as the only reasonable opinion, that these similar views run into each other, and unite their forces; so as to produce a stronger and clearer view, than what arises from any one alone. This is the manner, in which past experiments concur, when they are transfered to any future event. As to the manner of their opposition, it is evident, that as the contrary views are incompatible with each other, and it is impossible the object can at once exist conformable to both of them, their influence becomes mutually destructive, and the mind is determined to the superior only with that force, which remains, after subtracting the inferior.
Here’s a similar argument presented in a different way. All our reasoning about the likelihood of causes is based on applying past experiences to future situations. Applying any previous experiment to the future is enough to give us a perspective on the object, whether that experiment is individual or combined with others of the same type, and whether it is whole or countered by opposing ones. So, if it has both qualities of combination and opposition, it doesn’t lose its ability to present a view of the object; it just interacts with and counters other experiments that have a similar impact. Therefore, a question might come up about how both concurrence and opposition work. Regarding concurrence, we are left with a choice between these two hypotheses. First, that the perspective of the object, created by the transfer of each past experiment, remains intact and only increases the number of views. Or, second, that it merges with other similar and corresponding views, giving them a greater level of strength and clarity. However, the first hypothesis is clearly wrong based on experience, which tells us that belief in any reasoning results in one conclusion, not in a multitude of similar ones that would only confuse the mind, often becoming too many to be clearly understood by any finite capacity. Therefore, the only reasonable view left is that these similar perspectives merge and combine their strengths to create a stronger and clearer view than any single one could produce. This describes how past experiments collaborate when applied to any future event. As for their opposition, it is clear that since opposing views cannot coexist, and it’s impossible for the object to align with both at the same time, their effects cancel each other out, leaving the mind directed only toward the stronger one, with its influence reduced by the lesser.
I am sensible how abstruse all this reasoning must appear to the generality of readers, who not being accustomed to such profound reflections on the intellectual faculties of the mind, will be apt to reject as chimerical whatever strikes not in with the common received notions, and with the easiest and most obvious principles of philosophy. And no doubt there are some pains required to enter into these arguments; though perhaps very little are necessary to perceive the imperfection of every vulgar hypothesis on this subject, and the little light, which philosophy can yet afford us in such sublime and such curious speculations. Let men be once fully perswaded of these two principles, THAT THERE, IS NOTHING IN ANY OBJECT, CONSIDERED IN ITSELF, WHICH CAN AFFORD US A REASON FOR DRAWING A CONCLUSION BEYOND it; and, THAT EVEN AFTER THE OBSERVATION OF THE FREQUENT OR CONSTANT CONJUNCTION OF OBJECTS, WE HAVE NO REASON TO DRAW ANY INFERENCE CONCERNING ANY OBJECT BEYOND THOSE OF WHICH WE HAVE HAD EXPERIENCE; I say, let men be once fully convinced of these two principles, and this will throw them so loose from all common systems, that they will make no difficulty of receiving any, which may appear the most extraordinary. These principles we have found to be sufficiently convincing, even with regard to our most certain reasonings from causation: But I shall venture to affirm, that with regard to these conjectural or probable reasonings they still acquire a new degree of evidence.
I know how complicated all this reasoning must seem to most readers, who, not being used to such deep thoughts about the mind's intellectual capabilities, are likely to dismiss as unrealistic anything that doesn’t align with common beliefs or the simplest and most obvious principles of philosophy. It certainly takes some effort to engage with these arguments; however, it may require very little effort to recognize the shortcomings of every popular theory on this topic and the limited insight that philosophy can provide in such lofty and intriguing discussions. Once people are fully convinced of these two principles—that nothing in any object, when considered on its own, can give us a reason to draw a conclusion beyond it; and that even after observing the frequent or constant combination of objects, we have no reason to make any inferences about anything beyond what we've actually experienced—once people grasp these ideas, they'll find themselves free from all conventional systems, making it easy to accept whatever seems most extraordinary. We have found these principles to be strong enough even when it comes to our most certain reasoning about causation; and I would even argue that in relation to more conjectural or probable reasoning, they gain an entirely new level of evidence.
First, It is obvious, that in reasonings of this kind, it is not the object presented to us, which, considered in itself, affords us any reason to draw a conclusion concerning any other object or event. For as this latter object is supposed uncertain, and as the uncertainty is derived from a concealed contrariety of causes in the former, were any of the causes placed in the known qualities of that object, they would no longer be concealed, nor would our conclusion be uncertain.
First, it's clear that in discussions like this, it's not the object we're looking at that gives us any reason to conclude anything about another object or event. Since the latter object is seen as uncertain, and that uncertainty comes from hidden conflicting causes in the former, if any of those causes were related to the known qualities of that object, they wouldn't be hidden anymore, and our conclusion wouldn't be uncertain.
But, secondly, it is equally obvious in this species of reasoning, that if the transference of the past to the future were founded merely on a conclusion of the understanding, it could never occasion any belief or assurance. When we transfer contrary experiments to the future, we can only repeat these contrary experiments with their particular proportions; which could not produce assurance in any single event, upon which we reason, unless the fancy melted together all those images that concur, and extracted from them one single idea or image, which is intense and lively in proportion to the number of experiments from which it is derived, and their superiority above their antagonists. Our past experience presents no determinate object; and as our belief, however faint, fixes itself on a determinate object, it is evident that the belief arises not merely from the transference of past to future, but from some operation of the fancy conjoined with it. This may lead us to conceive the manner, in which that faculty enters into all our reasonings.
But, secondly, it's also clear in this type of reasoning that if transferring the past to the future were based only on a conclusion of the mind, it couldn’t create any belief or certainty. When we apply contradictory experiments to the future, we can only repeat those contradictory experiments with their specific proportions; this wouldn’t provide certainty in any single event we’re reasoning about unless the imagination blended all those images together and extracted one single idea or image, which is strong and vivid according to the number of experiments it comes from and their superiority over their opposites. Our past experience doesn’t present a clear object; and since our belief, however weak, focuses on a clear object, it’s clear that the belief doesn’t come solely from transferring past events to future ones, but also from some activity of the imagination combined with it. This might help us understand how that faculty plays a role in all our reasoning.
I shall conclude this subject with two reflections, which may deserve our attention. The FIRST may be explained after this manner. When the mind forms a reasoning concerning any matter of fact, which is only probable, it casts its eye backward upon past experience, and transferring it to the future, is presented with so many contrary views of its object, of which those that are of the same kind uniting together, and running into one act of the mind, serve to fortify and inliven it. But suppose that this multitude of views or glimpses of an object proceeds not from experience, but from a voluntary act of the imagination; this effect does not follow, or at least, follows not in the same degree. For though custom and education produce belief by such a repetition, as is not derived from experience, yet this requires a long tract of time, along with a very frequent and undesigned repetition. In general we may pronounce, that a person who would voluntarily repeat any idea in his mind, though supported by one past experience, would be no more inclined to believe the existence of its object, than if he had contented himself with one survey of it. Beside the effect of design; each act of the mind, being separate and independent, has a separate influence, and joins not its force with that of its fellows. Not being united by any common object, producing them, they have no relation to each other; and consequently make no transition or union of forces. This phænomenon we shall understand better afterwards.
I'll wrap up this topic with two thoughts that might be worth considering. The FIRST can be explained like this. When the mind thinks about any fact that’s only likely, it looks back at past experiences and applies that to the future. This leads to various conflicting perspectives on the subject, which, when similar ones group together and merge into a single thought, help strengthen and bring energy to that thought. But if this flood of perspectives on an object comes not from experience but from a deliberate act of imagination, that effect doesn’t happen, or at least not to the same extent. Even though habits and education can create belief through such repetition, which isn’t based on experience, this takes a long time and requires frequent and unintentional repetition. Generally, we can say that someone who deliberately repeats an idea in their mind, even if it's supported by one past experience, would be no more likely to believe in its existence than if they had only considered it once. Besides the impact of intention, each thought is separate and independent, influencing on its own and not combining its strength with others. Lacking a shared objective to tie them together, they have no connections to each other, and thus don’t create any transition or merging of forces. We’ll understand this phenomenon better later.
My second reflection is founded on those large probabilities, which the mind can judge of, and the minute differences it can observe betwixt them. When the chances or experiments on one side amount to ten thousand, and on the other to ten thousand and one, the judgment gives the preference to the latter, upon account of that superiority; though it is plainly impossible for the mind to run over every particular view, and distinguish the superior vivacity of the image arising from the superior number, where the difference is so inconsiderable. We have a parallel instance in the affections. It is evident, according to the principles above-mentioned, that when an object produces any passion in us, which varies according to the different quantity of the object; I say, it is evident, that the passion, properly speaking, is not a simple emotion, but a compounded one, of a great number of weaker passions, derived from a view of each part of the object. For otherwise it were impossible the passion should encrease by the encrease of these parts. Thus a man, who desires a thousand pound, has in reality a thousand or more desires which uniting together, seem to make only one passion; though the composition evidently betrays itself upon every alteration of the object, by the preference he gives to the larger number, if superior only by an unite. Yet nothing can be more certain, than that so small a difference would not be discernible in the passions, nor could render them distinguishable from each other. The difference, therefore, of our conduct in preferring the greater number depends not upon our passions, but upon custom, and general rules. We have found in a multitude of instances, that the augmenting the numbers of any sum augments the passion, where the numbers are precise and the difference sensible. The mind can perceive from its immediate feeling, that three guineas produce a greater passion than two; and this it transfers to larger numbers, because of the resemblance; and by a general rule assigns to a thousand guineas, a stronger passion than to nine hundred and ninety nine. These general rules we shall explain presently.
My second thought is based on those large probabilities that the mind can assess and the slight differences it can notice between them. When the chances or experiments on one side amount to ten thousand and on the other to ten thousand and one, the judgment leans towards the latter due to that slight edge; though it is clear that it’s impossible for the mind to consider every single detail and distinguish the greater vividness of the image that comes from the larger number when the difference is so small. There's a similar example in our feelings. It's clear, based on the principles mentioned earlier, that when an object stirs any emotion in us that varies according to the amount of the object, it’s clear that the emotion is not just a single feeling but a mix of many weaker feelings that come from viewing each part of the object. Otherwise, it wouldn’t be possible for the emotion to increase with the increase in these parts. So a person who desires a thousand pounds actually has a thousand or more desires that, when combined, appear to create just one feeling; yet this combination becomes obvious with any change in the object, as shown by the preference for the larger number, even if it’s just by one. However, it’s certain that such a small difference wouldn’t be noticeable in our emotions, nor could it make them distinguishable from one another. Therefore, our behavior in preferring the larger number doesn’t stem from our emotions but from habits and general rules. We’ve seen in many examples that increasing the numbers of any total amplifies the emotion when the amounts are clear and the difference is noticeable. The mind can feel right away that three guineas create a stronger emotion than two; it applies this understanding to larger numbers because of the similarity, and by a general rule, assigns a stronger emotion to a thousand guineas compared to nine hundred ninety-nine. We’ll explain these general rules shortly.
But beside these two species of probability, which are derived from an imperfect experience and from contrary causes, there is a third arising from ANALOGY, which differs from them in some material circumstances. According to the hypothesis above explained all kinds of reasoning from causes or effects are founded on two particulars, viz., the constant conjunction of any two objects in all past experience, and the resemblance of a present object to any one of them. The effect of these two particulars is, that the present object invigorates and inlivens the imagination; and the resemblance, along with the constant union, conveys this force and vivacity to the related idea; which we are therefore said to believe, or assent to. If you weaken either the union or resemblance, you weaken the principle of transition, and of consequence that belief, which arises from it. The vivacity of the first impression cannot be fully conveyed to the related idea, either where the conjunction of their objects is not constant, or where the present impression does not perfectly resemble any of those, whose union we are accustomed to observe. In those probabilities of chance and causes above-explained, it is the constancy of the union, which is diminished; and in the probability derived from analogy, it is the resemblance only, which is affected. Without some degree of resemblance, as well as union, it is impossible there can be any reasoning: but as this resemblance admits of many different degrees, the reasoning becomes proportionably more or less firm and certain. An experiment loses of its force, when transferred to instances, which are not exactly resembling; though it is evident it may still retain as much as may be the foundation of probability, as long as there is any resemblance remaining.
But besides these two types of probability, which come from imperfect experience and opposing causes, there is a third type that arises from ANALOGY, which differs from them in some significant ways. According to the hypothesis explained earlier, all reasoning from causes or effects is based on two key points: the consistent connection between any two objects in all past experiences and the similarity of a present object to either of them. The effect of these two points is that the present object stimulates and energizes the imagination; and the similarity, combined with the constant connection, transfers this energy and liveliness to the related idea, which we then say we believe or agree with. If you weaken either the connection or the similarity, you weaken the process of transitioning to that belief. The liveliness of the initial impression cannot be completely transferred to the related idea if the connection between their objects isn’t constant or if the current impression doesn’t closely resemble any of those we are used to seeing together. In the probabilities of chance and causes described earlier, it's the constancy of the connection that decreases; in analogy-based probability, it's only the similarity that is impacted. Without some degree of both similarity and connection, reasoning becomes impossible; but since this similarity can vary in many degrees, the reasoning becomes correspondingly more or less solid and certain. An experiment loses some of its effectiveness when applied to examples that aren’t exact matches; however, it’s clear it can still retain enough to form a basis for probability as long as some resemblance exists.
SECT. XIII. OF UNPHILOSOPHICAL PROBABILITY.
All these kinds of probability are received by philosophers, and allowed to be reasonable foundations of belief and opinion. But there are others, that are derived from the same principles, though they have not had the good fortune to obtain the same sanction. The first probability of this kind may be accounted for thus. The diminution of the union, and of the resemblance, as above explained, diminishes the facility of the transition, and by that means weakens the evidence; and we may farther observe, that the same diminution of the evidence will follow from a diminution of the impression, and from the shading of those colours, under which it appears to the memory or senses. The argument, which we found on any matter of fact we remember, is more or less convincing according as the fact is recent or remote; and though the difference in these degrees of evidence be not received by philosophy as solid and legitimate; because in that case an argument must have a different force to day, from what it shall have a month hence; yet notwithstanding the opposition of philosophy, it is certain, this circumstance has a considerable influence on the understanding, and secretly changes the authority of the same argument, according to the different times, in which it is proposed to us. A greater force and vivacity in the impression naturally conveys a greater to the related idea; and it is on the degrees of force and vivacity, that the belief depends, according to the foregoing system.
All these types of probability are accepted by philosophers and considered reasonable foundations for belief and opinion. However, there are others that come from the same principles but haven’t been as fortunate in gaining the same endorsement. The first of these probabilities can be explained as follows. The reduction of the union and resemblance, as explained above, decreases the ease of transition and, in turn, weakens the evidence. We can also observe that a similar reduction in evidence occurs from a decrease in the impression and from the dimming of the colors under which the memory or senses perceive it. The argument based on any fact we remember is more or less convincing depending on whether the fact is recent or distant; and although philosophy does not recognize the differences in these degrees of evidence as solid and legitimate—since that would mean an argument must have different strength today than it would a month from now—regardless of philosophy's stance, it is clear that this factor significantly influences our understanding and subtly alters the authority of the same argument, depending on the different times at which it is presented to us. A stronger and more vivid impression naturally conveys greater relevance to the related idea; and it is on these degrees of strength and vividness that belief relies, according to the previous system.
There is a second difference, which we may frequently observe in our degrees of belief and assurance, and which never fails to take place, though disclaimed by philosophers. An experiment, that is recent and fresh in the memory, affects us more than one that is in some measure obliterated; and has a superior influence on the judgment, as well as on the passions. A lively impression produces more assurance than a faint one; because it has more original force to communicate to the related idea, which thereby acquires a greater force and vivacity. A recent observation has a like effect; because the custom and transition is there more entire, and preserves better the original force in the communication. Thus a drunkard, who has seen his companion die of a debauch, is struck with that instance for some time, and dreads a like accident for himself: But as the memory of it decays away by degrees, his former security returns, and the danger seems less certain and real.
There’s another difference we often notice in how we believe and feel certain, and it always happens, even if philosophers deny it. An experiment that’s recent and fresh in our minds affects us more than one that’s somewhat forgotten; it has a stronger impact on our judgment and emotions. A vivid impression gives us more confidence than a faint one because it has more original power to influence the related idea, which then gains more strength and liveliness. A recent observation has a similar effect because the connection and transition are more complete, maintaining the original power in the communication. For example, a drunk person who has seen their friend die from excessive drinking is affected by that event for a while and fears a similar fate for themselves. But as they gradually forget it, their former sense of security returns, and the danger seems less certain and real.
I add, as a third instance of this kind, that though our reasonings from proofs and from probabilities be considerably different from each other, yet the former species of reasoning often degenerates insensibly into the latter, by nothing but the multitude of connected arguments. It is certain, that when an inference is drawn immediately from an object, without any intermediate cause or effect, the conviction is much stronger, and the persuasion more lively, than when the imagination is carryed through a long chain of connected arguments, however infallible the connexion of each link may be esteemed. It is from the original impression, that the vivacity of all the ideas is derived, by means of the customary transition of the imagination; and it is evident this vivacity must gradually decay in proportion to the distance, and must lose somewhat in each transition. Sometimes this distance has a greater influence than even contrary experiments would have; and a man may receive a more lively conviction from a probable reasoning, which is close and immediate, than from a long chain of consequences, though just and conclusive in each part. Nay it is seldom such reasonings produce any conviction; and one must have a very strong and firm imagination to preserve the evidence to the end, where it passes through so many, stages.
I want to add a third example of this kind, stating that although our reasoning based on proof and reasoning based on probability are quite different from each other, the first type of reasoning can often subtly turn into the second, simply because of the number of connected arguments involved. It's clear that when a conclusion is drawn directly from something, without any middle cause or effect, the belief is much stronger, and the persuasion is more vivid than when the imagination has to go through a long series of connected arguments, no matter how certain each link in that chain is considered. The vividness of all ideas comes from the original impression through the usual flow of the imagination, and it’s obvious this vividness will gradually fade the further removed it is, losing something with each step. Sometimes this distance has more impact than even opposing experiments would, and a person might feel a stronger conviction from a close and immediate line of reasoning than from a long series of conclusions, despite each part being accurate and conclusive. In fact, such reasoning rarely leads to any conviction; it takes a very strong and stable imagination to maintain the evidence all the way through when it goes through so many stages.
But here it may not be amiss to remark a very curious phænomenon, which the present subject suggests to us. It is evident there is no point of ancient history, of which we can have any assurance, but by passing through many millions of causes and effects, and through a chain of arguments of almost an immeasurable length. Before the knowledge of the fact could come to the first historian, it must be conveyed through many mouths; and after it is committed to writing, each new copy is a new object, of which the connexion with the foregoing is known only by experience and observation. Perhaps, therefore, it may be concluded from the precedent reasoning, that the evidence of all ancient history must now be lost; or at least, will be lost in time, as the chain of causes encreases, and runs on to a greater length. But as it seems contrary to common sense to think, that if the republic of letters, and the art of printing continue on the same footing as at present, our posterity, even after a thousand ages, can ever doubt if there has been such a man as JULIUS CAESAR; this may be considered as an objection to the present system. If belief consisted only in a certain vivacity, conveyed from an original impression, it would decay by the length of the transition, and must at last be utterly extinguished: And vice versa, if belief on some occasions be not capable of such an extinction; it must be something different from that vivacity.
But here it might be worth noting a very interesting phenomenon that the current topic brings to mind. It's clear that there is no point in ancient history we can be certain about without navigating through countless causes and effects, along with a chain of arguments that's almost unending. Before the initial historian could learn the fact, it had to pass through many people; and once it's written down, each new copy becomes a new entity, connected to the previous ones only through experience and observation. Therefore, it might be concluded from the previous reasoning that the evidence for all ancient history must now be lost, or at least will gradually disappear over time as the chain of causes continues to grow longer. However, it seems unreasonable to think that if the world of literature and the printing press continue as they are now, our descendants, even after a thousand years, could ever doubt that someone like JULIUS CAESAR existed; this can be seen as an argument against the current system. If belief depended only on a certain vividness passed down from an original impression, it would fade with the length of the transition and eventually disappear entirely. Conversely, if belief can sometimes persist despite such fading, it must be something different from mere vividness.
Before I answer this objection I shall observe, that from this topic there has been borrowed a very celebrated argument against the Christian Religion; but with this difference, that the connexion betwixt each link of the chain in human testimony has been there supposed not to go beyond probability, and to be liable to a degree of doubt and uncertainty. And indeed it must be confest, that in this manner of considering the subject, (which however is not a true one) there is no history or tradition, but what must in the end lose all its force and evidence. Every new probability diminishes the original conviction; and however great that conviction may be supposed, it is impossible it can subsist under such re-iterated diminutions. This is true in general; though we shall find afterwards,[9] that there is one very memorable exception, which is of vast consequence in the present subject of the understanding.
Before I address this objection, I want to point out that a well-known argument against Christianity has been drawn from this topic. However, there’s a key difference: in that argument, the connections between each link of human testimony are assumed to only reach the level of probability and are subject to a degree of doubt and uncertainty. In fact, it's important to acknowledge that when considering the subject this way—which isn't really the right approach—there's no history or tradition that doesn't eventually lose all its strength and credibility. Every new probability weakens the original belief, and no matter how strong that belief may seem, it can't hold up under repeated weakening. This is generally true, although we will discover later, [9] that there is one very notable exception that is highly significant to our current understanding.
[9] Part IV. Sect. 1.
Mean while to give a solution of the preceding objection upon the supposition, that historical evidence amounts at first to an entire proof; let us consider, that though the links are innumerable, that connect any original fact with the present impression, which is the foundation of belief; yet they are all of the same kind, and depend on the fidelity of Printers and Copyists. One edition passes into another, and that into a third, and so on, till we come to that volume we peruse at present. There is no variation in the steps. After we know one we know all of them; and after we have made one, we can have no scruple as to the rest. This circumstance alone preserves the evidence of history, and will perpetuate the memory of the present age to the latest posterity. If all the long chain of causes and effects, which connect any past event with any volume of history, were composed of parts different from each other, and which it were necessary for the mind distinctly to conceive, it is impossible we should preserve to the end any belief or evidence. But as most of these proofs are perfectly resembling, the mind runs easily along them, jumps from one part to another with facility, and forms but a confused and general notion of each link. By this means a long chain of argument, has as little effect in diminishing the original vivacity, as a much shorter would have, if composed of parts, which were different from each other, and of which each required a distinct consideration.
Meanwhile, to address the previous objection on the assumption that historical evidence initially amounts to complete proof; let’s consider that, although there are countless connections linking any original fact to the current impression, which forms the basis of belief, they are all of the same nature and rely on the accuracy of printers and copyists. One edition leads to another, which leads to a third, and so forth, until we arrive at the book we read today. There is no difference in the process. Once we understand one link, we understand all of them; and having made sense of one, we can have no doubt about the rest. This situation alone maintains the evidence of history and will keep the memory of the present age alive for future generations. If the entire long chain of causes and effects connecting any past event to any historical volume were made up of distinct parts that the mind had to grasp separately, it would be impossible to maintain any belief or evidence until the end. However, since most of these proofs are quite similar, the mind easily moves along them, jumps from one part to another effortlessly, and forms only a vague and general understanding of each link. In this way, a long chain of argument has as little effect on reducing the original clarity as a much shorter chain would if it were made up of different parts, each requiring separate consideration.
A fourth unphilosophical species of probability is that derived from general rules, which we rashly form to ourselves, and which are the source of what we properly call PREJUDICE. An IRISHMAN cannot have wit, and a Frenchman cannot have solidity; for which reason, though the conversation of the former in any instance be visibly very agreeable, and of the latter very judicious, we have entertained such a prejudice against them, that they must be dunces or fops in spite of sense and reason. Human nature is very subject to errors of this kind; and perhaps this nation as much as any other.
A fourth unthinking type of probability comes from general rules that we carelessly create for ourselves, which leads to what we truly call PREJUDICE. An IRISHMAN can't be witty, and a Frenchman can't be solid; for this reason, even though the former's conversation is often very enjoyable and the latter's very sensible, we have such a bias against them that we must see them as fools or superficial, despite logic and evidence. Human nature is prone to these kinds of errors, and perhaps this nation is as much affected by them as any other.
Should it be demanded why men form general rules, and allow them to influence their judgment, even contrary to present observation and experience, I should reply, that in my opinion it proceeds from those very principles, on which all judgments concerning causes and effects depend. Our judgments concerning cause and effect are derived from habit and experience; and when we have been accustomed to see one object united to another, our imagination passes from the first to the second, by a natural transition, which precedes reflection, and which cannot be prevented by it. Now it is the nature of custom not only to operate with its full force, when objects are presented, that are exactly the same with those to which we have been accustomed; but also to operate in an inferior degree, when we discover such as are similar; and though the habit loses somewhat of its force by every difference, yet it is seldom entirely destroyed, where any considerable circumstances remain the same. A man, who has contracted a custom of eating fruit by the use of pears or peaches, will satisfy himself with melons, where he cannot find his favourite fruit; as one, who has become a drunkard by the use of red wines, will be carried almost with the same violence to white, if presented to him. From this principle I have accounted for that species of probability, derived from analogy, where we transfer our experience in past instances to objects which are resembling, but are not exactly the same with those concerning which we have had experience. In proportion as the resemblance decays, the probability diminishes; but still has some force as long as there remain any traces of the resemblance.
If someone asks why men create general rules and let them shape their judgment, even when it goes against what they currently observe and experience, I would say that it comes from the same principles that support all judgments about causes and effects. Our judgments about cause and effect come from habit and experience; when we get used to seeing one thing connected to another, our imagination naturally moves from the first to the second without needing to think about it, and this process can't be stopped by reflection. Custom tends to work best when we encounter objects that are exactly the same as those we're familiar with, but it can also function to a lesser extent when we find similar ones. Although the effect of habit diminishes with every difference, it is rarely completely lost as long as some significant factors remain constant. For instance, someone who usually eats fruit like pears or peaches will be satisfied with melons if they can't find their favorites; similarly, a person who has become addicted to red wines will be drawn to white wines almost as strongly when offered. This principle helps explain the type of probability that comes from analogy, where we apply our experiences from past cases to similar but not identical objects. As the similarity lessens, the probability also decreases, but it still holds some weight as long as any resemblance is evident.
This observation we may carry farther; and may remark, that though custom be the foundation of all our judgments, yet sometimes it has an effect on the imagination in opposition to the judgment, and produces a contrariety in our sentiments concerning the same object. I explain myself. In almost all kinds of causes there is a complication of circumstances, of which some are essential, and others superfluous; some are absolutely requisite to the production of the effect, and others are only conjoined by accident. Now we may observe, that when these superfluous circumstances are numerous, and remarkable, and frequently conjoined with the essential, they have such an influence on the imagination, that even in the absence of the latter they carry us on to the conception of the usual effect, and give to that conception a force and vivacity, which make it superior to the mere fictions of the fancy. We may correct this propensity by a reflection on the nature of those circumstances: but it is still certain, that custom takes the start, and gives a biass to the imagination.
We can take this observation further and note that while customs are the basis of all our judgments, they can sometimes affect our imagination in ways that contradict our judgment, leading to conflicting feelings about the same thing. Let me clarify. In almost all types of situations, there's a mix of circumstances, some of which are essential and others are unnecessary; some are absolutely needed to produce the effect, while others are simply coincidental. Now, we can see that when these unnecessary circumstances are abundant, noteworthy, and often found alongside the essential ones, they significantly impact our imagination. Even in the absence of the essential factors, they push us toward imagining the usual outcome and give that imagination a strength and vividness that makes it stronger than mere daydreams. We can adjust this tendency by reflecting on the nature of those circumstances; however, it remains true that customs initially shape and influence our imagination.
To illustrate this by a familiar instance, let us consider the case of a man, who, being hung out from a high tower in a cage of iron cannot forbear trembling, when he surveys the precipice below him, though he knows himself to be perfectly secure from falling, by his experience of the solidity of the iron, which supports him; and though the ideas of fall and descent, and harm and death, be derived solely from custom and experience. The same custom goes beyond the instances, from which it is derived, and to which it perfectly corresponds; and influences his ideas of such objects as are in some respect resembling, but fall not precisely under the same rule. The circumstances of depth and descent strike so strongly upon him, that their influence can-not be destroyed by the contrary circumstances of support and solidity, which ought to give him a perfect security. His imagination runs away with its object, and excites a passion proportioned to it. That passion returns back upon the imagination and inlivens the idea; which lively idea has a new influence on the passion, and in its turn augments its force and violence; and both his fancy and affections, thus mutually supporting each other, cause the whole to have a very great influence upon him.
To illustrate this with a familiar example, let’s consider a man who is suspended from a high tower in an iron cage. He can’t help but tremble when he looks at the drop below him, even though he knows he’s completely safe from falling, thanks to his experience with the sturdy iron that holds him up. The feelings of falling, descending, danger, and death come solely from habit and experience. This habit extends beyond just the specific instances it comes from and affects his thoughts about similar situations that don’t exactly fit the same rules. The depth and the idea of falling impact him so intensely that their effect can’t be overridden by the reassuring factors of support and stability, which should make him feel completely secure. His imagination takes over and stirs up emotions in response. That emotion feeds back into his imagination, making the idea feel even more vivid, which then influences the emotion again, increasing its intensity. With both his thoughts and feelings reinforcing each other, they create a significant effect on him.
But why need we seek for other instances, while the present subject of philosophical probabilities offers us so obvious an one, in the opposition betwixt the judgment and imagination arising from these effects of custom? According to my system, all reasonings are nothing but the effects of custom; and custom has no influence, but by inlivening the imagination, and giving us a strong conception of any object. It may, therefore, be concluded, that our judgment and imagination can never be contrary, and that custom cannot operate on the latter faculty after such a manner, as to render it opposite to the former. This difficulty we can remove after no other manner, than by supposing the influence of general rules. We shall afterwards take[10] notice of some general rules, by which we ought to regulate our judgment concerning causes and effects; and these rules are formed on the nature of our understanding, and on our experience of its operations in the judgments we form concerning objects. By them we learn to distinguish the accidental circumstances from the efficacious causes; and when we find that an effect can be produced without the concurrence of any particular circumstance, we conclude that that circumstance makes not a part of the efficacious cause, however frequently conjoined with it. But as this frequent conjunction necessity makes it have some effect on the imagination, in spite of the opposite conclusion from general rules, the opposition of these two principles produces a contrariety in our thoughts, and causes us to ascribe the one inference to our judgment, and the other to our imagination. The general rule is attributed to our judgment; as being more extensive and constant. The exception to the imagination, as being more capricious and uncertain.
But why should we look for other examples when the current topic of philosophical probabilities gives us such a clear one, in the conflict between judgment and imagination arising from these effects of custom? According to my theory, all reasoning is just the result of custom; and custom only has an effect by stimulating the imagination and providing us with a vivid idea of any object. Therefore, it can be concluded that our judgment and imagination can never truly conflict, and that custom cannot influence the latter in a way that makes it oppose the former. We can resolve this difficulty only by considering the influence of general rules. We will later take[10] notice of some general rules that we should use to guide our judgment about causes and effects; these rules are based on the nature of our understanding and our experience with it in forming judgments about objects. Through them, we learn to differentiate between accidental circumstances and effective causes; and when we find that an effect can occur without the involvement of any specific circumstance, we conclude that this circumstance is not part of the effective cause, no matter how often it is associated with it. However, because this frequent association necessarily makes it influence the imagination, despite the contrary conclusion from general rules, the conflict between these two principles creates a contradiction in our thoughts, leading us to attribute one inference to our judgment and the other to our imagination. The general rule is assigned to our judgment since it is broader and more consistent. The exception is assigned to the imagination because it is more unpredictable and uncertain.
[10] Sect. 15.
Thus our general rules are in a manner set in opposition to each other. When an object appears, that resembles any cause in very considerable circumstances, the imagination naturally carries us to a lively conception of the usual effect, Though the object be different in the most material and most efficacious circumstances from that cause. Here is the first influence of general rules. But when we take a review of this act of the mind, and compare it with the more general and authentic operations of the understanding, we find it to be of an irregular nature, and destructive of all the most established principles of reasonings; which is the cause of our rejecting it. This is a second influence of general rules, and implies the condemnation of the former. Sometimes the one, sometimes the other prevails, according to the disposition and character of the person. The vulgar are commonly guided by the first, and wise men by the second. Mean while the sceptics may here have the pleasure of observing a new and signal contradiction in our reason, and of seeing all philosophy ready to be subverted by a principle of human nature, and again saved by a new direction of the very same principle. The following of general rules is a very unphilosophical species of probability; and yet it is only by following them that we can correct this, and all other unphilosophical probabilities.
So our general rules are sort of at odds with each other. When something looks like a cause under significant circumstances, our imagination tends to jump to a vivid idea of the usual effect, even if the object is quite different in key and influential aspects from that cause. This is the first impact of general rules. But when we reflect on this mental process and compare it with the broader and more reliable functions of our understanding, we realize it's irregular and undermines the most established reasoning principles; that's why we dismiss it. This is the second impact of general rules, contradicting the first. Sometimes one influence wins out, sometimes the other, depending on a person's mindset and character. Most people are typically led by the first, while wise individuals follow the second. Meanwhile, skeptics can enjoy spotting a new and clear contradiction in our reasoning, witnessing how all philosophy is on the brink of being overturned by a principle of human nature, only to be saved again by a new interpretation of that same principle. Following general rules is not a very philosophical kind of probability, but it’s only by adhering to them that we can correct this and other unphilosophical probabilities.
Since we have instances, where general rules operate on the imagination even contrary to the judgment, we need not be surprized to see their effects encrease, when conjoined with that latter faculty, and to observe that they bestow on the ideas they present to us a force superior to what attends any other. Every one knows, there is an indirect manner of insinuating praise or blame, which is much less shocking than the open flattery or censure of any person. However he may communicate his sentiments by such secret insinuations, and make them known with equal certainty as by the open discovery of them, it is certain that their influence is not equally strong and powerful. One who lashes me with concealed strokes of satire, moves not my indignation to such a degree, as if he flatly told me I was a fool and coxcomb; though I equally understand his meaning, as if he did. This difference is to be attributed to the influence of general rules.
Since there are situations where general rules affect our imagination even against our judgment, it shouldn't surprise us to see their effects increase when combined with that latter ability. We can observe that these rules give the ideas they present to us more power than any others. Everyone knows there’s a subtle way to suggest praise or blame that is much less shocking than directly flattering or criticizing someone. Even if he conveys his opinions through these subtle hints and makes them clear just as well as if he openly stated them, it’s evident that their influence is not as strong or forceful. Someone who critiques me with hidden sarcasm doesn’t provoke my anger to the same extent as if he outright called me a fool and a vain person; even though I understand his meaning just as clearly either way. This difference is due to the impact of general rules.
Whether a person openly, abuses me, or slyly intimates his contempt, in neither case do I immediately perceive his sentiment or opinion; and it is only by signs, that is, by its effects, I become sensible of it. The only difference, then, betwixt these two cases consists in this, that in the open discovery of his sentiments he makes use of signs, which are general and universal; and in the secret intimation employs such as are more singular and uncommon. The effect of this circumstance is, that the imagination, in running from the present impression to the absent idea, makes the transition with greater facility, and consequently conceives the object with greater force, where the connexion is common and universal, than where it is more rare and particular. Accordingly we may observe, that the open declaration of our sentiments is called the taking off the mask, as the secret intimation of our opinions is said to be the veiling of them. The difference betwixt an idea produced by a general connexion, and that arising from a particular one is here compared to the difference betwixt an impression and an idea. This difference in the imagination has a suitable effect on the passions; and this effect is augmented by another circumstance. A secret intimation of anger or contempt shews that we still have some consideration for the person, and avoid the directly abusing him. This makes a concealed satire less disagreeable; but still this depends on the same principle. For if an idea were not more feeble, when only intimated, it would never be esteemed a mark of greater respect to proceed in this method than in the other.
Whether someone openly insults me or subtly shows their disdain, I don't immediately recognize their feelings or opinions; I only become aware of it through signs, meaning the effects it has. The only difference between these two situations is that in the open expression of their feelings, they use signs that are general and universal, while in the subtle hinting, they use signs that are more specific and uncommon. This situation affects how easily the mind transitions from the present impression to the absent idea; it's easier and stronger when the connection is common and universal than when it's rare and specific. Consequently, we say that openly expressing our feelings is like taking off a mask, while subtly hinting at our opinions is like veiling them. The difference between an idea formed by a general connection and one formed by a specific one is similar to the difference between an impression and an idea. This difference in the mind influences emotions, and this impact is heightened by another factor. A subtle hint of anger or contempt suggests that we still care about the person and choose not to insult them directly. This makes covert sarcasm less unpleasant, but it still relies on the same principle. If an idea were not weaker when only hinted at, it wouldn't be seen as more respectful to communicate in this way rather than any other.
Sometimes scurrility is less displeasing than delicate satire, because it revenges us in a manner for the injury at the very time it is committed, by affording us a just reason to blame and contemn the person, who injures us. But this phænomenon likewise depends upon the same principle. For why do we blame all gross and injurious language, unless it be, because we esteem it contrary to good breeding and humanity? And why is it contrary, unless it be more shocking than any delicate satire? The rules of good breeding condemn whatever is openly disobliging, and gives a sensible pain and confusion to those, with whom we converse. After this is once established, abusive language is universally blamed, and gives less pain upon account of its coarseness and incivility, which render the person despicable, that employs it. It becomes less disagreeable, merely because originally it is more so; and it is more disagreeable, because it affords an inference by general and common rules, that are palpable and undeniable.
Sometimes, being rude is less bothersome than subtle satire because it gives us a chance to get back at someone for the harm they've done right when it happens, giving us a solid reason to criticize and look down on the person who wrongs us. But this idea works on the same principle. Why do we criticize all harsh and hurtful language if not because we see it as against good manners and humanity? And why is it against these values, unless it's more shocking than any delicate satire? The rules of good manners disapprove of anything that openly offends and causes real pain and embarrassment to those we interact with. Once this is established, abusive language is universally criticized, and it hurts less because of its coarseness and lack of civility, which make the person using it look pathetic. It becomes less unpleasant simply because it was initially worse; and it is worse because it leads to conclusions based on general and obvious rules that are clear and undeniable.
To this explication of the different influence of open and concealed flattery or satire, I shall add the consideration of another phenomenon, which is analogous to it. There are many particulars in the point of honour both of men and women, whose violations, when open and avowed, the world never excuses, but which it is more apt to overlook, when the appearances are saved, and the transgression is secret and concealed. Even those, who know with equal certainty, that the fault is committed, pardon it more easily, when the proofs seem in some measure oblique and equivocal, than when they are direct and undeniable. The same idea is presented in both cases, and, properly speaking, is equally assented to by the judgment; and yet its influence is different, because of the different manner, in which it is presented.
To this explanation of how open and hidden flattery or satire have different effects, I will also bring up another related phenomenon. There are many aspects of honor for both men and women, where violations are never excused by the world when they are open and acknowledged, but are more likely to be overlooked when appearances are maintained, and the wrongdoing is secret and hidden. Even those who know for sure that the fault has occurred are more likely to forgive it when the evidence seems somewhat indirect and ambiguous, rather than when it is straightforward and undeniable. The same idea applies in both situations and is, in principle, equally recognized by judgment; yet its impact varies due to the different ways in which it is presented.
Now if we compare these two cases, of the open and concealed violations of the laws of honour, we shall find, that the difference betwixt them consists in this, that in the first ease the sign, from which we infer the blameable action, is single, and suffices alone to be the foundation of our reasoning and judgment; whereas in the latter the signs are numerous, and decide little or nothing when alone and unaccompanyed with many minute circumstances, which are almost imperceptible. But it is certainly true, that any reasoning is always the more convincing, the more single and united it is to the eye, and the less exercise it gives to the imagination to collect all its parts, and run from them to the correlative idea, which forms the conclusion. The labour of the thought disturbs the regular progress of the sentiments, as we shall observe presently.[11] The idea strikes not on us with ouch vivacity; and consequently has no such influence on the passion and imagination.
If we compare these two cases, the open and concealed violations of the laws of honor, we’ll see that the difference between them lies in the fact that in the first case, the sign we use to infer the blameworthy action is clear and enough by itself to form the basis of our reasoning and judgment. In contrast, in the second case, the signs are many and don’t really clarify much when they stand alone without numerous subtle circumstances, which are nearly imperceptible. However, it's definitely true that any reasoning is more persuasive when it's clear and straightforward, requiring less effort from our imagination to piece together all its parts and connect them to the main idea that leads to the conclusion. The mental effort disrupts the smooth flow of feelings, as we will see shortly. The idea doesn’t impact us with the same intensity and therefore lacks the same influence on our emotions and imagination.
[11] Part IV. Sect. 1.
From the same principles we may account for those observations of the CARDINAL DE RETZ, that there are many things, in which the world wishes to be deceived; and that it more easily excuses a person in acting than in talking contrary to the decorum of his profession and character. A fault in words is commonly more open and distinct than one in actions, which admit of many palliating excuses, and decide not so clearly concerning the intention and views of the actor.
From the same principles, we can explain the observations of CARDINAL DE RETZ that there are many things in which people prefer to be misled. The world is much more forgiving of someone acting inappropriately than of them speaking out of line with their profession and character. A mistake in words is usually more obvious and clear-cut than one in actions, which can often be justified with various excuses and don't reveal the actor's true intentions or motives as clearly.
Thus it appears upon the whole, that every kind of opinion or judgment, which amounts not to knowledge, is derived entirely from the force and vivacity of the perception, and that these qualities constitute in the mind, what we call the BELIEF Of the existence of any object. This force and this vivacity are most conspicuous in the memory; and therefore our confidence in the veracity of that faculty is the greatest imaginable, and equals in many respects the assurance of a demonstration. The next degree of these qualities is that derived from the relation of cause and effect; and this too is very great, especially when the conjunction is found by experience to be perfectly constant, and when the object, which is present to us, exactly resembles those, of which we have had experience. But below this degree of evidence there are many others, which have an influence on the passions and imagination, proportioned to that degree of force and vivacity, which they communicate to the ideas. It is by habit we make the transition from cause to effect; and it is from some present impression we borrow that vivacity, which we diffuse over the correlative idea. But when we have not observed a sufficient number of instances, to produce a strong habit; or when these instances are contrary to each other; or when the resemblance is not exact; or the present impression is faint and obscure; or the experience in some measure obliterated from the memory; or the connexion dependent on a long chain of objects; or the inference derived from general rules, and yet not conformable to them: In all these cases the evidence diminishes by the diminution of the force and intenseness of the idea. This therefore is the nature of the judgment and probability.
So, overall, it seems that every type of opinion or judgment that isn't knowledge comes entirely from the strength and vividness of our perceptions, and these qualities form what we call BELIEF in the mind regarding the existence of any object. This strength and vividness are most clearly seen in memory, which is why we have an immense confidence in its accuracy, often equal to that of a demonstration. The next level of these qualities comes from the relationship between cause and effect, which is also quite significant, especially when we find through experience that the connection is consistently reliable, and the object we see closely resembles those we've experienced before. However, below this level of evidence, there are many others that affect our emotions and imagination based on the degree of strength and vividness they impart to our ideas. We transition from cause to effect by habit; we borrow that vividness from a current impression and apply it to the related idea. But when we haven't seen enough instances to form a strong habit; or when those instances conflict; or when the resemblance isn't precise; or when the current impression is weak and unclear; or when the experience is somewhat faded in memory; or when the connection relies on a long chain of objects; or when the inference is based on general rules but doesn't align with them: In all these situations, the evidence lessens as the strength and intensity of the idea diminish. This is the essence of judgment and probability.
What principally gives authority to this system is, beside the undoubted arguments, upon which each part is founded, the agreement of these parts, and the necessity of one to explain another. The belief, which attends our memory, is of the same nature with that, which is derived from our judgments: Nor is there any difference betwixt that judgment, which is derived from a constant and uniform connexion of causes and effects, and that which depends upon an interrupted and uncertain. It is indeed evident, that in all determinations, where the mind decides from contrary experiments, it is first divided within itself, and has an inclination to either side in proportion to the number of experiments we have seen and remember. This contest is at last determined to the advantage of that side, where we observe a superior number of these experiments; but still with a diminution of force in the evidence correspondent to the number of the opposite experiments. Each possibility, of which the probability is composed, operates separately upon the imagination; and it is the larger collection of possibilities, which at last prevails, and that with a force proportionable to its superiority. All these phenomena lead directly to the precedent system; nor will it ever be possible upon any other principles to give a satisfactory and consistent explication of them. Without considering these judgments as the effects of custom on the imagination, we shall lose ourselves in perpetual contradiction and absurdity.
What mainly gives authority to this system is, besides the undeniable arguments that support each part, the agreement of these parts and the necessity of one to explain another. The belief linked to our memory is similar to that which comes from our judgments: there's no difference between the judgment formed from a consistent and uniform connection of causes and effects, and that which relies on an interrupted and uncertain one. It’s clear that in all decisions where the mind weighs opposing experiences, it first becomes conflicted, leaning toward one side based on the number of experiences we remember. This conflict is ultimately resolved in favor of the side with more of these experiences, but with less strength in the evidence corresponding to the opposing experiences. Each possibility contributing to the probability acts separately on the imagination; it’s the larger collection of possibilities that ultimately wins out, with a force proportional to its superiority. All these phenomena clearly relate to the earlier system; it will never be possible, based on any other principles, to provide a satisfactory and consistent explanation for them. Without viewing these judgments as effects of habit on the imagination, we will get lost in endless contradictions and absurdities.
SECT. XIV. OF THE IDEA OF NECESSARY CONNEXION.
Having thus explained the manner, in which we reason beyond our immediate impressions, and conclude that such particular causes must have such particular effects; we must now return upon our footsteps to examine that question, which[12] first occured to us, and which we dropt in our way, viz. What is our idea of necessity, when we say that two objects are necessarily connected together. Upon this head I repeat what I have often had occasion to observe, that as we have no idea, that is not derived from an impression, we must find some impression, that gives rise to this idea of necessity, if we assert we have really such an idea. In order to this I consider, in what objects necessity is commonly supposed to lie; and finding that it is always ascribed to causes and effects, I turn my eye to two objects supposed to be placed in that relation; and examine them in all the situations, of which they are susceptible. I immediately perceive, that they are contiguous in time and place, and that the object we call cause precedes the other we call effect. In no one instance can I go any farther, nor is it possible for me to discover any third relation betwixt these objects. I therefore enlarge my view to comprehend several instances; where I find like objects always existing in like relations of contiguity and succession. At first sight this seems to serve but little to my purpose. The reflection on several instances only repeats the same objects; and therefore can never give rise to a new idea. But upon farther enquiry I find, that the repetition is not in every particular the same, but produces a new impression, and by that means the idea, which I at present examine. For after a frequent repetition, I find, that upon the appearance of one of the objects, the mind is determined by custom to consider its usual attendant, and to consider it in a stronger light upon account of its relation to the first object. It is this impression, then, or determination, which affords me the idea of necessity.
Having explained how we reason beyond our immediate impressions and conclude that certain causes must lead to specific effects, we should now revisit the question that first came to our mind and that we set aside earlier: What do we mean by necessity when we say that two objects are necessarily connected? I want to re-emphasize something I've often noticed: since we don't have any idea that isn't derived from an impression, we need to find an impression that gives rise to this idea of necessity if we claim to really have such an idea. To do this, I consider where necessity is usually thought to exist, and I notice that it is always attributed to causes and effects. I then look at two objects that are believed to be in that relationship and examine them in all the possible situations they can be in. I quickly see that they are situated close together in time and space, with the object we call the cause preceding the object we call the effect. In every single instance, I can't go any further, and it's not possible for me to find any third relationship between these objects. So, I broaden my perspective to include multiple instances, where I see similar objects consistently existing in similar relationships of closeness and sequence. At first glance, this seems to serve little purpose for my inquiry. Reflecting on several instances only repeats the same objects, and therefore can never spark a new idea. However, upon further investigation, I find that the repetition isn’t exactly the same each time, as it creates a new impression, and thus brings forth the idea I'm currently examining. After many repetitions, I discover that when one of the objects appears, my mind, through habit, is inclined to think of its usual counterpart and considers it more strongly due to its relationship with the first object. It is this impression or inclination that gives me the idea of necessity.
[12] Sect. 2.
I doubt not but these consequences will at first sight be received without difficulty, as being evident deductions from principles, which we have already established, and which we have often employed in our reasonings. This evidence both in the first principles, and in the deductions, may seduce us unwarily into the conclusion, and make us imagine it contains nothing extraordinary, nor worthy of our curiosity. But though such an inadvertence may facilitate the reception of this reasoning, it will make it be the more easily forgot; for which reason I think it proper to give warning, that I have just now examined one of the most sublime questions in philosophy, viz. that concerning the power and efficacy of causes; where all the sciences seem so much interested. Such a warning will naturally rouze up the attention of the reader, and make him desire a more full account of my doctrine, as well as of the arguments, on which it is founded. This request is so reasonable, that I cannot refuse complying with it; especially as I am hopeful that these principles, the more they are examined, will acquire the more force and evidence.
I have no doubt that at first glance, these outcomes will be accepted easily, as they follow directly from principles we've already established and often used in our reasoning. This clarity, both in our fundamental principles and in the conclusions we draw, might lead us to overlook how significant they are, making us think there's nothing unusual or noteworthy about them. However, while this oversight may help us accept the reasoning, it also makes it easier to forget. Therefore, I think it’s important to point out that I've just explored one of the most profound questions in philosophy: the nature and effectiveness of causes, which is crucial to all the sciences. This alert will naturally grab the reader's attention and spark a desire for a deeper understanding of my ideas and the arguments backing them. Such a request is perfectly reasonable, and I can't refuse it; especially since I believe that the more these principles are examined, the stronger and clearer they will become.
There is no question, which on account of its importance, as well as difficulty, has caused more disputes both among antient and modern philosophers, than this concerning the efficacy of causes, or that quality which makes them be followed by their effects. But before they entered upon these disputes, methinks it would not have been improper to have examined what idea we have of that efficacy, which is the subject of the controversy. This is what I find principally wanting in their reasonings, and what I shall here endeavour to supply.
There’s no doubt that this issue, because of its significance and complexity, has sparked more debates among ancient and modern philosophers than any other, especially regarding the effectiveness of causes or the qualities that lead to their effects. However, before diving into these arguments, I think it would have been wise to clarify what we mean by that effectiveness, which is the heart of the debate. This seems to be what is mostly missing in their reasoning, and it’s what I will try to address here.
I begin with observing that the terms of EFFICACY, AGENCY, POWER, FORCE, ENERGY, NECESSITY, CONNEXION, and PRODUCTIVE QUALITY, are all nearly synonymous; and therefore it is an absurdity to employ any of them in defining the rest. By this observation we reject at once all the vulgar definitions, which philosophers have given of power and efficacy; and instead of searching for the idea in these definitions, must look for it in the impressions, from which it is originally derived. If it be a compound idea, it must arise from compound impressions. If simple, from simple impressions.
I start by noting that the terms EFFICACY, AGENCY, POWER, FORCE, ENERGY, NECESSITY, CONNECTION, and PRODUCTIVE QUALITY are all quite similar in meaning; so it's pointless to use any of them to define the others. With this observation, we immediately discard all the common definitions that philosophers have provided for power and efficacy. Instead of trying to find the concept in those definitions, we should seek it in the impressions from which it originally comes. If it’s a compound idea, it must come from compound impressions. If it’s simple, it comes from simple impressions.
I believe the most general and most popular explication of this matter, is to say,[13] that finding from experience, that there are several new productions in matter, such as the motions and variations of body, and concluding that there must somewhere be a power capable of producing them, we arrive at last by this reasoning at the idea of power and efficacy. But to be convinced that this explication is more popular than philosophical, we need but reflect on two very obvious principles. First, that reason alone can never give rise to any original idea, and secondly, that reason, as distinguished from experience, can never make us conclude, that a cause or productive quality is absolutely requisite to every beginning of existence. Both these considerations have been sufficiently explained: and therefore shall not at present be any farther insisted on.
I think the simplest and most widely accepted explanation of this issue is to say, [13] that after noticing through experience that there are various new occurrences in matter, like the movements and changes of bodies, and concluding that there must be a power somewhere that can produce them, we eventually reach the idea of power and effectiveness through this reasoning. However, to understand that this explanation is more popular than philosophical, we just need to consider two very clear principles. First, that reason alone can never generate any original idea, and second, that reason, as opposed to experience, can never lead us to conclude that a cause or productive quality is absolutely necessary for every beginning of existence. These two points have been discussed thoroughly, so I won’t elaborate on them further right now.
I shall only infer from them, that since reason can never give rise to the idea of efficacy, that idea must be derived from experience, and from some particular instances of this efficacy, which make their passage into the mind by the common channels of sensation or reflection. Ideas always represent their objects or impressions; and vice versa, there are some objects necessary to give rise to every idea. If we pretend, therefore, to have any just idea of this efficacy, we must produce some instance, wherein the efficacy is plainly discoverable to the mind, and its operations obvious to our consciousness or sensation. By the refusal of this, we acknowledge, that the idea is impossible and imaginary, since the principle of innate ideas, which alone can save us from this dilemma, has been already refuted, and is now almost universally rejected in the learned world. Our present business, then, must be to find some natural production, where the operation and efficacy of a cause can be clearly conceived and comprehended by the mind, without any danger of obscurity or mistake.
I can only conclude from this that since reason can never create the idea of effectiveness, that idea must come from experience and specific examples of this effectiveness, which enter our minds through our senses or reflections. Ideas always represent their objects or impressions, and conversely, certain objects are necessary to generate every idea. Therefore, if we claim to have a clear idea of this effectiveness, we must provide an example where the effectiveness is clearly recognizable to the mind, and its actions are obvious to our awareness or senses. By failing to do this, we admit that the idea is impossible and imaginary, since the concept of innate ideas, which could have saved us from this problem, has already been disproven and is now widely dismissed in academic circles. Our current task must be to find a natural phenomenon where the operation and effectiveness of a cause can be clearly understood and grasped by the mind, without any risk of confusion or error.
In this research we meet with very little encouragement from that prodigious diversity, which is found in the opinions of those philosophers, who have pretended to explain the secret force and energy of causes.[14] There are some, who maintain, that bodies operate by their substantial form; others, by their accidents or qualities; several, by their matter and form; some, by their form and accidents; others, by certain virtues and faculties distinct from all this. All these sentiments again are mixed and varyed in a thousand different ways; and form a strong presumption, that none of them have any solidity or evidence, and that the supposition of an efficacy in any of the known qualities of matter is entirely without foundation. This presumption must encrease upon us, when we consider, that these principles of substantial forms, and accidents, and faculties, are not in reality any of the known properties of bodies, but are perfectly unintelligible and inexplicable. For it is evident philosophers would never have had recourse to such obscure and uncertain principles, had they met with any satisfaction in such as are clear and intelligible; especially in such an affair as this, which must be an object of the simplest understanding, if not of the senses. Upon the whole, we may conclude, that it is impossible in any one instance to shew the principle, in which the force and agency of a cause is placed; and that the most refined and most vulgar understandings are equally at a loss in this particular. If any one think proper to refute this assertion, he need not put himself to the trouble of inventing any long reasonings: but may at once shew us an instance of a cause, where we discover the power or operating principle. This defiance we are obliged frequently to make use of, as being almost the only means of proving a negative in philosophy.
In this research, we find very little encouragement from the vast range of opinions among philosophers who have tried to explain the hidden force and energy of causes.[14] Some argue that bodies act by their essential form, others by their accidents or qualities, some by their matter and form, and others by a combination of form and accidents. Furthermore, there are those who claim it's due to certain virtues and faculties that are separate from all of this. These views are mixed and vary in countless ways, strongly suggesting that none of them are solid or reliable, and the idea that any known qualities of matter have efficacy is completely unfounded. This suspicion grows when we realize that the principles of essential forms, accidents, and faculties are not actually recognized properties of bodies but are completely unintelligible and inexplicable. Clearly, philosophers wouldn’t have resorted to such obscure and uncertain principles if they had found any clarity in those that are straightforward and understandable, especially in matters like this, which should be easy to grasp, if not apparent to the senses. Overall, we can conclude that it's impossible to show, even once, the principle in which the force and agency of a cause lie, and that both the most sophisticated and the most basic minds are equally puzzled by this issue. If someone wants to challenge this statement, they don’t need to go through long arguments; they can simply provide us with an example of a cause where we can identify the power or operating principle. We often have to resort to this challenge, as it is almost the only way to prove a negative in philosophy.
[14] See Father Malbranche, Book vi. Part 2, chap. 3. And the illustrations upon it.
[14] See Father Malbranche, Book 6, Part 2, Chapter 3. And the illustrations related to it.
The small success, which has been met with in all the attempts to fix this power, has at last obliged philosophers to conclude, that the ultimate force and efficacy of nature is perfectly unknown to us, and that it is in vain we search for it in all the known qualities of matter. In this opinion they are almost unanimous; and it is only in the inference they draw from it, that they discover any difference in their sentiments. For some of them, as the CARTESIANS in particular, having established it as a principle, that we are perfectly acquainted with the essence of matter, have very naturally inferred, that it is endowed with no efficacy, and that it is impossible for it of itself to communicate motion, or produce any of those effects, which we ascribe to it. As the essence of matter consists in extension, and as extension implies not actual motion, but only mobility; they conclude, that the energy, which produces the motion, cannot lie in the extension.
The small success seen in all efforts to understand this power has finally led philosophers to conclude that the ultimate force and effectiveness of nature is completely unknown to us, and that it's pointless to look for it in the known properties of matter. They almost all agree on this point; the only differences in their views appear in the conclusions they draw from it. Some, particularly the CARTESIANS, have established as a principle that we fully understand the essence of matter, and they have logically inferred that it has no efficacy and cannot, on its own, create motion or produce any of the effects we attribute to it. Since the essence of matter involves extension, and extension implies not actual motion but only the potential for movement, they conclude that the energy needed for motion cannot reside in the extension itself.
This conclusion leads them into another, which they regard as perfectly unavoidable. Matter, say they, is in itself entirely unactive, and deprived of any power, by which it may produce, or continue, or communicate motion: But since these effects are evident to our senses, and since the power, that produces them, must be placed somewhere, it must lie in the DEITY, or that divine being, who contains in his nature all excellency and perfection. It is the deity, therefore, who is the prime mover of the universe, and who not only first created matter, and gave it it's original impulse, but likewise by a continued exertion of omnipotence, supports its existence, and successively bestows on it all those motions, and configurations, and qualities, with which it is endowed.
This conclusion brings them to another point, which they see as completely unavoidable. They argue that matter, on its own, is entirely inactive and lacks any power to create, maintain, or transfer motion. However, since these effects are clear to our senses, and since the power responsible for them must exist somewhere, it must reside in the DEITY, or that divine being who embodies all excellence and perfection. Therefore, it is the deity who is the primary mover of the universe, who not only initially created matter and gave it its original push, but also continuously uses omnipotence to sustain its existence and successively grants it all the motions, configurations, and qualities it possesses.
This opinion is certainly very curious, and well worth our attention; but it will appear superfluous to examine it in this place, if we reflect a moment on our present purpose in taking notice of it. We have established it as a principle, that as all ideas are derived from impressions, or some precedent perceptions, it is impossible we can have any idea of power and efficacy, unless some instances can be produced, wherein this power is perceived to exert itself. Now, as these instances can never be discovered in body, the Cartesians, proceeding upon their principle of innate ideas, have had recourse to a supreme spirit or deity, whom they consider as the only active being in the universe, and as the immediate cause of every alteration in matter. But the principle of innate ideas being allowed to be false, it follows, that the supposition of a deity can serve us in no stead, in accounting for that idea of agency, which we search for in vain in all the objects, which are presented to our senses, or which we are internally conscious of in our own minds. For if every idea be derived from an impression, the idea of a deity proceeds from the same origin; and if no impression, either of sensation or reflection, implies any force or efficacy, it is equally impossible to discover or even imagine any such active principle in the deity. Since these philosophers, therefore, have concluded, that matter cannot be endowed with any efficacious principle, because it is impossible to discover in it such a principle; the same course of reasoning should determine them to exclude it from the supreme being. Or if they esteem that opinion absurd and impious, as it really is, I shall tell them how they may avoid it; and that is, by concluding from the very first, that they have no adequate idea of power or efficacy in any object; since neither in body nor spirit, neither in superior nor inferior natures, are they able to discover one single instance of it.
This opinion is definitely intriguing and deserves our attention, but it seems unnecessary to delve into it here if we take a moment to consider why we're discussing it. We've established that all ideas come from impressions or previous perceptions, so we can't have any idea of power and effectiveness unless we can point to instances where this power is clearly observed. Since we can never find these instances in physical objects, the Cartesians, sticking to their belief in innate ideas, have turned to a supreme spirit or deity, whom they see as the only active being in the universe and the immediate cause of every change in matter. However, if we accept that the principle of innate ideas is false, then the idea of a deity doesn't help us explain the concept of agency that we fail to find in any objects presented to our senses or within our own minds. If every idea comes from an impression, then the idea of a deity must come from the same source, and if no impression—whether from sensation or reflection—implies any force or effectiveness, it's equally impossible to identify or even imagine any active principle in the deity. Therefore, since these philosophers have concluded that matter cannot possess any effective principle because they can't find it, the same reasoning should lead them to ignore the idea of such a principle in the supreme being. Or if they find that opinion absurd and disrespectful, which it truly is, I can suggest they avoid it by realizing from the very start that they have no clear idea of power or effectiveness in any object, since they can't find a single instance of it in either the physical or spiritual worlds, whether in higher or lower nature.
The same conclusion is unavoidable upon the hypothesis of those, who maintain the efficacy of second causes, and attribute a derivative, but a real power and energy to matter. For as they confess, that this energy lies not in any of the known qualities of matter, the difficulty still remains concerning the origin of its idea. If we have really an idea of power, we may attribute power to an unknown quality: But as it is impossible, that that idea can be derived from such a quality, and as there is nothing in known qualities, which can produce it; it follows that we deceive ourselves, when we imagine we are possest of any idea of this kind, after the manner we commonly understand it. All ideas are derived from, and represent impressions. We never have any impression, that contains any power or efficacy. We never therefore have any idea of power.
The same conclusion is unavoidable if we consider those who argue for the effectiveness of secondary causes and assign a derived but real power and energy to matter. They admit that this energy doesn't come from any of the known properties of matter, yet the question remains about the source of this idea. If we truly have an idea of power, we might associate power with an unknown quality. However, since it's impossible for that idea to come from such a quality, and since there’s nothing in the known qualities that can produce it, we are misled if we think we have any idea of this kind in the way we usually understand it. All ideas come from and reflect impressions. We never have an impression that includes any power or effectiveness. Therefore, we never have an idea of power.
Some have asserted, that we feel an energy, or power, in our own mind; and that having in this manner acquired the idea of power, we transfer that quality to matter, where we are not able immediately to discover it. The motions of our body, and the thoughts and sentiments of our mind, (say they) obey the will; nor do we seek any farther to acquire a just notion of force or power. But to convince us how fallacious this reasoning is, we need only consider, that the will being here considered as a cause, has no more a discoverable connexion with its effects, than any material cause has with its proper effect. So far from perceiving the connexion betwixt an act of volition, and a motion of the body; it is allowed that no effect is more inexplicable from the powers and essence of thought and matter. Nor is the empire of the will over our mind more intelligible. The effect is there distinguishable and separable from the cause, and could not be foreseen without the experience of their constant conjunction. We have command over our mind to a certain degree, but beyond that, lose all empire over it: And it is evidently impossible to fix any precise bounds to our authority, where we consult not experience. In short, the actions of the mind are, in this respect, the same with those of matter. We perceive only their constant conjunction; nor can we ever reason beyond it. No internal impression has an apparent energy, more than external objects have. Since, therefore, matter is confessed by philosophers to operate by an unknown force, we should in vain hope to attain an idea of force by consulting our own minds.[15]
Some people claim that we feel energy or power in our own minds, and that having acquired this idea of power, we apply it to objects where we can't immediately detect it. They argue that the movements of our bodies and the thoughts and feelings in our minds obey our will, and we don’t seek to understand force or power further. However, to show how flawed this reasoning is, we simply need to consider that when we think of the will as a cause, its connection to its effects is no clearer than that of any physical cause with its effect. In fact, we don't even see the link between an act of will and a body movement; it’s widely accepted that no effect is more difficult to explain based on the nature of thought and matter. The influence of the will over our minds is no clearer either. The effect can be recognized and separated from the cause and can't be anticipated without having experienced their consistent connection. We have control over our minds to a certain extent, but beyond that, we lose all authority over them: It's obviously impossible to define any exact limits to our control without relying on experience. In summary, the actions of the mind are similar to those of matter in this regard. We only observe their consistent connection and can’t reason beyond that. No internal impression shows any more influence than external objects do. Since philosophers agree that matter operates through an unknown force, it would be pointless to expect to understand force by looking within our own minds.[15]
[15] The same imperfection attends our ideas of the Deity; but this can have no effect either on religion or morals. The order of the universe proves an omnipotent mind; that is, a mind whose will is CONSTANTLY ATTENDED with the obedience of every creature and being. Nothing more is requisite to give a foundation to all the articles of religion, nor is It necessary we shoud form a distinct idea of the force and energy of the supreme Being.
[15] The same flaw affects our understanding of God; however, this does not impact religion or morals. The order of the universe shows that there is an all-powerful mind, meaning a mind whose will is ALWAYS FOLLOWED by every creature and being. Nothing more is needed to support all religious beliefs, nor do we need to create a separate concept of the power and energy of the supreme Being.
It has been established as a certain principle, that general or abstract ideas are nothing but individual ones taken in a certain light, and that, in reflecting on any object, it is as impossible to exclude from our thought all particular degrees of quantity and quality as from the real nature of things. If we be possest, therefore, of any idea of power in general, we must also be able to conceive some particular species of it; and as power cannot subsist alone, but is always regarded as an attribute of some being or existence, we must be able to place this power in some particular being, and conceive that being as endowed with a real force and energy, by which such a particular effect necessarily results from its operation. We must distinctly and particularly conceive the connexion betwixt the cause and effect, and be able to pronounce, from a simple view of the one, that it must be followed or preceded by the other. This is the true manner of conceiving a particular power in a particular body: and a general idea being impossible without an individual; where the latter is impossible, it is certain the former can never exist. Now nothing is more evident, than that the human mind cannot form such an idea of two objects, as to conceive any connexion betwixt them, or comprehend distinctly that power or efficacy, by which they are united. Such a connexion would amount to a demonstration, and would imply the absolute impossibility for the one object not to follow, or to be conceived not to follow upon the other: Which kind of connexion has already been rejected in all cases. If any one is of a contrary opinion, and thinks he has attained a notion of power in any particular object, I desire he may point out to me that object. But till I meet with such-a-one, which I despair of, I cannot forbear concluding, that since we can never distinctly conceive how any particular power can possibly reside in any particular object, we deceive ourselves in imagining we can form any such general idea.
It’s been established as a clear principle that general or abstract ideas are just individual ones viewed in a specific way, and that when we think about any object, it’s impossible to completely exclude all specific degrees of quantity and quality, just as it's impossible to do so in the true nature of things. Therefore, if we have any idea of power in general, we must also be capable of imagining some specific type of it; and since power can’t exist on its own but is always seen as an attribute of some being or existence, we must be able to associate this power with a particular being and imagine that being as having real force and energy, leading to specific effects as a result of its actions. We must clearly and specifically understand the connection between cause and effect, being able to conclude, just from looking at one, that it must be followed or preceded by the other. This is the correct way to understand a specific power in a specific entity: a general idea can’t exist without an individual one; where the latter is impossible, it’s certain the former can never exist. Now, it’s clear that the human mind cannot form an idea of two objects such that it perceives any connection between them, or distinctly comprehend the power or effectiveness that unites them. Such a connection would be a demonstration and imply that it’s absolutely impossible for one object not to follow, or be thought of as not following the other, which has already been dismissed in all cases. If anyone disagrees and thinks they have grasped the concept of power in some specific object, I ask them to show me that object. But until I come across such an object, which I doubt will happen, I can't help but conclude that since we can never distinctly understand how any particular power can reside in any specific object, we are fooling ourselves by believing we can form any such general idea.
Thus upon the whole we may infer, that when we talk of any being, whether of a superior or inferior nature, as endowed with a power or force, proportioned to any effect; when we speak of a necessary connexion betwixt objects, and suppose, that this connexion depends upon an efficacy or energy, with which any of these objects are endowed; in all these expressions, so applied, we have really no distinct meaning, and make use only of common words, without any clear and determinate ideas. But as it is more probable, that these expressions do here lose their true meaning by being wrong applied, than that they never have any meaning; it will be proper to bestow another consideration on this subject, to see if possibly we can discover the nature and origin of those ideas, we annex to them.
So overall, we can conclude that when we discuss any being, whether it's of a higher or lower nature, as having a power or force related to an effect; when we mention a necessary connection between objects and assume that this connection relies on an effectiveness or energy that any of these objects possess; in all these statements, we actually have no clear meaning and are just using common words without any specific and definite ideas. However, since it seems more likely that these expressions lose their true meaning by being misapplied rather than having no meaning at all, it would be wise to take another look at this topic to see if we might uncover the nature and origin of the ideas we associate with them.
Suppose two objects to be presented to us, of which the one is the cause and the other the effect; it is plain, that from the simple consideration of one, or both these objects we never shall perceive the tie by which they are united, or be able certainly to pronounce, that there is a connexion betwixt them. It is not, therefore, from any one instance, that we arrive at the idea of cause and effect, of a necessary connexion of power, of force, of energy, and of efficacy. Did we never see any but particular conjunctions of objects, entirely different from each other, we should never be able to form any such ideas.
Imagine we have two objects in front of us, one being the cause and the other the effect. It’s obvious that just by looking at either one of these objects, or even both, we won't really understand the connection that links them together, nor could we confidently say that there is a relationship between them. Therefore, we don’t develop the idea of cause and effect, or the necessary connection through power, force, energy, and effectiveness, from just one instance. If we only ever observed specific pairings of very different objects, we would never be able to form those kinds of concepts.
But again; suppose we observe several instances, in which the same objects are always conjoined together, we immediately conceive a connexion betwixt them, and begin to draw an inference from one to another. This multiplicity of resembling instances, therefore, constitutes the very essence of power or connexion, and is the source from which the idea of it arises. In order, then, to understand the idea of power, we must consider that multiplicity; nor do I ask more to give a solution of that difficulty, which has so long perplexed us. For thus I reason. The repetition of perfectly similar instances can never alone give rise to an original idea, different from what is to be found in any particular instance, as has been observed, and as evidently follows from our fundamental principle, that all ideas are copyed from impressions. Since therefore the idea of power is a new original idea, not to be found in any one instance, and which yet arises from the repetition of several instances, it follows, that the repetition alone has not that effect, but must either discover or produce something new, which is the source of that idea. Did the repetition neither discover nor produce anything new, our ideas might be multiplyed by it, but would not be enlarged above what they are upon the observation of one single instance. Every enlargement, therefore, (such as the idea of power or connexion) which arises from the multiplicity of similar instances, is copyed from some effects of the multiplicity, and will be perfectly understood by understanding these effects. Wherever we find anything new to be discovered or produced by the repetition, there we must place the power, and must never look for it in any other object.
But again, suppose we see several instances where the same objects are always connected; we quickly think of a link between them and start making inferences from one to another. This variety of similar instances is what defines the essence of power or connection and is where the idea comes from. To understand the idea of power, we need to look at that variety; I don’t ask for anything more to solve the problem that has puzzled us for so long. Here’s my reasoning: The repetition of completely similar instances can never on its own give rise to a new idea that isn't found in any specific instance, as has been pointed out, and as clearly follows from our basic principle that all ideas are derived from impressions. Since the idea of power is a new original idea, not found in just one instance, and yet comes from the repetition of several instances, it follows that the repetition alone doesn't have that effect; it must reveal or create something new, which is the source of that idea. If the repetition neither revealed nor created anything new, our ideas could be multiplied by it but wouldn't expand beyond what we see in a single instance. Therefore, every expansion (like the idea of power or connection) that comes from multiple similar instances is derived from some effects of that multiplicity and can be fully understood by grasping these effects. Wherever we find something new being discovered or produced by the repetition, that’s where we should identify the power, and we should never look for it in any other object.
But it is evident, in the first place, that the repetition of like objects in like relations of succession and contiguity discovers nothing new in any one of them: since we can draw no inference from it, nor make it a subject either of our demonstrative or probable reasonings;[16] as has been already proved. Nay suppose we could draw an inference, it would be of no consequence in the present case; since no kind of reasoning can give rise to a new idea, such as this of power is; but wherever we reason, we must antecedently be possest of clear ideas, which may be the objects of our reasoning. The conception always precedes the understanding; and where the one is obscure, the other is uncertain; where the one fails, the other must fail also.
But it’s clear, first of all, that repeating similar objects in similar sequences and proximity doesn't reveal anything new about any of them; we can’t draw any conclusions from it, nor make it the basis of our logical or probable reasoning;[16] as has already been demonstrated. Even if we could draw a conclusion, it wouldn’t matter in this case, since no kind of reasoning can create a new idea, like the concept of power is; but whenever we reason, we must already have clear ideas that can be the focus of our reasoning. The idea always comes before understanding; when one is unclear, the other is uncertain; when one fails, the other must also fail.
[16] Sect. 6.
Secondly, It is certain that this repetition of similar objects in similar situations produces nothing new either in these objects, or in any external body. For it will readily be allowed, that the several instances we have of the conjunction of resembling causes and effects are in themselves entirely independent, and that the communication of motion, which I see result at present from the shock of two billiard-balls, is totally distinct from that which I saw result from such an impulse a twelve-month ago. These impulses have no influence on each other. They are entirely divided by time and place; and the one might have existed and communicated motion, though the other never had been in being.
Secondly, it's clear that repeating similar things in similar situations doesn’t create anything new, either in those things or in anything outside of them. It’s easy to agree that the different instances we have of similar causes and effects are completely independent. The motion I observe now from the collision of two billiard balls is completely different from what I observed a year ago from the same type of impact. These impacts don’t affect one another. They are fully separated by time and space, and one could happen and cause motion without the other ever having existed.
There is, then, nothing new either discovered or produced in any objects by their constant conjunction, and by the uninterrupted resemblance of their relations of succession and contiguity. But it is from this resemblance, that the ideas of necessity, of power, and of efficacy, are derived. These ideas, therefore, represent not anything, that does or can belong to the objects, which are constantly conjoined. This is an argument, which, in every view we can examine it, will be found perfectly unanswerable. Similar instances are still the first source of our idea of power or necessity; at the same time that they have no influence by their similarity either on each other, or on any external object. We must, therefore, turn ourselves to some other quarter to seek the origin of that idea.
There’s nothing new discovered or produced in any objects by their constant connection and the unbroken similarity of their relationships in terms of order and proximity. However, it's from this similarity that the ideas of necessity, power, and effectiveness come. These ideas, therefore, don’t truly represent anything that actually belongs to the objects that are always linked. This is an argument that, from every angle we can look at it, is completely unrefuted. Similar cases are still the primary source of our idea of power or necessity, even though their similarity has no effect on each other or on any external object. We must, therefore, look elsewhere to find the source of that idea.
Though the several resembling instances, which give rise to the idea of power, have no influence on each other, and can never produce any new quality in the object, which can be the model of that idea, yet the observation of this resemblance produces a new impression in the mind, which is its real model. For after we have observed the resemblance in a sufficient number of instances, we immediately feel a determination of the mind to pass from one object to its usual attendant, and to conceive it in a stronger light upon account of that relation. This determination is the only effect of the resemblance; and therefore must be the same with power or efficacy, whose idea is derived from the resemblance. The several instances of resembling conjunctions lead us into the notion of power and necessity. These instances are in themselves totally distinct from each other, and have no union but in the mind, which observes them, and collects their ideas. Necessity, then, is the effect of this observation, and is nothing but an internal impression of the mind, or a determination to carry our thoughts from one object to another. Without considering it in this view, we can never arrive at the most distant notion of it, or be able to attribute it either to external or internal objects, to spirit or body, to causes or effects.
Although the various similar examples that lead to the idea of power do not affect one another and cannot create any new quality in the object that serves as the model for that idea, observing this similarity creates a new impression in the mind, which is its true model. After we have seen enough similar instances, we instinctively feel a tendency to move from one object to its usual counterpart and to see it more vividly because of that connection. This tendency is the only result of the resemblance and must be identical to power or effectiveness, as the idea of power comes from the resemblance. The different instances of similar associations lead us to the concept of power and necessity. These instances are completely separate from one another and unite only in the mind that observes them and gathers their ideas. Therefore, necessity is the result of this observation and is simply an internal impression of the mind, or a tendency to shift our thoughts from one object to another. Without viewing it this way, we can never reach any clearer understanding of it or attribute it to either external or internal objects, to spirit or body, or to causes or effects.
The necessary connexion betwixt causes and effects is the foundation of our inference from one to the other. The foundation of our inference is the transition arising from the accustomed union. These are, therefore, the same.
The necessary connection between causes and effects is the basis of our reasoning from one to the other. The basis of our reasoning is the shift that comes from the usual combination. Therefore, these are essentially the same.
The idea of necessity arises from some impression. There is no impression conveyed by our senses, which can give rise to that idea. It must, therefore, be derived from some internal impression, or impression of reflection. There is no internal impression, which has any relation to the present business, but that propensity, which custom produces, to pass from an object to the idea of its usual attendant. This therefore is the essence of necessity. Upon the whole, necessity is something, that exists in the mind, not in objects; nor is it possible for us ever to form the most distant idea of it, considered as a quality in bodies. Either we have no idea of necessity, or necessity is nothing but that determination of the thought to pass from causes to effects, and from effects to causes, according to their experienced union.
The concept of necessity comes from some kind of impression. There is no impression we get from our senses that can create that idea. It must, therefore, come from some internal impression or reflective thought. There is no internal impression relevant to this discussion except for the habit formed by experience, which leads us to connect an object with its usual associations. This is the essence of necessity. Overall, necessity is something that exists in the mind, not in objects; we can never even begin to think of it as a quality in things. Either we have no idea of necessity, or necessity is simply the way our thoughts move from causes to effects and back again, based on our past experiences of their connection.
Thus as the necessity, which makes two times two equal to four, or three angles of a triangle equal to two right ones, lies only in the act of the understanding, by which we consider and compare these ideas; in like manner the necessity or power, which unites causes and effects, lies in the determination of the mind to pass from the one to the other. The efficacy or energy of causes is neither placed in the causes themselves, nor in the deity, nor in the concurrence of these two principles; but belongs entirely to the soul, which considers the union of two or more objects in all past instances. It is here that the real power of causes is placed along with their connexion and necessity.
So just as the necessity that makes two plus two equal four, or the three angles of a triangle equal two right angles, exists only in our understanding when we think about and compare these ideas; similarly, the necessity or ability that connects causes and effects is found in our mind's decision to move from one to the other. The effectiveness or energy of causes isn't found in the causes themselves, nor in a deity, nor in the combination of these two principles; it fully resides in the mind, which reflects on the connection of two or more objects based on all past experiences. This is where the true power of causes, along with their connection and necessity, is located.
I am sensible, that of all the paradoxes, which I, have had, or shall hereafter have occasion to advance in the course of this treatise, the present one is the most violent, and that it is merely by dint of solid proof and reasoning I can ever hope it will have admission, and overcome the inveterate prejudices of mankind. Before we are reconciled to this doctrine, how often must we repeat to ourselves, that the simple view of any two objects or actions, however related, can never give us any idea, of power, or of a connexion betwixt them: that this idea arises from the repetition of their union: that the repetition neither discovers nor causes any thing in the objects, but has an influence only on the mind, by that customary transition it produces: that this customary transition is, therefore, the same with the power and necessity; which are consequently qualities of perceptions, not of objects, and are internally felt by the soul, and not perceivd externally in bodies? There is commonly an astonishment attending every thing extraordinary; and this astonishment changes immediately into the highest degree of esteem or contempt, according as we approve or disapprove of the subject. I am much afraid, that though the foregoing reasoning appears to me the shortest and most decisive imaginable; yet with the generality of readers the biass of the mind will prevail, and give them a prejudice against the present doctrine.
I realize that among all the paradoxes I've discussed or will discuss in this work, this one is the most extreme, and it's only through solid proof and reasoning that I can hope for it to be accepted and overcome the deep-seated biases of people. Before we can come to accept this idea, we need to remind ourselves repeatedly that simply looking at any two objects or actions, no matter how they relate, doesn’t give us any sense of power or connection between them. This understanding comes from the repeated observation of their association; this repetition doesn’t reveal or cause anything in the objects themselves, but instead affects our minds through the familiar shift it creates. This familiar transition is therefore the same as power and necessity; which are, in fact, qualities of our perceptions, not the objects themselves, and are felt internally by the mind, not externally observed in bodies. There’s usually a sense of amazement that accompanies anything extraordinary; this amazement quickly turns into either deep respect or contempt, depending on how we feel about the subject. I'm quite concerned that although the reasoning I've presented seems the shortest and most convincing to me, the majority of readers will likely be swayed by their own biases and develop a prejudice against this idea.
This contrary biass is easily accounted for. It is a common observation, that the mind has a great propensity to spread itself on external objects, and to conjoin with them any internal impressions, which they occasion, and which always make their appearance at the same time that these objects discover themselves to the senses. Thus as certain sounds and smells are always found to attend certain visible objects, we naturally imagine a conjunction, even in place, betwixt the objects and qualities, though the qualities be of such a nature as to admit of no such conjunction, and really exist no where. But of this more fully hereafter.[17] Mean while it is sufficient to observe, that the same propensity is the reason, why we suppose necessity and power to lie in the objects we consider, not in our mind that considers them; notwithstanding it is not possible for us to form the most distant idea of that quality, when it is not taken for the determination of the mind, to pass from the idea of an object to that of its usual attendant.
This biased view can be easily explained. It's a well-known fact that the mind tends to project itself onto external objects and associate any internal feelings they trigger, which always occur at the same time these objects reveal themselves to our senses. For example, certain sounds and smells are consistently linked to specific visible objects, so we naturally assume a connection, even in location, between the objects and their qualities, even though these qualities might not actually be connected at all and may not exist anywhere. But we'll get into that more later.[17] In the meantime, it's enough to note that this same tendency is why we think necessity and power reside in the objects we observe, rather than in our minds that perceive them; however, we can't even begin to imagine that quality when it’s not an intentional choice of the mind to move from thinking about an object to its usual associations.
[17] Part IV, Sect. 5.
But though this be the only reasonable account we can give of necessity, the contrary notion if; so riveted in the mind from the principles above-mentioned, that I doubt not but my sentiments will be treated by many as extravagant and ridiculous. What! the efficacy of causes lie in the determination of the mind! As if causes did not operate entirely independent of the mind, and would not continue their operation, even though there was no mind existent to contemplate them, or reason concerning them. Thought may well depend on causes for its operation, but not causes on thought. This is to reverse the order of nature, and make that secondary, which is really primary, To every operation there is a power proportioned; and this power must be placed on the body, that operates. If we remove the power from one cause, we must ascribe it to another: But to remove it from all causes, and bestow it on a being, that is no ways related to the cause or effect, but by perceiving them, is a gross absurdity, and contrary to the most certain principles of human reason.
But even though this is the only reasonable explanation we can give for necessity, the opposing idea is so deeply entrenched in people's minds due to the principles mentioned above that I'm sure many will find my views extravagant and ridiculous. What? The effectiveness of causes relies on the mind's determination? As if causes didn’t operate completely independently of the mind, and wouldn’t continue to function even if no mind existed to observe or think about them. Thought may very well depend on causes for its existence, but not the other way around. This reverses the natural order and makes what is secondary seem primary. For every action, there is a corresponding power, and this power must be attributed to the body causing the action. If we take the power away from one cause, we must assign it to another. But to remove it from all causes and give it to a being that is unrelated to the cause or effect, aside from simply perceiving them, is a serious absurdity and contradicts the most certain principles of human reason.
I can only reply to all these arguments, that the case is here much the same, as if a blind man should pretend to find a great many absurdities in the supposition, that the colour of scarlet is not the same with the sound of a trumpet, nor light the same with solidity. If we have really no idea of a power or efficacy in any object, or of any real connexion betwixt causes and effects, it will be to little purpose to prove, that an efficacy is necessary in all operations. We do not understand our own meaning in talking so, but ignorantly confound ideas, which are entirely distinct from each other. I am, indeed, ready to allow, that there may be several qualities both in material and immaterial objects, with which we are utterly unacquainted; and if we please to call these POWER or EFFICACY, it will be of little consequence to the world. But when, instead of meaning these unknown qualities, we make the terms of power and efficacy signify something, of which we have a clear idea, and which is incompatible with those objects, to which we apply it, obscurity and error begin then to take place, and we are led astray by a false philosophy. This is the case, when we transfer the determination of the thought to external objects, and suppose any real intelligible connexion betwixt them; that being a quality, which can only belong to the mind that considers them.
I can only respond to all these arguments by saying that it’s much the same as if a blind person were to argue that there are many absurdities in the idea that the color red is not the same as the sound of a trumpet, nor is light the same as solidity. If we truly have no concept of power or effectiveness in any object, or of any real connection between causes and effects, it will be pointless to prove that effectiveness is necessary in all actions. We don’t really grasp our own meaning when we say this and unintentionally mix up ideas that are completely separate from one another. I’m certainly willing to accept that there might be various qualities in both physical and non-physical objects that we are completely unaware of; and if we choose to call these POWER or EFFICACY, it won’t matter much in the grand scheme. However, when instead of referring to these unknown qualities, we make the terms power and efficacy mean something that we clearly understand and that does not fit with the objects we apply them to, confusion and misunderstanding begin to arise, and we get misled by false philosophy. This happens when we assign the determination of thought to external objects and assume there is any real, understandable connection between them; that is a quality that can only belong to the mind that is observing them.
As to what may be said, that the operations of nature are independent of our thought and reasoning, I allow it; and accordingly have observed, that objects bear to each other the relations of contiguity and succession: that like objects may be observed in several instances to have like relations; and that all this is independent of, and antecedent to the operations of the understanding. But if we go any farther, and ascribe a power or necessary connexion to these objects; this is what we can never observe in them, but must draw the idea of it from what we feel internally in contemplating them. And this I carry so far, that I am ready to convert my present reasoning into an instance of it, by a subtility, which it will not be difficult to comprehend.
As for the idea that nature's processes are separate from our thoughts and reasoning, I agree; I've noticed that objects have relationships based on being next to each other and following each other in time. I've observed that similar objects often have similar relationships, and all of this happens independently of our understanding. However, if we go further and attribute a power or necessary connection to these objects, we can never actually observe this in them; we must derive that idea from what we feel internally while thinking about them. I'm even willing to turn my current reasoning into an example of this, using a subtlety that won’t be hard to grasp.
When any object is presented to us, it immediately conveys to the mind a lively idea of that object, which is usually found to attend it; and this determination of the mind forms the necessary connexion of these objects. But when we change the point of view, from the objects to the perceptions; in that case the impression is to be considered as the cause, and the lively idea as the effect; and their necessary connexion is that new determination, which we feel to pass from the idea of the one to that of the other. The uniting principle among our internal perceptions is as unintelligible as that among external objects, and is not known to us any other way than by experience. Now the nature and effects of experience have been already sufficiently examined and explained. It never gives us any insight into the internal structure or operating principle of objects, but only accustoms the mind to pass from one to another.
When we see an object, it quickly brings to mind a vivid idea of that object, which usually comes along with it; this mental association creates a necessary connection between the two. However, when we shift our focus from the objects to our perceptions, the impression becomes the cause, and the vivid idea becomes the effect; this new connection is the change we feel as we move from thinking about one to the other. The underlying principle linking our internal perceptions is just as mysterious as the one connecting external objects, and we only understand it through experience. The nature and effects of experience have already been thoroughly examined and explained. It never reveals the internal structure or underlying principle of objects, but simply trains the mind to jump from one idea to another.
It is now time to collect all the different parts of this reasoning, and by joining them together form an exact definition of the relation of cause and effect, which makes the subject of the present enquiry. This order would not have been excusable, of first examining our inference from the relation before we had explained the relation itself, had it been possible to proceed in a different method. But as the nature of the relation depends so much on that of the inference, we have been obliged to advance in this seemingly preposterous manner, and make use of terms before we were able exactly to define them, or fix their meaning. We shall now correct this fault by giving a precise definition of cause and effect.
It’s time to gather all the different parts of this reasoning and combine them to create a clear definition of the relationship between cause and effect, which is the focus of this inquiry. We couldn’t have justified examining our inference from the relationship before explaining the relationship itself if there had been a different way to proceed. However, because the nature of the relationship is so tied to that of the inference, we’ve had to move forward in this seemingly illogical way and use terms before we could clearly define them or establish their meanings. We will now fix this issue by providing a precise definition of cause and effect.
There may two definitions be given of this relation, which are only different, by their presenting a different view of the same object, and making us consider it either as a philosophical or as a natural relation; either as a comparison of two ideas, or as an association betwixt them. We may define a CAUSE to be An object precedent and contiguous to another, and where all the objects resembling the former are placed in like relations of precedency and contiguity to those objects that resemble the latter. I If this definition be esteemed defective, because drawn from objects foreign to the cause, we may substitute this other definition in its place, viz. A CAUSE is an object precedent and contiguous to another, and so united with it, that the idea, of the one determines the mind to form the idea of the other, and the impression of the one to form a more lively idea of the other. 2 should this definition also be rejected for the same reason, I know no other remedy, than that the persons, who express this delicacy, should substitute a juster definition in its place. But for my part I must own my incapacity for such an undertaking. When I examine with the utmost accuracy those objects, which are commonly denominated causes and effects, I find, in considering a single instance, that the one object is precedent and contiguous to the other; and in inlarging my view to consider several instances, I find only, that like objects are constantly placed in like relations of succession and contiguity. Again, when I consider the influence of this constant conjunction, I perceive, that such a relation can never be an object of reasoning, and can never operate upon the mind, but by means of custom, which determines the imagination to make a transition from the idea of one object to that of its usual attendant, and from the impression of one to a more lively idea of the other. However extraordinary these sentiments may appear, I think it fruitless to trouble myself with any farther enquiry or reasoning upon the subject, but shall repose myself on them as on established maxims.
There are two definitions we can give for this relationship, which only differ in their perspective on the same concept, making us view it as either a philosophical or a natural relationship; either as a comparison of two ideas or as a connection between them. We can define a CAUSE as an object that is previous and adjacent to another, where all similar objects to the first one are placed in the same kinds of relationships of precedence and adjacency to the objects that resemble the second. If this definition is considered inadequate because it comes from objects unrelated to the cause, we can replace it with this other definition: A CAUSE is an object that is previous and adjacent to another, so linked with it that the idea of one compels the mind to form the idea of the other, and the impression of one provokes a clearer idea of the other. If this definition is also dismissed for the same reason, I don't know what else to suggest, except that those who find this definition too delicate should create a better one. But personally, I must admit my inability to do so. When I examine with great care the objects commonly called causes and effects, I find that in considering a single case, one object is previous and adjacent to the other; and as I broaden my scope to look at several cases, I find that similar objects are always placed in similar relationships of succession and adjacency. Moreover, when I think about the impact of this constant pairing, I realize that this relationship can never be the subject of reasoning and can only affect the mind through habit, which leads the imagination to move from the idea of one object to that of its usual counterpart, and from the impression of one to a more vivid idea of the other. While these thoughts may seem unusual, I think it’s pointless to delve deeper or reason further on this topic; I will rest on these ideas as if they are established truths.
It will only be proper, before we leave this subject, to draw some corrollaries from it, by which we may remove several prejudices and popular errors, that have very much prevailed in philosophy. First, We may learn from the foregoing, doctrine, that all causes are of the same kind, and that in particular there is no foundation for that distinction, which we sometimes make betwixt efficient causes and causes sine qua non; or betwixt efficient causes, and formal, and material, and exemplary, and final causes. For as our idea of efficiency is derived from the constant conjunction of two objects, wherever this is observed, the cause is efficient; and where it is not, there can never be a cause of any kind. For the same reason we must reject the distinction betwixt cause and occasion, when supposed to signify any thing essentially different from each other. If constant conjunction be implyed in what we call occasion, it is a real cause. If not, it is no relation at all, and cannot give rise to any argument or reasoning.
Before we move on from this topic, it’s important to highlight a few conclusions that can help clear up some common misconceptions and popular mistakes that have been prevalent in philosophy. First, we can see from the previous discussion that all causes are fundamentally the same. In particular, there is no real basis for the distinction we sometimes make between efficient causes and causes that are necessary; or between efficient causes and formal, material, exemplary, and final causes. Since our understanding of efficiency comes from the consistent connection of two objects, wherever this connection is observed, we have an efficient cause; where it isn’t observed, there can never be a cause of any kind. For the same reason, we should dismiss the distinction between cause and occasion when it is thought to imply something essentially different. If a constant connection is implied in what we call an occasion, it is a genuine cause. If not, it is not related at all and cannot lead to any argument or reasoning.
Secondly, The same course of reasoning will make us conclude, that there is but one kind of necessity, as there is but one kind of cause, and that the common distinction betwixt moral and physical necessity is without any foundation in nature. This clearly appears from the precedent explication of necessity. It is the constant conjunction of objects, along with the determination of the mind, which constitutes a physical necessity: And the removal of these is the same thing with chance. As objects must either be conjoined or not, and as the mind must either be determined or not to pass from one object to another, it is impossible to admit of any medium betwixt chance and an absolute necessity. In weakening this conjunction and determination you do not change the nature of the necessity; since even in the operation of bodies, these have different degrees of constancy and force, without producing a different species of that relation.
Secondly, the same line of reasoning leads us to conclude that there is only one type of necessity, just as there is only one type of cause, and that the common distinction between moral and physical necessity has no basis in nature. This is clearly evident from the previous explanation of necessity. It is the constant connection of objects, along with the determination of the mind, that creates physical necessity. Removing these amounts to chance. Since objects must either be connected or not, and the mind must either be determined or not to move from one object to another, it’s impossible to accept any middle ground between chance and absolute necessity. By weakening this connection and determination, you don't alter the nature of necessity; even in the behavior of bodies, they have different degrees of constancy and force without creating a different type of that relationship.
The distinction, which we often make betwixt POWER and the EXERCISE of it, is equally without foundation.
The distinction we often draw between POWER and the EXERCISE of it is equally unfounded.
Thirdly, We may now be able fully to overcome all that repugnance, which it is so natural for us to entertain against the foregoing reasoning, by which we endeavoured to prove, that the necessity of a cause to every beginning of existence is not founded on any arguments either demonstrative or intuitive. Such an opinion will not appear strange after the foregoing definitions. If we define a cause to be an object precedent and contiguous to another, and where all the objects resembling the farmer are placed in a like relation of priority and contiguity to those objects, that resemble the latter; we may easily conceive, that there is no absolute nor metaphysical necessity, that every beginning of existence should be attended with such an object. If we define a cause to be, AN OBJECT PRECEDENT AND CONTIGUOUS TO ANOTHER, AND SO UNITED WITH IT IN THE IMAGINATION, THAT THE IDEA OF THE ONE DETERMINES THE MIND TO FORM THE IDEA OF THE OTHER, AND THE IMPRESSION OF THE ONE TO FORM A MORE LIVELY IDEA OF THE OTHER; we shall make still less difficulty of assenting to this opinion. Such an influence on the mind is in itself perfectly extraordinary and incomprehensible; nor can we be certain of its reality, but from experience and observation.
Thirdly, we may now be able to fully move past any aversion we naturally feel towards the reasoning above, through which we tried to show that the necessity of a cause for every beginning of existence isn’t based on any demonstrable or intuitive arguments. This idea won’t seem strange after the previous definitions. If we define a cause as something that comes before and is next to another thing, and where all objects similar to the first are in the same order and proximity to those objects that resemble the second; we can easily understand that there’s no absolute or metaphysical requirement for every beginning of existence to have such an object. If we define a cause as AN OBJECT THAT COMES BEFORE AND IS NEXT TO ANOTHER, AND IS SO CONNECTED IN OUR MINDS THAT THE IDEA OF ONE LEADS US TO FORM THE IDEA OF THE OTHER, AND THE IMPRESSION OF ONE CREATES A STRONGER IDEA OF THE OTHER; we will find it even easier to accept this view. This influence on the mind is truly extraordinary and hard to grasp; we can only be sure of its reality through experience and observation.
I shall add as a fourth corrollary that we can never have reason to believe that any object exists, of which we cannot form an idea. For as all our reasonings concerning existence are derived from causation, and as all our reasonings concerning causation are derived from the experienced conjunction of objects, not from any reasoning or reflection, the same experience must give us a notion of these objects, and must remove all mystery from our conclusions. This is so evident, that it would scarce have merited our attention, were it not to obviate certain objections of this kind, which might arise against the following reasonings concerning matter and substance. I need not observe, that a full knowledge of the object is not requisite, but only of those qualities of it, which we believe to exist.
I want to add a fourth point: we can never reasonably believe that an object exists if we can’t form an idea of it. All our reasoning about existence comes from causation, and all our reasoning about causation comes from the actual experiences we have with objects, not from any kind of abstract thought or reflection. This experience must give us an understanding of these objects and eliminate any confusion from our conclusions. This is so clear that it hardly deserves our attention, except to address certain objections that might come up regarding the following discussions about matter and substance. I should point out that we don’t need to fully understand the object, just the qualities of it that we believe exist.
SECT. XV. RULES BY WHICH TO JUDGE OF CAUSES AND EFFECTS.
According to the precedent doctrine, there are no objects which by the mere survey, without consulting experience, we can determine to be the causes of any other; and no objects, which we can certainly determine in the same manner not to be the causes. Any thing may produce any thing. Creation, annihilation, motion, reason, volition; all these may arise from one another, or from any other object we can imagine. Nor will this appear strange, if we compare two principles explained above, THAT THE CONSTANT CONJUNCTION OF OBJECTS DETERMINES THEIR CAUSATION, AND[18] THAT, PROPERTY SPEAKING, NO OBJECTS ARE CONTRARY TO EACH OTHER BUT EXISTENCE AND NON-EXISTENCE. Where objects are not contrary, nothing hinders them from having that constant conjunction, on which the relation of cause and effect totally depends.
According to the principle of precedent, there are no objects that we can identify as causes of other things just by looking at them without relying on experience. Similarly, there are no objects we can definitively rule out as causes in the same way. Anything can lead to anything else. Creation, destruction, motion, reasoning, and willpower; all of these can come from one another or from any other object we can think of. This won’t seem strange if we consider the two principles mentioned earlier: THAT THE CONSTANT CONNECTION OF OBJECTS DETERMINES THEIR CAUSATION, AND[18] THAT, IN TERMS OF PROPERTY, NO OBJECTS ARE OPPOSED TO EACH OTHER EXCEPT FOR EXISTENCE AND NON-EXISTENCE. Where objects are not opposed, there’s nothing preventing them from having that constant connection, which is essential to the relationship between cause and effect.
[18] Part I. Sect. 5.
Since therefore it is possible for all objects to become causes or effects to each other, it may be proper to fix some general rules, by which we may know when they really are so.
Since it's possible for all objects to be causes or effects of each other, it makes sense to establish some general rules to help us understand when this is actually the case.
(1) The cause and effect must be contiguous in space and time.
(1) The cause and effect must be connected in both space and time.
(2) The cause must be prior to the effect.
(2) The cause has to come before the effect.
(3) There must be a constant union betwixt the cause and effect. It is chiefly this quality, that constitutes the relation.
(3) There must be a constant connection between the cause and effect. It's mainly this quality that defines the relationship.
(4) The same cause always produces the same effect, and the same effect never arises but from the same cause. This principle we derive from experience, and is the source of most of our philosophical reasonings. For when by any clear experiment we have discovered the causes or effects of any phænomenon, we immediately extend our observation to every phenomenon of the same kind, without waiting for that constant repetition, from which the first idea of this relation is derived.
(4) The same cause always leads to the same effect, and the same effect only comes from the same cause. We learn this principle from experience, and it’s the basis for most of our philosophical thinking. When we clearly identify the causes or effects of a phenomenon through experimentation, we quickly apply our findings to all similar phenomena, without needing to wait for the repeated occurrences that originally gave us this understanding.
(5) There is another principle, which hangs upon this, viz. that where several different objects produce the same effect, it must be by means of some quality, which we discover to be common amongst them. For as like effects imply like causes, we must always ascribe the causation to the circumstance, wherein we discover the resemblance.
(5) There’s another principle related to this: when different things create the same effect, it must be due to some quality they all share. Just as similar effects suggest similar causes, we should always attribute the cause to the aspect where we see the similarity.
(6) The following principle is founded on the same reason. The difference in the effects of two resembling objects must proceed from that particular, in which they differ. For as like causes always produce like effects, when in any instance we find our expectation to be disappointed, we must conclude that this irregularity proceeds from some difference in the causes.
(6) The following principle is based on the same reasoning. The difference in the effects of two similar objects must come from the specific way in which they differ. Just as similar causes always lead to similar effects, when we encounter a situation that doesn't meet our expectations, we should conclude that this inconsistency arises from some difference in the causes.
(7) When any object encreases or diminishes with the encrease or diminution of its cause, it is to be regarded as a compounded effect, derived from the union of the several different effects, which arise from the several different parts of the cause. The absence or presence of one part of the cause is here supposed to be always attended with the absence or presence of a proportionable part of the effect. This constant conjunction sufficiently proves, that the one part is the cause of the other. We must, however, beware not to draw such a conclusion from a few experiments. A certain degree of heat gives pleasure; if you diminish that heat, the pleasure diminishes; but it does not follow, that if you augment it beyond a certain degree, the pleasure will likewise augment; for we find that it degenerates into pain.
(7) When any object increases or decreases along with the increase or decrease of its cause, it should be seen as a combined effect, stemming from the connection of the different effects that arise from the various parts of the cause. The absence or presence of one part of the cause is assumed to always coincide with the absence or presence of a corresponding part of the effect. This consistent link clearly demonstrates that one part is the cause of the other. However, we must be careful not to draw conclusions based on just a few experiments. A certain level of heat is pleasurable; if you reduce that heat, the pleasure decreases. However, that doesn’t mean that if you increase it beyond a certain point, the pleasure will also increase; we see that it can turn into pain.
(8) The eighth and last rule I shall take notice of is, that an object, which exists for any time in its full perfection without any effect, is not the sole cause of that effect, but requires to be assisted by some other principle, which may forward its influence and operation. For as like effects necessarily follow from like causes, and in a contiguous time and place, their separation for a moment shews, that these causes are not compleat ones.
(8) The eighth and final rule I want to mention is that an object that exists in its complete form without producing any effect isn't the only cause of that effect. It needs assistance from another principle that can enhance its influence and operation. Just as similar effects inevitably come from similar causes, their brief separation in time and space shows that these causes aren’t complete on their own.
Here is all the LOGIC I think proper to employ in my reasoning; and perhaps even this was not very necessary, but might have been supplyd by the natural principles of our understanding. Our scholastic head-pieces and logicians shew no such superiority above the mere vulgar in their reason and ability, as to give us any inclination to imitate them in delivering a long system of rules and precepts to direct our judgment, in philosophy. All the rules of this nature are very easy in their invention, but extremely difficult in their application; and even experimental philosophy, which seems the most natural and simple of any, requires the utmost stretch of human judgment. There is no phænomenon in nature, but what is compounded and modifyd by so many different circumstances, that in order to arrive at the decisive point, we must carefully separate whatever is superfluous, and enquire by new experiments, if every particular circumstance of the first experiment was essential to it. These new experiments are liable to a discussion of the same kind; so that the utmost constancy is requird to make us persevere in our enquiry, and the utmost sagacity to choose the right way among so many that present themselves. If this be the case even in natural philosophy, how much more in moral, where there is a much greater complication of circumstances, and where those views and sentiments, which are essential to any action of the mind, are so implicit and obscure, that they often escape our strictest attention, and are not only unaccountable in their causes, but even unknown in their existence? I am much afraid lest the small success I meet with in my enquiries will make this observation bear the air of an apology rather than of boasting.
Here’s the logic I think is important to use in my reasoning; maybe even this wasn’t necessary, but could have been filled in by the natural principles of our understanding. Our academic minds and logicians don’t show any real superiority over the average person in their reasoning and skill, which doesn’t give us much reason to follow them in laying out an extensive system of rules and guidelines to direct our judgment in philosophy. All such rules are easy to come up with but extremely difficult to apply; even experimental philosophy, which seems the simplest and most natural of all, demands the greatest stretch of human judgment. Every phenomenon in nature is influenced and modified by so many different circumstances that to reach a conclusive point, we must carefully remove anything unnecessary and investigate through new experiments whether every detail from the first experiment was crucial. These new experiments are open to the same kind of scrutiny, so we require great persistence to continue our inquiries and sharp insight to choose the right path among the many that arise. If this is true in natural philosophy, how much more so is it in moral philosophy, where the complexities of circumstances are even greater, and where the views and feelings that are essential to any mental action are so implicit and unclear that they often slip past our closest examination, being not only unexplainable in their causes but also unknown in their existence? I’m quite concerned that the little success I’ve had in my inquiries might make this observation sound more like an excuse than a declaration of confidence.
If any thing can give me security in this particular, it will be the enlarging of the sphere of my experiments as much as possible; for which reason it may be proper in this place to examine the reasoning faculty of brutes, as well as that of human creatures.
If anything can provide me with confidence in this matter, it will be expanding the range of my experiments as much as possible. For this reason, it makes sense to explore the reasoning abilities of animals, alongside those of humans.
SECT. XVI OF THE REASON OF ANIMALS
Next to the ridicule of denying an evident truth, is that of taking much pains to defend it; and no truth appears to me more evident, than that beasts are endowd with thought and reason as well as men. The arguments are in this case so obvious, that they never escape the most stupid and ignorant.
Next to the embarrassment of denying an obvious truth is the struggle of trying hard to defend it; and no truth seems more obvious to me than that animals are endowed with thought and reason just like humans. The arguments in this case are so clear that even the most foolish and ignorant people can't overlook them.
We are conscious, that we ourselves, in adapting means to ends, are guided by reason and design, and that it is not ignorantly nor casually we perform those actions, which tend to self-preservation, to the obtaining pleasure, and avoiding pain. When therefore we see other creatures, in millions of instances, perform like actions, and direct them to the ends, all our principles of reason and probability carry us with an invincible force to believe the existence of a like cause. It is needless in my opinion to illustrate this argument by the enumeration of particulars. The smallest attention will supply us with more than are requisite. The resemblance betwixt the actions of animals and those of men is so entire in this respect, that the very first action of the first animal we shall please to pitch on, will afford us an incontestable argument for the present doctrine.
We understand that when we adapt our methods to our goals, we are guided by reason and intention, and that we don’t perform actions aimed at self-preservation, seeking pleasure, and avoiding pain without thought or care. Therefore, when we observe other creatures, in millions of cases, carrying out similar actions and directing them toward similar goals, all our principles of reason and probability compel us to believe in a similar cause. I think it’s unnecessary to elaborate on this argument by listing specifics. Even a little attention will give us more examples than we need. The similarity between the actions of animals and those of humans is so complete in this regard that even the very first action of the first animal we choose to consider will provide us with undeniable support for this doctrine.
This doctrine is as useful as it is obvious, and furnishes us with a kind of touchstone, by which we may try every system in this species of philosophy. It is from the resemblance of the external actions of animals to those we ourselves perform, that we judge their internal likewise to resemble ours; and the same principle of reasoning, carryd one step farther, will make us conclude that since our internal actions resemble each other, the causes, from which they are derivd, must also be resembling. When any hypothesis, therefore, is advancd to explain a mental operation, which is common to men and beasts, we must apply the same hypothesis to both; and as every true hypothesis will abide this trial, so I may venture to affirm, that no false one will ever be able to endure it. The common defect of those systems, which philosophers have employd to account for the actions of the mind, is, that they suppose such a subtility and refinement of thought, as not only exceeds the capacity of mere animals, but even of children and the common people in our own species; who are notwithstanding susceptible of the same emotions and affections as persons of the most accomplishd genius and understanding. Such a subtility is a dear proof of the falshood, as the contrary simplicity of the truth, of any system.
This idea is as useful as it is obvious, serving as a sort of benchmark that we can use to evaluate every approach in this area of philosophy. We judge that the internal experiences of animals are similar to ours based on the similarities in their external behavior. If we take this reasoning a step further, we can conclude that because our internal processes are alike, the causes behind them must also be similar. Therefore, when a theory is proposed to explain a mental process that's common to both humans and animals, we need to apply the same theory to both. Every valid theory will withstand this test, while I can confidently say that no false theory will ever pass it. A common flaw in the systems philosophers have used to explain mental actions is that they assume a level of subtlety and complexity in thought that not only exceeds that of mere animals but also surpasses that of children and everyday people in our own species. However, these groups are still capable of experiencing the same emotions and feelings as those with the most developed intelligence and understanding. Such complexity is a strong indicator of falsehood, in contrast to the simplicity of truth found in any valid system.
Let us therefore put our present system concerning the nature of the understanding to this decisive trial, and see whether it will equally account for the reasonings of beasts as for these of the human species.
Let’s put our current understanding system to the test and see if it can explain the reasoning of animals just as well as it does for humans.
Here we must make a distinction betwixt those actions of animals, which are of a vulgar nature, and seem to be on a level with their common capacities, and those more extraordinary instances of sagacity, which they sometimes discover for their own preservation, and the propagation of their species. A dog, that avoids fire and precipices, that shuns strangers, and caresses his master, affords us an instance of the first kind. A bird, that chooses with such care and nicety the place and materials of her nest, and sits upon her eggs for a due time, and in suitable season, with all the precaution that a chymist is capable of in the most delicate projection, furnishes us with a lively instance of the second.
Here we need to distinguish between the common actions of animals, which seem to match their typical abilities, and the more extraordinary displays of intelligence they sometimes show for their own survival and the continuation of their species. A dog that avoids fire and cliffs, stays away from strangers, and shows affection to its owner is an example of the first type. A bird that carefully selects the location and materials for its nest, incubates its eggs for the right amount of time, and does so at the proper season, with as much care as a chemist in a delicate experiment, provides us with a vivid example of the second.
As to the former actions, I assert they proceed from a reasoning, that is not in itself different, nor founded on different principles, from that which appears in human nature. It is necessary in the first place, that there be some impression immediately present to their memory or senses, in order to be the foundation of their judgment. From the tone of voice the dog infers his masters anger, and foresees his own punishment. From a certain sensation affecting his smell, he judges his game not to be far distant from him.
Regarding the earlier actions, I claim they come from a reasoning that isn't fundamentally different or based on different principles from what we see in human nature. First of all, there needs to be some impression that is immediately present in their memory or senses to serve as the basis for their judgment. From the tone of voice, the dog senses his master's anger and anticipates his own punishment. From a specific smell, he determines that his prey is not far away.
Secondly, The inference he draws from the present impression is built on experience, and on his observation of the conjunction of objects in past instances. As you vary this experience, he varies his reasoning. Make a beating follow upon one sign or motion for some time, and afterwards upon another; and he will successively draw different conclusions, according to his most recent experience.
Secondly, the conclusion he makes from the current impression is based on his experience and what he has noticed about the connection between things in the past. As you change this experience, he changes his reasoning. If you consistently respond to one sign or movement for a while, then switch to another, he will draw different conclusions based on his most recent experience.
Now let any philosopher make a trial, and endeavour to explain that act of the mind, which we call BELIEF, and give an account of the principles, from which it is derivd, independent of the influence of custom on the imagination, and let his hypothesis be equally applicable to beasts as to the human species; and after he has done this, I promise to embrace his opinion. But at the same time I demand as an equitable condition, that if my system be the only one, which can answer to all these terms, it may be receivd as entirely satisfactory and convincing. And that it is the only one, is evident almost without any reasoning. Beasts certainly never perceive any real connexion among objects. It is therefore by experience they infer one from another. They can never by any arguments form a general conclusion, that those objects, of which they have had no experience, resemble those of which they have. It is therefore by means of custom alone, that experience operates upon them. All this was sufficiently evident with respect to man. But with respect to beasts there cannot be the least suspicion of mistake; which must be ownd to be a strong confirmation, or rather an invincible proof of my system.
Now let any philosopher give it a try and try to explain that mental process we call BELIEF, detailing the principles it comes from, without relying on the influence of custom on our imagination. If his explanation can also apply to animals as well as humans, then I promise to accept his viewpoint. However, I also require that if my explanation is the only one that meets all these criteria, it should be accepted as completely satisfactory and convincing. It’s almost obvious without needing much reasoning that mine is the only valid one. Animals certainly don't perceive any real connections among objects. They rely on experience to draw inferences from one another. They can never logically conclude that objects they haven't encountered resemble those they have. So, it’s only through custom that experience affects them. This is clearly evident in humans. But regarding animals, there can be no doubt; this must be acknowledged as strong confirmation—or rather, an undeniable proof—of my view.
Nothing shews more the force of habit in reconciling us to any phaenomenoun, than this, that men are not astonished at the operations of their own reason, at the same time, that they admire the instinct of animals, and find a difficulty in explaining it, merely because it cannot be reduced to the very same principles. To consider the matter aright, reason is nothing but a wonderful and unintelligible instinct in our souls, which carries us along a certain train of ideas, and endows them with particular qualities, according to their particular situations and relations. This instinct, it is true, arises from past observation and experience; but can any one give the ultimate reason, why past experience and observation produces such an effect, any more than why nature alone shoud produce it? Nature may certainly produce whatever can arise from habit: Nay, habit is nothing but one of the principles of nature, and derives all its force from that origin.
Nothing shows more about how powerful habit is in making us accept things than the fact that people aren’t surprised by the workings of their own reasoning while they admire the instincts of animals and struggle to explain them, simply because those instincts can't be boiled down to the same principles. If we think about it, reason is just a fascinating and puzzling instinct within us, guiding us through a specific series of thoughts and giving them distinct qualities based on their unique contexts and relationships. This instinct indeed comes from our past observations and experiences, but can anyone truly explain why past experience and observation create such an impact, just as easily as they might explain why nature itself could produce it? Nature can certainly generate anything that can arise from habit; in fact, habit is just one of nature’s principles and gets all its power from that source.
SECT. I. OF SCEPTICISM WITH REGARD TO REASON.
In all demonstrative sciences the rules are certain and infallible; but when we apply them, our fallible said uncertain faculties are very apt to depart from them, and fall into error. We must, therefore, in every reasoning form a new judgment, as a check or controul on our first judgment or belief; and must enlarge our view to comprehend a kind of history of all the instances, wherein our understanding has deceived us, compared with those, wherein its testimony was just and true. Our reason must be considered as a kind of cause, of which truth is the natural effect; but such-a-one as by the irruption of other causes, and by the inconstancy of our mental powers, may frequently be prevented. By this means all knowledge degenerates into probability; and this probability is greater or less, according to our experience of the veracity or deceitfulness of our understanding, and according to the simplicity or intricacy of the question.
In all demonstrative sciences, the rules are clear and reliable; however, when we apply them, our unreliable and uncertain faculties often stray from these rules and make mistakes. Therefore, in every reasoning process, we need to form a new judgment to check or control our initial judgment or belief; and we must broaden our perspective to include a sort of history of all the instances where our understanding has misled us, compared to those where it was accurate and true. Our reasoning should be seen as a kind of cause, with truth being the natural outcome; but it can be frequently disrupted by other causes and the inconsistency of our mental abilities. Because of this, all knowledge risks becoming mere probability, and this probability fluctuates based on our experiences with the honesty or deception of our understanding, as well as the simplicity or complexity of the issue at hand.
There is no Algebraist nor Mathematician so expert in his science, as to place entire confidence in any truth immediately upon his discovery of it, or regard it as any thing, but a mere probability. Every time he runs over his proofs, his confidence encreases; but still more by the approbation of his friends; and is raised to its utmost perfection by the universal assent and applauses of the learned world. Now it is evident, that this gradual encrease of assurance is nothing but the addition of new probabilities, and is derived from the constant union of causes and effects, according to past experience and observation.
No mathematician or algebraist is so skilled in their field that they can fully trust a truth right after discovering it or see it as anything more than a simple possibility. Every time they review their proofs, their confidence grows; it grows even more with the approval of their peers and reaches its peak with the widespread agreement and praise from the academic community. Clearly, this gradual increase in certainty is just the accumulation of new possibilities, arising from the consistent relationship between causes and effects based on past experience and observation.
In accompts of any length or importance, Merchants seldom trust to the infallible certainty of numbers for their security; but by the artificial structure of the accompts, produce a probability beyond what is derived from the skill and experience of the accomptant. For that is plainly of itself some degree of probability; though uncertain and variable, according to the degrees of his experience and length of the accompt. Now as none will maintain, that our assurance in a long numeration exceeds probability, I may safely affirm, that there scarce is any proposition concerning numbers, of which we can have a fuller security. For it is easily possible, by gradually diminishing the numbers, to reduce the longest series of addition to the most simple question, which can be formed, to an addition of two single numbers; and upon this supposition we shall find it impracticable to shew the precise limits of knowledge and of probability, or discover that particular number, at which the one ends and the other begins. But knowledge and probability are of such contrary and disagreeing natures, that they cannot well run insensibly into each other, and that because they will not divide, but must be either entirely present, or entirely absent. Besides, if any single addition were certain, every one would be so, and consequently the whole or total sum; unless the whole can be different from all its parts. I had almost said, that this was certain; but I reflect that it must reduce itself, as well as every other reasoning, and from knowledge degenerate into probability.
In accounts of any length or significance, merchants rarely rely solely on the infallible accuracy of numbers for their security; instead, they create a structure within the accounts that offers a probability exceeding what comes from the accountant's skill and experience. That alone provides some level of probability, although it is uncertain and varies based on the accountant’s experience and the length of the account. No one would argue that our confidence in a lengthy calculation surpasses mere probability; thus, I can confidently state that there are few claims about numbers for which we can have greater certainty. It is possible, by gradually reducing the numbers, to simplify the longest series of additions down to a basic question of adding two single numbers. Under this premise, it becomes impractical to define the exact boundaries of knowledge and probability or to identify the specific number that marks the transition from one to the other. However, knowledge and probability are fundamentally different, making it difficult for them to seamlessly merge; they cannot coexist in a divided manner, but must either be completely present or completely absent. Moreover, if any single addition were certain, then every addition would also be certain, and consequently the overall total; unless the whole can differ from all its parts. I almost stated that this was certain, but I realize that it must ultimately fold back into probability, just like any other reasoning.
Since therefore all knowledge resolves itself into probability, and becomes at last of the same nature with that evidence, which we employ in common life, we must now examine this latter species of reasoning, and see on what foundation it stands.
Since all knowledge ultimately comes down to probability and becomes similar to the evidence we use in everyday life, we need to look into this type of reasoning and understand its foundation.
In every judgment, which we can form concerning probability, as well as concerning knowledge, we ought always to correct the first judgment, derived from the nature of the object, by another judgment, derived from the nature of the understanding. It is certain a man of solid sense and long experience ought to have, and usually has, a greater assurance in his opinions, than one that is foolish and ignorant, and that our sentiments have different degrees of authority, even with ourselves, in proportion to the degrees of our reason and experience. In the man of the best sense and longest experience, this authority is never entire; since even such-a-one must be conscious of many errors in the past, and must still dread the like for the future. Here then arises a new species of probability to correct and regulate the first, and fix its just standard and proportion. As demonstration is subject to the controul of probability, so is probability liable to a new correction by a reflex act of the mind, wherein the nature of our understanding, and our reasoning from the first probability become our objects.
In every judgment we make about probability, as well as knowledge, we should always adjust our initial judgment based on the nature of the object by considering another judgment that comes from our understanding. It’s clear that a person with common sense and extensive experience tends to have more confidence in their opinions than someone who is foolish and uninformed. Our beliefs carry different weights, even for ourselves, based on our levels of reason and experience. Even the most sensible and experienced person never has complete certainty; such a person is aware of past mistakes and still fears making similar ones in the future. This introduces a new kind of probability to refine and regulate the first, establishing its appropriate standard and balance. Just as demonstration is influenced by probability, probability itself can be adjusted by a reflective act of the mind, where the nature of our understanding and our reasoning from the initial probability become our focus.
Having thus found in every probability, beside the original uncertainty inherent in the subject, a new uncertainty derived from the weakness of that faculty, which judges, and having adjusted these two together, we are obliged by our reason to add a new doubt derived from the possibility of error in the estimation we make of the truth and fidelity of our faculties. This is a doubt, which immediately occurs to us, and of which, if we would closely pursue our reason, we cannot avoid giving a decision. But this decision, though it should be favourable to our preceding judgment, being founded only on probability, must weaken still further our first evidence, and must itself be weakened by a fourth doubt of the same kind, and so on in infinitum: till at last there remain nothing of the original probability, however great we may suppose it to have been, and however small the diminution by every new uncertainty. No finite object can subsist under a decrease repeated IN INFINITUM; and even the vastest quantity, which can enter into human imagination, must in this manner be reduced to nothing. Let our first belief be never so strong, it must infallibly perish by passing through so many new examinations, of which each diminishes somewhat of its force and vigour. When I reflect on the natural fallibility of my judgment, I have less confidence in my opinions, than when I only consider the objects concerning which I reason; and when I proceed still farther, to turn the scrutiny against every successive estimation I make of my faculties, all the rules of logic require a continual diminution, and at last a total extinction of belief and evidence.
Having found, in every case, alongside the original uncertainty that comes with the topic, a new uncertainty arising from the limitations of our judgment, and having combined these two, we must, by our reason, introduce a new doubt stemming from the potential for error in how we assess the truth and accuracy of our faculties. This doubt comes to mind immediately, and if we thoroughly follow our reasoning, we cannot avoid making a decision about it. However, this decision, even if it supports our previous judgment and is based only on probability, must further weaken our initial evidence and will itself be weakened by a fourth doubt of a similar nature, and so on indefinitely: until eventually, there’s nothing left of the original probability, regardless of how great we thought it was, and however minor the reduction with each new uncertainty. No finite object can persist under an infinite series of reductions; and even the largest quantity imaginable must eventually be reduced to nothing in this way. No matter how strong our initial belief is, it will surely fade away after being subjected to so many new examinations, each of which slightly diminishes its strength and vigor. When I consider the natural fallibility of my judgment, I have less confidence in my views than when I focus solely on the things I’m reasoning about; and when I push further, scrutinizing every subsequent assessment I make of my faculties, all the rules of logic demand a continuous decrease, ultimately leading to a complete extinction of belief and certainty.
Should it here be asked me, whether I sincerely assent to this argument, which I seem to take such pains to inculcate, and whether I be really one of those sceptics, who hold that all is uncertain, and that our judgment is not in any thing possest of any measures of truth and falshood; I should reply, that this question is entirely superfluous, and that neither I, nor any other person was ever sincerely and constantly of that opinion. Nature, by an absolute and uncontroulable necessity has determined us to judge as well as to breathe and feel; nor can we any more forbear viewing certain objects in a stronger and fuller light, upon account of their customary connexion with a present impression, than we can hinder ourselves from thinking as long, as we are awake, or seeing the surrounding bodies, when we turn our eyes towards them in broad sunshine. Whoever has taken the pains to refute the cavils of this total scepticism, has really disputed without an antagonist, and endeavoured by arguments to establish a faculty, which nature has antecedently implanted in the mind, and rendered unavoidable.
If you were to ask me whether I genuinely agree with this argument that I seem to emphasize so much, and whether I truly belong to those skeptics who believe that everything is uncertain and that our judgment has no reliable standards of truth and falsehood, I would say that this question is completely unnecessary. Neither I nor anyone else has ever sincerely and consistently held that view. Nature, by an unavoidable necessity, has compelled us to judge just as we breathe and feel. We can't avoid seeing certain things in a clearer and stronger way because of their usual connection with a current impression, any more than we can stop thinking while we are awake or seeing the objects around us when we look at them in bright sunlight. Anyone who has taken the time to counter the arguments of total skepticism has really been arguing with no one at all, trying to prove the existence of a capacity that nature has already given us in our minds and made inescapable.
My intention then in displaying so carefully the arguments of that fantastic sect, is only to make the reader sensible of the truth of my hypothesis, that all our reasonings concerning causes and effects are derived from nothing but custom; and that belief is more properly an act of the sensitive, than of the cogitative part of our natures. I have here proved, that the very same principles, which make us form a decision upon any subject, and correct that decision by the consideration of our genius and capacity, and of the situation of our mind, when we examined that subject; I say, I have proved, that these same principles, when carryed farther, and applied to every new reflex judgment, must, by continually diminishing the original evidence, at last reduce it to nothing, and utterly subvert all belief and opinion. If belief, therefore, were a simple act of the thought, without any peculiar manner of conception, or the addition of a force and vivacity, it must infallibly destroy itself, and in every case terminate in a total suspense of judgment. But as experience will sufficiently convince any one, who thinks it worth while to try, that though he can find no error in the foregoing arguments, yet he still continues to believe, and think, and reason as usual, he may safely conclude, that his reasoning and belief is some sensation or peculiar manner of conception, which it is impossible for mere ideas and reflections to destroy.
My goal in carefully laying out the arguments of that strange group is simply to help the reader understand the truth of my hypothesis: that all our reasoning about causes and effects comes from nothing but habit; and that belief is more accurately an action of our feelings than of our thinking nature. I've shown that the same principles that help us make a decision on any topic and adjust that decision based on our talents, capabilities, and our mindset when we considered that topic—those same principles, when taken further and applied to each new judgment, must, by constantly reducing the original evidence, eventually bring it down to nothing and completely overturn all belief and opinion. Therefore, if belief were a simple act of thought, without any unique way of understanding or added force and vividness, it would inevitably cancel itself out and in every case lead to a complete suspension of judgment. However, as experience clearly shows anyone willing to see, even if they can't find any flaws in the previous arguments, they still continue to believe, think, and reason as usual. They can confidently conclude that their reasoning and belief come from some sensation or unique way of understanding that mere ideas and reflections cannot erase.
But here, perhaps, it may be demanded, how it happens, even upon my hypothesis, that these arguments above-explained produce not a total suspense of judgment, and after what manner the mind ever retains a degree of assurance in any subject? For as these new probabilities, which by their repetition perpetually diminish the original evidence, are founded on the very same principles, whether of thought or sensation, as the primary judgment, it may seem unavoidable, that in either case they must equally subvert it, and by the opposition, either of contrary thoughts or sensations, reduce the mind to a total uncertainty. I suppose, there is some question proposed to me, and that after revolving over the impressions of my memory and senses, and carrying my thoughts from them to such objects, as are commonly conjoined with them, I feel a stronger and more forcible conception on the one side, than on the other. This strong conception forms my first decision. I suppose, that afterwards I examine my judgment itself, and observing from experience, that it is sometimes just and sometimes erroneous, I consider it as regulated by contrary principles or causes, of which some lead to truth, and some to error; and in ballancing these contrary causes, I diminish by a new probability the assurance of my first decision. This new probability is liable to the same diminution as the foregoing, and so on, IN INFINITUM. It is therefore demanded, how it happens, that even after all we retain a degree of belief, which is sufficient for our purpose, either in philosophy or common life.
But here, perhaps, one might ask how it is that even with my hypothesis, these arguments mentioned above don't completely suspend judgment, and how the mind still holds onto some level of certainty about any subject. Since these new probabilities, which get weaker with their repeated appearance, are based on the same principles, whether of thought or sensation, as the original judgment, it might seem inevitable that both would undermine it and, through opposing thoughts or sensations, lead the mind to total uncertainty. Let's say there’s a question posed to me, and after reflecting on my memories and senses and relating my thoughts to objects commonly associated with them, I find that I have a stronger and more compelling idea on one side than the other. This strong idea shapes my initial opinion. I assume that later I assess my judgment, noticing from experience that it can be both correct and incorrect. I consider it influenced by opposing principles or causes, some of which lead to truth and some to error. By weighing these opposing causes, I lessen my confidence in my initial opinion with a new probability. This new probability can be diminished in the same way as the previous one, and so on, endlessly. Therefore, it raises the question of how we still manage to maintain a certain degree of belief that is sufficient for our needs, whether in philosophy or everyday life.
I answer, that after the first and second decision; as the action of the mind becomes forced and unnatural, and the ideas faint and obscure; though the principles of judgment, and the ballancing of opposite causes be the same as at the very beginning; yet their influence on the imagination, and the vigour they add to, or diminish from the thought, is by no means equal. Where the mind reaches not its objects with easiness and facility, the same principles have not the same effect as in a more natural conception of the ideas; nor does the imagination feel a sensation, which holds any proportion with that which arises from its common judgments and opinions. The attention is on the stretch: The posture of the mind is uneasy; and the spirits being diverted from their natural course, are not governed in their movements by the same laws, at least not to the same degree, as when they flow in their usual channel.
I say that after the first and second decision, the mind's actions become forced and unnatural, and the ideas become faint and unclear. Even though the principles of judgment and the weighing of opposite causes are the same as at the very beginning, their impact on the imagination, as well as the strength they add to or take away from the thought, is definitely not the same. When the mind struggles to grasp its objectives easily, the same principles don't have the same effect as they do with a more natural understanding of the ideas. Similarly, the imagination doesn't feel a sensation that matches what comes from its usual judgments and opinions. Attention is strained; the mind feels uneasy; and the spirits, being diverted from their natural path, don't move according to the same rules—at least not to the same extent—as when they flow in their regular way.
If we desire similar instances, it will not be very difficult to find them. The present subject of metaphysics will supply us abundantly. The same argument, which would have been esteemed convincing in a reasoning concerning history or politics, has little or no influence in these abstruser subjects, even though it be perfectly comprehended; and that because there is required a study and an effort of thought, in order to its being comprehended: And this effort of thought disturbs the operation of our sentiments, on which the belief depends. The case is the same in other subjects. The straining of the imagination always hinders the regular flowing of the passions and sentiments. A tragic poet, that would represent his heroes as very ingenious and witty in their misfortunes, would never touch the passions. As the emotions of the soul prevent any subtile reasoning and reflection, so these latter actions of the mind are equally prejudicial to the former. The mind, as well as the body, seems to be endowed with a certain precise degree of force and activity, which it never employs in one action, but at the expense of all the rest. This is more evidently true, where the actions are of quite different natures; since in that case the force of the mind is not only diverted, but even the disposition changed, so as to render us incapable of a sudden transition from one action to the other, and still more of performing both at once. No wonder, then, the conviction, which arises from a subtile reasoning, diminishes in proportion to the efforts, which the imagination makes to enter into the reasoning, and to conceive it in all its parts. Belief, being a lively conception, can never be entire, where it is not founded on something natural and easy.
If we want similar examples, it won't be too hard to find them. The topic of metaphysics will provide us plenty. The same argument that would have been considered convincing in a discussion about history or politics has little to no effect in these more complex subjects, even if it's fully understood; and that's because understanding requires study and mental effort, which disrupts our feelings—on which belief relies. The same goes for other topics. Straining the imagination always hinders the smooth flow of our emotions and feelings. A tragic poet who tries to portray their heroes as clever and witty in their misfortunes will never stir the emotions. Just as the emotions of the soul prevent subtle reasoning and reflection, these latter mental activities are also detrimental to the former. The mind, like the body, seems to have a specific amount of force and energy that it uses for one action at the cost of others. This is especially true when the actions are very different; in that case, the mind's force gets diverted, and its focus changes, making it hard for us to switch suddenly from one action to another, and even harder to do both at the same time. So, it's no surprise that the conviction from subtle reasoning decreases as the imagination works harder to engage with the reasoning and understand it fully. Belief, being a vivid concept, can never be complete unless it's based on something natural and easy.
This I take to be the true state of the question, and cannot approve of that expeditious way, which some take with the sceptics, to reject at once all their arguments without enquiry or examination. If the sceptical reasonings be strong, say they, it is a proof, that reason may have some force and authority: if weak, they can never be sufficient to invalidate all the conclusions of our understanding. This argument is not just; because the sceptical reasonings, were it possible for them to exist, and were they not destroyed by their subtility, would be successively both strong and weak, according to the successive dispositions of the mind. Reason first appears in possession of the throne, prescribing laws, and imposing maxims, with an absolute sway and authority. Her enemy, therefore, is obliged to take shelter under her protection, and by making use of rational arguments to prove the fallaciousness and imbecility of reason, produces, in a manner, a patent under her and and seal. This patent has at first an authority, proportioned to the present and immediate authority of reason, from which it is derived. But as it is supposed to be contradictory to reason, it gradually diminishes the force of that governing power and its own at the same time; till at last they both vanish away into nothing, by a regulax and just diminution. The sceptical and dogmatical reasons are of the same kind, though contrary in their operation and tendency; so that where the latter is strong, it has an enemy of equal force in the former to encounter; and as their forces were at first equal, they still continue so, as long as either of them subsists; nor does one of them lose any force in the contest, without taking as much from its antagonist. It is happy, therefore, that nature breaks the force of all sceptical arguments in time, and keeps them from having any considerable influence on the understanding. Were we to trust entirely to their self-destruction, that can never take place, until they have first subverted all conviction, and have totally destroyed human reason.
I believe this is the real issue at hand, and I can't agree with those who quickly dismiss all arguments from sceptics without any questioning or investigation. They claim that if sceptical reasoning is strong, it proves that reason can have some power and authority; if it's weak, it can't possibly undermine all the conclusions we've come to through understanding. This reasoning isn't fair because sceptical arguments, if they were to exist and not be undermined by their own complexity, would vary in strength and weakness depending on the mindset of the person considering them. Reason initially takes the lead, setting rules and imposing principles with total control and authority. Its adversary must seek refuge under its protection, using rational arguments to demonstrate the flaws and weaknesses in reason, thereby gaining an endorsement from it. This endorsement initially holds authority proportional to reason's immediate power, but since it’s seen as contradicting reason, its power gradually weakens, along with that of reason itself, until both fade into nothingness through a regular and fair reduction. Sceptical and dogmatic arguments are fundamentally similar, even though they work and aim in opposite directions; where one is strong, the other presents an equally strong challenge. Their strengths were equal at the outset, and they remain so as long as either exists; one doesn't weaken without taking something away from the other in the struggle. Fortunately, nature eventually diminishes the impact of all sceptical arguments over time, preventing them from having a significant effect on understanding. If we were to rely solely on their self-destruction, that wouldn't happen until they had first undermined all conviction and completely eradicated human reason.
SECT. II. OF SCEPTICISM WITH REGARD TO THE SENSES.
Thus the sceptic still continues to reason and believe, even though he asserts, that he cannot defend his reason by reason; and by the same rule he must assent to the principle concerning the existence of body, though he cannot pretend by any arguments of philosophy to maintain its veracity. Nature has not left this to his choice, and has doubtless, esteemed it an affair of too great importance to be trusted to our uncertain reasonings and speculations. We may well ask, What causes induce us to believe in the existence of body? but it is in vain to ask, Whether there be body or not? That is a point, which we must take for granted in all our reasonings.
So, the skeptic keeps reasoning and believing, even though they claim they can't defend their reasoning with reason. By the same logic, they must agree with the idea of the existence of a body, even if they can't provide any philosophical arguments to prove its truth. Nature hasn’t left this up to us and clearly considers it too important to depend on our uncertain reasoning and speculations. We can definitely ask what causes lead us to believe in the existence of a body, but it's pointless to ask whether a body exists or not. That’s something we have to assume in all our reasoning.
The subject, then, of our present enquiry is concerning the causes which induce us to believe in the existence of body: And my reasonings on this head I shall begin with a distinction, which at first sight may seem superfluous, but which will contribute very much to the perfect understanding of what follows. We ought to examine apart those two questions, which are commonly confounded together, viz. Why we attribute a continued existence to objects, even when they are not present to the senses; and why we suppose them to have an existence DISTINCT from the mind and perception. Under this last head I comprehend their situation as well as relations, their external position as well as the independence of their existence and operation. These two questions concerning the continued and distinct existence of body are intimately connected together. For if the objects of our senses continue to exist, even when they are not perceived, their existence is of course independent of and distinct from the perception: and vice versa, if their existence be independent of the perception and distinct from it, they must continue to exist, even though they be not perceived. But though the decision of the one question decides the other; yet that we may the more easily discover the principles of human nature, from whence the decision arises, we shall carry along with us this distinction, and shall consider, whether it be the senses, reason, or the imagination, that produces the opinion of a continued or of a distinct existence. These are the only questions, that are intelligible on the present subject. For as to the notion of external existence, when taken for something specially different from our perceptions,[1] we have already shewn its absurdity.
The topic of our current inquiry is about the reasons that lead us to believe in the existence of physical objects. I will start my reasoning with a distinction that might seem unnecessary at first but will greatly help in understanding what follows. We need to look at two separate questions that are often confused: Why do we think that objects continue to exist even when we can't perceive them? And why do we believe they exist independently of our minds and perceptions? In this second question, I include their location and relationships, their external positions, and the independence of their existence and actions. These two questions about the continued and independent existence of physical objects are closely related. If the things we sense still exist even when we aren't aware of them, then their existence is clearly independent from and separate from our perceptions. Conversely, if their existence is independent and distinct from perception, then they must continue to exist even when we can't perceive them. While the answer to one question provides the answer to the other, to better understand the principles of human nature that inform these answers, we will keep this distinction in mind and consider whether it's the senses, reason, or imagination that shapes our belief in continued or distinct existence. These are the only clear questions in this topic. Regarding the idea of external existence as something fundamentally different from our perceptions, we have already shown its absurdity.
[1] Part. II. Sect. 6.
To begin with the SENSES, it is evident these faculties are incapable of giving rise to the notion of the continued existence of their objects, after they no longer appear to the senses. For that is a contradiction in terms, and suppose that the senses continue to operate, even after they have ceased all manner of operation. These faculties, therefore, if they have any influence in the present case, must produce the opinion of a distinct, not of a continued existence; and in order to that, must present their impressions either as images and representations, or as these very distinct and external existences.
To start with the SENSES, it's clear that these faculties can't lead to the idea that objects exist continuously after they are no longer perceived. That's a contradiction in terms; it would be like saying the senses keep working even after they've completely stopped. So, if these faculties have any role here, they must create the belief in something distinct, not in continuous existence. To do this, they must present their impressions either as images and representations or as these very distinct and external existences.
That our senses offer not their impressions as the images of something distinct, or independent, and external, is evident; because they convey to us nothing but a single perception, and never give us the least intimation of any thing beyond. A single perception can never produce the idea of a double existence, but by some inference either of the reason or imagination. When the mind looks farther than what immediately appears to it, its conclusions can never be put to the account of the senses; and it certainly looks farther, when from a single perception it infers a double existence, and supposes the relations of resemblance and causation betwixt them.
It's clear that our senses do not present their impressions as images of something separate, independent, and external. They provide us with only a single perception and never hint at anything beyond that. A single perception can't create the idea of two existences on its own, except through some reasoning or imagination. When the mind explores beyond what is immediately obvious, its conclusions can't be attributed to the senses. It definitely goes further when it infers a dual existence from a single perception and assumes relationships of similarity and causation between them.
If our senses, therefore, suggest any idea of distinct existences, they must convey the impressions as those very existences, by a kind of fallacy and illusion. Upon this bead we may observe, that all sensations are felt by the mind, such as they really are, and that when we doubt, whether they present themselves as distinct objects, or as mere impressions, the difficulty is not concerning their nature, but concerning their relations and situation. Now if the senses presented our impressions as external to, and independent of ourselves, both the objects and ourselves must be obvious to our senses, otherwise they could not be compared by these faculties. The difficulty, then, is how fax we are ourselves the objects of our senses.
If our senses suggest any idea of separate existences, they must convey those impressions as if they are those existences, through a kind of trick and illusion. Regarding this point, we can see that all sensations are experienced by the mind just as they actually are, and when we question whether they appear as distinct objects or just as impressions, the challenge isn't about their nature but about their relationships and positioning. Now, if our senses showed our impressions as being outside of us and independent, both the objects and ourselves would need to be clear to our senses; otherwise, we couldn't compare them using those faculties. Therefore, the challenge is how far we are actually the objects of our senses.
It is certain there is no question in philosophy more abstruse than that concerning identity, and the nature of the uniting principle, which constitutes a person. So far from being able by our senses merely to determine this question, we must have recourse to the most profound metaphysics to give a satisfactory answer to it; and in common life it is evident these ideas of self and person are never very fixed nor determinate. It is absurd, therefore, to imagine the senses can ever distinguish betwixt ourselves and external objects.
There's definitely no topic in philosophy more complicated than the one about identity and what makes someone a person. Instead of figuring this out through our senses alone, we need to dive into deep metaphysics to find a satisfying answer. In everyday life, it's clear that our ideas of self and person are often not very clear or defined. So, it's silly to think our senses can really tell the difference between ourselves and things outside of us.
Add to this, that every impression, external and internal, passions, affections, sensations, pains and pleasures, are originally on the same footing; and that whatever other differences we may observe among them, they appear, all of them, in their true colours, as impressions or perceptions. And indeed, if we consider the matter aright, it is scarce possible it should be otherwise, nor is it conceivable that our senses should be more capable of deceiving us in the situation and relations, than in the nature of our impressions. For since all actions and sensations of the mind are known to us by consciousness, they must necessarily appear in every particular what they are, and be what they appear. Every thing that enters the mind, being in reality a perception, it is impossible any thing should to feeling appear different. This were to suppose, that even where we are most intimately conscious, we might be mistaken.
Add to this that every impression, whether external or internal—like passions, emotions, sensations, pains, and pleasures—starts off on the same level. And although we might notice other differences among them, they all show up in their true form as impressions or perceptions. In fact, if we think about it carefully, it’s hardly possible for it to be any different, nor can we imagine that our senses would be more likely to mislead us regarding the context and relationships than they would about the nature of our impressions. Since all actions and sensations of the mind are known to us through consciousness, they have to appear exactly as they are in every detail and be what they seem. Everything that comes into the mind is, in reality, a perception, so it’s impossible for anything to feel different. To think otherwise would mean that, even when we are most acutely aware, we could be mistaken.
But not to lose time in examining, whether it is possible for our senses to deceive us, and represent our perceptions as distinct from ourselves, that is as external to and independent of us; let us consider whether they really do so, and whether this error proceeds from an immediate sensation, or from some other causes.
But let's not waste time wondering if our senses can deceive us and make our perceptions seem separate from us, as if they exist outside and independently. Instead, let's look at whether they actually do that and if this mistake comes from a direct sensation or from some other reasons.
To begin with the question concerning EXTERNAL existence, it may perhaps be said, that setting aside the metaphysical question of the identity of a thinking substance, our own body evidently belongs to us; and as several impressions appear exterior to the body, we suppose them also exterior to ourselves. The paper, on which I write at present, is beyond my hand. The table is beyond the paper. The walls of the chamber beyond the table. And in casting my eye towards the window, I perceive a great extent of fields and buildings beyond my chamber. From all this it may be infered, that no other faculty is required, beside the senses, to convince us of the external existence of body. But to prevent this inference, we need only weigh the three following considerations. First, That, properly speaking, it is not our body we perceive, when we regard our limbs and members, but certain impressions, which enter by the senses; so that the ascribing a real and corporeal existence to these impressions, or to their objects, is an act of the mind as difficult to explain, as that which we examine at present. Secondly, Sounds, and tastes, and smelts, though commonly regarded by the mind as continued independent qualities, appear not to have any existence in extension, and consequently cannot appear to the senses as situated externally to the body. The reason, why we ascribe a place to them, shall be: considered afterwards. Thirdly, Even our sight informs us not of distance or outness (so to speak) immediately and without a certain reasoning and experience, as is acknowledged by the most rational philosophers.
To start with the question about EXTERNAL existence, it could be said that, ignoring the metaphysical issue of the identity of a thinking substance, our own body clearly belongs to us. Since several impressions seem to be outside our body, we assume they are also outside ourselves. The paper I'm currently writing on is away from my hand. The table is beyond the paper. The walls of the room are beyond the table. And when I look toward the window, I see a large expanse of fields and buildings beyond my room. From all this, we can conclude that no other ability is needed besides the senses to convince us of the external existence of bodies. However, to challenge this conclusion, we only need to consider the following three points. First, technically, we aren’t perceiving our body when we look at our limbs and parts; we are actually perceiving certain impressions that come through the senses. Therefore, attributing real and physical existence to these impressions or their objects is a mental act as hard to explain as the one we are currently examining. Second, sounds, tastes, and smells, although usually perceived as ongoing independent qualities, don’t seem to exist in physical space and therefore can't be sensed as existing outside of the body. The reason we assign them a location will be considered later. Third, our sight doesn’t immediately inform us of distance or externality (so to speak) without some reasoning and experience, as acknowledged by the most rational philosophers.
As to the independency of our perceptions on ourselves, this can never be an object of the senses; but any opinion we form concerning it, must be derived from experience and observation: And we shall see afterwards, that our conclusions from experience are far from being favourable to the doctrine of the independency of our perceptions. Mean while we may observe that when we talk of real distinct existences, we have commonly more in our eye their independency than external situation in place, and think an object has a sufficient reality, when its Being is uninterrupted, and independent of the incessant revolutions, which we are conscious of in ourselves.
The independence of our perceptions about ourselves can never be something we sense directly; instead, any opinion we form on it must come from our experiences and observations. Later, we’ll see that our conclusions based on experience do not support the idea that our perceptions are independent. For now, we can note that when we discuss real and distinct existences, we often focus more on their independence than on their external location. We tend to believe that something has enough reality when its existence is constant and not affected by the constant changes we are aware of within ourselves.
Thus to resume what I have said concerning the senses; they give us no notion of continued existence, because they cannot operate beyond the extent, in which they really operate. They as little produce the opinion of a distinct existence, because they neither can offer it to the mind as represented, nor as original. To offer it as represented, they must present both an object and an image. To make it appear as original, they must convey a falshood; and this falshood must lie in the relations and situation: In order to which they must be able to compare the object with ourselves; and even in that case they do not, nor is it possible they should, deceive us. We may, therefore, conclude with certainty, that the opinion of a continued and of a distinct existence never arises from the senses.
To sum up what I've said about the senses: they don't provide us with a concept of lasting existence because they can't function beyond their actual range. They also don’t create the idea of a separate existence, since they can't present it to the mind either as a representation or as something original. To present it as a representation, they would need to show both an object and an image. To make it seem original, they would have to convey a falsehood, and that falsehood would depend on relationships and context. For that, they would have to compare the object with ourselves, and even then, they can't deceive us, nor is it possible for them to do so. Therefore, we can confidently conclude that the belief in a continuous and distinct existence never comes from the senses.
To confirm this we may observe, that there are three different kinds of impressions conveyed by the senses. The first are those of the figure, bulk, motion and solidity of bodies. The second those of colours, tastes, smells, sounds, heat and cold. The third are the pains and pleasures, that arise from the application of objects to our bodies, as by the cutting of our flesh with steel, and such like. Both philosophers and the vulgar suppose the first of these to have a distinct continued existence. The vulgar only regard the second as on the same footing. Both philosophers and the vulgar, again, esteem the third to be merely perceptions and consequently interrupted and dependent beings.
To confirm this, we can see that there are three different types of impressions that our senses convey. The first type includes the shapes, size, movement, and solidity of objects. The second type covers colors, tastes, smells, sounds, heat, and cold. The third type consists of the pains and pleasures we experience when objects interact with our bodies, like when our skin is cut by a blade, and similar occurrences. Both philosophers and regular people believe the first type has a distinct, continuous existence. Regular people usually consider the second type to be similar. However, both philosophers and regular people think that the third type is just perceptions, and therefore, transient and dependent entities.
Now it is evident, that, whatever may be our philosophical opinion, colours, Sounds, heat and cold, as far as appears to the senses, exist after the same manner with motion and solidity, and that the difference we make betwixt them in this respect, arises not from the mere perception. So strong the prejudice for the distinct continued existence Of the former qualities, that when the contrary opinion is advanced by modern philosophers, people imagine they can almost refute it from their feeling and experience, and that their very senses contradict this philosophy. It is also evident, that colours, sounds, &c. are originally on the same footing with the pain that arises from steel, and pleasure that proceeds from a fire; and that the difference betwixt them is founded neither on perception nor reason, but on the imagination. For as they are confest to be, both of them, nothing but perceptions arising from the particular configurations and motions of the parts of body, wherein possibly can their difference consist? Upon the whole, then, we may conclude, that as far as the senses are judges, all perceptions are the same in the manner of their existence.
Now it’s clear that, regardless of our philosophical views, colors, sounds, heat, and cold, as they appear to the senses, exist in the same way as motion and solidity. The distinction we make between them stems not from mere perception. The belief in the distinct, persistent existence of these qualities is so ingrained that when modern philosophers challenge it, people think they can easily counter it based on their feelings and experiences, believing their very senses contradict this philosophy. It’s also clear that colors, sounds, and so on, are fundamentally similar to the pain from a sharp object or the pleasure from warmth; the difference between them isn’t based on perception or reason, but on imagination. Since they are acknowledged to be nothing more than perceptions arising from the specific configurations and movements of physical parts, where then can their differences lie? Overall, we can conclude that as far as the senses judge, all perceptions exist in the same way.
We may also observe in this instance of sounds and colours, that we can attribute a distinct continued existence to objects without ever consulting REASON, or weighing our opinions by any philosophical principles. And indeed, whatever convincing arguments philosophers may fancy they can produce to establish the belief of objects independent of the mind, it is obvious these arguments are known but to very few, and that it is not by them, that children, peasants, and the greatest part of mankind are induced to attribute objects to some impressions, and deny them to others. Accordingly we find, that all the conclusions, which the vulgar form on this head, are directly contrary to those, which are confirmed by philosophy. For philosophy informs us, that every thing, which appears to the mind, is nothing but a perception, and is interrupted, and dependent on the mind: whereas the vulgar confound perceptions and objects, and attribute a distinct continued existence to the very things they feel or see. This sentiment, then, as it is entirely unreasonable, must proceed from some other faculty than the understanding. To which we may add, that as long as we take our perceptions and objects to be the same, we can never infer the existence of the one from that of the other, nor form any argument from the relation of cause and effect; which is the only one that earl assure us of matter of fact. Even after we distinguish our perceptions from our objects, it will appear presently, that we are still incapable of reasoning from the existence of one to that of the other: So that upon the whole our reason neither does, nor is it possible it ever should, upon any supposition, give us an assurance of the continued and distinct existence of body. That opinion must be entirely owing to the IMAGINATION: which must now be the subject of our enquiry.
We can see in this example of sounds and colors that we can believe in the ongoing existence of objects without ever using REASON or judging our thoughts by any philosophical standards. In fact, no matter how persuasive arguments philosophers think they can come up with to support the belief in objects existing independently of the mind, it’s clear these arguments are known only to a select few. It’s not these arguments that lead children, peasants, and most people to attribute objects to certain impressions and deny them to others. As a result, we find that all the conclusions that ordinary people draw on this matter are directly opposed to those confirmed by philosophy. Philosophy tells us that everything that appears to the mind is just a perception and is interrupted and dependent on the mind. In contrast, ordinary people confuse perceptions with objects and believe that the things they feel or see have a continuous existence. This idea, then, since it has no reasonable foundation, must come from a different part of the mind than understanding. Additionally, as long as we consider our perceptions and objects to be the same, we can never conclude the existence of one from the existence of the other or create any arguments based on the relationship of cause and effect, which is the only way that can assure us of factual matters. Even after we separate our perceptions from our objects, it will become clear that we are still unable to reason from the existence of one to that of the other. Thus, overall, our reasoning neither does nor can ever, under any circumstances, give us certainty about the continued and distinct existence of physical objects. That belief must entirely come from the IMAGINATION, which will now be the focus of our inquiry.
Since all impressions are internal and perishing existences, and appear as such, the notion of their distinct and continued existence must arise from a concurrence of some of their qualities with the qualities of the imagination, and since this notion does not extend to all of them, it must arise from certain qualities peculiar to some impressions. It will therefore be easy for us to discover these qualities by a comparison of the impressions, to which we attribute a distinct and continued existence, with those, which we regard as internal and perishing.
Since all impressions are internal and fleeting experiences, and seem that way, the idea of their separate and ongoing existence must come from how some of their qualities align with the qualities of our imagination. And since this idea doesn’t apply to all impressions, it must come from certain qualities unique to some of them. So, it should be easy for us to identify these qualities by comparing the impressions we consider to have distinct and ongoing existence with those we see as internal and fleeting.
We may observe, then, that it is neither upon account of the involuntariness of certain impressions, as is commonly supposed, nor of their superior force and violence, that we attribute to them a reality, and continued existence, which we refuse to others, that are voluntary or feeble. For it is evident our pains and pleasures, our passions and affections, which we never suppose to have any existence beyond our perception, operate with greater violence, and are equally involuntary, as the impressions of figure and extension, colour and sound, which we suppose to be permanent beings. The heat of a fire, when moderate, is supposed to exist in the fire; but the pain, which it causes upon a near approach, is not taken to have any being, except in the perception.
We can see that it's not because certain impressions are involuntary, as people often think, or because they are stronger and more intense, that we see them as real and lasting, while dismissing others that are voluntary or weaker. It's clear that our pains and pleasures, our emotions and feelings, which we never believe have any existence beyond our own perception, act with just as much intensity and are just as involuntary as the impressions of shape and size, color and sound, which we consider to be permanent entities. The warmth of a fire, when it's at a moderate level, is thought to exist in the fire itself; however, the pain it causes when we get too close is not considered to exist outside of our perception.
These vulgar opinions, then, being rejected, we must search for some other hypothesis, by which we may discover those peculiar qualities in our impressions, which makes us attribute to them a distinct and continued existence.
These crude opinions, then, being dismissed, we need to look for another explanation to uncover the unique qualities in our impressions that lead us to assign them a separate and ongoing existence.
After a little examination, we shall find, that all those objects, to which we attribute a continued existence, have a peculiar constancy, which distinguishes them from the impressions, whose existence depends upon our perception. Those mountains, and houses, and trees, which lie at present under my eye, have always appeared to me in the same order; and when I lose sight of them by shutting my eyes or turning my head, I soon after find them return upon me without the least alteration. My bed and table, my books and papers, present themselves in the same uniform manner, and change not upon account of any interruption in my seeing or perceivilng them. This is the case with all the impressions, whose objects are supposed to have an external existence; and is the case with no other impressions, whether gentle or violent, voluntary or involuntary.
After a little examination, we will find that all those things we believe have a lasting existence share a unique consistency that sets them apart from impressions that depend on our perception. The mountains, houses, and trees that I currently see always appear to me in the same way; when I close my eyes or turn my head, I quickly find them return to me without any change. My bed and table, my books and papers, show up in the same consistent manner and don’t change regardless of any interruption in my sight or perception. This applies to all the impressions whose objects are thought to have an external existence and does not apply to any other impressions, whether subtle or intense, voluntary or involuntary.
This constancy, however, is not so perfect as not to admit of very considerable exceptions. Bodies often change their position and qualities, and after a little absence or interruption may become hardly knowable. But here it is observable, that even in these changes they preserve a coherence, and have a regular dependence on each other; which is the foundation of a kind of reasoning from causation, and produces the opinion of their continued existence. When I return to my chamber after an hour's absence, I find not my fire in the same situation, in which I left it: But then I am accustomed in other instances to see a like alteration produced in a like time, whether I am present or absent, near or remote. This coherence, therefore, in their changes is one of the characteristics of external objects, as well as their constancy.
This consistency, however, isn’t so perfect that it doesn’t allow for significant exceptions. Objects often change their position and qualities, and after a brief absence or interruption, they can become almost unrecognizable. However, it’s worth noting that even in these changes, they maintain a connection and have a regular dependence on one another; this forms the basis of reasoning from causation and leads to the belief in their continued existence. When I return to my room after being gone for an hour, I don’t find my fire in the same state I left it in. But I’ve become accustomed to seeing similar changes occur in a similar timeframe, whether I’m present or absent, close by or far away. Therefore, this connection in their changes is a characteristic of external objects, just like their consistency.
Having found that the opinion of the continued existence of body depends on the COHERENCE, and CONSTANCY of certain impressions, I now proceed to examine after what manner these qualities give rise to so extraordinary an opinion. To begin with the coherence; we may observe, that though those internal impressions, which we regard as fleeting and perishing, have also a certain coherence or regularity in their appearances, yet it is of somewhat a different nature, from that which we discover in bodies. Our passions are found by experience to have a mutual connexion with and dependence on each other; but on no occasion is it necessary to suppose, that they have existed and operated, when they were not perceived, in order to preserve the same dependence and connexion, of which we have had experience. The case is not the same with relation to external objects. Those require a continued existence, or otherwise lose, in a great measure, the regularity of their operation. I am here seated in my chamber with my face to the fire; and all the objects, that strike my senses, are contained in a few yards around me. My memory, indeed, informs me of the existence of many objects; but then this information extends not beyond their past existence, nor do either my senses or memory give any testimony to the continuance of their being. When therefore I am thus seated, and revolve over these thoughts, I hear on a sudden a noise as of a door turning upon its hinges; and a little after see a porter, who advances towards me. This gives occasion to many new reflections and reasonings. First, I never have observed, that this noise could proceed from any thing but the motion of a door; and therefore conclude, that the present phænomenon is a contradiction to all past experience, unless the door, which I remember on the other side the chamber, be still in being. Again, I have always found, that a human body was possest of a quality, which I call gravity, and which hinders it from mounting in the air, as this porter must have done to arrive at my chamber, unless the stairs I remember be not annihilated by my absence. But this is not all. I receive a letter, which upon, opening it I perceive by the hand-writing and subscription to have come from a friend, who says he is two hundred leagues distant. It is evident I can never account for this phenomenon, conformable to my experience in other instances, without spreading out in my mind the whole sea and continent between us, and supposing the effects and continued existence of posts and ferries, according to my Memory and observation. To consider these phaenomena of the porter and letter in a certain light, they are contradictions to common experience, and may be regarded as objections to those maxims, which we form concerning the connexions of causes and effects. I am accustomed to hear such a sound, and see such an object in motion at the same time. I have not received in this particular instance both these perceptions. These observations are contrary, unless I suppose that the door still remains, and that it was opened without my perceiving it: And this supposition, which was at first entirely arbitrary and hypothetical, acquires a force and evidence by its being the only one, upon which I can reconcile these contradictions. There is scarce a moment of my life, wherein there is not a similar instance presented to me, and I have not occasion to suppose the continued existence of objects, in order to connect their past and present appearances, and give them such an union with each other, as I have found by experience to be suitable to their particular natures and circumstances. Here then I am naturally led to regard the world, as something real and durable, and as preserving its existence, even when it is no longer present to my perception.
Having found that the belief in the ongoing existence of objects relies on the COHERENCE and CONSTANCY of certain impressions, I will now examine how these qualities contribute to such an extraordinary belief. To start with coherence, we can notice that while those internal impressions we see as fleeting and temporary do have some coherence or regularity in their appearances, it's of a different kind than what we observe in physical objects. Our emotions are known to have a connection and dependency on each other, but we don't need to assume they existed and operated when they weren't perceived to maintain that connection we've experienced. This isn't the case for external objects. They need to exist continuously; otherwise, they largely lose their regularity of operation. Sitting in my room with my face toward the fire, all the objects that appeal to my senses are within a few yards of me. Although my memory tells me about the existence of many objects, this only extends to their past existence, and neither my senses nor memory provide any proof of their continued existence. So, while I'm seated and thinking about this, I suddenly hear a noise like a door turning on its hinges, and shortly after, I see a porter approaching me. This triggers many new thoughts and reflections. First, I've never noticed this sound coming from anything other than the motion of a door, so I conclude that this current event contradicts all past experience unless the door I remember on the other side of the room still exists. Additionally, I’ve always found that a human body has a quality I call gravity, which prevents it from floating in the air, as the porter would have had to do to reach my room unless the stairs I remember were destroyed by my absence. But that’s not all. I receive a letter that, when opened, I can tell by the handwriting and signature came from a friend who claims to be two hundred leagues away. It’s clear I can’t make sense of this situation in line with my experiences without imagining the entire sea and continent between us, assuming the continued existence of mail and ferries based on my memory and observation. If I consider the incidents of the porter and the letter in a certain way, they contradict common experience and can be viewed as challenges to the rules we form about the connections between causes and effects. I’m used to hearing such a sound and seeing such an object move at the same time. In this specific case, I haven’t received both perceptions. These observations contradict each other unless I assume that the door still exists and that it was opened without my noticing. This assumption, which started as entirely arbitrary and hypothetical, gains strength and validity because it's the only one that can reconcile these contradictions. There’s hardly a moment in my life when I don’t encounter a similar situation, and I often find myself needing to assume the continued existence of objects to relate their past and present appearances and connect them in a way I’ve found, through experience, to align with their specific natures and circumstances. Therefore, I’m naturally led to view the world as something real and lasting, maintaining its existence even when it is no longer present to my perception.
But though this conclusion from the coherence of appearances may seem to be of the same nature with our reasonings concerning causes and effects; as being derived from custom, and regulated by past experience; we shall find upon examination, that they are at the bottom considerably different from each other, and that this inference arises from the understanding, and from custom in an indirect and oblique manner. For it will readily be allowed, that since nothing is ever really present to the mind, besides its own perceptions, it is not only impossible, that any habit should ever be acquired otherwise than by the regular succession of these perceptions, but also that any habit should ever exceed that degree of regularity. Any degree, therefore, of regularity in our perceptions, can never be a foundation for us to infer a greater degree of regularity in some objects, which are not perceived; since this supposes a contradiction, viz. a habit acquired by what was never present to the mind. But it is evident, that whenever we infer the continued existence of the objects of sense from their coherence, and the frequency of their union, it is in order to bestow on the objects a greater regularity than what is observed in our mere perceptions. We remark a connexion betwixt two kinds of objects in their past appearance to the senses, but are not able to observe this connexion to be perfectly constant, since the turning about of our head or the shutting of our eyes is able to break it. What then do we suppose in this case, but that these objects still continue their usual connexion, notwithstanding their apparent interruption, and that the irregular appearances are joined by something, of which we are insensible? But as all reasoning concerning matters of fact arises only from custom, and custom can only be the effect of repeated perceptions, the extending of custom and reasoning beyond the perceptions can never be the direct and natural effect of the constant repetition and connexion, but must arise from the co-operation of some other principles.
But even though this conclusion based on the consistency of experiences might seem similar to our reasoning about causes and effects—since it comes from habit and is shaped by past experiences—upon closer inspection, we’ll find that they are quite different at their core, and that this inference comes from the understanding in a roundabout way. It's generally accepted that since nothing is ever truly present in our minds except for our own perceptions, it’s impossible for any habit to be formed other than through the regular sequence of these perceptions, and that no habit can go beyond that level of regularity. Therefore, any degree of regularity in our perceptions can’t serve as a basis for us to assume a greater level of regularity in some objects that we don’t perceive; this would imply a contradiction, namely, a habit formed from what was never present in the mind. However, it’s clear that whenever we assume the continued existence of sensory objects based on their coherence and the frequency of their connection, we are trying to attribute to those objects a greater regularity than what we observe in our own perceptions. We note a connection between two types of objects based on their past appearance to our senses, but we can’t observe this connection to be perfectly constant since simply turning our head or closing our eyes can disrupt it. So what do we suppose in this situation? We assume that these objects still maintain their usual connection, despite the apparent break, and that the irregular appearances are linked by something of which we are unaware. But since all reasoning about facts arises solely from habit, and habit can only be the result of repeated perceptions, extending habit and reasoning beyond what we perceive can never be a direct and natural outcome of constant repetition and connection; it must come from the interaction of other principles.
I have already observed,[2] in examining the foundation of mathematics, that the imagination, when set into any train of thinking, is apt to continue, even when its object fails it, and like a galley put in motion by the oars, carries on its course without any new impulse. This I have assigned for the reason, why, after considering several loose standards of equality, and correcting them by each other, we proceed to imagine so correct and exact a standard of that relation, as is not liable to the least error or variation. The same principle makes us easily entertain this opinion of the continued existence of body. Objects have a certain coherence even as they appear to our senses; but this coherence is much greater and more uniform, if we suppose the object.% to have a continued existence; and as the mind is once in the train of observing an uniformity among objects, it naturally continues, till it renders the uniformity as compleat as possible. The simple supposition of their continued existence suffices for this purpose, and gives us a notion of a much greater regularity among objects, than what they have when we look no farther than our senses.
I have already noticed, [2] in exploring the foundation of mathematics, that our imagination, once engaged in a particular line of thought, tends to keep going even when its subject no longer holds our attention. It's like a boat that keeps moving forward even without any new push. I believe this explains why, after thinking about various loose standards of equality and correcting them against one another, we start to picture an incredibly precise standard of that relationship, one that seems immune to error or variation. This same principle leads us to easily accept the idea of the continued existence of objects. Things appear to be connected, at least as far as our senses can tell; however, this connection feels much stronger and more consistent if we assume that the object continues to exist. Once our mind begins to notice a consistency among objects, it naturally keeps going until it makes that consistency as complete as possible. Just assuming their continued existence is enough to create this impression and gives us a sense of much greater regularity among objects than what we gather from our senses alone.
[2] Part II, Sect. 4.
But whatever force we may ascribe to this principle, I am afraid it is too weak to support alone so vast an edifice, as is that of the continued existence of all external bodies; and that we must join the constancy of their appearance to the coherence, in order to give a satisfactory account of that opinion. As the explication of this will lead me into a considerable compass of very profound reasoning; I think it proper, in order to avoid confusion, to give a short sketch or abridgment of my system, and afterwards draw out all its parts in their full compass. This inference from the constancy of our perceptions, like the precedent from their coherence, gives rise to the opinion of the continued existence of body, which is prior to that of its distinct existence, and produces that latter principle.
But no matter how much importance we place on this principle, I’m afraid it’s too weak to support on its own such a vast structure as the ongoing existence of all external things. We need to combine the consistency of their appearance with coherence to provide a satisfactory explanation for that belief. Since explaining this will take me through a lot of deep reasoning, I think it’s best, to avoid confusion, to first give a brief overview of my system and then elaborate on all its parts in detail. This conclusion about the consistency of our perceptions, similar to the earlier one about their coherence, leads to the belief in the ongoing existence of objects, which comes before the belief in their separate existence and forms the basis for that latter principle.
When we have been accustomed to observe a constancy in certain impressions, and have found, that the perception of the sun or ocean, for instance, returns upon us after an absence or annihilation with like parts and in a like order, as at its first appearance, we are not apt to regard these interrupted perceptions as different, (which they really are) but on the contrary consider them as individually the same, upon account of their resemblance. But as this interruption of their existence is contrary to their perfect identity, and makes us regard the first impression as annihilated, and the second as newly created, we find ourselves somewhat at a loss, and are involved in a kind of contradiction. In order to free ourselves from this difficulty, we disguise, as much as possible, the interruption, or rather remove it entirely, by supposing that these interrupted perceptions are connected by a real existence, of which we are insensible. This supposition, or idea of continued existence, acquires a force and vivacity from the memory of these broken impressions, and from that propensity, which they give us, to suppose them the same; and according to the precedent reasoning, the very essence of belief consists in the force and vivacity of the conception.
When we get used to noticing that certain experiences remain consistent, and we see that the perception of the sun or the ocean, for example, comes back to us after a break or absence in the same way and order as when we first experienced them, we tend not to see these interrupted perceptions as different (which they actually are). Instead, we view them as the same because of their similarity. However, this break in their existence contradicts their perfect identity, leading us to see the first impression as gone and the second as newly created, which puts us in a bit of a conundrum and creates a kind of contradiction. To resolve this difficulty, we try to downplay or completely eliminate the interruption by assuming that these interrupted perceptions are linked by a real existence that we aren't aware of. This assumption, or idea of continuous existence, gains strength and liveliness from the memory of these disrupted impressions and from our tendency to think of them as the same. According to the earlier reasoning, the true essence of belief lies in the strength and vividness of that idea.
In order to justify this system, there are four things requisite. First, To explain the PRINCIPIUM INDIVIDUATIONIS, or principle of identity. Secondly, Give a reason, why the resemblance of our broken and interrupted perceptions induces us to attribute an identity to them. Thirdly, Account for that propensity, which this illusion gives, to unite these broken appearances by a continued existence. Fourthly and lastly, Explain that force and vivacity of conception, which arises from the propensity.
To justify this system, four things are necessary. First, explain the PRINCIPIUM INDIVIDUATIONIS, or principle of identity. Second, provide a reason why the resemblance of our fragmented and interrupted perceptions leads us to attribute identity to them. Third, account for the tendency that this illusion creates to connect these fragmented appearances by a continuous existence. Lastly, explain the strength and vividness of conception that comes from this tendency.
First, As to the principle of individuation; we may observe, that the view of any one object is not sufficient to convey the idea of identity. For in that proposition, an object is the same with itself, if the idea expressed by the word, object, were no ways distinguished from that meant by itself; we really should mean nothing, nor would the proposition contain a predicate and a subject, which however are implyed in this affirmation. One single object conveys the idea of unity, not that of identity.
First, regarding the principle of individuation, we can note that seeing a single object isn’t enough to convey the idea of identity. In that statement, an object is the same as itself only if the idea conveyed by the term "object" is not different from what is meant by "itself." If that were the case, we wouldn't be saying anything meaningful, and the statement wouldn’t include a subject and a predicate, which are implied in this affirmation. A single object conveys the idea of unity, not of identity.
On the other hand, a multiplicity of objects can never convey this idea, however resembling they may be supposed. The mind always pronounces the one not to be the other, and considers them as forming two, three, or any determinate number of objects, whose existences are entirely distinct and independent.
On the other hand, a variety of objects can never communicate this idea, no matter how similar they might seem. The mind always recognizes that one is not the other and views them as separate objects, whether that’s two, three, or any specific number, with their existences being completely distinct and independent.
Since then both number and unity are incompatible with the relation of identity, it must lie in something that is neither of them. But to tell the truth, at first sight this seems utterly impossible. Betwixt unity and number there can be no medium; no more than betwixt existence and nonexistence. After one object is supposed to exist, we must either suppose another also to exist; in which case we have the idea of number: Or we must suppose it not to exist; in which case the first object remains at unity.
Since then, both quantity and oneness don’t mix with the relationship of being the same, so it has to be something that is neither. Honestly, at first glance, this seems completely impossible. There can be no middle ground between oneness and quantity, just like there’s none between existence and nonexistence. Once we assume that one thing exists, we either have to assume another also exists, which gives us the concept of quantity, or we must assume it doesn’t exist, which leaves the first thing as one.
To remove this difficulty, let us have recourse to the idea of time or duration. I have already observ’d,[3] that time, in a strict sense, implies succession, and that when we apply its idea to any unchangeable object, it is only by a fiction of the imagination, by which the unchangeable object is supposd to participate of the changes of the co-existent objects, and in particular of that of our perceptions. This fiction of the imagination almost universally takes place; and it is by means of it, that a single object, placd before us, and surveyd for any time without our discovering in it any interruption or variation, is able to give us a notion of identity. For when we consider any two points of this time, we may place them in different lights: We may either survey them at the very same instant; in which case they give us the idea of number, both by themselves and by the object; which must be multiplyd, in order to be conceivd at once, as existent in these two different points of time: Or on the other hand, we may trace the succession of time by a like succession of ideas, and conceiving first one moment, along with the object then existent, imagine afterwards a change in the time without any VARIATION or INTERRUPTION in the object; in which case it gives us the idea of unity. Here then is an idea, which is a medium betwixt unity and number; or more properly speaking, is either of them, according to the view, in which we take it: And this idea we call that of identity. We cannot, in any propriety of speech, say, that an object is the same with itself, unless we mean, that the object existent at one time is the same with itself existent at another. By this means we make a difference, betwixt the idea meant by the word, OBJECT, and that meant by ITSELF, without going the length of number, and at the same time without restraining ourselves to a strict and absolute unity.
To solve this issue, let’s refer to the concept of time or duration. I've already noted that time, in a strict sense, involves succession, and when we apply this idea to anything unchangeable, it's merely a fictional concept created by our imagination. This fiction allows the unchangeable object to be thought of as experiencing the changes of related objects, especially those changes in our perceptions. This imaginative fiction is almost universally accepted; it allows a single object placed in front of us, which we observe for some time without noticing any interruption or variation, to give us a sense of identity. When we look at any two points in this timeframe, we can view them in different ways: we can either consider them at the exact same moment, which gives us the idea of number, both individually and with the object, which must be multiplied in our minds to understand it as existing in these two different points in time. Or, alternatively, we can follow the succession of time through a similar succession of ideas, first imagining one moment along with the object that exists then, and then envisioning a change in time without any change or interruption in the object; in this case, it gives us the idea of unity. Here we have a concept that serves as a bridge between unity and number; or more accurately, it can be either, depending on the perspective we take. This concept is what we refer to as identity. We cannot accurately say that an object is the same as itself unless we mean that the object existing at one time is identical to itself existing at another time. This distinction allows us to differentiate between the idea represented by the word OBJECT and that represented by ITSELF, without extending to the concept of number, while also not limiting ourselves to a strict and absolute unity.
[3] Part II, Sect. 5.
Thus the principle of individuation is nothing but the INVARIABLENESS and UNINTERRUPTEDNESS of any object, thro a supposd variation of time, by which the mind can trace it in the different periods of its existence, without any break of the view, and without being obligd to form the idea of multiplicity or number.
Thus, the principle of individuation is simply the consistency and continuity of any object through a supposed variation of time, allowing the mind to track it across different periods of its existence without losing sight of it and without having to think in terms of multiplicity or numbers.
I now proceed to explain the SECOND part of my system, and shew why the constancy of our perceptions makes us ascribe to them a perfect numerical identity, tho there be very long intervals betwixt their appearance, and they have only one of the essential qualities of identity, VIZ, INVARIABLENESS. That I may avoid all ambiguity and confusion on this head, I shall observe, that I here account for the opinions and belief of the vulgar with regard to the existence of body; and therefore must entirely conform myself to their manner of thinking and of expressing themselves. Now we have already observ’d, that however philosophers may distinguish betwixt the objects and perceptions of the senses; which they suppose co-existent and resembling; yet this is a distinction, which is not comprehended by the generality of mankind, who as they perceive only one being, can never assent to the opinion of a double existence and representation. Those very sensations, which enter by the eye or ear, are with them the true objects, nor can they readily conceive that this pen or paper, which is immediately perceivd, represents another, which is different from, but resembling it. In order, therefore, to accommodate myself to their notions, I shall at first suppose; that there is only a single existence, which I shall call indifferently OBJECT or PERCEPTION, according as it shall seem best to suit my purpose, understanding by both of them what any common man means by a hat, or shoe, or stone, or any other impression, conveyd to him by his senses. I shall be sure to give warning, when I return to a more philosophical way of speaking and thinking.
I will now explain the SECOND part of my system and show why the consistency of our perceptions leads us to believe that they have a perfect numerical identity, even though there are long gaps between their appearances, and they only possess one of the essential qualities of identity, namely, INVARIABLENESS. To avoid any ambiguity and confusion regarding this matter, I will account for the beliefs and opinions of the general public regarding the existence of physical objects; therefore, I must fully align myself with their way of thinking and expressing themselves. We’ve already noted that although philosophers may distinguish between the objects and perceptions of the senses—believing they exist simultaneously and resemble each other—this distinction is not understood by most people, who perceive only one existence and cannot agree with the idea of a double existence and representation. The sensations that enter through the eye or ear are, for them, the true objects, and they find it hard to grasp that this pen or paper, which they directly perceive, represents something else that is different but resembles it. To align with their understanding, I will initially assume that there is only one existence, which I will refer to interchangeably as OBJECT or PERCEPTION, depending on what best suits my purpose, using both terms to mean what any average person understands by a hat, shoe, stone, or any other impression conveyed to them by their senses. I will make it clear when I switch back to a more philosophical way of speaking and thinking.
To enter, therefore, upon the question concerning the source of the error and deception with regard to identity, when we attribute it to our resembling perceptions, notwithstanding their interruption; I must here recal an observation, which I have already provd and explain’d.[4] Nothing is more apt to make us mistake one idea for another, than any relation betwixt them, which associates them together in the imagination, and makes it pass with facility from one to the other. Of all relations, that of resemblance is in this respect the most efficacious; and that because it not only causes an association of ideas, but also of dispositions, and makes us conceive the one idea by an act or operation of the mind, similar to that by which we conceive the other. This circumstance I have observ’d to be of great moment; and we may establish it for a general rule, that whatever ideas place the mind in the same disposition or in similar ones, are very apt to be confounded. The mind readily passes from one to the other, and perceives not the change without a strict attention, of which, generally speaking, it is wholly incapable.
To dive into the question of where the error and confusion about identity come from, especially when we link it to our similar perceptions despite their interruptions, I need to bring up something I’ve already proven and explained. Nothing makes us mistake one idea for another more than any relationship between them that connects them in our minds, allowing us to switch easily from one to the other. Among all types of relationships, resemblance is the most effective in this regard; it not only connects ideas but also how we feel about them, leading us to understand one idea through a mental process that's similar to how we grasp the other. I’ve noticed this is really important, and we can generalize that any ideas that put the mind in the same or similar state are likely to get mixed up. The mind smoothly transitions from one to the other and usually doesn’t notice the shift without focused attention, which, generally speaking, it’s often incapable of.
[4] Part II. Sect. 5.
In order to apply this general maxim, we must first examine the disposition of the mind in viewing any object which preserves a perfect identity, and then find some other object, that is confounded with it, by causing a similar disposition. When we fix our thought on any object, and suppose it to continue the same for some time; it is evident we suppose the change to lie only in the time, and never exert ourselves to produce any new image or idea of the object. The faculties of the mind repose themselves in a manner, and take no more exercise, than what is necessary to continue that idea, of which we were formerly possest, and which subsists without variation or interruption. The passage from one moment to another is scarce felt, and distinguishes not itself by a different perception or idea, which may require a different direction of the spirits, in order to its conception.
To use this general principle, we first need to look at how our mind interacts with any object that maintains a consistent identity, and then identify another object that blends with it by creating a similar mindset. When we focus our attention on an object and assume it remains the same for a period, it’s clear we believe the change only relates to time, and we don’t make an effort to form a new image or idea of the object. Our mind settles into a sort of rest and only engages as much as needed to keep that idea we previously held, which exists without change or interruption. The shift from one moment to the next is barely noticed and doesn’t stand out with a different perception or idea that would require a different mental focus to understand it.
Now what other objects, beside identical ones, are capable of placing the mind in the same disposition, when it considers them, and of causing the same uninterrupted passage of the imagination from one idea to another? This question is of the last importance. For if we can find any such objects, we may certainly conclude, from the foregoing principle, that they are very naturally confounded with identical ones, and are taken for them in most of our reasonings. But though this question be very important, it is not very difficult nor doubtful. For I immediately reply, that a succession of related objects places the mind in this disposition, and is considered with the same smooth and uninterrupted progress of the imagination, as attends the view of the same invariable object. The very nature and essence of relation is to connect our ideas with each other, and upon the appearance of one, to facilitate the transition to its correlative. The passage betwixt related ideas is, therefore, so smooth and easy, that it produces little alteration on the mind, and seems like the continuation of the same action; and as the continuation of the same action is an effect of the continued view of the same object, it is for this reason we attribute sameness to every succession of related objects. The thought slides along the succession with equal facility, as if it considered only one object; and therefore confounds the succession with the identity.
What other objects, besides identical ones, can put the mind in the same frame when we think about them and allow our imagination to flow smoothly from one idea to another? This question is really important. If we can identify any such objects, we can definitely conclude, based on the previous principle, that they are often mixed up with identical ones and mistaken for them in most of our reasoning. However, even though this question is significant, it’s not too difficult or uncertain. I can quickly answer that a series of related objects puts the mind in that same state and is considered with the same smooth and seamless flow of imagination as when we look at the same unchanging object. The very nature of relations is to connect our ideas, making it easier to transition from one to its counterpart when one appears. The shift between related ideas is so smooth and effortless that it barely changes the mind and feels like a continuation of the same process; since this continuation is an effect of viewing the same object repeatedly, we tend to see every series of related objects as the same. The thought moves through the series just as easily as if it were focused on a single object; thus, we confuse the series with identity.
We shall afterwards see many instances of this tendency of relation to make us ascribe an identity to different objects; but shall here confine ourselves to the present subject. We find by experience, that there is such a constancy in almost all the impressions of the senses, that their interruption produces no alteration on them, and hinders them not from returning the same in appearance and in situation as at their first existence. I survey the furniture of my chamber; I shut my eyes, and afterwards open them; and find the new perceptions to resemble perfectly those, which formerly struck my senses. This resemblance is observed in a thousand instances, and naturally connects together our ideas of these interrupted perceptions by the strongest relation, and conveys the mind with an easy transition from one to another. An easy transition or passage of the imagination, along the ideas of these different and interrupted perceptions, is almost the same disposition of mind with that in which we consider one constant and uninterrupted perception. It is therefore very natural for us to mistake the one for the other.[5]
We will later explore many examples of this tendency to relate things that lead us to see different objects as the same; for now, let's focus on the current topic. We notice from experience that there is such a consistency in nearly all sensory impressions that interruptions don’t change them, and they return just as they were in appearance and position as when they first occurred. I look around my room; I close my eyes, and then open them again, only to find that the new perceptions closely match those that initially captured my attention. This similarity appears in countless situations and naturally links our ideas of these interrupted perceptions with a strong connection, allowing the mind to move smoothly from one to another. This smooth transition or flow of imagination among the ideas of these different and interrupted perceptions is almost the same mental state as when we consider a single, constant perception. It’s therefore quite natural for us to confuse one for the other.[5]
[5] This reasoning, it must be confest, is somewhat abstruse, and difficult to be comprehended; but it is remarkable, that this very difficulty may be converted into a proof of the reasoning. We may observe, that there are two relations, and both of them resemblances, which contribute to our mistaking the succession of our interrupted perceptions for an identical object. The first is, the resemblance of the perceptions: The second is the resemblance, which the act of the mind in surveying a succession of resembling objects bears to that in surveying an identical object. Now these resemblances we are apt to confound with each other; and it is natural we shoud, according to this very reasoning. But let us keep them distinct, and we shall find no difficulty in conceiving the precedent argument.
[5] This reasoning, I must admit, is a bit complex and hard to understand; however, it’s interesting that this very difficulty can actually serve as proof of the reasoning itself. We can notice that there are two types of relationships, both similarities, that lead us to confuse the flow of our interrupted perceptions for a single, identical object. The first is the similarity of the perceptions themselves. The second is the similarity in the way our minds process a series of similar objects compared to how we process a single identical object. We tend to mix up these similarities, which is entirely understandable given this reasoning. But if we keep them separate, we won't have any trouble grasping the previous argument.
The persons, who entertain this opinion concerning the identity of our resembling perceptions, are in general an the unthinking and unphilosophical part of mankind, (that is, all of us, at one time or other) and consequently such as suppose their perceptions to be their only objects, and never think of a double existence internal and external, representing and represented. The very image, which is present to the senses, is with us the real body; and it is to these interrupted images we ascribe a perfect identity. But as the interruption of the appearance seems contrary to the identity, and naturally leads us to regard these resembling perceptions as different from each other, we here find ourselves at a loss how to reconcile such opposite opinions. The smooth passage of the imagination along the ideas of the resembling perceptions makes us ascribe to them a perfect identity. The interrupted manner of their appearance makes us consider them as so many resembling, but still distinct beings, which appear after certain intervals. The perplexity arising from this contradiction produces a propension to unite these broken appearances by the fiction of a continued existence, which is the third part of that hypothesis I proposed to explain.
The people who hold this opinion about the similarity of our perceptions are generally the unthinking and unphilosophical part of humanity—meaning everyone at some point. They assume their perceptions are their only reality and never consider that there are two existences, one internal and one external, representing and represented. The image we see with our senses feels like the real thing to us, and we attribute perfect identity to these fragmented images. However, since the interruptions in their appearance seem to contradict their identity, it leads us to view these similar perceptions as different from one another. This leaves us confused about how to reconcile these opposing views. The smooth flow of our imagination connecting the ideas of similar perceptions makes us attribute perfect identity to them. Yet, their interrupted appearances make us think of them as many similar but still distinct beings that emerge at various intervals. The confusion arising from this contradiction creates a tendency to combine these broken appearances with the idea of a continuous existence, which is the third part of the hypothesis I proposed to explain.
Nothing is more certain from experience, than that any contradiction either to the sentiments or passions gives a sensible uneasiness, whether it proceeds from without or from within; from the opposition of external objects, or from the combat of internal principles. On the contrary, whatever strikes in with the natural propensities, and either externally forwards their satisfaction, or internally concurs with their movements, is sure to give a sensible pleasure. Now there being here an opposition betwixt the notion of the identity of resembling perceptions, and the interruption of their appearance, the mind must be uneasy in that situation, and will naturally seek relief from the uneasiness. Since the uneasiness arises from the opposition of two contrary principles, it must look for relief by sacrificing the one to the other. But as the smooth passage of our thought along our resembling perceptions makes us ascribe to them an identity, we can never without reluctance yield up that opinion. We must, therefore, turn to the other side, and suppose that our perceptions are no longer interrupted, but preserve a continued as well as an invariable existence, and are by that means entirely the same. But here the interruptions in the appearance of these perceptions are so long and frequent, that it is impossible to overlook them; and as the appearance of a perception in the mind and its existence seem at first sight entirely the same, it may be doubted, whether we can ever assent to so palpable a contradiction, and suppose a perception to exist without being present to the mind. In order to clear up this matter, and learn how the interruption in the appearance of a perception implies not necessarily an interruption in its existence, it will be proper to touch upon some principles, which we shall have occasion to explain more fully afterwards.[6]
Nothing is more certain from experience than that any contradiction to our feelings or emotions creates noticeable discomfort, whether it comes from outside influences or from internal conflicts. Conversely, anything that aligns with our natural tendencies, and either facilitates their satisfaction externally or supports their movements internally, is guaranteed to cause noticeable pleasure. Given the opposition between the idea of the identity of similar perceptions and the disruption of their appearance, the mind must feel uneasy in that situation and will instinctively seek relief from that discomfort. Since the discomfort arises from the clash of two opposing principles, it will look for relief by prioritizing one over the other. However, because the smooth flow of our thoughts along similar perceptions leads us to attribute an identity to them, we are always reluctant to abandon that belief. Therefore, we must consider an alternative perspective and assume that our perceptions are no longer interrupted, but instead maintain a continuous and unchanging existence, thus being entirely the same. Yet, the interruptions in the appearance of these perceptions are so frequent and lengthy that they cannot be ignored; and since the appearance of a perception in the mind and its existence initially seem entirely identical, one might question whether we can ever accept such an obvious contradiction and believe that a perception can exist without being present in the mind. To clarify this issue and understand how the disruption in the appearance of a perception does not necessarily mean an interruption in its existence, it will be useful to touch on some principles that we will elaborate on more fully later. [6]
[6] Sect. 6.
We may begin with observing, that the difficulty in the present case is not concerning the matter of fact, or whether the mind forms such a conclusion concerning the continued existence of its perceptions, but only concerning the manner in which the conclusion is formed, and principles from which it is derived. It is certain, that almost all mankind, and even philosophers themselves, for the greatest part of their lives, take their perceptions to be their only objects, and suppose, that the very being, which is intimately present to the mind, is the real body or material existence. It is also certain, that this very perception or object is supposed to have a continued uninterrupted being, and neither to be annihilated by our absence, nor to be brought into existence by our presence. When we are absent from it, we say it still exists, but that we do not feel, we do not see it. When we are present, we say we feel, or see it. Here then may arise two questions; First, How we can satisfy ourselves in supposing a perception to be absent from the mind without being annihilated. Secondly, After what manner we conceive an object to become present to the mind, without some new creation of a perception or image; and what we mean by this seeing, and feeling, and perceiving.
We can start by noting that the issue at hand isn’t about the facts or whether the mind concludes that its perceptions continue to exist, but rather about how that conclusion is formed and the principles behind it. It’s clear that almost everyone, including philosophers, for most of their lives, consider their perceptions as their only reality and believe that what is immediately present in the mind is the actual body or material existence. It’s also clear that this perception or object is thought to have an ongoing, uninterrupted existence, and is neither destroyed by our absence nor created by our presence. When we are not experiencing it, we say it still exists, but we just don’t feel or see it. When we are experiencing it, we say we feel or see it. This leads to two questions: First, how can we convince ourselves that a perception can be absent from the mind without being destroyed? Second, how do we understand that an object can become present to the mind without creating a new perception or image? And what do we really mean by feeling, seeing, and perceiving?
As to the first question; we may observe, that what we call a mind, is nothing but a heap or collection of different perceptions, united together by certain relations, and supposed, though falsely, to be endowed with a perfect simplicity and identity. Now as every perception is distinguishable from another, and may be considered as separately existent; it evidently follows, that there is no absurdity in separating any particular perception from the mind; that is, in breaking off all its relations, with that connected mass of perceptions, which constitute a thinking being.
Regarding the first question, we can notice that what we refer to as a mind is really just a mix or collection of different perceptions linked together by certain relationships, and it is mistakenly thought to have perfect simplicity and identity. Since every perception is distinct from another and can be seen as existing independently, it clearly follows that there is no contradiction in separating any specific perception from the mind; that is, in disconnecting it from the network of perceptions that make up a thinking entity.
The same reasoning affords us an answer to the second question. If the name of perception renders not this separation from a mind absurd and contradictory, the name of object, standing for the very same thing, can never render their conjunction impossible. External objects are seen, and felt, and become present to the mind; that is, they acquire such a relation to a connected heap of perceptions, as to influence them very considerably in augmenting their number by present reflections and passions, and in storing the memory with ideas. The same continued and uninterrupted Being may, therefore, be sometimes present to the mind, and sometimes absent from it, without any real or essential change in the Being itself. An interrupted appearance to the senses implies not necessarily an interruption in the existence. The supposition of the continued existence of sensible objects or perceptions involves no contradiction. We may easily indulge our inclination to that supposition. When the exact resemblance of our perceptions makes us ascribe to them an identity, we may remove the seeming interruption by feigning a continued being, which may fill those intervals, and preserve a perfect and entire identity to our perceptions.
The same reasoning gives us an answer to the second question. If the term perception doesn’t make the separation from a mind seem absurd or contradictory, then the term object, which refers to the same thing, can never make their combination impossible. External objects are seen and felt, and they become present to the mind; this means they develop a connection to a collection of perceptions, significantly influencing them by increasing their number through immediate thoughts and emotions, and by filling our memory with ideas. The same continuous being can, therefore, sometimes be present to the mind and sometimes absent from it, without any real or essential change in that being itself. An interrupted appearance to the senses doesn’t necessarily mean there’s an interruption in existence. Assuming that sensible objects or perceptions continue to exist doesn’t involve any contradiction. We can easily allow ourselves to entertain that assumption. When the exact similarity of our perceptions leads us to attribute identity to them, we can eliminate the apparent interruption by imagining a continuous being that fills those gaps, maintaining a perfect and complete identity for our perceptions.
But as we here not only feign but believe this continued existence, the question is, from whence arises such a belief; and this question leads us to the fourth member of this system. It has been proved already, that belief in general consists in nothing, but the vivacity of an idea; and that an idea may acquire this vivacity by its relation to some present impression. Impressions are naturally the most vivid perceptions of the mind; and this quality is in part conveyed by the relation to every connected idea. The relation causes a smooth passage from the impression to the idea, and even gives a propensity to that passage. The mind falls so easily from the one perception to the other, that it scarce perceives the change, but retains in the second a considerable share of the vivacity of the first. It is excited by the lively impression; and this vivacity is conveyed to the related idea, without any great diminution in the passage, by reason of the smooth transition and the propensity of the imagination.
But as we not only pretend but truly believe in this ongoing existence, the question arises: where does such a belief come from? This question leads us to the fourth part of this system. It has already been established that belief, in general, is nothing more than the intensity of an idea, and that an idea can gain this intensity through its connection to some current impression. Impressions are naturally the most vivid perceptions of the mind; and this quality is partly conveyed through its connection to every related idea. This connection allows for a smooth transition from the impression to the idea and even encourages that transition. The mind moves so easily from one perception to the other that it barely notices the change and retains a significant amount of the intensity of the first in the second. It is stimulated by the vivid impression, and this intensity transfers to the related idea without much loss in the transition, thanks to the smooth flow and the tendency of the imagination.
But suppose, that this propensity arises from some other principle, besides that of relation; it is evident it must still have the same effect, and convey the vivacity from the impression to the idea. Now this is exactly the present case. Our memory presents us with a vast number of instances of perceptions perfectly resembling each other, that return at different distances of time, and after considerable interruptions. This resemblance gives us a propension to consider these interrupted perceptions as the same; and also a propension to connect them by a continued existence, in order to justify this identity, and avoid the contradiction, in which the interrupted appearance of these perceptions seems necessarily to involve us. Here then we have a propensity to feign the continued existence of all sensible objects; and as this propensity arises from some lively impressions of the memory, it bestows a vivacity on that fiction: or in other words, makes us believe the continued existence of body. If sometimes we ascribe a continued existence to objects, which are perfectly new to us, and of whose constancy and coherence we have no experience, it is because the manner, in which they present themselves to our senses, resembles that of constant and coherent objects; and this resemblance is a source of reasoning and analogy, and leads us to attribute the same qualities to similar objects.
But let's say that this tendency comes from some other principle, aside from the idea of relation; it’s clear it must still have the same impact, transferring the liveliness from the impression to the idea. This is exactly the situation we’re in now. Our memory shows us a huge number of instances of perceptions that are almost identical, appearing at different times and after significant gaps. This similarity makes us inclined to view these interrupted perceptions as the same; and it also makes us want to connect them through a continuous existence to justify this identity and avoid the contradiction that the interrupted nature of these perceptions seems to create. So, we have a tendency to pretend that all physical objects continue to exist; and since this tendency stems from vivid memories, it adds liveliness to that idea: in other words, it makes us believe in the ongoing existence of physical things. If we sometimes attribute ongoing existence to objects that are completely new to us, and where we have no experience of their consistency and coherence, it's because the way they come to our senses is similar to consistent and coherent objects; this similarity fuels our reasoning and analogy, leading us to assign the same qualities to similar objects.
I believe an intelligent reader will find less difficulty to assent to this system, than to comprehend it fully and distinctly, and will allow, after a little reflection, that every part carries its own proof along with it. It is indeed evident, that as the vulgar suppose their perceptions to be their only objects, and at the same time believe the continued existence of matter, we must account for the origin of the belief upon that supposition. Now upon that supposition, it is a false opinion that any of our objects, or perceptions, are identically the same after an interruption; and consequently the opinion of their identity can never arise from reason, but must arise from the imagination. The imagination is seduced into such an opinion only by means of the resemblance of certain perceptions; since we find they are only our resembling perceptions, which we have a propension to suppose the same. This propension to bestow an identity on our resembling perceptions, produces the fiction of a continued existence; since that fiction, as well as the identity, is really false, as is acknowledged by all philosophers, and has no other effect than to remedy the interruption of our perceptions, which is the only circumstance that is contrary to their identity. In the last place this propension causes belief by means of the present impressions of the memory; since without the remembrance of former sensations, it is plain we never should have any belief of the continued existence of body. Thus in examining all these parts, we find that each of them is supported by the strongest proofs: and that all of them together form a consistent system, which is perfectly convincing. A strong propensity or inclination alone, without any present impression, will sometimes cause a belief or opinion. How much more when aided by that circumstance?
I believe a smart reader will find it easier to agree with this system than to fully and clearly understand it, and will recognize, after some thought, that each part carries its own proof. It’s clear that, while most people think their perceptions are their only objects and at the same time believe in the ongoing existence of matter, we need to explain how that belief originates based on that assumption. Now, according to that assumption, it is incorrect to say that any of our objects or perceptions are exactly the same after a break; therefore, the belief in their identity cannot arise from reason, but must come from imagination. The imagination is led to this belief only through the similarity of certain perceptions; since we find that it’s only our similar perceptions that we tend to think are the same. This tendency to assign identity to our similar perceptions creates the idea of continued existence; however, that idea, like the identity itself, is really false, as all philosophers agree, and serves only to resolve the interruption of our perceptions, which is the only factor that contradicts their identity. Lastly, this tendency creates belief through the present impressions of memory; since without remembering past sensations, it’s clear we would never have any belief in the ongoing existence of bodies. Therefore, when we examine all these parts, we see that each one is supported by strong evidence, and together they create a consistent system that is entirely convincing. A strong inclination alone, without any current impression, can sometimes lead to a belief or opinion. How much more effective is it when supported by that factor?
But though we are led after this manner, by the natural propensity of the imagination, to ascribe a continued existence to those sensible objects or perceptions, which we find to resemble each other in their interrupted appearance; yet a very little reflection and philosophy is sufficient to make us perceive the fallacy of that opinion. I have already observed, that there is an intimate connexion betwixt those two principles, of a continued and of a distinct or independent existence, and that we no sooner establish the one than the other follows, as a necessary consequence. It is the opinion of a continued existence, which first takes place, and without much study or reflection draws the other along with it, wherever the mind follows its first and most natural tendency. But when we compare experiments, and reason a little upon them, we quickly perceive, that the doctrine of the independent existence of our sensible perceptions is contrary to the plainest experience. This leads us backward upon our footsteps to perceive our error in attributing a continued existence to our perceptions, and is the origin of many very curious opinions, which we shall here endeavour to account for.
Although we tend to believe that the things we perceive continue to exist because they resemble each other in their brief appearances, a little thought and reflection can help us see the error in that belief. I've already pointed out that there's a close connection between the ideas of continued existence and distinct or independent existence. Once we accept one, the other naturally follows. Initially, it's the belief in continued existence that arises first, drawing the other concept along with it as our minds gravitate towards its most instinctive inclination. However, when we compare different experiences and think critically about them, we quickly realize that believing in the independent existence of our perceptions contradicts our simplest experiences. This realization causes us to retrace our steps and recognize our mistake in assigning continued existence to our perceptions, paving the way for many intriguing ideas that we will attempt to explain here.
It will first be proper to observe a few of those experiments, which convince us, that our perceptions are not possest of any independent existence. When we press one eye with a finger, we immediately perceive all the objects to become double, and one half of them to be removed from their common and natural position. But as we do not attribute to continued existence to both these perceptions, and as they are both of the same nature, we clearly perceive, that all our perceptions are dependent on our organs, and the disposition of our nerves and animal spirits. This opinion is confirmed by the seeming encrease and diminution of objects, according to their distance; by the apparent alterations in their figure; by the changes in their colour and other qualities from our sickness and distempers: and by an infinite number of other experiments of the same kind; from all which we learn, that our sensible perceptions are not possest of any distinct or independent existence.
First, it's important to note a few experiments that show us our perceptions don’t exist independently. When we press one eye with a finger, we immediately notice that all objects appear doubled, and one half seems to shift from their usual position. However, we don’t consider both perceptions to be continuously real, and since they share the same nature, it’s clear that all our perceptions depend on our senses, the structure of our nerves, and our mental state. This idea is backed up by the apparent increase and decrease of objects depending on how far away they are, the changes in their shape, as well as shifts in their color and other traits due to illness or disturbances we experience. Countless other experiments support the same idea; from all this, we understand that our sensory perceptions don't have a separate or independent existence.
The natural consequence of this reasoning should be, that our perceptions have no more a continued than an independent existence; and indeed philosophers have so far run into this opinion, that they change their system, and distinguish, (as we shall do for the future) betwixt perceptions and objects, of which the former are supposed to be interrupted, and perishing, and different at every different return; the latter to be uninterrupted, and to preserve a continued existence and identity. But however philosophical this new system may be esteemed, I assert that it is only a palliative remedy, and that it contains all the difficulties of the vulgar system, with some others, that are peculiar to itself. There are no principles either of the understanding or fancy, which lead us directly to embrace this opinion of the double existence of perceptions and objects, nor can we arrive at it but by passing through the common hypothesis of the identity and continuance of our interrupted perceptions. Were we not first perswaded, that our perceptions are our only objects, and continue to exist even when they no longer make their appearance to the senses, we should never be led to think, that our perceptions and objects are different, and that our objects alone preserve a continued existence. The latter hypothesis has no primary recommendation either to reason or the imagination, but acquires all its influence on the imagination from the former. This proposition contains two parts, which we shall endeavour to prove as distinctly and clearly, as such abstruse subjects will permit.
The natural result of this reasoning should be that our perceptions have neither a continuous nor an independent existence; and in fact, philosophers have adopted this view to the extent that they modify their systems and differentiate (as we will do from now on) between perceptions and objects, with the former being seen as disrupted, fleeting, and varying with each return, while the latter is regarded as uninterrupted, having a continuous existence and identity. However philosophical this new perspective may be considered, I argue that it is merely a temporary fix and carries the same problems as the common view, along with some additional ones unique to itself. There are no principles of understanding or imagination that directly lead us to accept the idea of the dual existence of perceptions and objects; we can only reach it by first believing that our perceptions are our only objects and continue to exist even when they are not present to our senses. Without that belief, we would never think that our perceptions and objects are different, and that only our objects maintain a continuous existence. The latter idea doesn’t have any intrinsic appeal to reason or imagination but gains its influence on imagination from the former. This statement has two parts, which we will try to prove as clearly and distinctly as such complex topics will allow.
As to the first part of the proposition, that this philosophical hypothesis has no primary recommendation, either to reason, or the imagination, we may soon satisfy ourselves with regard to reason by the following reflections. The only existences, of which we are certain, are perceptions, which being immediately present to us by consciousness, command our strongest assent, and are the first foundation of all our conclusions. The only conclusion we can draw from the existence of one thing to that of another, is by means of the relation of cause and effect, which shews, that there is a connexion betwixt them, and that the existence of one is dependent on that of the other. The idea of this relation is derived from past experience, by which we find, that two beings are constantly conjoined together, and are always present at once to the mind. But as no beings are ever present to the mind but perceptions; it follows that we may observe a conjunction or a relation of cause and effect between different perceptions, but can never observe it between perceptions and objects. It is impossible, therefore, that from the existence or any of the qualities of the former, we can ever form any conclusion concerning the existence of the latter, or ever satisfy our reason in this particular.
Regarding the first part of the argument, that this philosophical idea has no primary appeal to either reason or imagination, we can quickly clarify our thoughts on reason through the following reflections. The only things we can be sure of are our perceptions, which are immediately accessible to us through consciousness and command our strongest agreement, serving as the foundation for all our conclusions. The only inference we can draw from one thing's existence to another is based on the relationship of cause and effect, which shows that there is a connection between them, meaning that one’s existence depends on the other. Our understanding of this relationship comes from past experiences, where we observe that two beings are consistently linked together and are always present in our minds at the same time. However, since the only things present in our minds are perceptions, it follows that we can notice a connection or a cause-and-effect relationship between different perceptions but can never find it between perceptions and objects. Therefore, it’s impossible for us to form any conclusions about the existence or qualities of the latter based on the former, nor can we satisfy our reason in this regard.
It is no less certain, that this philosophical system has no primary recommendation to the imagination, and that that faculty would never, of itself, and by its original tendency, have fallen upon such a principle. I confess it will be somewhat difficult to prove this to the fall satisfaction of the reader; because it implies a negative, which in many cases will not admit of any positive proof. If any one would take the pains to examine this question, and would invent a system, to account for the direct origin of this opinion from the imagination, we should be able, by the examination of that system, to pronounce a certain judgment in the present subject. Let it be taken for granted, that our perceptions are broken, and interrupted, and however like, are still different from each other; and let any one upon this supposition shew why the fancy, directly and immediately, proceeds to the belief of another existence, resembling these perceptions in their nature, but yet continued, and uninterrupted, and identical; and after he has done this to my satisfaction, I promise to renounce my present opinion. Mean while I cannot forbear concluding, from the very abstractedness and difficulty of the first supposition, that it is an improper subject for the fancy to work upon. Whoever would explain the origin of the common opinion concerning the continued and distinct existence of body, must take the mind in its common situation, and must proceed upon the supposition, that our perceptions are our only objects, and continue to exist even when they are not perceived. Though this opinion be false, it is the most natural of any, and has alone any primary recommendation to the fancy.
It's clear that this philosophical system doesn't have a strong appeal to the imagination, and that this mental ability wouldn't naturally arrive at such a principle on its own. I admit it will be somewhat challenging to convincingly demonstrate this to the reader because it involves a negative claim, which often lacks positive proof. If someone were to take the effort to investigate this issue and create a system to explain the direct origin of this belief coming from imagination, we would then be able to make a definitive judgment on the topic. Let's assume our perceptions are fragmented and interrupted, and though they may seem alike, they are still different from one another; if someone can show why the imagination would jump to the belief in another existence that resembles these perceptions in nature but is continuous, uninterrupted, and identical, and they do this to my satisfaction, I promise to change my mind. In the meantime, I can't help but conclude, based on the complexity and difficulty of the initial assumption, that it's not a suitable topic for the imagination to explore. Anyone trying to explain the common belief in the continued and distinct existence of bodies must consider the mind in its usual state and operate on the assumption that our perceptions are our only objects and continue to exist even when they aren't perceived. Although this belief is false, it is the most natural one and offers the strongest appeal to the imagination.
As to the second part of the proposition, that the philosophical system acquires all its influence on the imagination from the vulgar one; we may observe, that this is a natural and unavoidable consequence of the foregoing conclusion, that it has no primary recommendation to reason or the imagination. For as the philosophical system is found by experience to take hold of many minds, and in particular of all those, who reflect ever so little on this subject, it must derive all its authority from the vulgar system; since it has no original authority of its own. The manner, in which these two systems, though directly contrary, are connected together, may be explains, as follows.
Regarding the second part of the argument, which states that the philosophical system gets all its influence on the imagination from the common one; we can see that this is a natural and unavoidable result of the earlier conclusion that it lacks any primary appeal to reason or the imagination. Since the philosophical system is known to capture the interest of many people, especially those who think even a little about the topic, it must get all its authority from the common system because it has no original authority of its own. The way these two systems, despite being directly opposed, are connected can be explained as follows.
The imagination naturally runs on in this train of thinking. Our perceptions are our only objects: Resembling perceptions are the same, however broken or uninterrupted in their appearance: This appealing interruption is contrary to the identity: The interruption consequently extends not beyond the appearance, and the perception or object really continues to exist, even when absent from us: Our sensible perceptions have, therefore, a continued and uninterrupted existence. But as a little reflection destroys this conclusion, that our perceptions have a continued existence, by shewing that they have a dependent one, it would naturally be expected, that we must altogether reject the opinion, that there is such a thing in nature as a continued existence, which is preserved even when it no longer appears to the senses. The case, however, is otherwise. Philosophers are so far from rejecting the opinion of a continued existence upon rejecting that of the independence and continuance of our sensible perceptions, that though all sects agree in the latter sentiment, the former, which is, in a manner, its necessary consequence, has been peculiar to a few extravagant sceptics; who after all maintained that opinion in words only, and were never able to bring themselves sincerely to believe it.
The imagination naturally continues along this line of thinking. Our perceptions are our only focus: similar perceptions are the same, whether they seem broken or continuous: This appealing interruption contradicts identity: Therefore, the interruption doesn't go beyond what appears, and the perception or object still really exists, even when it's not in front of us: Our sensory perceptions thus have a continuous and uninterrupted existence. However, a little reflection contradicts this conclusion that our perceptions have a continuous existence by showing that they depend on something else, leading us to expect that we should entirely dismiss the idea that there is such a thing in nature as continuous existence that can be maintained even when it no longer appears to our senses. The reality is different, though. Philosophers aren’t rejecting the idea of continuous existence simply because they reject the independence and continuity of our sensory perceptions; instead, while all schools of thought agree on the latter view, the former, which is almost a necessary consequence, has been uniquely held by a few extreme skeptics, who ultimately only maintained that view in words and never truly believed it.
There is a great difference betwixt such opinions as we form after a calm and profound reflection, and such as we embrace by a kind of instinct or natural impulse, on account of their suitableness and conformity to the mind. If these opinions become contrary, it is not difficult to foresee which of them will have the advantage. As long as our attention is bent upon the subject, the philosophical and studyed principle may prevail; but the moment we relax our thoughts, nature will display herself, and draw us back to our former opinion. Nay she has sometimes such an influence, that she can stop our progress, even in the midst of our most profound reflections, and keep us from running on with all the consequences of any philosophical opinion. Thus though we clearly perceive the dependence and interruption of our perceptions, we stop short in our career, and never upon that account reject the notion of an independent and continued existence. That opinion has taken such deep root in the imagination, that it is impossible ever to eradicate it, nor will any strained metaphysical conviction of the dependence of our perceptions be sufficient for that purpose.
There's a big difference between the opinions we form after careful thought and those we accept instinctively or naturally because they fit with our mindset. When these opinions clash, it's not hard to predict which one will win out. As long as we're focused on the topic, the well-thought-out principle might dominate; but the moment we let our minds wander, our natural inclinations take over and pull us back to what we initially believed. In fact, sometimes our instincts are so powerful that they can halt our progress, even when we're in the middle of deep thinking, preventing us from pursuing all the implications of a philosophical viewpoint. So even though we recognize how our perceptions depend on and interrupt each other, we still hesitate to move forward, never truly rejecting the idea of an independent and continuous existence. That belief is so ingrained in our imagination that it's impossible to fully eliminate it, and no forced philosophical argument about the dependence of our perceptions will change that.
But though our natural and obvious principles here prevail above our studied reflections, it is certain there must be sonic struggle and opposition in the case: at least so long as these rejections retain any force or vivacity. In order to set ourselves at ease in this particular, we contrive a new hypothesis, which seems to comprehend both these principles of reason and imagination. This hypothesis is the philosophical, one of the double existence of perceptions and objects; which pleases our reason, in allowing, that our dependent perceptions are interrupted and different; and at the same time is agreeable to the imagination, in attributing a continued existence to something else, which we call objects. This philosophical system, therefore, is the monstrous offspring of two principles, which are contrary to each other, which are both at once embraced by the mind, and which are unable mutually to destroy each other. The imagination tells us, that our resembling perceptions have a continued and uninterrupted existence, and are not annihilated by their absence. Reflection tells us, that even our resembling perceptions are interrupted in their existence, and different from each other. The contradiction betwixt these opinions we elude by a new fiction, which is conformable to the hypotheses both of reflection and fancy, by ascribing these contrary qualities to different existences; the interruption to perceptions, and the continuance to objects. Nature is obstinate, and will not quit the field, however strongly attacked by reason; and at the same time reason is so clear in the point, that there is no possibility of disguising her. Not being able to reconcile these two enemies, we endeavour to set ourselves at ease as much as possible, by successively granting to each whatever it demands, and by feigning a double existence, where each may find something, that has all the conditions it desires. Were we fully convinced, that our resembling perceptions are continued, and identical, and independent, we should never run into this opinion of a double existence, since we should find satisfaction in our first supposition, and would not look beyond. Again, were we fully convinced, that our perceptions are dependent, and interrupted, and different, we should be as little inclined to embrace the opinion of a double existence; since in that case we should clearly perceive the error of our first supposition of a continued existence, and would never regard it any farther. It is therefore from the intermediate situation of the mind, that this opinion arises, and from such an adherence to these two contrary principles, as makes us seek some pretext to justify our receiving both; which happily at last is found in the system of a double existence.
But even though our natural and obvious principles take precedence over our well-thought-out reflections, it’s clear there has to be some struggle and conflict in this situation: at least as long as these rejections remain relevant or vivid. To ease our minds about this, we create a new hypothesis that seems to cover both principles of reason and imagination. This hypothesis is the philosophical one about the dual existence of perceptions and objects; it satisfies our reason by allowing that our dependent perceptions are disrupted and different, while also appealing to our imagination by suggesting a continuous existence for something else we call objects. Therefore, this philosophical system is the strange result of two opposing principles, both of which the mind simultaneously accepts, even though they can’t destroy each other. The imagination tells us that our similar perceptions have a continuous and uninterrupted existence and aren’t erased by their absence. Reflection tells us that even our similar perceptions are disrupted in their existence and are distinct from one another. The contradiction between these views is resolved through a new fiction that aligns with both the reflection and fantasy hypotheses by attributing these opposing qualities to different existences: interruption to perceptions and continuity to objects. Nature is stubborn and won’t back down, no matter how strongly reason attacks; simultaneously, reason is so clear on this point that it can’t be hidden. Unable to reconcile these two opposing forces, we try to find comfort by gradually conceding to each what it demands and by pretending there’s a dual existence where each can find something that has all the qualities it desires. If we were completely convinced that our similar perceptions are continuous, identical, and independent, we wouldn’t delve into the notion of dual existence since we would be satisfied with our initial assumption and wouldn’t look any further. Conversely, if we were entirely convinced that our perceptions are dependent, interrupted, and different, we would have little motivation to accept the idea of dual existence; in that case, we would clearly recognize the mistake in our original assumption of continuous existence and wouldn’t give it any more thought. This opinion, therefore, comes from the mind’s intermediate state and from our clinging to these two opposing principles, leading us to seek some justification for accepting both; fortunately, this is ultimately found in the concept of dual existence.
Another advantage of this philosophical system is its similarity to the vulgar one; by which means we can humour our reason for a moment, when it becomes troublesome and sollicitous; and yet upon its least negligence or inattention, can easily return to our vulgar and natural notions. Accordingly we find, that philosophers neglect not this advantage; but immediately upon leaving their closets, mingle with the rest of mankind in those exploded opinions, that our perceptions are our only objects, and continue identically and uninterruptedly the same in all their interrupted appearances.
Another benefit of this philosophical system is how much it resembles the common one; this allows us to entertain our reason for a moment when it becomes bothersome and anxious; and yet, with just a little negligence or distraction, we can easily revert back to our everyday and instinctive ideas. As a result, we see that philosophers don't overlook this advantage; as soon as they step out of their studies, they engage with the rest of society, embracing those outdated beliefs that our perceptions are our only objects and remain identical and continuous despite their varied appearances.
There are other particulars of this system, wherein we may remark its dependence on the fancy, in a very conspicuous manner. Of these, I shall observe the two following. First, We suppose external objects to resemble internal perceptions. I have already shewn, that the relation of cause and effect can never afford us any just conclusion from the existence or qualities of our perceptions to the existence of external continued objects: And I shall farther add, that even though they could afford such a conclusion, we should never have any reason to infer, that our objects resemble our perceptions. That opinion, therefore, is derived from nothing but the quality of the fancy above-explained, (that it borrows all its ideas from some precedent perception). We never can conceive any thing but perceptions, and therefore must make every thing resemble them.
There are other details of this system that clearly show its reliance on imagination. I will highlight the following two. First, we assume that external objects are similar to internal perceptions. I have already demonstrated that the relationship between cause and effect cannot lead us to valid conclusions about the existence or characteristics of our perceptions regarding the existence of external, ongoing objects. Furthermore, even if it could lead to such conclusions, we would have no reason to believe that our objects resemble our perceptions. That belief, therefore, comes solely from the quality of imagination just mentioned (which borrows all its ideas from previous perceptions). We can only conceive of perceptions, so we have to make everything resemble them.
Secondly, As we suppose our objects in general to resemble our perceptions, so we take it for granted, that every particular object resembles that perception, which it causes. The relation of cause and effect determines us to join the other of resemblance; and the ideas of these existences being already united together in the fancy by the former relation, we naturally add the latter to compleat the union. We have a strong propensity to compleat every union by joining new relations to those which we have before observed betwixt any ideas, as we shall have occasion to observe presently.[7]
Secondly, just as we assume that our objects generally resemble our perceptions, we also take it for granted that each specific object resembles the perception it creates. The relationship between cause and effect leads us to connect this with the idea of resemblance; since these ideas are already linked in our imagination by the former relationship, we naturally add the latter to complete the connection. We have a strong tendency to complete every connection by adding new relationships to those we have previously observed between any ideas, as we will see shortly.[7]
[7] Sect. 5.
Having thus given an account of all the systems both popular and philosophical, with regard to external existences, I cannot forbear giving vent to a certain sentiment, which arises upon reviewing those systems. I begun this subject with premising, that we ought to have an implicit faith in our senses, and that this would be the conclusion, I should draw from the whole of my reasoning. But to be ingenuous, I feel myself at present of a quite contrary sentiment, and am more inclined to repose no faith at all in my senses, or rather imagination, than to place in it such an implicit confidence. I cannot conceive how such trivial qualities of the fancy, conducted by such false suppositions, can ever lead to any solid and rational system. They are the coherence and constancy of our perceptions, which produce the opinion of their continued existence; though these qualities of perceptions have no perceivable connexion with such an existence. The constancy of our perceptions has the most considerable effect, and yet is attended with the greatest difficulties. It is a gross illusion to suppose, that our resembling perceptions are numerically the same; and it is this illusion, which leads us into the opinion, that these perceptions are uninterrupted, and are still existent, even when they are not present to the senses. This is the case with our popular system. And as to our philosophical one, it is liable to the same difficulties; and is over-and-above loaded with this absurdity, that it at once denies and establishes the vulgar supposition. Philosophers deny our resembling perceptions to be identically the same, and uninterrupted; and yet have so great a propensity to believe them such, that they arbitrarily invent a new set of perceptions, to which they attribute these qualities. I say, a new set of perceptions: For we may well suppose in general, but it is impossible for us distinctly to conceive, objects to be in their nature any thing but exactly the same with perceptions. What then can we look for from this confusion of groundless and extraordinary opinions but error and falshood? And how can we justify to ourselves any belief we repose in them?
Having given an overview of all the popular and philosophical systems concerning external realities, I feel compelled to express a certain sentiment that arises when I review these systems. I started this discussion by stating that we should have complete faith in our senses, and that this would be the conclusion I would draw from my reasoning. However, to be honest, I currently hold quite the opposite view and am more inclined to distrust my senses, or rather my imagination, than to place such unwavering faith in them. I can't understand how such trivial qualities of imagination, driven by false assumptions, could ever lead to a solid and rational system. It is the consistency and stability of our perceptions that create the belief in their ongoing existence, even though these qualities of perception are not connected to any real existence. The stability of our perceptions is significant, yet it comes with great challenges. It is a serious misconception to think that our similar perceptions are exactly the same; this illusion leads us to believe that these perceptions are continuous and still exist, even when they are not sensed. This applies to our popular system. As for our philosophical one, it faces the same hurdles and is burdened with the absurdity of simultaneously denying and supporting common beliefs. Philosophers argue that our similar perceptions are not identical or uninterrupted; yet, they are so inclined to believe this that they invent a new set of perceptions, attributing these qualities to them. I mention a new set of perceptions because we can generally assume one thing, but it is impossible for us to clearly conceive of objects being anything other than exactly the same as our perceptions. So what can we expect from this confusion of baseless and extraordinary beliefs but error and falsehood? And how can we justify any faith we place in them?
This sceptical doubt, both with respect to reason and the senses, is a malady, which can never be radically cured, but must return upon us every moment, however we may chace it away, and sometimes may seem entirely free from it. It is impossible upon any system to defend either our understanding or senses; and we but expose them farther when we endeavour to justify them in that manner. As the sceptical doubt arises naturally from a profound and intense reflection on those subjects, it always encreases, the farther we carry our reflections, whether in opposition or conformity to it. Carelessness and in-attention alone can afford us any remedy. For this reason I rely entirely upon them; and take it for granted, whatever may be the reader's opinion at this present moment, that an hour hence he will be persuaded there is both an external and internal world; and going upon that supposition, I intend to examine some general systems both ancient and modern, which have been proposed of both, before I proceed to a more particular enquiry concerning our impressions. This will not, perhaps, in the end be found foreign to our present purpose.
This skeptical doubt, regarding both reason and the senses, is a condition that can never be completely cured but will return to us at any moment, no matter how hard we try to chase it away, and sometimes we might seem entirely free of it. It’s impossible to defend either our understanding or our senses in any system; trying to justify them only exposes them further. Since skeptical doubt naturally arises from deep and intense reflection on these topics, it only grows the more we reflect, whether we oppose or conform to it. Only carelessness and inattention can provide us any relief. For this reason, I rely entirely on them; and I assume, regardless of the reader's current opinion, that in an hour they'll be convinced there is both an external and internal world. Based on that assumption, I plan to examine some general theories, both ancient and modern, that have been proposed about both, before moving on to a more detailed inquiry into our impressions. This may ultimately prove relevant to our current discussion.
SECT. III. OF THE ANTIENT PHILOSOPHY.
Several moralists have recommended it as an excellent method of becoming acquainted with our own hearts, and knowing our progress in virtue, to recollect our dreams in a morning, and examine them with the same rigour, that we would our most serious and most deliberate actions. Our character is the same throughout, say they, and appears best where artifice, fear, and policy have no place, and men can neither be hypocrites with themselves nor others. The generosity, or baseness of our temper, our meekness or cruelty, our courage or pusilanimity, influence the fictions of the imagination with the most unbounded liberty, and discover themselves in the most glaring colours. In like manner, I am persuaded, there might be several useful discoveries made from a criticism of the fictions of the antient philosophy, concerning substances, and substantial form, and accidents, and occult qualities; which, however unreasonable and capricious, have a very intimate connexion with the principles of human nature.
Many moralists have suggested that a great way to understand our own hearts and gauge our growth in virtue is to remember our dreams each morning and analyze them with the same intensity we would our most serious and deliberate actions. They argue that our character remains consistent, especially when there’s no deception, fear, or strategy involved, and people can't be hypocritical toward themselves or others. The generosity or stinginess of our nature, our kindness or cruelty, our bravery or cowardice, influence the creations of our imagination with total freedom and reveal themselves in vivid detail. Similarly, I believe there could be many valuable insights gained from analyzing the ideas of ancient philosophy regarding substances, substantial forms, accidents, and hidden qualities; these concepts, while seemingly unreasonable and whimsical, are closely linked to the principles of human nature.
It is confest by the most judicious philosophers, that our ideas of bodies are nothing but collections formed by the mind of the ideas of the several distinct sensible qualities, of which objects are composed, and which we find to have a constant union with each other. But however these qualities may in themselves be entirely distinct, it is certain we commonly regard the compound, which they form, as ONE thing, and as continuing the SAME under very considerable alterations. The acknowledged composition is evidently contrary to this supposed simplicity, and the variation to the identity. It may, therefore, be worth while to consider the causes, which make us almost universally fall into such evident contradictions, as well as the means by which we endeavour to conceal them.
It’s acknowledged by the most insightful philosophers that our understanding of physical objects is just collections created by the mind from the various distinct sensory qualities that make up those objects, which we consistently find to be connected. However, even though these qualities might be entirely separate, we usually perceive the whole they create as ONE thing, and view it as remaining the SAME even with significant changes. This recognized composition clearly contradicts the idea of simplicity, and the changes conflict with the notion of identity. Therefore, it might be worth exploring the reasons why we almost universally fall into such obvious contradictions, as well as the ways we try to hide them.
It is evident, that as the ideas of the several distinct, successive qualities of objects are united together by a very close relation, the mind, in looking along the succession, must be carryed from one part of it to another by an easy transition, and will no more perceive the change, than if it contemplated the same unchangeable object. This easy transition is the effect, or rather essence of relation; I and as the imagination readily takes one idea for another, where their influence on the mind is similar; hence it proceeds, that any such succession of related qualities is readily considered as one continued object, existing without any variation. The smooth and uninterrupted progress of the thought, being alike in both cases, readily deceives the mind, and makes us ascribe an identity to the changeable succession of connected qualities.
It's clear that as the ideas of various distinct, successive qualities of objects are closely related, the mind, when following that succession, moves easily from one part to another without noticing the change, just as if it were contemplating the same unchanging object. This smooth transition is the essence of relation; the imagination easily accepts one idea for another when their effect on the mind is similar. Thus, any succession of related qualities is easily seen as one continuous object, existing without any variation. The smooth and uninterrupted flow of thought is the same in both cases, which easily misleads the mind and makes us attribute an identity to the changing succession of connected qualities.
But when we alter our method of considering the succession, and instead of traceing it gradually through the successive points of time, survey at once Any two distinct periods of its duration, and compare the different conditions of the successive qualities; in that case the variations, which were insensible when they arose gradually, do now appear of consequence, and seem entirely to destroy the identity. By this means there arises a kind of contrariety in our method of thinking, from the different points of view, in which we survey the object, and from the nearness or remoteness of those instants of time, which we compare together. When we gradually follow an object in its successive changes, the smooth progress of the thought makes us ascribe an identity to the succession; because it is by a similar act of the mind we consider an unchangeable object. When we compare its situation after a considerable change the progress of the thought is broke; and consequently we are presented with the idea of diversity: In order to reconcile which contradictions the imagination is apt to feign something unknown and invisible, which it supposes to continue the same under all these variations; and this unintelligible something it calls a substance, or original and first matter.
But when we change how we think about succession and instead of tracing it gradually through time, we look at two distinct periods simultaneously and compare the different conditions of the qualities over time, the variations that seemed minor when they occurred gradually now appear significant and seem to completely undermine the idea of identity. This creates a sort of conflict in our thinking based on the different perspectives from which we examine the object and how close or far apart the moments in time we are comparing are. When we follow an object through its changes gradually, the smooth flow of thought leads us to attribute identity to the succession, since we consider an unchanging object in a similar manner. However, when we compare its state after a significant change, the flow of thought is interrupted, and we start to see the concept of diversity. To resolve these contradictions, our imagination tends to invent something unknown and invisible that it assumes remains the same through all these changes; this unclear entity is referred to as substance or original matter.
We entertain a like notion with regard to the simplicity of substances, and from like causes. Suppose an object perfectly simple and indivisible to be presented, along with another object, whose co-existent parts are connected together by a strong relation, it is evident the actions of the mind, in considering these two objects, are not very different. The imagination conceives the simple object at once, with facility, by a single effort of thought, without change or variation. The connexion of parts in the compound object has almost the same effect, and so unites the object within itself, that the fancy feels not the transition in passing from one part to another. Hence the colour, taste, figure, solidity, and other qualities, combined in a peach or melon, are conceived to form one thing; and that on account of their close relation, which makes them affect the thought in the same manner, as if perfectly uncompounded. But the mind rests not here. Whenever it views the object in another light, it finds that all these qualities are different, and distinguishable, and separable from each other; which view of things being destructive of its primary and more natural notions, obliges the imagination to feign an unknown something, or original substance and matter, as a principle of union or cohesion among these qualities, and as what may give the compound object a title to be called one thing, notwithstanding its diversity and composition.
We have a similar idea about the simplicity of substances and their causes. Imagine one object that is completely simple and indivisible, alongside another object whose parts are strongly connected. It's clear the way our mind thinks about these two objects isn't that different. We can easily grasp the simple object all at once, with a single thought, without any change. The connection of parts in the complex object has a similar effect, allowing us to perceive it as a whole so smoothly that we hardly notice shifting from one part to another. So, the color, taste, shape, solidity, and other qualities found in a peach or melon are seen as one thing because their close relationship impacts our thought similarly as if they were completely simple. However, our mind doesn't stop there. When we look at the object differently, we realize that all these qualities are distinct and separable. This perception, which clashes with our initial and more natural understanding, forces our imagination to invent an unknown entity, or original substance and matter, as a principle of unity or connection among these qualities, giving the complex object a reason to be considered a single thing, despite its diversity and complexity.
The peripatetic philosophy asserts the original matter to be perfectly homogeneous in all bodies, and considers fire, water, earth, and air, as of the very same substance; on account of their gradual revolutions and changes into each other. At the same time it assigns to each of these species of objects a distinct substantial form, which it supposes to be the source of all those different qualities they possess, and to be a new foundation of simplicity and identity to each particular species. All depends on our manner of viewing the objects. When we look along the insensible changes of bodies, we suppose all of them to be of the same substance or essence. When we consider their sensible differences, we attribute to each of them a substantial and essential difference. And in order to indulge ourselves in both these ways of considering our objects, we suppose all bodies to have at once a substance and a substantial form.
The peripatetic philosophy claims that the basic matter in all bodies is completely uniform and treats fire, water, earth, and air as being made of the same substance, due to their gradual transformations into one another. At the same time, it assigns a unique substantial form to each of these types of matter, which it believes is the source of all the different qualities they have, providing a new basis for simplicity and identity for each specific type. Everything depends on how we perceive these objects. When we look at the imperceptible changes in bodies, we assume they all share the same substance or essence. However, when we consider their noticeable differences, we attribute a substantial and essential difference to each one. To allow for both ways of viewing our objects, we assume that all bodies possess both a substance and a substantial form.
The notion of accidents is an unavoidable consequence of this method of thinking with regard to substances and substantial forms; nor can we forbear looking upon colours, sounds, tastes, figures, and other properties of bodies, as existences, which cannot subsist apart, but require a subject of inhesion to sustain and support them. For having never discovered any of these sensible qualities, where, for the reasons above-mentioned, we did not likewise fancy a substance to exist; the same habit, which makes us infer a connexion betwixt cause and effect, makes us here infer a dependence of every quality on the unknown substance. The custom of imagining a dependence has the same effect as the custom of observing it would have. This conceit, however, is no more reasonable than any of the foregoing. Every quality being a distinct thing from another, may be conceived to exist apart, and may exist apart, not only from every other quality, but from that unintelligible chimera of a substance.
The idea of accidents is an unavoidable part of this way of thinking about substances and their essential forms. We can’t help but see colors, sounds, tastes, shapes, and other properties of things as existences that can’t exist on their own but need a subject to support them. Since we’ve never found any of these tangible qualities without also imagining a substance exists, the same habit that leads us to connect cause and effect also leads us to believe every quality depends on some unknown substance. The habit of imagining this dependence has the same effect as actually observing it would. However, this idea is just as unreasonable as the ones mentioned earlier. Each quality is distinct and can be thought of as existing on its own, separate not only from other qualities but also from that unclear concept of a substance.
But these philosophers carry their fictions still farther in their sentiments concerning occult qualities, and both suppose a substance supporting, which they do not understand, and an accident supported, of which they have as imperfect an idea. The whole system, therefore, is entirely incomprehensible, and yet is derived from principles as natural as any of these above-explained.
But these philosophers take their ideas even further in their beliefs about hidden qualities, and they assume a substance underneath that they don't really grasp, as well as an accident that is dependent on it, of which they have only a vague understanding. Therefore, the whole system is completely unclear, even though it’s based on principles as natural as the ones mentioned above.
In considering this subject we may observe a gradation of three opinions, that rise above each other, according as the persons, who form them, acquire new degrees of reason and knowledge. These opinions are that of the vulgar, that of a false philosophy, and that of the true; where we shall find upon enquiry, that the true philosophy approaches nearer to the sentiments of the vulgar, than to those of a mistaken knowledge. It is natural for men, in their common and care, less way of thinking, to imagine they perceive a connexion betwixt such objects as they have constantly found united together; and because custom has rendered it difficult to separate the ideas, they are apt to fancy such a separation to be in itself impossible and absurd. But philosophers, who abstract from the effects of custom, and compare the ideas of objects, immediately perceive the falshood of these vulgar sentiments, and discover that there is no known connexion among objects. Every different object appears to them entirely distinct and separate; and they perceive, that it is not from a view of the nature and qualities of objects we infer one from another, but only when in several instances we observe them to have been constantly conjoined. But these philosophers, instead of drawing a just inference from this observation, and concluding, that we have no idea of power or agency, separate from the mind, and belonging to causes; I say, instead of drawing this conclusion, they frequently search for the qualities, in which this agency consists, and are displeased with every system, which their reason suggests to them, in order to explain it. They have sufficient force of genius to free them from the vulgar error, that there is a natural and perceivable connexion betwixt the several sensible qualities and actions of matter; but not sufficient to keep them from ever seeking for this connexion in matter, or causes. Had they fallen upon the just conclusion, they would have returned back to the situation of the vulgar, and would have regarded all these disquisitions with indolence and indifference. At present they seem to be in a very lamentable condition, and such as the poets have given us but a faint notion of in their descriptions of the punishment of Sisyphus and Tantalus. For what can be imagined more tormenting, than to seek with eagerness, what for ever flies us; and seek for it in a place, where it is impossible it can ever exist?
In discussing this topic, we can notice three levels of opinion that are ranked based on how much reason and knowledge the people hold. These opinions are those of the common person, those of a flawed philosophy, and those of true philosophy. Upon investigation, we find that true philosophy is closer in sentiment to the common person than to flawed knowledge. It's natural for people, in their everyday and careless way of thinking, to believe they see a connection between objects they've always found together; and because habit makes it hard to separate these ideas, they tend to think such separation is impossible and absurd. However, philosophers, who take a step back from the impact of habit and compare ideas, quickly recognize the falsehood in these common beliefs and discover that there is no known connection among objects. Each distinct object appears to them completely separate; they understand that we don’t infer one from the other based on their nature and qualities, but only when we see them constantly paired in various instances. Yet, instead of correctly concluding from this observation that we have no notion of power or agency apart from the mind and related to causes, they often look for the qualities that embody this agency and get frustrated with every explanation their reason suggests. They have enough intellectual strength to free themselves from the common misunderstanding that there’s a natural and perceivable connection between the various sensory qualities and actions of matter, but not enough to stop searching for this connection in matter or causes. If they had arrived at the right conclusion, they would have returned to the state of the common person, viewing all these inquiries with apathy and indifference. Currently, they seem to be in a very troubling position, reminiscent of the descriptions by poets of the punishments of Sisyphus and Tantalus. For what could be more tormenting than eagerly searching for something that forever eludes us and looking for it in a place where it can never exist?
But as nature seems to have observed a kind of justice and compensation in every thing, she has not neglected philosophers more than the rest of the creation; but has reserved them a consolation amid all their disappointments and afflictions. This consolation principally consists in their invention of the words: faculty and occult quality. For it being usual, after the frequent use of terms, which are really significant and intelligible, to omit the idea, which we would express by them, and to preserve only the custom, by which we recal the idea at pleasure; so it naturally happens, that after the frequent use of terms, which are wholly insignificant and unintelligible, we fancy them to be on the same footing with the precedent, and to have a secret meaning, which we might discover by reflection. The resemblance of their appearance deceives the mind, as is usual, and makes us imagine a thorough resemblance and conformity. By this means these philosophers set themselves at ease, and arrive at last, by an illusion, at the same indifference, which the people attain by their stupidity, and true philosophers by their moderate scepticism. They need only say, that any phenomenon, which puzzles them, arises from a faculty or an occult quality, and there is an end of all dispute and enquiry upon the matter.
But just as nature seems to follow a kind of justice and balance in everything, she hasn’t overlooked philosophers any more than the rest of creation; instead, she has given them a source of comfort amid all their disappointments and hardships. This comfort mainly comes from their creation of the terms: faculty and occult quality. Since it's common, after frequently using terms that are genuinely meaningful and clear, to drop the actual idea they represent and just hold onto the custom of recalling that idea whenever we like, it naturally occurs that after often using terms that are completely meaningless and unclear, we start to believe they hold the same significance as the former and have a hidden meaning we could uncover through thought. The similarity in their appearance tricks the mind, as is often the case, leading us to think there’s a complete resemblance and alignment. This way, these philosophers find peace and eventually, through an illusion, reach the same indifference that regular people achieve through their ignorance, and true philosophers attain through their measured skepticism. They only need to say that any phenomenon that confuses them is due to a faculty or an occult quality, and that ends all debate and inquiry on the subject.
But among all the instances, wherein the Peripatetics have shewn they were guided by every trivial propensity of the imagination, no one is more-remarkable than their sympathies, antipathies, and horrors of a vacuum. There is a very remarkable inclination in human nature, to bestow on external objects the same emotions, which it observes in itself; and to find every where those ideas, which are most present to it. This inclination, it is true, is suppressed by a little reflection, and only takes place in children, poets, and the antient philosophers. It appears in children, by their desire of beating the stones, which hurt them: In poets, by their readiness to personify every thing: And in the antient philosophers, by these fictions of sympathy and antipathy. We must pardon children, because of their age; poets, because they profess to follow implicitly the suggestions of their fancy: But what excuse shall we find to justify our philosophers in so signal a weakness?
But among all the examples where the Peripatetics have shown they were influenced by every little whim of the imagination, none is more striking than their sympathies, antipathies, and fears of a vacuum. There is a notable tendency in human nature to project onto external objects the same emotions that we experience ourselves, and to see those ideas everywhere that are most prominent in our minds. This tendency, it’s true, can be suppressed with a bit of thought, and it mostly appears in children, poets, and the ancient philosophers. We see it in children when they want to hit the stones that hurt them; in poets, when they readily personify everything; and in the ancient philosophers through their fictions of sympathy and antipathy. We can excuse children because of their age, and poets because they claim to follow their imagination without restraint. But what justification can we find for our philosophers in such a glaring weakness?
SECT. IV. OF THE MODERN PHILOSOPHY.
But here it may be objected, that the imagination, according to my own confession, being the ultimate judge of all systems of philosophy, I am unjust in blaming the antient philosophers for making use of that faculty, and allowing themselves to be entirely guided by it in their reasonings. In order to justify myself, I must distinguish in the imagination betwixt the principles which are permanent, irresistible, and universal; such as the customary transition from causes to effects, and from effects to causes: And the principles, which are changeable, weak, and irregular; such as those I have just now taken notice of. The former are the foundation of all our thoughts and actions, so that upon their removal human nature must immediately perish and go to ruin. The latter are neither unavoidable to mankind, nor necessary, or so much as useful in the conduct of life; but on the contrary are observed only to take place in weak minds, and being opposite to the other principles of custom and reasoning, may easily be subverted by a due contrast and opposition. For this reason the former are received by philosophy, and the latter rejected. One who concludes somebody to be near him, when he hears an articulate voice in the dark, reasons justly and naturally; though that conclusion be derived from nothing but custom, which infixes and inlivens the idea of a human creature, on account of his usual conjunction with the present impression. But one, who is tormented he knows not why, with the apprehension of spectres in the dark, may, perhaps, be said to reason, and to reason naturally too: But then it must be in the same sense, that a malady is said to be natural; as arising from natural causes, though it be contrary to health, the most agreeable and most natural situation of man.
But here it might be argued that, according to my own admission, the imagination serves as the ultimate judge of all philosophical systems, so it's unfair for me to criticize the ancient philosophers for relying on that faculty and letting it fully guide their reasoning. To defend my position, I need to differentiate between the aspects of imagination that are permanent, compelling, and universal—like the usual connection from causes to effects and from effects to causes—and those that are changeable, weak, and irregular, like the ones I've just mentioned. The former are the foundation of all our thoughts and actions; without them, human nature would collapse and fall apart. The latter are not essential to humanity, nor are they necessary or even useful in everyday life; instead, they seem to occur only in fragile minds and, being opposed to the other principles of custom and reasoning, can be easily overturned through proper contrast and opposition. For this reason, the former are accepted by philosophy, while the latter are dismissed. Someone who concludes that another person is nearby just because they hear a clear voice in the dark is reasoning correctly and naturally, even though that conclusion stems solely from custom, which strongly associates the idea of a human being with the current impression. However, someone who is irrationally disturbed by the fear of ghosts in the dark may also be said to reason, and to reason naturally too; but that reasoning is similar to how we talk about a sickness as being natural, coming from natural causes, even though it contradicts health, which is the most agreeable and natural state for a human being.
The opinions of the antient philosophers, their fictions of substance and accident, and their reasonings concerning substantial forms and occult qualities, are like the spectres in the dark, and are derived from principles, which, however common, are neither universal nor unavoidable in human nature. The modern philosophy pretends to be entirely free from this defect, and to arise only from the solid, permanent, and consistent principles of the imagination. Upon what grounds this pretension is founded must now be the subject of our enquiry.
The views of ancient philosophers, their ideas about substance and accident, and their reasoning about essential forms and hidden qualities are like shadows in the dark, based on principles that, while common, are neither universal nor inevitable in human nature. Modern philosophy claims to be completely free from these flaws and to be based solely on solid, lasting, and consistent principles of imagination. We must now explore the basis for this claim.
The fundamental principle of that philosophy is the opinion concerning colours, sounds, tastes, smells, heat and cold; which it asserts to be nothing but impressions in the mind, derived from the operation of external objects, and without any resemblance to the qualities of the objects. Upon examination, I find only one of the reasons commonly produced for this opinion to be satisfactory, viz. that derived from the variations of those impressions, even while the external object, to all appearance, continues the same. These variations depend upon several circumstances. Upon the different situations of our health: A man in a malady feels a disagreeable taste in meats, which before pleased him the most. Upon the different complexions and constitutions of men That seems bitter to one, which is sweet to another. Upon the difference of their external situation and position: Colours reflected from the clouds change according to the distance of the clouds, and according to the angle they make with the eye and luminous body. Fire also communicates the sensation of pleasure at one distance, and that of pain at another. Instances of this kind are very numerous and frequent.
The main idea of that philosophy is the view on colors, sounds, tastes, smells, heat, and cold; it claims these are just impressions in the mind that come from the influence of external objects, without actually resembling the properties of those objects. Upon closer look, I find that only one of the commonly offered reasons for this view is convincing, which is the one related to the changes in those impressions, even when the external object seems to remain the same. These changes depend on several factors. First, they relate to our health: a person who is sick might find a previously enjoyable food tastes unpleasant. Then there are the different physical makeups and conditions of people: what tastes bitter to one person may be sweet to another. Lastly, the external circumstances and positions also matter: the colors reflected by clouds shift depending on their distance and the angle relative to the eye and light source. Fire can also create feelings of pleasure at one distance and pain at another. There are many examples like this.
The conclusion drawn from them, is likewise as satisfactory as can possibly be imagined. It is certain, that when different impressions of the same sense arise from any object, every one of these impressions has not a resembling quality existent in the object. For as the same object cannot, at the same time, be endowed with different qualities of the same sense, and as the same quality cannot resemble impressions entirely different; it evidently follows, that many of our impressions have no external model or archetype. Now from like effects we presume like causes. Many of the impressions of colour, sound, &c. are confest to be nothing but internal existences, and to arise from causes, which no ways resemble them. These impressions are in appearance nothing different from the other impressions of colour, sound, &c. We conclude, therefore, that they are, all of them, derived from a like origin.
The conclusion drawn from them is just as satisfactory as one could imagine. It's clear that when different impressions of the same sense come from an object, not every one of those impressions has a corresponding quality in the object. Since the same object can't have different qualities of the same sense at the same time, and since the same quality can't resemble entirely different impressions, it’s evident that many of our impressions don’t have any external model or archetype. Now, from similar effects, we assume similar causes. Many impressions of color, sound, etc., are recognized to be nothing but internal experiences, arising from causes that don’t resemble them at all. These impressions appear no different from other impressions of color, sound, etc. Therefore, we conclude that they all come from a similar origin.
This principle being once admitted, all the other doctrines of that philosophy seem to follow by an easy consequence. For upon the removal of sounds, colours, beat, cold, and other sensible qualities, from the rank of continued independent existences, we are reduced merely to what are called primary qualities, as the only real ones, of which we have any adequate notion. These primary qualities are extension and solidity, with their different mixtures and modifications; figure, motion, gravity, and cohesion. The generation, encrease, decay, and corruption of animals and vegetables, are nothing but changes of figure and motion; as also the operations of all bodies on each other; of fire, of light, water, air, earth, and of all the elements and powers of nature. One figure and motion produces another figure and motion; nor does there remain in the material universe any other principle, either active or passive, of which we can form the most distant idea.
Once this principle is accepted, all the other ideas in that philosophy seem to follow quite easily. When we remove sounds, colors, heat, cold, and other observable qualities from the category of independent existences, we're left with only what are called primary qualities, which are the only real ones we have a clear understanding of. These primary qualities are extension and solidity, along with their various mixtures and modifications; shape, motion, gravity, and cohesion. The birth, growth, decline, and decay of animals and plants are simply changes in shape and motion, just like the interactions of all bodies with one another; including fire, light, water, air, earth, and all the elements and forces of nature. One shape and motion leads to another shape and motion, and there are no other principles in the material universe, whether active or passive, that we can even begin to imagine.
I believe many objections might be made to this system But at present I shall confine myself to one, which is in my opinion very decisive. I assert, that instead of explaining the operations of external objects by its means, we utterly annihilate all these objects, and reduce ourselves to the opinions of the most extravagant scepticism concerning them. If colours, sounds, tastes, and smells be merely perceptions, nothing we can conceive is possest of a real, continued, and independent existence; not even motion, extension and solidity, which are the primary qualities chiefly insisted on.
I believe many objections can be raised against this system. However, for now, I'll focus on one that I think is very decisive. I assert that instead of using it to explain how external objects operate, we completely eliminate all these objects and are left with the most extreme skepticism about them. If colors, sounds, tastes, and smells are just perceptions, then nothing we can imagine has a real, ongoing, and independent existence—not even motion, extension, and solidity, which are the primary qualities that are typically emphasized.
To begin with the examination of motion; it is evident this is a quality altogether inconceivable alone, and without a reference to some other object. The idea of motion necessarily supposes that of a body moving. Now what is our idea of the moving body, without which motion is incomprehensible? It must resolve itself into the idea of extension or of solidity; and consequently the reality of motion depends upon that of these other qualities.
To start examining motion, it’s clear that this quality cannot be understood by itself and needs a reference to some other object. The concept of motion inherently involves the idea of a body that is moving. Now, what do we think of as the moving body, without which motion doesn't make sense? It must break down into the idea of extension or solidity; therefore, the existence of motion relies on the existence of these other qualities.
This opinion, which is universally acknowledged concerning motion, I have proved to be true with regard to extension; and have shewn that it is impossible to conceive extension, but as composed of parts, endowed with colour or solidity. The idea of extension is a compound idea; but as it is not compounded of an infinite number of parts or inferior ideas, it must at last resolve itself into such as are perfectly simple and indivisible. These simple and indivisible parts, not being ideas of extension, must be non entities, unless conceived as coloured or solid. Colour is excluded from any real existence. The reality, therefore, of our idea of extension depends upon the reality of that of solidity, nor can the former be just while the latter is chimerical. Let us, then, lend our attention to the examination of the idea of solidity.
This widely accepted view on motion, I have demonstrated to be valid regarding extension; and I have shown that it's impossible to imagine extension without thinking of it as made up of parts that have color or solidity. The concept of extension is a complex idea; but since it isn’t made up of an infinite number of parts or lesser ideas, it ultimately has to break down into parts that are completely simple and indivisible. These simple and indivisible parts, which are not ideas of extension, must be non-existent unless considered as colored or solid. Color is not part of any real existence. Thus, the reality of our idea of extension hinges on the reality of solidity, and the former cannot hold true if the latter is merely imaginary. So, let’s focus our attention on analyzing the idea of solidity.
The idea of solidity is that of two objects, which being impelled by the utmost force, cannot penetrate each other; but still maintain a separate and distinct existence. Solidity, therefore, is perfectly incomprehensible alone, and without the conception of some bodies, which are solid, and maintain this separate and distinct existence. Now what idea have we of these bodies? The ideas of colours, sounds, and other secondary qualities are excluded. The idea of motion depends on that of extension, and the idea of extension on that of solidity. It is impossible, therefore, that the idea of solidity can depend on either of them. For that would be to run in a circle, and make one idea depend on another, while at the same time the latter depends on the former. Our modern philosophy, therefore, leaves us no just nor satisfactory idea of solidity; nor consequently of matter.
The concept of solidity refers to two objects that, when pushed with the greatest force, cannot pass through each other, yet still exist separately and distinctly. Solidity, therefore, is completely incomprehensible on its own, without the understanding of some solid bodies that maintain this separate and distinct existence. So, what do we understand about these bodies? The ideas of colors, sounds, and other secondary qualities are not included. The idea of motion relies on the idea of extension, and the idea of extension relies on the idea of solidity. Therefore, it’s impossible for the idea of solidity to depend on either of them. That would create a circular dependency, making one idea rely on another, which in turn relies on the first. Our modern philosophy, consequently, does not provide a clear or satisfactory concept of solidity, nor, therefore, of matter.
This argument will appear entirely conclusive to every one that comprehends it; but because it may seem abstruse and intricate to the generality of readers, I hope to be excused, if I endeavour to render it more obvious by some variation of the expression. In order to form an idea of solidity, we must conceive two bodies pressing on each other without any penetration; and it is impossible to arrive at this idea, when we confine ourselves to one object, much more without conceiving any. Two non-entities cannot exclude each other from their places; because they never possess any place, nor can be endowed with any quality. Now I ask, what idea do we form of these bodies or objects, to which we suppose solidity to belong? To say, that we conceive them merely as solid, is to run on in infinitum. To affirm, that we paint them out to ourselves as extended, either resolves all into a false idea, or returns in a circle. Extension must necessarily be considered either as coloured, which is a false idea; I or as solid, which brings us back to the first question. We may make the same observation concerning mobility and figure; and upon the whole must conclude, that after the exclusion of colours, sounds, heat and cold from the rank of external existences, there remains nothing, which can afford us a just and constituent idea of body.
This argument will seem completely convincing to anyone who understands it; however, since it might appear complex and complicated to most readers, I hope I can be forgiven for trying to make it clearer by changing the wording a bit. To understand solidity, we need to imagine two objects pressing against each other without penetrating; and it's impossible to grasp this idea if we focus on just one object, especially without considering any at all. Two non-entities can't occupy space since they don't have a place or any qualities. So, what idea do we have of these bodies or objects to which we assume solidity belongs? To say we view them simply as solid keeps us going in circles forever. If we say we visualize them as extended, it either leads to a false idea or comes back around to the same point. Extension has to be seen either as colored, which is a false idea, or as solid, which brings us back to the original question. We can make the same observation about movement and shape; altogether, we must conclude that if we eliminate colors, sounds, heat, and cold from external realities, there’s nothing left that gives us a clear and fundamental idea of a body.
Add to this, that, properly speaking, solidity or impenetrability is nothing, but an impossibility of annihilation, as[8] has been already observed: For which reason it is the more necessary for us to form some distinct idea of that object, whose annihilation we suppose impossible. An impossibility of being annihilated cannot exist, and can never be conceived to exist, by itself: but necessarily requires some object or real existence, to which it may belong. Now the difficulty still remains, how to form an idea of this object or existence, without having recourse to the secondary and sensible qualities.
Add to this that, properly speaking, solidity or impenetrability is nothing but the impossibility of destruction, as [8] has already noted. For this reason, it's even more important for us to form a clear idea of the object we believe cannot be destroyed. An impossibility of being destroyed cannot exist and can't be thought of by itself; it necessarily requires some object or real existence to which it can relate. Now the challenge remains: how do we come up with an idea of this object or existence without relying on secondary and observable qualities?
[8] Part II. Sect. 4.
Nor must we omit on this occasion our accustomed method of examining ideas by considering those impressions, from which they are derived. The impressions, which enter by the sight and hearing, the smell and taste, are affirmed by modern philosophy to be without any resembling objects; and consequently the idea of solidity, which is supposed to be real, can never be derived from any of these senses. There remains, therefore, the feeling as the only sense, that can convey the impression, which is original to the idea of solidity; and indeed we naturally imagine, that we feel the solidity of bodies, and need but touch any object in order to perceive this quality. But this method of thinking is more popular than philosophical; as will appear from the following reflections.
We shouldn't overlook our usual approach of examining ideas by looking at the impressions they come from. Modern philosophy claims that the impressions we get from sight, hearing, smell, and taste don't have any matching objects. Therefore, the concept of solidity, which we believe to be real, can't be derived from any of these senses. So, the only sense left that can deliver the impression essential to the idea of solidity is touch; we naturally assume that we can feel the solidity of objects, and we just need to touch something to recognize this quality. However, this line of thinking is more popular than philosophical, as will be evident from the following reflections.
First, It is easy to observe, that though bodies are felt by means of their solidity, yet the feeling is a quite different thing from the solidity; and that they have not the least resemblance to each other. A man, who has the palsey in one hand, has as perfect an idea of impenetrability, when he observes that hand to be supported by the table, as when he feels the same table with the other hand. An object, that presses upon any of our members, meets with resistance; and that resistance, by the motion it gives to the nerves and animal spirits, conveys a certain sensation to the mind; but it does not follow, that the sensation, motion, and resistance are any ways resembling.
First, it's easy to see that although we perceive objects through their solidity, the sensation of feeling is completely different from that solidity, and they have no resemblance to each other. A person who has paralysis in one hand can fully understand the concept of impenetrability when they see that hand resting on the table, just as they do when they feel the same table with their other hand. An object that applies pressure on any part of our body encounters resistance; this resistance, through the movement it causes in the nerves and nervous system, brings a specific sensation to the mind. However, this doesn’t mean that sensation, movement, and resistance are in any way similar.
Secondly, The impressions of touch are simple impressions, except when considered with regard to their extension; which makes nothing to the present purpose: And from this simplicity I infer, that they neither represent solidity, nor any real object. For let us put two cases, viz. that of a man, who presses a stone, or any solid body, with his hand, and that of two stones, which press each other; it will readily be allowed, that these two cases are not in every respect alike, but that in the former there is conjoined with the solidity, a feeling or sensation, of which there is no appearance in the latter. In order, therefore, to make these two cases alike, it is necessary to remove some part of the impression, which the man feels by his hand, or organ of sensation; and that being impossible in a simple impression, obliges us to remove the whole, and proves that this whole impression has no archetype or model in external objects. To which we may add, that solidity necessarily supposes two bodies, along with contiguity and impulse; which being a compound object, can never be represented by a simple impression. Not to mention, that though solidity continues always invariably the same, the impressions of touch change every moment upon us; which is a clear proof that the latter are not representations of the former.
Secondly, the sensations of touch are straightforward experiences, unless we look at them in terms of their extent, which doesn't really matter here. From this simplicity, I conclude that they don’t represent solidity or any real object. Let’s consider two cases: one where a person presses a stone or any solid object with their hand, and another where two stones press against each other. It’s clear that these two situations aren’t identical since, in the first case, there’s a feeling or sensation that isn’t present in the second. To make these two cases comparable, we would need to remove part of the sensation that the person feels through their hand or sense organ; and since it's impossible to remove just a part of a simple impression, we end up needing to remove the whole sensation, showing that this entire impression has no counterpart in external objects. Additionally, solidity inherently requires two bodies, along with closeness and force, which is a combination of elements that can't be captured by a simple impression. Not to mention, while solidity remains consistently the same, our sensations of touch change constantly, which clearly indicates that these sensations do not represent solidity.
Thus there is a direct and total opposition betwixt our reason and our senses; or more properly speaking, betwixt those conclusions we form from cause and effect, and those that persuade us of the continued and independent existence of body. When we reason from cause and effect, we conclude, that neither colour, sound, taste, nor smell have a continued and independent existence. When we exclude these sensible qualities there remains nothing in the universe, which has such an existence.
So there’s a complete and direct conflict between our reasoning and our senses; or more accurately, between the conclusions we draw based on cause and effect and those that convince us of the ongoing and independent existence of physical objects. When we reason from cause and effect, we conclude that color, sound, taste, and smell do not have an ongoing and independent existence. When we eliminate these sensory qualities, nothing in the universe remains that has such an existence.
SECT. V. OF THE IMMATERIALITY OF THE SOUL.
Having found such contradictions and difficulties in every system concerning external objects, and in the idea of matter, which we fancy so clear and determinate, We shall naturally expect still greater difficulties and contradictions in every hypothesis concerning our internal perceptions, and the nature of the mind, which we are apt to imagine so much more obscure, and uncertain. But in this we should deceive ourselves. The intellectual world, though involved in infinite obscurities, is not perplexed with any such contradictions, as those we have discovered in the natural. What is known concerning it, agrees with itself; and what is unknown, we must be contented to leave so.
Having discovered contradictions and challenges in every system regarding external objects and in the concept of matter, which we think is so clear-cut, we would naturally expect even greater difficulties and contradictions in any theory about our internal perceptions and the nature of the mind, which we tend to see as much more vague and uncertain. But in doing so, we would be mistaken. The intellectual realm, despite being filled with countless obscurities, is not troubled by the same kinds of contradictions we found in the natural world. What we do know about it is consistent with itself, and what remains unknown, we must accept as such.
It is true, would we hearken to certain philosophers, they promise to diminish our ignorance; but I am afraid it is at the hazard of running us into contradictions, from which the subject is of itself exempted. These philosophers are the curious reasoners concerning the material or immaterial substances, in which they suppose our perceptions to inhere. In order to put a stop to these endless cavils on both sides, I know no better method, than to ask these philosophers in a few words, What they mean by substance and inhesion? And after they have answered this question, it will then be reasonable, and not till then, to enter seriously into the dispute.
It's true that if we listen to some philosophers, they claim they can reduce our ignorance; however, I'm worried that it might lead us into contradictions that the topic itself is free from. These philosophers are the ones who get caught up in debating material versus immaterial substances, where they think our perceptions exist. To put an end to these endless arguments on both sides, I can't think of a better approach than to simply ask these philosophers what they mean by substance and inhesion. Only after they answer this question will it make sense to seriously engage in the debate.
This question we have found impossible to be answered with regard to matter and body: But besides that in the case of the mind, it labours under all the same difficulties, it is burthened with some additional ones, which are peculiar to that subject. As every idea is derived from a precedent impression, had we any idea of the substance of our minds, we must also have an impression of it; which is very difficult, if not impossible, to be conceived. For how can an impression represent a substance, otherwise than by resembling it? And how can an impression resemble a substance, since, according to this philosophy, it is not a substance, and has none of the peculiar qualities or characteristics of a substance?
We've found it impossible to answer this question regarding matter and physical bodies. Moreover, when it comes to the mind, it faces all the same challenges, along with some additional ones that are unique to that topic. Since every idea comes from a previous impression, if we had any idea of the substance of our minds, we would also need to have an impression of it; this is very difficult, if not impossible, to imagine. How can an impression represent a substance unless it resembles it? And how can an impression resemble a substance, given that, according to this philosophy, it is not a substance and lacks the specific qualities or characteristics of a substance?
But leaving the question of what may or may not be, for that other what actually is, I desire those philosophers, who pretend that we have an idea of the substance of our minds, to point out the impression that produces it, and tell distinctly after what manner that impression operates, and from what object it is derived. Is it an impression of sensation or of reflection? Is it pleasant, or painful, or indifferent? I Does it attend us at all times, or does it only return at intervals? If at intervals, at what times principally does it return, and by what causes is it produced?
But putting aside the question of what might be, let’s focus on what actually is. I want those philosophers who claim we understand the essence of our minds to identify the impression that creates it, and explain clearly how that impression works and where it comes from. Is it an impression from our senses or our thoughts? Is it enjoyable, bothersome, or neutral? Does it stay with us all the time, or does it come and go? If it comes and goes, when does it mostly return, and what triggers it?
If instead of answering these questions, any one should evade the difficulty, by saying, that the definition of a substance is something which may exist by itself; and that this definition ought to satisfy us: should this be said, I should observe, that this definition agrees to every thing, that can possibly be conceived; and never will serve to distinguish substance from accident, or the soul from its perceptions. For thus I reason. Whatever is clearly conceived may exist; and whatever is clearly conceived, after any manner, may exist after the same manner. This is one principle, which has been already acknowledged. Again, every thing, which is different, is distinguishable, and every thing which is distinguishable, is separable by the imagination. This is another principle. My conclusion from both is, that since all our perceptions are different from each other, and from every thing else in the universe, they are also distinct and separable, and may be considered as separately existent, and may exist separately, and have no need of any thing else to support their existence. They are, therefore, substances, as far as this definition explains a substance.
If someone tried to avoid these questions by saying that a substance is something that can exist on its own and that this definition should be enough for us, I would point out that this definition applies to everything that can be imagined and will never help us distinguish substance from accident or the soul from its perceptions. Here's my reasoning: anything that is clearly understood can exist, and anything that is clearly understood in one way can exist that way again. This is one principle we've already accepted. Furthermore, anything that is different can be distinguished, and anything that can be distinguished can be separated in our minds. This is another principle. Therefore, my conclusion is that since all our perceptions are different from one another and from everything else in the universe, they are also distinct and separable. They can be considered as existing on their own, can exist independently, and do not need anything else to support their existence. Thus, they are substances, at least according to this definition of substance.
Thus neither by considering the first origin of ideas, nor by means of a definition are we able to arrive at any satisfactory notion of substance; which seems to me a sufficient reason for abandoning utterly that dispute concerning the materiality and immateriality of the soul, and makes me absolutely condemn even the question itself. We have no perfect idea of any thing but of a perception. A substance is entirely different from a perception. We have, therefore, no idea of a substance. Inhesion in something is supposed to be requisite to support the existence of our perceptions. Nothing appears requisite to support the existence of a perception. We have, therefore, no idea of inhesion. What possibility then of answering that question, Whether perceptions inhere in a material or immaterial substance, when we do not so much as understand the meaning of the question?
So, by looking at the original source of ideas or by trying to define them, we still can’t reach a clear understanding of substance. This makes me think we should completely drop the argument about whether the soul is material or immaterial, and I actually reject even the question itself. We only have a clear idea of perceptions. A substance is completely different from a perception. Therefore, we have no idea of a substance. It’s assumed that some sort of support is needed for our perceptions to exist. But nothing seems to be necessary to support the existence of a perception. Thus, we have no idea of this supposed support. So, how can we possibly answer the question of whether perceptions belong to a material or immaterial substance when we don’t even understand the question?
There is one argument commonly employed for the immateriality of the soul, which seems to me remarkable. Whatever is extended consists of parts; and whatever consists of parts is divisible, if not in reality, at least in the imagination. But it is impossible anything divisible can be conjoined to a thought or perception, which is a being altogether inseparable and indivisible. For supposing such a conjunction, would the indivisible thought exist on the left or on the right hand of this extended divisible body? On the surface or in the middle? On the back or fore side of it? If it be conjoined with the extension, it must exist somewhere within its dimensions. If it exist within its dimensions, it must either exist in one particular part; and then that particular part is indivisible, and the perception is conjoined only with it, not with the extension: Or if the thought exists in every part, it must also be extended, and separable, and divisible, as well as the body; which is utterly absurd and contradictory. For can any one conceive a passion of a yard in length, a foot in breadth, and an inch in thickness? Thought, therefore, and extension are qualities wholly incompatible, and never can incorporate together into one subject.
One popular argument for the immateriality of the soul really stands out to me. Anything that has physical extension is made up of parts, and anything made up of parts can be divided, even if just in our minds. But it’s impossible for anything that can be divided to be linked to a thought or perception, which is something entirely inseparable and indivisible. If we assume such a connection exists, would the indivisible thought be positioned on the left or right side of this extended, divisible body? On the surface or in the middle? On the back or the front? If it’s connected to the extension, it has to exist somewhere within its dimensions. If it exists within those dimensions, it must exist in one specific part; in that case, that part is indivisible, and the perception is only connected to it, not to the whole extension. Or, if the thought exists in every part, it must also be extended, separable, and divisible, just like the body, which is completely absurd and contradictory. Can anyone really imagine a thought that measures a yard long, a foot wide, and an inch thick? Thus, thought and physical extension are completely incompatible qualities and can never merge into one subject.
This argument affects not the question concerning the substance of the soul, but only that concerning its local conjunction with matter; and therefore it may not be improper to consider in general what objects are, or are not susceptible of a local conjunction. This is a curious question, and may lead us to some discoveries of considerable moment.
This argument doesn't affect the issue of the soul's essence, but rather its physical connection with matter. So, it might be worthwhile to think about what objects can or cannot have a physical connection. This is an interesting question and could lead us to some important discoveries.
The first notion of space and extension is derived solely from the senses of sight and feeling; nor is there any thing, but what is coloured or tangible, that has parts disposed after such a manner, as to convey that idea. When we diminish or encrease a relish, it is not after the same manner that we diminish or encrease any visible object; and when several sounds strike our hearing at once, custom and reflection alone make us form an idea of the degrees of the distance and contiguity of those bodies, from which they are derived. Whatever marks the place of its existence either must be extended, or must be a mathematical point, without parts or composition. What is extended must have a particular figure, as square, round, triangular; none of which will agree to a desire, or indeed to any impression or idea, except to these two senses above-mentioned. Neither ought a desire, though indivisible, to be considered as a mathematical point. For in that case it would be possible, by the addition of others, to make two, three, four desires, and these disposed and situated in such a manner, as to have a determinate length, breadth and thickness; which is evidently absurd.
The first idea of space and extension comes only from our senses of sight and touch; nothing exists that isn't colored or tangible and has parts arranged in a way that conveys that idea. When we adjust our sense of taste, it's not the same as changing a visible object, and when multiple sounds reach our ears at once, it's only through experience and thought that we can grasp the degrees of distance and closeness of the sources they come from. Anything that indicates its place of existence must either be extended or be a mathematical point without parts or composition. What is extended must have a specific shape, like square, round, or triangular; none of these can relate to a desire or any impression or idea, except for those two senses mentioned earlier. A desire, even if it seems indivisible, shouldn’t be treated as a mathematical point. If it were, we could add desires together to create two, three, or four desires, arranged in such a way that they have a specific length, width, and thickness, which is clearly absurd.
It will not be surprising after this, if I deliver a maxim, which is condemned by several metaphysicians, and is esteemed contrary to the most certain principles of hum reason. This maxim is that an object may exist, and yet be no where: and I assert, that this is not only possible, but that the greatest part of beings do and must exist after this manner. An object may be said to be no where, when its parts are not so situated with respect to each other, as to form any figure or quantity; nor the whole with respect to other bodies so as to answer to our notions of contiguity or distance. Now this is evidently the case with all our perceptions and objects, except those of the sight and feeling. A moral reflection cannot be placed on the right or on the left hand of a passion, nor can a smell or sound be either of a circular or a square figure. These objects and perceptions, so far from requiring any particular place, are absolutely incompatible with it, and even the imagination cannot attribute it to them. And as to the absurdity of supposing them to be no where, we may consider, that if the passions and sentiments appear to the perception to have any particular place, the idea of extension might be derived from them, as well as from the sight and touch; contrary to what we have already established. If they APPEAR not to have any particular place, they may possibly exist in the same manner; since whatever we conceive is possible.
It won’t be surprising after this if I share a principle that several philosophers criticize and that seems to go against basic ideas of human reason. This principle is that an object can exist and yet be nowhere. I claim that this is not only possible but that most beings do and must exist in this way. An object can be said to be nowhere when its parts aren’t arranged in relation to each other to create any shape or size, nor is the whole arranged in relation to other bodies in a way that fits our ideas of closeness or distance. This clearly applies to all our perceptions and objects, except those we see and feel. A moral reflection can’t be placed to the right or left of a feeling, nor can a smell or sound have a circular or square shape. These objects and perceptions don’t require a specific location; in fact, they are completely incompatible with it, and even our imagination can’t assign a location to them. As for the absurdity of thinking they are nowhere, we might consider that if feelings and sentiments seem to have a specific location, the idea of extension might come from them just like it does from sight and touch, which goes against what we’ve already said. If they don’t seem to have a specific location, they could very well exist in the same way; since whatever we imagine is possible.
It will not now be necessary to prove, that those perceptions, which are simple, and exist no where, are incapable of any conjunction in place with matter or body, which is extended and divisible; since it is impossible to found a relation but on some common quality. It may be better worth our while to remark, that this question of the local conjunction of objects does not only occur in metaphysical disputes concerning the nature of the soul, but that even in common life we have every moment occasion to examine it. Thus supposing we consider a fig at one end of the table, and an olive at the other, it is evident, that in forming the complex ideas of these substances, one of the most obvious is that of their different relishes; and it is as evident, that we incorporate and conjoin these qualities with such as are coloured and tangible. The bitter taste of the one, and sweet of the other are supposed to lie in the very visible body, and to be separated from each other by the whole length of the table. This is so notable and so natural an illusion, that it may be proper to consider the principles, from which it is derived.
It isn't necessary anymore to prove that those perceptions which are simple and exist nowhere are unable to join with matter or bodies that are extended and divisible. This is because a relationship can only be based on some common quality. It might be more productive to point out that this question of the spatial relationship of objects not only comes up in metaphysical debates about the nature of the soul but also arises in our everyday lives. For example, if we look at a fig at one end of the table and an olive at the other, it's clear that when we form the complex ideas of these substances, one of the most obvious aspects is their different tastes. It's also clear that we combine and associate these qualities with those that are visible and tangible. The bitter taste of one and the sweet taste of the other are thought to exist in the visible bodies themselves, separated by the whole length of the table. This is such a notable and natural illusion that it’s worth considering the principles from which it arises.
Though an extended object be incapable of a conjunction in place with another, that exists without any place or extension, yet are they susceptible of many other relations. Thus the taste and smell of any fruit are inseparable from its other qualities of colour and tangibility; and whichever of them be the cause or effect, it is certain they are always co-existent. Nor are they only co-existent in general, but also co-temporary in their appearance in the mind; and it is upon the application of the extended body to our senses we perceive its particular taste and smell. These relations, then, of causation, and contiguity in the time of their appearance, betwixt the extended object and the quality, which exists without any particular place, must have such an effect on the mind, that upon the appearance of one it will immediately turn its thought to the conception of the other. Nor is this all. We not only turn our thought from one to the other upon account of their relation, but likewise endeavour to give them a new relation, viz. that of a CONJUNCTION IN PLACE, that we may render the transition more easy and natural. For it is a quality, which I shall often have occasion to remark in human nature, and shall explain more fully in its proper place, that when objects are united by any relation, we have a strong propensity to add some new relation to them, in order to compleat the union. In our arrangement of bodies we never fail to place such as are resembling, in contiguity to each other, or at least in correspondent points of view: Why? but because we feel a satisfaction in joining the relation of contiguity to that of resemblance, or the resemblance of situation to that of qualities. The effects this propensity have been[9] already observed in that resemblance, which we so readily suppose betwixt particular impressions and their external causes. But we shall not find a more evident effect of it, than in the present instance, where from the relations of causation and contiguity in time betwixt two objects, we feign likewise that of a conjunction in place, in order to strengthen the connexion.
Though a large object may not physically connect with another that has no distinct location or extension, they can still have many other relationships. For example, the taste and smell of a fruit are closely linked to its color and texture; regardless of which one causes the other, they consistently coexist. They not only coexist in general but also appear simultaneously in our minds; we perceive a fruit's specific taste and smell when it interacts with our senses. Therefore, the relationships of causation and simultaneous appearance between the extended object and the quality that exists without a specific location must impact our minds so that when one appears, we immediately think of the other. That's not all. We not only switch our thoughts between them because of their relationship, but we also try to create a new relationship, that of a CONNECTION IN PLACE, to make the transition smoother and more natural. This is a quality of human nature that I will discuss frequently and explain in detail later, which is that when objects are linked by any relationship, we have a strong tendency to add another relationship to complete the connection. In organizing objects, we always place similar ones next to each other or at least in corresponding viewpoints: Why? Because we find it satisfying to combine the relationship of proximity with that of similarity, or the similarity of location with that of qualities. The effects of this tendency have already been observed in the resemblance we readily assume between specific impressions and their external causes. However, we find no clearer example of it than in this case, where due to the relationships of causation and simultaneous appearance between two objects, we also imagine a connection in place to reinforce the link.
[9] Sect. 2, towards the end.
But whatever confused notions we may form of an union in place betwixt an extended body, as a fig, and its particular taste, it is certain that upon reflection we must observe this union something altogether unintelligible and contradictory. For should we ask ourselves one obvious question, viz. if the taste, which we conceive to be contained in the circumference of the body, is in every part of it or in one only, we must quickly find ourselves at a loss, and perceive the impossibility of ever giving a satisfactory answer. We cannot rely, that it is only in one part: For experience convinces us, that every part has the same relish. We can as little reply, that it exists in every part: For then we must suppose it figured and extended; which is absurd and incomprehensible. Here then we are influenced by two principles directly contrary to each other, viz. that inclination of our fancy by which we are determined to incorporate the taste with the extended object, and our reason, which shows us the impossibility of such an union. Being divided betwixt these opposite principles, we renounce neither one nor the other, but involve the subject in such confusion and obscurity, that we no longer perceive the opposition. We suppose, that the taste exists within the circumference of the body, but in such a manner, that it fills the whole without extension, and exists entire in every part without separation. In short, we use in our most familiar way of thinking, that scholastic principle, which, when crudely proposed, appears so shocking, of TOTUM IN TOTO & TOLUM IN QUALIBET PARTE: Which is much the same, as if we should say, that a thing is in a certain place, and yet is not there.
But whatever confused ideas we might have about how a body, like a fig, connects with its specific taste, it's clear that upon reflection, this connection seems completely unintelligible and contradictory. If we ask ourselves one obvious question, namely, whether the taste we think is contained in the whole body is found in every part of it or just in one section, we quickly realize we're at a loss and recognize the impossibility of providing a satisfying answer. We can't just say that it's only in one part because experience shows us that every part has the same flavor. And we also can't claim it exists in every part because that would imply it is shaped and extended, which is absurd and incomprehensible. Here, we are caught between two directly opposing ideas: our tendency to associate the taste with the physical object and our reason, which highlights the impossibility of such a union. Torn between these conflicting principles, we don't give up on either one, but instead, we muddle the subject into such confusion and ambiguity that we no longer see the contradiction. We assume that taste exists within the bounds of the body, but in such a way that it fills the whole thing without extending and is fully present in every part without separation. In short, in our everyday thinking, we apply that scholastic principle, which, when stated plainly, seems so shocking: TOTUM IN TOTO & TOLUM IN QUALIBET PARTE. This is very much like saying that something is in a specific place and yet is not there.
All this absurdity proceeds from our endeavouring to bestow a place on what is utterly incapable of it; and that endeavour again arises from our inclination to compleat an union, which is founded on causation, and a contiguity of time, by attributing to the objects a conjunction in place. But if ever reason be of sufficient force to overcome prejudice, it is certain, that in the present case it must prevail. For we have only this choice left, either to suppose that some beings exist without any place; or that they are figured and extended; or that when they are incorporated with extended objects, the whole is in the whole, and the whole in every part. The absurdity of the two last suppositions proves sufficiently the veracity of the first. Nor is there any fourth opinion. For as to the supposition of their existence in the manner of mathematical points, it resolves itself into the second opinion, and supposes, that several passions may be placed in a circular figure, and that a certain number of smells, conjoined with a certain number of sounds, may make a body of twelve cubic inches; which appears ridiculous upon the bare mentioning of it.
All this nonsense comes from our attempt to assign a place to something that is completely incapable of it; and that attempt comes from our desire to complete a union that is based on causation and a proximity in time by attributing a connection in space to the objects. But if reason ever has enough power to overcome bias, it must succeed in this case. We are left with only this choice: either to believe that some beings exist without any place; or that they are shaped and extended; or that when they are combined with extended objects, the whole is in the whole, and the whole is in every part. The absurdity of the last two options clearly supports the truth of the first. There isn’t a fourth option. The idea of their existence like mathematical points simply resolves into the second option and suggests that several feelings can be arranged in a circular shape, and that a certain number of smells, combined with a certain number of sounds, can create a body of twelve cubic inches; which sounds ridiculous just to say.
But though in this view of things we cannot refuse to condemn the materialists, who conjoin all thought with extension; yet a little reflection will show us equal reason for blaming their antagonists, who conjoin all thought with a simple and indivisible substance. The most vulgar philosophy informs us, that no external object can make itself known to the mind immediately, and without the interposition of an image or perception. That table, which just now appears to me, is only a perception, and all its qualities are qualities of a perception. Now the most obvious of all its qualities is extension. The perception consists of parts. These parts are so situated, as to afford us the notion of distance and contiguity; of length, breadth, and thickness. The termination of these three dimensions is what we call figure. This figure is moveable, separable, and divisible. Mobility, and separability are the distinguishing properties of extended objects. And to cut short all disputes, the very idea of extension is copyed from nothing but an impression, and consequently must perfectly agree to it. To say the idea of extension agrees to any thing, is to say it is extended.
But even though we can't help but criticize materialists for linking all thought to physical things, a bit of thought will show us that we have equal reason to criticize their opponents, who link all thought to a simple, indivisible substance. The most basic philosophy tells us that no outside object can be known to the mind directly, without the mediation of an image or perception. That table, which I see right now, is just a perception, and all its qualities are qualities of that perception. The most obvious quality is extension. The perception is made up of parts. These parts are arranged in a way that gives us the idea of distance and closeness; of length, width, and thickness. The edges of these three dimensions are what we call shape. This shape is movable, separable, and divisible. Movement and separability are the key features of extended objects. To settle all debates, the very idea of extension comes from nothing but an impression, and therefore must align perfectly with it. To say the idea of extension aligns with anything is to say it is extended.
The free-thinker may now triumph in his turn; and having found there are impressions and ideas really extended, may ask his antagonists, how they can incorporate a simple and indivisible subject with an extended perception? All the arguments of Theologians may here be retorted upon them. Is the indivisible subject, or immaterial substance, if you will, on the left or on the right hand of the perception? Is it in this particular part, or in that other? Is it in every part without being extended? Or is it entire in any one part without deserting the rest? It is impossible to give any answer to these questions, but what will both be absurd in itself, and will account for the union of our indivisible perceptions with an extended substance.
The free-thinker can now celebrate his victory; having discovered that there are tangible impressions and ideas, he may challenge his opponents by asking how they can connect a simple, indivisible subject with something that has an extended perception. All the arguments from theologians can be thrown back at them here. Is the indivisible subject, or immaterial substance, if you prefer, on the left side or the right side of perception? Is it in this specific part, or in another part? Is it in every part without being extended? Or is it whole in any one part without leaving out the rest? It’s impossible to provide any answer to these questions that wouldn’t be absurd in itself and explain the connection between our indivisible perceptions and an extended substance.
This gives me an occasion to take a-new into consideration the question concerning the substance of the soul; and though I have condemned that question as utterly unintelligible, yet I cannot forbear proposing some farther reflections concerning it. I assert, that the doctrine of the immateriality, simplicity, and indivisibility of a thinking substance is a true atheism, and will serve to justify all those sentiments, for which Spinoza is so universally infamous. From this topic, I hope at least to reap one advantage, that my adversaries will not have any pretext to render the present doctrine odious by their declamations, when they see that they can be so easily retorted on them.
This gives me a chance to rethink the question about the nature of the soul; and although I've dismissed that question as completely confusing, I can't resist sharing some additional thoughts on it. I argue that the belief in the immateriality, simplicity, and indivisibility of a thinking substance is actually a form of atheism, and it supports all the views for which Spinoza has become so widely criticized. From this discussion, I hope to gain at least one benefit: my opponents won’t have any grounds to make the current theory look bad through their arguments when they realize that they can be easily turned back on them.
The fundamental principle of the atheism of Spinoza is the doctrine of the simplicity of the universe, and the unity of that substance, in which he supposes both thought and matter to inhere. There is only one substance, says he, in the world; and that substance is perfectly simple and indivisible, and exists every where, without any local presence. Whatever we discover externally by sensation; whatever we feel internally by reflection; all these are nothing but modifications of that one, simple, and necessarily existent being, and are not possest of any separate or distinct existence. Every passion of the soul; every configuration of matter, however different and various, inhere in the same substance, and preserve in themselves their characters of distinction, without communicating them to that subject, in which they inhere. The same substratum, if I may so speak, supports the most different modifications, without any difference in itself; and varies them, without any variation. Neither time, nor place, nor all the diversity of nature are able to produce any composition or change in its perfect simplicity and identity.
The core idea of Spinoza's atheism is the belief in the simplicity of the universe and the unity of the substance in which he thinks both thought and matter exist. He claims there is only one substance in the world, which is completely simple and indivisible, and exists everywhere without being limited to a specific location. Everything we perceive externally through our senses and everything we feel internally through reflection are merely variations of that one simple and necessarily existing being, and do not have any separate or distinct existence. Every emotion of the soul and every arrangement of matter, no matter how different or diverse, exists within that same substance while maintaining their unique characteristics without transferring them to the substance itself. The same underlying entity, if I may put it that way, underpins the most varied modifications without any difference in itself and alters them without changing. Neither time nor space, nor all the variety found in nature can create any composition or change in its perfect simplicity and identity.
I believe this brief exposition of the principles of that famous atheist will be sufficient for the present purpose, and that without entering farther into these gloomy and obscure regions, I shall be able to shew, that this hideous hypothesis is almost the same with that of the immateriality of the soul, which has become so popular. To make this evident, let us[10] remember, that as every idea is derived from a preceding perception, it is impossible our idea of a perception, and that of an object or external existence can ever represent what are specifically different from each other. Whatever difference we may suppose betwixt them, it is still incomprehensible to us; and we are obliged either to conceive an external object merely as a relation without a relative, or to make it the very same with a perception or impression.
I think this brief overview of the principles of that well-known atheist will be enough for now, and that without diving deeper into these dark and obscure areas, I can show that this disturbing hypothesis is almost identical to the idea of the immateriality of the soul, which has become so popular. To make this clear, let us[10] remember that since every idea comes from a prior perception, it's impossible for our idea of a perception and that of an object or external existence to represent things that are fundamentally different from each other. No matter what differences we might imagine between them, it’s still beyond our understanding; we are forced to either think of an external object simply as a relationship without a relative or to consider it as exactly the same as a perception or impression.
[10] Part II, Sect. 6.
The consequence I shall draw from this may, at first sight, appear a mere sophism; but upon the least examination will be found solid and satisfactory. I say then, that since we may suppose, but never can conceive a specific deference betwixt an object and impression; any conclusion we form concerning the connexion and repugnance of impressions, will not be known certainly to be applicable to objects; but that on the other hand, whatever conclusions of this kind we form concerning objects, will most certainly be applicable to impressions. The reason is not difficult. As an object is supposed to be different from an impression, we cannot be sure, that the circumstance, upon which we found our reasoning, is common to both, supposing we form the reasoning upon the impression. It is still possible, that the object may differ from it in that particular. But when we first form our reasoning concerning the object, it is beyond doubt, that the same reasoning must extend to the impression: And that because the quality of the object, upon which the argument is founded, must at least be conceived by the mind; and could not be conceived, unless it were common to an impression; since we have no idea but what is derived from that origin. Thus we may establish it as a certain maxim, that we can never, by any principle, but by an irregular kind[11] of reasoning from experience, discover a connexion or repugnance betwixt objects, which extends not to impressions; though the inverse proposition may not be equally true, that all the discoverable relations of impressions are common to objects.
The conclusion I’m going to draw from this might seem like a simple trick at first, but if you look into it a little, you’ll see it’s solid and satisfying. I’m saying that since we can assume, but never fully grasp, a specific difference between an object and its impression, any conclusions we make about the connections and conflicts of impressions won’t definitely apply to objects. On the other hand, any conclusions we make about objects will definitely apply to impressions. The reason is pretty straightforward. Since we think of an object as being different from an impression, we can’t be sure that the basis for our reasoning is something both share, especially if our reasoning starts with the impression. It’s still possible that the object might differ in that specific way. But when we base our reasoning on the object first, it’s clear that the same reasoning must also apply to the impression. This is because the quality of the object, which our argument relies on, must at least be recognized by the mind; and it couldn’t be recognized unless it were shared with an impression, since all our ideas come from that source. Thus, we can establish it as a clear principle that we can never, through any standard approach but rather through an irregular kind of reasoning based on experience, discover a connection or conflict between objects that doesn’t also apply to impressions; although the reverse isn’t necessarily true, as not all the discoverable relationships of impressions are shared with objects.
[11] Such as that of Sect. 2, form the coherence of our perceptions.
[11] Like that of Sect. 2, shape the unity of our perceptions.
To apply this to the present case; there are two different systems of being presented, to which I suppose myself under necessity of assigning some substance, or ground of inhesion. I observe first the universe of objects or of body: The sun, moon and stars; the earth, seas, plants, animals, men, ships, houses, and other productions either of art or nature. Here Spinoza appears, and tells me, that these are only modifications; and that the subject, in which they inhere, is simple, incompounded, and indivisible. After this I consider the other system of beings, viz. the universe of thought, or my impressions and ideas. There I observe another sun, moon and stars; an earth, and seas, covered and inhabited by plants and animals; towns, houses, mountains, rivers; and in short every thing I can discover or conceive in the first system. Upon my enquiring concerning these, Theologians present themselves, and tell me, that these also are modifications, and modifications of one simple, uncompounded, and indivisible substance. Immediately upon which I am deafened with the noise of a hundred voices, that treat the first hypothesis with detestation and scorn, and the second with applause and veneration. I turn my attention to these hypotheses to see what may be the reason of so great a partiality; and find that they have the same fault of being unintelligible, and that as far as we can understand them, they are so much alike, that it is impossible to discover any absurdity in one, which is not common to both of them. We have no idea of any quality in an object, which does not agree to, and may not represent a quality in an impression; and that because all our ideas are derived from our impressions. We can never, therefore, find any repugnance betwixt an extended object as a modification, and a simple uncompounded essence, as its substance, unless that repugnance takes place equally betwixt the perception or impression of that extended object, and the same uncompounded essence. Every idea of a quality in an object passes through an impression; and therefore every perceivable relation, whether of connexion or repugnance, must be common both to objects and impressions.
To apply this to the current situation, there are two distinct systems being presented, and I feel the need to assign some substance or basis for their connection. I first look at the universe of objects or physical things: the sun, moon, stars, Earth, seas, plants, animals, humans, ships, houses, and all other creations, whether from nature or human effort. Here, Spinoza comes in and tells me that these are merely modifications, and the fundamental subject in which they exist is simple, uncompounded, and indivisible. Next, I consider the other system of being, which is the universe of thought, or my impressions and ideas. In this realm, I observe another sun, moon, stars, Earth, and seas filled and populated by plants and animals; towns, houses, mountains, rivers; in short, everything I can recognize or imagine from the first system. When I inquire about these, theologians emerge and tell me that these, too, are modifications of one simple, uncompounded, and indivisible substance. Immediately, I'm overwhelmed by the noise of a hundred voices that treat the first hypothesis with disdain and the second with admiration and reverence. I focus on these hypotheses to understand why there is such a strong bias, and I find that they share the same flaw of being hard to grasp, and that as far as we can understand them, they are so similar that it is impossible to identify any absurdity in one that doesn’t also apply to the other. We have no concept of any quality in an object that doesn’t also relate to a quality in an impression; this is because all our ideas come from our impressions. Therefore, we can never find any contradiction between an extended object as a modification and a simple, uncompounded essence as its substance, unless that contradiction also occurs between the perception or impression of that extended object and the same uncompounded essence. Every idea of a quality in an object goes through an impression; thus, every observable relationship, whether of connection or opposition, must be shared by both objects and impressions.
But though this argument, considered in general, seems evident beyond all doubt and contradiction, yet to make it more clear and sensible, let us survey it in detail; and see whether all the absurdities, which have been found in the system of Spinoza, may not likewise be discovered in that of Theologians.[12]
But even though this argument, when looked at broadly, seems completely clear and indisputable, let's break it down further and examine it in detail. We should see if all the absurdities identified in Spinoza's system can also be found in the system of theologians. [12]
[12] See Bayle's dictionary, article of Spinoza.
See Bayle's dictionary, article on Spinoza.
First, It has been said against Spinoza, according to the scholastic way of talking, rather than thinking, that a mode, not being any distinct or separate existence, must be the very same with its substance, and consequently the extension of the universe, must be in a manner identifyed with that, simple, uncompounded essence, in which the universe is supposed to inhere. But this, it may be pretended, is utterly impossible and inconceivable unless the indivisible substance expand itself, so as to correspond to the extension, or the extension contract itself, so as to answer to the indivisible substance. This argument seems just, as far as we can understand it; and it is plain nothing is required, but a change in the terms, to apply the same argument to our extended perceptions, and the simple essence of the soul; the ideas of objects and perceptions being in every respect the same, only attended with the supposition of a difference, that is unknown and incomprehensible.
First, it has been argued against Spinoza, using more of a scholastic talking style rather than clear thinking, that a mode, not being a distinct or separate existence, must be identical to its substance. Consequently, the universe's extension must, in a way, be the same as that simple, uncompounded essence in which the universe is thought to exist. However, one might claim that this is completely impossible and inconceivable unless the indivisible substance expands to match the extension, or the extension compresses to correspond to the indivisible substance. This argument seems reasonable, as far as we can grasp it, and it's clear that a change in terms is all that's needed to apply the same reasoning to our extended perceptions and the simple essence of the soul; the ideas of objects and perceptions are essentially the same but are accompanied by an assumption of a difference that is unknown and incomprehensible.
Secondly, It has been said, that we have no idea of substance, which is not applicable to matter; nor any idea of a distinct substance, which is not applicable to every distinct portion of matter. Matter, therefore, is not a mode but a substance, and each part of matter is not a distinct mode, but a distinct substance. I have already proved, that we have no perfect idea of substance; but that taking it for something, that can exist by itself, it is evident every perception is a substance, and every distinct part of a perception a distinct substance: And consequently the one hypothesis labours under the same difficulties in this respect with the other.
Secondly, it has been said that we have no concept of substance that doesn't relate to matter, nor do we have any idea of a distinct substance that doesn't relate to every separate piece of matter. Therefore, matter is not just a mode but a substance, and each part of matter is not just a distinct mode but a distinct substance. I have already shown that we don’t have a perfect understanding of substance; however, if we consider it as something that can exist on its own, it is clear that every perception is a substance, and every separate part of a perception is a distinct substance. Consequently, both theories face the same difficulties regarding this issue.
Thirdly, It has been objected to the system of one simple substance in the universe, that this substance being the support or substratum of every thing, must at the very same instant be modifyed into forms, which are contrary and incompatible. The round and square figures are incompatible in the same substance at the same time. How then is it possible, that the same substance can at once be modifyed into that square table, and into this round one? I ask the same question concerning the impressions of these tables; and find that the answer is no more satisfactory in one case than in the other.
Thirdly, people have raised objections to the idea of a single simple substance in the universe, arguing that since this substance serves as the foundation for everything, it must simultaneously take on forms that are contradictory and incompatible. Round and square shapes cannot coexist in the same substance at the same time. So, how can the same substance be shaped into both this square table and that round one at the same time? I have the same question about the impressions of these tables, and I find that the answer is just as unsatisfactory in both cases.
It appears, then, that to whatever side we turn, the same difficulties follow us, and that we cannot advance one step towards the establishing the simplicity and immateriality o the soul, without preparing the way for a dangerous and irrecoverable atheism. It is the same case, if instead o calling thought a modification of the soul, we should give it the more antient, and yet more modish name of an action. By an action we mean much the same thing, as what is commonly called an abstract mode; that is, something, which, properly speaking, is neither distinguishable, nor separable from its substance, and is only conceived by a distinction of reason, or an abstraction. But nothing is gained by this change of the term of modification, for that of action; nor do we free ourselves from one single difficulty by its means; as will appear from the two following reflexions.
It seems that no matter which way we turn, the same challenges keep following us, and we can’t make any progress in establishing the simplicity and immateriality of the soul without paving the way for a dangerous and irreversible atheism. The situation is the same if, instead of calling thought a modification of the soul, we give it the older yet trendier name of an action. By an action, we mean almost the same thing as what is commonly referred to as an abstract mode; that is, something that, strictly speaking, is neither distinguishable nor separable from its substance and is only understood through a distinction of reason or an abstraction. However, this change from the term modification to action doesn’t help us resolve any difficulties; as will become clear from the following two reflections.
First, I observe, that the word, action, according to this explication of it, can never justly be applied to any perception, as derived from a mind or thinking substance. Our perceptions are all really different, and separable, and distinguishable from each other, and from everything else, which we can imagine: and therefore it is impossible to conceive, how they can be the action or abstract mode of any substance. The instance of motion, which is commonly made use of to shew after what manner perception depends, as an action, upon its substance, rather confounds than instructs us. Motion to all appearance induces no real nor essential change on the body, but only varies its relation to other objects. But betwixt a person in the morning walking a garden with company, agreeable to him; and a person in the afternoon inclosed in a dungeon, and full of terror, despair, and resentment, there seems to be a radical difference, and of quite another kind, than what is produced on a body by the change of its situation. As we conclude from the distinction and separability of their ideas, that external objects have a separate existence from each other; so when we make these ideas themselves our objects, we must draw the same conclusion concerning them, according to the precedent reasoning. At least it must be confest, that having idea of the substance of the soul, it is impossible for us to tell how it can admit of such differences, and even contrarieties of perception without any fundamental change; and consequently can never tell in what sense perceptions are actions of that substance. The use, therefore, of the word, action, unaccompanyed with any meaning, instead of that of modification, makes no addition to our knowledge, nor is of any advantage to the doctrine of the immateriality of the soul.
First, I notice that the word "action," according to this explanation, can never accurately describe any perception that comes from a mind or thinking substance. Our perceptions are all genuinely different, separate, and distinguishable from each other and from everything else we can imagine. Therefore, it’s impossible to understand how they can be the action or abstract mode of any substance. The example of motion, often used to show how perception depends on its substance as an action, is more confusing than helpful. Motion, it seems, doesn’t actually change the body in any real or essential way; it just changes its relationship to other objects. However, between a person walking in a garden with friends in the morning and a person trapped in a dungeon in the afternoon, filled with fear, despair, and anger, there seems to be a fundamental difference of a different kind than what happens to a body due to a change in its position. Just as we conclude from the difference and separability of their ideas that external objects exist separately from one another, we must draw the same conclusion about these ideas themselves, following the same reasoning. At the very least, we must admit that when we have an idea of the substance of the soul, it’s impossible to explain how it can experience such differences and even oppositions in perception without any fundamental change; thus, we can never truly understand in what sense perceptions are actions of that substance. Therefore, the use of the word "action," without any specific meaning, instead of "modification," doesn’t enhance our understanding nor does it support the doctrine of the soul's immateriality.
I add in the second place, that if it brings any advantage to that cause, it must bring an equal to the cause of atheism. For do our Theologians pretend to make a monopoly of the word, action, and may not the atheists likewise take possession of it, and affirm that plants, animals, men, &c. are nothing but particular actions of one simple universal substance, which exerts itself from a blind and absolute necessity? This you'll say is utterly absurd. I own it is unintelligible; but at the same time assert, according to the principles above-explained, that it is impossible to discover any absurdity in the supposition, that all the various objects in nature are actions of one simple substance, which absurdity will not be applicable to a like supposition concerning impressions and ideas.
I also want to point out that if this supports one cause, it must equally support the cause of atheism. Do our theologians really think they have exclusive rights to the concepts and actions? Can't atheists also claim them and argue that plants, animals, humans, etc., are just specific actions of one simple, universal substance that operates out of blind and absolute necessity? You might say this is completely ridiculous. I agree it's hard to understand, but I also maintain, based on the principles I've explained, that it’s impossible to find any absurdity in the idea that all the different things in nature are actions of one simple substance, and that same absurdity would apply to similar ideas about impressions and thoughts.
From these hypotheses concerning the substance and local conjunction of our perceptions, we may pass to another, which is more intelligible than the former, and more important than the latter, viz. concerning the cause of our perceptions. Matter and motion, it is commonly said in the schools, however varyed, are still matter and motion, and produce only a difference in the position and situation of objects. Divide a body as often as you please, it is still body. Place it in any figure, nothing ever results but figure, or the relation of parts. Move it in any manner, you still find motion or a change of relation. It is absurd to imagine, that motion in a circle, for instance, should be nothing but merely motion in a circle; while motion in another direction, as in an ellipse, should also be a passion or moral reflection: That the shocking of two globular particles should become a sensation of pain, and that the meeting of two triangular ones should afford a pleasure. Now as these different shocks, and variations, and mixtures are the only changes, of which matter is susceptible, and as these never afford us any idea of thought or perception, it is concluded to be impossible, that thought can ever be caused by matter.
From these ideas about the nature and connection of our perceptions, we can move on to another idea that is clearer than the previous one and more significant than the latter, which concerns the cause of our perceptions. It’s often taught that matter and motion, no matter how varied, remain matter and motion, producing merely a difference in the arrangement and position of objects. No matter how many times you divide something, it’s still that thing. If you shape it differently, it still only shows shape or the relationship of its parts. If you move it in any way, all you observe is motion or a change in relationships. It’s unreasonable to think that moving in a circle is just that—a circular motion—while moving in another way, like in an ellipse, should somehow translate into a feeling or moral reflection: that the collision of two round particles would create a sensation of pain, while the collision of two triangle-shaped ones would result in pleasure. Since these different impacts, variations, and mixtures are the only changes matter can undergo, and since they never give us any idea of thought or perception, it leads to the conclusion that thought can never be caused by matter.
Few have been able to withstand the seeming evidence of this argument; and yet nothing in the world is more easy than to refute it. We need only reflect on what has been proved at large, that we are never sensible of any connexion betwixt causes and effects, and that it is only by our experience of their constant conjunction, we can arrive at any knowledge of this relation. Now as all objects, which are not contrary, are susceptible of a constant conjunction, and as no real objects are contrary;[13] I have inferred from these principles, that to consider the matter A PRIORI, any thing may produce any thing, and that we shall never discover a reason, why any object may or may not be the cause of any other, however great, or however little the resemblance may be betwixt them. This evidently destroys the precedent reasoning concerning the cause of thought or perception. For though there appear no manner of connexion betwixt motion or thought, the case is the same with all other causes and effects. Place one body of a pound weight on one end of a lever, and another body of the same weight on another end; you will never find in these bodies any principle of motion dependent on their distances from the center, more than of thought and perception. If you pretend, therefore, to prove a priori, that such a position of bodies can never cause thought; because turn it which way you will, it is nothing but a position of bodies; you must by the same course of reasoning conclude, that it can never produce motion; since there is no more apparent connexion in the one case than in the other. But as this latter conclusion is contrary to evident experience, and as it is possible we may have a like experience in the operations of the mind, and may perceive a constant conjunction of thought and motion; you reason too hastily, when from the mere consideration of the ideas, you conclude that it is impossible motion can ever produce thought, or a different position of parts give rise to a different passion or reflection. Nay it is not only possible we may have such an experience, but it is certain we have it; since every one may perceive, that the different dispositions of his body change his thoughts and sentiments. And should it be said, that this depends on the union of soul and body; I would answer, that we must separate the question concerning the substance of the mind from that concerning the cause of its thought; and that confining ourselves to the latter question we find by the comparing their ideas, that thought and motion are different from each other, and by experience, that they are constantly united; which being all the circumstances, that enter into the idea of cause and effect, when applied to the operations of matter, we may certainly conclude, that motion may be, and actually is, the cause of thought and perception.
Few have been able to withstand the apparent evidence of this argument; yet nothing in the world is easier to refute. We only need to think about what has been widely established: we are never aware of any connection between causes and effects, and it’s only through our experience of their constant association that we can gain any understanding of this relationship. Since all objects that are not opposites can be constantly associated, and since no real objects are opposites; [13] I have concluded from these principles that when considering the matter A PRIORI, anything can produce anything, and we will never find a reason why any object can or cannot be the cause of another, regardless of how similar or dissimilar they might be. This clearly undermines the previous reasoning regarding the cause of thought or perception. Although there seems to be no connection between motion and thought, the same is true for all other causes and effects. Place one body weighing a pound on one end of a lever and another body of the same weight on the other end; you will never find any principle of motion in these bodies that depends on their distances from the center, just as with thought and perception. Therefore, if you try to prove a priori that such a position of bodies can never cause thought—because however you position it, it’s just a position of bodies—you must, by the same reasoning, conclude that it can never produce motion, since there is no more apparent connection in one case than in the other. But since this latter conclusion contradicts evident experience, and since it is possible we may have a similar experience in the workings of the mind and may perceive a constant association of thought and motion, you are reasoning too quickly when you conclude that it’s impossible for motion to ever produce thought or that a different arrangement of parts cannot lead to different emotions or reflections. In fact, it’s not only possible to have such an experience, but it’s certain we do; as anyone can notice that different conditions of their body change their thoughts and feelings. And should someone argue that this relies on the union of soul and body, I would say we need to separate the question about the substance of the mind from that regarding the cause of its thoughts. When we focus on the latter question, we find by comparing their ideas that thought and motion are distinct from one another, and through experience, that they are consistently connected. Given that these are all the factors involved in the idea of cause and effect when applied to the workings of matter, we can confidently conclude that motion can be, and in fact is, the cause of thought and perception.
[13] Part III. Sect. 15.
There seems only this dilemma left us in the present case; either to assert, that nothing can be the cause of another, but where the mind can perceive the connexion in its idea of the objects: Or to maintain, that all objects, which we find constantly conjoined, are upon that account to be regarded as causes and effects. If we choose the first part of the dilemma, these are the consequences. First, We in reality affirm, that there is no such thing in the universe as a cause or productive principle, not even the deity himself; since our idea of that supreme Being is derived from particular impressions, none of which contain any efficacy, nor seem to have any connexion with any other existence. As to what may be said, that the connexion betwixt the idea of an infinitely powerful being, and that of any effect, which he wills, is necessary and unavoidable; I answer, that we have no idea of a being endowed with any power, much less of one endowed with infinite power. But if we will change expressions, we can only define power by connexion; and then in saying, that the idea, of an infinitely powerful being is connected with that of every effect, which he wills, we really do no more than assert, that a being, whose volition is connected with every effect, is connected with every effect: which is an identical proposition, and gives us no insight into the nature of this power or connexion. But, secondly, supposing, that the deity were the great and efficacious principle, which supplies the deficiency of all causes, this leads us into the grossest impieties and absurdities. For upon the same account, that we have recourse to him in natural operations, and assert that matter cannot of itself communicate motion, or produce thought, viz. because there is no apparent connexion betwixt these objects; I say, upon the very same account, we must acknowledge that the deity is the author of all our volitions and perceptions; since they have no more apparent connexion either with one another, or with the supposed but unknown substance of the soul. This agency of the supreme Being we know to have been asserted by[14] several philosophers with relation to all the actions of the mind, except volition, or rather an inconsiderable part of volition; though it is easy to perceive, that this exception is a mere pretext, to avoid the dangerous consequences of that doctrine. If nothing be active but what has an apparent power, thought is in no case any more active than matter; and if this inactivity must make us have recourse to a deity, the supreme being is the real cause of all our actions, bad as well as good, vicious as well as virtuous.
There seems to be only one dilemma left for us in this situation: either we claim that nothing can cause anything else unless the mind can see the connection in its idea of the objects, or we argue that all objects we consistently see together should be considered causes and effects. If we opt for the first part of the dilemma, here are the consequences. First, we would essentially be saying that there is no such thing in the universe as a cause or productive principle, not even the deity himself; since our understanding of that supreme Being comes from specific experiences, none of which carry any efficacy or appear to connect with any other existence. As for the argument that the connection between the idea of an infinitely powerful being and any effect he desires is necessary and unavoidable, I would reply that we have no idea of a being having any power, much less one with infinite power. However, if we change our wording, we can only define power by its connection; and by saying that the idea of an infinitely powerful being is linked to every effect he wills, we are really just asserting that a being whose will is connected to every effect is connected to every effect, which is a tautology and gives us no insight into the nature of this power or connection. Secondly, if we assume the deity is the great and effective principle that fills in the gaps of all causes, this leads us to grave impieties and absurdities. For just as we rely on him for natural processes and argue that matter cannot, on its own, create motion or produce thought—because there is no clear connection between these objects—I say we must also recognize that the deity is the source of all our desires and perceptions since they have no more evident connection with each other or with the assumed but unknown essence of the soul. This action of the supreme Being has been asserted by[14] several philosophers regarding all the actions of the mind, except for will or, rather, a trivial part of will; though it is easy to see that this exception is merely a pretext to avoid the troubling consequences of that belief. If nothing is active except what appears to have power, then thought is in no case more active than matter; and if this inactivity requires us to turn to a deity, the supreme being is the true cause of all our actions, both bad and good, both vicious and virtuous.
[14] As father Malebranche and other Cartesians.
As Father Malebranche and other Cartesians.
Thus we are necessarily reduced to the other side of the dilemma, viz.. that all objects, which are found to be constantly conjoined, are upon that account only to be regarded as causes and effects. Now as all objects, which are not contrary, are susceptible of a constant conjunction, and as no real objects are contrary: it follows, that for ought we can determine by the mere ideas, any thing may be the cause or effect of any thing; which evidently gives the advantage to the materialists above their antagonists.
Thus, we are inevitably led to the other side of the dilemma, which is that all objects that are found to be constantly connected should only be seen as causes and effects. Since all objects that are not opposing can be consistently joined, and since no real objects are opposing, it follows that based solely on our ideas, anything can be the cause or effect of anything else. This clearly gives an advantage to the materialists over their opponents.
To pronounce, then, the final decision upon the whole; the question concerning the substance of the soul is absolutely unintelligible: All our perceptions are not susceptible of a local union, either with what is extended or unextended: there being some of them of the one kind, and some of the other: And as the constant conjunction of objects constitutes the very essence of cause and effect, matter and motion may often be regarded as the causes of thought, as far as we have any notion of that relation.
To conclude with a final decision on the matter, the issue regarding the nature of the soul is completely unclear: none of our perceptions can be locally connected to what is either physical or non-physical, as we have some perceptions of one type and some of another. And since the regular association of objects forms the essence of cause and effect, matter and motion can often be seen as the causes of thought, at least to the extent that we have any understanding of that connection.
It is certainly a kind of indignity to philosophy, whose sovereign authority ought every where to be acknowledged, to oblige her on every occasion to make apologies for her conclusions, and justify herself to every particular art and science, which may be offended at her. This puts one in mind of a king arrainged for high-treason against his subjects. There is only one occasion, when philosophy will think it necessary and even honourable to justify herself, and that is, when religion may seem to be in the least offended; whose rights are as dear to her as her own, and are indeed the same. If any one, therefore, should imagine that the foregoing arguments are any ways dangerous to religion, I hope the following apology will remove his apprehensions.
It's definitely a kind of disrespect to philosophy, whose authority should be recognized everywhere, to force her to constantly apologize for her conclusions and defend herself to every specific art and science that might take offense. It reminds you of a king put on trial for treason against his subjects. There’s only one situation where philosophy will feel it’s necessary and even honorable to defend herself, and that’s when religion seems to be even slightly offended; its rights are just as important to her as her own, and they are truly the same. So, if anyone thinks that the previous arguments are in any way a threat to religion, I hope the following explanation eases their concerns.
There is no foundation for any conclusion a priori, either concerning the operations or duration of any object, of which it is possible for the human mind to form a conception. Any object may be imagined to become entirely inactive, or to be annihilated in a moment; and it is an evident principle, that whatever we can imagine, is possible. Now this is no more true of matter, than of spirit; of an extended compounded substance, than of a simple and unextended. In both cases the metaphysical arguments for the immortality of the soul are equally inconclusive: and in both cases the moral arguments and those derived from the analogy of nature are equally strong and convincing. If my philosophy, therefore, makes no addition to the arguments for religion, I have at least the satisfaction to think it takes nothing from them, but that every thing remains precisely as before.
There’s no basis for any conclusion made in advance, whether regarding the actions or lifespan of any object that the human mind can conceive. Any object can be imagined to become completely inactive or to be wiped out in an instant; and it’s a clear principle that whatever we can imagine is possible. This is just as true for matter as it is for spirit; for a complex substance as it is for a simple one. In both cases, the arguments for the soul's immortality are equally unconvincing: and in both cases, the moral arguments and those based on the analogy of nature are equally strong and persuasive. So, if my philosophy doesn’t add to the arguments for religion, I at least take satisfaction in knowing it doesn’t take anything away from them, and everything remains exactly the same as before.
SECT. VI. OF PERSONAL IDENTITY
There are some philosophers who imagine we are every moment intimately conscious of what we call our SELF; that we feel its existence and its continuance in existence; and are certain, beyond the evidence of a demonstration, both o its perfect identity and simplicity. The strongest sensation, the most violent passion, say they, instead of distracting us from this view, only fix it the more intensely, and make us consider their influence on self either by their pain or pleasure. To attempt a farther proof of this were to weaken its evidence; since no proof can be derived from any fact, of which we are so intimately conscious; nor is there any thing, of which we can be certain, if we doubt of this.
Some philosophers believe that we are always acutely aware of what we call our SELF; that we sense its existence and its ongoing presence; and that we are confident, beyond any need for proof, of its complete identity and simplicity. They argue that the strongest feelings or most intense emotions, rather than pulling us away from this awareness, actually draw us in deeper, prompting us to reflect on how they affect our sense of self, whether through pain or pleasure. Trying to provide further proof of this would actually undermine its clarity, since no evidence can come from a fact we are so closely aware of; and if we doubt this, then nothing else can be certain.
Unluckily all these positive assertions are contrary to that very experience, which is pleaded for them, nor have we any idea of self, after the manner it is here explained. For from what impression could this idea be derived? This question it is impossible to answer without a manifest contradiction and absurdity; and yet it is a question, which must necessarily be answered, if we would have the idea of self pass for clear and intelligible, It must be some one impression, that gives rise to every real idea. But self or person is not any one impression, but that to which our several impressions and ideas are supposed to have a reference. If any impression gives rise to the idea of self, that impression must continue invariably the same, through the whole course of our lives; since self is supposed to exist after that manner. But there is no impression constant and invariable. Pain and pleasure, grief and joy, passions and sensations succeed each other, and never all exist at the same time. It cannot, therefore, be from any of these impressions, or from any other, that the idea of self is derived; and consequently there is no such idea.
Unfortunately, all these positive claims contradict the very experience that supports them, and we have no clear concept of self as it is described here. What experience could possibly lead to this idea? It's impossible to answer this question without falling into clear contradiction and absurdity; yet, this question must be answered if we want the notion of self to be considered clear and understandable. It must stem from a single impression that generates every real idea. However, the self or person isn't just one impression but rather the reference point for all our various impressions and ideas. If any impression were to give rise to the idea of self, that impression would have to remain completely consistent throughout our lives since we assume the self exists in that way. But no impression is constant and unchanging. Pain and pleasure, grief and joy, emotions and sensations come one after the other and never all exist at the same time. Thus, it can't be from any of these impressions or any other that the idea of self originates; therefore, there is no such idea.
But farther, what must become of all our particular perceptions upon this hypothesis? All these are different, and distinguishable, and separable from each other, and may be separately considered, and may exist separately, and have no Deed of tiny thing to support their existence. After what manner, therefore, do they belong to self; and how are they connected with it? For my part, when I enter most intimately into what I call myself, I always stumble on some particular perception or other, of heat or cold, light or shade, love or hatred, pain or pleasure. I never can catch myself at any time without a perception, and never can observe any thing but the perception. When my perceptions are removed for any time, as by sound sleep; so long am I insensible of myself, and may truly be said not to exist. And were all my perceptions removed by death, and could I neither think, nor feel, nor see, nor love, nor hate after the dissolution of my body, I should be entirely annihilated, nor do I conceive what is farther requisite to make me a perfect non-entity. If any one, upon serious and unprejudiced reflection thinks he has a different notion of himself, I must confess I call reason no longer with him. All I can allow him is, that he may be in the right as well as I, and that we are essentially different in this particular. He may, perhaps, perceive something simple and continued, which he calls himself; though I am certain there is no such principle in me.
But further, what happens to all our specific perceptions based on this idea? Each of these is different, identifiable, and separate from one another, and can be considered individually, existing on their own without any small action to support their existence. So, how do they relate to the self, and how are they connected to it? Personally, when I examine what I refer to as myself, I always encounter some specific perception, whether it’s of heat or cold, light or darkness, love or hate, pain or pleasure. I can never find myself at any moment without a perception, and I can only observe perceptions. When my perceptions are absent for a time, like during deep sleep, I am unaware of myself and can truly be said not to exist. If all my perceptions were removed by death, and I couldn’t think, feel, see, love, or hate after my body disintegrates, I would be completely annihilated, and I don’t see what else is needed to make me a total non-entity. If anyone, after serious and unbiased consideration, believes they have a different understanding of themselves, I must admit that I can no longer reason with them. All I can concede is that they might be right, just as I am, and that we fundamentally differ in this regard. They might perceive something simple and continuous that they call themselves, although I am sure there is no such principle in me.
But setting aside some metaphysicians of this kind, I may venture to affirm of the rest of mankind, that they are nothing but a bundle or collection of different perceptions, which succeed each other with an inconceivable rapidity, and are in a perpetual flux and movement. Our eyes cannot turn in their sockets without varying our perceptions. Our thought is still more variable than our sight; and all our other senses and faculties contribute to this change; nor is there any single power of the soul, which remains unalterably the same, perhaps for one moment. The mind is a kind of theatre, where several perceptions successively make their appearance; pass, re-pass, glide away, and mingle in an infinite variety of postures and situations. There is properly no simplicity in it at one time, nor identity in different; whatever natural propension we may have to imagine that simplicity and identity. The comparison of the theatre must not mislead us. They are the successive perceptions only, that constitute the mind; nor have we the most distant notion of the place, where these scenes are represented, or of the materials, of which it is composed.
But putting aside some metaphysicians of this kind, I can confidently say that the rest of humanity is nothing more than a collection of different perceptions that come and go at an incredibly fast pace, constantly changing and moving. Our eyes can’t move without altering our perceptions. Our thoughts are even more changeable than our sight, and all our other senses and abilities contribute to this change. There’s no single aspect of the mind that stays the same, even for a moment. The mind is like a theater where different perceptions appear one after another, pass by, fade away, and mix in endless combinations and positions. At any given time, there’s really no simplicity or identity; despite our natural tendency to think there is. The theater comparison shouldn’t confuse us. It’s the shifting perceptions alone that make up the mind, and we don’t have the slightest idea of the place where these scenes occur or the substance of which it’s made.
What then gives us so great a propension to ascribe an identity to these successive perceptions, and to suppose ourselves possest of an invariable and uninterrupted existence through the whole course of our lives? In order to answer this question, we must distinguish betwixt personal identity, as it regards our thought or imagination, and as it regards our passions or the concern we take in ourselves. The first is our present subject; and to explain it perfectly we must take the matter pretty deep, and account for that identity, which we attribute to plants and animals; there being a great analogy betwixt it, and the identity of a self or person.
What makes us so inclined to attribute an identity to these ongoing perceptions and to believe we have a consistent and unbroken existence throughout our lives? To answer this question, we need to differentiate between personal identity as it relates to our thoughts or imagination and how it connects to our feelings or our concern for ourselves. The former is our current focus, and to fully explain it, we need to delve deeply into the topic and consider the identity that we assign to plants and animals; there is a strong similarity between this and the identity of a self or a person.
We have a distinct idea of an object, that remains invariable and uninterrupted through a supposed variation of time; and this idea we call that of identity or sameness. We have also a distinct idea of several different objects existing in succession, and connected together by a close relation; and this to an accurate view affords as perfect a notion of diversity, as if there was no manner of relation among the objects. But though these two ideas of identity, and a succession of related objects be in themselves perfectly distinct, and even contrary, yet it is certain, that in our common way of thinking they are generally confounded with each other. That action of the imagination, by which we consider the uninterrupted and invariable object, and that by which we reflect on the succession of related objects, are almost the same to the feeling, nor is there much more effort of thought required in the latter case than in the former. The relation facilitates the transition of the mind from one object to another, and renders its passage as smooth as if it contemplated one continued object. This resemblance is the cause of the confusion and mistake, and makes us substitute the notion of identity, instead of that of related objects. However at one instant we may consider the related succession as variable or interrupted, we are sure the next to ascribe to it a perfect identity, and regard it as enviable and uninterrupted. Our propensity to this mistake is so great from the resemblance above-mentioned, that we fall into it before we are aware; and though we incessantly correct ourselves by reflection, and return to a more accurate method of thinking, yet we cannot long sustain our philosophy, or take off this biass from the imagination. Our last resource is to yield to it, and boldly assert that these different related objects are in effect the same, however interrupted and variable. In order to justify to ourselves this absurdity, we often feign some new and unintelligible principle, that connects the objects together, and prevents their interruption or variation. Thus we feign the continued existence of the perceptions of our senses, to remove the interruption: and run into the notion of a soul, and self, and substance, to disguise the variation. But we may farther observe, that where we do not give rise to such a fiction, our propension to confound identity with relation is so great, that we are apt to imagine[15] something unknown and mysterious, connecting the parts, beside their relation; and this I take to be the case with regard to the identity we ascribe to plants and vegetables. And even when this does not take place, we still feel a propensity to confound these ideas, though we are not able fully to satisfy ourselves in that particular, nor find any thing invariable and uninterrupted to justify our notion of identity.
We have a clear idea of an object that stays the same and unchanged despite supposed changes over time; this idea is what we call identity or sameness. We also have a clear idea of several different objects existing one after another and closely related to each other, which gives us a perfect understanding of diversity, as if there were no connection among the objects. However, even though these two ideas of identity and the succession of related objects are completely distinct and even opposite, it's clear that in our everyday thinking, we usually confuse them. The way our imagination works, where we see the uninterrupted and unchanging object, is almost the same as when we think about the succession of related objects. There’s not much more effort involved in the latter than in the former. The connection helps our minds transition smoothly from one object to another, making it feel like we're looking at one continuous object. This similarity causes confusion and errors, leading us to substitute the idea of identity for that of related objects. Although we can sometimes view the related succession as changeable or interrupted, we will inevitably attribute perfect identity to it afterward and see it as consistent and uninterrupted. Our tendency to make this mistake is so strong, due to the aforementioned similarity, that we fall into it without realizing it; and even though we constantly correct ourselves through reflection and return to more accurate thinking, we can't maintain our philosophy for long or shake this bias from our imagination. Our last resort is to give in to it and boldly claim that these different related objects are essentially the same, no matter how inconsistent or changeable they are. To justify this absurdity to ourselves, we often create some new and incomprehensible principle that connects the objects and prevents their interruption or change. For instance, we imagine the continuous existence of our sensory perceptions to eliminate the gaps and cling to the ideas of a soul, self, and substance to mask the variation. Moreover, we notice that when we don’t create such fictions, our tendency to confuse identity with relation is so strong that we tend to imagine something unknown and mysterious linking the parts, beyond their relation; I believe this is true regarding the identity we attribute to plants and vegetables. Even when this doesn’t happen, we still feel a tendency to confuse these ideas, though we can’t fully satisfy ourselves on that point or find anything unchanging and uninterrupted to support our notion of identity.
[15] If the reader is desirous to see how a great genius may be influencd by these seemingly trivial principles of the imagination, as well as the mere vulgar, let him read my Lord SHAFTSBURY’S reasonings concerning the uniting principle of the universe, and the identity of plants and animals. See his MORALISTS: or, PHILOSOPHICAL RHAPSODY.
[15] If the reader wants to see how a brilliant mind can be shaped by these seemingly minor principles of imagination, just like ordinary people, they should check out Lord SHAFTSBURY’S ideas about the unifying principle of the universe and the similarities between plants and animals. See his MORALISTS: or, PHILOSOPHICAL RHAPSODY.
Thus the controversy concerning identity is not merely a dispute of words. For when we attribute identity, in an improper sense, to variable or interrupted objects, our mistake is not confined to the expression, but is commonly attended with a fiction, either of something invariable and uninterrupted, or of something mysterious and inexplicable, or at least with a propensity to such fictions. What will suffice to prove this hypothesis to the satisfaction of every fair enquirer, is to shew from daily experience and observation, that the objects, which are variable or interrupted, and yet are supposed to continue the same, are such only as consist of a succession of parts, connected together by resemblance, contiguity, or causation. For as such a succession answers evidently to our notion of diversity, it can only be by mistake we ascribe to it an identity; and as the relation of parts, which leads us into this mistake, is really nothing but a quality, which produces an association of ideas, and an easy transition of the imagination from one to another, it can only be from the resemblance, which this act of the mind bears to that, by which we contemplate one continued object, that the error arises. Our chief business, then, must be to prove, that all objects, to which we ascribe identity, without observing their invariableness and uninterruptedness, are such as consist of a succession of related objects.
The debate about identity isn't just a matter of words. When we incorrectly assign identity to objects that change or are disrupted, our error goes beyond just language. It typically involves imagining something constant and seamless, something mysterious and hard to explain, or at the very least, a tendency toward those fictions. To convince every fair-minded inquirer of this idea, we need to show from everyday experience that the objects we consider variable or interrupted—yet still believe to be the same—are actually made up of a series of parts that are linked by similarity, proximity, or causation. This succession clearly aligns with our understanding of diversity, so it's only a mistake that leads us to label it as identity. The connection between parts that causes this mistake is really just a quality that forms an association of ideas and makes it easy for our minds to move from one to another. This misunderstanding arises from the similarity in how our minds perceive one continuous object. Therefore, our main task is to demonstrate that all objects we attribute identity to—without recognizing their lack of consistency and continuity—are actually made up of a series of related objects.
In order to this, suppose any mass of matter, of which the parts are contiguous and connected, to be placed before us; it is plain we must attribute a perfect identity to this mass, provided all the parts continue uninterruptedly and invariably the same, whatever motion or change of place we may observe either in the whole or in any of the parts. But supposing some very small or inconsiderable part to be added to the mass, or subtracted from it; though this absolutely destroys the identity of the whole, strictly speaking; yet as we seldom think so accurately, we scruple not to pronounce a mass of matter the same, where we find so trivial an alteration. The passage of the thought from the object before the change to the object after it, is so smooth and easy, that we scarce perceive the transition, and are apt to imagine, that it is nothing but a continued survey of the same object.
To illustrate this, let’s consider a mass of matter where the parts are touching and connected. It's clear we must view this mass as having a perfect identity, as long as all its parts remain uninterrupted and unchanged, no matter how much it moves or shifts. However, if a tiny or insignificant part is added or taken away from the mass, even though this technically ruins the identity of the whole, we rarely think that precisely. We don’t hesitate to say that a mass of matter is the same even with such a minor change. The flow of thought from the object before the change to the object after it is so smooth and easy that we hardly notice the shift and tend to believe it's nothing but a continuous observation of the same object.
There is a very remarkable circumstance, that attends this experiment; which is, that though the change of any considerable part in a mass of matter destroys the identity of the whole, let we must measure the greatness of the part, not absolutely, but by its proportion to the whole. The addition or diminution of a mountain would not be sufficient to produce a diversity in a planet: though the change of a very few inches would be able to destroy the identity of some bodies. It will be impossible to account for this, but by reflecting that objects operate upon the mind, and break or interrupt the continuity of its actions not according to their real greatness, but according to their proportion to each other: And therefore, since this interruption makes an object cease to appear the same, it must be the uninterrupted progress o the thought, which constitutes the imperfect identity.
There’s a pretty interesting point that comes with this experiment; specifically, even though changing any significant part of a mass of matter destroys the identity of the whole, we need to measure how significant that part is not in absolute terms, but in relation to the whole. Adding or removing a mountain wouldn’t be enough to change a planet’s identity, while a change of just a few inches could completely alter the identity of some objects. We can’t fully explain this without considering that objects affect our minds and disrupt the continuity of our thoughts not based on their actual size, but on how they relate to each other. So, since this disruption makes something stop appearing the same, it’s the seamless flow of thought that creates this imperfect identity.
This may be confirmed by another phenomenon. A change in any considerable part of a body destroys its identity; but it is remarkable, that where the change is produced gradually and insensibly we are less apt to ascribe to it the same effect. The reason can plainly be no other, than that the mind, in following the successive changes of the body, feels an easy passage from the surveying its condition in one moment to the viewing of it in another, and at no particular time perceives any interruption in its actions. From which continued perception, it ascribes a continued existence and identity to the object.
This can be confirmed by another phenomenon. A significant change in any part of a body destroys its identity; however, it's interesting to note that when the change happens gradually and subtly, we are less likely to attribute the same effect to it. The reason is simply that the mind, in observing the gradual changes in the body, experiences a smooth transition from viewing its state at one moment to viewing it at another, and at no specific time notices any interruption in its actions. From this ongoing perception, it assigns a sense of continuous existence and identity to the object.
But whatever precaution we may use in introducing the changes gradually, and making them proportionable to the whole, it is certain, that where the changes are at last observed to become considerable, we make a scruple of ascribing identity to such different objects. There is, however, another artifice, by which we may induce the imagination to advance a step farther; and that is, by producing a reference of the parts to each other, and a combination to some common end or purpose. A ship, of which a considerable part has been changed by frequent reparations, is still considered as the same; nor does the difference of the materials hinder us from ascribing an identity to it. The common end, in which the parts conspire, is the same under all their variations, and affords an easy transition of the imagination from one situation of the body to another.
But no matter how carefully we introduce changes gradually, ensuring they are proportional to the whole, it’s clear that when those changes become significant, we hesitate to say that such different objects are the same. However, there's another tactic we can use to help our imagination take a further step, and that’s by creating a connection between the parts and combining them for a common goal or purpose. A ship, which has had much of its structure replaced through frequent repairs, is still regarded as the same ship; the difference in materials doesn’t stop us from seeing it as one entity. The shared goal of the parts is constant, even with their variations, making it easy for our imagination to shift from one state of the object to another.
But this is still more remarkable, when we add a sympathy of parts to their common end, and suppose that they bear to each other, the reciprocal relation of cause and effect in all their actions and operations. This is the case with all animals and vegetables; where not only the several parts have a reference to some general purpose, but also a mutual dependence on, and connexion with each other. The effect of so strong a relation is, that though every one must allow, that in a very few years both vegetables and animals endure a total change, yet we still attribute identity to them, while their form, size, and substance are entirely altered. An oak, that grows from a small plant to a large tree, is still the same oak; though there be not one particle of matter, or figure of its parts the same. An infant becomes a man-, and is sometimes fat, sometimes lean, without any change in his identity.
But this is even more remarkable when we consider the way their parts work together towards a common goal and assume that they have a mutual relationship of cause and effect in all their actions and functions. This applies to all animals and plants, where not only do the individual parts serve a general purpose, but they also depend on and connect with one another. The result of such a strong relationship is that, although everyone acknowledges that both plants and animals undergo a complete transformation in just a few years, we still recognize them as the same, even when their shape, size, and substance have entirely changed. An oak that grows from a small plant into a large tree is still considered the same oak, even though there isn't a single particle of matter or configuration of its parts that remains unchanged. An infant grows into a man and may sometimes be chubby or thin without losing his identity.
We may also consider the two following phaenomena, which are remarkable in their kind. The first is, that though we commonly be able to distinguish pretty exactly betwixt numerical and specific identity, yet it sometimes happens, that we confound them, and in our thinking and reasoning employ the one for the other. Thus a man, who bears a noise, that is frequently interrupted and renewed, says, it is still the same noise; though it is evident the sounds have only a specific identity or resemblance, and there is nothing numerically the same, but the cause, which produced them. In like manner it may be said without breach of the propriety of language, that such a church, which was formerly of brick, fell to ruin, and that the parish rebuilt the same church of free-stone, and according to modern architecture. Here neither the form nor materials are the same, nor is there any thing common to the two objects, but their relation to the inhabitants of the parish; and yet this alone is sufficient to make us denominate them the same. But we must observe, that in these cases the first object is in a manner annihilated before the second comes into existence; by which means, we are never presented in any one point of time with the idea of difference and multiplicity: and for that reason are less scrupulous in calling them the same.
We can also take a look at two notable phenomena. The first is that, although we usually can tell the difference between numerical and specific identity, sometimes we get them mixed up and use one in place of the other in our thinking and reasoning. For example, a person who hears a noise that is often interrupted and starts again may say it’s still the same noise, even though it’s clear that the sounds only have a specific identity or resemblance, and nothing is numerically the same except for the cause that produced them. Similarly, we can correctly say that a church that used to be made of brick fell into disrepair and that the parish rebuilt the same church using free-stone and modern architecture. Here, neither the form nor the materials are the same, and there’s nothing in common between the two objects except for their relationship to the parish residents; yet this is enough for us to call them the same. However, we need to note that in these cases, the first object is essentially gone before the second comes into being, which means we’re never faced with the idea of difference and multiplicity at any one moment in time. For this reason, we’re less particular about referring to them as the same.
Secondly, We may remark, that though in a succession of related objects, it be in a manner requisite, that the change of parts be not sudden nor entire, in order to preserve the identity, yet where the objects are in their nature changeable and inconstant, we admit of a more sudden transition, than would otherwise be consistent with that relation. Thus as the nature of a river consists in the motion and change of parts; though in less than four and twenty hours these be totally altered; this hinders not the river from continuing the same during several ages. What is natural and essential to any thing is, in a manner, expected; and what is expected makes less impression, and appears of less moment, than what is unusual and extraordinary. A considerable change of the former kind seems really less to the imagination, than the most trivial alteration of the latter; and by breaking less the continuity of the thought, has less influence in destroying the identity.
Secondly, we can note that although in a series of connected objects it’s necessary for the change of parts to be gradual and not complete in order to maintain identity, when the objects are inherently changeable and unstable, we can accept a more abrupt transition than would normally fit that relationship. For example, the essence of a river is in its flow and constant change of parts; even though these parts can completely change in less than twenty-four hours, this doesn't stop the river from being recognized as the same one over many years. What is natural and essential to something is somewhat expected, and what is expected makes a smaller impression and seems less significant than what is unusual and extraordinary. A significant change of the former type actually feels less impactful to the imagination than the smallest alteration of the latter type; and since it disrupts the continuity of thought less, it has a smaller effect on destroying the sense of identity.
We now proceed to explain the nature of personal identity, which has become so great a question ill philosophy, especially of late years in England, where all the abstruser sciences are studyed with a peculiar ardour and application. And here it is evident, the same method of reasoning must be continued which has so successfully explained the identity of plants, and animals, and ships, and houses, and of all the compounded and changeable productions either of art or nature. The identity, which we ascribe to the mind of man, is only a fictitious one, and of a like kind with that which we ascribe to vegetables and animal bodies. It cannot, therefore, have a different origin, but must proceed from a like operation of the imagination upon like objects.
We will now discuss the nature of personal identity, which has become such a significant question in philosophy, especially in recent years in England, where all the more complex sciences are studied with particular passion and dedication. Here, it’s clear that we must continue using the same reasoning that has successfully explained the identity of plants, animals, ships, houses, and all the complex and changing creations of both art and nature. The identity we attribute to the human mind is merely a fictional one, similar to what we attribute to plants and animals. Therefore, it cannot have a different origin; it must arise from a similar use of the imagination on similar objects.
But lest this argument should not convince the reader; though in my opinion perfectly decisive; let him weigh the following reasoning, which is still closer and more immediate. It is evident, that the identity, which we attribute to the human mind, however perfect we may imagine it to be, is not able to run the several different perceptions into one, and make them lose their characters of distinction and difference, which are essential to them. It is still true, that every distinct perception, which enters into the composition of the mind, is a distinct existence, and is different, and distinguishable, and separable from every other perception, either contemporary or successive. But, as, notwithstanding this distinction and separability, we suppose the whole train of perceptions to be united by identity, a question naturally arises concerning this relation of identity; whether it be something that really binds our several perceptions together, or only associates their ideas in the imagination. That is, in other words, whether in pronouncing concerning the identity of a person, we observe some real bond among his perceptions, or only feel one among the ideas we form of them. This question we might easily decide, if we would recollect what has been already proud at large, that the understanding never observes any real connexion among objects, and that even the union of cause and effect, when strictly examined, resolves itself into a customary association of ideas. For from thence it evidently follows, that identity is nothing really belonging to these different perceptions, and uniting them together; but is merely a quality, which we attribute to them, because of the union of their ideas in the imagination, when we reflect upon them. Now the only qualities, which can give ideas an union in the imagination, are these three relations above-mentioned. There are the uniting principles in the ideal world, and without them every distinct object is separable by the mind, and may be separately considered, and appears not to have any more connexion with any other object, than if disjoined by the greatest difference and remoteness. It is, therefore, on some of these three relations of resemblance, contiguity and causation, that identity depends; and as the very essence of these relations consists in their producing an easy transition of ideas; it follows, that our notions of personal identity, proceed entirely from the smooth and uninterrupted progress of the thought along a train of connected ideas, according to the principles above-explained.
But in case this argument doesn't persuade the reader, even though I believe it's completely convincing, let him consider the following reasoning, which is even more direct. It’s clear that the identity we attribute to the human mind, no matter how perfect we think it is, can't merge the various perceptions into one and make them lose their distinct and different characteristics, which are essential to them. It's still true that every distinct perception that enters the mind is a distinct existence and is different, distinguishable, and separable from every other perception, whether happening at the same time or one after the other. However, even though this distinction and separability exist, we assume that the entire flow of perceptions is united by identity. This raises a natural question about this relation of identity: is it something that truly connects our various perceptions together, or does it simply connect their ideas in our imagination? In other words, when we talk about a person's identity, are we recognizing some real bond among their perceptions, or are we just feeling a connection among the ideas we form about them? We could easily answer this question if we would remember what has already been discussed at length: that our understanding doesn't observe any real connection among objects and that even the connection between cause and effect, when closely examined, breaks down into a habitual association of ideas. Therefore, it clearly follows that identity is not something that really belongs to these different perceptions, connecting them together; it is merely a quality we assign to them due to the union of their ideas in our imagination when we reflect on them. The only qualities that can create a union of ideas in the imagination are the three relations mentioned above. These are the uniting principles in the ideal world, and without them, every distinct object is separable by the mind, can be considered separately, and seems to have no more connection with any other object than if separated by the greatest difference and distance. Thus, identity relies on one of these three relations: resemblance, contiguity, and causation; and since the essence of these relations consists in their facilitating a smooth transition of ideas, it follows that our concepts of personal identity arise entirely from the smooth and continuous flow of thought along a sequence of connected ideas, according to the principles explained above.
The only question, therefore, which remains, is, by what relations this uninterrupted progress of our thought is produced, when we consider the successive existence of a mind or thinking person. And here it is evident we must confine ourselves to resemblance and causation, and must drop contiguity, which has little or no influence in the present case.
The only question that remains is how the continuous development of our thoughts occurs when we think about the ongoing existence of a mind or a thinking person. It’s clear that we need to focus on resemblance and causation while leaving out contiguity, which doesn’t have much impact in this situation.
To begin with resemblance; suppose we could see clearly into the breast of another, and observe that succession of perceptions, which constitutes his mind or thinking principle, and suppose that he always preserves the memory of a considerable part of past perceptions; it is evident that nothing could more contribute to the bestowing a relation on this succession amidst all its variations. For what is the memory but a faculty, by which we raise up the images of past perceptions? And as an image necessarily resembles its object, must not. The frequent placing of these resembling perceptions in the chain of thought, convey the imagination more easily from one link to another, and make the whole seem like the continuance of one object? In this particular, then, the memory not only discovers the identity, but also contributes to its production, by producing the relation of resemblance among the perceptions. The case is the same whether we consider ourselves or others.
To start with resemblance, imagine we could clearly see into someone else's mind and observe the flow of perceptions that make up their thoughts. If we assume they retain memories of many past perceptions, it's clear that this memory helps establish a connection between all those varying perceptions. After all, what is memory if not the ability to recall images of past experiences? Since an image naturally resembles what it represents, doesn’t frequently encountering these similar perceptions in our thoughts help us transition more smoothly from one to the next and make everything feel like a continuation of a single concept? In this way, memory not only reveals identity but also helps create it by linking perceptions through resemblance. This applies to both ourselves and others.
As to causation; we may observe, that the true idea of the human mind, is to consider it as a system of different perceptions or different existences, which are linked together by the relation of cause and effect, and mutually produce, destroy, influence, and modify each other. Our impressions give rise to their correspondent ideas; said these ideas in their turn produce other impressions. One thought chaces another, and draws after it a third, by which it is expelled in its turn. In this respect, I cannot compare the soul more properly to any thing than to a republic or commonwealth, in which the several members are united by the reciprocal ties of government and subordination, and give rise to other persons, who propagate the same republic in the incessant changes of its parts. And as the same individual republic may not only change its members, but also its laws and constitutions; in like manner the same person may vary his character and disposition, as well as his impressions and ideas, without losing his identity. Whatever changes he endures, his several parts are still connected by the relation of causation. And in this view our identity with regard to the passions serves to corroborate that with regard to the imagination, by the making our distant perceptions influence each other, and by giving us a present concern for our past or future pains or pleasures.
Regarding causation, we can see that the true concept of the human mind is to think of it as a system of different perceptions or existences that are connected by the relationship of cause and effect, and that mutually create, destroy, influence, and modify each other. Our impressions lead to corresponding ideas; then these ideas, in turn, generate other impressions. One thought triggers another, leading to a third thought, which is then pushed out in its own time. In this sense, I think of the soul as similar to a republic or commonwealth, where the different members are connected by mutual ties of governance and hierarchy, and give rise to new individuals who continue the republic through constant changes in its components. Just as the same republic can not only change its members but also its laws and constitutions, the same person can alter their character and disposition, as well as their impressions and ideas, without losing their identity. No matter what changes they go through, their various parts remain linked by the relationship of causation. In this way, our identity concerning our emotions reinforces our identity regarding our imagination, as it makes our distant perceptions influence one another and creates a present concern for our past or future pains and pleasures.
As a memory alone acquaints us with the continuance and extent of this succession of perceptions, it is to be considered, upon that account chiefly, as the source of personal identity. Had we no memory, we never should have any notion of causation, nor consequently of that chain of causes and effects, which constitute our self or person. But having once acquired this notion of causation from the memory, we can extend the same chain of causes, and consequently the identity of car persons beyond our memory, and can comprehend times, and circumstances, and actions, which we have entirely forgot, but suppose in general to have existed. For how few of our past actions are there, of which we have any memory? Who can tell me, for instance, what were his thoughts and actions on the 1st of January 1715, the 11th of March 1719, and the 3rd of August 1733? Or will he affirm, because he has entirely forgot the incidents of these days, that the present self is not the same person with the self of that time; and by that means overturn all the most established notions of personal identity? In this view, therefore, memory does not so much produce as discover personal identity, by shewing us the relation of cause and effect among our different perceptions. It will be incumbent on those, who affirm that memory produces entirely our personal identity, to give a reason why we can thus extend our identity beyond our memory.
Since memory is what helps us understand the continuity and range of our experiences, it should be seen primarily as the foundation of personal identity. Without memory, we wouldn’t grasp the concept of causation, or the chain of causes and effects that constitute who we are. However, once we understand causation through memory, we can extend this chain and our identity beyond what we can remember, allowing us to recognize times, circumstances, and actions that we’ve completely forgotten but generally believe to have occurred. Just how few of our past actions can we actually remember? Who can recall their thoughts and actions on January 1, 1715, March 11, 1719, or August 3, 1733? Would someone argue that because they’ve completely forgotten the events of those days, their current self is not the same person they were back then, thereby challenging the well-established ideas of personal identity? From this perspective, memory doesn't create personal identity; it reveals it by showing us the connections of cause and effect among our various perceptions. Those who claim that memory entirely shapes our personal identity must explain how we can still extend our identity beyond what we remember.
The whole of this doctrine leads us to a conclusion, which is of great importance in the present affair, viz. that all the nice and subtile questions concerning personal identity can never possibly be decided, and are to be regarded rather as gramatical than as philosophical difficulties. Identity depends on the relations of ideas; and these relations produce identity, by means of that easy transition they occasion. But as the relations, and the easiness of the transition may diminish by insensible degrees, we have no just standard, by which we can decide any dispute concerning the time, when they acquire or lose a title to the name of identity. All the disputes concerning the identity of connected objects are merely verbal, except so fax as the relation of parts gives rise to some fiction or imaginary principle of union, as we have already observed.
The entire doctrine leads us to an important conclusion regarding this matter: that all the complicated and subtle questions about personal identity can never truly be resolved and should be seen more as grammatical rather than philosophical challenges. Identity relies on the relationships between ideas, and these relationships create identity through the smooth transitions they enable. However, as those relationships and the ease of transition might fade gradually, we lack a clear standard to resolve any arguments about when they gain or lose the label of identity. All disputes over the identity of connected objects are basically just verbal, except to the extent that the relationship of parts creates some fictional or imaginary principle of unity, as we've noted before.
What I have said concerning the first origin and uncertainty of our notion of identity, as applied to the human mind, may be extended with little or no variation to that of simplicity. An object, whose different co-existent parts are bound together by a close relation, operates upon the imagination after much the same manner as one perfectly simple and indivisible and requires not a much greater stretch of thought in order to its conception. From this similarity of operation we attribute a simplicity to it, and feign a principle of union as the support of this simplicity, and the center of all the different parts and qualities of the object.
What I’ve said about the initial origin and uncertainty of our idea of identity, as it relates to the human mind, can be applied similarly to the idea of simplicity. An object, whose various connected parts are closely related, affects our imagination in much the same way as a perfectly simple and indivisible object, and it doesn’t require much more effort to understand. Because of this similarity in how they operate, we assign a sense of simplicity to it and invent a unifying principle as the foundation of this simplicity, serving as the center for all the different parts and characteristics of the object.
Thus we have finished our examination of the several systems of philosophy, both of the intellectual and natural world; and in our miscellaneous way of reasoning have been led into several topics; which will either illustrate and confirm some preceding part of this discourse, or prepare the way for our following opinions. It is now time to return to a more close examination of our subject, and to proceed in the accurate anatomy of human nature, having fully explained the nature of our judgment and understandings.
Thus, we have completed our review of the various systems of philosophy, both about the intellectual and natural world; through our diverse reasoning, we've explored several topics that will either clarify and support some earlier parts of this discussion or set the stage for our upcoming thoughts. It's now time to return to a more detailed examination of our subject and continue with the precise analysis of human nature, having thoroughly explained the nature of our judgment and understanding.
SECT. VII. CONCLUSION OF THIS BOOK.
But before I launch out into those immense depths of philosophy, which lie before me, I find myself inclined to stop a moment in my present station, and to ponder that voyage, which I have undertaken, and which undoubtedly requires the utmost art and industry to be brought to a happy conclusion. Methinks I am like a man, who having struck on many shoals, and having narrowly escaped shipwreck in passing a small frith, has yet the temerity to put out to sea in the same leaky weather-beaten vessel, and even carries his ambition so far as to think of compassing the globe under these disadvantageous circumstances. My memory of past errors and perplexities, makes me diffident for the future. The wretched condition, weakness, and disorder of the faculties, I must employ in my enquiries, encrease my apprehensions. And the impossibility of amending or correcting these faculties, reduces me almost to despair, and makes me resolve to perish on the barren rock, on which I am at present, rather than venture myself upon that boundless ocean, which runs out into immensity. This sudden view of my danger strikes me with melancholy; and as it is usual for that passion, above all others, to indulge itself; I cannot forbear feeding my despair, with all those desponding reflections, which the present subject furnishes me with in such abundance.
But before I dive into those deep philosophical ideas ahead of me, I feel the urge to pause for a moment in my current position and think about the journey I’ve embarked on, which definitely requires all my skill and effort to end successfully. I feel like a guy who, after running aground on many hidden hazards and barely escaping a shipwreck while navigating a narrow channel, still has the nerve to head out to sea in the same old, leaky boat, even dreaming of circling the globe under these tough conditions. My memories of past mistakes and confusion make me hesitant about the future. The poor state, weakness, and disarray of the abilities I need for my inquiries heighten my worries. The impossibility of fixing or improving these abilities almost drives me to despair, making me consider staying put on the barren rock where I currently am rather than risk myself on that endless ocean that stretches into infinity. This sudden realization of my danger fills me with sadness; and as is typical for such feelings to do, I can’t help but feed my despair with all the gloomy thoughts that the current topic provides in such abundance.
I am first affrighted and confounded with that forelorn solitude, in which I am placed in my philosophy, and fancy myself some strange uncouth monster, who not being able to mingle and unite in society, has been expelled all human commerce, and left utterly abandoned and disconsolate. Fain would I run into the crowd for shelter and warmth; but cannot prevail with myself to mix with such deformity. I call upon others to join me, in order to make a company apart; but no one will hearken to me. Every one keeps at a distance, and dreads that storm, which beats upon me from every side. I have exposed myself to the enmity of all metaphysicians, logicians, mathematicians, and even theologians; and can I wonder at the insults I must suffer? I have declared my disapprobation of their systems; and can I be surprized, if they should express a hatred of mine and of my person? When I look abroad, I foresee on every side, dispute, contradiction, anger, calumny and detraction. When I turn my eye inward, I find nothing but doubt and ignorance. All the world conspires to oppose and contradict me; though such is my weakness, that I feel all my opinions loosen and fall of themselves, when unsupported by the approbation of others. Every step I take is with hesitation, and every new reflection makes me dread an error and absurdity in my reasoning.
I feel scared and overwhelmed by the loneliness of my thinking, imagining myself as some strange, awkward creature who can't fit in and has been totally kicked out of society, left all alone and heartbroken. I wish I could dive into the crowd for comfort and warmth, but I can’t bring myself to mix with such ugliness. I shout for others to join me, hoping to create a separate group, but no one listens. Everyone stays away, afraid of the storm that’s hitting me from all sides. I've put myself at odds with all the philosophers, logicians, mathematicians, and even theologians; can I be shocked by the insults I face? I've openly criticized their ideas; so why should I be surprised if they hate my views and me? When I look around, I see conflict, contradiction, anger, slander, and criticism everywhere. When I look within, all I find is doubt and ignorance. The whole world seems to conspire against me; yet I am so weak that I feel my beliefs shake and crumble when they aren't backed by others' approval. Every step I take is filled with hesitation, and each new thought makes me fear that I’ll be wrong or absurd in my reasoning.
For with what confidence can I venture upon such bold enterprises, when beside those numberless infirmities peculiar to myself, I find so many which are common to human nature? Can I be sure, that in leaving all established opinions I am following truth; and by what criterion shall I distinguish her, even if fortune should at last guide me on her foot-steps? After the most accurate and exact of my reasonings, I can give no reason why I should assent to it; and feel nothing but a strong propensity to consider objects strongly in that view, under which they appear to me. Experience is a principle, which instructs me in the several conjunctions of objects for the past. Habit is another principle, which determines me to expect the same for the future; and both of them conspiring to operate upon the imagination, make me form certain ideas in a more intense and lively manner, than others, which are not attended with the same advantages. Without this quality, by which the mind enlivens some ideas beyond others (which seemingly is so trivial, and so little founded on reason) we could never assent to any argument, nor carry our view beyond those few objects, which are present to our senses. Nay, even to these objects we could never attribute any existence, but what was dependent on the senses; and must comprehend them entirely in that succession of perceptions, which constitutes our self or person. Nay farther, even with relation to that succession, we could only admit of those perceptions, which are immediately present to our consciousness, nor could those lively images, with which the memory presents us, be ever received as true pictures of past perceptions. The memory, senses, and understanding are, therefore, all of them founded on the imagination, or the vivacity of our ideas.
How can I confidently take on such daring projects when, in addition to my countless personal weaknesses, I see so many that are common to all of humanity? Can I really be sure that by abandoning all accepted beliefs I'm actually pursuing the truth? And how will I recognize it, even if luck finally leads me to her path? After all my careful reasoning, I can’t explain why I should agree with it; instead, I feel a strong inclination to view things in the way they seem to me. Experience teaches me about the different connections between things from the past. Habit encourages me to expect the same in the future, and together, they influence my imagination, causing me to form certain ideas more vividly than others that don’t have the same benefits. Without this ability, by which the mind enhances some ideas over others (which seems so trivial and not very rational), we could never agree with any argument or look beyond the few things that our senses present to us. In fact, even regarding those things, we could only attribute existence to what depends on our senses and must understand them entirely as part of the flow of perceptions that make up our self or identity. Furthermore, even concerning that flow, we could only accept those perceptions that are immediately in our awareness, and those vivid images that memory gives us could never be taken as accurate representations of past perceptions. Thus, memory, senses, and understanding are all based on the imagination, or the liveliness of our ideas.
No wonder a principle so inconstant and fallacious should lead us into errors, when implicitly followed (as it must be) in all its variations. It is this principle, which makes us reason from causes and effects; and it is the same principle, which convinces us of the continued existence of external objects, when absent from the senses. But though these two operations be equally natural and necessary in the human mind, yet in some circumstances they are[16] directly contrary, nor is it possible for us to reason justly and regularly from causes and effects, and at the same time believe the continued existence of matter. How then shall we adjust those principles together? Which of them shall we prefer? Or in case we prefer neither of them, but successively assent to both, as is usual among philosophers, with what confidence can we afterwards usurp that glorious title, when we thus knowingly embrace a manifest contradiction?
It’s no surprise that such an unreliable and misleading principle leads us into mistakes when we follow it blindly in all its variations. This principle is what makes us reason from causes to effects, and it also convinces us that external objects continue to exist even when they’re not sensed. While both of these mental processes are equally natural and necessary, they can sometimes be directly opposed. It’s impossible for us to reason correctly and consistently from causes to effects while also believing in the ongoing existence of matter. So how do we reconcile these principles? Which one do we choose? Or if we choose neither and instead agree with both at different times, as philosophers often do, how can we confidently claim that title of being wise when we knowingly accept a clear contradiction?
[16] Sect. 4.
This contradiction[17] would be more excusable, were it compensated by any degree of solidity and satisfaction in the other parts of our reasoning. But the case is quite contrary. When we trace up the human understanding to its first principles, we find it to lead us into such sentiments, as seem to turn into ridicule all our past pains and industry, and to discourage us from future enquiries. Nothing is more curiously enquired after by the mind of man, than the causes of every phenomenon; nor are we content with knowing the immediate causes, but push on our enquiries, till we arrive at the original and ultimate principle. We would not willingly stop before we are acquainted with that energy in the cause, by which it operates on its effect; that tie, which connects them together; and that efficacious quality, on which the tie depends. This is our aim in all our studies and reflections: And how must we be disappointed, when we learn, that this connexion, tie, or energy lies merely in ourselves, and is nothing but that determination of the mind, which is acquired by custom, and causes us to make a transition from an object to its usual attendant, and from the impression of one to the lively idea of the other? Such a discovery not only cuts off all hope of ever attaining satisfaction, but even prevents our very wishes; since it appears, that when we say we desire to know the ultimate and operating principle, as something, which resides in the external object, we either contradict ourselves, or talk without a meaning.
This contradiction[17] would be more understandable if it was balanced by any sense of clarity and satisfaction in the other parts of our reasoning. But that's not the case at all. When we trace human understanding back to its fundamental principles, we find it leads us to ideas that seem to mock all our past efforts and discourage us from future inquiries. Nothing fascinates the human mind more than discovering the causes of every phenomenon; we’re not satisfied with just knowing the immediate causes but push our inquiries until we reach the original and ultimate principle. We don’t want to stop until we grasp that force in the cause that drives it to produce its effect; that connection that binds them together; and that effective quality that underpins that connection. This is our goal in all our studies and reflections. And how disappointed we must feel when we discover that this connection, tie, or force exists solely within us, a product of habit that leads us to jump from one object to its usual companion, and from the impression of one to the vivid idea of the other. Such a realization not only crushes any hope of ever achieving satisfaction but also thwarts our very desires; because it seems that when we claim to want to know the ultimate and operating principle as something that exists in the external object, we either contradict ourselves or speak without clarity.
[17] Part III. Sect. 14.
This deficiency in our ideas is not, indeed, perceived in common life, nor are we sensible, that in the most usual conjunctions of cause and effect we are as ignorant of the ultimate principle, which binds them together, as in the most unusual and extraordinary. But this proceeds merely from an illusion of the imagination; and the question is, how far we ought to yield to these illusions. This question is very difficult, and reduces us to a very dangerous dilemma, whichever way we answer it. For if we assent to every trivial suggestion of the fancy; beside that these suggestions are often contrary to each other; they lead us into such errors, absurdities, and obscurities, that we must at last become ashamed of our credulity. Nothing is more dangerous to reason than the flights of the imagination, and nothing has been the occasion of more mistakes among philosophers. Men of bright fancies may in this respect be compared to those angels, whom the scripture represents as covering their eyes with their wings. This has already appeared in so many instances, that we may spare ourselves the trouble of enlarging upon it any farther.
This lack of understanding in our thoughts isn't something we notice in everyday life, nor do we realize that in the most common cause-and-effect situations, we're just as clueless about the fundamental principle connecting them as we are in the rare and extraordinary cases. However, this is simply an illusion created by our imagination; the real question is how much we should let these illusions influence us. This question is quite challenging and places us in a very risky dilemma, regardless of how we respond. If we agree with every trivial whim of our imagination, not only are these whims often contradictory, but they also lead us into so many mistakes, absurdities, and confusions that we eventually feel embarrassed by our gullibility. There’s nothing more harmful to reason than the flights of the imagination, and nothing has caused more errors among philosophers. People with vibrant imaginations can be likened to the angels depicted in scripture as hiding their eyes with their wings. This has been demonstrated in so many examples that we need not elaborate further.
But on the other hand, if the consideration of these instances makes us take a resolution to reject all the trivial suggestions of the fancy, and adhere to the understanding, that is, to the general and more established properties of the imagination; even this resolution, if steadily executed, would be dangerous, and attended with the most fatal consequences. For I have already shewn,[18] that the understanding, when it acts alone, and according to its most general principles, entirely subverts itself, and leaves not the lowest degree of evidence in any proposition, either in philosophy or common life. We save ourselves from this total scepticism only by means of that singular and seemingly trivial property of the fancy, by which we enter with difficulty into remote views of things, and are not able to accompany them with so sensible an impression, as we do those, which are more easy and natural. Shall we, then, establish it for a general maxim, that no refined or elaborate reasoning is ever to be received? Consider well the consequences of such a principle. By this means you cut off entirely all science and philosophy: You proceed upon one singular quality of the imagination, and by a parity of reason must embrace all of them: And you expressly contradict yourself; since this maxim must be built on the preceding reasoning, which will be allowed to be sufficiently refined and metaphysical. What party, then, shall we choose among these difficulties? If we embrace this principle, and condemn all refined reasoning, we run into the most manifest absurdities. If we reject it in favour of these reasonings, we subvert entirely the human understanding. We have, therefore, no choice left but betwixt a false reason and none at all. For my part, know not what ought to be done in the present case. I can only observe what is commonly done; which is, that this difficulty is seldom or never thought of; and even where it has once been present to the mind, is quickly forgot, and leaves but a small impression behind it. Very refined reflections have little or no influence upon us; and yet we do not, and cannot establish it for a rule, that they ought not to have any influence; which implies a manifest contradiction.
But on the other hand, if thinking about these examples leads us to decide to ignore all the trivial suggestions of the imagination and stick only to our understanding—meaning the general and more established features of the mind—then even that decision, if consistently followed, could be dangerous and lead to the worst outcomes. I have already shown,[18] that when the understanding operates alone and strictly according to its most basic principles, it completely undermines itself and produces no solid evidence in any statement, whether in philosophy or everyday life. We escape this total skepticism only through that unique and seemingly trivial trait of the imagination, which makes it hard for us to grasp distant concepts, leaving them less impactful compared to those that are more immediate and straightforward. Should we then establish a general rule that no sophisticated or elaborate reasoning should be accepted? Think carefully about the implications of such a principle. By doing so, you entirely eliminate all science and philosophy. You focus on just one distinct quality of the imagination and must, by the same reasoning, accept all of them. And you contradict yourself outright; because this principle must be based on the previous reasoning, which will be recognized as sufficiently complex and philosophical. So, which option do we choose amid these challenges? If we adopt this principle and dismiss all sophisticated reasoning, we fall into clear absurdities. If we reject it in favor of these reasonings, we completely undermine human understanding. Therefore, we're left with no choice but between flawed reasoning and none at all. As for me, I don't know what should be done in this situation. I can only point out what is typically done: this difficulty is rarely considered, and even when it comes to mind, it's quickly forgotten, leaving only a faint impression. Very sophisticated thoughts have little to no effect on us, yet we can't establish as a rule that they shouldn't have any effect, which would clearly be a contradiction.
[18] Sect. 1.
But what have I here said, that reflections very refined and metaphysical have little or no influence upon us? This opinion I can scarce forbear retracting, and condemning from my present feeling and experience. The intense view of these manifold contradictions and imperfections in human reason has so wrought upon me, and heated my brain, that I am ready to reject all belief and reasoning, and can look upon no opinion even as more probable or likely than another. Where am I, or what? From what causes do I derive my existence, and to what condition shall I return? Whose favour shall I court, and whose anger must I dread? What beings surround me? and on whom have, I any influence, or who have any influence on me? I am confounded with all these questions, and begin to fancy myself in the most deplorable condition imaginable, invironed with the deepest darkness, and utterly deprived of the use of every member and faculty.
But what have I just said, that deep and philosophical thoughts have little or no impact on us? I can barely hold back from changing my mind and condemning this with my current feelings and experiences. The intense awareness of these many contradictions and flaws in human reasoning has really affected me and clouded my mind, making me ready to dismiss all beliefs and reasoning, unable to see any opinion as more probable or likely than any other. Where am I, or who am I? What causes have led to my existence, and to what state will I return? Whose favor should I seek, and whose anger should I fear? What beings are around me? Who do I have any influence over, and who has influence over me? I feel overwhelmed by all these questions and start to imagine myself in the most miserable situation possible, surrounded by complete darkness and completely unable to use any part of my mind or body.
Most fortunately it happens, that since reason is incapable of dispelling these clouds, nature herself suffices to that purpose, and cures me of this philosophical melancholy and delirium, either by relaxing this bent of mind, or by some avocation, and lively impression of my senses, which obliterate all these chimeras. I dine, I play a game of backgammon, I converse, and am merry with my friends; and when after three or four hours' amusement, I would return to these speculations, they appear so cold, and strained, and ridiculous, that I cannot find in my heart to enter into them any farther.
Fortunately, since reason can't clear away these clouds, nature steps in and helps me shake off this philosophical sadness and confusion. She either relaxes my mind or distracts me with vibrant experiences that wipe out all these illusions. I have dinner, play a game of backgammon, chat, and enjoy myself with my friends. And when, after three or four hours of fun, I try to return to these thoughts, they seem so unappealing, forced, and silly that I can't bring myself to engage with them any further.
Here then I find myself absolutely and necessarily determined to live, and talk, and act like other people in the common affairs of life. But notwithstanding that my natural propensity, and the course of my animal spirits and passions reduce me to this indolent belief in the general maxims of the world, I still feel such remains of my former disposition, that I am ready to throw all my books and papers into the fire, and resolve never more to renounce the pleasures of life for the sake of reasoning and philosophy. For those are my sentiments in that splenetic humour, which governs me at present. I may, nay I must yield to the current of nature, in submitting to my senses and understanding; and in this blind submission I shew most perfectly my sceptical disposition and principles. But does it follow, that I must strive against the current of nature, which leads me to indolence and pleasure; that I must seclude myself, in some measure, from the commerce and society of men, which is so agreeable; and that I must torture my brains with subtilities and sophistries, at the very time that I cannot satisfy myself concerning the reasonableness of so painful an application, nor have any tolerable prospect of arriving by its means at truth and certainty. Under what obligation do I lie of making such an abuse of time? And to what end can it serve either for the service of mankind, or for my own private interest? No: If I must be a fool, as all those who reason or believe any thing certainly are, my follies shall at least be natural and agreeable. Where I strive against my inclination, I shall have a good reason for my resistance; and will no more be led a wandering into such dreary solitudes, and rough passages, as I have hitherto met with.
Here I find myself completely and inevitably determined to live, speak, and act like everyone else in everyday life. However, despite my natural inclinations and the way my emotions and passions push me toward this lazy acceptance of the world’s common beliefs, I still feel remnants of my old self, which makes me want to throw all my books and papers into the fire and promise to never give up the joys of life for the sake of reasoning and philosophy. Those are my feelings in this gloomy mood that's dominating me right now. I may, or rather I must, go along with the flow of nature, submitting to my senses and understanding; and in this blind submission, I clearly show my skeptical nature and beliefs. But does it mean that I must fight against the current of nature, which draws me towards laziness and pleasure? Must I isolate myself from the enjoyable company of others, and torture my mind with complexities and arguments when I cannot even convince myself of the reasonableness of such a painful endeavor, nor do I see any reasonable chance of finding truth and certainty through it? Why should I waste my time like this? And what purpose could it serve for either humanity or my own interests? No: If I have to be a fool, as those who reason or believe anything certainly are, my foolishness will at least be natural and enjoyable. Where I go against my inclination, I'll have a good reason for my resistance; and I will no longer wander into the bleak loneliness and harsh paths I've encountered until now.
These are the sentiments of my spleen and indolence; and indeed I must confess, that philosophy has nothing to oppose to them, and expects a victory more from the returns of a serious good-humoured disposition, than from the force of reason and conviction. In all the incidents of life we ought still to preserve our scepticism. If we believe, that fire warms, or water refreshes, it is only because it costs us too much pains to think otherwise. Nay if we are philosophers, it ought only to be upon sceptical principles, and from an inclination, which we feel to the employing ourselves after that manner. Where reason is lively, and mixes itself with some propensity, it ought to be assented to. Where it does not, it never can have any title to operate upon us.
These are the feelings of my frustration and laziness; and honestly, I have to admit that philosophy has nothing to counter them and relies more on the benefits of a genuinely good-natured attitude than on the strength of reason and conviction. In all aspects of life, we should continue to maintain our skepticism. If we believe that fire provides warmth or water is refreshing, it's only because it's too much effort to think otherwise. Even if we are philosophers, it should only be based on skeptical principles and a natural inclination to engage with things this way. When reason is active and blends with some inclination, we should go along with it. If it doesn’t, it never has any right to influence us.
At the time, therefore, that I am tired with amusement and company, and have indulged a reverie in my chamber, or in a solitary walk by a river-side, I feel my mind all collected within itself, and am naturally inclined to carry my view into all those subjects, about which I have met with so many disputes in the course of my reading and conversation. I cannot forbear having a curiosity to be acquainted with the principles of moral good and evil, the nature and foundation of government, and the cause of those several passions and inclinations, which actuate and govern me. I am uneasy to think I approve of one object, and disapprove of another; call one thing beautiful, and another deformed; decide concerning truth and falshood, reason and folly, without knowing upon what principles I proceed. I am concerned for the condition of the learned world, which lies under such a deplorable ignorance in all these particulars. I feel an ambition to arise in me of contributing to the instruction of mankind, and of acquiring a name by my inventions and discoveries. These sentiments spring up naturally in my present disposition; and should I endeavour to banish them, by attaching myself to any other business or diversion, I feel I should be a loser in point of pleasure; and this is the origin of my philosophy.
At the time, when I am worn out from fun and company, and have indulged in daydreaming in my room or on a quiet walk by the river, I feel my mind coming together and I naturally want to explore all those topics I've encountered in debates during my reading and conversations. I'm curious about the principles of moral good and evil, the nature and foundation of government, and the reasons behind the various emotions and impulses that drive me. It makes me uneasy to realize that I approve of one thing and disapprove of another, to call one thing beautiful and another ugly, to judge truth and falsehood, reason and nonsense, without understanding the principles guiding my thoughts. I'm worried about the state of the learned world, which is stuck in such ignorance regarding all these matters. I feel a desire rising within me to contribute to the education of humanity and to earn recognition through my ideas and discoveries. These feelings come naturally to me in my current state; if I tried to push them away by engaging in other activities or distractions, I sense I would miss out on joy, and this is the origin of my philosophy.
But even suppose this curiosity and ambition should not transport me into speculations without the sphere of common life, it would necessarily happen, that from my very weakness I must be led into such enquiries. It is certain, that superstition is much more bold in its systems and hypotheses than philosophy; and while the latter contents itself with assigning new causes and principles to the phaenomena, which appear in the visible world, the former opens a world of its own, and presents us with scenes, and beings, and objects, which are altogether new. Since therefore it is almost impossible for the mind of man to rest, like those of beasts, in that narrow circle of objects, which are the subject of daily conversation and action, we ought only to deliberate concerning the choice of our guide, and ought to prefer that which is safest and most agreeable. And in this respect I make bold to recommend philosophy, and shall not scruple to give it the preference to superstition of every kind or denomination. For as superstition arises naturally and easily from the popular opinions of mankind, it seizes more strongly on the mind, and is often able to disturb us in the conduct of our lives and actions. Philosophy on the contrary, if just, can present us only with mild and moderate sentiments; and if false and extravagant, its opinions are merely the objects of a cold and general speculation, and seldom go so far as to interrupt the course of our natural propensities. The CYNICS are an extraordinary instance of philosophers, who from reasonings purely philosophical ran into as great extravagancies of conduct as any Monk or Dervise that ever was in the world. Generally speaking, the errors in religion are dangerous; those in philosophy only ridiculous.
But even if this curiosity and ambition don't lead me into ideas beyond the realm of everyday life, my own weaknesses would inevitably push me into such inquiries. It's clear that superstition is much bolder in its theories and ideas than philosophy; while the latter focuses on assigning new reasons and principles to the phenomena we see in the world, the former creates its own world, presenting us with completely new scenes, beings, and objects. Since it's almost impossible for the human mind to stay, like animals, within that limited circle of things that are part of our daily conversations and actions, we should only think about which guide to choose and opt for the one that is safest and most agreeable. In this regard, I confidently recommend philosophy and won't hesitate to prefer it over any kind of superstition. Superstition easily arises from popular beliefs and has a stronger grip on the mind, often disrupting how we live and act. In contrast, philosophy, if it's sound, offers us gentle and moderate thoughts; if it's false and extreme, its ideas are just subjects for cold, general speculation and rarely disrupt our natural inclinations. The CYNICS are a striking example of philosophers who, through purely philosophical reasoning, ended up in behaviors as extreme as any monk or mystic in history. Generally speaking, errors in religion are dangerous; those in philosophy are just silly.
I am sensible, that these two cases of the strength and weakness of the mind will not comprehend all mankind, and that there are in England, in particular, many honest gentlemen, who being always employed in their domestic affairs, or amusing themselves in common recreations, have carried their thoughts very little beyond those objects, which are every day exposed to their senses. And indeed, of such as these I pretend not to make philosophers, nor do I expect them either to be associates in these researches or auditors of these discoveries. They do well to keep themselves in their present situation; and instead of refining them into philosophers, I wish we could communicate to our founders of systems, a share of this gross earthy mixture, as an ingredient, which they commonly stand much in need of, and which would serve to temper those fiery particles, of which they are composed. While a warm imagination is allowed to enter into philosophy, and hypotheses embraced merely for being specious and agreeable, we can never have any steady principles, nor any sentiments, which will suit with common practice and experience. But were these hypotheses once removed, we might hope to establish a system or set of opinions, which if not true (for that, perhaps, is too much to be hoped for) might at least be satisfactory to the human mind, and might stand the test of the most critical examination. Nor should we despair of attaining this end, because of the many chimerical systems, which have successively arisen and decayed away among men, would we consider the shortness of that period, wherein these questions have been the subjects of enquiry and reasoning. Two thousand years with such long interruptions, and under such mighty discouragements are a small space of time to give any tolerable perfection to the sciences; and perhaps we are still in too early an age of the world to discover any principles, which will bear the examination of the latest posterity. For my part, my only hope is, that I may contribute a little to the advancement of knowledge, by giving in some particulars a different turn to the speculations of philosophers, and pointing out to them more distinctly those subjects, where alone they can expect assurance and conviction. Human Nature is the only science of man; and yet has been hitherto the most neglected. It will be sufficient for me, if I can bring it a little more into fashion; and the hope of this serves to compose my temper from that spleen, and invigorate it from that indolence, which sometimes prevail upon me. If the reader finds himself in the same easy disposition, let him follow me in my future speculations. If not, let him follow his inclination, and wait the returns of application and good humour. The conduct of a man, who studies philosophy in this careless manner, is more truly sceptical than that of one, who feeling in himself an inclination to it, is yet so overwhelmed with doubts and scruples, as totally to reject it. A true sceptic will be diffident of his philosophical doubts, as well as of his philosophical conviction; and will never refuse any innocent satisfaction, which offers itself, upon account of either of them.
I understand that these two examples of the mind's strengths and weaknesses won't cover everyone, and that in England, especially, there are many decent people who are constantly busy with their home lives or enjoying everyday pastimes, and as a result, their thoughts rarely go beyond those things that they encounter daily. Honestly, I don't expect to turn people like this into philosophers, nor do I expect them to join me in these explorations or even listen to these findings. They’re better off staying in their current state, and instead of trying to refine them into philosophers, I wish we could give our system founders a bit of this down-to-earth substance they really lack, which would help balance out the fiery ideas they typically hold. As long as a passionate imagination is allowed to influence philosophy and theories are accepted just because they're appealing and pleasing, we won’t have any solid principles or ideas that align with everyday practice and experience. However, if we could remove such theories, we might hope to establish a system of beliefs that, while not necessarily true (which may be too much to expect), could at least satisfy the human mind and withstand even the harshest scrutiny. We shouldn't feel discouraged by the many unrealistic theories that have come and gone, especially considering the short span of time these questions have been debated. Two thousand years, despite long breaks and significant challenges, is a brief period for achieving anything close to perfection in the sciences; we might still be living in an early age in the world to find principles that will hold up under future examination. Personally, I hope to contribute a bit to advancing knowledge by offering a fresh perspective on philosophers' ideas and clearly highlighting the topics where they can find certainty and understanding. Human Nature is the only true science of humanity, and yet it has been the most overlooked. It would be enough for me if I could make it a bit more fashionable; the hope of doing so helps keep me from despair and boosts me from the lethargy that sometimes takes over. If you, the reader, find yourself in a similar relaxed mindset, feel free to follow my upcoming explorations. If not, go with your instincts and wait for inspiration and good vibes to strike. A person studying philosophy nonchalantly is more genuinely skeptical than someone who feels drawn to it but is so burdened with doubts that they reject it entirely. A true skeptic will be unsure of both their doubts and their beliefs and won't shy away from any innocent pleasure that comes their way because of either.
Nor is it only proper we should in general indulge our inclination in the most elaborate philosophical researches, notwithstanding our sceptical principles, but also that we should yield to that propensity, which inclines us to be positive and certain in particular points, according to the light, in which we survey them in any particular instant. It is easier to forbear all examination and enquiry, than to check ourselves in so natural a propensity, and guard against that assurance, which always arises from an exact and full survey of an object. On such an occasion we are apt not only to forget our scepticism, but even our modesty too; and make use of such terms as these, it is evident, it is certain, it is undeniable; which a due deference to the public ought, perhaps, to prevent. I may have fallen into this fault after the example of others; but I here enter a caveat against any Objections, which may be offered on that head; and declare that such expressions were extorted from me by the present view of the object, and imply no dogmatical spirit, nor conceited idea of my own judgment, which are sentiments that I am sensible can become no body, and a sceptic still less than any other.
It’s not just right that we generally indulge our tendency to dive into complex philosophical studies, even with our skeptical beliefs, but we should also give in to that urge to be firm and sure about certain points, depending on how we see them in any given moment. It’s easier to avoid all investigation and questioning than to hold back from such a natural inclination and resist that confidence that comes from a thorough examination of something. In such moments, we tend to not only forget our skepticism but also our humility, using phrases like “it’s obvious,” “it’s certain,” or “it can’t be denied,” which we should probably avoid out of respect for the public. I might have made this mistake following others' examples; however, I’d like to caution against any objections that might arise from this. I declare that these expressions were prompted by my current view of the subject and do not reflect a dogmatic attitude or an inflated sense of my own judgment, feelings that I know don’t suit anyone, especially a skeptic less than anyone else.
SECT. I DIVISION OF THE SUBJECT
As all the perceptions of the mind may be divided into impressions and ideas, so the impressions admit of another division into original and secondary. This division of the impressions is the same with that which[1] I formerly made use of when I distinguished them into impressions of sensation and reflection. Original impressions or impressions of sensation are such as without any antecedent perception arise in the soul, from the constitution of the body, from the animal spirits, or from the application of objects to the external organs. Secondary, or reflective impressions are such as proceed from some of these original ones, either immediately or by the interposition of its idea. Of the first kind are all the impressions of the senses, and all bodily pains and pleasures: Of the second are the passions, and other emotions resembling them.
All the thoughts we have can be divided into impressions and ideas. Impressions can be further divided into original and secondary. This division is similar to the one I used before when I categorized them as impressions of sensation and reflection. Original impressions or impressions of sensation happen without any prior thoughts; they arise in the mind due to the body's make-up, the animal spirits, or when objects interact with our senses. Secondary, or reflective impressions, come from these original impressions, either directly or through the idea that they generate. The first type includes all sensory impressions, along with all physical pains and pleasures. The second type encompasses passions and other similar emotions.
It is certain, that the mind, in its perceptions, must begin somewhere; and that since the impressions precede their correspondent ideas, there must be some impressions, which without any introduction make their appearance in the soul. As these depend upon natural and physical causes, the examination of them would lead me too far from my present subject, into the sciences of anatomy and natural philosophy. For this reason I shall here confine myself to those other impressions, which I have called secondary and reflective, as arising either from the original impressions, or from their ideas. Bodily pains and pleasures are the source of many passions, both when felt and considered by the mind; but arise originally in the soul, or in the body, whichever you please to call it, without any preceding thought or perception. A fit of the gout produces a long train of passions, as grief, hope, fear; but is not derived immediately from any affection or idea. The reflective impressions may be divided into two kinds, viz. the calm and the VIOLENT. Of the first kind is the sense of beauty and deformity in action, composition, and external objects. Of the second are the passions of love and hatred, grief and joy, pride and humility. This division is far from being exact. The raptures of poetry and music frequently rise to the greatest height; while those other impressions, properly called PASSIONS, may decay into so soft an emotion, as to become, in a manner, imperceptible. But as in general the passions are more violent than the emotions arising from beauty and deformity, these impressions have been commonly distinguished from each other. The subject of the human mind being so copious and various, I shall here take advantage of this vulgar and spacious division, that I may proceed with the greater order; and having said all I thought necessary concerning our ideas, shall now explain those violent emotions or passions, their nature, origin, causes, and effects.
It's clear that the mind must start somewhere in its perceptions; and since impressions come before their corresponding ideas, there must be some impressions that appear in the soul without any prior thought. Because these depend on natural and physical causes, exploring them would take me too far from my current topic into the fields of anatomy and natural philosophy. For this reason, I will focus on the other types of impressions, which I've labeled secondary and reflective, arising either from the original impressions or from their ideas. Physical pains and pleasures lead to many passions, both when experienced and when contemplated by the mind; but they originate in the soul, or in the body—whichever term you prefer—without any preceding thought or perception. A gout attack can trigger a long series of emotions such as grief, hope, and fear, but it doesn't directly come from any feeling or idea. Reflective impressions can be categorized into two types: calm and VIOLENT. The first type includes the sense of beauty and ugliness in action, composition, and external objects. The second type encompasses the passions of love and hate, grief and joy, pride and humility. This classification is not exact. The ecstasies of poetry and music often reach incredible heights, while those other impressions, which we commonly refer to as PASSIONS, can diminish into such gentle emotions that they become almost undetectable. However, generally speaking, passions are more intense than the emotions stemming from beauty and ugliness, leading to these impressions typically being distinguished from one another. Given the extensive and varied nature of the human mind, I'll use this common and broad division to maintain better organization; having covered everything I deemed necessary about our ideas, I will now explain those intense emotions or passions, including their nature, origins, causes, and effects.
When we take a survey of the passions, there occurs a division of them into DIRECT and INDIRECT. By direct passions I understand such as arise immediately from good or evil, from pain or pleasure. By indirect such as proceed from the same principles, but by the conjunction of other qualities. This distinction I cannot at present justify or explain any farther. I can only observe in general, that under the indirect passions I comprehend pride, humility, ambition, vanity, love, hatred, envy, pity, malice, generosity, with their dependants. And under the direct passions, desire, aversion, grief, joy, hope, fear, despair and security. I shall begin with the former.
When we look at the passions, we can divide them into DIRECT and INDIRECT. By direct passions, I mean those that come directly from good or evil, pain or pleasure. Indirect passions arise from the same basic principles, but involve other qualities as well. I can't explain this distinction any further right now. I can only generally say that I include pride, humility, ambition, vanity, love, hatred, envy, pity, malice, and generosity, along with their related feelings, under the indirect passions. The direct passions include desire, aversion, grief, joy, hope, fear, despair, and security. I'll start with the former.
SECT. II OF PRIDE AND HUMILITY, THEIR OBJECTS AND CAUSES
The passions of PRIDE and HUMILITY being simple and uniform impressions, it is impossible we can ever, by a multitude of words, give a just definition of them, or indeed of any of the passions. The utmost we can pretend to is a description of them, by an enumeration of such circumstances, as attend them: But as these words, PRIDE and humility, are of general use, and the impressions they represent the most common of any, every one, of himself, will be able to form a just idea of them, without any danger of mistake. For which reason, not to lose time upon preliminaries, I shall immediately enter upon the examination of these passions.
The feelings of PRIDE and HUMILITY are straightforward and consistent, so it's impossible for us to provide a clear definition of them, or really any of the emotions, using a lot of words. The best we can do is describe them by listing the circumstances associated with them. However, since the terms PRIDE and HUMILITY are widely used, and the feelings they represent are among the most common, everyone can understand them correctly without much risk of confusion. For this reason, I won't waste time on introductions and will dive right into the analysis of these emotions.
It is evident, that pride and humility, though directly contrary, have yet the same OBJECT. This object is self, or that succession of related ideas and impressions, of which we have an intimate memory and consciousness. Here the view always fixes when we are actuated by either of these passions. According as our idea of ourself is more or less advantageous, we feel either of those opposite affections, and are elated by pride, or dejected with humility. Whatever other objects may be comprehended by the mind, they are always considered with a view to ourselves; otherwise they would never be able either to excite these passions, or produce the smallest encrease or diminution of them. When self enters not into the consideration, there is no room either for pride or humility.
It’s clear that pride and humility, even though they are completely opposite, focus on the same thing: the self, or that ongoing flow of connected thoughts and feelings that we deeply remember and are aware of. This is where our attention goes when we experience either of these emotions. Depending on whether we view ourselves in a more or less favorable light, we either feel pride and are uplifted, or we feel humility and are brought down. No matter what other subjects our minds may engage with, we always relate them back to ourselves; otherwise, they wouldn’t be able to trigger these feelings or change their intensity, even slightly. If self isn’t part of the equation, there’s no space for either pride or humility.
But though that connected succession of perceptions, which we call SELF, be always the object of these two passions, it is impossible it can be their CAUSE, or be sufficient alone to excite them. For as these passions are directly contrary, and have the same object in common; were their object also their cause; it could never produce any degree of the one passion, but at the same time it must excite an equal degree of the other; which opposition and contrariety must destroy both. It is impossible a man can at the same time be both proud and humble; and where he has different reasons for these passions, as frequently happens, the passions either take place alternately; or if they encounter, the one annihilates the other, as far as its strength goes, and the remainder only of that, which is superior, continues to operate upon the mind. But in the present case neither of the passions could ever become superior; because supposing it to be the view only of ourself, which excited them, that being perfectly indifferent to either, must produce both in the very same proportion; or in other words, can produce neither. To excite any passion, and at the same time raise an equal share of its antagonist, is immediately to undo what was done, and must leave the mind at last perfectly calm and indifferent.
But even though that ongoing stream of experiences, which we call SELF, is always the focus of these two emotions, it cannot be their CAUSE or be enough on its own to trigger them. Since these emotions are completely opposite and share the same focus, if their focus were also their cause, it could never produce one of the emotions without simultaneously triggering an equal degree of the other; this conflict and opposition would negate both. A person can't be both proud and humble at the same time; when they have different reasons for feeling these emotions, as often happens, the emotions either take turns or, if they clash, one cancels out the other based on its strength, and only the remaining portion of the stronger emotion continues to affect the mind. In this case, neither emotion could ever dominate because if it were just our own perception that triggered them, being totally neutral to either would lead to both being produced in equal measure; in other words, it could produce neither. To trigger one emotion while simultaneously elevating an equivalent amount of its opposite is essentially to reverse what was done, leaving the mind ultimately calm and indifferent.
We must therefore, make a distinction betwixt the cause and the object of these passions; betwixt that idea, which excites them, and that to which they direct their view, when excited. Pride and humility, being once raised, immediately turn our attention to ourself, and regard that as their ultimate and final object; but there is something farther requisite in order to raise them: Something, which is peculiar to one of the passions, and produces not both in the very same degree. The first idea, that is presented to the mind, is that of the cause or productive principle. This excites the passion, connected with it; and that passion, when excited, turns our view to another idea, which is that of self. Here then is a passion placed betwixt two ideas, of which the one produces it, and the other is produced by it. The first idea, therefore, represents the cause, the second the object of the passion.
We must therefore make a distinction between the cause and the object of these emotions; between the idea that triggers them and the one they focus on when stirred up. Once pride and humility are stirred, they immediately draw our attention to ourselves and see that as their ultimate goal; however, something more is needed to invoke them: something that is unique to one of the emotions and doesn’t produce both in the same way. The first idea that comes to mind is the cause or the productive principle. This triggers the related emotion, and that emotion, once activated, directs our focus to another idea, which is the idea of self. So, we have an emotion situated between two ideas, with one generating it and the other resulting from it. The first idea represents the cause, while the second represents the object of the emotion.
To begin with the causes of pride and humility; we may observe, that their most obvious and remarkable property is the vast variety of subjects, on which they may be placed. Every valuable quality of the mind, whether of the imagination, judgment, memory or disposition; wit, good-sense, learning, courage, justice, integrity; all these are the cause of pride; and their opposites of humility. Nor are these passions confined to the mind but extend their view to the body likewise. A man may be proud of his beauty, strength, agility, good mein, address in dancing, riding, and of his dexterity in any manual business or manufacture. But this is not all. The passions looking farther, comprehend whatever objects are in the least allyed or related to us. Our country, family, children, relations, riches, houses, gardens, horses, dogs, cloaths; any of these may become a cause either of pride or of humility.
To start with the reasons for pride and humility, we can see that their most obvious and striking characteristic is the wide range of subjects they can apply to. Every valuable quality of the mind—whether it's imagination, judgment, memory, or personality; wit, common sense, knowledge, courage, fairness, integrity—all of these can lead to pride, while their opposite qualities lead to humility. These feelings aren't limited to the mind but also include the body. A person might take pride in their appearance, strength, agility, good looks, skills in dancing, riding, and their ability to handle manual tasks. But that's not all. These feelings extend further to include anything that is in some way connected to us—our country, family, children, loved ones, wealth, houses, gardens, horses, dogs, clothing; any of these can become a source of either pride or humility.
From the consideration of these causes, it appears necessary we shoud make a new distinction in the causes of the passion, betwixt that QUALITY, which operates, and the subject, on which it is placed. A man, for instance, is vain of a beautiful house, which belongs to him, or which he has himself built and contrived. Here the object of the passion is himself, and the cause is the beautiful house: Which cause again is sub-divided into two parts, viz. the quality, which operates upon the passion, and the subject in which the quality inheres. The quality is the beauty, and the subject is the house, considered as his property or contrivance. Both these parts are essential, nor is the distinction vain and chimerical. Beauty, considered merely as such, unless placed upon something related to us, never produces any pride or vanity; and the strongest relation alone, without beauty, or something else in its place, has as little influence on that passion. Since, therefore, these two particulars are easily separated and there is a necessity for their conjunction, in order to produce the passion, we ought to consider them as component parts of the cause; and infix in our minds an exact idea of this distinction.
Considering these causes, it seems necessary to create a new distinction in the causes of passion, between the QUALITY that affects it and the subject it is directed toward. For example, a man is proud of a beautiful house he owns or has built himself. In this case, the object of the passion is himself, and the cause is the beautiful house. This cause can be further divided into two parts: the quality that influences the passion and the subject in which that quality exists. The quality is beauty, and the subject is the house, viewed as his property or creation. Both parts are essential, and the distinction is neither trivial nor imaginary. Beauty, in itself, does not generate pride or vanity unless it is associated with something connected to us; conversely, a strong connection without beauty, or something else occupying that role, has little effect on that passion. Therefore, since these two elements can be easily separated and their union is necessary to produce the passion, we should view them as essential parts of the cause and firmly grasp this distinction in our minds.
SECT. III WHENCE THESE OBJECTS AND CAUSES ARE DERIVED
Being so far advanced as to observe a difference betwixt the object of the passions and their cause, and to distinguish in the cause the quality, which operates on the passions, from the subject, in which it inheres; we now proceed to examine what determines each of them to be what it is, and assigns such a particular object, and quality, and subject to these affections. By this means we shall fully understand the origin of pride and humility.
Being so advanced that we can see a difference between the object of our emotions and their cause, and to identify in the cause the quality that affects our emotions, separate from the subject in which it exists; we will now explore what determines each of these to be what they are, and what assigns a specific object, quality, and subject to these feelings. This way, we will gain a complete understanding of the origins of pride and humility.
It is evident in the first place, that these passions are determined to have self for their object, not only by a natural but also by an original property. No one can doubt but this property is natural from the constancy and steadiness of its operations. It is always self, which is the object of pride and humility; and whenever the passions look beyond, it is still with a view to ourselves, nor can any person or object otherwise have any influence upon us.
It’s clear from the start that these emotions are focused on self, not just by nature but also by an inherent quality. No one can deny that this quality is natural due to the consistency and reliability of its actions. It's always ourselves that pride and humility are directed towards; whenever our emotions look elsewhere, it’s still in relation to us, and no person or thing can affect us in any other way.
That this proceeds from an original quality or primary impulse, will likewise appear evident, if we consider that it is the distinguishing characteristic of these passions Unless nature had given some original qualities to the mind, it could never have any secondary ones; because in that case it would have no foundation for action, nor could ever begin to exert itself. Now these qualities, which we must consider as original, are such as are most inseparable from the soul, and can be resolved into no other: And such is the quality, which determines the object of pride and humility. We may, perhaps, make it a greater question, whether the causes, that produce the passion, be as natural as the object, to which it is directed, and whether all that vast variety proceeds from caprice or from the constitution of the mind. This doubt we shall soon remove, if we cast our eye upon human nature, and consider that in all nations and ages, the same objects still give rise to pride and humility; and that upon the view even of a stranger, we can know pretty nearly, what will either encrease or diminish his passions of this kind. If there be any variation in this particular, it proceeds from nothing but a difference in the tempers and complexions of men; and is besides very inconsiderable. Can we imagine it possible, that while human nature remains the same, men will ever become entirely indifferent to their power, riches, beauty or personal merit, and that their pride and vanity will not be affected by these advantages?
That this comes from an original quality or primary impulse is also clear when we recognize that it’s the distinguishing feature of these emotions. If nature hadn’t given the mind some original qualities, it wouldn’t be able to have any secondary ones; without them, it wouldn’t have a basis for action and could never begin to exert itself. The qualities we consider original are those that are most tightly linked to the soul and can’t be broken down further. One such quality determines the object of pride and humility. We might even raise a bigger question: whether the causes that create these emotions are as natural as the objects they focus on, and whether all this vast variety comes from whim or from the structure of the mind. We can quickly clarify this doubt by looking at human nature, noting that throughout all nations and ages, the same objects consistently lead to pride and humility; even when observing a stranger, we can fairly accurately predict what will increase or decrease their feelings in these areas. If there is any variation, it’s simply due to differences in people’s temperaments and dispositions, and it’s fairly minor. Can we seriously think that while human nature stays the same, people will ever be completely indifferent to their power, wealth, beauty, or personal worth, and that their pride and vanity won’t be influenced by these advantages?
But though the causes of pride and humility be plainly natural, we shall find upon examination, that they are not original, and that it is utterly impossible they should each of them be adapted to these passions by a particular provision, and primary constitution of nature, Beside their prodigious number, many of them are the effects of art, and arise partly from the industry, partly from the caprice, and partly from the good fortune of men, Industry produces houses, furniture, cloaths. Caprice determines their particular kinds and qualities. And good fortune frequently contributes to all this, by discovering the effects that result from the different mixtures and combinations of bodies. It is absurd, therefore, to imagine, that each of these was foreseen and provided for by nature, and that every new production of art, which causes pride or humility; instead of adapting itself to the passion by partaking of some general quality, that naturally operates on the mind; is itself the object of an original principle, which till then lay concealed in the soul, and is only by accident at last brought to light. Thus the first mechanic, that invented a fine scritoire, produced pride in him, who became possest of it, by principles different from those, which made him proud of handsome chairs and tables. As this appears evidently ridiculous, we must conclude, that each cause of pride and humility is not adapted to the passions by a distinct original quality; but that there are some one or more circumstances common to all of them, on which their efficacy depends.
But even though the reasons for pride and humility are clearly natural, upon closer inspection, we’ll see that they aren’t inherent, and it’s completely unrealistic to think that each is specifically tailored to these emotions by some unique design or fundamental aspect of nature. Besides their overwhelming number, many of them result from human creativity, stemming partly from effort, partly from whim, and partly from good luck. Effort creates homes, furniture, and clothing. Whim determines their specific types and qualities. And good luck often plays a role by revealing the outcomes that come from different mixtures and combinations of materials. It’s absurd, then, to believe that each of these was anticipated and arranged for by nature, and that every new creation from human ingenuity that triggers pride or humility isn’t simply related to the emotion by sharing some general quality that naturally influences the mind; instead, it’s thought to be the result of an original principle that until then was hidden within the soul and is only brought to light by chance. For instance, the first craftsman who created a beautiful desk made someone who owned it feel pride through different principles than those that might inspire pride in stylish chairs and tables. Since this seems clearly ridiculous, we must conclude that each cause of pride and humility isn’t connected to the emotions by a distinct original quality; rather, there are one or more shared circumstances that all of them rely on for their effect.
Besides, we find in the course of nature, that though the effects be many, the principles, from which they arise, are commonly but few and simple, and that it is the sign of an unskilful naturalist to have recourse to a different quality, in order to explain every different operation. How much more must this be true with regard to the human mind, which being so confined a subject may justly be thought incapable of containing such a monstrous heap of principles, as would be necessary to excite the passions of pride and humility, were each distinct cause adapted to the passion by a distinct set of principles?
Also, in nature, we see that even though there are many effects, the principles behind them are usually just a few and simple. It’s a sign of an inexperienced naturalist to rely on different qualities to explain every distinct operation. This is even truer for the human mind, which is such a limited subject that it clearly can't hold a huge number of principles necessary to trigger the emotions of pride and humility if each distinct cause were tied to a separate set of principles.
Here, therefore, moral philosophy is in the same condition as natural, with regard to astronomy before the time of COPERNICUS. The antients, though sensible of that maxim, THAT NATURE DOES NOTHING IN VAIN, contrived such intricate systems of the heavens, as seemed inconsistent with true philosophy, and gave place at last to something more simple and natural. To invent without scruple a new principle to every new phænomenon, instead of adapting it to the old; to overload our hypotheses with a variety of this kind; are certain proofs, that none of these principles is the just one, and that we only desire, by a number of falsehoods, to cover our ignorance of the truth.
Here, moral philosophy is in a similar state to natural philosophy was before COPERNICUS in astronomy. The ancients, despite understanding the principle that NATURE DOES NOTHING IN VAIN, developed such complicated systems of the heavens that seemed at odds with genuine philosophy, eventually giving way to something simpler and more natural. To invent a new principle without hesitation for each new phenomenon, instead of aligning it with existing ones; to burden our theories with various ideas like this; are clear signs that none of these principles is the correct one, and that we are merely using a series of falsehoods to mask our ignorance of the truth.
SECT. IV OF THE RELATIONS OF IMPRESSIONS AND IDEAS
Thus we have established two truths without any obstacle or difficulty, that IT IS FROM NATURAL PRINCIPLES THIS VARIETY OF CAUSES EXCITES PRIDE AND HUMILITY, and that IT IS NOT BY A DIFFERENT PRINCIPLE EACH DIFFERENT CAUSE IS ADAPTED TO ITS PASSION. We shall now proceed to enquire how we may reduce these principles to a lesser number, and find among the causes something common, on which their influence depends.
Thus we have established two truths without any obstacles or difficulties: that it is from natural principles that this variety of causes inspires pride and humility, and that it is not by a different principle that each different cause is suited to its passion. We will now look into how we can simplify these principles to a smaller number and find something common among the causes on which their influence relies.
In order to this we must reflect on certain properties of human nature, which though they have a mighty influence on every operation both of the understanding and passions, are not commonly much insisted on by philosophers. The first of these is the association of ideas, which I have so often observed and explained. It is impossible for the mind to fix itself steadily upon one idea for any considerable time; nor can it by its utmost efforts ever arrive at such a constancy. But however changeable our thoughts may be, they are not entirely without rule and method in their changes. The rule, by which they proceed, is to pass from one object to what is resembling, contiguous to, or produced by it. When one idea is present to the imagination, any other, united by these relations, naturally follows it, and enters with more facility by means of that introduction.
To understand this, we need to think about certain aspects of human nature that, while they significantly affect both our understanding and emotions, aren’t often discussed by philosophers. The first of these is the association of ideas, which I've frequently mentioned and explained. It's impossible for the mind to focus on a single idea for very long; even with the greatest effort, it can't maintain that focus. However, even if our thoughts are quite changeable, they do follow some sort of pattern in their transitions. The pattern they follow is to move from one idea to something that is similar, nearby, or connected to it. When one idea comes to mind, another related idea naturally follows, making it easier to connect the two.
The second property I shall observe in the human mind is a like association of impressions. All resembling impressions are connected together, and no sooner one arises than the rest immediately follow. Grief and disappointment give rise to anger, anger to envy, envy to malice, and malice to grief again, till the whole circle be compleated. In like manner our temper, when elevated with joy, naturally throws itself into love, generosity, pity, courage, pride, and the other resembling affections. It is difficult for the mind, when actuated by any passion, to confine itself to that passion alone, without any change or variation. Human nature is too inconstant to admit of any such regularity. Changeableness is essential to it. And to what can it so naturally change as to affections or emotions, which are suitable to the temper, and agree with that set of passions, which then prevail? It is evident, then, there is an attraction or association among impressions, as well as among ideas; though with this remarkable difference, that ideas are associated by resemblance, contiguity, and causation; and impressions only by resemblance.
The second characteristic I’ll point out about the human mind is the way similar impressions are connected. When one impression comes up, the others quickly follow. Grief and disappointment lead to anger, which leads to envy, then to malice, and back to grief, completing the whole cycle. Similarly, when our mood is lifted by joy, it naturally transitions into love, generosity, pity, courage, pride, and other related feelings. It’s hard for the mind, when driven by any strong emotion, to stick to just that one feeling without any shift or change. Human nature is too unpredictable to allow for that kind of consistency. Changeability is part of our makeup. And what better way to change than to feelings or emotions that fit our mood and match the prevailing passions? Therefore, it’s clear that there is a connection or association among impressions, just as there is with ideas; however, the key difference is that ideas link through similarity, proximity, and cause, while impressions only link through similarity.
In the THIRD place, it is observable of these two kinds of association, that they very much assist and forward each other, and that the transition is more easily made where they both concur in the same object. Thus a man, who, by any injury from another, is very much discomposed and ruffled in his temper, is apt to find a hundred subjects of discontent, impatience, fear, and other uneasy passions; especially if he can discover these subjects in or near the person, who was the cause of his first passion. Those principles, which forward the transition of ideas, here concur with those, which operate on the passions; and both uniting in one action, bestow on the mind a double impulse. The new passion, therefore, must arise with so much greater violence, and the transition to it must be rendered so much more easy and natural.
In the third place, it's noticeable that these two types of associations really help each other and that the switch between them is much easier when they both focus on the same thing. For instance, a person who feels upset and agitated due to an injury from someone else tends to find a hundred reasons to feel discontent, impatient, fearful, and other unpleasant emotions, especially if he can identify those reasons in or around the person who caused his initial feelings. The principles that facilitate the flow of ideas work together with those that affect emotions, and when they come together in one action, they give the mind a stronger push. As a result, the new emotion can arise much more intensely, and the shift to it becomes much easier and more natural.
Upon this occasion I may cite the authority of an elegant writer, who expresses himself in the following manner.
On this occasion, I can reference an elegant writer who puts it this way.
"As the fancy delights in every thing that is great, strange, or beautiful, and is still more pleased the more it finds of these perfections in the same object, so it is capable of receiving a new satisfaction by the assistance of another sense. Thus any continued sound, as the music of birds, or a fall of waters, awakens every moment the mind of the beholder, and makes him more attentive to the several beauties of the place, that lie before him. Thus if there arises a fragrancy of smells or perfumes, they heighten the pleasure of the imagination, and make even the colours and verdure of the landschape appear more agreeable; for the ideas of both senses recommend each other, and are pleasanter together than when they enter the mind separately: As the different colours of a picture, when they are well disposed, set off one another, and receive an additional beauty from the advantage of the situation."[2] In this phænomenon we may remark the association both of impressions and ideas, as well as the mutual assistance they lend each other.
"As the fancy enjoys everything that is grand, unusual, or beautiful, and finds even greater pleasure the more of these qualities it encounters in the same object, it is also capable of gaining new satisfaction through another sense. For instance, any continuous sound, like birdsong or flowing water, engages the mind of the observer and makes them more aware of the various beauties in their surroundings. Similarly, if there is a pleasant fragrance or scent, it enhances the pleasure of the imagination and makes the colors and greenery of the landscape appear more appealing; because the perceptions of both senses complement each other and are more enjoyable together than when they are experienced alone: Like the different colors in a painting that, when arranged well, enhance one another and gain added beauty from their positioning."[2] In this phenomenon, we can observe the connection between impressions and ideas, as well as the mutual support they provide each other.
[2] Addison, SPECTATOR 412, final paragraph.
SECT. V OF THE INFLUENCE OF THESE RELATIONS ON PRIDE AND HUMILITY.
These principles being established on unquestionable experience, I begin to consider how we shall apply them, by revolving over all the causes of pride and humility, whether these causes be regarded, as the qualities, that operate, or as the subjects, on which the qualities are placed. In examining these qualities I immediately find many of them to concur in producing the sensation of pain and pleasure, independent of those affections, which I here endeavour to explain. Thus the beauty of our person, of itself, and by its very appearance, gives pleasure, as well as pride; and its deformity, pain as well as humility. A magnificent feast delights us, and a sordid one displeases. What I discover to be true in some instances, I suppose to be so in all; and take it for granted at present, without any farther proof, that every cause of pride, by its peculiar qualities, produces a separate pleasure, and of humility a separate uneasiness.
These principles are based on undeniable experience, so I’ll start considering how we can apply them by looking at all the reasons for pride and humility, whether we see these reasons as the qualities that act or as the subjects on which those qualities are placed. While examining these qualities, I immediately notice that many of them lead to feelings of pain and pleasure, separate from the emotions I’m trying to explain here. For instance, our physical attractiveness, in itself and just by being seen, brings pleasure and also pride; whereas its unattractiveness brings pain and humility. A lavish feast brings us joy, while a meager one brings disappointment. What I find to be true in some cases, I assume is true in all; and for now, I take it for granted, without further evidence, that every cause of pride, through its specific qualities, brings a unique pleasure, and every cause of humility brings a distinct discomfort.
Again, in considering the subjects, to which these qualities adhere, I make a new supposition, which also appears probable from many obvious instances, viz, that these subjects are either parts of ourselves, or something nearly related to us. Thus the good and bad qualities of our actions and manners constitute virtue and vice, and determine our personal character, than which nothing operates more strongly on these passions. In like manner, it is the beauty or deformity of our person, houses, equipage, or furniture, by which we are rendered either vain or humble. The same qualities, when transfered to subjects, which bear us no relation, influence not in the smallest degree either of these affections.
Again, when thinking about the subjects that these qualities connect to, I make a new assumption, which also seems likely based on many clear examples: these subjects are either parts of ourselves or something closely related to us. So, the good and bad qualities of our actions and behaviors make up virtue and vice, and shape our personal character, which influences these emotions more than anything else. Similarly, it’s the beauty or ugliness of our appearance, homes, belongings, or furniture that makes us either vain or humble. The same qualities, when applied to things that have no connection to us, don’t affect either of these feelings at all.
Having thus in a manner supposed two properties of the causes of these affections, viz, that the qualities produce a separate pain or pleasure, and that the subjects, on which the qualities are placed, are related to self; I proceed to examine the passions themselves, in order to find something in them, correspondent to the supposed properties of their causes. First, I find, that the peculiar object of pride and humility is determined by an original and natural instinct, and that it is absolutely impossible, from the primary constitution of the mind, that these passions should ever look beyond self, or that individual person. of whose actions and sentiments each of us is intimately conscious. Here at last the view always rests, when we are actuated by either of these passions; nor can we, in that situation of mind, ever lose sight of this object. For this I pretend not to give any reason; but consider such a peculiar direction of the thought as an original quality.
Having assumed two characteristics of the causes of these feelings, namely that qualities create a distinct pain or pleasure, and that the subjects to which these qualities apply are connected to the self, I will now explore the passions themselves to find something in them that matches the assumed characteristics of their causes. First, I find that the specific object of pride and humility is defined by an innate and natural instinct, and it is completely impossible, given the mind's fundamental nature, for these passions to ever extend beyond the self, or to any individual person whose actions and feelings each of us is deeply aware of. Ultimately, our focus always remains on this individual when we are driven by either of these passions; in such a mental state, we can never lose sight of this object. I don’t intend to provide any reasoning for this, but I regard such a specific focus of thought as an inherent quality.
The SECOND quality, which I discover in these passions, and which I likewise consider an an original quality, is their sensations, or the peculiar emotions they excite in the soul, and which constitute their very being and essence. Thus pride is a pleasant sensation, and humility a painful; and upon the removal of the pleasure and pain, there is in reality no pride nor humility. Of this our very feeling convinces us; and beyond our feeling, it is here in vain to reason or dispute.
The second quality I notice in these passions, which I also see as a fundamental quality, is the sensations or unique emotions they stir in our hearts, which make up their true nature and essence. For example, pride brings a pleasurable feeling, while humility brings a painful one; without the pleasure and pain, there is really no pride or humility. Our own feelings confirm this, and beyond our feelings, it’s pointless to argue or debate.
If I compare, therefore, these two established properties of the passions, viz, their object, which is self, and their sensation, which is either pleasant or painful, to the two supposed properties of the causes, viz, their relation to self, and their tendency to produce a pain or pleasure, independent of the passion; I immediately find, that taking these suppositions to be just, the true system breaks in upon me with an irresistible evidence. That cause, which excites the passion, is related to the object, which nature has attributed to the passion; the sensation, which the cause separately produces, is related to the sensation of the passion: From this double relation of ideas and impressions, the passion is derived. The one idea is easily converted into its correlative; and the one impression into that, which resembles and corresponds to it: With how much greater facility must this transition be made, where these movements mutually assist each other, and the mind receives a double impulse from the relations both of its impressions and ideas?
If I compare these two established aspects of emotions—specifically, their focus on the self and their feelings, which are either enjoyable or painful—with the two supposed characteristics of causes, namely, their connection to the self and their ability to create pain or pleasure independent of the emotion, I quickly realize that if these assumptions hold true, the actual system presents itself to me with undeniable clarity. The cause that triggers the emotion is linked to the object that nature assigns to the emotion; the feeling that the cause produces separately is connected to the feeling of the emotion. From this dual relationship of ideas and impressions, the emotion arises. One idea can easily be transformed into its counterpart, and one impression into something that resembles and aligns with it. How much easier must this transition be when these processes support each other, and the mind receives a double push from the relationships of both its impressions and ideas?
That we may comprehend this the better, we must suppose, that nature has given to the organs of the human mind, a certain disposition fitted to produce a peculiar impression or emotion, which we call pride: To this emotion she has assigned a certain idea, viz, that of self, which it never fails to produce. This contrivance of nature is easily conceived. We have many instances of such a situation of affairs. The nerves of the nose and palate are so disposed, as in certain circumstances to convey such peculiar sensations to the mind: The sensations of lust and hunger always produce in us the idea of those peculiar objects, which are suitable to each appetite. These two circumstances are united in pride. The organs are so disposed as to produce the passion; and the passion, after its production, naturally produces a certain idea. All this needs no proof. It is evident we never should be possest of that passion, were there not a disposition of mind proper for it; and it is as evident, that the passion always turns our view to ourselves, and makes us think of our own qualities and circumstances.
To better understand this, we need to assume that nature has given the human mind certain characteristics designed to create a specific feeling or emotion known as pride. This emotion is linked to the concept of self, which it always generates. This natural design is easy to grasp. There are many examples of similar situations. The nerves in our nose and mouth are arranged to send particular sensations to the mind under certain conditions. The feelings of desire and hunger always lead us to think of the specific things that satisfy each craving. These two aspects come together in pride. The mind's makeup allows for the feeling to arise, and once that feeling occurs, it naturally leads us to consider a particular idea. This is undeniable. It’s clear that we could never experience this feeling if we didn't have a mindset suited for it, and it’s equally clear that this feeling directs our attention inward, prompting us to reflect on our own qualities and circumstances.
This being fully comprehended, it may now be asked, WHETHER NATURE PRODUCES THE PASSION IMMEDIATELY, OF HERSELF; OR WHETHER SHE MUST BE ASSISTED BY THE CO-OPERATION OF OTHER CAUSES? For it is observable, that in this particular her conduct is different in the different passions and sensations. The palate must be excited by an external object, in order to produce any relish: But hunger arises internally, without the concurrence of any external object. But however the case may stand with other passions and impressions, it is certain, that pride requires the assistance of some foreign object, and that the organs, which produce it, exert not themselves like the heart and arteries, by an original internal movement. For first, daily experience convinces us, that pride requires certain causes to excite it, and languishes when unsupported by some excellency in the character, in bodily accomplishments, in cloaths, equipage or fortune. SECONDLY, it is evident pride would be perpetual, if it arose immediately from nature; since the object is always the same, and there is no disposition of body peculiar to pride, as there is to thirst and hunger. Thirdly, Humility is in the very same situation with pride; and therefore, either must, upon this supposition, be perpetual likewise, or must destroy the contrary passion from, the very first moment; so that none of them could ever make its appearance. Upon the whole, we may rest satisfyed with the foregoing conclusion, that pride must have a cause, as well as an object, and that the one has no influence without the other.
Once this is fully understood, we can now ask whether nature creates passion on its own or whether it needs help from other factors. It's clear that her behavior varies with different passions and sensations. For example, the sense of taste must be stimulated by something external to create any enjoyment: but hunger occurs internally, without needing any outside influence. However this may be with other feelings and sensations, it is clear that pride depends on some external factor, and that the mechanisms behind it do not operate with the same instinctive internal movement as the heart and arteries do. First, everyday experience shows us that pride needs certain triggers to emerge, and it fades when it isn’t supported by some excellence in character, physical attributes, clothing, status, or wealth. Second, it’s obvious that pride would last forever if it came solely from nature, since the subject of pride is always the same, and there isn't a specific physical state related to pride, unlike with thirst or hunger. Third, humility is in the same boat as pride; thus, on this assumption, both must either be ever-present or one must eliminate the other right from the start, which means neither would ever manifest. Overall, we can confidently conclude that pride requires both a cause and an object, and that neither can have any effect without the other.
The difficulty, then, is only to discover this cause, and find what it is that gives the first motion to pride, and sets those organs in action, which are naturally fitted to produce that emotion. Upon my consulting experience, in order to resolve this difficulty, I immediately find a hundred different causes, that produce pride; and upon examining these causes, I suppose, what at first I perceive to be probable, that all of them concur in two circumstances; which are, that of themselves they produce an impression, allyed to the passion, and are placed on a subject, allyed to the object of the passion. When I consider after this the nature of relation, and its effects both on the passions and ideas, I can no longer doubt, upon these suppositions, that it is the very principle, which gives rise to pride, and bestows motion on those organs, which being naturally disposed to produce that affection, require only a first impulse or beginning to their action. Any thing, that gives a pleasant sensation, and is related to self, excites the passion of pride, which is also agreeable, and has self for its object.
The challenge, then, is simply to identify the cause and figure out what triggers pride and activates the mechanisms that naturally lead to that feeling. When I look into my experiences to solve this issue, I quickly come across countless factors that cause pride. Upon examining these factors, I initially think it’s likely that they all share two common elements: they automatically create an impression related to the emotion and are associated with a subject connected to the object of that emotion. After considering the nature of relationships and their impact on emotions and ideas, I can no longer doubt, based on these assumptions, that this is the fundamental principle that leads to pride and stimulates those mechanisms, which are naturally inclined to evoke that feeling, needing just an initial push to get started. Anything that creates a pleasurable feeling and relates to the self stirs up the emotion of pride, which is also enjoyable and centered on the self.
What I have said of pride is equally true of humility. The sensation of humility is uneasy, as that of pride is agreeable; for which reason the separate sensation, arising from the causes, must be reversed, while the relation to self continues the same. Though pride and humility are directly contrary in their effects, and in their sensations, they have notwithstanding the same object; so that it is requisite only to change the relation of impressions, without making any change upon that of ideas. Accordingly we find, that a beautiful house, belonging to ourselves, produces pride; and that the same house, still belonging to ourselves, produces humility, when by any accident its beauty is changed into deformity, and thereby the sensation of pleasure, which corresponded to pride, is transformed into pain, which is related to humility. The double relation between the ideas and impressions subsists in both cases, and produces an easy transition from the one emotion to the other.
What I’ve said about pride is just as true for humility. The feeling of humility is uncomfortable, while pride feels good; for this reason, the different feelings that come from these causes must be switched around, even though our self-perception remains the same. While pride and humility have opposite effects and sensations, they still share the same object. So, all that’s needed is to change how we feel about the impressions without altering the ideas themselves. For instance, a beautiful house that belongs to us makes us feel pride; however, when something happens that changes its beauty to ugliness, that same house makes us feel humility. The pleasure we felt before turns into pain related to humility. The connection between our ideas and feelings exists in both cases, allowing for an easy shift from one emotion to the other.
In a word, nature has bestowed a kind of attraction on certain impressions and ideas, by which one of them, upon its appearance, naturally introduces its correlative. If these two attractions or associations of impressions and ideas concur on the same object, they mutually assist each other, and the transition of the affections and of the imagination is made with the greatest ease and facility. When an idea produces an impression, related to an impression, which is connected with an idea, related to the first idea, these two impressions must be in a manner inseparable, nor will the one in any case be unattended with the other. It is after this manner, that the particular causes of pride and humility are determined. The quality, which operates on the passion, produces separately an impression resembling it; the subject, to which the quality adheres, is related to self, the object of the passion: No wonder the whole cause, consisting of a quality and of a subject, does so unavoidably give rise to the pass on.
In short, nature has given certain feelings and ideas a special appeal, so that when one appears, it naturally brings up its related counterpart. When these two attractions or connections of feelings and ideas align with the same object, they support each other, and the shift in emotions and thoughts happens easily and smoothly. When an idea creates a feeling that's linked to another feeling, which is tied to the first idea, these two feelings become almost inseparable, and one will always be accompanied by the other. This is how the specific reasons for pride and humility are established. The quality that affects the emotion creates a feeling that reflects it; the subject that has this quality relates to the self, which is the focus of the emotion. It's no surprise that this whole reason, made up of a quality and a subject, inevitably leads to the emotional response.
To illustrate this hypothesis we may compare it to that, by which I have already explained the belief attending the judgments, which we form from causation. I have observed, that in all judgments of this kind, there is always a present impression and a related idea; and that the present impression gives a vivacity to the fancy, and the relation conveys this vivacity, by an easy transition, to the related idea. Without the present impression, the attention is not fixed, nor the spirits excited. Without the relation, this attention rests on its first object, and has no farther consequence. There is evidently a great analogy betwixt that hypothesis and our present one of an impression and idea, that transfuse themselves into another impression and idea by means of their double relation: Which analogy must be allowed to be no despicable proof of both hypotheses.
To illustrate this hypothesis, we can compare it to the one I’ve already used to explain the beliefs tied to the judgments we make based on causation. I've noticed that in all such judgments, there is always a current impression and a related idea; the current impression adds vividness to our imagination, and the connection allows this vividness to easily transfer to the related idea. Without the current impression, our focus isn't captured, nor do we feel any excitement. Without the connection, our focus stays on the initial object and doesn’t lead to anything further. There is clearly a strong similarity between this hypothesis and our current one regarding an impression and an idea that transfer into another impression and idea through their dual connection. This similarity should be considered a significant piece of evidence for both hypotheses.
SECT. VI LIMITATIONS OF THIS SYSTEM
But before we proceed farther in this subject, and examine particularly all the causes of pride and humility, it will be proper to make some limitations to the general system, THAT ALL AGREEABLE OBJECTS, RELATED TO OURSELVES, BY AN ASSOCIATION OF IDEAS AND OF IMPRESSIONS, PRODUCE PRIDE, AND DISAGREEABLE ONES, HUMILITY: And these limitations are derived from the very nature of the subject.
But before we go further into this topic and take a closer look at all the reasons for pride and humility, it’s important to set some boundaries to the overall idea that ALL PLEASANT OBJECTS, CONNECTED TO US THROUGH A NETWORK OF THOUGHTS AND IMPRESSIONS, CAUSE PRIDE, WHILE UNPLEASANT ONES CAUSE HUMILITY: These boundaries come from the very nature of the topic.
I. Suppose an agreeable object to acquire a relation to self, the first passion, that appears on this occasion, is joy; and this passion discovers itself upon a slighter relation than pride and vain-glory. We may feel joy upon being present at a feast, where our senses are regard with delicacies of every kind: But it is only the master of the feast, who, beside the same joy, has the additional passion of self-applause and vanity. It is true, men sometimes boast of a great entertainment, at which they have only been present; and by so small a relation convert their pleasure into pride: But however, this must in general be owned, that joy arises from a more inconsiderable relation than vanity, and that many things, which are too foreign to produce pride, are yet able to give us a delight and pleasure, The reason of the difference may be explained thus. A relation is requisite to joy, in order to approach the object to us, and make it give us any satisfaction. But beside this, which is common to both passions, it is requisite to pride, in order to produce a transition from one passion to another, and convert the falsification into vanity. As it has a double task to perform, it must be endowed with double force and energy. To which we may add, that where agreeable objects bear not a very close relation to ourselves, they commonly do to some other person; and this latter relation not only excels, but even diminishes, and sometimes destroys the former, as we shall see afterwards.[3]
I. Let's say we see something we want to connect with ourselves; the first feeling that comes up is joy. This feeling shows up with a weaker connection than pride or vanity. We might feel joy at a feast, where we're treated to all kinds of delicious foods. But it’s only the host of the feast who feels that same joy along with an added feeling of self-satisfaction and vanity. It's true that people sometimes brag about a big event they only attended, and through that small connection, they turn their enjoyment into pride. However, it can generally be said that joy comes from a connection that's less significant than vanity, and many things that aren’t close enough to create pride can still give us happiness and enjoyment. The reason for this difference can be explained like this: a connection is needed for joy to bring the object closer to us and provide satisfaction. But in addition to this common requirement for both feelings, pride needs to create a shift from one emotion to another, turning a false sense of self into vanity. Since it has to do double duty, it needs to have more strength and energy. Moreover, when enjoyable things don’t have a close connection to us, they often have a closer link to someone else; and this second connection not only stands out but can even lessen or completely erase the first, as we’ll discuss later. [3]
[3] Part II. Sec. 4.
Here then is the first limitation, we must make to our general position, that every thing related to us, which produces pleasure or pain, produces likewise pride or humility. There is not only a relation required, but a close one, and a closer than is required to joy.
Here is the first limitation we have to set on our overall view: everything connected to us that brings pleasure or pain also brings about pride or humility. It's not just any relationship needed, but a strong one, even stronger than what is needed for joy.
II. The second limitation is, that the agreeable or disagreeable object be not only closely related, but also peculiar to ourselves, or at least common to us with a few persons. It is a quality observable in human nature, and which we shall endeavour to explain afterwards, that every thing, which is often presented and to which we have been long accustomed, loses its value in our eyes, and is in a little time despised and neglected. We likewise judge of objects more from comparison than from their real and intrinsic merit; and where we cannot by some contrast enhance their value, we are apt to overlook even what is essentially good in them. These qualities of the mind have an effect upon joy as well as pride; and it is remarkable, that goods which are common to all mankind, and have become familiar to us by custom, give us little satisfaction; though perhaps of a more excellent kind, than those on which, for their singularity, we set a much higher value. But though this circumstance operates on both these passions, it has a much greater influence on vanity. We are rejoiced for many goods, which, on account of their frequency, give us no pride. Health, when it returns after a long absence, affords us a very sensible satisfaction; but is seldom regarded as a subject of vanity, because it is shared with such vast numbers.
II. The second limitation is that the things we find pleasant or unpleasant are not only closely related but also unique to us, or at least something we share with only a few people. It's a trait of human nature that we'll explain later, but when something is often presented to us and we become used to it, it loses value in our eyes and is quickly disregarded and neglected. We also judge things more by comparison than by their actual worth; when we can't find a way to make something look better by comparing it to something else, we tend to overlook even its essential goodness. These traits of the mind affect both joy and pride. Notably, things that are common to everyone and that we have become familiar with through habit tend to bring us little satisfaction, even if they are of a higher quality than those unique items we value much more. While this aspect influences both feelings, it has a much stronger impact on vanity. We find joy in many things that, due to their commonness, don't make us feel proud. For example, health, when it returns after being away for a long time, brings us significant satisfaction, but it's rarely seen as a source of vanity because so many people share it.
The reason, why pride is so much more delicate in this particular than joy, I take to be, as follows. In order to excite pride, there are always two objects we must contemplate, viz. the cause or that object which produces pleasure; and self, which is the real object of the passion. But joy has only one object necessary to its production, viz. that which gives pleasure; and though it be requisite, that this bear some relation to self, yet that is only requisite in order to render it agreeable; nor is self, properly speaking, the object of this passion. Since, therefore, pride has in a manner two objects, to which it directs our view; it follows, that where neither of them have any singularity, the passion must be more weakened upon that account, than a passion, which has only one object. Upon comparing ourselves with others, as we are every moment apt to do, we find we are not in the least distinguished; and upon comparing the object we possess, we discover still the same unlucky circumstance. By two comparisons so disadvantageous the passion must be entirely destroyed.
The reason pride is much more delicate than joy, in my opinion, is as follows. To trigger pride, we always have to consider two things: the cause, or the object that brings pleasure, and ourselves, which is the true focus of the feeling. However, joy only requires one object for its existence: the thing that brings pleasure. While it does need to relate to us in some way to be enjoyable, self is not the main focus of this emotion. Since pride involves two objects that capture our attention, it means that if neither of them is unique or special, the feeling will be weaker compared to an emotion with just one object. When we compare ourselves to others, which we tend to do all the time, we often find that we aren't special at all. And when we compare what we have, we come across the same unfortunate reality. With these two unfavorable comparisons, the feeling of pride can be completely diminished.
III The third limitation is, that the pleasant or painful object be very discernible and obvious, and that not only to ourselves, but to others also. This circumstance, like the two foregoing, has an effect upon joy, as well as pride. We fancy Ourselves more happy, as well as more virtuous or beautiful, when we appear so to others; but are still more ostentatious of our virtues than of our pleasures. This proceeds from causes, which I shall endeavour to explain afterwards.
III The third limitation is that the pleasant or painful object must be very clear and obvious, not just to ourselves, but to others as well. This factor, like the two before it, influences both joy and pride. We think we’re happier, as well as more virtuous or attractive, when we seem that way to others; however, we are usually more showy about our virtues than our pleasures. This comes from reasons that I will try to explain later.
IV. The fourth limitation is derived from the inconstancy of the cause of these passions, and from the short duration of its connexion with ourselves. What is casual and inconstant gives but little joy, and less pride. We are not much satisfyed with the thing itself; and are still less apt to feel any new degrees of self-satisfaction upon its account. We foresee and anticipate its change by the imagination; which makes us little satisfyed with the thing: We compare it to ourselves, whose existence is more durable; by which means its inconstancy appears still greater. It seems ridiculous to infer an excellency in ourselves from an object, which is of so much shorter duration, and attends us during so small a part of our existence. It will be easy to comprehend the reason, why this cause operates not with the same force in joy as in pride; since the idea of self is not so essential to the former passion as to the latter.
IV. The fourth limitation comes from the inconsistency of the source of these feelings and from how briefly it connects with us. Things that are random and unstable bring little happiness and even less pride. We aren’t very satisfied with the things themselves and are even less likely to feel any deeper sense of self-satisfaction because of them. We foresee and expect their change in our minds, which makes us less satisfied with the thing. We compare it to ourselves, whose existence lasts longer, which makes its inconsistency seem even greater. It seems silly to claim we are exceptional because of something that lasts such a short time and is with us for such a small part of our lives. It's easy to see why this cause doesn’t have the same impact on joy as it does on pride, since the concept of self is not as essential to joy as it is to pride.
V. I may add as a fifth limitation, or rather enlargement of this system, that general rules have a great influence upon pride and humility, as well as on all the other passions. Hence we form a notion of different ranks of men, suitable to the power of riches they are possest of; and this notion we change not upon account of any peculiarities of the health or temper of the persons, which may deprive them of all enjoyment in their possessions. This may be accounted for from the same principles, that explained the influence of general rules on the understanding. Custom readily carries us beyond the just bounds in our passions, as well as in our reasonings.
V. I can add a fifth limitation, or more accurately, an expansion of this system: general rules greatly affect pride and humility, as well as all other emotions. Because of this, we develop ideas about different social standings based on the wealth people have. We don’t change this perception because of any specific issues with a person’s health or temperament that might prevent them from enjoying their wealth. This can be explained by the same principles that clarify how general rules impact our understanding. Custom often pushes us past the right limits in our emotions, just like it does in our reasoning.
It may not be amiss to observe on this occasion, that the influence of general rules and maxims on the passions very much contributes to facilitate the effects of all the principles, which we shall explain in the progress of this treatise. For it is evident, that if a person full-grown, and of the same nature with ourselves, were on a sudden-transported into our world, he would be very much embarrased with every object, and would not readily find what degree of love or hatred, pride or humility, or any other passion he ought to attribute to it. The passions are often varyed by very inconsiderable principles; and these do not always play with a perfect regularity, especially on the first trial. But as custom and practice have brought to light all these principles, and have settled the just value of every thing; this must certainly contribute to the easy production of the passions, and guide us, by means of general established maxims, in the proportions we ought to observe in preferring one object to another. This remark may, perhaps, serve to obviate difficulties, that mayarise concerning some causes, which I shall hereafter ascribe to particular passions, and which may be esteemed too refined to operate so universally and certainly, as they are found to do.
It may be worth noting on this occasion that the influence of general rules and maxims on our emotions greatly helps to clarify the effects of all the principles we will explain as this treatise progresses. It's clear that if an adult, similar to us, were suddenly transported into our world, they would be quite confused by every object and wouldn't easily determine the appropriate level of love or hate, pride or humility, or any other emotion to attach to it. Emotions can often change due to very minor principles, and these don't always operate perfectly, especially on first encounters. However, as habits and experiences have revealed these principles and established the true value of everything, this certainly helps in the easy expression of emotions and guides us, through general established maxims, in how we should value one object over another. This observation may help to address difficulties that might arise regarding some causes that I will later attribute to specific emotions, which may be seen as too subtle to function as universally and reliably as they do.
I shall close this subject with a reflection derived from these five limitations. This reflection is, that the persons, who are proudest, and who in the eye of the world have most reason for their pride, are not always the happiest; nor the most humble always the most miserable, as may at first sight be imagined from this system. An evil may be real. though its cause has no relation to us: It may be real, without being peculiar: It may be real, without shewing itself to others: It may be real, without being constant: And it may be real, without falling under the general rules. Such evils as these will not fail to render us miserable, though they have little tendency to diminish pride: And perhaps the most real and the most solid evils of life will be found of this nature.
I'll wrap up this topic with a thought based on these five limitations. This thought is that the people who are the most proud, and who seem to have the most reason to be proud in the eyes of the world, aren’t always the happiest; nor are the most humble always the most miserable, as one might initially think from this perspective. A problem can be genuine even if its cause doesn’t relate to us: it can be real without being unique: it can exist without being visible to others: it can be real without being permanent: and it can be real without fitting into general patterns. Such problems will definitely make us unhappy, even if they don’t really lessen our pride: and perhaps the most genuine and significant struggles in life will be of this kind.
SECT. VII OF VICE AND VIRTUE
Taking these limitations along with us, let us proceed to examine the causes of pride and humility; and see, whether in every case we can discover the double relations, by which they operate on the passions. If we find that all these causes are related to self, and produce a pleasure or uneasiness separate from the passion, there will remain no farther scruple with regard to the present system. We shall principally endeavour to prove the latter point; the former being in a manner self-evident.
Taking these limitations into account, let’s move on to explore the reasons behind pride and humility, and see if we can identify the dual relationships that affect our emotions in each case. If we find that all these reasons are tied to the self and create a sense of pleasure or discomfort apart from the emotions, there will be no further doubt about the current framework. We will primarily focus on proving the latter point, as the former is somewhat self-evident.
To begin, with vice and virtue; which are the most obvious causes of these passions; it would be entirely foreign to my present purpose to enter upon the controversy, which of late years has so much excited the curiosity of the publick. WHETHER THESE MORAL DISTINCTIONS BE FOUNDED ON NATURAL AND ORIGINAL PRINCIPLES, OR ARISE FROM INTEREST AND EDUCATION. The examination of this I reserve for the following book; and in the mean time I shall endeavour to show, that my system maintains its ground upon either of these hypotheses; which will be a strong proof of its solidity.
To start with, vice and virtue, which are the most obvious causes of these feelings, it would be completely unrelated to my current purpose to dive into the debate that has sparked so much public interest in recent years: WHETHER THESE MORAL DISTINCTIONS ARE BASED ON NATURAL AND INHERENT PRINCIPLES, OR COME FROM SELF-INTEREST AND EDUCATION. I will address this in the next book; for now, I will try to demonstrate that my system stands firm on either of these ideas, which will be a strong testament to its validity.
For granting that morality had no foundation in nature, it must still be allowed, that vice and virtue, either from self-interest or the prejudices of education, produce in us a real pain and pleasure; and this we may observe to be strenuously asserted by the defenders of that hypothesis. Every passion, habit, or turn of character (say they) which has a tendency to our advantage or prejudice, gives a delight or uneasiness; and it is from thence the approbation or disapprobation arises. We easily gain from the liberality of others, but are always in danger of losing by their avarice: Courage defends us, but cowardice lays us open to every attack: Justice is the support of society, but injustice, unless checked would quickly prove its ruin: Humility exalts; but pride mortifies us. For these reasons the former qualities are esteemed virtues, and the latter regarded as vices. Now since it is granted there is a delight or uneasiness still attending merit or demerit of every kind, this is all that is requisite for my purpose.
Even if we accept that morality isn’t rooted in nature, we still have to recognize that both vice and virtue, whether stemming from self-interest or the biases of upbringing, generate real feelings of pain and pleasure in us. This point is strongly argued by those who support that idea. They say every emotion, habit, or personality trait that benefits us or harms us brings us joy or discomfort; it’s from this that our approval or disapproval comes. We easily benefit from the generosity of others but always risk suffering from their greed. Courage protects us, while cowardice leaves us vulnerable to attacks. Justice holds society together, but without limits, injustice would quickly lead to its downfall. Humility lifts us up, while pride brings us down. That’s why the first set of qualities is considered virtues, and the second is seen as vices. Since it’s acknowledged that there’s pleasure or discomfort associated with the merit or demerit of all kinds, that’s all I need for my argument.
But I go farther, and observe, that this moral hypothesis and my present system not only agree together, but also that, allowing the former to be just, it is an absolute and invincible proof of the latter. For if all morality be founded on the pain or pleasure, which arises from the prospect of any loss or advantage, that may result from our own characters, or from those of others, all the effects of morality must-be derived from the same pain or pleasure, and among the rest, the passions of pride and humility. The very essence of virtue, according to this hypothesis, is to produce pleasure and that of vice to give pain. The virtue and vice must be part of our character in order to excite pride or humility. What farther proof can we desire for the double relation of impressions and ideas?
But I take it further and note that this moral theory and my current system not only align with each other, but that if we accept the former as true, it serves as a clear and undeniable validation of the latter. If all morality is based on the pain or pleasure that comes from the possibility of any loss or gain related to our own actions or those of others, then all the effects of morality must stem from that same pain or pleasure, including the feelings of pride and humility. According to this theory, the essence of virtue is to generate pleasure, while the essence of vice is to cause pain. Virtue and vice must be part of our character to provoke feelings of pride or humility. What more proof do we need of the dual relationship between impressions and ideas?
The same unquestionable argument may be derived from the opinion of those, who maintain that morality is something real, essential, and founded on nature. The most probable hypothesis, which has been advanced to explain the distinction betwixt vice and virtue, and the origin of moral rights and obligations, is, that from a primary constitution of nature certain characters and passions, by the very view and contemplation, produce a pain, and others in like manner excite a pleasure. The uneasiness and satisfaction are not only inseparable from vice and virtue, but constitute their very nature and essence. To approve of a character is to feel an original delight upon its appearance. To disapprove of it is to be sensible of an uneasiness. The pain and pleasure, therefore, being the primary causes of vice and virtue, must also be the causes of all their effects, and consequently of pride and humility, which are the unavoidable attendants of that distinction.
The same undeniable argument can be made by those who believe that morality is something real, essential, and based on nature. The most likely explanation put forward to clarify the difference between vice and virtue, as well as the origins of moral rights and obligations, is that certain traits and emotions, by their very nature, cause us pain when we contemplate them, while others produce pleasure. The discomfort and satisfaction are not only associated with vice and virtue, but they also define their very essence. To approve of a character means to feel an innate pleasure when we see it. Disapproving of it brings about discomfort. Thus, pain and pleasure are the foundational causes of vice and virtue, and they are also responsible for all their effects, including pride and humility, which are the unavoidable companions of that distinction.
But supposing this hypothesis of moral philosophy should be allowed to be false, it is still evident, that pain and pleasure, if not the causes of vice and virtue, are at least inseparable from them. A generous and noble character affords a satisfaction even in the survey; and when presented to us, though only in a poem or fable, never fails to charm and delight us. On the other hand cruelty and treachery displease from their very nature; nor is it possible ever to reconcile us to these qualities, either in ourselves or others. Thus one hypothesis of morality is an undeniable proof of the foregoing system, and the other at worst agrees with it. But pride and humility arise not from these qualities alone of the mind, which, according to the vulgar systems of ethicks, have been comprehended as parts of moral duty, but from any other that has a connexion with pleasure and uneasiness. Nothing flatters our vanity more than the talent of pleasing by our wit, good humour, or any other accomplishment; and nothing gives us a more sensible mortification than a disappointment in any attempt of that nature. No one has ever been able to tell what wit is, and to-shew why such a system of thought must be received under that denomination, and such another rejected. It is only by taste we can decide concerning it, nor are we possest of any other standard, upon which we can form a judgment of this kind. Now what is this taste, from which true and false wit in a manner receive their being, and without which no thought can have a title to either of these denominations? It is plainly nothing but a sensation of pleasure from true wit, and of uneasiness from false, without oar being able to tell the reasons of that pleasure or uneasiness. The power of bestowing these opposite sensations is, therefore, the very essence of true and false wit; and consequently the cause of that pride or humility, which arises from them.
But if we assume this moral philosophy is false, it's still clear that pain and pleasure, even if they're not the root of vice and virtue, are at least closely connected to them. A generous and noble character brings us satisfaction just by observing it, and whether we see it in a poem or a fable, it never fails to charm and delight us. In contrast, cruelty and treachery inherently leave us feeling displeased; it's impossible to accept these traits, either in ourselves or in others. Thus, one moral hypothesis backs up the previous system, and the other, at worst, aligns with it. However, pride and humility don't stem solely from these specific mental qualities that traditional ethics have defined as part of moral duty, but from anything that ties to pleasure and discomfort. Nothing flatters our ego more than being able to please others with our wit, good humor, or any other skill; conversely, nothing gives us a more acute sense of disappointment than failing at that. No one has been able to define what wit truly is, or explain why some thoughts fit that label while others don't. We can only judge it by taste, and we have no other standard to base our judgment on. So, what is this taste, from which true and false wit derive their existence, and without which no thought can claim either label? It is simply a feeling of pleasure from true wit and discomfort from false wit, without our being able to articulate the reasons for that pleasure or discomfort. The ability to evoke these opposing sensations is, therefore, the essence of true and false wit, and the root of the pride or humility that comes from them.
There may, perhaps, be some, who being accustomed to the style of the schools and pulpit, and having never considered human nature in any other light, than that in which they place it, may here be surprized to hear me talk of virtue as exciting pride, which they look upon as a vice; and of vice as producing humility, which they have been taught to consider as a virtue. But not to dispute about words, I observe, that by pride I understand that agreeable impression, which arises in the mind, when the view either of our virtue, beauty, riches or power makes us satisfyed with ourselves: and that by humility I mean the opposite impression. It is evident the former impression is not always vicious, nor the latter virtuous. The most rigid morality allows us to receive a pleasure from reflecting on a generous action; and it is by none esteemed a virtue to feel any fruitless remorses upon the thoughts of past villainy and baseness. Let us, therefore, examine these impressions, considered in themselves; and enquire into their causes, whether placed on the mind or body, without troubling ourselves at present with that merit or blame, which may attend them.
Some people, who are used to the way schools and churches talk and have never thought about human nature in any other way than how they've been taught, might be surprised to hear me say that virtue can lead to pride, which they see as a bad thing, and that vice can lead to humility, which they've been taught to view as good. But rather than argue over definitions, I want to clarify that by pride, I mean that pleasant feeling we get when our virtues, beauty, wealth, or power make us feel good about ourselves, and by humility, I mean the opposite feeling. It's clear that feeling pride isn't always bad, nor is feeling humble always good. Even strict moral standards allow us to enjoy reflecting on a kind act, and it's not considered virtuous to dwell on guilt from past wrongdoing and shame. So, let's take a closer look at these feelings on their own and explore their causes, whether they come from the mind or the body, without worrying right now about any praise or blame that may come with them.
SECT. VIII OF BEAUTY AND DEFORMITY
Whether we consider the body as a part of ourselves, or assent to those philosophers, who regard it as something external, it must still be allowed to be near enough connected with us to form one of these double relations, which I have asserted to be necessary to the causes of pride and humility. Wherever, therefore, we can find the other relation of impressions to join to this of ideas, we may expect with assurance either of these passions, according as the impression is pleasant or uneasy. But beauty of all kinds gives us a peculiar delight and satisfaction; as deformity produces pain, upon whatever subject it may be placed, and whether surveyed in an animate or inanimate object. If the beauty or deformity, therefore, be placed upon our own bodies, this pleasure or uneasiness must be converted into pride or humility, as having in this case all the circumstances requisite to produce a perfect transition of impressions and ideas. These opposite sensations are related to the opposite passions. The beauty or deformity is closely related to self, the object of both these passions. No wonder, then our own beauty becomes an object of pride, and deformity of humility.
Whether we see the body as part of ourselves or agree with those philosophers who view it as something separate, it's still close enough to us to create one of those dual relationships that I’ve said is essential for pride and humility. So, wherever we can find another connection between impressions and ideas, we can confidently expect either of these emotions, depending on whether the impression feels good or uncomfortable. However, beauty of all kinds gives us a unique pleasure and satisfaction; in contrast, deformity causes pain, regardless of the subject, whether it’s a living being or an inanimate object. Therefore, if beauty or deformity is associated with our own bodies, this pleasure or discomfort will translate into pride or humility, as all the conditions needed for a complete shift of impressions and ideas are present. These contrasting feelings are linked to opposing emotions. Beauty or deformity is closely tied to the self, which is the focus of both emotions. It’s no surprise, then, that our own beauty becomes a source of pride, while deformity brings about humility.
But this effect of personal and bodily qualities is not only a proof of the present system, by shewing that the passions arise not in this case without all the circumstances I have required, but may be employed as a stronger and more convincing argument. If we consider all the hypotheses, which have been formed either by philosophy or common reason, to explain the difference betwixt beauty and deformity, we shall find that all of them resolve into this, that beauty is such an order and construction of parts, as either by the primary constitution of our nature, by custom, or by caprice, is fitted to give a pleasure and satisfaction to the soul. This is the distinguishing character of beauty, and forms all the difference betwixt it and deformity, whose natural tendency is to produce uneasiness. Pleasure and pain, therefore, are not only necessary attendants of beauty and deformity, but constitute their very essence. And indeed, if we consider, that a great part of the beauty, which we admire either in animals or in other objects, is derived from the idea of convenience and utility, we shall make no scruple to assent to this opinion. That shape, which produces strength, is beautiful in one animal; and that which is a sign of agility in another. The order and convenience of a palace are no less essential to its beauty, than its mere figure and appearance. In like manner the rules of architecture require, that the top of a pillar should be more slender than its base, and that because such a figure conveys to us the idea of security, which is pleasant; whereas the contrary form gives us the apprehension of danger, which is uneasy. From innumerable instances of this kind, as well as from considering that beauty like wit, cannot be defined, but is discerned only by a taste or sensation, we may conclude, that beauty is nothing but a form, which produces pleasure, as deformity is a structure of parts, which conveys pain; and since the power of producing pain and pleasure make in this manner the essence of beauty and deformity, all the effects of these qualities must be derived from the sensation; and among the rest pride and humility, which of all their effects are the most common and remarkable.
But the impact of personal and physical attributes not only supports the current system by demonstrating that passions don’t arise in this case without all the conditions I mentioned, but can also be used as a stronger and more compelling argument. If we look at all the theories that have been created, whether by philosophy or common sense, to explain the difference between beauty and ugliness, we will see that they all boil down to this: beauty is an arrangement and structure of parts that, due to our natural instincts, customs, or whims, is designed to provide pleasure and satisfaction to the soul. This is what defines beauty and distinguishes it from ugliness, which naturally tends to cause discomfort. So, pleasure and pain are not just constant companions of beauty and ugliness, but they form their very essence. In fact, if we consider that much of the beauty we admire in animals or other objects comes from the idea of practicality and usefulness, we will have no trouble agreeing with this view. The shape that provides strength is beautiful in one animal, while a form that indicates agility is beautiful in another. The layout and functionality of a palace are just as important to its beauty as its shape and appearance. Similarly, architectural rules dictate that the top of a column should be thinner than its base, because such a shape conveys a sense of security, which is pleasing; whereas the opposite shape gives off a sense of danger, which is unsettling. From countless examples of this kind, as well as from the understanding that beauty, like wit, can’t be defined but is recognized solely by taste or sensation, we can conclude that beauty is simply a form that produces pleasure, while ugliness is a structure that conveys pain. Since the ability to evoke pain and pleasure essentially defines beauty and ugliness, all the effects of these qualities must come from sensation; among these effects, pride and humility are the most common and noteworthy.
This argument I esteem just and decisive; but in order to give greater authority to the present reasoning, let us suppose it false for a moment, and see what will follow. It is certain, then, that if the power of producing pleasure and pain forms not the essence of beauty and deformity, the sensations are at least inseparable from the qualities, and it is even difficult to consider them apart. Now there is nothing common to natural and moral beauty, (both of which are the causes of pride) but this power of producing pleasure; and as a common effect supposes always a common cause, it is plain the pleasure must in both cases be the real and influencing cause of the passion. Again; there is nothing originally different betwixt the beauty of our bodies and the beauty of external and foreign objects, but that the one has a near relation to ourselves, which is wanting in the other. This original difference, therefore, must be the cause of all their other differences, and among the rest, of their different influence upon the passion of pride, which is excited by the beauty of our person, but is not affected in the least by that of foreign and external objects. Placing, then, these two conclusions together, we find they compose the preceding system betwixt them, viz, that pleasure, as a related or resembling impression, when placed on a related object by a natural transition, produces pride; and its contrary, humility. This system, then, seems already sufficiently confirmed by experience; that we have not yet exhausted all our arguments.
I consider this argument fair and convincing; however, to give more weight to our reasoning, let’s momentarily assume it’s false and see what follows. It’s clear that if the ability to create pleasure and pain isn’t the essence of beauty and ugliness, these sensations are at least tied to the qualities, making it hard to think of them separately. There’s nothing shared between natural and moral beauty, both of which cause pride, except for this ability to create pleasure; and since a shared effect implies a shared cause, it’s obvious that pleasure must be the real and driving cause of the passion in both cases. Furthermore, there’s nothing fundamentally different between the beauty of our bodies and that of external objects, except that one has a closer connection to us, which the other lacks. This fundamental difference must cause all their other differences, including their varying influence on the feeling of pride, which is stirred by our own beauty but not at all affected by the beauty of external objects. By aligning these two conclusions, we see they form the previous system: that pleasure, as a related or similar impression that connects to a related object through a natural transition, produces pride, while its opposite produces humility. This system, then, seems already well-supported by experience, though we haven’t yet explored all our arguments.
It is not the beauty of the body alone that produces pride, but also its strength and force. Strength is a kind of power; and therefore the desire to excel in strength is to be considered as an inferior species of ambition. For this reason the present phænomenon will be sufficiently accounted for, in explaining that passion.
It's not just the beauty of the body that creates pride, but also its strength and power. Strength is a form of power, so wanting to be strong can be seen as a lesser form of ambition. That's why we can fully understand this phenomenon by explaining that desire.
Concerning all other bodily accomplishments we may observe in general, that whatever in ourselves is either useful, beautiful, or surprising, is an object of pride; and it's contrary, of humility. Now it is obvious, that every thing useful, beautiful or surprising, agrees in producing a separate pleasure and agrees in nothing else. The pleasure, therefore, with the relation to self must be the cause of the passion.
Concerning all other physical achievements, we can generally see that anything in us that is useful, beautiful, or surprising is a source of pride; while its opposite brings humility. It's clear that everything useful, beautiful, or surprising creates a distinct pleasure and doesn't share anything else in common. Therefore, the pleasure related to oneself must be the reason behind the emotion.
Though it should be questioned, whether beauty be not something real, and different from the power of producing pleasure, it can never be disputed, that as surprize is nothing but a pleasure arising from novelty, it is not, properly speaking, a quality in any object, but merely a passion or impression in the soul. It must, therefore, be from that impression, that pride by a natural transition arises. And it arises so naturally, that there is nothing in us or belonging to us, which produces surprize, that does not at the same time excite that other passion. Thus we are vain of the surprising adventures we have met with, the escapes we have made, and dangers we have been exposed to. Hence the origin of vulgar lying; where men without any interest, and merely out of vanity, heap up a number of extraordinary events, which are either the fictions of their brain, or if true, have at least no connexion with themselves. Their fruitful invention supplies them with a variety of adventures; and where that talent is wanting, they appropriate such as belong to others, in order to satisfy their vanity.
Although it can be questioned whether beauty is something real and distinct from the ability to produce pleasure, it can't be denied that surprise is simply a pleasure that comes from novelty. It's not truly a quality of any object but rather a feeling or impression in our minds. Thus, this impression must be where pride naturally comes from. It arises so instinctively that anything in us or about us that creates surprise also stirs that other feeling. That's why we take pride in the surprising experiences we've had, the narrow escapes we've made, and the dangers we've faced. This is the root of common exaggeration; people, lacking any real interest and driven only by vanity, embellish their tales with amazing events that are either made up or, if they're true, have no real connection to them. Their vivid imagination provides them with many adventures, and when that creativity is lacking, they appropriate the stories of others to feed their vanity.
In this phænomenon are contained two curious experiments, which if we compare them together, according to the known rules, by which we judge of cause and effect in anatomy, natural philosophy, and other sciences, will be an undeniable argument for that influence of the double relations above-mentioned. By one of these experiments we find, that an object produces pride merely by the interposition of pleasure; and that because the quality, by which it produces pride, is in reality nothing but the power of producing pleasure. By the other experiment we find, that the pleasure produces the pride by a transition along related ideas; because when we cut off that relation the passion is immediately destroyed.. A surprising adventure, in which we have been ourselves engaged, is related to us, and by that means produces pride: But the adventures of others, though they may cause pleasure, yet for want of this relation of ideas, never excite that passion. What farther proof can be desired for the present system?
In this phenomenon are two interesting experiments. When we compare them using the well-known rules we apply to understand cause and effect in anatomy, natural philosophy, and other sciences, they provide solid evidence for the influence of the double relationships mentioned earlier. In one experiment, we see that an object generates pride simply through the experience of pleasure, because the quality that creates pride is really just the ability to create pleasure. In the other experiment, we find that pleasure leads to pride through a connection with related ideas; when we remove that connection, the feeling is instantly gone. A surprising personal experience that we've had relates to us and in turn generates pride. However, the experiences of others, while they may bring pleasure, do not create that feeling because they lack that necessary connection of ideas. What more proof could be needed for the current theory?
There is only one objection to this system with regard to our body: which is, that though nothing be more agreeable than health, and more painful than sickness, yet commonly men are neither proud of the one, nor mortifyed with the other. This will easily be accounted for, if we consider the second and fourth limitations, proposed to our general system. It was observed, that no object ever produces pride or humility, if it has not something peculiar to ourself; as also, that every cause of that passion must be in some measure constant, and hold some proportion to the duration of our self, which, is its object. Now as health and sickness vary incessantly to all men, and there is none, who is solely or certainly fixed in either, these accidental blessings and calamities are in a manner separated from us, and are never considered as connected with our being and existence. And that this account is just appears hence, that wherever a malady of any kind is so rooted in our constitution, that we no longer entertain any hopes of recovery, from that moment it becomes an object of humility; as is evident in old men, whom nothing mortifies more than the consideration of their age and infirmities. They endeavour, as long as possible, to conceal their blindness and deafness, their rheums and gouts; nor do they ever confess them without reluctance and uneasiness. And though young men are not ashamed of every head-ach or cold they fall into, yet no topic is so proper to mortify human pride, and make us entertain a mean opinion of our nature, than this, that we are every moment of our lives subject to such infirmities. This sufficiently proves that bodily pain and sickness are in themselves proper causes of humility; though the custom of estimating every thing by comparison more than by its intrinsic worth and value, makes us overlook these calamities, which we find to be incident to every one, and causes us to form an idea of our merit and character independent of them.
There’s only one criticism of this system regarding our bodies: although nothing is more enjoyable than being healthy and more distressing than being sick, people rarely take pride in good health or feel humiliated by illness. This can be explained by considering the second and fourth limitations we proposed for our general system. It’s been noted that no object can evoke pride or humility unless it has something unique to ourselves; also, any cause of that emotion must be somewhat constant and relate to how long we exist. Since health and sickness fluctuate constantly for everyone, and no one is strictly fixed in either state, these temporary blessings and misfortunes are somewhat detached from us and are not seen as tied to our existence. This explanation holds true because whenever an illness becomes so entrenched in our bodies that we no longer hope for recovery, it shifts into an object of humility. This is clear with elderly people, for whom nothing feels more humiliating than being aware of their age and weaknesses. They try their best to hide their blindness, deafness, and ailments, and they rarely acknowledge them without discomfort. Young people may not be embarrassed by every headache or cold they get, but there’s no topic more likely to humble human pride and make us reflect poorly on our nature than the fact that we are vulnerable to such weaknesses at every moment. This clearly shows that physical pain and illness naturally lead to humility; however, our tendency to judge everything based on comparison rather than intrinsic value leads us to overlook these troubles, which everyone faces, and causes us to form opinions about our worth and character that are separate from them.
We are ashamed of such maladies as affect others, and are either dangerous or disagreeable to them. Of the epilepsy; because it gives a horror to every one present: Of the itch; because it is infectious: Of the king's-evil; because it commonly goes to posterity. Men always consider the sentiments of others in their judgment of themselves. This has evidently appeared in some of the foregoing reasonings; and will appear still more evidently, and be more fully explained afterwards.
We feel embarrassed by illnesses that affect other people and that are either dangerous or unpleasant for them. Take epilepsy, for example; it terrifies everyone around. The itch is another one, as it's contagious. And then there's the king's evil, which is often hereditary. People always take into account how others perceive them when judging themselves. This has already been clear in some of the previous arguments and will become even clearer and more thoroughly explained later on.
SECT. IX OF EXTERNAL ADVANTAGES AND DISADVANTAGES
But though pride and humility have the qualities of our mind and body that is self, for their natural and more immediate causes, we find by experience, that there are many other objects, which produce these affections, and that the primary one is, in some measure, obscured and lost by the multiplicity of foreign and extrinsic. We found a vanity upon houses, gardens, equipages, as well as upon personal merit and accomplishments; and though these external advantages be in themselves widely distant from thought or a person, yet they considerably influence even a passion, which is directed to that as its ultimate object. This happens when external objects acquire any particular relation to ourselves, and are associated or connected with us. A beautiful fish in the ocean, an animal in a desert, and indeed any thing that neither belongs, nor is related to us, has no manner of influence on our vanity, whatever extraordinary qualities it may be endowed with, and whatever degree of surprize and admiration it may naturally occasion. It must be some way associated with us in order to touch our pride. Its idea must hang in a manner, upon that of ourselves and the transition from the one to the other must be easy and natural.
But while pride and humility are qualities of our mind and body that pertain to the self, we find through experience that many other factors can trigger these feelings. The primary cause tends to get obscured by a variety of unrelated external influences. We often take pride in our homes, gardens, vehicles, and even our personal achievements; and although these external advantages may seem distant from our thoughts or our identity, they significantly affect passions directed toward them as final goals. This occurs when outside objects gain a specific connection to us and become associated with our identity. A beautiful fish in the ocean, an animal in the desert, or anything else that isn't tied to us won't influence our vanity, no matter how remarkable it is or how much surprise and admiration it might evoke. It needs to be somehow linked to us to impact our pride. Its concept has to, in some way, relate to our sense of self, and the shift from one to the other should be smooth and natural.
But here it is remarkable, that though the relation of resemblance operates upon the mind in the same manner as contiguity and causation, in conveying us from one idea to another, yet it is seldom a foundation either of pride or of humility. If we resemble a person in any of the valuable parts of his character, we must, in some degree, possess the quality, in which we resemble him; and this quality we always chuse to survey directly in ourselves rather than by reflexion in another person, when we would found upon it any degree of vanity. So that though a likeness may occasionally produce that passion by suggesting a more advantageous idea of ourselves, it is there the view fixes at last, and the passion finds its ultimate and final cause.
However, it's interesting to note that while the concept of resemblance affects our minds similarly to how proximity and causation do in linking one idea to another, it rarely serves as a basis for pride or humility. If we share similarities with someone in any of their admirable traits, we must possess some level of that quality ourselves, and we tend to focus on that quality directly within ourselves rather than reflecting on it through another person when we want to feel any sense of vanity. So, while a similarity might sometimes trigger that feeling by presenting a more positive perception of ourselves, our focus ultimately stays on that perception, and the feeling finds its true source there.
There are instances, indeed, wherein men shew a vanity in resembling a great man in his countenance, shape, air, or other minute circumstances, that contribute not in any degree to his reputation; but it must be confessed that this extends not very far, nor is of any considerable moment in these affections. For this I assign the following reason. We can never have a vanity of resembling in trifles any person, unless he be possessed of very shining qualities, which give us a respect and veneration for him. These qualities, then, are, properly speaking, the causes of our vanity, by means of their relation to ourselves. Now after what manner are they related to ourselves? They are parts of the person we value, and consequently connected with these trifles; which are also supposed to be parts of him. These trifles are connected with the resembling qualities in us; and these qualities in us, being parts, are connected with the whole; and by that means form a chain of several links of the person we resemble. But besides that this multitude of relations must weaken the connexion; it is evident the mind, in passing from the shining qualities to the trivial ones, must by that contrast the better perceive the minuteness of the latter, and be in some measure ashamed of the comparison and resemblance.
There are cases where people show a desire to look like a great person in their facial features, body shape, mannerisms, or other small details that don't really affect his reputation at all. However, it's important to note that this doesn’t go very far and isn’t really significant in these feelings. I believe the reason for this is as follows. We can only feel vanity about resembling someone in trivial ways if that person has impressive qualities that command our respect and admiration. These qualities are, in reality, the reasons for our vanity, related to our own self-esteem. Now, how are they related to us? They are part of the person we admire, and thus linked to these trivial details, which are also seen as parts of him. These trivial aspects connect with our own resembling qualities; those qualities in us, being parts of our identity, connect back to the whole, creating a chain of connections to the person we resemble. However, the sheer number of these connections tends to weaken the bond, and it's clear that as the mind moves from the impressive qualities to the insignificant ones, the contrast highlights the triviality of the latter, making us somewhat embarrassed by the comparison and the resemblance.
The relation, therefore, of contiguity, or that of causation, betwixt the cause and object of pride and humility, is alone requisite to give rise to these passions; and these relations are nothing else but qualities, by which the imagination is conveyed from one idea to another. Now let us consider what effect these can possibly have upon the mind, and by what means they become so requisite to the production of the passions. It is evident, that the association of ideas operates in so silent and imperceptible a manner, that we are scarce sensible of it, and discover it more by its effects than by any immediate feeling or perception. It produces no emotion, and gives rise to no new impression of any kind, but only modifies those ideas, of which the mind was formerly possessed, and which it could recal upon occasion. From this reasoning, as well as from undoubted experience, we may conclude, that an association of ideas, however necessary, is not alone sufficient to give rise to any passion.
The connection between cause and the feelings of pride and humility is essential for these emotions to arise; these connections are simply qualities that lead the imagination from one idea to another. Now, let’s think about what effect these can have on the mind and how they are necessary for generating emotions. It’s clear that the association of ideas works in such a quiet and subtle way that we barely notice it, recognizing it more by its effects than by direct awareness. It doesn’t create any strong emotions or new impressions; it only alters the ideas that the mind already has and can recall when needed. From this reasoning, along with clear experience, we can conclude that while an association of ideas is important, it’s not enough on its own to spark any emotion.
It is evident, then, that when the mind feels the passion either of pride or humility upon the appearance of related object, there is, beside the relation or transition of thought, an emotion or original impression produced by some other principle. The question is, whether the emotion first produced be the passion itself, or some other impression related to it. This question we cannot be long in deciding, For besides all the other arguments, with which this subject abounds, it must evidently appear, that the relation of ideas, which experience shews to be so requisite a circumstance to the production of the passion, would be entirely superfluous, were it not to second a relation of affections, and facilitate the transition from one impression to another. If nature produced immediately the passion of pride or humility, it would be compleated in itself, and would require no farther addition or encrease from any other affection. But supposing the first emotion to be only related to pride or humility, it is easily conceived to what purpose the relation of objects may serve, and how the two different associations, of impressions and ideas, by uniting their forces, may assist each other's operation. This is not only easily conceived, but I will venture to affirm it is the only manner, in which we can conceive this subject. An easy transition of ideas, which, of itself, causes no emotion, can never be necessary, or even useful to the passions, but by forwarding the transition betwixt some related impressions. Not to mention, that the same object causes a greater or smaller degree of pride, not only in proportion to the encrease or decrease of its qualities, but also to the distance or nearness of the relation; which is a clear argument for the transition of affections along the relation of ideas; since every change in the relation produces a proportionable change in the passion. Thus one part of the preceding system, concerning the relations of ideas is a sufficient proof of the other, concerning that of impressions; and is itself so evidently founded on experience, that it would be lost time to endeavour farther to prove it.
It’s clear, then, that when the mind experiences either pride or humility in response to a related object, there’s not just the connection or flow of thought, but also an emotion or initial impression created by some other factor. The question is whether the first emotion is the passion itself or a different impression linked to it. We don’t need long to figure this out. Besides all the other arguments surrounding this topic, it’s obvious that the connection of ideas, which experience shows is essential for creating the passion, would be completely unnecessary if it didn’t also facilitate a connection of feelings and help transition from one impression to another. If nature directly triggered the passion of pride or humility, it would be complete by itself and wouldn’t need any further input or support from any other emotion. But if we assume the first emotion is just related to pride or humility, it’s easy to see how the connection of objects might be useful, and how the two different associations of impressions and ideas can work together to support each other’s function. This isn’t just easy to imagine; I’d go as far as to say it’s the only way we can understand this topic. A simple flow of ideas, which by itself doesn’t trigger any emotion, is never necessary or even helpful to the passions, except by aiding the transition between related impressions. Not to mention that the same object can cause a higher or lower level of pride, not only based on the increase or decrease of its qualities but also on how close or far the relationship is; this clearly shows how the movement of feelings aligns with the connection of ideas since any change in the relationship results in a corresponding change in the passion. Thus, one aspect of the previous discussion about the relationships of ideas serves as solid evidence for the other concerning impressions, and is so clearly based on experience that it would be a waste of time to try to prove it further.
This will appear still more evidently in particular instances. Men are vain of the beauty of their country, of their county, of their parish. Here the idea of beauty plainly produces a pleasure. This pleasure is related to pride. The object or cause of this pleasure is, by the supposition, related to self, or the object of pride. By this double relation of impressions and ideas, a transition is made from the one impression to the other.
This will be even clearer in specific examples. People take pride in the beauty of their country, their county, and their local area. Here, the idea of beauty clearly brings pleasure. This pleasure is connected to pride. The source of this pleasure, by definition, relates to oneself or the object of pride. Through this dual connection of impressions and ideas, a shift occurs from one impression to another.
Men are also vain of the temperature of the climate, in which they were born; of the fertility of their native soil; of the goodness of the wines, fruits or victuals, produced by it; of the softness or force of their language; with other particulars of that kind. These objects have plainly a reference to the pleasures of the senses, and are originally considered as agreeable to the feeling, taste or hearing. How is it possible they could ever become objects of pride, except by means of that transition above-explained?
Men also take pride in the climate they were born in, the fertility of their homeland, the quality of its wines, fruits, or food, the softness or strength of their language, and other similar aspects. These things are clearly linked to sensory pleasures and are initially seen as enjoyable to the senses of touch, taste, or hearing. How could they ever become sources of pride if not through the process described earlier?
There are some, that discover a vanity of an opposite kind, and affect to depreciate their own country, in comparison of those, to which they have travelled. These persons find, when they are at home, and surrounded with their countrymen, that the strong relation betwixt them and their own nation is shared with so many, that it is in a manner lost to them; whereas their distant relation to a foreign country, which is formed by their having seen it and lived in it, is augmented by their considering how few there are who have done the same. For this reason they always admire the beauty, utility and rarity of what is abroad, above what is at home.
Some people discover a different kind of vanity and tend to belittle their own country compared to those they have traveled to. These individuals realize that when they are back home, surrounded by people from their own nation, the strong connection they have with it is diluted because so many share that bond; in contrast, their distant connection to a foreign country, which develops from having seen and lived there, feels stronger because they appreciate how few others have experienced it. For this reason, they always admire the beauty, usefulness, and uniqueness of what’s abroad more than what’s at home.
Since we can be vain of a country, climate or any inanimate object, which bears a relation to us, it is no wonder we are vain of the qualities of those, who are connected with us by blood or friendship. Accordingly we find, that the very same qualities, which in ourselves produce pride, produce also in a lesser degree the same affection, when discovered in persons related to us. The beauty, address, merit, credit and honours of their kindred are carefully displayed by the proud, as some of their most considerable sources of their vanity.
Since we can take pride in a country, climate, or any inanimate object that relates to us, it’s no surprise that we also take pride in the qualities of those connected to us by blood or friendship. As a result, we see that the same qualities that make us proud also create a similar, though lesser, affection when found in our relatives. The beauty, charm, talent, reputation, and honors of their family members are often showcased by the proud as significant sources of their vanity.
As we are proud of riches in ourselves, so to satisfy our vanity we desire that every one, who has any connexion with us, should likewise be possest of them, and are ashamed of any one, that is mean or poor, among our friends and relations. For this reason we remove the poor as far from us as possible; and as we cannot prevent poverty in some distant collaterals, and our forefathers are taken to be our nearest relations; upon this account every one affects to be of a good family, and to be descended from a long succession of rich and honourable ancestors.
As we take pride in our own wealth, we want everyone connected to us to have the same, and we feel embarrassed if any of our friends or family are poor or lack status. Because of this, we distance ourselves from those in need as much as we can; and since we can’t control poverty among distant relatives, and since our ancestors are seen as our closest connections, everyone tries to claim they come from a good family and are descended from a long line of wealthy and respectable ancestors.
I have frequently observed, that those, who boast of the antiquity of their families, are glad when they can join this circumstance, that their ancestors for many generations have been uninterrupted proprietors of the same portion of land, and that their family has never changed its possessions, or been transplanted into any other county or province. I have also observed, that it is an additional subject of vanity, when they can boast, that these possessions have been transmitted through a descent composed entirely of males, and that the honour, and fortune have never past through any female. Let us endeavour to explain these phaenomena by the foregoing system.
I often notice that those who take pride in their family's long history are happy to point out that their ancestors have consistently owned the same piece of land for many generations and that their family has never changed its holdings or moved to another county or province. I've also seen that it adds to their pride when they can claim that these possessions have been passed down through a line of only men, and that the honor and wealth have never gone through any women. Let's try to explain these phenomena using the system mentioned earlier.
It is evident, that when any one boasts of the antiquity of his family, the subjects of his vanity are not merely the extent of time and number of ancestors, but also their riches and credit, which are supposed to reflect a lustre on himself on account of his relation to them. He first considers these objects; is affected by them in an agreeable manner; and then returning back to himself, through the relation of parent and child, is elevated with the passion of pride, by means of the double relation, of impressions and ideas. Since therefore the passion depends on these relations, whatever strengthens any of the relations must also encrease the passion, and whatever weakens the relations must diminish the passion. Now it is certain the identity of the possesion strengthens the relation of ideas arising from blood and kindred, and conveys the fancy with greater facility from one generation to another, from the remote ancestors to their posterity, who are both their heirs and their descendants. By this facility the impression is transmitted more entire, and excites a greater degree of pride and vanity.
It's clear that when someone brags about their family's history, they're not just talking about how long their family has been around or how many ancestors they have, but also about their wealth and reputation, which they believe enhance their own image because of their connection to those ancestors. They first reflect on these aspects, feel positively about them, and then, when they think of their own identity in relation to their family, they experience a surge of pride, fueled by both the impressions and ideas tied to their lineage. Therefore, since pride relies on these connections, anything that strengthens these connections will increase that pride, while anything that weakens them will reduce it. It's clear that having family wealth reinforces the ties of blood and kinship and helps the idea of these ties pass more easily from one generation to the next, from distant ancestors to their descendants, who are both their heirs and their successors. This ease of transmission keeps the impression intact and heightens feelings of pride and vanity.
The case is the same with the transmission of the honours and fortune through a succession of males without their passing through any female. It is a quality of human nature, which we shall consider[4] afterwards, that the imagination naturally turns to whatever is important and considerable; and where two objects are presented to it, a small and a great one, usually leaves the former, and dwells entirely upon the latter. As in the society of marriage, the male sex has the advantage above the female, the husband first engages our attention; and whether we consider him directly, or reach him by passing through related objects, the thought both rests upon him with greater satisfaction, and arrives at him with greater facility than his consort. It is easy to see, that this property must strengthen the child's relation to the father, and weaken that to the mother. For as all relations are nothing but a propensity to pass from one idea to another, whatever strengthens the propensity strengthens the relation; and as we have a stronger propensity to pass from the idea of the children to that of the father, than from the same idea to that of the mother, we ought to regard the former relation as the closer and more considerable. This is the reason why children commonly bear their father's name, and are esteemed to be of nobler or baser birth, according to his family. And though the mother should be possest of a superior spirit and genius to the father, as often happens, the general rule prevails, notwithstanding the exception, according to the doctrine above-explained. Nay even when a superiority of any kind is so great, or when any other reasons have such an effect, as to make the children rather represent: the mother's family than the father's, the general rule still retains such an efficacy that it weakens the relation, and makes a kind of break in the line of ancestors. The imagination runs not along them with facility, nor is able to transfer the honour and credit of the ancestors to their posterity of the same name and family so readily, as when the transition is conformable to the general rules, and passes from father to son, or from brother to brother.
The situation is similar when it comes to passing down honors and wealth through a line of males without involving any females. It’s a part of human nature, which we will explore later, that our imagination tends to focus on what’s important and significant; when faced with two options, one small and one large, we usually overlook the smaller one and concentrate on the larger. In marriage, the male has the upper hand over the female, so the husband catches our attention first; whether we consider him directly or think of him through related people, our thoughts tend to linger on him with more satisfaction and are more easily directed to him than to his wife. It's easy to see that this tendency must reinforce a child's connection to the father while weakening their bond with the mother. Since all relationships are essentially the inclination to move from one idea to another, anything that strengthens this inclination enhances the relationship; and given that we have a stronger tendency to connect the idea of children with their father rather than with their mother, we should view the former relationship as closer and more significant. This explains why children typically take their father's last name and are seen as more prestigious or less so, based on their father's lineage. Even if the mother possesses greater qualities or talent than the father, which often happens, the overall trend still holds true, despite exceptions, based on the reasoning outlined above. Furthermore, even when the advantages are significant enough or other factors lead to children being more associated with the mother’s family, the general trend still has such a strong impact that it weakens the relationship and creates a sort of break in the family line. The imagination doesn’t flow easily along this line nor can it readily transfer the honor and reputation of ancestors to their descendants of the same name and family as smoothly as when the transition follows the standard pattern from father to son, or from brother to brother.
[4] Part II. Sect, 2.
SECT. X OF PROPERTY AND RICHES
But the relation, which is esteemed the closest, and which of all others produces most commonly the passion of pride, is that of property. This relation it will be impossible for me fully to explain before I come to treat of justice and the other moral virtues. It is sufficient to observe on this occasion, that property may be defined, such a relation betwixt a person and an object as permits him, but forbids any other, the free use and possession of it, without violating the laws of justice and moral equity. If justice, therefore, be a virtue, which has a natural and original influence on the human mind, property may be looked upon as a particular species of causation; whether we consider the liberty it gives the proprietor to operate as he please upon the object or the advantages, which he reaps from it. It is the same case, if justice, according to the system of certain philosophers, should be esteemed an artificial and not a natural virtue. For then honour, and custom, and civil laws supply the place of natural conscience, and produce, in some degree, the same effects. This in the mean time is certain, that the mention of the property naturally carries our thought to the proprietor, and of the proprietor to the property; which being a proof of a perfect relation of ideas is all that is requisite to our present purpose. A relation of ideas, joined to that of impressions, always produces a transition of affections; and therefore, whenever any pleasure or pain arises from an object, connected with us by property. we may be certain, that either pride or humility must arise from this conjunction of relations; if the foregoing system be solid and satisfactory. And whether it be so or not, we may soon satisfy ourselves by the most cursory view of human life.
But the relationship deemed the closest, which most often stirs feelings of pride, is that of property. I won't be able to fully explain this relationship until I discuss justice and other moral virtues. For now, it's enough to note that property can be defined as a connection between a person and an object that allows the person, but prohibits anyone else, to freely use and possess it without breaking the laws of justice and moral fairness. If justice is indeed a virtue that naturally influences the human mind, property can be seen as a specific type of causation; whether we look at the freedom it gives the owner to act as they wish with the object, or the benefits they gain from it. The situation is similar if justice, according to certain philosophers' views, is seen as an artificial virtue rather than a natural one. In that case, honor, custom, and civil laws take the place of natural conscience, producing similar effects to some extent. What is certain is that talking about property naturally brings our thoughts to the owner, and vice versa; this connection of ideas is all that's needed for our current discussion. A connection of ideas combined with impressions always leads to a shift in feelings, so whenever pleasure or pain arises from an object linked to us through property, we can be sure that either pride or humility will result from this combination of relationships; if the previous reasoning holds true. Whether it does or not, we can quickly assess this by taking a look at human life.
Every thing belonging to a vain man is the best that is anywhere to be found. His houses, equipage, furniture, doaths, horses, hounds, excel all others in his conceit; and it is easy to observe, that from the least advantage in any of these, he draws a new subject of pride and vanity. His wine, if you'll believe him, has a finer flavour than any other; his cookery is more exquisite; his table more orderly; his servants more expert; the air, in which he lives, more healthful; the soil he cultivates more fertile; his fruits ripen earlier and to greater perfection: Such a thing is remarkable for its novelty; such another for its antiquity: This is the workmanship of a famous artist; that belonged once to such a prince or great man: All objects, in a word, that are useful, beautiful or surprising, or are related to such, may, by means of property, give rise to this passion. These agree in giving pleasure, and agree in nothing else. This alone is common to them; and therefore must be the quality that produces the passion, which is their common effect. As every new instance is a new argument, and as the instances are here without number, I may venture to affirm, that scarce any system was ever so fully proved by experience, as that which I have here advanced.
Everything a vain person owns is the best there is. Their homes, possessions, furniture, clothes, horses, and dogs are all superior in their eyes, and it's easy to see that from even the smallest advantage in any of these things, they create new reasons for pride and vanity. Their wine, if you believe them, has a better flavor than any other; their cooking is more refined; their table is more organized; their servants are more skilled; the air they breathe is healthier; the land they farm is more productive; their fruits ripen faster and better. One thing is outstanding because it's new; another is notable for being old; this item was crafted by a famous artist; that one once belonged to a notable prince or figure. In short, anything that is useful, beautiful, surprising, or related to such things can, through ownership, ignite this passion. They share the ability to provide pleasure but have nothing else in common. This is the only trait they share, and thus it must be the quality that generates the passion, which is the common result. Since every new example is a new point, and there are countless examples here, I can confidently say that few theories have been as thoroughly validated by experience as the one I’ve presented.
If the property of any thing, that gives pleasure either by its utility, beauty or novelty, produces also pride by a double relation of impressions and ideas; we need not be surprized, that the power of acquiring this property, should have the same effect. Now riches are to be considered as the power of acquiring the property of what pleases; and it is only in this view they have any influence on the passions. Paper will, on many occasions, be considered as riches, and that because it may convey the power of acquiring money: And money is not riches, as it is a metal endowed with certain qualities of solidity, weight and fusibility; but only as it has a relation to the pleasures and conveniences of life. Taking then this for granted, which is in itself so evident, we may draw from it one of the strongest arguments I have yet employed to prove the influence of the double relations on pride and humility.
If the qualities of something that bring pleasure through its usefulness, beauty, or novelty also create pride through a connection of impressions and ideas, we shouldn't be surprised that the ability to acquire that quality has the same effect. Now, wealth can be seen as the ability to acquire things that please us, and it’s only in this context that it affects our emotions. Paper will often be viewed as wealth because it can give you the power to acquire money. And money isn’t wealth in itself, as it’s just a metal with specific properties like solidity, weight, and ability to melt; it's only valuable because of its connection to life's pleasures and conveniences. Accepting this as obvious, we can derive one of the strongest arguments I've presented so far to demonstrate how these connections influence pride and humility.
It has been observed in treating of the understanding, that the distinction, which we sometimes make betwixt a power and the exercise of it, is entirely frivolous, and that neither man nor any other being ought ever to be thought possest of any ability, unless it be exerted and put in action. But though this be strictly true in a just and philosophical way of thinking, it is certain it is not the philosophy of our passions; but that many things operate upon them by means of the idea and supposition of power, independent of its actual exercise. We are pleased when we acquire an ability of procuring pleasure, and are displeased when another acquires a power of giving pain. This is evident from experience; but in order to give a just explication of the matter, and account for this satisfaction and uneasiness, we must weigh the following reflections.
It has been noted in discussions about understanding that the distinction we sometimes make between having the ability and using it is completely pointless, and that neither people nor any other beings should be considered to have any ability unless it is actually used and put into action. While this is absolutely true in a logical and philosophical sense, it's clear that this isn’t how our emotions work. Many things influence our feelings based on the idea and assumption of power, regardless of whether it’s actually exercised. We feel happy when we gain the ability to obtain pleasure, and we feel unhappy when someone else gains the power to inflict pain. This is clear from experience; however, to provide a proper explanation of the situation and account for this happiness and discomfort, we need to consider the following reflections.
It is evident the error of distinguishing power from its exercise proceeds not entirely from the scholastic doctrine of free-will, which, indeed, enters very little into common life, and has but small influence on our vulgar and popular ways of thinking. According to that doctrine, motives deprive us not of free-will, nor take away our power of performing or forbearing any action. But according to common notions a man has no power, where very considerable motives lie betwixt him and the satisfaction of his desires, and determine him to forbear what he wishes to perform. I do not think I have fallen into my enemy's power, when I see him pass me in the streets with a sword by his side, while I am unprovided of any weapon. I know that the fear of the civil magistrate is as strong a restraint as any of iron, and that I am in as perfect safety as if he were chained or imprisoned. But when a person acquires such an authority over me, that not only there is no external obstacle to his actions; but also that he may punish or reward me as he pleases, without any dread of punishment in his turn, I then attribute a full power to him, and consider myself as his subject or vassal.
It’s clear that the mistake of separating power from its use doesn't entirely come from the old-school idea of free will, which really doesn’t play a big role in everyday life and has minimal impact on how people typically think. According to that idea, motives don’t take away our free will or our ability to do or not do something. However, in everyday thinking, a person is considered powerless when significant motives stand between them and fulfilling their desires, thus pushing them to hold back on what they want to do. I don’t feel like I’m under someone else’s control when I see them walk past me in the street with a sword while I’m unarmed. I understand that the fear of law enforcement is just as strong a restraint as any physical chain, and I feel just as safe as if that person were locked up. But when someone gains such authority over me that there’s no external barrier to their actions, and they can punish or reward me as they wish without fearing any consequences themselves, I then see them as having full power over me and view myself as their subject or subordinate.
Now if we compare these two cases, that of a person, who has very strong motives of interest or safety to forbear any action, and that of another, who lies under no such obligation, we shall find, according to the philosophy explained in the foregoing book, that the only known difference betwixt them lies in this, that in the former case we conclude from past experience, that the person never will perform that action, and in the latter, that he possibly or probably will perform it. Nothing is more fluctuating and inconstant on many occasions, than the will of man; nor is there any thing but strong motives, which can give us an absolute certainty in pronouncing concerning any of his future actions. When we see a person free from these motives, we suppose a possibility either of his acting or forbearing; and though in general we may conclude him to be determined by motives and causes, yet this removes not the uncertainty of our judgment concerning these causes, nor the influence of that uncertainty on the passions. Since therefore we ascribe a power of performing an action to every one, who has no very powerful motive to forbear it, and refuse it to such as have; it may justly be concluded, that power has always a reference to its exercise, either actual or probable, and that we consider a person as endowed with any ability when we find from past experience, that it is probable, or at least possible he may exert it. And indeed, as our passions always regard the real existence of objects, and we always judge of this reality from past instances; nothing can be more likely of itself, without any farther reasoning, than that power consists in the possibility or probability of any action, as discovered by experience and the practice of the world.
If we compare these two situations—one where a person has strong reasons related to interest or safety to refrain from acting, and another where someone doesn’t have such obligations—we’ll find, according to the ideas discussed in the previous book, that the main difference between them is this: in the first case, we conclude from past experience that the person will never take that action, while in the second case, we think he might or probably will. The will of man can often be very changeable and unpredictable; nothing but strong motives can give us complete certainty about any of his future actions. When we see someone free from these motives, we assume it's possible for him to either act or hold back; and although we generally believe he will be influenced by motives and causes, that doesn’t eliminate our uncertainty regarding those causes or the effect of that uncertainty on feelings. Therefore, we ascribe the ability to perform an action to anyone who doesn’t have a strong reason to avoid it, and deny it to those who do. It’s reasonable to conclude that power always refers to its actual or potential exercise, and we see someone as having an ability when past experience suggests it’s likely, or at least possible, that they may use it. Indeed, since our feelings are always tied to the actual existence of things, and we judge that reality based on past experiences, it’s reasonable to think that power is about the possibility or likelihood of any action, as shown by experience and what we observe in daily life.
Now it is evident, that wherever a person is in such a situation with regard to me, that there is no very powerful motive to deter him from injuring me, and consequently it is uncertain whether he will injure me or not, I must be uneasy in such a situation, and cannot consider the possibility or probability of that injury without a sensible concern. The passions are not only affected by such events as are certain and infallible, but also in an inferior degree by such as are possible and contingent. And though perhaps I never really feel any harm, and discover by the event, that, philosophically speaking, the person never had any power of harming me; since he did not exert any; this prevents not my uneasiness from the preceding uncertainty. The agreeable passions may here operate as well as the uneasy, and convey a pleasure when I perceive a good to become either possible or probable by the possibility or probability of another's bestowing it on me, upon the removal of any strong motives, which might formerly have hindered him.
Now it's clear that whenever someone is in a position towards me where there's no strong reason to stop them from harming me, it's uncertain whether they will actually cause me harm or not. In that situation, I can't help but feel uneasy, and I can't think about the chance of that harm without feeling real concern. Our feelings are influenced not only by things that are certain and definite but also by those that are merely possible or uncertain. And even if I never actually experience any harm and find out that, from a philosophical standpoint, the person never had the ability to harm me since they didn’t act on it, that doesn’t stop my unease from the prior uncertainty. Positive feelings can come into play here just like negative ones, giving me pleasure when I see a good thing becoming possible or likely because someone might choose to give it to me, especially after any strong reasons that may have previously held them back are removed.
But we may farther observe, that this satisfaction encreases, when any good approaches in such a manner that it is in one's own power to take or leave it, and there neither is any physical impediment, nor any very strong motive to hinder our enjoyment. As all men desire pleasure, nothing can be more probable, than its existence when there is no external obstacle to the producing it, and men perceive no danger in following their inclinations. In that case their imagination easily anticipates the satisfaction, and conveys the same joy, as if they were persuaded of its real and actual existence.
But we can also note that this satisfaction increases when a good thing comes close enough that it’s in our power to choose whether to take it or leave it, and there’s no physical barrier or strong reason to stop us from enjoying it. Since everyone wants pleasure, it’s very likely to exist when there are no outside obstacles to create it, and people don’t see any danger in following their desires. In that situation, their imagination easily predicts the satisfaction and brings the same joy as if they were sure it truly existed.
But this accounts not sufficiently for the satisfaction, which attends riches. A miser receives delight from his money; that is, from the power it affords him of procuring all the pleasures and conveniences of life, though he knows he has enjoyed his riches for forty years without ever employing them; and consequently cannot conclude by any species of reasoning, that the real existence of these pleasures is nearer, than if he were entirely deprived of all his possessions. But though he cannot form any such conclusion in a way of reasoning concerning the nearer approach of the pleasure, it is certain he imagines it to approach nearer, whenever all external obstacles are removed, along with the more powerful motives of interest and danger, which oppose it. For farther satisfaction on this head I must refer to my account of the will, where I shall[5] explain that false sensation of liberty, which makes us imagine we can perform any thing, that is not very dangerous or destructive. Whenever any other person is under no strong obligations of interest to forbear any pleasure, we judge from experience, that the pleasure will exist, and that he will probably obtain it. But when ourselves are in that situation, we judge from an illusion of the fancy, that the pleasure is still closer and more immediate. The will seems to move easily every way, and casts a shadow or image of itself, even to that side, on which it did not settle. By means of this image the enjoyment seems to approach nearer to us, and gives us the same lively satisfaction, as if it were perfectly certain and unavoidable.
But this doesn’t fully explain the pleasure that comes with wealth. A miser finds joy in his money; that is, in the power it gives him to obtain all the pleasures and comforts of life, even though he realizes he has enjoyed his wealth for forty years without actually using it. Therefore, he can’t logically conclude that the true existence of these pleasures is any closer than if he had nothing at all. However, even if he can’t reason that the pleasure is nearer, he definitely believes it comes closer whenever all external barriers, along with stronger motives of interest and danger, are removed. For further insight on this topic, I’ll refer you to my discussion about the will, where I will explain that false sense of freedom that leads us to think we can pursue anything that isn’t very risky or harmful. When someone else has no strong incentives to avoid a pleasure, we assume based on experience that the pleasure exists and that they are likely to attain it. But when we find ourselves in that situation, we are misled by our imagination into thinking the pleasure is even closer and more immediate. The will appears to move freely in all directions and projects an image of itself in the direction it doesn’t settle on. Through this image, the enjoyment seems to come closer to us and gives us the same lively satisfaction as if it were completely certain and unavoidable.
[5] Part III. Sect. 2.
It will now be easy to draw this whole reasoning to a point, and to prove, that when riches produce any pride or vanity in their possessors, as they never fail to do, it is only by means of a double relation of impressions and ideas. The very essence of riches consists in the power of procuring the pleasures and conveniences of life. The very essence of this consists in the probability of its exercise, and in its causing us to anticipate, by a true or false reasoning, the real existence of the pleasure. This anticipation of pleasure is, in itself, a very considerable pleasure; and as its cause is some possession or property, which we enjoy, and which is thereby related to us, we here dearly see all the parts of the foregoing system most exactly and distinctly drawn out before us. For the same reason, that riches cause pleasure and pride, and poverty excites uneasiness and humility, power must produce the former emotions, and slavery the latter. Power or an authority over others makes us capable of satisfying all our desires; as slavery, by subjecting us to the will of others, exposes us to a thousand wants, and mortifications.
It’s now straightforward to summarize this entire argument and demonstrate that when wealth creates any sense of pride or vanity in its holders, which it always does, it happens through a combination of impressions and ideas. The essence of wealth lies in its ability to provide life's pleasures and conveniences. The core of this is the likelihood we will experience those pleasures, and our ability to anticipate, whether accurately or not, the real presence of that pleasure. This anticipation itself is a significant pleasure; and since its source is some possession or property we have, which is connected to us, we can clearly see all the components of the previous system laid out before us. Similarly, just as wealth brings pleasure and pride, and poverty brings discomfort and humility, power generates the former emotions, while slavery brings about the latter. Having power or authority over others allows us to fulfill all our desires; on the other hand, slavery, by forcing us to conform to others' will, leaves us vulnerable to countless needs and humiliations.
It is here worth observing, that the vanity of power, or shame of slavery, are much augmented by the consideration of the persons, over whom we exercise our authority, or who exercise it over us. For supposing it possible to frame statues of such an admirable mechanism, that they could move and act in obedience to the will; it is evident the possession of them would give pleasure and pride, but not to such a degree, as the same authority, when exerted over sensible and rational creatures, whose condition, being compared to our own, makes it seem more agreeable and honourable. Comparison is in every case a sure method of augmenting our esteem of any thing. A rich man feels the felicity of his condition better by opposing it to that of a beggar. But there is a peculiar advantage in power, by the contrast, which is, in a manner, presented to us, betwixt ourselves and the person we command. The comparison is obvious and natural: The imagination finds it in the very subject: The passage of the thought to its conception is smooth and easy. And that this circumstance has a considerable effect in augmenting its influence, will appear afterwards in examining the nature of malice and envy.
It's worth noting that the vanity of power and the shame of slavery are heightened by who we have authority over or who has authority over us. If we could create statues that could move and act according to our wishes, owning them would bring pleasure and pride, but not to the same extent as having power over sentient beings. The comparison of their condition to our own makes it seem more desirable and honorable. In any case, comparison is a reliable way to enhance our appreciation of something. A wealthy person understands their happiness better when they contrast it with that of a beggar. There's a unique advantage to power in this contrast between ourselves and those we command. The comparison is clear and instinctive; our imagination easily connects the two. This factor has a significant impact on increasing its influence, as will be shown later when we explore the nature of malice and envy.
SECT. XI OF THE LOVE OF FAME
But beside these original causes of pride and humility, there is a secondary one in the opinions of others, which has an equal influence on the affections. Our reputation, our character, our name are considerations of vast weight and importance; and even the other causes of pride; virtue, beauty and riches; have little influence, when not seconded by the opinions and sentiments of others. In order to account for this phænomenon it will be necessary to take some compass, and first explain the nature of sympathy.
But in addition to these fundamental reasons for pride and humility, there’s a secondary one rooted in how others perceive us, which has a significant impact on our feelings. Our reputation, character, and name carry immense weight and importance; indeed, even other sources of pride—like virtue, beauty, and wealth—hold little power unless supported by the opinions and feelings of those around us. To understand this phenomenon, we first need to broaden our perspective and explain the nature of sympathy.
No quality of human nature is more remarkable, both in itself and in its consequences, than that propensity we have to sympathize with others, and to receive by communication their inclinations and sentiments, however different from, or even contrary to our own. This is not only conspicuous in children, who implicitly embrace every opinion proposed to them; but also in men of the greatest judgment and understanding, who find it very difficult to follow their own reason or inclination, in opposition to that of their friends and daily companions. To this principle we ought to ascribe the great uniformity we may observe in the humours and turn of thinking of those of the same nation; and it is much more probable, that this resemblance arises from sympathy, than from any influence of the soil and climate, which, though they continue invariably the same, are not able to preserve the character of a nation the same for a century together. A good-natured man finds himself in an instant of the same humour with his company; and even the proudest and most surly take a tincture from their countrymen and acquaintance. A chearful countenance infuses a sensible complacency and serenity into my mind; as an angry or sorrowful one throws a sudden dump upon me. Hatred, resentment, esteem, love, courage, mirth and melancholy; all these passions I feel more from communication than from my own natural temper and disposition. So remarkable a phænomenon merits our attention, and must be traced up to its first principles.
No aspect of human nature is more noteworthy, both in itself and in its effects, than our tendency to empathize with others and to absorb their feelings and attitudes, no matter how different or even opposite they are from our own. This is clear not only in children, who easily accept every opinion given to them, but also in highly intelligent and discerning adults, who struggle to adhere to their own reasoning or desires when they conflict with those of their friends and everyday companions. We should attribute the significant consistency we observe in the moods and thought patterns of people from the same nation to this principle. It’s much more likely that this similarity comes from empathy rather than from the influence of the land and climate, which, while they remain constant, cannot sustain a nation's character for a century. A good-natured person instantly aligns their mood with those around them; even the proudest and gruffest individuals are influenced by their fellow countrymen and acquaintances. A cheerful expression brings a sense of comfort and calm to my mind, while an angry or sad one quickly brings me down. Feelings like hatred, resentment, admiration, love, courage, joy, and sadness are more strongly felt through interaction with others than from my own natural temperament. Such a striking phenomenon deserves our attention and should be traced back to its core principles.
When any affection is infused by sympathy, it is at first known only by its effects, and by those external signs in the countenance and conversation, which convey an idea of it. This idea is presently converted into an impression, and acquires such a degree of force and vivacity, as to become the very passion itself, and produce an equal emotion, as any original affection. However instantaneous this change of the idea into an impression may be, it proceeds from certain views and reflections, which will not escape the strict scrutiny of a philosopher, though they may the person himself, who makes them.
When any feeling is triggered by sympathy, it’s initially recognized only through its effects and the external signs in a person’s expression and conversation that suggest its presence. This notion quickly transforms into a strong impression that can become the very emotion itself, evoking a response as intense as any original feeling. Despite how quickly this shift from idea to impression occurs, it stems from specific thoughts and reflections that a philosopher would not overlook, even if the person experiencing it might.
It is evident, that the idea, or rather impression of ourselves is always intimately present with us, and that our consciousness gives us so lively a conception of our own person, that it is not possible to imagine, that any thing can in this particular go beyond it. Whatever object, therefore, is related to ourselves must be conceived with a little vivacity of conception, according to the foregoing principles; and though this relation should not be so strong as that of causation, it must still have a considerable influence. Resemblance and contiguity are relations not to be neglected; especially when by an inference from cause and effect, and by the observation of external signs, we are informed of the real existence of the object, which is resembling or contiguous.
It's clear that our idea, or more accurately, our impression of ourselves is always right there with us, and our awareness gives us such a vivid understanding of our own identity that it’s hard to believe anything could surpass it in this regard. Any object related to ourselves must be understood with a bit of liveliness in our thoughts, based on the principles mentioned earlier; and even if this connection isn’t as strong as a causal relationship, it still has a significant impact. Similarity and proximity are connections we shouldn’t overlook, especially when we deduce information from cause and effect and observe external signs that inform us of the real existence of the object that is similar or nearby.
Now it is obvious, that nature has preserved a great resemblance among all human creatures, and that we never remark any passion or principle in others, of which, in some degree or other, we may not find a parallel in ourselves. The case is the same with the fabric of the mind, as with that of the body. However the parts may differ in shape or size, their structure and composition are in general the same. There is a very remarkable resemblance, which preserves itself amidst all their variety; and this resemblance must very much contribute to make us enter into the sentiments of others; and embrace them with facility and pleasure. Accordingly we find, that where, beside the general resemblance of our natures, there is any peculiar similarity in our manners, or character, or country, or language, it facilitates the sympathy. The stronger the relation is betwixt ourselves and any object, the more easily does the imagination make the transition, and convey to the related idea the vivacity of conception, with which we always form the idea of our own person.
It's clear that nature has kept a strong similarity among all humans, and we often notice emotions or principles in others that we can, in some way, relate to ourselves. The same goes for the mind's structure as it does for the body. Even if the parts vary in shape or size, their overall structure and makeup are generally alike. There’s a significant similarity that persists despite all the differences; this similarity helps us connect with the feelings of others and accept them easily and happily. We find that when there are unique similarities in our behaviors, characteristics, country, or language on top of our general commonalities, it makes empathy easier. The stronger our connection to something is, the easier it is for our imagination to shift and bring that related idea to life with the same intensity we feel about ourselves.
Nor is resemblance the only relation, which has this effect, but receives new force from other relations, that may accompany it. The sentiments of others have little influence, when far removed from us, and require the relation of contiguity, to make them communicate themselves entirely. The relations of blood, being a species of causation, may sometimes contribute to the same effect; as also acquaintance, which operates in the same manner with education and custom; as we shall see more fully[6] afterwards. All these relations, when united together, convey the impression or consciousness of our own person to the idea of the sentiments or passions of others, and makes us conceive them in the strongest and most lively manner.
Resemblance isn't the only connection that creates this effect; it gains even more strength from other relationships that may accompany it. The feelings of others have little impact when they are far away from us, and we need to be close to truly share those feelings. Family ties, which are a type of cause-and-effect relationship, can sometimes create the same effect. Likewise, familiarity works the same way as education and habit, as we'll discuss in more detail later. When all these relationships come together, they help us feel and understand our own identity with respect to the feelings or emotions of others, making us perceive them in the most intense and vivid way.
[6] Part II. Sect. 4.
It has been remarked in the beginning of this treatise, that all ideas are borrowed from impressions, and that these two kinds of perceptions differ only in the degrees of force and vivacity, with which they strike upon the soul. The component part of ideas and impressions are precisely alike. The manner and order of their appearance may be the same. The different degrees of their force and vivacity are, therefore, the only particulars, that distinguish them: And as this difference may be removed, in some measure, by a relation betwixt the impressions and ideas, it is no wonder an idea of a sentiment or passion, may by this means be inlivened as to become the very sentiment or passion. The lively idea of any object always approaches is impression; and it is certain we may feel sickness and pain from the mere force of imagination, and make a malady real by often thinking of it. But this is most remarkable in the opinions and affections; and it is there principally that a lively idea is converted into an impression. Our affections depend more upon ourselves, and the internal operations of the mind, than any other impressions; for which reason they arise more naturally from the imagination, and from every lively idea we form of them. This is the nature and cause of sympathy; and it is after this manner we enter so deep into the opinions and affections of others, whenever we discover them.
It was noted at the beginning of this work that all ideas come from impressions, and that these two types of perceptions only differ in the intensity and vividness with which they impact the mind. The fundamental elements of ideas and impressions are exactly the same. Their appearance can occur in similar ways and sequences. Therefore, the varying degrees of their intensity and vividness are the only factors that set them apart. Since this difference can sometimes be lessened by a connection between impressions and ideas, it’s not surprising that an idea of a feeling or emotion can become so vivid that it turns into the actual feeling or emotion. A vivid idea of any object tends to resemble an impression; it’s clear we can experience illness and pain simply through the power of imagination, making a condition feel real by frequently thinking about it. This is particularly evident in beliefs and emotions; it's mainly here that a vivid idea transforms into an impression. Our emotions rely more on ourselves and the inner workings of the mind than on other impressions, which is why they arise more naturally from our imagination and from every vivid idea we create about them. This explains the nature and cause of sympathy, and it’s how we become deeply engaged with the opinions and emotions of others whenever we recognize them.
What is principally remarkable in this whole affair is the strong confirmation these phaenomena give to the foregoing system concerning the understanding, and consequently to the present one concerning the passions; since these are analogous to each other. It is indeed evident, that when we sympathize with the passions and sentiments of others, these movements appear at first in our mind as mere ideas, and are conceived to belong to another person, as we conceive any other matter of fact. It is also evident, that the ideas of the affections of others are converted into the very impressions they represent, and that the passions arise in conformity to the images we form of them. All this is an object of the plainest experience, and depends not on any hypothesis of philosophy. That science can only be admitted to explain the phaenomena; though at the same time it must be confest, they are so clear of themselves, that there is but little occasion to employ it. For besides the relation of cause and effect, by which we are convinced of the reality of the passion, with which we sympathize; besides this, I say, we must be assisted by the relations of resemblance and contiguity, in order to feel the sympathy in its full perfection. And since these relations can entirely convert an idea into an impression, and convey the vivacity of the latter into the former, so perfectly as to lose nothing of it in the transition, we may easily conceive how the relation of cause and effect alone, may serve to strengthen and inliven an idea. In sympathy there is an evident conversion of an idea into an impression. This conversion arises from the relation of objects to ourself. Ourself is always intimately present to us. Let us compare all these circumstances, and we shall find, that sympathy is exactly correspondent to the operations of our understanding; and even contains something more surprizing and extraordinary.
What's most noteworthy in this whole situation is how strongly these phenomena support the previous theory about understanding, and, consequently, the current one about passions, since they are similar to each other. It's clear that when we empathize with the feelings and emotions of others, these reactions initially appear in our mind as simple ideas and are understood to belong to someone else, just like anything else we perceive. It's also obvious that the ideas of others' emotions transform into the very feelings they represent, and that our passions develop in response to the images we create of them. All of this is supported by the most straightforward experience and doesn't rely on any philosophical hypothesis. That science can be used to explain these phenomena, but it's important to admit that they are self-evident enough that we rarely need to rely on it. Besides the cause-and-effect relationship that convinces us of the reality of the passion we empathize with; in addition to that, we need to rely on the relationships of similarity and proximity in order to feel sympathy to its fullest extent. Since these relationships can completely transform an idea into a feeling and convey the intensity of the latter into the former, so thoroughly that nothing is lost in the process, it's easy to understand how the cause-and-effect relationship alone can strengthen and energize an idea. In sympathy, there is a clear transformation of an idea into a feeling. This transformation comes from the relationship of objects to ourselves. We are always acutely aware of ourselves. If we compare all these factors, we will see that sympathy aligns perfectly with the functions of our understanding and even has something more surprising and extraordinary.
It is now time to turn our view from the general consideration of sympathy, to its influence on pride and humility, when these passions arise from praise and blame, from reputation and infamy. We may observe, that no person is ever praised by another for any quality, which would not, if real, produce, of itself, a pride in the person possest of it. The elogiums either turn upon his power, or riches, or family, or virtue; all of which are subjects of vanity, that we have already explained and accounted for. It is certain, then, that if a person considered himself in the same light, in which he appears to his admirer, he would first receive a separate pleasure, and afterwards a pride or self-satisfaction, according to the hypothesis above explained. Now nothing is more natural than for us to embrace the opinions of others in this particular; both from sympathy, which renders all their sentiments intimately present to us; and from reasoning, which makes us regard their judgment, as a kind of argument for what they affirm. These two principles of authority and sympathy influence almost all our opinions; but must have a peculiar influence, when we judge of our own worth and character. Such judgments are always attended with passion;[7] and nothing tends more to disturb our understanding, and precipitate us into any opinions, however unreasonable, than their connexion with passion; which diffuses itself over the imagination, and gives an additional force to every related idea. To which we may add, that being conscious of great partiality in our own favour, we are peculiarly pleased with any thing, that confirms the good opinion we have of ourselves, and are easily shocked with whatever opposes it.
It’s now time to shift our focus from a general view of sympathy to its impact on pride and humility, especially when these feelings stem from praise and blame, reputation and infamy. We can see that no one is ever praised for a quality that wouldn’t, if true, naturally lead to pride in the person who has it. The compliments usually center around their power, wealth, family, or virtues—all of which are sources of vanity that we’ve already discussed. Therefore, if someone viewed themselves in the same way their admirer does, they would first derive a distinct pleasure from this recognition, and later feel pride or self-satisfaction, as explained earlier. It’s quite natural for us to adopt the opinions of others in this regard; both due to sympathy, which makes their feelings resonate with us, and because reasoning allows us to see their judgment as a form of proof for their claims. These two factors—authority and sympathy—shape nearly all our opinions but have a specific influence when evaluating our own worth and character. Such evaluations always come with strong feelings; nothing disrupts our clarity of thought and leads us to adopt, however irrationally, any beliefs more than their link to our emotions, which cloud our imagination and amplify every related thought. Furthermore, being aware of our own bias towards ourselves makes us particularly happy with anything that supports our self-image and easily offended by anything that contradicts it.
All this appears very probable in theory; but in order to bestow a full certainty on this reasoning, we must examine the phaenonena of the passions, and see if they agree with it.
All of this seems very likely in theory; but to give full certainty to this reasoning, we need to look at the phenomena of emotions and check if they align with it.
Among these phaenomena we may esteem it a very favourable one to our present purposes that though fame in general be agreeable, yet we receive a much greater satisfaction from the approbation of those, whom we ourselves esteem and approve of, than of those, whom we hate and despise. In like measure we are principally mortifyed with the contempt of persons, upon whose judgment we set some value, and are, in a peat measure, indifferent about the opinions of the rest of mankind. But if the mind received from any original instinct a desire of fame and aversion to infamy, fame and infamy would influence us without distinction; and every opinion, according as it were favourable or unfavourable, would equally excite that desire or aversion. The judgment of a fool is the judgment of another person, as well as that of a wise man, and is only inferior in its influence on our own judgment.
Among these phenomena, we can consider it quite beneficial for our current purposes that, while fame in general is pleasant, we gain much more satisfaction from the approval of those we respect and admire than from those we hate and look down on. Similarly, we are mainly hurt by the contempt of people whose opinions we value, and we are largely indifferent to the views of the rest of humanity. However, if our minds had an inherent desire for fame and a dislike for infamy, both fame and infamy would affect us equally; every opinion, whether positive or negative, would similarly trigger that desire or aversion. The judgment of a fool is just another person's opinion, like that of a wise person, and is only less influential on our own judgment.
We are not only better pleased with the approbation of a wise man than with that of a fool, but receive an additional satisfaction from the former, when it is obtained after a long and intimate acquaintance. This is accounted for after the same manner.
We not only feel more satisfied with the approval of a wise person than with that of a fool, but we also gain extra satisfaction from the former when it's given after a long and close relationship. This can be explained in the same way.
The praises of others never give us much pleasure, unless they concur with our own opinion, and extol us for those qualities, in which we chiefly excel. A mere soldier little values the character of eloquence: A gownman of courage: A bishop of humour: Or a merchant of learning. Whatever esteem a man may have for any quality, abstractedly considered; when he is conscious he is not possest of it; the opinions of the whole world will give him little pleasure in that particular, and that because they never will be able to draw his own opinion after them.
Praise from others rarely brings us much joy unless it matches our own views and highlights the qualities we take the most pride in. A soldier doesn’t place much importance on eloquence, a scholar on courage, a bishop on humor, or a merchant on knowledge. No matter how much a person might value a particular quality, when they know they don’t possess it, the opinions of everyone else won’t provide them much satisfaction in that area, simply because those opinions can’t change their own.
Nothing is more usual than for men of good families, but narrow circumstances, to leave their friends and country, and rather seek their livelihood by mean and mechanical employments among strangers, than among those, who are acquainted with their birth and education. We shall be unknown, say they, where we go. No body will suspect from what family we are sprung. We shall be removed from all our friends and acquaintance, and our poverty and meanness will by that means sit more easy upon us. In examining these sentiments, I find they afford many very convincing arguments for my present purpose.
Nothing is more common than for people from good families, but difficult situations, to leave their friends and home and choose to make a living through low-paying and manual jobs among strangers rather than with those who know their background and education. They say, "We’ll be unknown wherever we go. No one will suspect our family connections. We’ll be far from all our friends, and being poor and struggling will feel easier this way." When I look closely at these feelings, I find they give many strong reasons for what I'm trying to say.
First, We may infer from them, that the uneasiness of being contemned depends on sympathy, and that sympathy depends on the relation of objects to ourselves; since we are most uneasy under the contempt of persons, who are both related to us by blood, and contiguous in place. Hence we seek to diminish this sympathy and uneasiness by separating these relations, and placing ourselves in a contiguity to strangers, and at a distance from relations.
First, we can conclude from this that the discomfort of being scorned relies on sympathy, and that sympathy depends on how closely objects relate to us; because we feel most uncomfortable when we’re looked down upon by people who are both related to us by blood and nearby. Therefore, we try to lessen this sympathy and discomfort by creating distance from these relationships and surrounding ourselves with strangers instead.
Secondly, We may conclude, that relations are requisite to sympathy, not absolutely considered as relations, but by their influence in converting our ideas of the sentiments of others into the very sentiments, by means of the association betwixt the idea of their persons, and that of our own. For here the relations of kindred and contiguity both subsist; but not being united in the same persons, they contribute in a less degree to the sympathy.
Secondly, we can conclude that relationships are necessary for sympathy, not just as relationships themselves, but because they help us transform our understanding of other people's feelings into the actual feelings themselves, through the connection between our perception of them and our own. Here, both kinship and proximity exist, but since they are not found in the same individuals, they play a smaller role in creating sympathy.
Thirdly, This very circumstance of the diminution of sympathy by the separation of relations is worthy of our attention. Suppose I am placed in a poor condition among strangers, and consequently am but lightly treated; I yet find myself easier in that situation, than when I was every day exposed to the contempt of my kindred and countrymen. Here I feel a double contempt; from my relations, but they are absent; from those about me, but they are strangers. This double contempt is likewise strengthened by the two relations of kindred and contiguity. But as the persons are not the same, who are connected with me by those two relations, this difference of ideas separates the impressions arising from the contempt, and keeps them from running into each other. The contempt of my neighbours has a certain influence; as has also that of my kindred: But these influences are distinct, and never unite; as when the contempt proceeds from persons who are at once both my neighbours and kindred. This phænomenon is analogous to the system of pride and humility above-explained, which may seem so extraordinary to vulgar apprehensions.
Thirdly, the fact that our sympathy decreases with the separation from our relations is worth noting. Imagine I find myself in a tough situation among strangers, and as a result, I'm treated with indifference; I still feel more comfortable in that situation than I did when I faced daily disdain from my family and fellow countrymen. In this case, I experience a double brand of contempt: one from my relatives, who are absent, and another from the people around me, who are strangers. This double contempt is also reinforced by the two connections of family ties and physical proximity. However, since the individuals linked to me by these two connections are different, this distinction in understanding separates the feelings stemming from contempt and prevents them from merging. The disdain from my neighbors has a certain effect, as does the disdain from my relatives; but these effects are separate and never blend together, unlike when the contempt comes from people who are both my neighbors and relatives. This phenomenon is similar to the system of pride and humility explained earlier, which may seem quite unusual to common perceptions.
Fourthly, A person in these circumstances naturally conceals his birth from those among whom he lives, and is very uneasy, if any one suspects him to be of a family, much superior to his present fortune and way of living. Every thing in this world is judged of by comparison. What is an immense fortune for a private gentleman is beggary for a prince. A peasant would think himself happy in what cannot afford necessaries for a gentleman. When a man has either been accustomed to a more splendid way of living, or thinks himself intitled to it by his birth and quality, every thing below is disagreeable and even shameful; and it is with the greatest industry he conceals his pretensions to a better fortune. Here he himself knows his misfortunes; but as those, with whom he lives. are ignorant of them, he has the disagreeable reflection and comparison suggested only by his own thoughts, and never receives it by a sympathy with others; which must contribute very much to his ease and satisfaction.
Fourthly, in these situations, a person will naturally hide their background from those around them and feels very uncomfortable if anyone suspects they come from a family much wealthier than their current circumstances. Everything in this world is judged by comparison. What seems like a huge fortune to a regular person looks like poverty to a prince. A peasant might consider themselves lucky with what wouldn't even cover a gentleman's basic needs. When someone is used to a more lavish lifestyle or believes they deserve one because of their birth and status, everything less than that feels unpleasant and even shameful; they work hard to hide their claims to a better life. While they are aware of their misfortunes, the people they live with remain unaware, so their feelings of discomfort and comparison come only from their own mind and not through a shared understanding with others, which could really help ease their situation and bring them some satisfaction.
If there be any objections to this hypothesis, THAT THE PLEASURE, WHICH WE RECEIVE FROM PRAISE, ARISES FROM A COMMUNICATION OF SENTIMENTS, we shall find, upon examination, that these objections, when taken in a proper light, will serve to confirm it. Popular fame may be agreeable even to a man, who despises the vulgar; but it is because their multitude gives them additional weight and authority. Plagiaries are delighted with praises, which they are conscious they do not deserve; but this is a kind of castle-building, where the imagination amuses itself with its own fictions, and strives to render them firm and stable by a sympathy with the sentiments of others. Proud men are most shocked with contempt, should they do not most readily assent to it; but it is because of the opposition betwixt the passion, which is natural to them, and that received by sympathy. A violent lover in like manner is very much displeased when you blame and condemn his love; though it is evident your opposition can have no influence, but by the hold it takes of himself, and by his sympathy with you. If he despises you, or perceives you are in jest, whatever you say has no effect upon him.
If there are any objections to this idea, THAT THE PLEASURE WE GET FROM PRAISE COMES FROM A SHARING OF FEELINGS, we'll find, upon closer look, that these objections, when viewed correctly, actually support it. Popular admiration can be pleasing even to someone who looks down on the masses; this is because their numbers add extra weight and authority. Plagiarists are happy with praise that they know they don't deserve; this is like daydreaming, where the mind enjoys its own creations and tries to make them strong and lasting by connecting with the feelings of others. Proud individuals are most hurt by contempt if they don’t immediately agree with it; this is due to the clash between their natural feelings and those they sense from others. Similarly, a passionate lover is very upset when you criticize their love; although it's clear that your disapproval can only affect him through his own feelings and his connection to you. If he looks down on you, or realizes you're joking, whatever you say has no impact on him.
SECT. XII OF THE PRIDE AND HUMILITY OF ANIMALS
Thus in whatever light we consider this subject, we may still observe, that die causes of pride and humility correspond exactly to our hypothesis, and that nothing can excite either of these passions, unless it be both related to ourselves, and produces a pleasure or pain independent of the passion. We have not only proved, that a tendency to produce pleasure or pain is common to all the causes of pride or humility, but also that it is the only thing, which is common; and consequently is the quality, by which they operate. We have farther proved, that the most considerable causes of these passions are really nothing but the power of producing either agreeable or uneasy sensations; and therefore that all their effects, and amongst the rest, pride and humility, are derived solely from that origin. Such simple and natural principles, founded on such solid proofs, cannot fail to be received by philosophers, unless opposed by some objections, that have escaped me.
So, no matter how we look at this topic, we can still see that the causes of pride and humility match our theory perfectly. Nothing can trigger either of these emotions unless it relates to us and creates a feeling of pleasure or pain that is separate from the emotion itself. We have not only shown that a tendency to create pleasure or pain is shared by all the causes of pride or humility but also that this is the only common factor; thus, it is the principle by which they operate. We have further demonstrated that the main causes of these emotions are really just the ability to generate pleasant or unpleasant sensations; therefore, all their effects, including pride and humility, come solely from this source. Such straightforward and natural principles, based on solid evidence, should be accepted by philosophers unless there are objections that I have overlooked.
It is usual with anatomists to join their observations and experiments on human bodies to those on beasts, and from the agreement of these experiments to derive an additional argument for any particular hypothesis. It is indeed certain, that where the structure of parts in brutes is the same as in men, and the operation of these parts also the same, the causes of that operation cannot be different, and that whatever we discover to be true of the one species, may be concluded without hesitation to be certain of the other. Thus though the mixture of humours and the composition of minute parts may justly be presumed so be somewhat different in men from what it is in mere animals; and therefore any experiment we make upon the one concerning the effects of medicines will not always apply to the other; yet as the structure of the veins and muscles, the fabric and situation of the heart, of the lungs, the stomach, the liver and other parts, are the same or nearly the same in all animals, the very same hypothesis, which in one species explains muscular motion, the progress of the chyle, the circulation of the blood, must be applicable to every one; and according as it agrees or disagrees with the experiments we may make in any species of creatures, we may draw a proof of its truth or falshood on the whole. Let us, therefore, apply this method of enquiry, which is found so just and useful in reasonings concerning the body, to our present anatomy of the mind, and see what discoveries we can make by it.
It's common for anatomists to combine their observations and experiments on human bodies with those on animals, using the similarities in these experiments to support specific hypotheses. It’s clear that when the structures of parts in animals are the same as in humans, and their functions are also the same, the reasons behind those functions can't be different. Whatever we find to be true for one species can confidently be applied to the other. However, while the mix of biological fluids and the composition of tiny parts might differ between humans and simple animals, meaning that experiments on one may not always be relevant to the other regarding the effects of medicines, the structure of veins and muscles, as well as the design and placement of the heart, lungs, stomach, liver, and other organs, are generally the same or very similar across all animals. Therefore, the same hypothesis that explains muscle movement, the flow of chyle, and blood circulation in one species should also apply to every other. Depending on whether this aligns or conflicts with experiments in various species, we can validate or invalidate its accuracy overall. So, let’s use this method of inquiry, which proves to be both sound and valuable in discussions about the body, to guide our current study of the mind and see what insights we can uncover.
In order to this we must first shew the correspondence of passions in men and animals, and afterwards compare the causes, which produce these passions.
To do this, we first need to show the similarities in the emotions of humans and animals, and then compare the causes that lead to these emotions.
It is plain, that almost in every species of creatures, but especially of the nobler kind, there are many evident marks of pride and humility. The very port and gait of a swan, or turkey, or peacock show the high idea he has entertained of himself, and his contempt of all others. This is the more remarkable, that in the two last species of animals, the pride always attends the beauty, and is discovered in the male only. The vanity and emulation of nightingales in singing have been commonly remarked; as likewise that of horses in swiftness, of hounds in sagacity and smell, of the bull and cock in strength, and of every other animal in his particular excellency. Add to this, that every species of creatures, which approach so often to man, as to familiarize themselves with him, show an evident pride in his approbation, and are pleased with his praises and caresses, independent of every other consideration. Nor are they the caresses of every one without distinction, which give them this vanity, but those principally of the persons they know and love; in the same manner as that passion is excited in mankind. All these are evident proofs, that pride and humility are not merely human passions, but extend themselves over the whole animal creation.
It's clear that nearly every species of creature, especially the more noble ones, displays obvious signs of pride and humility. The very stance and movement of a swan, turkey, or peacock show the high opinion they have of themselves and their disdain for others. This is especially notable in the last two species, where pride is associated with beauty and is found only in males. The vanity and rivalry of nightingales when singing have been widely noticed, just as with horses in speed, hounds in intelligence and scent, and bulls and roosters in strength, along with every other animal in its particular excellence. Additionally, every species of creature that often interacts with humans and becomes familiar with them shows clear pride in receiving their approval and enjoys their praise and affection, regardless of other considerations. It's not just any praise that gives them this pride, but primarily the attention of those they know and love, much like how this feeling arises in humans. All of this serves as clear evidence that pride and humility are not just human emotions but are present throughout the entire animal kingdom.
The CAUSES of these passions are likewise much the same in beasts as in us, making a just allowance for our superior knowledge and understanding. Thus animals have little or no sense of virtue or vice; they quickly lose sight of the relations of blood; and are incapable of that of right and property: For which reason the causes of their pride and humility must lie solely in the body, and can never be placed either in the mind or external objects. But so far as regards the body, the same qualities cause pride in the animal as in the human kind; and it is on beauty, strength, swiftness or some other useful or agreeable quality that this passion is always founded.
The reasons for these feelings are pretty much the same in animals as they are in us, considering our greater knowledge and understanding. Animals generally have little to no grasp of virtue or vice; they quickly forget family ties and don’t understand concepts of right and ownership. For this reason, the roots of their pride and humility must be purely physical and cannot be linked to the mind or external things. However, when it comes to the body, animals experience pride for the same reasons as humans do; this feeling is always based on beauty, strength, speed, or some other useful or appealing quality.
The next question is, whether, since those passions are the same, and arise from the same causes through the whole creation, the manner, in which the causes operate, be also the same. According to all rules of analogy, this is justly to be expected; and if we find upon trial, that the explication of these phaenomena, which we make use of in one species, will not apply to the rest, we may presume that that explication, however specious, is in reality without foundation.
The next question is whether, since those emotions are the same and come from the same causes throughout all of creation, the way those causes work is also the same. By the rules of analogy, this is to be expected; and if we find that the explanation of these phenomena, which we use for one type, doesn't apply to others, we can assume that that explanation, no matter how convincing it seems, is actually unfounded.
In order to decide this question, let us consider, that there is evidently the same relation of ideas, and derived from the same causes, in the minds of animals as in those of men. A dog, that has hid a bone, often forgets the place; but when brought to it, his thought passes easily to what he formerly concealed, by means of the contiguity, which produces a relation among his ideas. In like manner, when he has been heartily beat in any place, he will tremble on his approach to it, even though he discover no signs of any present danger. The effects of resemblance are not so remarkable; but as that relation makes a considerable ingredient in causation, of which all animals shew so evident a judgment, we may conclude that the three relations of resemblance, contiguity and causation operate in the same manner upon beasts as upon human creatures.
To answer this question, let's consider that there is clearly the same relationship of ideas, stemming from the same causes, in the minds of animals as there is in humans. A dog that has buried a bone often forgets where it is, but when taken back to the spot, he easily thinks of what he hid before, thanks to the closeness of the two ideas. Similarly, if he has been beaten in a certain place, he will shake with fear when approaching it, even if there are no signs of immediate danger. The effects of similarity are less noticeable, but since that relationship is a significant part of causation, which all animals show a clear understanding of, we can conclude that the three relationships of similarity, closeness, and causation work the same way on animals as they do on humans.
There are also instances of the relation of impressions, sufficient to convince us, that there is an union of certain affections with each other in the inferior species of creatures as well as in the superior, and that their minds are frequently conveyed through a series of connected emotions. A dog, when elevated with joy, runs naturally into love and kindness, whether of his master or of the sex. In like manner, when full of pain and sorrow, he becomes quarrelsome and ill-natured; and that passion; which at first was grief, is by the smallest occasion converted into anger.
There are also examples showing that certain feelings are linked to each other in lower forms of life just as they are in higher ones, convincing us that their emotions often flow through a series of connected feelings. A happy dog instinctively expresses love and affection, whether towards its owner or a mate. Similarly, when a dog is in pain or sad, it can become aggressive and irritable; that initial feeling of grief can easily turn into anger over the slightest trigger.
Thus all the internal principles, that are necessary in us to produce either pride or humility, are common to all creatures; and since the causes, which excite these passions, are likewise the same, we may justly conclude, that these causes operate after the same manner through the whole animal creation. My hypothesis Is so simple, and supposes so little reflection and judgment, that it is applicable to every sensible creature; which must not only be allowed to be a convincing proof of its veracity, but, I am confident, will be found an objection to every other system.
So, all the internal principles that we need to feel either pride or humility are common to all living beings; and since the triggers for these feelings are also the same, we can rightly conclude that these triggers work in the same way across all animals. My theory is so straightforward and requires so little thought and reasoning that it applies to every sentient being; this not only serves as strong evidence of its truth but I’m sure it will also be a challenge to any other system.
SECT. I OF THE OBJECT AND CAUSES OF LOVE AND HATRED
It is altogether impossible to give any definition of the passions of love and hatred; and that because they produce merely a simple impression, without any mixture or composition. Twould be as unnecessary to attempt any description of them, drawn from their nature, origin, causes and objects; and that both because these are the subjects of our present enquiry, and because these passions of themselves are sufficiently known from our common feeling and experience. This we have already observed concerning pride and humility, and here repeat it concerning love and hatred; and indeed there is so great a resemblance betwixt these two sets of passions, that we shall be obliged to begin with a kind of abridgment of our reasonings concerning the former, in order to explain the latter.
It's completely impossible to define the feelings of love and hatred because they simply create a straightforward impression, without any complexity. It would be just as pointless to try to describe them based on their nature, origin, causes, and objects; not only because these are the subjects we’re currently examining, but also because we already understand these feelings well from our own experiences. We’ve already noted this about pride and humility, and we repeat it here regarding love and hatred; in fact, there’s so much similarity between these two sets of feelings that we need to start with a summary of our reasoning about the first set to explain the second.
As the immediate object of pride and humility is self or that identical person, of whose thoughts, actions, and sensations we are intimately conscious; so the object of love and hatred is some other person, of whose thoughts, actions, and sensations we are not conscious. This is sufficiently evident from experience. Our love and hatred are always directed to some sensible being external to us; and when we talk of self-love, it is not in a proper sense, nor has the sensation it produces any thing in common with that tender emotion which is excited by a friend or mistress. It is the same case with hatred. We may be mortified by our own faults and follies; but never feel any anger or hatred except from the injuries of others.
The main focus of pride and humility is ourselves—our own thoughts, actions, and feelings that we are deeply aware of. In contrast, love and hatred are directed toward other people, whose thoughts, actions, and feelings we do not have the same awareness of. This is clear from our experiences. We always direct our love and hatred toward some external being; and when we mention self-love, it doesn’t really fit in the proper sense, nor does the feeling it creates compare to the deep emotions we feel for a friend or partner. The same goes for hatred. We might feel embarrassed by our own mistakes and shortcomings, but we only experience anger or hatred in response to the wrongs done to us by others.
But though the object of love and hatred be always some other person, it is plain that the object is not, properly speaking, the cause of these passions, or alone sufficient to excite them. For since love and hatred are directly contrary in their sensation, and have the same object in common, if that object were also their cause, it would produce these opposite passions in an equal degree; and as they must, from the very first moment, destroy each other, none of them would ever be able to make its appearance. There must, therefore, be some cause different from the object.
But even though the target of love and hate is always someone else, it’s clear that this person isn’t, strictly speaking, the cause of these feelings, nor is that person enough to trigger them on their own. Since love and hate are completely opposite in how they feel and share the same target, if that target were also their cause, it would create these conflicting feelings equally. Since they must, from the very start, cancel each other out, neither would ever be able to emerge. Therefore, there must be a cause that is different from the object.
If we consider the causes of love and hatred, we shall find they are very much diversifyed, and have not many things in common. The virtue, knowledge, wit, good sense, good humour of any person, produce love and esteem; as the opposite qualities, hatred and contempt. The same passions arise from bodily accomplishments, such as beauty, force, swiftness, dexterity; and from their contraries; as likewise from the external advantages and disadvantages of family, possession, cloaths, nation and climate. There is not one of these objects, but what by its different qualities may produce love and esteem, or hatred and contempt.
If we look at the reasons behind love and hatred, we'll see they are really quite different and don’t share much in common. The qualities of a person, like their virtue, knowledge, intelligence, good judgment, and sense of humor, generate love and respect; while the opposite traits lead to hatred and disdain. The same feelings come from physical attributes, such as beauty, strength, speed, and skill; and from their opposites. They also arise from external factors like family background, wealth, clothing, nationality, and climate. Each of these factors can elicit either love and respect or hatred and contempt, depending on their different qualities.
From the view of these causes we may derive a new distinction betwixt the quality that operates, and the subject on which it is placed. A prince, that is possessed of a stately palace, commands the esteem of the people upon that account; and that first, by the beauty of the palace, and secondly, by the relation of property, which connects it with him. The removal of either of these destroys the passion; which evidently proves that the cause Is a compounded one.
From these causes, we can draw a new distinction between the quality that acts and the subject it is applied to. A prince who owns an impressive palace earns the admiration of the people for two reasons: first, because of the beauty of the palace, and second, because of the ownership that ties it to him. If either of these is taken away, the admiration fades, clearly showing that the cause is a complex one.
Twould be tedious to trace the passions of love and hatred, through all the observations which we have formed concerning pride and humility, and which are equally applicable to both sets of passions. Twill be sufficient to remark in general, that the object of love and hatred is evidently some thinking person; and that the sensation of the former passion is always agreeable, and of the latter uneasy. We may also suppose with some shew of probability, THAT THE CAUSE OF BOTH THESE PASSIONS IS ALWAYS RELATED TO A THINKING BEING, AND THAT THE CAUSE OF THE FORMER PRODUCE A SEPARATE PLEASURE, AND OF THE LATTER A SEPARATE UNEASINESS.
It would be tedious to trace the feelings of love and hatred through all the observations we've made about pride and humility, which apply similarly to both passions. It’s enough to point out that the target of love and hatred is clearly another thinking person, and that the feelings associated with love are always pleasant, while those tied to hatred are always uncomfortable. We can also reasonably assume that the cause of both of these feelings is always connected to a thinking being, and that the cause of love produces distinct pleasure, while the cause of hatred leads to distinct discomfort.
One of these suppositions, viz, that the cause of love and hatred must be related to a person or thinking being, in order to produce these passions, is not only probable, but too evident to be contested. Virtue and vice, when considered in the abstract; beauty and deformity, when placed on inanimate objects; poverty and riches when belonging to a third person, excite no degree of love or hatred, esteem or contempt towards those, who have no relation to them. A person looking out at a window, sees me in the street, and beyond me a beautiful palace, with which I have no concern: I believe none will pretend, that this person will pay me the same respect, as if I were owner of the palace.
One of these ideas, specifically that love and hatred have to be connected to a person or a thinking being to create these feelings, is not just likely but so clear that it can’t be argued against. Virtue and vice, when thought of in general terms; beauty and ugliness, when associated with inanimate things; and poverty and wealth when relating to someone else, don’t inspire any love or hatred, admiration or disdain towards those who aren’t connected to them. If someone looks out a window and sees me in the street, and beyond me a beautiful palace that I have nothing to do with, I doubt anyone would claim that this person would show me the same respect as if I were the owner of the palace.
It is not so evident at first sight, that a relation of impressions is requisite to these passions, and that because in the transition the one impression is so much confounded with the other, that they become in a manner undistinguishable. But as in pride and humility, we have easily been able to make the separation, and to prove, that every cause of these passions, produces a separate pain or pleasure, I might here observe the same method with the same success, in examining particularly the several causes of love and hatred. But as I hasten a full and decisive proof of these systems, I delay this examination for a moment: And in the mean time shall endeavour to convert to my present purpose all my reasonings concerning pride and humility, by an argument that is founded on unquestionable examination.
It's not immediately obvious that a connection between impressions is necessary for these feelings, and that's because during their transition, one impression blends so much with the other that they become hard to tell apart. However, just like with pride and humility, we've been able to clearly differentiate them and show that each cause of these feelings creates a distinct pain or pleasure. I could apply the same approach with equal success to explore the different causes of love and hatred. But as I rush to provide a complete and conclusive proof of these ideas, I’ll pause this exploration for a moment. In the meantime, I will try to adapt all my reasoning about pride and humility to support my current argument, using points that are based on indisputable analysis.
There are few persons, that are satisfyed with their own character, or genius, or fortune, who are nor desirous of shewing themselves to the world, and of acquiring the love and approbation of mankind. Now it is evident, that the very same qualities and circumstances, which are the causes of pride or self-esteem, are also the causes of vanity or the desire of reputation; and that we always put to view those particulars with which in ourselves we are best satisfyed. But if love and esteem were not produced by the same qualities as pride, according as these qualities are related to ourselves or others, this method of proceeding would be very absurd, nor could men expect a correspondence in the sentiments of every other person, with those themselves have entertained. It is true, few can form exact systems of the passions, or make reflections on their general nature and resemblances. But without such a progress in philosophy, we are not subject to many mistakes in this particular, but are sufficiently guided by common experience, as well as by a kind of presentation; which tells us what will operate on others, by what we feel immediately in ourselves. Since then the same qualities that produce pride or humility, cause love or hatred; all the arguments that have been employed to prove, that the causes of the former passions excite a pain or pleasure independent of the passion, will be applicable with equal evidence to the causes of the latter.
Few people are satisfied with their own character, talent, or fortune, who don't want to show themselves to the world and gain the love and approval of others. It's clear that the same qualities and circumstances that lead to pride or self-esteem also lead to vanity or the desire for reputation, and we tend to showcase the aspects of ourselves that we are most pleased with. However, if love and esteem didn’t arise from the same qualities that create pride, depending on whether those qualities relate to ourselves or others, this approach would be quite strange. People wouldn't expect others to share the same feelings they have. It's true that few can create precise systems of emotions or reflect on their general nature and similarities. Yet, without deep philosophical understanding, we still make relatively few mistakes in this area, guided by our everyday experiences and a kind of intuition that informs us about what will resonate with others based on what we feel ourselves. Since the same qualities that cause pride or humility also lead to love or hatred, all the arguments used to show that the causes of the former passions generate pain or pleasure independent of the feelings will also apply equally clearly to the causes of the latter.
SECT. II EXPERIMENTS TO CONFIRM THIS SYSTEM
Upon duly weighing these arguments, no one will make any scruple to assent to that conclusion I draw from them, concerning the transition along related impressions and ideas, especially as it is a principle, in itself, so easy and natural. But that we may place this system beyond doubt both with regard to love and hatred, pride and humility, it will be proper to make some new experiments upon all these passions, as well as to recall a few of these observations, which I have formerly touched upon.
Once you carefully consider these arguments, no one should hesitate to agree with the conclusion I’ve drawn from them about the connections between related thoughts and feelings, especially since it’s a principle that’s so simple and natural. However, to solidify this system regarding love and hatred, pride and humility, it would be appropriate to conduct some new experiments on all these emotions, as well as to revisit a few observations I’ve mentioned before.
In order to make these experiments, let us suppose I am in company with a person, whom I formerly regarded without any sentiments either of friendship or enmity. Here I have the natural and ultimate object of all these four passions placed before me. Myself am the proper object of pride or humility; the other person of love or hatred.
To conduct these experiments, let's imagine I'm with someone I used to see without any feelings of friendship or dislike. In this situation, I have the natural and final focus of all four of these emotions in front of me. I am the right target for pride or humility; the other person is the focus for love or hatred.
Regard now with attention the nature of these passions, and their situation with respect to each other. It is evident here are four affections, placed, as it were, in a square or regular connexion with, and distance from each other. The passions of pride and humility, as well as those of love and hatred, are connected together by the identity of their object, which to the first set of passions is self, to the second some other person. These two lines of communication or connexion form two opposite sides of the square. Again, pride and love are agreeable passions; hatred and humility uneasy. This similitude of sensation betwixt pride and love, and that betwixt humility and hatred form a new connexion, and may be considered as the other two sides of the square. Upon the whole, pride is connected with humility, love with hatred, by their objects or ideas: Pride with love, humility with hatred, by their sensations or impressions.
Now, take a moment to consider the nature of these emotions and how they relate to one another. It's clear that there are four feelings arranged, so to speak, in a square or regular connection with equal distances between them. The emotions of pride and humility, as well as those of love and hatred, are linked by their shared focus—self for the first pair and another person for the second. These two connections create two opposite sides of the square. Furthermore, pride and love are positive emotions, while hatred and humility are more negative. This similarity in feeling between pride and love, and between humility and hatred, creates another connection, forming the other two sides of the square. Overall, pride is linked to humility, and love to hatred, through their respective objects or ideas: pride connects with love, and humility with hatred through their emotional effects or impressions.
I say then, that nothing can produce any of these passions without bearing it a double relation, viz, of ideas to the object of the passion, and of sensation to the passion itself. This we must prove by our experiments. First Experiment. To proceed with the greater order in these experiments, let us first suppose, that being placed in the situation above-mentioned, viz, in company with some other person, there is an object presented, that has no relation either of impressions or ideas to any of these passions. Thus suppose we regard together an ordinary stone, or other common object, belonging to neither of us, and causing of itself no emotion, or independent pain and pleasure: It is evident such an object will produce none of these four passions. Let us try it upon each of them successively. Let us apply it to love, to hatred, to humility, to pride; none of them ever arises in the smallest degree imaginable. Let us change the object, as oft as we please; provided still we choose one, that has neither of these two relations. Let us repeat the experiment in all the dispositions, of which the mind is susceptible. No object, in the vast variety of nature, will, in any disposition, produce any passion without these relations.
I argue that nothing can create any of these feelings without having a dual connection: one between ideas and the object of the feeling, and another between sensation and the feeling itself. We need to demonstrate this through experiments. First Experiment. To maintain better organization in these experiments, let’s imagine a situation where we are with someone else, and an object is presented that has no link, either of impressions or ideas, to any of these feelings. For example, let’s look at a regular stone or another common object that doesn’t belong to either of us and doesn’t provoke any emotion, pain, or pleasure on its own: it’s clear that such an object won’t generate any of these four feelings. Let’s test it against each of them one by one. Let’s apply it to love, to hatred, to humility, to pride; none of them will arise even to the slightest extent. We can change the object as often as we want, as long as we still choose one that has neither of these two connections. Let’s repeat the experiment in all the different states the mind can experience. No object, regardless of the vast variety in nature, will generate any feeling without these connections.
Second Experiment. Since an object, that wants both these relations can never produce any passion, let us bestow on it only one of these relations; and see what will follow. Thus suppose, I regard a stone or any common object, that belongs either to me or my companion, and by that means acquires a relation of ideas to the object of the passions: It is plain, that to consider the matter a priori, no emotion of any kind can reasonably be expected. For besides, that a relation of ideas operates secretly and calmly on the mind, it bestows an equal impulse towards the opposite passions of pride and humility, love and hatred, according as the object belongs to ourselves or others; which opposition of the passions must destroy both, and leave the mind perfectly free from any affection or emotion. This reasoning a priori is confirmed by experience. No trivial or vulgar object, that causes not a pain or pleasure, independent of the passion, will ever, by its property or other relations either to ourselves or others, be able to produce the affections of pride or humility, love or hatred.
Second Experiment. Since an object that wants both these relationships can never cause any emotion, let’s give it just one of these relationships and see what happens. So, let's say I look at a stone or any ordinary object that belongs either to me or my companion, and by doing so, it has a connection of ideas to the object of the emotions: Obviously, when considering this beforehand, no emotion of any kind can be reasonably expected. Besides the fact that a connection of ideas works quietly and calmly in the mind, it creates an equal pull toward the opposite emotions of pride and humility, love and hatred, depending on whether the object belongs to us or to others; this conflict of emotions must cancel each other out, leaving the mind completely free from any feelings or emotions. This reasoning ahead of time is supported by experience. No trivial or common object that does not cause pain or pleasure, independent of the emotion, will ever, due to its property or other connections to ourselves or others, be able to create the feelings of pride or humility, love or hatred.
Third Experiment. It is evident, therefore, that a relation of ideas is not able alone to give rise to these affections. Let us now remove this relation, and in its stead place a relation of impressions, by presenting an object, which is agreeable or disagreeable, but has no relation either to ourself or companion; and let us observe the consequences. To consider the matter first a priori, as in the preceding experiment; we may conclude, that the object will have a small, but an uncertain connexion with these passions. For besides, that this relation is not a cold and imperceptible one, it has not the inconvenience of the relation of ideas, nor directs us with equal force to two contrary passions, which by their opposition destroy each other. But if we consider, on the other hand, that this transition from the sensation to the affection is not forwarded by any principle, that produces a transition of ideas; but, on the contrary, that though the one impression be easily transfused into the other, yet the change of objects is supposed contrary to all the principles, that cause a transition of that kind; we may from thence infer, that nothing will ever be a steady or durable cause of any passion, that is connected with the passion merely by a relation of impressions. What our reason would conclude from analogy, after balancing these arguments, would be, that an object, which produces pleasure or uneasiness, but has no manner of connexion either with ourselves or others, may give such a turn to the disposition, as that may naturally fall into pride or love, humility or hatred, and search for other objects, upon which by a double relation, it can found these affections; but that an object, which has only one of these relations, though the most advantageous one, can never give rise to any constant and established passion.
Third Experiment. It’s clear that a relationship of ideas alone can’t create these feelings. Let’s take away this relationship and instead present an object that is either pleasing or unpleasant, but has no connection to us or to anyone else, and see what happens. Thinking about it first logically, like in the last experiment, we can conclude that the object will have a weak but uncertain connection to these emotions. This connection isn’t cold and hard to notice, and it doesn’t have the downsides of a relationship of ideas, nor does it force us into two opposing feelings that cancel each other out. However, if we consider that the shift from sensation to emotion isn’t helped by any principle that allows the flow of ideas, and that while one impression can easily transition to another, changing objects goes against all the principles that usually cause that transition, we can conclude that nothing can be a stable or durable cause of any emotion if it’s linked to the emotion solely through a relationship of impressions. Based on what reason would suggest through analogy after weighing these arguments, we can say that an object which brings pleasure or discomfort, but has no connection to us or others, may shift our mood so that it leans towards pride or love, humility or hatred, and lead us to seek other objects that can connect these feelings through two relationships; but an object that only has one of these relationships, even if it’s the most beneficial one, can never create a lasting and stable emotion.
Most fortunately all this reasoning is found to be exactly conformable to experience, and the phaenomena of the passions. Suppose I were travelling with a companion through a country, to which we are both utter strangers; it is evident, that if the prospects be beautiful, the roads agreeable, and the inns commodious, this may put me into good humour both with myself and fellow-traveller. But as we suppose, that this country has no relation either to myself or friend it can never be the immediate cause of pride or love; and therefore if I found not the passion on some other object, that bears either of us a closer relation, my emotions are rather to be considerd as the overflowings of an elevate or humane disposition, than as an established passion. The case is the same where the object produces uneasiness.
Fortunately, all this reasoning aligns perfectly with our experiences and the way we feel. Imagine I'm traveling with a friend in an unfamiliar place; it’s clear that if the scenery is beautiful, the roads are pleasant, and the inns are comfortable, I might feel happy both with myself and my travel companion. However, if this place has no connection to either of us, it can never be the direct cause of feelings like pride or love. So, if I don’t find those emotions directed at something that relates to either of us more closely, my feelings are more likely to be seen as expressions of a positive or compassionate nature, rather than as a strong passion. The same applies when the surroundings cause discomfort.
Fourth Experiment. Having found, that neither an object without any relation of ideas or impressions, nor an object, that has only one relation, can ever cause pride or humility, love or hatred; reason alone may convince us, without any farther experiment, that whatever has a double relation must necessarily excite these passions; since it is evident they must have some cause. But to leave as little room for doubt as possible, let us renew our experiments, and see whether the event in this case answers our expectation. I choose an object, such as virtue, that causes a separate satisfaction: On this object I bestow a relation to self; and find, that from this disposition of affairs, there immediately arises a passion. But what passion? That very one of pride, to which this object bears a double relation. Its idea is related to that of self, the object of the passion: The sensation it causes resembles the sensation of the passion. That I may be sure I am not mistaken in this experiment, I remove first one relation; then another; and find, that each removal destroys the passion, and leaves the object perfectly indifferent. But I am not content with this. I make a still farther trial; and instead of removing the relation, I only change it for one of a different kind. I suppose the virtue to belong to my companion, not to myself; and observe what follows from this alteration. I immediately perceive the affections wheel to about, and leaving pride, where there is only one relation, viz, of impressions, fall to the side of love, where they are attracted by a double relation of impressions and ideas. By repeating the same experiment, in changing anew the relation of ideas, I bring the affections back to pride; and by a new repetition I again place them at love or kindness. Being fully convinced of the influence of this relation, I try the effects of the other; and by changing virtue for vice, convert the pleasant impression, which arises from the former, into the disagreeable one, which proceeds from the latter. The effect still answers expectation. Vice, when placed on another, excites, by means of its double relations, the passion of hatred, instead of love, which for the same reason arises from virtue. To continue the experiment, I change anew the relation of ideas, and suppose the vice to belong to myself. What follows? What is usual. A subsequent change of the passion from hatred to humility. This humility I convert into pride by a new change of the impression; and find after all that I have compleated the round, and have by these changes brought back the passion to that very situation, in which I first found it.
Fourth Experiment. I discovered that neither an object without any connection to ideas or impressions, nor an object that has only one connection, can really cause feelings of pride or humility, love or hatred; reason alone can convince us, without any further experiments, that anything with a double connection must inevitably trigger these emotions since it’s clear they need a cause. To minimize any doubt, let’s repeat our experiments and see if the outcome meets our expectations. I choose an object, like virtue, which brings a separate satisfaction. I relate this object to myself and find that this setup immediately triggers a passion. But which passion? It’s the passion of pride, since this object has a double connection to it. Its idea relates to self, the object of the passion: the feeling it produces resembles the sensation of pride. To ensure I’m not mistaken in this experiment, I first remove one connection; then another; and see that each removal wipes out the passion and leaves the object completely indifferent. But that’s not enough for me. I conduct an even further trial; instead of removing the connection, I swap it for a different kind. I imagine the virtue belongs to my friend, not to me; and notice what happens from this change. I quickly see the feelings shift, moving away from pride, where there’s only one connection, which is impressions, and instead leaning towards love, drawn in by a double connection of impressions and ideas. By repeating the same experiment and changing the connection of ideas again, I bring the feelings back to pride; with another repetition, I take them back to love or kindness. Being fully convinced of the power of this connection, I test the effects of the opposite; by switching virtue for vice, I turn the pleasant feeling from the former into the unpleasant one from the latter. The effect still meets expectations. Vice, when attributed to another, evokes, through its double connections, the feeling of hatred, instead of love, which similarly arises from virtue. To continue the experiment, I shift the connection of ideas once more and assume the vice belongs to me. What happens next? The usual. A subsequent change in feeling from hatred to humility. I transform this humility into pride by changing the impression again; and find that after all, I've completed the cycle and, through these changes, brought the feeling back to exactly where I first found it.
But to make the matter still more certain, I alter the object; and instead of vice and virtue, make the trial upon beauty and deformity, riches and poverty, power and servitude. Each of these objects runs the circle of the passions in the same manner, by a change of their relations: And in whatever order we proceed, whether through pride, love, hatred, humility, or through humility, hatred, love, pride, the experiment is not in the least diversifyed. Esteem and contempt, indeed, arise on some occasions instead of love and hatred; but these are at the bottom the same passions, only diversifyed by some causes, which we shall explain afterwards.
But to make things even clearer, I change the focus; instead of looking at vice and virtue, I examine beauty and ugliness, wealth and poverty, power and servitude. Each of these categories goes through the same range of emotions based on how they relate to each other. No matter how we approach it—whether it’s through pride, love, hatred, humility, or in the reverse order—the experience remains fundamentally the same. Respect and disdain can sometimes replace love and hatred, but at their core, these are essentially the same feelings, just expressed differently due to various factors that we will explain later.
Fifth Experiment. To give greater authority to these experiments, let us change the situation of affairs as much as possible, and place the passions and objects in all the different positions, of which they are susceptible. Let us suppose, beside the relations above-mentioned, that the person, along with whom I make all these experiments, is closely connected with me either by blood or friendship. He is, we shall suppose, my son or brother, or is united to me by a long and familiar acquaintance. Let us next suppose, that the cause of the passion acquires a double relation of impressions and ideas to this person; and let us see what the effects are of all these complicated attractions and relations.
Fifth Experiment. To strengthen the credibility of these experiments, let's change the circumstances as much as we can and position the emotions and objects in every possible way they can relate. Let's assume, in addition to the previously mentioned relationships, that the person I'm conducting all these experiments with is closely tied to me by either family or friendship. Let's say, for instance, that he is my son or brother, or that we have a long-standing and familiar relationship. Furthermore, let's assume that the reason behind the emotion has a dual connection of impressions and ideas for this person, and let's observe the outcomes of all these complex attractions and relationships.
Before we consider what they are in fact, let us determine what they ought to be, conformable to my hypothesis. It is plain, that, according as the impression is either pleasant or uneasy, the passion of love or hatred must arise towards the person, who is thus connected to the cause of the impression by these double relations, which I have all along required. The virtue of a brother must make me love him; as his vice or infamy must excite the contrary passion. But to judge only from the situation of affairs, I should not expect, that the affections would rest there, and never transfuse themselves into any other impression. As there is here a person, who by means of a double relation is the object of my passion, the very same reasoning leads me to think the passion will be carryed farther. The person has a relation of ideas to myself, according to the supposition; the passion, of which he is the object, by being either agreeable or uneasy, has a relation of impressions to pride or humility. It is evident, then, that one of these passions must arise from the love or hatred.
Before we discuss what they really are, let’s figure out what they should be according to my theory. It’s clear that depending on whether the impression is pleasant or unpleasant, love or hate will develop towards the person related to that impression through these dual connections I’ve mentioned. The virtues of a brother should make me love him, while his faults or disgrace should stir the opposite feeling. However, just based on the situation, I wouldn’t expect those feelings to stay put and not spill over into other impressions. Since there’s someone who, due to a dual relationship, is the focus of my emotions, the same reasoning suggests that those feelings will go further. The person is related to me in terms of ideas, based on the assumption; the emotion he triggers, whether it’s positive or negative, connects to feelings of pride or humility. Therefore, it’s clear that one of these emotions must arise from love or hatred.
This is the reasoning I form in conformity to my hypothesis; and am pleased to find upon trial that every thing answers exactly to my expectation. The virtue or vice of a son or brother not only excites love or hatred, but by a new transition, from similar causes, gives rise to pride or humility. Nothing causes greater vanity than any shining quality in our relations; as nothing mortifies us more than their vice or infamy. This exact conformity of experience to our reasoning is a convincing proof of the solidity of that hypothesis, upon which we reason.
This is the reasoning I develop based on my hypothesis, and I'm happy to find that everything aligns perfectly with my expectations. The qualities, good or bad, of a son or brother not only spark love or hatred but also, through similar influences, lead to pride or humility. Nothing boosts our vanity more than remarkable traits in our relatives, just as nothing wounds us more than their faults or disgrace. This clear alignment of experience with our reasoning is strong evidence for the validity of the hypothesis we are basing our reasoning on.
Sixth Experiment. This evidence will be still augmented, if we reverse the experiment, and preserving still the same relations, begin only with a different passion. Suppose, that instead of the virtue or vice of a son or brother, which causes first love or hatred, and afterwards pride or humility, we place these good or bad qualities on ourselves, without any immediate connexion with the person, who is related to us: Experience shews us, that by this change of situation the whole chain is broke, and that the mind is not conveyed from one passion to another, as in the preceding instance. We never love or hate a son or brother for the virtue or vice we discern in ourselves; though it is evident the same qualities in him give us a very sensible pride or humility. The transition from pride or humility to love or hatred is not so natural as from love or hatred to pride or humility. This may at first sight be esteemed contrary to my hypothesis; since the relations of impressions and ideas are in both cases precisely the same. Pride and humility are impressions related to love and hatred. Myself am related to the person. It should, therefore, be expected, that like causes must produce like effects, and a perfect transition arise from the double relation, as in all other cases. This difficulty we may easily solve by the following reflections.
Sixth Experiment. This evidence will be even stronger if we flip the experiment around and, while keeping the same relationships, start with a different emotion. Let's say that instead of the virtue or vice of a son or brother triggering first love or hatred and then pride or humility, we attribute these good or bad qualities to ourselves, with no direct connection to the person related to us. Experience shows us that by making this change, the whole chain is broken, and the mind doesn't move from one emotion to another as it did in the earlier example. We never love or hate a son or brother based on the virtue or vice we see in ourselves; however, it's clear that recognizing the same qualities in him brings us significant pride or humility. The shift from pride or humility to love or hatred isn't as natural as from love or hatred to pride or humility. At first glance, this may seem to contradict my hypothesis since the relationships between impressions and ideas are the same in both cases. Pride and humility are impressions linked to love and hatred. I am connected to the person. Thus, it would be expected that similar causes should lead to similar effects, resulting in a smooth transition from the dual relationship, as in all other cases. We can easily resolve this difficulty with the following thoughts.
It is evident, that as we are at all times intimately conscious of ourselves, our sentiments and passions, their ideas must strike upon us with greater vivacity than the ideas of the sentiments and passions of any other person. But every thing, that strikes upon us with vivacity, and appears in a full and strong light, forces itself, in a manner, into our consideration, and becomes present to the mind on the smallest hint and most trivial relation. For the same reason, when it is once present, it engages the attention, and keeps it from wandering to other objects, however strong may be their relation to our first object. The imagination passes easily from obscure to lively ideas, but with difficulty from lively to obscure. In the one case the relation is aided by another principle: In the other case, it is opposed by it.
It's clear that since we are constantly aware of ourselves, our feelings and emotions resonate with us more intensely than the feelings and emotions of anyone else. Anything that impacts us strongly and appears vividly demands our attention and becomes prominent in our thoughts with just a hint or slightest connection. For the same reason, once it captures our focus, it holds our attention, preventing it from drifting to other subjects, no matter how relevant those might be to our initial focus. The mind transitions easily from unclear to vivid ideas, but struggles to shift from vivid to unclear. In one instance, the connection is supported by another principle; in the other, it is hindered by it.
Now I have observed, that those two faculties of the mind, the imagination and passions, assist each other in their operations when their propensities are similar, and when they act upon the same object. The mind has always a propensity to pass from a passion to any other related to it; and this propensity is forwarded when the object of the one passion is related to that of the other. The two impulses concur with each other, and render the whole transition more smooth and easy. But if it should happen, that while the relation of ideas, strictly speaking, continues the same, its influence, in causing a transition of the imagination, should no longer take place, it is evident its influence on the passions must also cease, as being dependent entirely on that transition. This is the reason why pride or humility is not transfused into love or hatred with the same ease, that the latter passions are changed into the former. If a person be my brother I am his likewise: but though the relations be reciprocal they have very different effects on the imagination. The passage is smooth and open from the consideration of any person related to us to that of ourself, of whom we are every moment conscious. But when the affections are once directed to ourself, the fancy passes not with the same facility from that object to any other person, how closely so ever connected with us. This easy or difficult transition of the imagination operates upon the passions, and facilitates or retards their transition, which is a clear proof, that these two faculties of the passions and imagination are connected together, and that the relations of ideas have an influence upon the affections. Besides innumerable experiments that prove this, we here find, that even when the relation remains; if by any particular circumstance its usual effect upon the fancy in producing an association or transition of ideas, is prevented; its usual effect upon the passions, in conveying us from one to another, is in like manner prevented.
I've noticed that the two mental faculties, imagination and emotions, work together when their tendencies align and they focus on the same thing. The mind naturally shifts from one emotion to another related one, and this shift is easier when the objects of those emotions are connected. The two drives support one another, making the transition smoother. However, if the relationship between ideas stays the same but stops prompting a shift in imagination, it’s clear that it will also stop influencing emotions since the transition is what ties them together. This explains why pride or humility doesn't easily transfer to love or hate like the latter can switch to the former. If someone is my brother, I'm his too, but although these relationships are mutual, they affect the imagination differently. The transition from thinking about anyone related to us to thinking about ourselves, of whom we are constantly aware, is smooth and straightforward. But once our feelings are directed toward ourselves, it doesn’t shift easily to someone else, no matter how closely connected. This ease or difficulty in the imagination affects emotions, helping or hindering their transition, clearly showing that these two faculties—emotions and imagination—are connected, and that the relationships between ideas influence our feelings. Beyond countless experiments that demonstrate this, we see that even when the relationship remains, if a specific circumstance disrupts its usual impact on the imagination in creating an association or transition of ideas, the typical effect on emotions, in moving us from one to another, is similarly blocked.
Some may, perhaps, find a contradiction betwixt this phænomenon and that of sympathy, where the mind passes easily from the idea of ourselves to that of any other object related to us. But this difficulty will vanish, if we consider that in sympathy our own person is not the object of any passion, nor is there any thing, that fixes our attention on ourselves; as in the present case, where we are supposed to be actuated with pride or humility. Ourself, independent of the perception of every other object, is in reality nothing: For which reason we must turn our view to external objects; and it is natural for us to consider with most attention such as lie contiguous to us, or resemble us. But when self is the object of a passion, it is not natural to quit the consideration of it, till the passion be exhausted: in which case the double relations of impressions and ideas can no longer operate.
Some might find a contradiction between this phenomenon and sympathy, where our minds easily shift from thinking about ourselves to any other related object. However, this difficulty disappears when we realize that in sympathy, we’re not focused on ourselves, nor is anything drawing our attention back to us. In this case, we are assumed to be experiencing pride or humility. Our sense of self, independent of the awareness of any other object, is actually nothing. For this reason, we naturally focus our attention on external objects, particularly those that are close to us or resemble us. But when our self is the focus of an emotion, it’s not normal to move our attention away from it until that emotion has passed; in this situation, the dual relationships of impressions and ideas can no longer function.
Seventh Experiment. To put this whole reasoning to a farther trial, let us make a new experiment; and as we have already seen the effects of related passions and ideas, let us here suppose an identity of passions along with a relation of ideas; and let us consider the effects of this new situation. It is evident a transition of the passions from the one object to the other is here in all reason to be expected; since the relation of ideas is supposed still to continue, and identity of impressions must produce a stronger connexion, than the most perfect resemblance, that can be imagined. If a double relation, therefore, of impressions and ideas is able to produce a transition from one to the other, much more an identity of impressions with a relation of ideas. Accordingly we find, that when we either love or hate any person, the passions seldom continue within their first bounds; but extend themselves towards all the contiguous objects, and comprehend the friends and relations of him we love or hate. Nothing is more natural than to bear a kindness to one brother on account of our friendship for another, without any farther examination of his character. A quarrel with one person gives us a hatred for the whole family, though entirely innocent of that, which displeases us. Instances of this kind are everywhere to be met with.
Seventh Experiment. To further test this reasoning, let’s conduct a new experiment. Since we’ve already seen the effects of related emotions and ideas, let’s assume there’s a connection of emotions alongside a relationship of ideas, and consider the effects of this situation. It’s clear that we would expect a transition of feelings from one object to another, as the relationship of ideas continues, and the similarity of impressions should create a stronger connection than even the greatest resemblance imaginable. Therefore, if a dual relationship of impressions and ideas can create a transition from one to another, an identity of impressions with a relationship of ideas should do so even more effectively. We see that when we love or hate someone, our feelings rarely stay contained; they often extend to all the related people and friends of the one we love or hate. It’s completely natural to feel a fondness for one sibling because of our friendship with another, without needing to judge the character of the one we’re favoring. A conflict with one person can lead to animosity toward their entire family, even if they’re completely innocent of what upset us. Such examples are everywhere to be found.
There is only one difficulty in this experiment, which it will be necessary to account for, before we proceed any farther. It is evident, that though all passions pass easily from one object to another related to it, yet this transition is made with greater facility, where the more considerable object is first presented, and the lesser follows it, than where this order is reversed, and the lesser takes the precedence. Thus it is more natural for us to love the son upon account of the father, than the father upon account of the son; the servant for the master, than the master for the servant; the subject for the prince, than the prince for the subject. In like manner we more readily contract a hatred against a whole family, where our first quarrel is with the head of it, than where we are displeased with a son, or servant, or some inferior member. In short, our passions, like other objects, descend with greater facility than they ascend.
There's only one challenge in this experiment that we need to address before moving on. It's clear that while all emotions can easily shift from one related object to another, this transition happens more smoothly when the more significant object is introduced first, followed by the lesser one, rather than the other way around. For example, it's more natural for us to love the son because of the father, rather than the father because of the son; to care for the servant because of the master, rather than the master because of the servant; or to support the subject because of the prince, rather than the prince because of the subject. Similarly, we are more likely to develop a hatred for an entire family when our initial conflict is with the head of the family, rather than with a son, servant, or another less prominent member. In short, our emotions, like other things, flow down more easily than they rise up.
That we may comprehend, wherein consists the difficulty of explaining this phænomenon, we must consider, that the very same reason, which determines the imagination to pass from remote to contiguous objects, with more facility than from contiguous to remote, causes it likewise to change with more ease, the less for the greater, than the greater for the less. Whatever has the greatest influence is most taken notice of; and whatever is most taken notice of, presents itself most readily to the imagination. We are more apt to over-look in any subject, what is trivial, than what appears of considerable moment; but especially if the latter takes the precedence, and first engages our attention. Thus if any accident makes us consider the Satellites of JUPITER, our fancy is naturally determined to form the idea of that planet; but if we first reflect on the principal planet, it is more natural for us to overlook its attendants. The mention of the provinces of any empire conveys our thought to the seat of the empire; but the fancy returns not with the same facility to the consideration of the provinces. The idea of the servant makes us think of the master; that of the subject carries our view to the prince. But the same relation has not an equal influence in conveying us back again. And on this is founded that reproach of Cornelia to her sons, that they ought to be ashamed she should be more known by the title of the daughter of Scipio than by that of the mother of the Gracchi. This was, in other words, exhorting them to render themselves as illustrious and famous as their grandfather, otherwise the imagination of the people, passing from her who was intermediate, and placed in an equal relation to both, would always leave them, and denominate her by what was more considerable and of greater moment. On the same principle is founded that common custom of making wives bear the name of their husbands, rather than husbands that of their wives; as also the ceremony of giving the precedency to those, whom we honour and respect. We might find many other instances to confirm this principle, were it not already sufficiently evident.
To understand the difficulty in explaining this phenomenon, we need to recognize that the same reason that makes it easier for our imagination to move from distant to nearby objects also allows it to switch more easily from the smaller to the larger, rather than the other way around. What has the most impact is noticed more, and what is noticed the most comes to mind more readily. We're more likely to overlook what's trivial in any topic than what seems important, especially if the important thing catches our attention first. For example, if an event makes us think about Jupiter's moons, our imagination will naturally lead us to the planet itself; conversely, if we first think of Jupiter, we’re likely to ignore its moons. When we mention the provinces of an empire, our thoughts go to the capital; but our minds don't easily revert back to the provinces. The idea of a servant leads us to think of the master, and the idea of a subject brings our thoughts to the prince. However, this connection doesn't work in reverse as easily. This idea is what Cornelia criticized in her sons, suggesting they should feel ashamed that she is known more as Scipio's daughter than as the mother of the Gracchi. In other words, she encouraged them to make their own names as renowned as their grandfather’s; otherwise, people's perception, moving from her—which places her equally linked to both—would always leave them out and refer to her by something more significant. The same reasoning underlies the common practice of wives taking their husbands' names instead of the other way around, as well as the tradition of giving precedence to those we honor and respect. We could find many more examples to support this principle if it weren't already quite clear.
Now since the fancy finds the same facility in passing from the lesser to the greater, as from remote to contiguous, why does not this easy transition of ideas assist the transition of passions in the former case, as well as in the latter? The virtues of a friend or brother produce first love, and then pride; because in that case the imagination passes from remote to contiguous, according to its propensity. Our own virtues produce not first pride, and then love to a friend or brother; because the passage in that case would be from contiguous to remote, contrary to its propensity. But the love or hatred of an inferior causes not readily any passion to the superior, though that be the natural propensity of the imagination: While the love or hatred of a superior, causes a passion to the inferior, contrary to its propensity. In short, the same facility of transition operates not in the same manner upon superior and inferior as upon contiguous and remote. These two phaenomena appear contradictory, and require some attention to be reconciled.
Since the mind finds it just as easy to move from the lesser to the greater as it does from distant to nearby, why doesn’t this smooth transition of ideas help the shift in emotions in the first case, just like it does in the second? The qualities of a friend or brother initially create love, followed by pride; here, the imagination moves from distant to nearby as it tends to do. In contrast, our own qualities don’t lead to pride first and then love for a friend or brother, because that would involve moving from nearby to distant, which is against its usual tendency. However, the love or dislike of someone inferior doesn’t easily produce any strong feelings in the superior, even though that's how the imagination naturally works; on the other hand, the love or dislike of someone superior does provoke strong feelings in the inferior, going against its natural tendency. In summary, the same ease of transition doesn’t affect those above and below in the same way as it does with nearby and distant. These two situations seem contradictory and need some thought to be understood.
As the transition of ideas is here made contrary to the natural propensity of the imagination, that faculty must be overpowered by some stronger principle of another kind; and as there is nothing ever present to the mind but impressions and ideas, this principle must necessarily lie in the impressions. Now it has been observed, that impressions or passions are connected only by their resemblance, and that where any two passions place the mind in the same or in similar dispositions, it very naturally passes from the one to the other: As on the contrary, a repugnance in the dispositions produces a difficulty in the transition of the passions. But it is observable, that this repugnance may arise from a difference of degree as well as of kind; nor do we experience a greater difficulty in passing suddenly from a small degree of love to a small degree of hatred, than from a small to a great degree of either of these affections. A man, when calm or only moderately agitated, is so different, in every respect, from himself, when disturbed with a violent passion, that no two persons can be more unlike; nor is it easy to pass from the one extreme to the other, without a considerable interval betwixt them.
As the shift of ideas happens against the natural tendency of the imagination, that mental ability must be overridden by a stronger principle of another sort; and since there is nothing in the mind except impressions and ideas, this principle must be based in the impressions. It has been noted that impressions or feelings are linked only by their similarity, and when two feelings put the mind in the same or a similar state, it naturally moves from one to the other. In contrast, a conflict in these states makes it difficult to switch between feelings. It’s important to note that this conflict can come from differences in both degree and type; we don’t find it harder to suddenly move from a small amount of love to a small amount of hate than we do transitioning from a small to a large amount of either feeling. A person, when calm or only slightly agitated, is so different in every way from himself when overwhelmed by a strong emotion that no two people could be more dissimilar; and it’s not easy to go from one extreme to the other without a significant gap in between.
The difficulty is not less, if it be not rather greater, in passing from the strong passion to the weak, than in passing from the weak to the strong, provided the one passion upon its appearance destroys the other, and they do not both of them exist at once. But the case is entirely altered, when the passions unite together, and actuate the mind at the same time. A weak passion, when added to a strong, makes not so considerable a change in the disposition, as a strong when added to a weak; for which reason there is a closer connexion betwixt the great degree and the small, than betwixt the small degree and the great.
The challenge is not any less, and may actually be greater, when moving from a strong passion to a weak one than when going from weak to strong, as long as the strong passion completely overshadows the weak one upon its emergence, preventing them from coexisting. However, the situation completely shifts when the passions come together and influence the mind simultaneously. A weak passion added to a strong one doesn’t significantly alter the overall disposition as much as a strong passion combined with a weak one does; this is why there’s a closer connection between the stronger degree and the weaker one than between the weaker degree and the stronger.
The degree of any passion depends upon the nature of its object; and an affection directed to a person, who is considerable in our eyes, fills and possesses the mind much more than one, which has for its object a person we esteem of less consequence. Here then the contradiction betwixt the propensities of the imagination and passion displays itself. When we turn our thought to a great and a small object, the imagination finds more facility in passing from the small to the great, than from the great to the small; but the affections find a greater difficulty: And as the affections are a more powerful principle than the imagination, no wonder they prevail over it, and draw the mind to their side. In spite of the difficulty of passing from the idea of great to that of little, a passion directed to the former, produces always a similar passion towards the latter; when the great and little are related together. The idea of the servant conveys our thought most readily to the master; but the hatred or love of the master produces with greater facility anger or good-will to the servant. The strongest passion in this case takes the precedence; and the addition of the weaker making no considerable change on the disposition, the passage is by that means rendered more easy and natural betwixt them.
The intensity of any passion depends on what it's aimed at; an affection directed towards a person we admire holds our attention much more than one aimed at someone we see as less significant. Here, the conflict between the tendencies of imagination and passion becomes clear. When we think about something big and something small, our imagination finds it easier to shift from the small to the big than vice versa; however, the affections struggle more with this transition. Since affections are a stronger force than imagination, it makes sense that they dominate and pull our thoughts in their direction. Even though it's challenging to move from thinking about something big to something small, a passion aimed at the big always sparks a similar passion for the small when they are connected. The idea of a servant easily leads our thoughts to the master; however, the love or hate we feel for the master more readily translates into feelings of anger or goodwill toward the servant. In this case, the strongest passion takes precedence, and since the weaker one doesn’t significantly change our feelings, the transition between them becomes smoother and more natural.
As in the foregoing experiment we found, that a relation of ideas, which, by any particular circumstance, ceases to produce its usual effect of facilitating the transition of ideas, ceases likewise to operate on the passions; so in the present experiment we find the same property of the impressions. Two different degrees of the same passion are surely related together; but if the smaller be first present, it has little or no tendency to introduce the greater; and that because the addition of the great to the little, produces a more sensible alteration on the temper, than the addition of the little to the great. These phaenomena, when duly weighed, will be found convincing proofs of this hypothesis.
In the previous experiment, we discovered that when a certain idea stops having its usual effect due to a specific circumstance, it no longer influences our emotions either. Similarly, in this experiment, we observe the same property of impressions. Two different levels of the same emotion are definitely connected, but if the lesser one comes first, it has little to no impact on bringing about the stronger one. This happens because adding the stronger emotion to the weaker one causes a more noticeable change in our mood than adding the weaker to the stronger. When you consider these phenomena carefully, you'll find they provide strong evidence for this hypothesis.
And these proofs will be confirmed, if we consider the manner in which the mind here reconciles the contradiction, I have observed betwixt the passions and the imagination. The fancy passes with more facility from the less to the greater, than from the greater to the less: But on the contrary a violent passion produces more easily a feeble, than that does a violent. In this opposition the passion in the end prevails over the imagination; but it is commonly by complying with it, and by seeking another quality, which may counter-ballance that principle, from whence the opposition arises. When we love the father or master of a family, we little think of his children or servants. But when these are present with us, or when it lies any ways in our power to serve them, the nearness and contiguity in this case encreases their magnitude, or at least removes that opposition, which the fancy makes to the transition of the affections. If the imagination finds a difficulty in passing from greater to less, it finds an equal facility in passing from remote to contiguous, which brings the matter to an equality, and leaves the way open from the one passion to the other.
And these proofs will be confirmed if we look at how the mind reconciles the contradiction that I've noticed between feelings and imagination. The mind more easily shifts from the less important to the more important than from the more important to the less. However, a strong emotion can more easily lead to a weak one than vice versa. In this conflict, emotions ultimately take precedence over imagination; but this usually happens by agreeing with it and by finding another quality that can balance out the principle from which the conflict arises. When we love the head of a family, we rarely think about his children or servants. But when they are around us, or when we have any opportunity to help them, their proximity increases their significance or at least removes the obstacle that the mind creates to switch our affections. If the imagination struggles to transition from something greater to something lesser, it can easily shift from something distant to something close, which brings everything to an equal level and keeps the path open from one emotion to another.
Eighth Experiment. I have observed that the transition from love or hatred to pride or humility, is more easy than from pride or humility to love or hatred; and that the difficulty, which the imagination finds in passing from contiguous to remote, is the cause why we scarce have any instance of the latter transition of the affections. I must, however, make one exception, viz, when the very cause of the pride and humility is placed in some other person. For in that case the imagination is necessitated to consider the person, nor can it possibly confine its view to ourselves. Thus nothing more readily produces kindness and affection to any person, than his approbation of our conduct and character: As on the other hand, nothing inspires us with a stronger hatred, than his blame or contempt. Here it is evident, that the original passion is pride or humility, whose object is self; and that this passion is transfused into love or hatred, whose object is some other person, notwithstanding the rule I have already established, THAT THE IMAGINATION PASSES WITH DIFFICULTY FROM CONTIGUOUS TO REMOTE. But the transition in this case is not made merely on account of the relation betwixt ourselves and the person; but because that very person is the real cause of our first passion, and of consequence is intimately connected with it. It is his approbation that produces pride; and disapprobation, humility. No wonder, then, the imagination returns back again attended with the related passions of love and hatred. This is not a contradiction, but an exception to the rule; and an exception that arises from the same reason with the rule itself.
Eighth Experiment. I've noticed that moving from love or hatred to pride or humility is easier than shifting from pride or humility to love or hatred. The challenge that our imagination faces in going from something close to something distant explains why we rarely see the latter transition in feelings. However, I should make one exception: when the source of pride and humility is found in another person. In that case, the imagination has to focus on that person and can't just stick to thinking about ourselves. Nothing creates kindness and affection for someone more effectively than their approval of our actions and character. Conversely, nothing inspires stronger hatred than their criticism or contempt. It's clear that the original feeling is pride or humility, directed at ourselves, and that this feeling transforms into love or hatred directed at someone else, even though I've already established that the imagination struggles to shift from the nearby to the distant. But in this situation, the transition isn’t just based on the relationship between us and the other person; it's because that person is the actual cause of our initial feeling, and therefore is closely connected to it. Their approval breeds pride, while their disapproval breeds humility. So it makes sense that the imagination circles back, bringing along the linked emotions of love and hatred. This isn’t a contradiction; it’s a special case that arises for the same reason as the rule itself.
Such an exception as this is, therefore, rather a confirmation of the rule. And indeed, if we consider all the eight experiments I have explained, we shall find that the same principle appears in all of them, and that it is by means of a transition arising from a double relation of impressions and ideas, pride and humility, love and hatred are produced. An object without[1] a relation, or[2] with but one, never produces either of these passions; and it is[3] found that the passion always varies in conformity to the relation. Nay we may observe, that where the relation, by any particular circumstance, has not its usual effect of producing a transition either of[4] ideas or of impressions, it ceases to operate upon the passions, and gives rise neither to pride nor love, humility nor hatred. This rule we find still to hold good,[5] even under the appearance of its contrary; and as relation is frequently experienced to have no effect; which upon examination is found to proceed from some particular circumstance, that prevents the transition; so even in instances, where that circumstance, though present, prevents not the transition, it is found to arise from some other circumstance, which counter-balances it. Thus not only the variations resolve themselves into the general principle, but even the variations of these variations.
Such an exception is actually a confirmation of the rule. If we look at all eight experiments I've explained, we can see that the same principle is present in all of them. It's through a shift caused by a double relationship of impressions and ideas that feelings like pride and humility, love and hatred come about. An object without a relation, or one with just a single relation, never generates these emotions; and it's evident that the feeling always changes according to the relation. Moreover, we can notice that when a relation, due to some specific circumstance, doesn't have its usual effect in creating a shift in ideas or impressions, it stops affecting our emotions and doesn't lead to pride, love, humility, or hatred. We find that this rule still applies, even when it seems contrary; and since we often see that a relation has no effect, which on closer inspection turns out to be due to some specific circumstance preventing the shift, we also see that even in cases where that circumstance is present but doesn't stop the shift, it results from some other factor that balances it out. Thus, not only do the variations resolve into the overall principle, but even the variations of those variations.
[1] First Experiment.
First Experiment.
[2] Second and Third Experiments.
Second and Third Experiments.
[3] Fourth Experiment.
Fourth Experiment.
[4] Sixth Experiment.
[5] Seventh and Eighth Experiments.
7th and 8th Experiments.
SECT. III DIFFICULTIES SOLVED
After so many and such undeniable proofs drawn from daily experience and observation, it may seem superfluous to enter into a particular examination of all the causes of love and hatred. I shall, therefore, employ the sequel of this part, First, In removing some difficulties, concerning particular causes of these passions. Secondly, In examining the compound affections, which arise from the mixture of love and hatred with other emotions.
After so many clear examples from everyday life and observation, it might seem unnecessary to go into detail about all the reasons for love and hate. So, I will use the rest of this section to do two things: First, to clear up some misunderstandings about specific causes of these emotions. Second, to look at the mixed feelings that come from combining love and hate with other emotions.
Nothing is more evident, than that any person acquires our kindness, or is exposed to our ill-will, in proportion to the pleasure or uneasiness we receive from him, and that the passions keep pace exactly with the sensations in all their changes and variations. Whoever can find the means either by his services, his beauty, or his flattery, to render himself useful or agreeable to us, is sure of our affections: As on the other hand, whoever harms or displeases us never fails to excite our anger or hatred. When our own nation is at war with any other, we detest them under the character of cruel, perfidious, unjust and violent: But always esteem ourselves and allies equitable, moderate, and merciful. If the general of our enemies be successful, it is with difficulty we allow him the figure and character of a man. He is a sorcerer: He has a communication with daemons; as is reported of OLIVER CROMWELL, and the DUKE OF LUXEMBOURG: He is bloody-minded, and takes a pleasure in death and destruction. But if the success be on our side, our commander has all the opposite good qualities, and is a pattern of virtue, as well as of courage and conduct. His treachery we call policy: His cruelty is an evil inseparable from war. In short, every one of his faults we either endeavour to extenuate, or dignify it with the name of that virtue, which approaches it. It is evident the same method of thinking runs through common life.
Nothing is clearer than that people gain our kindness or face our dislike based on how much pleasure or discomfort they bring us. Our feelings closely follow our sensations in all their changes. Anyone who can make themselves useful or enjoyable to us, whether through their services, looks, or flattery, is guaranteed our affection. Conversely, anyone who harms or annoys us inevitably stirs our anger or hatred. When our country is at war with another, we see them as cruel, treacherous, unjust, and violent, while we view ourselves and our allies as fair, moderate, and merciful. If the leader of our enemies is successful, we struggle to see him as human; we think of him as a sorcerer with dark powers, like OLIVER CROMWELL and the DUKE OF LUXEMBOURG. He is bloodthirsty and enjoys death and destruction. But if the victory is ours, our commander possesses all the opposite virtues and is a model of both bravery and skill. His treachery becomes wise strategy; his cruelty is simply a necessary part of war. Ultimately, we either downplay his flaws or elevate them by linking them to some positive quality. It's clear that this way of thinking applies to everyday life as well.
There are some, who add another condition, and require not only that the pain and pleasure arise from the person, but likewise that it arise knowingly, and with a particular design and intention. A man, who wounds and harms us by accident, becomes not our enemy upon that account, nor do we think ourselves bound by any ties of gratitude to one, who does us any service after the same manner. By the intention we judge of the actions, and according as that is good or bad, they become causes of love or hatred.
Some people add another condition, stating that not only should pain and pleasure come from a person, but it should also be intentional and aware. A man who accidentally hurts us is not considered our enemy because of that, nor do we feel any obligation to be grateful to someone who helps us in the same way. We judge actions based on intention, and depending on whether that intention is good or bad, those actions become reasons for love or hatred.
But here we must make a distinction. If that quality in another, which pleases or displeases, be constant and inherent in his person and character, it will cause love or hatred independent of the intention: But otherwise a knowledge and design is requisite, in order to give rise to these passions. One that is disagreeable by his deformity or folly is the object of our aversion, though nothing be more certain, than that he has not the least intention of displeasing us by these qualities. But if the uneasiness proceed not from a quality, but an action, which is produced and annihilated in a moment, it is necessary, in order to produce some relation, and connect this action sufficiently with the person, that it be derived from a particular fore-thought and design. It is not enough, that the action arise from the person, and have him for its immediate cause and author. This relation alone is too feeble and inconstant to be a foundation for these passions. It reaches not the sensible and thinking part, and neither proceeds from any thing durable in him, nor leaves any thing behind it; but passes in a moment, and is as if it had never been. On the other hand, an intention shews certain qualities, which remaining after the action is performed, connect it with the person, and facilitate the transition of ideas from one to the other. We can never think of him without reflecting on these qualities; unless repentance and a change of life have produced an alteration in that respect: In which case the passion is likewise altered. This therefore is one reason, why an intention is requisite to excite either love or hatred.
But here we need to make a distinction. If a quality in someone else, whether pleasing or unpleasing, is constant and part of their character, it will lead to love or hate regardless of intent. However, if that discomfort comes from an action, which happens and fades away in an instant, a specific intention and design are needed to link that action to the person in a meaningful way. It's not enough for the action to simply come from the person; that connection is too weak and unstable to support these feelings. It doesn't reach our sensitive or thoughtful side, doesn't stem from something lasting, and leaves no lasting impact; it happens in a flash and feels as if it never occurred. In contrast, an intention reveals certain qualities that persist even after the action, linking it to the person and making it easier for us to connect our thoughts about one to the other. We can't think of that person without considering those qualities, unless regret and a change in behavior have created a shift in that regard; in such cases, the feelings we have also change. This is one reason why an intention is necessary to stir feelings of love or hatred.
But we must farther consider, that an intention, besides its strengthening the relation of ideas, is often necessary to produce a relation of impressions, and give rise to pleasure and uneasiness. For it is observable, that the principal part of an injury is the contempt and hatred, which it shews in the person, that injures us; and without that, the mere harm gives us a less sensible uneasiness. In like manner, a good office is agreeable, chiefly because it flatters our vanity, and is a proof of the kindness and esteem of the person, who performs it. The removal of the intention, removes the mortification in the one case, and vanity in the other, and must of course cause a remarkable diminution in the passions of love and hatred.
But we must also consider that an intention not only strengthens the connection between ideas but is often necessary to create a connection between impressions and lead to pleasure or discomfort. It's noticeable that the main part of an injury is the contempt and hatred expressed by the person who harms us; without that, the actual harm causes us less noticeable discomfort. Similarly, a kind action is enjoyable mainly because it flatters our vanity and shows the kindness and regard of the person who performs it. Removing the intention lessens the humiliation in one case and the vanity in the other, which naturally leads to a significant reduction in the emotions of love and hatred.
I grant, that these effects of the removal of design, in diminishing the relations of impressions and ideas, are not entire, nor able to remove every degree of these relations. But then I ask, if the removal of design be able entirely to remove the passion of love and hatred? Experience, I am sure, informs us of the contrary, nor is there any thing more certain, than that men often fall into a violent anger for injuries, which they themselves must own to be entirely involuntary and accidental. This emotion, indeed, cannot be of long continuance; but still is sufficient to shew, that there is a natural connexion betwixt uneasiness and anger, and that the relation of impressions will operate upon a very small relation of ideas. But when the violence of the impression is once a little abated, the defect of the relation begins to be better felt; and as the character of a person is no wise interested in such injuries as are casual and involuntary, it seldom happens that on their account, we entertain a lasting enmity.
I admit that these effects of removing design, which lessen the connections between impressions and ideas, are not complete and can't eliminate every aspect of those connections. But I ask, can the absence of design completely eliminate feelings of love and hate? Experience clearly tells us otherwise, and there’s nothing more certain than that people often get extremely angry over injuries that they know are completely unintentional and random. This anger, while not lasting, is enough to show that there is a natural link between discomfort and anger, and that the connection between impressions can influence a very small connection between ideas. However, once the intensity of the impression starts to fade a bit, the lack of connection becomes more noticeable; since a person's character isn't affected by injuries that are random and unintentional, we rarely hold a lasting grudge because of them.
To illustrate this doctrine by a parallel instance, we may observe, that not only the uneasiness, which proceeds from another by accident, has but little force to excite our passion, but also that which arises from an acknowledged necessity and duty. One that has a real design of harming us, proceeding not from hatred and ill-will, but from justice and equity, draws not upon him our anger, if we be in any degree reasonable; notwithstanding he is both the cause, and the knowing cause of our sufferings. Let us examine a little this phænomenon.
To illustrate this principle with a parallel example, we can see that the discomfort caused by someone accidentally has little power to stir our emotions, and the same goes for discomfort that comes from a recognized obligation or duty. Someone who truly intends to harm us, but does so not out of hatred or malice, but from a sense of justice and fairness, doesn't provoke our anger if we are at all reasonable; even though they are both the cause and fully aware of our suffering. Let’s take a closer look at this phenomenon.
It is evident in the first place, that this circumstance is not decisive; and though it may be able to diminish the passions, it is seldom it can entirely remove them. How few criminals are there, who have no ill-will to the person, that accuses them, or to the judge, that condemns them, even though they be conscious of their own deserts? In like manner our antagonist in a law-suit, and our competitor for any office, are commonly regarded as our enemies; though we must acknowledge, if we would but reflect a moment, that their motive is entirely as justifiable as our own.
It's clear from the start that this situation isn't a game-changer; while it might help tone down the emotions, it rarely completely eliminates them. How many criminals exist who feel no resentment towards the person accusing them or the judge passing judgment, even if they know they deserve it? Similarly, in a legal dispute or when competing for a position, we usually see the other party as our enemy, even though we must admit, if we take a moment to think about it, that their motivations are just as valid as ours.
Besides we may consider, that when we receive harm from any person, we are apt to imagine him criminal, and it is with extreme difficulty we allow of his justice and innocence. This is a clear proof, that, independent of the opinion of iniquity, any harm or uneasiness has a natural tendency to excite our hatred, and that afterwards we seek for reasons upon which we may justify and establish the passion. Here the idea of injury produces not the passion, but arises from it.
Besides, we might consider that when we get hurt by someone, we tend to think of them as guilty, and it’s really hard for us to believe in their fairness and innocence. This clearly shows that, regardless of our views on wrongdoing, any harm or discomfort naturally stirs up our hatred, and afterward, we look for reasons to justify and support that feeling. In this case, the idea of being wronged doesn’t create the feeling; it actually comes from it.
Nor is it any wonder that passion should produce the opinion of injury; since otherwise it must suffer a considerable diminution, which all the passions avoid as much as possible. The removal of injury may remove the anger, without proving that the anger arises only from the injury. The harm and the justice are two contrary objects, of which the one has a tendency to produce hatred, and the other love; and it is according to their different degrees, and our particular turn of thinking, that either of the objects prevails, and excites its proper passion.
It's not surprising that strong feelings can lead to feelings of being wronged; otherwise, those feelings would significantly lessen, which all strong emotions try to avoid as much as possible. Removing the feeling of being wronged can ease the anger, but that doesn't prove that the anger only comes from the feeling of being wronged. Harm and justice are two opposing concepts, where one tends to create hatred and the other inspires love; it depends on their varying intensities and our individual perspectives that determine which feeling takes over and stimulates its corresponding emotion.
SECT. IV OF THE LOVE OF RELATIONS
Having given a reason, why several actions, that cause a real pleasure or uneasiness, excite not any degree, or but a small one, of the passion of love or hatred towards the actors; it will be necessary to shew, wherein consists the pleasure or uneasiness of many objects, which we find by experience to produce these passions.
Having provided a reason why some actions that cause genuine pleasure or discomfort don't trigger much, if any, love or hatred towards the people responsible; it’s important to demonstrate what creates the pleasure or discomfort in many things that we see, through experience, lead to these emotions.
According to the preceding system there is always required a double relation of impressions and ideas betwixt the cause and effect, in order to produce either love or hatred. But though this be universally true, it is remarkable that the passion of love may be excited by only one relation of a different kind, viz, betwixt ourselves and the object; or more properly speaking, that this relation is always attended with both the others. Whoever is united to us by any connexion is always sure of a share of our love, proportioned to the connexion, without enquiring into his other qualities. Thus the relation of blood produces the strongest tie the mind is capable of in the love of parents to their children, and a lesser degree of the same affection, as the relation lessens. Nor has consanguinity alone this effect, but any other relation without exception. We love our country-men, our neighbours, those of the same trade, profession, and even name with ourselves. Every one of these relations is esteemed some tie, and gives a title to a share of our affection.
According to the previous system, there is always a requirement for a double connection of impressions and ideas between cause and effect to create either love or hatred. However, it’s interesting that the feeling of love can be stirred by just one type of connection, which is the one between us and the object of our affection; or more accurately, this connection always comes with the other types. Anyone who has a connection to us is guaranteed a portion of our love, based on the strength of that connection, without needing to consider their other qualities. For example, the bond of blood creates the strongest attachment the mind can have, like the love parents have for their children, with a lesser degree of that same love as the connection weakens. This effect isn’t just limited to familial ties; any type of connection has the same impact. We feel affection for our fellow countrymen, our neighbors, those in the same trade or profession, and even those who share our name. Each of these connections is considered some kind of bond and earns a place in our affection.
There is another phænomenon, which is parallel to this, viz, that acquaintance, without any kind of relation, gives rise to love and kindness. When we have contracted a habitude and intimacy with any person; though in frequenting his company we have not been able to discover any very valuable quality, of which he is possessed; yet we cannot forebear preferring him to strangers, of whose superior merit we are fully convinced. These two phaenomena of the effects of relation and acquaintance will give mutual light to each other, and may be both explained from the same principle.
There’s another phenomenon that’s similar to this: familiarity, even without a real relationship, can lead to love and kindness. When we develop a habit and intimacy with someone, even if we don’t find any remarkable qualities in them, we still tend to prefer them over strangers, despite being fully aware of those strangers' superior qualities. These two phenomena—how relationships and familiarity affect us—can illuminate each other and can both be understood through the same principle.
Those, who take a pleasure in declaiming against human nature, have observed, that man is altogether insufficient to support himself; and that when you loosen all the holds, which he has of external objects, he immediately drops down into the deepest melancholy and despair. From this, say they, proceeds that continual search after amusement in gaming, in hunting, in business; by which we endeavour to forget ourselves, and excite our spirits from the languid state, into which they fall, when not sustained by some brisk and lively emotion. To this method of thinking I so far agree, that I own the mind to be insufficient, of itself, to its own entertainment, and that it naturally seeks after foreign objects, which may produce a lively sensation, and agitate the spirits. On the appearance of such an object it awakes, as it were, from a dream: The blood flows with a new tide: The heart is elevated: And the whole man acquires a vigour, which he cannot command in his solitary and calm moments. Hence company is naturally so rejoicing, as presenting the liveliest of all objects, viz, a rational and thinking Being like ourselves, who communicates to us all the actions of his mind; makes us privy to his inmost sentiments and affections; and lets us see, in the very instant of their production, all the emotions, which are caused by any object. Every lively idea is agreeable, but especially that of a passion, because such an idea becomes a kind of passion, and gives a more sensible agitation to the mind, than any other image or conception.
People who enjoy criticizing human nature have noted that humans are completely unable to stand on their own. They argue that when we detach ourselves from external influences, we quickly sink into deep sadness and despair. From this, they claim, comes our constant search for entertainment in activities like gaming, hunting, or work; we try to distract ourselves and lift our spirits from the lethargy that sets in when we’re not surrounded by some vibrant and engaging emotions. I somewhat agree with this perspective, admitting that the mind alone isn't enough for its own amusement and that it naturally seeks external stimuli to create lively feelings and stir our spirits. When such a stimulus appears, it’s like waking from a dream: our energy surges, our hearts lift, and we gain a vigor that we can’t summon during solitary, calm moments. Therefore, being with others is naturally uplifting since it presents the most vibrant of all stimuli—a rational, thinking being like ourselves—who shares their thoughts and emotions with us, revealing their deepest feelings and reactions in real time. Every vivid idea is pleasing, but especially those involving passion, because such ideas evoke a kind of passion themselves and create a more intense stir in the mind than any other image or thought.
This being once admitted, all the rest is easy. For as the company of strangers is agreeable to us for a short time, by inlivening our thought; so the company of our relations and acquaintance must be peculiarly agreeable, because it has this effect in a greater degree, and is of more durable influence. Whatever is related to us is conceived in a lively manner by the easy transition from ourselves to the related object. Custom also, or acquaintance facilitates the entrance, and strengthens the conception of any object. The first case is parallel to our reasonings from cause and effect; the second to education. And as reasoning and education concur only in producing a lively and strong idea of any object; so is this the only particular, which is common to relation and acquaintance. This must, therefore, be the influencing quality, by which they produce all their common effects; and love or kindness being one of these effects, it must be from the force and liveliness of conception, that the passion is derived. Such a conception is peculiarly agreeable, and makes us have an affectionate regard for every thing, that produces it, when the proper object of kindness and goodwill.
Once we accept this idea, everything else becomes straightforward. Just as being around strangers can be enjoyable for a short time because it energizes our thoughts, being with our family and friends is even more enjoyable because it has a stronger and longer-lasting impact. Anything related to us is imagined vividly due to the easy connection we make from ourselves to what is related. Familiarity, or knowing someone, also helps us understand and reinforces our thoughts about something. The first situation is similar to how we think about cause and effect, while the second relates to education. Just as reasoning and education work together to create a strong and vivid idea of something, this quality is what both relationships and familiarity share. Therefore, this has to be the key quality that drives their shared effects; since love or kindness is one of these effects, it must stem from the intensity and clarity of our thoughts. Such a clear understanding is especially enjoyable and makes us feel a sense of affection for everything that brings it about, when it is appropriate for kindness and goodwill.
It is obvious, that people associate together according to their particular tempers and dispositions, and that men of gay tempers naturally love the gay; as the serious bear an affection to the serious. This not only happens, where they remark this resemblance betwixt themselves and others, but also by the natural course of the disposition, and by a certain sympathy, which always arises betwixt similar characters. Where they remark the resemblance, it operates after the manner of a relation, by producing a connexion of ideas. Where they do not remark it, it operates by some other principle; and if this latter principle be similar to the former, it must be received as a confirmation of the foregoing reasoning.
It's clear that people tend to group together based on their unique personalities and temperaments. Those who are cheerful naturally gravitate towards others who are also cheerful, just as serious individuals tend to connect with fellow serious people. This happens not only when they notice a similarity between themselves and others but also through the natural flow of their personalities and a certain bond that forms between similar characters. When they notice the resemblance, it works like a family tie, creating a connection of ideas. When they don't notice it, it works on a different principle, and if this principle is similar to the first, it strengthens the previous argument.
The idea of ourselves is always intimately present to us, and conveys a sensible degree of vivacity to the idea of any other object, to which we are related. This lively idea changes by degrees into a real impression; these two kinds of perception being in a great measure the same, and differing only in their degrees of force and vivacity. But this change must be produced with the greater ease, that our natural temper gives us a propensity to the same impression, which we observe in others, and makes it arise upon any slight occasion. In that case resemblance converts the idea into an impression, not only by means of the relation, and by transfusing the original vivacity into the related idea; but also by presenting such materials as take fire from the least spark. And as in both cases a love or affection arises from the resemblance, we may learn that a sympathy with others is agreeable only by giving an emotion to the spirits, since an easy sympathy and correspondent emotions are alone common to RELATION, ACQUAINTANCE, and RESEMBLANCE.
The way we see ourselves is always closely tied to us, and it adds a noticeable energy to how we perceive anything else we’re connected to. This vibrant perception gradually shifts into a genuine impression; these two types of awareness are largely the same, differing mainly in how intense and lively they are. However, this transition happens more easily because our natural disposition leads us to have a tendency toward the same impression we notice in others, which can surface even with minor triggers. In this instance, similarity turns the idea into an impression, not just through connection and by transferring the original energy to the related idea, but also by providing materials that ignite with the smallest spark. And since affection or attachment arises from this similarity, we can understand that being in sync with others is enjoyable primarily because it stirs emotion within us, as this effortless connection and shared feelings are what are common to RELATION, ACQUAINTANCE, and RESEMBLANCE.
The great propensity men have to pride may be considered as another similar phænomenon. It often happens, that after we have lived a considerable time in any city; however at first it might be disagreeable to us; yet as we become familiar with the objects, and contact an acquaintance, though merely with the streets and buildings, the aversion diminishes by degrees, and at last changes into the opposite passion. The mind finds a satisfaction and ease in the view of objects, to which it is accustomed, and naturally prefers them to others, which, though, perhaps, in themselves more valuable, are less known to it. By the same quality of the mind we are seduced into a good opinion of ourselves, and of all objects, that belong to us. They appear in a stronger light; are more agreeable; and consequently fitter subjects of pride and vanity, than any other.
The strong tendency people have toward pride can be seen as another similar phenomenon. It often happens that after we’ve lived in a city for a significant amount of time, even if we found it unpleasant at first, our feelings change. As we become familiar with our surroundings and even develop a sort of connection with the streets and buildings, our dislike gradually fades and eventually turns into affection. Our minds find comfort and satisfaction in things we’re used to, and naturally prefer them over others, which, although they might be more valuable, are less familiar to us. This same tendency leads us to develop a positive view of ourselves and everything we own. These things seem enhanced, more appealing, and in turn, become better sources of pride and vanity than anything else.
It may not be amiss, in treating of the affection we bear our acquaintance and relations, to observe some pretty curious phaenomena, which attend it. It is easy to remark in common life, that children esteem their relation to their mother to be weakened, in a great measure, by her second marriage, and no longer regard her with the same eye, as if she had continued in her state of widow-hood. Nor does this happen only, when they have felt any inconveniences from her second marriage, or when her husband is much her inferior; but even without any of these considerations, and merely because she has become part of another family. This also takes place with regard to the second marriage of a father; but in a much less degree: And it is certain the ties of blood are not so much loosened in the latter case as by the marriage of a mother. These two phaenomena are remarkable in themselves, but much more so when compared.
It might be worthwhile, when discussing the feelings we have for our friends and family, to point out some interesting phenomena that come with it. It's easy to notice in everyday life that children often feel their connection to their mother weakens significantly after she remarries. They no longer see her in the same way as if she had stayed a widow. This change doesn't only happen because they've experienced difficulties due to her remarriage or because her new husband is much less suitable; it occurs simply because she has become part of a different family. The same can be observed with a father's second marriage, but to a much lesser extent. It's clear that blood ties are not as weakened in this case as they are when a mother remarries. These two phenomena are noteworthy on their own, but they become even more interesting when compared to each other.
In order to produce a perfect relation betwixt two objects, it is requisite, not only that the imagination be conveyed from one to the other by resemblance, contiguity or causation, but also that it return back from the second to the first with the same ease and facility. At first sight this may seem a necessary and unavoidable consequence. If one object resemble another, the latter object must necessarily resemble the former. If one object be the cause of another, the second object is effect to its cause. It is the same case with contiguity: And therefore the relation being always reciprocal, it may be thought, that the return of the imagination from the second to the first must also, in every case, be equally natural as its passage from the first to the second. But upon farther examination we shall easily discover our mistake. For supposing the second object, beside its reciprocal relation to the first, to have also a strong relation to a third object; in that case the thought, passing from the first object to the second, returns not back with the same facility, though the relation continues the same; but is readily carryed on to the third object, by means of the new relation, which presents itself, and gives a new impulse to the imagination. This new relation, therefore, weakens the tie betwixt the first and second objects. The fancy is by its very nature wavering and inconstant; and considers always two objects as more strongly related together, where it finds the passage equally easy both in going and returning, than where the transition is easy only in one of these motions. The double motion is a kind of a double tie, and binds the objects together in the closest and most intimate manner.
To create a strong connection between two objects, it's essential that the imagination moves from one to the other through resemblance, proximity, or causation, and that it can also easily return from the second to the first. At first glance, this might seem like an obvious and unavoidable conclusion. If one object resembles another, the second must necessarily resemble the first. If one object causes another, the second is the effect of its cause. The same applies to proximity; therefore, since the relationship is always mutual, it might be assumed that the imagination's return from the second to the first is just as natural as its journey from the first to the second. However, upon closer inspection, we'll quickly realize that this assumption is incorrect. If the second object, in addition to its mutual relationship with the first, has a strong connection to a third object, then the thought process moving from the first object to the second may not easily return, even though the connection remains the same. Instead, it might easily flow to the third object, due to the new relationship that presents itself and gives a fresh impulse to the imagination. This new connection, therefore, weakens the bond between the first and second objects. The imagination is inherently fickle and inconsistent; it always perceives two objects as being more closely related when it finds it easy to move back and forth between them, rather than when the transition is easy in only one direction. This two-way movement acts as a double bond, connecting the objects in the most intimate way.
The second marriage of a mother breaks not the relation of child and parent; and that relation suffices to convey my imagination from myself to her with the greatest ease and facility. But after the imagination is arrived at this point of view, it finds its object to be surrounded with so many other relations, which challenge its regard, that it knows not which to prefer, and is at a loss what new object to pitch upon. The ties of interest and duty bind her to another family, and prevent that return of the fancy from her to myself, which is necessary to support the union. The thought has no longer the vibration, requisite to set it perfectly at ease, and indulge its inclination to change. It goes with facility, but returns with difficulty; and by that interruption finds the relation much weakened from what it would be were the passage open and easy on both sides.
A mother’s second marriage doesn’t break the bond between her and her child; that bond allows my imagination to shift from myself to her effortlessly. However, once my imagination reaches that perspective, it realizes that she is surrounded by many other relationships that demand attention, making it hard to know which one to focus on and leaving me uncertain about what new connection to pursue. The responsibilities and obligations tie her to another family, making it hard for her to turn her thoughts back to me, which is essential for maintaining our bond. The thought no longer resonates in a way that brings comfort or allows for a shift in focus. It flows easily outward but struggles to return; this imbalance weakens our relationship compared to what it could be if the communication were smooth and unrestricted in both directions.
Now to give a reason, why this effect follows not in the same degree upon the second marriage of a father: we may reflect on what has been proved already, that though the imagination goes easily from the view of a lesser object to that of a greater, yet it returns not with the same facility from the greater to the less. When my imagination goes from myself to my father, it passes not so readily from him to his second wife, nor considers him as entering into a different family, but as continuing the head of that family, of which I am myself a part. His superiority prevents the easy transition of the thought from him to his spouse, but keeps the passage still open for a return to myself along the same relation of child and parent. He is not sunk in the new relation he acquires; so that the double motion or vibration of thought is still easy and natural. By this indulgence of the fancy in its inconstancy, the tie of child and parent still preserves its full force and influence. A mother thinks not her tie to a son weakened, because it is shared with her husband: Nor a son his with a parent, because it is shared with a brother. The third object is here related to the first, as well as to the second; so that the imagination goes and comes along all of them with the greatest facility.
Now, to explain why this effect doesn't occur to the same extent in a father's second marriage: we can reflect on what has already been shown, that while the mind easily shifts from thinking about a smaller object to a larger one, it doesn't transition back as easily from the larger to the smaller. When my mind moves from thinking about myself to thinking about my father, it doesn't transition as smoothly to his second wife. Instead, I see him as still being the head of the family I'm a part of, rather than as someone who has joined a new family. His authority makes it difficult for my thoughts to shift from him to his wife, but it still allows me to connect back to myself in the role of child to parent. He doesn't diminish in his new relationship; thus, this back-and-forth thinking remains easy and natural. Because of this flexibility in my thoughts, the bond between parent and child retains its full strength and impact. A mother doesn't see her connection to her son as weaker because it includes her husband, nor does a son feel any less connected to a parent because of a sibling. The third person here is connected to both the first and the second, allowing the mind to move easily among them.
SECT. V OF OUR ESTEEM FOR THE RICH AND POWERFUL
Nothing has a greater tendency to give us an esteem for any person, than his power and riches; or a contempt, than his poverty and meanness: And as esteem and contempt are to be considered as species of love and hatred, it will be proper in this place to explain these phaenomena.
Nothing makes us respect someone more than their power and wealth, or look down on them more than their poverty and low status. Since respect and contempt can be seen as forms of love and hatred, it’s appropriate here to explain these phenomena.
Here it happens most fortunately, that the greatest difficulty is not to discover a principle capable of producing such an effect, but to choose the chief and predominant among several, that present themselves. The satisfaction we take in the riches of others, and the esteem we have for the possessors may be ascribed to three different causes. FIRST, To the objects they possess; such as houses, gardens, equipages; which, being agreeable in themselves, necessarily produce a sentiment of pleasure in every one; that either considers or surveys them. SECONDLY, To the expectation of advantage from the rich and powerful by our sharing their possessions. THIRDLY, To sympathy, which makes us partake of the satisfaction of every one, that approaches us. All these principles may concur in producing the present phænomenon. The question is, to which of them we ought principally to ascribe it.
Here, it turns out that the biggest challenge isn’t figuring out a principle that can create such an effect, but rather deciding which one stands out the most among several options that come to mind. The pleasure we feel from the wealth of others and the admiration we have for those who own it can be attributed to three main reasons. FIRST, it’s about the things they own, like houses, gardens, and cars; these possessions are appealing in themselves and naturally bring a sense of joy to anyone who sees or thinks about them. SECOND, it’s the anticipation of benefiting from the rich and powerful by sharing in their wealth. THIRD, it’s sympathy, which allows us to share in the joy of anyone who is nearby. All of these factors can contribute to the current situation. The question is, which one should we primarily credit for it?
It is certain, that the first principle, viz, the reflection on agreeable objects, has a greater influence, than what, at first sight, we may be apt to imagine. We seldom reflect on what is beautiful or ugly, agreeable or disagreeable, without an emotion of pleasure or uneasiness; and though these sensations appear not much in our common indolent way of thinking, it is easy, either in reading or conversation, to discover them. Men of wit always turn the discourse on subjects that are entertaining to the imagination; and poets never present any objects but such as are of the same nature. Mr Philips has chosen CYDER for the subject of an excellent poem. Beer would not have been so proper, as being neither so agreeable to the taste nor eye. But he would certainly have preferred wine to either of them, could his native country have afforded him so agreeable a liquor. We may learn from thence, that every thing, which is agreeable to the senses, is also in some measure agreeable to the fancy, and conveys to the thought an image of that satisfaction, which it gives by its real application to the bodily organs.
It's clear that the first principle, which is the reflection on pleasing things, has a bigger impact than we might initially think. We rarely think about what is beautiful or ugly, pleasing or unpleasant, without feeling some kind of pleasure or discomfort; and although these feelings don’t often show up in our everyday lazy thought processes, they're easy to spot in reading or conversation. Witty people always steer the conversation toward topics that entertain the imagination; and poets only present things that are of a similar nature. Mr. Philips chose CYDER as the subject of an excellent poem. Beer wouldn't have been as fitting, since it’s not as pleasing to the taste or the eye. But he would definitely have preferred wine over both, if his home country had provided such a delightful drink. From this, we can learn that everything that pleases the senses is also somewhat pleasing to the mind and gives a mental image of the satisfaction it provides through its real effect on our physical senses.
But though these reasons may induce us to comprehend this delicacy of the imagination among the causes of the respect, which we pay the rich and powerful, there are many other reasons, that may keep us from regarding it as the sole or principal. For as the ideas of pleasure can have an influence only by means of their vivacity, which makes them approach impressions, it is most natural those ideas should have that influence, which are favoured by most circumstances, and have a natural tendency to become strong and lively; such as our ideas of the passions and sensations of any human creature. Every human creature resembles ourselves, and by that means has an advantage above any other object, in operating on the imagination.
But even though these reasons might lead us to understand this sensitivity of the imagination as one of the reasons we respect the wealthy and powerful, there are many other reasons that prevent us from seeing it as the only or primary one. Since the ideas of pleasure can only have an effect through their intensity, which makes them similar to impressions, it’s only natural that those ideas would have that effect when they are supported by most circumstances and have a natural tendency to become strong and vivid; like our ideas about the passions and sensations of any human being. Every human being is like us, and for that reason, has an advantage over anything else in influencing our imagination.
Besides, if we consider the nature of that faculty, and the great influence which all relations have upon it, we shall easily be persuaded, that however the ideas of the pleasant wines, music, or gardens, which the rich man enjoys, may become lively and agreeable, the fancy will not confine itself to them, but will carry its view to the related objects; and in particular, to the person, who possesses them. And this is the more natural, that the pleasant idea or image produces here a passion towards the person, by means of his relation to the object; so that it is unavoidable but he must enter into the original conception, since he makes the object of the derivative passion: But if he enters into the original conception, and is considered as enjoying these agreeable objects, it is sympathy, which is properly the cause of the affection; and the third principle is more powerful and universal than the first.
Also, if we think about the nature of that ability and how much all relationships affect it, we can easily see that while the ideas of fine wines, music, or gardens enjoyed by a wealthy person may seem lively and enjoyable, the imagination won't just focus on them; it will look at the related things, especially the person who owns them. This is even more natural since the pleasant idea or image creates a feeling toward the person because of their connection to the object. Therefore, it’s unavoidable that the person becomes part of the original idea since they are the focus of the resulting feeling. But if they become part of the original idea and are seen as enjoying these delightful things, it is sympathy that truly causes the affection; and this third factor is stronger and more universal than the first.
Add to this, that riches and power alone, even though unemployed, naturally cause esteem and respect: And consequently these passions arise not from the idea of any beautiful or agreeable objects. It is true; money implies a kind of representation of such objects, by the power it affords of obtaining them; and for that reason may still be esteemed proper to convey those agreeable images, which may give rise to the passion. But as this prospect is very distant, it is more natural for us to take a contiguous object, viz, the satisfaction, which this power affords the person, who is possest of it. And of this we shall be farther satisfyed, if we consider, that riches represent the goods of life, only by means of the will; which employs them; and therefore imply in their very nature an idea of the person, and cannot be considered without a kind of sympathy with his sensations and enjoyments.
In addition, wealth and power alone, even when not in use, naturally command esteem and respect. As a result, these feelings don't stem from any beautiful or pleasing objects. It's true that money suggests a way to access such objects because of the power it provides to obtain them; for this reason, it might still be seen as a suitable means to convey those pleasing images that can inspire passion. However, since this prospect is quite distant, it makes more sense for us to focus on the immediate object, which is the satisfaction that this power brings to the person who possesses it. We can understand this better if we consider that wealth symbolizes life's goods only through the will that uses them, and therefore inherently includes an idea of the person, along with a kind of sympathy for their feelings and pleasures.
This we may confirm by a reflection, which to some will, perhaps, appear too subtile and refined. I have already observed, that power, as distinguished from its exercise, has either no meaning at all, or is nothing but a possibility or probability of existence; by which any object approaches to reality, and has a sensible influence on the mind. I have also observed, that this approach, by an illusion of the fancy, appears much greater, when we ourselves are possest of the power, than when it is enjoyed by another; and that in the former case the objects seem to touch upon the very verge of reality, and convey almost an equal satisfaction, as if actually in our possession. Now I assert, that where we esteem a person upon account of his riches, we must enter into this sentiment of the proprietor, and that without such a sympathy the idea of the agreeable objects, which they give him the power to produce, would have but a feeble influence upon us. An avaricious man is respected for his money, though he scarce is possest of a power; that is, there scarce is a probability or even possibility of his employing it in the acquisition of the pleasures and conveniences of life. To himself alone this power seems perfect and entire; and therefore we must receive his sentiments by sympathy, before we can have a strong intense idea of these enjoyments, or esteem him upon account of them.
We can confirm this by considering a reflection that might seem too subtle and overly refined to some. I've already mentioned that power, distinct from its use, either has no meaning or is merely a possibility or probability of existence. This is how any object moves closer to reality and has a tangible impact on the mind. I've also noted that this feeling of closeness, due to an illusion of the imagination, appears much stronger when we possess the power ourselves than when it belongs to someone else. In the former case, the objects seem to be on the brink of reality and offer almost the same satisfaction as if we actually owned them. Now, I argue that when we admire someone for their wealth, we have to connect with the feelings of the owner. Without this shared feeling, the idea of the enjoyable things they can create with their wealth would have a weak influence on us. A greedy person might be respected for their money, even if they hardly have the ability to use it to gain the pleasures and comforts of life. To them, that power seems complete and whole; thus, we need to resonate with their feelings before we can have a strong, vivid idea of those pleasures or value them because of it.
Thus we have found, that the first principle, viz, the agreeable idea of those objects, which riches afford the enjoyment of; resolves itself in a great measure into the third, and becomes a sympathy with the person we esteem or love. Let us now examine the second principle, viz, the agreeable expectation of advantage, and see what force we may justly attribute to it.
Thus, we've discovered that the first principle, namely the pleasant idea of the objects that wealth allows us to enjoy, largely boils down to the third principle and turns into a connection with the person we admire or love. Now, let's look into the second principle, which is the pleasant expectation of benefit, and see what significance we can reasonably assign to it.
It is obvious, that though riches and authority undoubtedly give their owner a power of doing us service, yet this power is not to be considered as on the same footing with that, which they afford him, of pleasing himself, and satisfying his own appetites. Self-love approaches the power and exercise very near each other in the latter case; but in order to produce a similar effect in the former, we must suppose a friendship and good-will to be conjoined with the riches. Without that circumstance it is difficult to conceive on what we can found our hope of advantage from the riches of others, though there is nothing more certain, than that we naturally esteem and respect the rich, even before we discover in them any such favourable disposition towards us.
It's clear that while wealth and power definitely give their owner the ability to help us, that ability shouldn’t be seen on the same level as the pleasure and satisfaction they gain from fulfilling their own desires. In the case of self-love, the power and its use are very close together; however, for us to benefit similarly from someone else's wealth, we need to assume there’s friendship and goodwill linked to that wealth. Without that aspect, it's hard to see how we can expect to gain from others' riches, even though it's certain that we naturally admire and respect wealthy people, often before we even notice any positive feelings they have towards us.
But I carry this farther, and observe, not only that we respect the rich and powerful, where they shew no inclination to serve us, but also when we lie so much out of the sphere of their activity, that they cannot even be supposed to be endowed with that power. Prisoners of war are always treated with a respect suitable to their condition; and it is certain riches go very far towards fixing the condition of any person. If birth and quality enter for a share, this still affords us an argument of the same kind. For what is it we call a man of birth, but one who is descended from a long succession of rich and powerful ancestors, and who acquires our esteem by his relation to persons whom we esteem? His ancestors, therefore, though dead, are respected, in some measure, on account of their riches, and consequently without any kind of expectation.
But I take this further and notice that we respect the rich and powerful, even when they show no desire to help us, and also when we are so far removed from their sphere of influence that it’s hard to imagine they possess that power. Prisoners of war are always treated with respect appropriate to their situation; and it’s clear that wealth plays a significant role in determining a person's status. If family background and social standing also factor in, this still supports the same argument. Because when we refer to a person of noble birth, we're talking about someone descended from a long line of wealthy and powerful ancestors, and they gain our respect by their connection to people we admire. Their ancestors, even though they are gone, are still honored to some extent because of their wealth, and this happens without any expectation of something in return.
But not to go so far as prisoners of war and the dead to find instances of this disinterested esteem for riches, let us observe with a little attention those phaenomena that occur to us in common life and conversation. A man, who is himself of a competent fortune, upon coming into a company of strangers, naturally treats them with different degrees of respect and deference, as he is informed of their different fortunes and conditions; though it is impossible he can ever propose, and perhaps would not accept of any advantage from them. A traveller is always admitted into company, and meets with civility, in proportion as his train and equipage speak him a man of great or moderate fortune. In short, the different ranks of men are, in a great measure, regulated by riches, and that with regard to superiors as well as inferiors, strangers as well as acquaintance.
But without going as far as discussing prisoners of war or the dead to find examples of this selfless admiration for wealth, let’s take a closer look at the phenomena we encounter in daily life and conversation. A man who has a decent fortune will naturally show varying levels of respect and courtesy to strangers based on what he learns about their different wealth and status, even though he likely has no intention of gaining anything from them and perhaps wouldn’t accept any favors. A traveler is always welcomed into social circles and treated with politeness, depending on whether his entourage and means suggest he’s wealthy or moderately well-off. In short, the different social ranks among people are largely determined by wealth, affecting both those above and below him, as well as strangers and acquaintances alike.
There is, indeed, an answer to these arguments, drawn from the influence of general rules. It may be pretended, that being accustomed to expect succour and protection from the rich and powerful, and to esteem them upon that account, we extend the same sentiments to those, who resemble them in their fortune, but from whom we can never hope for any advantage. The general rule still prevails, and by giving a bent to the imagination draws along the passion, in the same manner as if its proper object were real and existent.
There is, in fact, an answer to these arguments, based on the influence of general rules. It might be suggested that because we are used to expecting help and protection from the rich and powerful, and we respect them for that reason, we project those same feelings onto others who are similar in wealth, even though we can't hope to gain anything from them. The general rule still holds, and by shaping our imagination, it influences our emotions, just as if the actual object were real and present.
But that this principle does not here take place, will easily appear, if we consider, that in order to establish a general rule, and extend it beyond its proper bounds, there is required a certain uniformity in our experience, and a great superiority of those instances, which are conformable to the rule, above the contrary. But here the case is quite otherwise. Of a hundred men of credit and fortune I meet with, there is not, perhaps, one from whom I can expect advantage; so that it is impossible any custom can ever prevail in the present case.
But it’s clear that this principle doesn’t apply here, if we consider that establishing a general rule and extending it beyond its rightful limits requires a certain consistency in our experiences and a significant number of instances that support the rule compared to those that don’t. However, in this situation, it’s quite the opposite. Out of a hundred reputable and wealthy men I encounter, there’s hardly anyone I can expect to gain anything from; therefore, it’s impossible for any custom to take hold in this case.
Upon the whole, there remains nothing, which can give us an esteem for power and riches, and a contempt for meanness and poverty, except the principle of sympathy, by which we enter into the sentiments of the rich and poor, and partake of their pleasure and uneasiness. Riches give satisfaction to their possessor; and this satisfaction is conveyed to the beholder by the imagination, which produces an idea resembling the original impression in force and vivacity. This agreeable idea or impression is connected with love, which is an agreeable passion. It proceeds from a thinking conscious being, which is the very object of love. From this relation of impressions, and identity of ideas, the passion arises, according to my hypothesis.
Overall, there's nothing that earns our respect for power and wealth, and our disdain for lowliness and poverty, except the principle of sympathy. This principle allows us to understand the feelings of both the rich and the poor, sharing in their joys and frustrations. Wealth provides satisfaction to its owner, and this satisfaction is communicated to the observer through imagination, creating a mental image that matches the original experience in intensity and liveliness. This pleasant idea or impression is linked to love, which is a positive feeling. It comes from a conscious thinking being, who is the very focus of love. From this connection of impressions and similarity of ideas, the passion arises, according to my theory.
The best method of reconciling us to this opinion is to take a general survey of the universe, and observe the force of sympathy through the whole animal creation, and the easy communication of sentiments from one thinking being to another. In all creatures, that prey not upon others, and are not agitated with violent passions, there appears a remarkable desire of company, which associates them together, without any advantages they can ever propose to reap from their union. This is still more conspicuous in man, as being the creature of the universe, who has the most ardent desire of society, and is fitted for it by the most advantages. We can form no wish, which has not a reference to society. A perfect solitude is, perhaps, the greatest punishment we can suffer. Every pleasure languishes when enjoyed a-part from company, and every pain becomes more cruel and intolerable. Whatever other passions we may be actuated by; pride, ambition, avarice, curiosity, revenge or lust; the soul or animating principle of them all is sympathy; nor would they have any force, were we to abstract entirely from the thoughts and sentiments of others. Let all the powers and elements of nature conspire to serve and obey one man: Let the sun rise and set at his command: The sea and rivers roll as he pleases, and the earth furnish spontaneously whatever may be useful or agreeable to him: He will still be miserable, till you give him some one person at least, with whom he may share his happiness, and whose esteem and friendship he may enjoy.
The best way to reconcile ourselves to this idea is to take a broad look at the universe and notice the power of sympathy throughout the entire animal kingdom, and how easily feelings can be shared among thinking beings. In all creatures that don’t prey on others and aren’t driven by intense emotions, there’s a notable desire for companionship that brings them together without any real benefits they can gain from their association. This is even more evident in humans, as the creatures of the universe with the strongest need for social connection, equipped for it with many advantages. We can’t make a single wish that doesn’t relate to society. Perfect solitude is possibly the worst punishment we can endure. Every joy fades when experienced alone, and every suffering becomes more painful and unbearable. Regardless of the other desires we may feel—pride, ambition, greed, curiosity, revenge, or lust—the core motivation behind them all is sympathy; none would have any power if we completely detached ourselves from the thoughts and feelings of others. Let all the forces and elements of nature work together to serve and obey one man; let the sun rise and set at his command, let the seas and rivers flow at his will, and let the earth provide anything he finds useful or enjoyable—it wouldn’t matter. He would still be unhappy unless he has at least one person to share his happiness with and whose respect and friendship he can enjoy.
This conclusion from a general view of human nature, we may confirm by particular instances, wherein the force of sympathy is very remarkable. Most kinds of beauty are derived from this origin; and though our first object be some senseless inanimate piece of matter, it is seldom we rest there, and carry not our view to its influence on sensible and rational creatures. A man, who shews us any house or building, takes particular care among other things to point out the convenience of the apartments, the advantages of their situation, and the little room lost in the stairs, antichambers and passages; and indeed it is evident, the chief part of the beauty consists in these particulars. The observation of convenience gives pleasure, since convenience is a beauty. But after what manner does it give pleasure? It is certain our own interest is not in the least concerned; and as this is a beauty of interest, not of form, so to speak, it must delight us merely by communication, and by our sympathizing with the proprietor of the lodging. We enter into his interest by the force of imagination, and feel the same satisfaction, that the objects naturally occasion in him.
This conclusion about human nature can be confirmed through specific examples where the power of sympathy is very striking. Most forms of beauty come from this source, and even though our initial focus might be on an inanimate object, we rarely stop there; we usually think about how it affects living, rational beings. When someone shows us a house or building, they make an effort to highlight things like the layout of the rooms, the benefits of the location, and the minimal space taken up by the stairs, hallways, and passages. In fact, it's clear that much of the beauty comes from these details. Noticing convenience brings us pleasure since convenience is a form of beauty. But how does it bring us pleasure? It's clear that our own interest isn't involved at all; and since this beauty is about practicality rather than appearance, it must please us through the experience of sharing in the happiness of the owner. We connect with their interest through our imagination and feel the same satisfaction that the features naturally evoke in them.
This observation extends to tables, chairs, scritoires, chimneys, coaches, sadles, ploughs, and indeed to every work of art; it being an universal rule, that their beauty is chiefly derived from their utility, and from their fitness for that purpose, to which they are destined. But this is an advantage, that concerns only the owner, nor is there any thing but sympathy, which can interest the spectator.
This observation applies to tables, chairs, desks, chimneys, coaches, saddles, plows, and really to every piece of art; it's a universal rule that their beauty mainly comes from their usefulness and how well they serve their intended purpose. However, this is a benefit that only affects the owner, and there’s nothing but empathy that can connect with the spectator.
It is evident, that nothing renders a field more agreeable than its fertility, and that scarce any advantages of ornament or situation will be able to equal this beauty. It is the same case with particular trees and plants, as with the field on which they grow. I know not but a plain, overgrown with furze and broom, may be, in itself, as beautiful as a hill covered with vines or olive-trees; though it will never appear so to one, who is acquainted with the value of each. But this is a beauty merely of imagination, and has no foundation in what appears to the senses. Fertility and value have a plain reference to use; and that to riches, joy, and plenty; in which though we have no hope of partaking, yet we enter into them by the vivacity of the fancy, and share them, in some measure, with the proprietor.
It’s clear that nothing makes a field more appealing than its fertility, and hardly any decorative features or locations can match this beauty. The same goes for specific trees and plants, just like the field they grow in. A flat area overrun with gorse and broom can be just as beautiful as a hill covered with vines or olive trees; however, it may not seem that way to someone who understands the value of each. But this is a beauty that exists only in our imagination and doesn’t have a basis in sensory perception. Fertility and value are directly tied to utility, which links to wealth, joy, and abundance; even if we have no hope of experiencing them, we engage with them through the vividness of our imagination and share them, to some extent, with the owner.
There is no rule in painting more reasonable than that of ballancing the figures, and placing them with the greatest exactness on their proper centers of gravity. A figure, which is not justly ballanced, is disagreeable; and that because it conveys the ideas of its fall, of harm, and of pain: Which ideas are painful, when by sympathy they acquire any degree of force and vivacity.
There’s no rule in painting more logical than balancing the figures and placing them accurately on their correct centers of gravity. A figure that isn’t balanced properly feels off and unpleasant because it suggests falling, danger, and suffering. These thoughts are discomforting, especially when they evoke strong emotions.
Add to this, that the principal part of personal beauty is an air of health and vigour, and such a construction of members as promises strength and activity. This idea of beauty cannot be accounted for but by sympathy.
Add to this that the main aspect of personal beauty is a sense of health and vitality, along with a physical appearance that suggests strength and energy. This concept of beauty can only be understood through empathy.
In general we may remark, that the minds of men are mirrors to one another, not only because they reflect each others emotions, but also because those rays of passions, sentiments and opinions may be often reverberated, and may decay away by insensible degrees. Thus the pleasure, which a rich man receives from his possessions, being thrown upon the beholder, causes a pleasure and esteem; which sentiments again, being perceived and sympathized with, encrease the pleasure of the possessor; and being once more reflected, become a new foundation for pleasure and esteem in the beholder. There is certainly an original satisfaction in riches derived from that power, which they bestow, of enjoying all the pleasures of life; and as this is their very nature and essence, it must be the first source of all the passions, which arise from them. One of the most considerable of these passions is that of love or esteem in others, which therefore proceeds from a sympathy with the pleasure of the possessor. But the possessor has also a secondary satisfaction in riches arising from the love and esteem he acquires by them, and this satisfaction is nothing but a second reflexion of that original pleasure, which proceeded from himself. This secondary satisfaction or vanity becomes one of the principal recommendations of riches, and is the chief reason, why we either desire them for ourselves, or esteem them in others. Here then is a third rebound of the original pleasure; after which it is difficult to distinguish the images and reflexions, by reason of their faintness and confusion.
In general, we can say that people's minds act like mirrors to each other, not just because they reflect each other's emotions, but also because those feelings, sentiments, and opinions can echo back and gradually fade away. For example, the pleasure a wealthy person derives from their possessions is reflected onto others, creating pleasure and admiration in them; these feelings, once noticed and shared, increase the pleasure of the wealthy person, and are reflected again, forming a new basis for pleasure and admiration in the observer. There is undeniably a fundamental satisfaction in wealth that comes from the power it provides to enjoy all of life's pleasures; since this is its very nature, it must be the primary source of all the feelings that arise from it. One significant passion arising from this is the love or esteem from others, which comes from sharing in the pleasure of the wealthy individual. However, the wealthy person also experiences a secondary satisfaction from the love and esteem they gain through their wealth, which is merely a new reflection of the original pleasure they felt. This secondary satisfaction or vanity becomes one of the main appeals of wealth and is the main reason we desire it for ourselves or admire it in others. Thus, we see a third reflection of the original pleasure; after this, it becomes hard to tell apart the different images and reflections due to their vagueness and confusion.
SECT. VI OF BENEVOLENCE AND ANGER
Ideas may be compared to the extension and solidity of matter, and impressions, especially reflective ones, to colours, tastes, smells and other sensible qualities. Ideas never admit of a total union, but are endowed with a kind of impenetrability, by which they exclude each other, and are capable of forming a compound by their conjunction, not by their mixture. On the other hand, impressions and passions are susceptible of an entire union; and like colours, may be blended so perfectly together, that each of them may lose itself, and contribute only to vary that uniform impression, which arises from the whole. Some of the most curious phaenomena of the human mind are derived from this property of the passions.
Ideas can be compared to the size and solidity of physical objects, while impressions, especially reflective ones, are like colors, tastes, smells, and other sensory qualities. Ideas can never completely unite, as they have a sort of impenetrability that prevents them from merging; instead, they can combine to form a compound through their conjunction, not through mixing. In contrast, impressions and emotions can completely unite and, like colors, can blend so seamlessly that each one may lose its individuality and only serve to change the overall impression created by the whole. Some of the most intriguing phenomena of the human mind come from this characteristic of emotions.
In examining those ingredients, which are capable of uniting with love and hatred, I begin to be sensible, in some measure, of a misfortune, that has attended every system of philosophy, with which the world has been yet acquainted. It is commonly found, that in accounting for the operations of nature by any particular hypothesis; among a number of experiments, that quadrate exactly with the principles we would endeavour to establish; there is always some phænomenon, which is more stubborn, and will not so easily bend to our purpose. We need not be surprized, that this should happen in natural philosophy. The essence and composition of external bodies are so obscure, that we must necessarily, in our reasonings, or rather conjectures concerning them, involve ourselves in contradictions and absurdities. But as the perceptions of the mind are perfectly known, and I have used all imaginable caution in forming conclusions concerning them, I have always hoped to keep clear of those contradictions, which have attended every other system. Accordingly the difficulty, which I have at present in my eye, is nowise contrary to my system; but only departs a little from that simplicity, which has been hitherto its principal force and beauty.
In looking at those factors that can combine with love and hatred, I start to realize, to some extent, a misfortune that has affected every philosophy the world has known. It's often the case that when trying to explain natural phenomena through a specific hypothesis, among many experiments that align perfectly with the principles we aim to establish, there's always some phenomenon that is more stubborn and doesn't easily conform to our intentions. We shouldn't be surprised that this happens in natural philosophy. The essence and makeup of external objects are so unclear that we inevitably find ourselves in contradictions and absurdities when we try to reason or guess about them. However, since the perceptions of the mind are well understood, and I've taken every possible precaution in drawing conclusions about them, I've always hoped to avoid the contradictions that have plagued other systems. Therefore, the challenge I'm facing now doesn't contradict my system; it just slightly deviates from the simplicity that has been its main strength and appeal.
The passions of love and hatred are always followed by, or rather conjoined with benevolence and anger. It is this conjunction, which chiefly distinguishes these affections from pride and humility. For pride and humility are pure emotions in the soul, unattended with any desire, and not immediately exciting us to action. But love and hatred are not compleated within themselves, nor rest in that emotion, which they produce, but carry the mind to something farther. Love is always followed by a desire of the happiness of the person beloved, and an aversion to his misery: As hatred produces a desire of the misery and an aversion to the happiness of the person hated. So remarkable a difference betwixt these two sets of passions of pride and humility, love and hatred, which in so many other particulars correspond to each other, merits our attention.
The feelings of love and hate are always accompanied by, or rather linked to, kindness and anger. It is this connection that mainly sets these feelings apart from pride and humility. Pride and humility are pure emotions in the soul, not tied to any desire, and don’t immediately push us to act. But love and hate are not complete within themselves, nor do they stay in the emotion they generate; instead, they drive the mind to something more. Love always comes with a desire for the happiness of the person loved and a dislike for their suffering. In contrast, hatred creates a wish for the misery and a dislike for the happiness of the person hated. This notable difference between these two groups of feelings—pride and humility, love and hate—deserves our attention, especially since they correspond in many other ways.
The conjunction of this desire and aversion with love and hatred may be accounted for by two different hypotheses. The first is, that love and hatred have not only a cause, which excites them, viz, pleasure and pain; and an object, to which they are directed, viz, a person or thinking being; but likewise an end, which they endeavour to attain, viz, the happiness or misery of the person beloved or hated; all which views, mixing together, make only one passion. According to this system, love is nothing but the desire of happiness to another person, and hatred that of misery. The desire and aversion constitute the very nature of love and hatred. They are not only inseparable but the same.
The combination of desire and aversion with love and hatred can be explained by two different theories. The first is that love and hatred have not just a trigger that stirs them, like pleasure and pain, and a target they are aimed at, like a person or a thinking being, but also a goal they strive to achieve, which is either the happiness or misery of the person they love or hate. All these aspects blend together to form a single emotion. According to this view, love is simply the desire for someone else's happiness, while hatred is the desire for their misery. Desire and aversion are the core essence of love and hatred. They are not just linked; they are essentially the same.
But this is evidently contrary to experience. For though it is certain we never love any person without desiring his happiness, nor hate any without wishing his misery, yet these desires arise only upon the ideas of the happiness or misery of our friend or enemy being presented by the imagination, and are not absolutely essential to love and hatred. They are the most obvious and natural sentiments of these affections, but not the only ones. The passions may express themselves in a hundred ways, and may subsist a considerable time, without our reflecting on the happiness or misery of their objects; which clearly proves, that these desires are not the same with love and hatred, nor make any essential part of them.
But this clearly goes against experience. While it’s true that we never love someone without wanting them to be happy, nor hate someone without wishing them to suffer, these feelings only arise when our imagination brings up the ideas of our friend or enemy's happiness or misery. They are not absolutely necessary for love and hate. These feelings are the most obvious and natural expressions of these emotions, but they're not the only ones. Our feelings can show themselves in many ways and can last a significant amount of time without us thinking about the happiness or misery of the person we feel this way about, which clearly shows that these desires are not the same as love and hate, nor are they an essential part of them.
We may, therefore, infer, that benevolence and anger are passions different from love and hatred, and only conjoined with them, by the original constitution of the mind. As nature has given to the body certain appetites and inclinations, which she encreases, diminishes, or changes according to the situation of the fluids or solids; she has proceeded in the same manner with the mind. According as we are possessed with love or hatred, the correspondent desire of the happiness or misery of the person, who is the object of these passions, arises in the mind, and varies with each variation of these opposite passions. This order of things, abstractedly considered, is not necessary. Love and hatred might have been unattended with any such desires, or their particular connexion might have been entirely reversed. If nature had so pleased, love might have had the same effect as hatred, and hatred as love. I see no contradiction in supposing a desire of producing misery annexed to love, and of happiness to hatred. If the sensation of the passion and desire be opposite, nature could have altered the sensation without altering the tendency of the desire, and by that means made them compatible with each other.
We can therefore conclude that benevolence and anger are emotions distinct from love and hatred, and they're only connected to them due to the way our minds are originally structured. Just as nature has given the body certain needs and tendencies that she increases, decreases, or changes based on the state of the fluids or solids; she has done the same with the mind. Depending on whether we feel love or hatred, a corresponding desire for the happiness or misery of the person who is the focus of these emotions arises in our minds, and this changes with shifts in these opposing feelings. This arrangement, considered in an abstract way, isn't necessary. Love and hatred could exist without any related desires, or their specific connections could entirely be reversed. If nature had chosen, love could have the same effects as hatred, and vice versa. I see no contradiction in imagining a desire to cause misery linked to love, and a desire for happiness connected to hatred. If the emotions and desires are opposites, nature could have changed the emotions without affecting the direction of the desire, thus making them compatible with each other.
SECT. VII OF COMPASSION
But though the desire of the happiness or misery of others, according to the love or hatred we bear them, be an arbitrary and original instinct implanted in our nature, we find it may be counterfeited on many occasions, and may arise from secondary principles. Pity is a concern for, and malice a joy in the misery of others, without any friendship or enmity to occasion this concern or joy. We pity even strangers, and such as are perfectly indifferent to us: And if our ill-will to another proceed from any harm or injury, it is not, properly speaking, malice, but revenge. But if we examine these affections of pity and malice we shall find them to be secondary ones, arising from original affections, which are varied by some particular turn of thought and imagination.
But even though our desire for the happiness or suffering of others—based on the love or hate we feel for them—seems to be an instinct built into our nature, we can see that it can be faked on many occasions and can come from secondary principles. Pity is a concern for others, while malice is a sense of joy in the suffering of others, without any friendship or hatred causing this concern or joy. We feel pity for even strangers and people who don’t really matter to us. If our bad feelings towards someone come from any harm or injury, it’s not really malice but rather revenge. However, if we look closely at these feelings of pity and malice, we’ll find that they are secondary emotions that stem from original feelings, influenced by a specific way of thinking and imagining.
It will be easy to explain the passion of pity, from the precedent reasoning concerning sympathy. We have a lively idea of every thing related to us. All human creatures are related to us by resemblance. Their persons, therefore, their interests, their passions, their pains and pleasures must strike upon us in a lively manner, and produce an emotion similar to the original one; since a lively idea is easily converted into an impression. If this be true in general, it must be more so of affliction and sorrow. These have always a stronger and more lasting influence than any pleasure or enjoyment.
It’s easy to explain the passion for pity based on the earlier reasoning about sympathy. We have a vivid understanding of everything connected to us. All human beings are related to us through similarity. Their identities, interests, passions, pains, and pleasures affect us deeply, creating an emotion similar to the original feeling; after all, a vivid idea can quickly turn into a strong impression. If this is generally true, it holds even more for grief and sorrow. These emotions always have a stronger and more lasting impact than any pleasure or enjoyment.
A spectator of a tragedy passes through a long train of grief, terror, indignation, and other affections, which the poet represents in the persons he introduces. As many tragedies end happily, and no excellent one can be composed without some reverses of fortune, the spectator must sympathize with all these changes, and receive the fictitious joy as well as every other passion. Unless, therefore, it be asserted, that every distinct passion is communicated by a distinct original quality, and is not derived from the general principle of sympathy above-explained, it must be allowed, that all of them arise from that principle. To except any one in particular must appear highly unreasonable. As they are all first present in the mind of one person, and afterwards appear in the mind of another; and as the manner of their appearance, first as an idea, then as an impression, is in every case the same, the transition must arise from the same principle. I am at least sure, that this method of reasoning would be considered as certain, either in natural philosophy or common life.
A person watching a tragedy goes through a long series of feelings like grief, fear, anger, and others that the writer portrays through the characters he includes. Since many tragedies end on a positive note, and a truly great one can’t be made without some ups and downs, the viewer has to connect with all these emotional shifts and accept the fictional joy along with every other feeling. Unless it’s claimed that every specific feeling comes from a different original quality and isn’t based on the general idea of sympathy mentioned earlier, it has to be acknowledged that all these feelings come from that principle. To exclude any specific feeling would seem quite unreasonable. Since they all first exist in one person’s mind and then show up in another’s, and because the way they appear—first as an idea and then as a sensation—is the same in every case, the change must come from the same principle. I’m at least confident that this way of thinking would be seen as valid, whether in science or everyday life.
Add to this, that pity depends, in a great measure, on the contiguity, and even sight of the object; which is a proof, that it is derived from the imagination. Not to mention that women and children are most subject to pity, as being most guided by that faculty. The same infirmity, which makes them faint at the sight of a naked sword, though in the hands of their best friend, makes them pity extremely those, whom they find in any grief or affliction. Those philosophers, who derive this passion from I know not what subtile reflections on the instability of fortune, and our being liable to the same miseries we behold, will find this observation contrary to them among a great many others, which it were easy to produce.
Add to this that pity largely depends on the proximity and even the sight of the person in need, which shows it comes from our imagination. Not to mention, women and children are more likely to feel pity since they are more influenced by that sense. The same vulnerability that makes them faint at the sight of a sword, even if it’s in the hands of a close friend, makes them feel deep pity for anyone they see in pain or distress. Those philosophers who explain this emotion through elaborate thoughts about the unpredictability of fortune and our susceptibility to the same suffering we witness will find this observation contradicts many of their points, of which there are plenty to choose from.
There remains only to take notice of a pretty remarkable phænomenon of this passion; which is, that the communicated passion of sympathy sometimes acquires strength from the weakness of its original, and even arises by a transition from affections, which have no existence. Thus when a person obtains any honourable office, or inherits a great fortune, we are always the more rejoiced for his prosperity, the less sense he seems to have of it, and the greater equanimity and indifference he shews in its enjoyment. In like manner a man, who is not dejected by misfortunes, is the more lamented on account of his patience; and if that virtue extends so far as utterly to remove all sense of uneasiness, it still farther encreases our compassion. When a person of merit falls into what is vulgarly esteemed a great misfortune, we form a notion of his condition; and carrying our fancy from the cause to the usual effect, first conceive a lively idea of his sorrow, and then feel an impression of it, entirely over-looking that greatness of mind, which elevates him above such emotions, or only considering it so far as to encrease our admiration, love and tenderness for him. We find from experience, that such a degree of passion is usually connected with such a misfortune; and though there be an exception in the present case, yet the imagination is affected by the general rule, and makes us conceive a lively idea of the passion, or rather feel the passion itself, in the same manner, as if the person were really actuated by it. From the same principles we blush for the conduct of those, who behave themselves foolishly before us; and that though they shew no sense of shame, nor seem in the least conscious of their folly. All this proceeds from sympathy; but it is of a partial kind, and views its objects only on one side, without considering the other, which has a contrary effect, and would entirely destroy that emotion, which arises from the first appearance.
There’s one more thing to note about a pretty remarkable phenomenon of this passion: the communicated passion of sympathy sometimes gets stronger from the weakness of its source and can even arise from feelings that don’t actually exist. For example, when someone gets a prestigious job or inherits a large fortune, we are often happier about their success the less they seem to appreciate it and the more calm and indifferent they are while enjoying it. Similarly, when someone isn’t downcast by their misfortunes, we feel more pity for them because of their patience; and if that virtue goes so far as to completely remove any sense of distress, it even increases our compassion further. When a deserving person experiences what is commonly seen as a significant misfortune, we form an idea of their situation. We then take our thoughts from the cause to the usual effect, first imagining their sorrow vividly, and then feeling an echo of it, totally overlooking the greatness of mind that lifts them above such feelings, or only considering it enough to heighten our admiration, love, and tenderness for them. From experience, we know that such a level of passion usually accompanies such misfortune; and although there may be exceptions in specific cases, our imagination is influenced by the general rule, leading us to vividly conceive or even feel that passion as if the person were truly feeling it. By the same principles, we feel embarrassed for those who behave foolishly in front of us, even if they show no signs of shame or awareness of their folly. All this comes from sympathy; but it’s a selective kind that only looks at one side of its object, ignoring the other side, which has an opposite effect and would completely eliminate the emotion that arises from the initial impression.
We have also instances, wherein an indifference and insensibility under misfortune encreases our concern for the misfortunate, even though the indifference proceed not from any virtue and magnanimity. It is an aggravation of a murder, that it was committed upon persons asleep and in perfect security; as historians readily observe of any infant prince, who is captive in the hands of his enemies, that he is the more worthy of compassion the less sensible he is of his miserable condition. As we ourselves are here acquainted with the wretched situation of the person, it gives us a lively idea and sensation of sorrow, which is the passion that generally attends it; and this idea becomes still more lively, and the sensation more violent by a contrast with that security and indifference, which we observe in the person himself. A contrast of any kind never fails to affect the imagination, especially when presented by the subject; and it is on the imagination that pity entirely depends.[6]
We also see cases where being indifferent and unaffected by misfortune actually makes us more concerned for those who are suffering, even if that indifference doesn't come from any kind of virtue or nobility. It's particularly cruel when a murder is committed against someone who is asleep and completely safe; historians note that a young prince held captive by his enemies is all the more deserving of our sympathy the less aware he is of his miserable situation. Since we are aware of the terrible circumstances surrounding the person, it gives us a strong feeling of sadness, which is a common response to such situations. This feeling becomes even stronger and more intense when we contrast it with the security and indifference we see in the person themselves. Any kind of contrast tends to stir the imagination, especially when it's illustrated by the subject at hand; and it’s the imagination that drives our ability to feel pity.[6]
[6] To prevent all ambiguity, I must observe, that where I oppose the imagination to the memory, I mean in general the faculty that presents our fainter ideas. In all other places, and particularly when it is opposed to the understanding, I understand the same faculty, excluding only our demonstrative and probable reasonings.
[6] To avoid any confusion, I want to clarify that when I contrast imagination with memory, I'm referring to the general ability that brings forth our subtler thoughts. In all other instances, especially when it's compared to understanding, I'm talking about the same ability, but I exclude our conclusive and likely reasoning.
SECT. VIII OF MALICE AND ENVY
We must now proceed to account for the passion of malice, which imitates the effects of hatred, as pity does those of love; and gives us a joy in the sufferings and miseries of others, without any offence or injury on their part.
We now need to explain the feeling of malice, which resembles the effects of hatred, just as pity resembles those of love; it gives us pleasure in the suffering and hardships of others, without any wrongdoing or harm on their part.
So little are men governed by reason in their sentiments and opinions, that they always judge more of objects by comparison than from their intrinsic worth and value. When the mind considers, or is accustomed to, any degree of perfection, whatever falls short of it, though really esteemable, has notwithstanding the same effect upon the passions; as what is defective and ill. This is an original quality of the soul, and similar to what we have every day experience of in our bodies. Let a man heat one hand and cool the other; the same water will, at the same time, seem both hot and cold, according to the disposition of the different organs. A small degree of any quality, succeeding a greater, produces the same sensation, as if less than it really is, and even sometimes as the opposite quality. Any gentle pain, that follows a violent one, seems as nothing, or rather becomes a pleasure; as on the other hand a violent pain, succeeding a gentle one, is doubly grievous and uneasy.
People are so rarely guided by reason in their feelings and opinions that they tend to judge things more by comparison than by their actual worth. When the mind thinks about, or gets used to, any level of perfection, anything that falls short of it, even if it’s truly admirable, has the same effect on our emotions as something that is flawed or poor. This is an inherent quality of the mind, similar to what we experience in our bodies every day. If a person warms one hand and cools the other, the same water will feel both hot and cold at the same time, depending on the condition of each hand. A small amount of any quality that follows a greater amount creates the same sensation, as if it were less than it actually is, and sometimes even as if it were the opposite quality. A mild pain that comes after a severe one feels like nothing, or even becomes pleasurable; while, on the other hand, a severe pain that follows a mild one feels much worse and more uncomfortable.
This no one can doubt of with regard to our passions and sensations. But there may arise some difficulty with regard to our ideas and objects. When an object augments or diminishes to the eye or imagination from a comparison with others, the image and idea of the object are still the same, and are equally extended in the retina, and in the brain or organ of perception. The eyes refract the rays of light, and the optic nerves convey the images to the brain in the very same manner, whether a great or small object has preceded; nor does even the imagination alter the dimensions of its object on account of a comparison with others. The question then is, how from the same impression and the same idea we can form such different judgments concerning the same object, and at one time admire its bulk, and at another despise its littleness. This variation in our judgments must certainly proceed from a variation in some perception; but as the variation lies not in the immediate impression or idea of the object, it must lie in some other impression, that accompanies it.
No one can doubt this when it comes to our feelings and sensations. However, there can be some confusion regarding our ideas and objects. When an object appears larger or smaller compared to others, the image and idea of the object remain the same and are still projected on the retina and in the brain or perception organ. The eyes bend the light rays, and the optic nerves send the images to the brain in the exact same way, whether a large or small object has come first; even the imagination doesn’t change the size of its object based on comparisons with others. The question is then, how can we form such different judgments about the same object from the same impression and idea, sometimes admiring its size and other times criticizing its smallness? This difference in our judgments must stem from a variation in some perception; but since this variation doesn’t come from the immediate impression or idea of the object, it must originate from another impression that accompanies it.
In order to explain this matter, I shall just touch upon two principles, one of which shall be more fully explained in the progress of this treatise; the other has been already accounted for. I believe it may safely be established for a general maxim, that no object is presented to the senses, nor image formed in the fancy, but what is accompanyed with some emotion or movement of spirits proportioned to it; and however custom may make us insensible of this sensation and cause us to confound it with the object or idea, it will be easy, by careful and exact experiments, to separate and distinguish them. For to instance only in the cases of extension and number; it is evident, that any very bulky object, such as the ocean, an extended plain, a vast chain of mountains, a wide forest: or any very numerous collection of objects, such as an army, a fleet, a crowd, excite in the mind a sensible emotion; and that the admiration, which arises on the appearance of such objects, is one of the most lively pleasures, which human nature is capable of enjoying. Now as this admiration encreases or diminishes by the encrease or diminution of the objects, we may conclude, according to our foregoing[7] principles, that it is a compound effect, proceeding from the conjunction of the several effects, which arise from each part of the cause. Every part, then, of extension, and every unite of number has a separate emotion attending it; and though that emotion be not always agreeable, yet by its conjunction with others, and by its agitating the spirits to a just pitch, it contributes to the production of admiration, which is always agreeable. If this be allowed with respect to extension and number, we can make no difficulty with respect to virtue and vice, wit and folly, riches and poverty, happiness and misery, and other objects of that kind, which are always attended with an evident emotion.
To explain this issue, I'll briefly touch on two principles; one will be expanded on later in this treatise, while the other has already been addressed. I believe it's safe to say as a general rule that no object presented to our senses or image formed in our minds comes without some corresponding emotion or mental response. Although habit may numb us to this sensation and lead us to confuse it with the object or idea, it is possible through careful and precise experiments to separate and distinguish them. For example, when it comes to size and quantity, it's clear that any very large object, like the ocean, a vast plain, a mountain range, or a large forest, or any extremely numerous collection of things, like an army, a fleet, or a crowd, generates a significant emotion in our minds. The admiration that arises from witnessing such objects is among the most intense pleasures that human nature can experience. As this admiration increases or decreases with the size or number of the objects, we can conclude, based on our earlier principles, that it is a mixed effect arising from the combination of the individual effects from each part of the cause. Each part of size, and each unit of number, has a distinct emotion associated with it; and while that emotion may not always be pleasant, its blend with others, and its ability to stimulate our spirits to a suitable level, contributes to the feeling of admiration, which is always enjoyable. If we accept this for size and number, we should have no trouble applying it to concepts like virtue and vice, wit and foolishness, wealth and poverty, happiness and misery, and related subjects that consistently evoke clear emotions.
The second principle I shall take notice of is that of our adherence to general rules; which has such a mighty influence on the actions and understanding, and is able to impose on the very senses. When an object is found by experience to be always accompanyed with another; whenever the first object appears, though changed in very material circumstances; we naturally fly to the conception of the second, and form an idea of it in as lively and strong a manner, as if we had infered its existence by the justest and most authentic conclusion of our understanding. Nothing can undeceive us, not even our senses, which, instead of correcting this false judgment, are often perverted by it, and seem to authorize its errors.
The second principle I want to point out is our commitment to general rules, which greatly influences our actions and understanding and can even affect our senses. When we consistently find that one object is always accompanied by another, the moment we see the first object—despite any significant changes—we instinctively think of the second object and create a vivid and strong idea of it, as if we had logically concluded its existence through the most accurate and reliable reasoning. Nothing can change our minds about this, not even our senses, which instead of correcting this mistaken judgment, are often twisted by it and seem to support its flaws.
The conclusion I draw from these two principles, joined to the influence of comparison above-mentioned, is very short and decisive. Every object is attended with some emotion proportioned to it; a great object with a great emotion, a small object with a small emotion. A great object, therefore, succeeding a small one makes a great emotion succeed a small one. Now a great emotion succeeding a small one becomes still greater, and rises beyond its ordinary proportion. But as there is a certain degree of an emotion, which commonly attends every magnitude of an object; when the emotion encreases, we naturally imagine that the object has likewise encreased. The effect conveys our view to its usual cause, a certain degree of emotion to a certain magnitude of the object; nor do we consider, that comparison may change the emotion without changing anything in the object. Those who are acquainted with the metaphysical part of optics and know how we transfer the judgments and conclusions of the understanding to the senses, will easily conceive this whole operation.
The conclusion I reach from these two principles, along with the effect of the comparisons mentioned earlier, is straightforward and clear. Every object is associated with some emotion that matches its size; a large object brings a strong emotion, while a small object brings a weaker one. So, when a large object comes after a small one, a strong emotion follows a weak one. This strong emotion, succeeding a weak one, becomes even stronger and exceeds its usual level. However, since there's a typical level of emotion that corresponds to every size of an object, when the emotion increases, we naturally assume that the object has also increased in size. The effect directs our attention to its usual cause: a certain level of emotion corresponds to a certain size of the object. We often overlook the fact that comparison can alter our emotions without changing anything about the object itself. Those familiar with the philosophical aspects of optics and how we transfer judgments and conclusions from our understanding to our senses will easily grasp this entire process.
But leaving this new discovery of an impression, that secretly attends every idea; we must at least allow of that principle, from whence the discovery arose, that objects appear greater or less by a comparison with others. We have so many instances of this, that it is impossible we can dispute its veracity; and it is from this principle I derive the passions of malice and envy.
But setting aside this new discovery of an impression that quietly accompanies every idea, we must acknowledge the principle from which this discovery came: that objects seem larger or smaller when compared to others. We have so many examples of this that it's impossible to deny its truth, and it is from this principle that I understand the feelings of malice and envy.
It is evident we must receive a greater or less satisfaction or uneasiness from reflecting on our own condition and circumstances, in proportion as they appear more or less fortunate or unhappy, in proportion to the degrees of riches, and power, and merit, and reputation, which we think ourselves possest of. Now as we seldom judge of objects from their intrinsic value, but form our notions of them from a comparison with other objects; it follows, that according as we observe a greater or less share of happiness or misery in others, we must make an estimate of our own, and feel a consequent pain or pleasure. The misery of another gives us a more lively idea of our happiness, and his happiness of our misery. The former, therefore, produces delight; and the latter uneasiness.
It's clear that we experience varying levels of satisfaction or discomfort based on how we reflect on our own situation and circumstances, which we see as more or less fortunate or unfortunate, depending on the amount of wealth, power, merit, and reputation we believe we have. Since we rarely judge things based on their actual worth, but rather compare them with other things, it follows that as we notice more or less happiness or suffering in others, we assess our own circumstances and feel either pain or pleasure as a result. Seeing someone else's misery highlights our own happiness, while their happiness emphasizes our own misery. Consequently, the former brings us joy, while the latter causes discomfort.
Here then is a kind of pity reverst, or contrary sensations arising in the beholder, from those which are felt by the person, whom he considers. In general we may observe, that in all kinds of comparison an object makes us always receive from another, to which it is compared, a sensation contrary to what arises from itself in its direct and immediate survey. A small object makes a great one appear still greater. A great object makes a little one appear less. Deformity of itself produces uneasiness; but makes us receive new pleasure by its contrast with a beautiful object, whose beauty is augmented by it; as on the other hand, beauty, which of itself produces pleasure, makes us receive a new pain by the contrast with any thing ugly, whose deformity it augments. The case, therefore, must be the same with happiness and misery. The direct survey of another's pleasure naturally gives us pleasure, and therefore produces pain when compared with our own. His pain, considered in itself, is painful to us, but augments the idea of our own happiness, and gives us pleasure.
Here’s a kind of reversed pity, or contrasting feelings that arise in the observer compared to what the person being observed feels. Generally, we notice that in all types of comparisons, an object always makes us experience a sensation that contrasts with the feelings it evokes directly and immediately. A small object makes a large one look even larger. A large object makes a small one appear even smaller. Deformity itself causes discomfort, but it can give us new pleasure by contrasting with a beautiful object, whose beauty is highlighted by it; conversely, beauty, which brings us pleasure, can lead to a new discomfort when compared to something ugly, whose deformity it emphasizes. The same must hold true for happiness and misery. Observing someone else's pleasure naturally brings us joy, but it can cause pain when we compare it to our own. Their pain, in isolation, is painful for us, but it enhances our perception of our own happiness and gives us pleasure.
Nor will it appear strange, that we may feel a reverst sensation from the happiness and misery of others; since we find the same comparison may give us a kind of malice against ourselves, and make us rejoice for our pains, and grieve for our pleasures. Thus the prospect of past pain is agreeable, when we are satisfyed with our present condition; as on the other hand our past pleasures give us uneasiness, when we enjoy nothing at present equal to them. The comparison being the same, as when we reflect on the sentiments of others, must be attended with the same effects.
It shouldn't be surprising that we can feel mixed emotions from the happiness and suffering of others. We often find that the same comparisons can make us resentful towards ourselves, causing us to take pleasure in our pain and feel sad about our joys. In this way, thinking about past pain can be comforting when we're happy with our current situation; conversely, our past joys can make us uneasy if we’re not experiencing anything as fulfilling right now. The comparison works the same way when we consider how others feel, leading to similar outcomes.
Nay a person may extend this malice against himself, even to his present fortune, and carry it so far as designedly to seek affliction, and encrease his pains and sorrows. This may happen upon two occasions. First, Upon the distress and misfortune of a friend, or person dear to him. Secondly, Upon the feeling any remorses for a crime, of which he has been guilty. It is from the principle of comparison that both these irregular appetites for evil arise. A person, who indulges himself in any pleasure, while his friend lies under affliction, feels the reflected uneasiness from his friend more sensibly by a comparison with the original pleasure, which he himself enjoys. This contrast, indeed, ought also to inliven the present pleasure. But as grief is here supposed to be the predominant passion, every addition falls to that side, and is swallowed up in it, without operating in the least upon the contrary affection. It is the same case with those penances, which men inflict on themselves for their past sins and failings. When a criminal reflects on the punishment he deserves, the idea of it is magnifyed by a comparison with his present ease and satisfaction; which forces him, in a manner, to seek uneasiness, in order to avoid so disagreeable a contrast.
No one can inflict this kind of harm on themselves, even regarding their current situation, and go so far as to intentionally seek out suffering, increasing their own pain and sorrow. This can happen in two situations. First, when a friend or someone close is going through distress or misfortune. Second, when someone feels remorse for a crime they committed. Both of these unhealthy desires for harm arise from the principle of comparison. A person enjoying a pleasure while their friend is suffering feels their friend's pain more acutely because of the contrast with their own enjoyment. This contrast should enhance their current pleasure. However, since grief is the stronger feeling here, every addition contributes to that feeling of grief and overshadows any positive emotion. The same applies to the punishments that people impose on themselves for their past wrongdoings. When someone reflects on the punishment they deserve, the idea of it grows larger in comparison to their current comfort and satisfaction, forcing them, in a way, to seek discomfort to avoid that unpleasant contrast.
This reasoning will account for the origin of envy as well as of malice. The only difference betwixt these passions lies in this, that envy is excited by some present enjoyment of another, which by comparison diminishes our idea of our own: Whereas malice is the unprovoked desire of producing evil to another, in order to reap a pleasure from the comparison. The enjoyment, which is the object of envy, is commonly superior to our own. A superiority naturally seems to overshade us, and presents a disagreeable comparison. But even in the case of an inferiority, we still desire a greater distance, in order to augment, still more the idea of ourself. When this distance diminishes, the comparison is less to our advantage; and consequently gives us less pleasure, and is even disagreeable. Hence arises that species of envy, which men feel, when they perceive their inferiors approaching or overtaking them in the pursuits of glory or happiness. In this envy we may see the effects of comparison twice repeated. A man, who compares himself to his inferior, receives a pleasure from the comparison: And when the inferiority decreases by the elevation of the inferior, what should only have been a decrease of pleasure, becomes a real pain, by a new comparison with its preceding condition.
This reasoning explains the origins of both envy and malice. The main difference between these two feelings is that envy arises from someone else’s current enjoyment, which makes us feel worse about our own situation. On the other hand, malice is the unprovoked desire to harm someone else for the sake of feeling good about ourselves in comparison. The enjoyment that triggers envy is usually better than what we have. Superiority tends to overshadow us and creates an unpleasant comparison. However, even when we are in a better position, we want a greater gap to enhance our self-image. When that gap narrows, the comparison becomes less favorable for us, leading to less pleasure and even discomfort. This explains the type of envy people experience when they see those who are ranked lower beginning to catch up or surpass them in their accomplishments or happiness. In this form of envy, the effects of comparison happen twice. A person who compares themselves to someone they view as inferior initially feels good about it. Yet, when that inferiority lessens due to the other person's success, what should have been a simple loss of pleasure turns into real pain through a new comparison with how things were before.
It is worthy of observation concerning that envy, which arises from a superiority in others, that it is not the great disproportion betwixt ourself and another, which produces it; but on the contrary, our proximity. A common soldier bears no such envy to his general as to his sergeant or corporal; nor does an eminent writer meet with so great jealousy in common hackney scribblers, as in authors, that more nearly approach him. It may, indeed, be thought, that the greater the disproportion is, the greater must be the uneasiness from the comparison. But we may consider on the other hand, that the great disproportion cuts off the relation, and either keeps us from comparing ourselves with what is remote from us, or diminishes the effects of the comparison. Resemblance and proximity always produce a relation of ideas; and where you destroy these ties, however other accidents may bring two ideas together; as they have no bond or connecting quality to join them in the imagination; it is impossible they can remain long united, or have any considerable influence on each other.
It's worth noting that envy, which comes from seeing others as superior, doesn't stem from a huge gap between us and someone else; instead, it arises from our closeness to them. A regular soldier doesn't feel as much envy towards his general as he does towards his sergeant or corporal; similarly, a well-known writer feels less jealousy from ordinary, low-level writers than from those who are more similar to him. It might seem that the bigger the gap, the more discomfort arises from the comparison. However, it's also true that a large gap removes the connection and either prevents us from comparing ourselves to those who are far removed or lessens the impact of that comparison. Similarity and closeness create a relationship between ideas; when these connections are severed, even if other factors bring two ideas together, they lack a bond to connect them in our minds, making it impossible for them to stay linked for long or to have any significant effect on each other.
I have observed in considering the nature of ambition, that the great feel a double pleasure in authority from the comparison of their own condition with that of their slaves; and that this comparison has a double influence, because it is natural, and presented by the subject. When the fancy, in the comparison of objects, passes not easily from the one object to the other, the action of the mind is, in a great measure, broke, and the fancy, in considering the second object, begins, as it were, upon a new footing. The impression, which attends every object, seems not greater in that case by succeeding a less of the same kind; but these two impressions are distinct, and produce their distinct effects, without any communication together. The want of relation in the ideas breaks the relation of the impressions, and by such a separation prevents their mutual operation and influence.
I've noticed that when it comes to ambition, those in power take a unique pleasure in their authority by comparing their lives to those of their subordinates. This comparison has a twofold impact because it's instinctive and directly related to the situation. When the mind struggles to transition smoothly between two objects, its activity is partially disrupted, and as the mind considers the second object, it begins fresh, so to speak. The impression created by each object doesn't seem stronger just because one follows another of the same kind; instead, these two impressions are separate and produce different effects without interacting with each other. The lack of connection between the ideas disrupts the relationship of the impressions, and this separation prevents them from influencing each other.
To confirm this we may observe, that the proximity in the degree of merit is not alone sufficient to give rise to envy, but must be assisted by other relations. A poet is not apt to envy a philosopher, or a poet of a different kind, of a different nation, or of a different age. All these differences prevent or weaken the comparison, and consequently the passion.
To confirm this, we can see that being close in ability alone isn't enough to spark envy; it also needs other factors to come into play. A poet is unlikely to feel envious of a philosopher, or of another poet from a different style, country, or time period. All these differences hinder or lessen the comparison, and as a result, the feeling of envy.
This too is the reason, why all objects appear great or little, merely by a comparison with those of the same species. A mountain neither magnifies nor diminishes a horse in our eyes; but when a Flemish and a Welsh horse are seen together, the one appears greater and the other less, than when viewed apart.
This is also why all objects seem big or small just by comparing them to others of the same kind. A mountain doesn’t make a horse look bigger or smaller to us; but when you see a Flemish horse next to a Welsh horse, one looks bigger and the other looks smaller than when you see them alone.
From the same principle we may account for that remark of historians, that any party in a civil war always choose to call in a foreign enemy at any hazard rather than submit to their fellow-citizens. Guicciardin applies this remark to the wars in Italy, where the relations betwixt the different states are, properly speaking, nothing but of name, language, and contiguity. Yet even these relations, when joined with superiority, by making the comparison more natural, make it likewise more grievous, and cause men to search for some other superiority, which may be attended with no relation, and by that means may have a less sensible influence on the imagination. The mind quickly perceives its several advantages and disadvantages; and finding its situation to be most uneasy, where superiority is conjoined with other relations, seeks its repose as much as possible, by their separation, and by breaking that association of ideas, which renders the comparison so much more natural and efficacious. When it cannot break the association, it feels a stronger desire to remove the superiority; and this is the reason why travellers are commonly so lavish of their praises to the Chinese and Persians, at the same time, that they depreciate those neighbouring nations, which may stand upon a foot of rivalship with their native country.
From the same principle, we can understand why historians note that any faction in a civil war would rather invite a foreign enemy than submit to their fellow citizens. Guicciardin applies this observation to the wars in Italy, where the connections between the different states are really just based on name, language, and proximity. Yet even these connections, when combined with a sense of superiority, make comparisons feel more obvious and, therefore, more painful. This drives people to seek out another kind of superiority that doesn’t come with such relationships, thus having a less noticeable effect on their thinking. The mind quickly identifies its various advantages and disadvantages; realizing that its situation is most uncomfortable when superiority is intertwined with other connections, it looks for relief as much as possible by separating them and breaking the association of ideas that makes the comparison feel so much more natural and impactful. When it can’t break the association, it feels an even stronger urge to eliminate the superiority. This is why travelers often lavish praise on the Chinese and Persians while simultaneously belittling neighboring nations that might compete with their homeland.
These examples from history and common experience are rich and curious; but we may find parallel ones in the arts, which are no less remarkable. should an author compose a treatise, of which one part was serious and profound, another light and humorous, every one would condemn so strange a mixture, and would accuse him of the neglect of all rules of art and criticism. These rules of art are founded on the qualities of human nature; and the quality of human nature, which requires a consistency in every performance is that which renders the mind incapable of passing in a moment from one passion and disposition to a quite different one. Yet this makes us not blame Mr Prior for joining his Alma and his Solomon in the same volume; though that admirable poet has succeeded perfectly well in the gaiety of the one, as well as in the melancholy of the other. Even supposing the reader should peruse these two compositions without any interval, he would feel little or no difficulty in the change of passions: Why, but because he considers these performances as entirely different, and by this break in the ideas, breaks the progress of the affections, and hinders the one from influencing or contradicting the other?
These examples from history and everyday life are rich and intriguing; however, we can find similar ones in the arts that are just as noteworthy. If an author were to write a treatise that included one part that was serious and profound and another that was light and humorous, everyone would criticize such an unusual mix and accuse the author of ignoring all rules of art and criticism. These artistic rules are based on the qualities of human nature, which require consistency in every work. This quality of human nature makes it hard for the mind to quickly switch from one emotion or state of mind to something completely different. Yet, we don’t blame Mr. Prior for combining his “Alma” and “Solomon” in the same volume; even though that amazing poet has done wonderfully in capturing the lightheartedness of one piece and the sadness of the other. Even if a reader were to go through both of these works without any break, they would feel little to no difficulty in switching between emotions. This is because the reader treats these works as entirely separate, and this pause in ideas interrupts the flow of feelings and prevents one from affecting or contradicting the other.
An heroic and burlesque design, united in one picture, would be monstrous; though we place two pictures of so opposite a character in the same chamber, and even close by each other, without any scruple or difficulty.
A heroic and comical design combined in one picture would be absurd; yet we can put two pictures of such different styles in the same room, and even right next to each other, without any hesitation or issue.
In a word, no ideas can affect each other, either by comparison, or by the passions they separately produce, unless they be united together by some relation, which may cause an easy transition of the ideas, and consequently of the emotions or impressions, attending the ideas; and may preserve the one impression in the passage of the imagination to the object of the other. This principle is very remarkable, because it is analogous to what we have observed both concerning the understanding and the passions. Suppose two objects to be presented to me, which are not connected by any kind of relation. Suppose that each of these objects separately produces a passion; and that these two passions are in themselves contrary: We find from experience, that the want of relation in the objects or ideas hinders the natural contrariety of the passions, and that the break in the transition of the thought removes the affections from each other, and prevents their opposition. It is the same case with comparison; and from both these phaenomena we may safely conclude, that the relation of ideas must forward the transition of impressions; since its absence alone is able to prevent it, and to separate what naturally should have operated upon each other. When the absence of an object or quality removes any usual or natural effect, we may certainly conclude that its presence contributes to the production of the effect.
In short, no ideas can influence each other, either through comparison or through the feelings they each generate, unless they are connected by some relationship that allows for a smooth transition between the ideas and, consequently, the emotions or impressions linked to those ideas. This connection can maintain one impression as the imagination moves to the other. This principle is significant because it aligns with what we’ve seen regarding both understanding and emotions. Imagine two objects presented to me that aren’t related in any way. Assume each object individually evokes an emotion, and that these two emotions are in conflict. Experience shows us that the lack of connection between the objects or ideas prevents the natural conflict between the emotions, and the disruption in the flow of thought keeps the feelings from interacting, avoiding their opposition. The same applies to comparison; from both of these phenomena, we can confidently conclude that the relationship of ideas facilitates the transition of impressions, as its absence is what can hinder it and separate what should naturally influence each other. When the absence of an object or quality eliminates a typical or natural effect, we can definitely conclude that its presence helps produce that effect.
SECT. IX OF THE MIXTURE OF BENEVOLENCE AND ANGER WITH COMPASSION AND MALICE
Thus we have endeavoured to account for pity and malice. Both these affections arise from the imagination, according to the light, in which it places its object. When our fancy considers directly the sentiments of others, and enters deep into them, it makes us sensible of all the passions it surveys, but in a particular manner of grief or sorrow. On the contrary, when we compare the sentiments of others to our own, we feel a sensation directly opposite to the original one, viz. a joy from the grief of others, and a grief from their joy. But these are only the first foundations of the affections of pity and malice. Other passions are afterwards confounded with them. There is always a mixture of love or tenderness with pity, and of hatred or anger with malice. But it must be confessed, that this mixture seems at first sight to be contradictory to my system. For as pity is an uneasiness, and malice a joy, arising from the misery of others, pity should naturally, as in all other cases, produce hatred; and malice, love. This contradiction I endeavour to reconcile, after the following manner.
So, we've tried to explain pity and malice. Both of these feelings come from the imagination, depending on how it perceives its object. When we directly consider the feelings of others and really delve into them, we become aware of all the emotions we observe, especially grief or sorrow. In contrast, when we compare others' feelings to our own, we experience the opposite sensation—joy from others' grief and sadness from their joy. But these are just the basic foundations of pity and malice. Other emotions then get mixed in with them. There’s usually a blend of love or tenderness with pity, and of hatred or anger with malice. However, it must be noted that this mixture initially seems to contradict my idea. Since pity is an unease and malice is a joy that arises from the suffering of others, pity should naturally, like in all other instances, lead to hatred, and malice to love. I try to resolve this contradiction in the following way.
In order to cause a transition of passions, there is required a double relation of impressions and ideas, nor is one relation sufficient to produce this effect. But that we may understand the full force of this double relation, we must consider, that it is not the present sensation alone or momentary pain or pleasure, which determines the character of any passion, but the whole bent or tendency of it from the beginning to the end. One impression may be related to another, not only when their sensations are resembling, as we have all along supposed in the preceding cases; but also when their impulses or directions are similar and correspondent. This cannot take place with regard to pride and humility; because these are only pure sensations, without any direction or tendency to action. We are, therefore, to look for instances of this peculiar relation of impressions only in such affections, as are attended with a certain appetite or desire; such as those of love and hatred.
To trigger a change in feelings, we need a connection between impressions and ideas; just one connection isn't enough to create this effect. To grasp the full impact of this dual connection, we should recognize that it isn't just the immediate sensation or fleeting pleasure or pain that defines any feeling, but the overall direction or trend of that feeling from start to finish. One impression can relate to another, not just when their sensations are similar, as we've assumed in earlier examples, but also when their urges or directions align. This doesn't apply to pride and humility, as these are just pure sensations without any direction or action associated with them. Thus, we need to find examples of this specific relationship between impressions only in emotions that come with a certain longing or desire, like love and hate.
Benevolence or the appetite, which attends love, is a desire of the happiness of the person beloved, and an aversion to his misery; as anger or the appetite, which attends hatred, is a desire of the misery of the person hated, and an aversion to his happiness. A desire, therefore, of the happiness of another, and aversion to his misery, are similar to benevolence; and a desire of his misery and aversion to his happiness are correspondent to anger. Now pity is a desire of happiness to another, and aversion to his misery; as malice is the contrary appetite. Pity, then, is related to benevolence; and malice to anger: And as benevolence has been already found to be connected with love, by a natural and original quality, and anger with hatred; it is by this chain the passions of pity and malice are connected with love and hatred.
Benevolence, or the desire that comes with love, is a wish for the happiness of the person you love and a dislike for their suffering. Conversely, anger, or the desire tied to hatred, is a wish for the suffering of the person you hate and a dislike for their happiness. So, wanting someone else's happiness and disliking their suffering is similar to benevolence, while wanting their suffering and disliking their happiness corresponds to anger. Now, pity is wanting happiness for another person and disliking their suffering, while malice is the opposite desire. Thus, pity relates to benevolence, and malice relates to anger. Since benevolence has already been linked to love through a natural and inherent quality, and anger is linked to hatred, this is how the emotions of pity and malice are connected to love and hatred.
This hypothesis is founded on sufficient experience. A man, who from any motives has entertained a resolution of performing an action, naturally runs into every other view or motive, which may fortify that resolution, and give it authority and influence on the mind. To confirm us in any design, we search for motives drawn from interest, from honour, from duty. What wonder, then, that pity and benevolence, malice, and anger, being the same desires arising from different principles, should so totally mix together as to be undistinguishable? As to the connexion betwixt benevolence and love, anger and hatred, being original and primary, it admits of no difficulty.
This hypothesis is based on enough experience. When a person decides to take action for any reason, they naturally start considering all other perspectives or motives that might reinforce that decision and give it power and influence over their thoughts. To support any plan, we look for motives related to interest, honor, or duty. So, it’s no surprise that feelings like pity and kindness, malice, and anger—being desires stemming from different sources—often mix together to the point that they become indistinguishable. Regarding the connection between kindness and love, anger and hatred, since they are fundamental and primary, it poses no challenge.
We may add to this another experiment, viz, that benevolence and anger, and consequently love and hatred, arise when our happiness or misery have any dependance on the happiness or misery of another person, without any farther relation. I doubt not but this experiment will appear so singular as to excuse us for stopping a moment to consider it.
We can add another experiment, namely that kindness and anger, and therefore love and hate, emerge when our happiness or misery depends on someone else’s happiness or misery, without any further connection. I’m sure this experiment will seem so unique that it justifies us taking a moment to think about it.
Suppose, that two persons of the same trade should seek employment in a town, that is not able to maintain both, it is plain the success of one is perfectly incompatible with that of the other, and that whatever is for the interest of either is contrary to that of his rival, and so vice versa. Suppose again, that two merchants, though living in different parts of the world, should enter into co-partnership together, the advantage or loss of one becomes immediately the advantage or loss of his partner, and the same fortune necessarily attends both. Now it is evident, that in the first case, hatred always follows upon the contrariety of interests; as in the second, love arises from their union. Let us consider to what principle we can ascribe these passions.
Imagine two people with the same job trying to find work in a town that can't support both of them. Clearly, if one succeeds, it completely clashes with the other’s success, and whatever benefits one is a disadvantage for the other, and vice versa. Now, let's say two merchants, even though they're based in different parts of the world, decide to form a partnership; the gain or loss for one directly affects the gain or loss for the other, meaning both share the same fate. It’s clear that in the first scenario, conflict arises due to conflicting interests, while in the second scenario, a bond forms due to their collaboration. Now, let’s think about what underlying principle we can attribute these emotions to.
It is plain they arise not from the double relations of impressions and ideas, if we regard only the present sensation. For takeing the first case of rivalship; though the pleasure and advantage of an antagonist necessarily causes my pain and loss, yet to counter-ballance this, his pain and loss causes my pleasure and advantage; and supposing him to be unsuccessful, I may by this means receive from him a superior degree of satisfaction. In the same manner the success of a partner rejoices me, but then his misfortunes afflict me in an equal proportion; and it is easy to imagine, that the latter sentiment may in many cases preponderate. But whether the fortune of a rival or partner be good or bad, I always hate the former and love the latter.
It's clear that these feelings don't come from the complex relationship between impressions and ideas if we focus only on the current sensation. Take the first case of competition: even though the pleasure and benefit of a rival definitely cause me pain and a sense of loss, the pain and loss my rival experiences can actually bring me pleasure and an advantage. If he ends up failing, I might derive even greater satisfaction from that. Similarly, I'm happy when a partner succeeds, but I also feel equally upset when they face misfortune; it's easy to see that the latter feeling can often outweigh the former. However, regardless of whether a rival's situation is good or bad, I always dislike the rival and care for the partner.
This love of a partner cannot proceed from the relation or connexion betwixt us; in the same manner as I love a brother or countryman. A rival has almost as close a relation to me as a partner. For as the pleasure of the latter causes my pleasure, and his pain my pain; so the pleasure of the former causes my pain, and his pain my pleasure. The connexion, then, of cause and effect is the same in both cases; and if in the one case, the cause and effect have a farther relation of resemblance, they have that of contrariety in the other; which, being also a species of resemblance, leaves the matter pretty equal.
This kind of love for a partner can't be compared to the bond I share with a brother or a fellow countryman. A rival can feel almost as connected to me as a partner can. Just as the joy of a partner brings me joy and their pain brings me pain, the joy of a rival brings me pain while their pain gives me joy. So, the relationship of cause and effect is the same in both scenarios; and while in one case, the cause and effect share a resemblance, in the other they are opposites—which is also a kind of resemblance—making the situation fairly equal.
The only explication, then, we can give of this phænomenon is derived from that principle of a parallel direction above-mentioned. Our concern for our own interest gives us a pleasure in the pleasure, and a pain in the pain of a partner, after the same manner as by sympathy we feel a sensation correspondent to those, which appear in any person, who is present with us. On the other hand, the same concern for our interest makes us feel a pain in the pleasure, and a pleasure in the pain of a rival; and in short the same contrariety of sentiments as arises from comparison and malice. Since, therefore, a parallel direction of the affections, proceeding from interest, can give rise to benevolence or anger, no wonder the same parallel direction, derived from sympathy and from comparison, should have the same effect.
The only explanation we can provide for this phenomenon comes from the principle of a parallel direction mentioned earlier. Our concern for our own interests makes us feel happy when someone we care about is happy and sad when they are sad, similar to how we experience feelings that match those of someone who is physically present with us. Conversely, our concern for our own interests also causes us to feel unhappy when a rival is happy and happy when they are in pain, reflecting the same conflicting emotions that arise from comparison and malice. Therefore, it's not surprising that a parallel direction of emotions, stemming from self-interest, can lead to kindness or anger; the same type of parallel direction, originating from sympathy and comparison, would have the same impact.
In general we may observe, that it is impossible to do good to others, from whatever motive, without feeling some touches of kindness and good-will towards them; as the injuries we do, not only cause hatred in the person, who suffers them, but even in ourselves. These phaenomena, indeed, may in part be accounted for from other principles.
In general, we can see that it's impossible to do good for others, no matter the reason, without feeling some kindness and goodwill towards them; just as the harm we cause not only breeds hatred in the person who suffers but also in ourselves. These phenomena can, indeed, be partially explained by other principles.
But here there occurs a considerable objection, which it will be necessary to examine before we proceed any farther. I have endeavoured to prove, that power and riches, or poverty and meanness; which give rise to love or hatred, without producing any original pleasure or uneasiness; operate upon us by means of a secondary sensation derived from a sympathy with that pain or satisfaction, which they produce in the person, who possesses them. From a sympathy with his pleasure there arises love; from that with his uneasiness, hatred. But it is a maxim, which I have just now established, and which is absolutely necessary to the explication of the phaenomena of pity and malice, that it is not the present sensation or momentary pain or pleasure, which determines the character of any passion, but the general bent or tendency of it from the beginning to the end. For this reason, pity or a sympathy with pain produces love, and that because it interests us in the fortunes of others, good or bad, and gives us a secondary sensation correspondent to the primary; in which it has the same influence with love and benevolence. Since then this rule holds good in one case, why does it not prevail throughout, and why does sympathy in uneasiness ever produce any passion beside good-will and kindness? Is it becoming a philosopher to alter his method of reasoning, and run from one principle to its contrary, according to the particular phænomenon, which he would explain?
But there’s a significant objection that we need to address before moving on. I’ve tried to show that power and wealth, or poverty and insignificance, which can lead to love or hate without creating any initial pleasure or pain, affect us through a secondary feeling that comes from empathizing with the joy or suffering of those who have them. From empathizing with someone’s happiness, love develops; from empathizing with their suffering, hatred arises. However, it’s a principle I’ve just established and is crucial for understanding the phenomena of pity and malice—that it’s not the immediate sensation or temporary pleasure or pain that shapes the character of any emotion, but the overall direction or trend of it from the start to the finish. For this reason, pity or empathy with suffering generates love because it connects us with the fates of others, whether good or bad, and gives us a secondary sensation that matches the primary one; in this sense, it works similarly to love and kindness. Since this rule applies in one case, why doesn’t it apply universally, and why does empathy in suffering produce any emotion other than goodwill and kindness? Is it appropriate for a philosopher to change his reasoning approach and shift from one principle to its opposite based on the specific phenomenon he’s trying to explain?
I have mentioned two different causes, from which a transition of passion may arise, viz, a double relation of ideas and impressions, and what is similar to it, a conformity in the tendency and direction of any two desires, which arise from different principles. Now I assert, that when a sympathy with uneasiness is weak, it produces hatred or contempt by the former cause; when strong, it produces love or tenderness by the latter. This is the solution of the foregoing difficulty, which seems so urgent; and this is a principle founded on such evident arguments, that we ought to have established it, even though it were not necessary to the explication of any phænomenon.
I’ve mentioned two different causes that can lead to a shift in emotions: a connection between ideas and impressions, and something similar—a shared tendency and direction of two desires that come from different sources. Now, I assert that when sympathy with unease is weak, it results in hatred or contempt due to the first cause; when it’s strong, it leads to love or tenderness because of the second. This explains the earlier difficulty that seems so pressing; and this principle is based on such clear arguments that we should have established it, even if it wasn't necessary to explain any phenomenon.
It is certain, that sympathy is not always limited to the present moment, but that we often feel by communication the pains and pleasures of others, which are not in being, and which we only anticipate by the force of imagination. For supposing I saw a person perfectly unknown to me, who, while asleep in the fields, was in danger of being trod under foot by horses, I should immediately run to his assistance; and in this I should be actuated by the same principle of sympathy, which makes me concerned for the present sorrows of a stranger. The bare mention of this is sufficient. Sympathy being nothing but a lively idea converted into an impression, it is evident, that, in considering the future possible or probable condition of any person, we may enter into it with so vivid a conception as to make it our own concern; and by that means be sensible of pains and pleasures, which neither belong to ourselves, nor at the present instant have any real existence.
It's clear that sympathy isn't just about the here and now; we often share in the joys and sorrows of others through communication, even if those feelings aren't happening right now but are just anticipated through our imagination. For instance, if I saw someone I didn't know who was sleeping in a field and was about to be trampled by horses, I would immediately rush to help them. This reaction comes from the same feeling of sympathy that makes me care about the current struggles of a stranger. Just mentioning this is enough. Sympathy is essentially a strong idea turned into a feeling, and it's clear that when we think about someone else's possible future situation, we can deeply relate to it and make it our own concern. This way, we can experience feelings of joy and pain that don't actually belong to us and that aren't real at this moment.
But however we may look forward to the future in sympathizing with any person, the extending of our sympathy depends in a great measure upon our sense of his present condition. It is a great effort of imagination, to form such lively ideas even of the present sentiments of others as to feel these very sentiments; but it is impossible we could extend this sympathy to the future, without being aided by some circumstance in the present, which strikes upon us in a lively manner. When the present misery of another has any strong influence upon me, the vivacity of the conception is not confined merely to its immediate object, but diffuses its influence over all the related ideas, and gives me a lively notion of all the circumstances of that person, whether past, present, or future; possible, probable or certain. By means of this lively notion I am interested in them; take part with them; and feel a sympathetic motion in my breast, conformable to whatever I imagine in his. If I diminish the vivacity of the first conception, I diminish that of the related ideas; as pipes can convey no more water than what arises at the fountain. By this diminution I destroy the future prospect, which is necessary to interest me perfectly in the fortune of another. I may feel the present impression, but carry my sympathy no farther, and never transfuse the force of the first conception into my ideas of the related objects. If it be another's misery, which is presented in this feeble manner, I receive it by communication, and am affected with all the passions related to it: But as I am not so much interested as to concern myself in his good fortune, as well as his bad, I never feel the extensive sympathy, nor the passions related to it.
However we might look forward to the future while empathizing with someone, our ability to feel sympathy largely depends on our understanding of their current situation. It takes a significant effort of imagination to vividly grasp even the present feelings of others to the point where we can actually share those feelings. However, we can't extend our sympathy to the future without being influenced by something in the present that resonates with us. When another person's current suffering strongly impacts me, the clarity of that perception doesn't just focus on its immediate subject; it spreads its influence across all connected thoughts, giving me a vivid understanding of everything related to that person, whether it's in the past, present, or future—possible, likely, or certain. With this vivid understanding, I become invested in them, share in their experiences, and feel a sympathetic response that aligns with what I imagine they feel. If I weaken the intensity of my initial perception, I also weaken the connections to related thoughts; just as pipes can only carry as much water as what comes from the source. By weakening it, I destroy the potential to fully engage with someone else's future. I might experience the immediate impact, but I won’t extend my sympathy beyond that, and I won’t transfer the strength of the initial perception into my thoughts about related matters. If I encounter someone else’s hardship presented in a weak way, I can still acknowledge it and feel all the emotions associated with it. However, because I’m not sufficiently invested to care about their good fortune in addition to their misfortune, I don’t experience the broad empathy or the emotions that come with it.
Now in order to know what passions are related to these different kinds of sympathy, we must consider, that benevolence is an original pleasure arising from the pleasure of the person beloved, and a pain proceeding from his pain: From which correspondence of impressions there arises a subsequent desire of his pleasure, and aversion to his pain. In order, then, to make a passion run parallel with benevolence, it is requisite we should feel these double impressions, correspondent to those of the person, whom we consider; nor is any one of them alone sufficient for that purpose. When we sympathize only with one impression, and that a painful one, this sympathy is related to anger and to hatred, upon account of the uneasiness it conveys to us. But as the extensive or limited sympathy depends upon the force of the first sympathy; it follows, that the passion of love or hatred depends upon the same principle. A strong impression, when communicated, gives a double tendency of the passions; which is related to benevolence and love by a similarity of direction; however painful the first impression might have been. A weak impression, that is painful, is related to anger and hatred by the resemblance of sensations. Benevolence, therefore, arises from a great degree of misery, or any degree strongly sympathized with: Hatred or contempt from a small degree, or one weakly sympathized with; which is the principle I intended to prove and explain.
To understand the emotions connected to these different types of sympathy, we need to recognize that benevolence is a genuine joy that comes from the happiness of someone we care about, as well as a pain that stems from their suffering. This relationship between our feelings leads to a desire for their happiness and a dislike for their pain. To align an emotion with benevolence, we need to experience these dual feelings in response to the person we are considering; one alone isn’t enough. When we only sympathize with one feeling, especially if it’s a painful one, that sympathy is linked to anger and hatred because of the discomfort it brings us. Since the extent of sympathy is tied to the intensity of the initial feeling, it follows that love or hatred is based on the same principle. A strong feeling, when shared, creates a double inclination of emotions that align with benevolence and love, regardless of how painful the initial feeling may have been. In contrast, a weak painful feeling connects us to anger and hatred due to the similarity of the sensations. Thus, benevolence arises from a significant amount of suffering or from any strong empathized feeling, while hatred or contempt emerges from a minor or weakly empathized feeling. This is the principle I aimed to demonstrate and clarify.
Nor have we only our reason to trust to for this principle, but also experience. A certain degree of poverty produces contempt; but a degree beyond causes compassion and good-will. We may under-value a peasant or servant; but when the misery of a beggar appears very great, or is painted in very lively colours, we sympathize with him in his afflictions; and feel in our heart evident touches of pity and benevolence. The same object causes contrary passions according to its different degrees. The passions, therefore, must depend upon principles, that operate in such certain degrees, according to my hypothesis. The encrease of the sympathy has evidently the same effect as the encrease of the misery.
We have not just our reasoning to rely on for this idea, but also our experiences. A certain level of poverty leads to contempt; however, when it goes beyond a certain point, it evokes compassion and goodwill. We might underestimate a peasant or a servant, but when the suffering of a beggar appears extremely severe or is depicted vividly, we empathize with him in his struggles and feel genuine pity and kindness in our hearts. The same situation can stir opposing emotions depending on its intensity. Therefore, emotions must be based on principles that operate in specific degrees, according to my theory. The increase in sympathy clearly has the same impact as the increase in misery.
A barren or desolate country always seems ugly and disagreeable, and commonly inspires us with contempt for the inhabitants. This deformity, however, proceeds in a great measure from a sympathy with the inhabitants, as has been already observed; but it is only a weak one, and reaches no farther than the immediate sensation, which is disagreeable. The view of a city in ashes conveys benevolent sentiments; because we there enter so deep into the interests of the miserable inhabitants, as to wish for their prosperity, as well as feel their adversity.
A barren or desolate land always looks unattractive and off-putting, often leading us to feel contempt for the people living there. This negative impression, however, largely comes from a slight connection we have with the inhabitants, as noted before; but it’s a weak connection and only goes as far as the immediate unpleasant feeling. Seeing a city in ruins evokes compassionate feelings because we become so involved in the struggles of the unfortunate residents that we hope for their recovery, as well as empathize with their hardships.
But though the force of the impression generally produces pity and benevolence, it is certain, that by being carryed too far it ceases to have that effect. This, perhaps, may be worth our notice. When the uneasiness is either small in itself, or remote from us, it engages not the imagination, nor is able to convey an equal concern for the future and contingent good, as for the present and real evil Upon its acquiring greater force, we become so interested in the concerns of the person, as to be sensible both of his good and had fortune; and from that compleat sympathy there arises pity and benevolence. But it will easily be imagined, that where the present evil strikes with more than ordinary force, it may entirely engage our attention, and prevent that double sympathy, above-mentioned. Thus we find, that though every one, but especially women, are apt to contract a kindness for criminals, who go to the scaffold, and readily imagine them to be uncommonly handsome and wellshaped; yet one, who is present at the cruel execution of the rack, feels no such tender emotions; but is in a manner overcome with horror, and has no leisure to temper this uneasy sensation by any opposite sympathy.
But although the strength of the impression usually creates feelings of pity and kindness, it’s clear that if it goes too far, it stops having that effect. This is possibly worth noting. When the discomfort is either minor or distant, it doesn’t capture our imagination and fails to generate the same concern for future potential good as it does for immediate real harm. As the discomfort grows stronger, we become more invested in the person’s situation, making us aware of both their good and bad fortunes; from that complete empathy, pity and kindness emerge. However, it’s easy to see that when the present suffering hits us particularly hard, it can completely capture our attention and block that dual empathy I mentioned earlier. Thus, we observe that while everyone, especially women, tends to develop a soft spot for criminals facing execution, often imagining them as unusually attractive and well-proportioned, someone witnessing a brutal execution feels none of those tender emotions; instead, they are almost overwhelmed with horror and have no time to soften this distressing feeling with any counteracting empathy.
But the instance, which makes the most clearly for my hypothesis, is that wherein by a change of the objects we separate the double sympathy even from a midling degree of the passion; in which case we find, that pity, instead of producing love and tenderness as usual, always gives rise to the contrary affection. When we observe a person in misfortunes, we are affected with pity and love; but the author of that misfortune becomes the object of our strongest hatred, and is the more detested in proportion to the degree of our compassion. Now for what reason should the same passion of pity produce love to the person, who suffers the misfortune, and hatred to the person, who causes it; unless it be because in the latter case the author bears a relation only to the misfortune; whereas in considering the sufferer we carry our view on every side, and wish for his prosperity, as well as are sensible of his affliction?
But the situation that best supports my hypothesis is when, by changing the subjects, we separate the dual feelings even from a moderate level of the emotion; in this case, we find that pity, instead of typically leading to love and tenderness, often produces the opposite feeling. When we see someone in distress, we feel both pity and love; however, the person responsible for that distress becomes the target of our strongest hatred, and this hatred increases based on how much compassion we feel for the sufferer. So, why should the same feeling of pity create love for the person enduring the misfortune while generating hatred for the person who caused it, unless it's because in the latter case, the person is only connected to the misfortune, while when we consider the sufferer, we look at the whole situation and wish for their well-being, as well as feeling their pain?
I. shall just observe, before I leave the present subject, that this phænomenon of the double sympathy, and its tendency to cause love, may contribute to the production of the kindness, which we naturally bear our relations and acquaintance. Custom and relation make us enter deeply into the sentiments of others; and whatever fortune we suppose to attend them, is rendered present to us by the imagination, and operates as if originally our own. We rejoice in their pleasures, and grieve for their sorrows, merely from the force of sympathy. Nothing that concerns them is indifferent to us; and as this correspondence of sentiments is the natural attendant of love, it readily produces that affection.
I just want to mention, before I move on from this topic, that the phenomenon of double sympathy and its tendency to create love may play a role in the kindness we naturally feel for our family and friends. Customs and relationships deepen our connection to the feelings of others, and whatever fortune we imagine they experience feels real to us, affecting us as if it were our own. We share in their joys and feel their pain purely through sympathy. Nothing that affects them is unimportant to us; and since this alignment of feelings naturally accompanies love, it easily leads to that affection.
SECT. X OF RESPECT AND CONTEMPT
There now remains only to explain the passion of respect and contempt, along with the amorous affection, in order to understand all the passions which have any mixture of love or hatred. Let us begin with respect and contempt.
There is now just one more thing to explain: the feelings of respect and contempt, along with romantic affection, to fully grasp all the emotions that have some blend of love or hate. Let's start with respect and contempt.
In considering the qualities and circumstances of others, we may either regard them as they really are in themselves; or may make a comparison betwixt them and our own qualities and circumstances; or may join these two methods of consideration. The good qualities of others, from the first point of view, produce love; from the second, humility; and from the third, respect; which is a mixture of these two passions. Their bad qualities, after the same manner, cause either hatred, or pride, or contempt, according to the light in which we survey them.
When we think about the qualities and situations of others, we can either see them for who they really are, compare them to our own qualities and circumstances, or combine these two ways of looking at things. From the first perspective, the good qualities of others inspire love; from the second, humility; and from the third, respect, which blends those two emotions. Similarly, their bad qualities can lead to either hatred, pride, or contempt, depending on how we view them.
That there is a mixture of pride in contempt, and of humility in respect, is, I think, too evident, from their very feeling or appearance, to require any particular proof. That this mixture arises from a tacit comparison of the person contemned or respected with ourselves is no less evident. The same man may cause either respect, love, or contempt by his condition and talents, according as the person, who considers him, from his inferior becomes his equal or superior. In changing the point of view, though the object may remain the same, its proportion to ourselves entirely alters; which is the cause of an alteration in the passions. These passions, therefore, arise from our observing the proportion; that is, from a comparison.
There's a mix of pride in feeling contempt and humility in showing respect, which is pretty clear just from how we feel or what we see, so it doesn't really need any extra proof. This mix comes from an unspoken comparison between the person we look down on or admire and ourselves, which is equally obvious. The same person can inspire either respect, love, or contempt based on their situation and abilities, depending on whether the person judging them sees them as below, at the same level, or above themselves. By changing our perspective, even if the person remains the same, how we relate to them completely changes, which alters our feelings. So, these feelings come from us noticing that relationship, or in other words, from making a comparison.
I have already observed, that the mind has a much stronger propensity to pride than to humility, and have endeavoured, from the principles of human nature, to assign a cause for this phænomenon. Whether my reasoning be received or not, the phænomenon is undisputed, and appears in many instances. Among the rest, it is the reason why there is a much greater mixture of pride in contempt, than of humility in respect, and why we are more elevated with the view of one below us, than mortifyed with the presence of one above us. Contempt or scorn has so strong a tincture of pride, that there scarce is any other passion discernable: Whereas in esteem or respect, love makes a more considerable ingredient than humility. The passion of vanity is so prompt, that it rouzes at the least call; while humility requires a stronger impulse to make it exert itself.
I've noticed that the mind tends to lean more toward pride than humility, and I've tried to explain this phenomenon based on human nature. Whether people agree with my reasoning or not, this phenomenon is undeniable and appears in many situations. For example, this explains why there's often more pride in contempt than there is humility in respect, and why we feel more uplifted when looking down on someone than we feel diminished by someone's superiority. Contempt or scorn is so heavily tinted with pride that it's hard to see any other emotion in it. In contrast, when it comes to esteem or respect, love plays a bigger role than humility. Vanity is quick to react, responding at the slightest prompt, while humility needs a stronger push to make itself known.
But here it may reasonably be asked, why this mixture takes place only in some cases, and appears not on every occasion. All those objects, which cause love, when placed on another person, are the causes of pride, when transfered to ourselves; and consequently ought to be causes of humility, as well as love, while they belong to others, and are only compared to those, which we ourselves possess. In like manner every quality, which, by being directly considered, produces hatred, ought always to give rise to pride by comparison, and by a mixture of these passions of hatred and pride ought to excite contempt or scorn. The difficulty then is, why any objects ever cause pure love or hatred, and produce not always the mixt passions of respect and contempt.
But here it’s reasonable to ask why this mix only happens in some situations and not all the time. All the things that inspire love when directed towards someone else become sources of pride when we focus on ourselves; therefore, they should also lead to feelings of humility, as well as love, when they belong to others and are just compared to what we have. Similarly, any trait that directly causes hate should always lead to pride in comparison, and this mix of hate and pride should provoke feelings of disdain or scorn. So the question is, why do some things ever lead to pure love or hate without always mixing in feelings of respect and contempt?
I have supposed all along, that the passions of love and pride, and those of humility and hatred are similar in their sensations, and that the two former are always agreeable, and the two latter painful. But though this be universally true, it is observable, that the two agreeable, as well as the two painful passions, have some difference, and even contrarieties, which distinguish them. Nothing invigorates and exalts the mind equally with pride and vanity; though at the same time love or tenderness is rather found to weaken and infeeble it. The same difference is observable betwixt the uneasy passions. Anger and hatred bestow a new force on all our thoughts and actions; while humility and shame deject and discourage us. Of these qualities of the passions, it will be necessary to form a distinct idea. Let us remember, that pride and hatred invigorate the soul; and love and humility infeeble it.
I have always thought that the feelings of love and pride, as well as those of humility and hatred, are similar in how they make us feel, with the former being pleasant and the latter being painful. However, while this is generally true, it’s noticeable that both the pleasant and the painful feelings have some differences and even oppositions that set them apart. Nothing lifts and energizes the mind quite like pride and vanity; meanwhile, love or tenderness tends to weaken and drain it. The same kind of differences can be seen in the uncomfortable emotions. Anger and hatred give us a new strength in our thoughts and actions, while humility and shame bring us down and make us feel discouraged. It’s important to clearly understand these qualities of emotions. Let’s remember that pride and hatred strengthen the soul, while love and humility weaken it.
From this it follows, that though the conformity betwixt love and hatred in the agreeableness of their sensation makes them always be excited by the same objects, yet this other contrariety is the reason, why they are excited in very different degrees. Genius and learning are pleasant and magnificent objects, and by both these circumstances are adapted to pride and vanity; but have a relation to love by their pleasure only. Ignorance and simplicity are disagreeable and mean, which in the same manner gives them a double connexion with humility, and a single one with hatred. We may, therefore, consider it as certain, that though the same object always produces love and pride, humility and hatred, according to its different situations, yet it seldom produces either the two former or the two latter passions, in the same proportion.
From this, it follows that even though love and hatred are similar in how agreeable they feel and are both triggered by the same objects, the other differences between them explain why they arise in very different intensities. Genius and education are enjoyable and impressive, which connects them to pride and vanity; however, they relate to love only through their pleasurable nature. Ignorance and simplicity are unappealing and lowly, which gives them a double connection to humility and a single one to hatred. Therefore, we can be certain that while the same object always evokes love and pride, humility and hatred, depending on its context, it rarely produces either the first pair or the second pair of emotions in the same degree.
It is here we must seek for a solution of the difficulty above-mentioned, why any object ever excites pure love or hatred, and does not always produce respect or contempt, by a mixture of humility or pride. No quality in another gives rise to humility by comparison, unless it would have produced pride by being placed in ourselves; and vice versa no object excites pride by comparison, unless it would have produced humility by the direct survey. This is evident, objects always produce by comparison a sensation directly contrary to their original one. Suppose, therefore, an object to be presented, which is peculiarly fitted to produce love, but imperfectly to excite pride; this object, belonging to another, gives rise directly to a great degree of love, but to a small one of humility by comparison; and consequently that latter passion is scarce felt in the compound, nor is able to convert the love into respect. This is the case with good nature, good humour, facility, generosity, beauty, and many other qualities. These have a peculiar aptitude to produce love in others; but not so great a tendency to excite pride in ourselves: For which reason the view of them, as belonging to another person, produces pure love, with but a small mixture of humility and respect. It is easy to extend the same reasoning to the opposite passions.
We need to find a solution to the previously mentioned issue of why certain objects evoke pure love or hate, rather than just respect or contempt through a mix of humility or pride. No quality in someone else generates humility through comparison unless it would lead to pride if it were in ourselves; and similarly, no object inspires pride through comparison unless it would have caused humility when viewed directly. This is clear: objects consistently create a sensation that is the opposite of their initial one through comparison. Imagine an object that is particularly suited to inspire love but only slightly capable of provoking pride; such an object, belonging to someone else, would directly spark a strong feeling of love but a weak feeling of humility in comparison. As a result, that latter emotion is hardly felt in the mix and doesn't turn love into respect. This applies to qualities like kindness, humor, ease, generosity, beauty, and many others. These qualities have a unique ability to inspire love in others, but not as strong a tendency to evoke pride in ourselves. Therefore, seeing these traits in another person leads to pure love, with only a minor mix of humility and respect. The same logic easily applies to the opposing emotions.
Before we leave this subject, it may not be amiss to account for a pretty curious phænomenon, viz, why we commonly keep at a distance such as we contemn, and allow not our inferiors to approach too near even in place and situation. It has already been observed, that almost every kind of idea is attended with some emotion, even the ideas of number and extension, much more those of such objects as are esteemed of consequence in life, and fix our attention. It is not with entire indifference we can survey either a rich man or a poor one, but must feel some faint touches at least, of respect in the former case, and of contempt in the latter. These two passions are contrary to each other; but in order to make this contrariety be felt, the objects must be someway related; otherwise the affections are totally separate and distinct, and never encounter. The relation takes place wherever the persons become contiguous; which is a general reason why we are uneasy at seeing such disproportioned objects, as a rich man and a poor one, a nobleman and a porter, in that situation.
Before we wrap up this topic, it might be worth noting a curious phenomenon: why we usually keep a distance from those we look down on and don’t let our inferiors get too close, even physically. It has already been noted that almost every type of idea comes with some emotion; this is true even for ideas like numbers and sizes, but even more so for important things in life that capture our attention. We can’t look at either a wealthy person or a poor one without feeling some emotions—some level of respect for the former and some level of disdain for the latter. These two feelings are opposites, but for us to sense that contrast, the people involved must be somehow related; otherwise, those feelings remain completely separate and don’t collide. This relationship occurs whenever people come into close proximity, which is a key reason why we feel uncomfortable seeing such mismatched figures, like a rich person and a poor one, or a nobleman and a porter, in that situation.
This uneasiness, which is common to every spectator, must be more sensible to the superior; and that because the near approach of the inferior is regarded as a piece of ill-breeding, and shews that he is not sensible of the disproportion, and is no way affected by it. A sense of superiority in another breeds in all men an inclination to keep themselves at a distance from him, and determines them to redouble the marks of respect and reverence, when they are obliged to approach him; and where they do not observe that conduct, it is a proof they are not sensible of his superiority. From hence too it proceeds, that any great difference in the degrees of any quality is called a distance by a common metaphor, which, however trivial it may appear, is founded on natural principles of the imagination. A great difference inclines us to produce a distance. The ideas of distance and difference are, therefore, connected together. Connected ideas are readily taken for each other; and this is in general the source of the metaphor, as we shall have occasion to observe afterwards.
This unease, which every observer feels, is even more pronounced for those in positions of superiority. This is because when someone of lower status comes too close, it’s seen as rude and indicates a lack of awareness of the social gap. A sense of superiority in someone else makes people want to keep their distance and leads them to show extra respect and reverence when they need to get closer. If they fail to do this, it suggests they're unaware of that person’s superiority. Additionally, any significant difference in qualities is often referred to as a "distance" in a common metaphor. Though it may seem trivial, this is rooted in natural principles of imagination. A major difference prompts us to create a sense of distance. Thus, the ideas of distance and difference are linked. Connected ideas tend to be mistaken for one another, which is generally the source of the metaphor, as we will discuss later.
SECT. XI OF THE AMOROUS PASSION, OR LOVE BETWIXT THE SEXES
Of all the compound passions, which proceed from a mixture of love and hatred with other affections, no one better deserves our attention, than that love, which arises betwixt the sexes, as well on account of its force and violence, as those curious principles of philosophy, for which it affords us an uncontestable argument. It is plain, that this affection, in its most natural state, is derived from the conjunction of three different impressions or passions, viz. The pleasing sensation arising from beauty; the bodily appetite for generation; and a generous kindness or good-will. The origin of kindness from beauty may be explained from the foregoing reasoning. The question is how the bodily appetite is excited by it.
Of all the complex emotions that come from a mix of love and hatred with other feelings, none is more worthy of our attention than the love that develops between sexes, due to both its intensity and the fascinating philosophical principles it presents. It’s clear that this emotion, in its most natural form, stems from the combination of three different feelings: the pleasure we get from beauty, the physical desire for reproduction, and a sincere kindness or goodwill. We can understand how kindness arises from beauty based on the earlier discussion. The question remains, though, how does this physical desire get triggered by beauty?
The appetite of generation, when confined to a certain degree, is evidently of the pleasant kind, and has a strong connexion with, all the agreeable emotions. Joy, mirth, vanity, and kindness are all incentives to this desire; as well as music, dancing, wine, and good cheer. On the other hand, sorrow, melancholy, poverty, humility are destructive of it. From this quality it is easily conceived why it should be connected with the sense of beauty.
The desire of a generation, when kept within limits, is clearly enjoyable and closely linked to all the positive emotions. Happiness, laughter, pride, and kindness all motivate this desire, along with music, dancing, drinks, and good times. Conversely, sadness, gloom, poverty, and humility destroy it. This connection makes it easy to understand why it relates to the sense of beauty.
But there is another principle that contributes to the same effect. I have observed that the parallel direction of the desires is a real relation, and no less than a resemblance in their sensation, produces a connexion among them. That we may fully comprehend the extent of this relation, we must consider, that any principal desire may be attended with subordinate ones, which are connected with it, and to which if other desires are parallel, they are by that means related to the principal one. Thus hunger may oft be considered as the primary inclination of the soul, and the desire of approaching the meat as the secondary one; since it is absolutely necessary to the satisfying that appetite. If an object, therefore, by any separate qualities, inclines us to approach the meat, it naturally encreases our appetite; as on the contrary, whatever inclines us to set our victuals at a distance, is contradictory to hunger, and diminishes our inclination to them. Now it is plain that beauty has the first effect, and deformity the second: Which is the reason why the former gives us a keener appetite for our victuals, and the latter is sufficient to disgust us at the most savoury dish that cookery has invented. All this is easily applicable to the appetite for generation.
But there's another principle that contributes to the same effect. I've noticed that the parallel direction of desires is a real connection, and that a similarity in their sensations creates a link among them. To fully understand this connection, we need to consider that any main desire can have related subordinate desires, which, if they align with other desires, are connected to the main one. For instance, hunger can often be seen as the primary urge of the soul, while the desire to approach food is the secondary urge since it’s essential for satisfying that appetite. If an object, through its separate qualities, draws us closer to food, it naturally boosts our appetite; conversely, anything that makes us set our food aside goes against hunger and reduces our desire for it. It’s clear that beauty has the first effect, while deformity has the second: this is why beauty sharpens our appetite for food, and deformity can turn us off even the most delicious dish that cooking has created. All of this applies easily to the desire for reproduction.
From these two relations, viz, resemblance and a parallel desire, there arises such a connexion betwixt the sense of beauty, the bodily appetite, and benevolence, that they become in a manner inseparable: And we find from experience that it is indifferent which of them advances first; since any of them is almost sure to be attended with the related affections. One, who is inflamed with lust, feels at least a momentary kindness towards the object of it, and at the same time fancies her more beautiful than ordinary; as there are many, who begin with kindness and esteem for the wit and merit of the person, and advance from that to the other passions. But the most common species of love is that which first arises from beauty, and afterwards diffuses itself into kindness and into the bodily appetite. Kindness or esteem, and the appetite to generation, are too remote to unite easily together. The one is, perhaps, the most refined passion of the soul; the other the most gross and vulgar. The love of beauty is placed in a just medium betwixt them, and partakes of both their natures: From whence it proceeds, that it is so singularly fitted to produce both.
From these two relationships—similarity and a shared desire—there's a connection between our sense of beauty, physical attraction, and kindness that makes them almost inseparable. Experience shows us that it doesn't matter which one comes first; any of them typically brings along the related emotions. Someone who is filled with desire will at least temporarily feel kindness toward the object of that desire and will often see her as more beautiful than usual. Many start with kindness and admiration for someone's intelligence or qualities, which then leads to more passionate feelings. However, the most common type of love begins with physical beauty and then spreads into kindness and physical desire. Kindness or admiration and the urge for physical intimacy are too distant from each other to easily connect. The former is perhaps the most refined emotion of the soul, while the latter is more basic and ordinary. The love of beauty strikes a balance between the two, possessing elements of both, which is why it is uniquely suited to foster both kinds of feelings.
This account of love is not peculiar to my system, but is unavoidable on any hypothesis. The three affections, which compose this passion, are evidently distinct, and has each of them its distinct object. It is certain, therefore, that it is only by their relation they produce each other. But the relation of passions is not alone sufficient. It is likewise necessary, there should be a relation of ideas. The beauty of one person never inspires us with love for another. This then is a sensible proof of the double relation of impressions and ideas. From one instance so evident as this we may form a judgment of the rest.
This account of love isn't unique to my system; it's unavoidable under any theory. The three feelings that make up this passion are clearly distinct, and each has its own specific object. Therefore, it's clear that they only produce each other through their connection. But the connection of passions alone isn't enough. It's also necessary to have a connection of ideas. The beauty of one person doesn't make us love another. This is a clear example of the dual connection of impressions and ideas. From such a clear instance, we can judge the others.
This may also serve in another view to illustrate what I have insisted on concerning the origin of pride and humility, love and hatred. I have observed, that though self be the object of the first set of passions, and some other person of the second, yet these objects cannot alone be the causes of the passions; as having each of them a relation to two contrary affections, which must from the very first moment destroy each other. Here then is the situation of the mind, as I have already described it. It has certain organs naturally fitted to produce a passion; that passion, when produced, naturally turns the view to a certain object. But this not being sufficient to produce the passion, there is required some other emotion, which by a double relation of impressions and ideas may set these principles in action, and bestow on them their first impulse. This situation is still more remarkable with regard to the appetite of generation. Sex is not only the object, but also the cause of the appetite. We not only turn our view to it, when actuated by that appetite; but the reflecting on it suffices to excite the appetite. But as this cause loses its force by too great frequency, it is necessary it should be quickened by some new impulse; and that impulse we find to arise from the beauty of the person; that is, from a double relation of impressions and ideas. Since this double relation is necessary where an affection has both a distinct cause, and object, how much more so, where it has only a distinct object, without any determinate cause?
This can also help illustrate what I’ve pointed out about the origins of pride and humility, love and hatred. I’ve noticed that while the self is the focus of the first group of emotions, and another person is the focus of the second, these subjects alone can’t be the sources of these emotions. Each relates to two opposing feelings that ultimately cancel each other out from the very beginning. So, here’s the state of the mind as I’ve described it before. It has certain faculties that are naturally designed to create a feeling; when that feeling arises, it naturally focuses on a specific object. However, this alone isn’t enough to produce the emotion; another feeling is needed that, through a combination of impressions and ideas, can activate these principles and give them their initial push. This situation becomes even more evident when it comes to the drive for reproduction. Sexual attraction is not just the object but also the driving force behind this desire. We don’t just focus on it when driven by that desire; thinking about it is enough to stimulate the desire. But since this drive diminishes with too much repetition, it needs to be re-energized by a fresh impulse; we find that this impulse comes from the beauty of the person—meaning from a combination of impressions and ideas. Since this combination is essential when a feeling has both a clear cause and object, it’s even more crucial when there’s only a distinct object without a specific cause.
SECT. XII OF THE LOVE AND HATRED OF ANIMALS
But to pass from the passions of love and hatred, and from their mixtures and compositions, as they appear in man, to the same affections, as they display themselves in brutes; we may observe, not only that love and hatred are common to the whole sensitive creation, but likewise that their causes, as above-explained, are of so simple a nature, that they may easily be supposed to operate on mere animals. There is no force of reflection or penetration required. Every thing is conducted by springs and principles, which are not peculiar to man, or any one species of animals. The conclusion from this is obvious in favour of the foregoing system.
But moving from the feelings of love and hate, and their combinations as seen in humans, to the same emotions as they show up in animals; we can see that love and hate are found throughout all sentient beings. Moreover, their causes, as explained earlier, are so straightforward that it’s easy to see them at work in simple animals. There’s no need for deep thought or insight. Everything operates based on mechanisms and principles that are not exclusive to humans or any specific species of animals. The conclusion drawn from this clearly supports the previous system.
Love in animals, has not for its only object animals of the same species, but extends itself farther, and comprehends almost every sensible and thinking being. A dog naturally loves a man above his own species, and very commonly meets with a return of affection.
Love in animals isn't limited to just those of the same species; it goes beyond that and includes almost every sensitive and thinking being. A dog naturally loves a human more than other dogs, and it's quite common for that affection to be returned.
As animals are but little susceptible either of the pleasures or pains of the imagination, they can judge of objects only by the sensible good or evil, which they produce, and from that must regulate their affections towards them. Accordingly we find, that by benefits or injuries we produce their love or hatred; and that by feeding and cherishing any animal, we quickly acquire his affections; as by beating and abusing him we never fail to draw on us his enmity and ill-will.
Animals are not very affected by the pleasures or pains of the imagination, so they can only evaluate things based on the tangible good or harm they bring. This leads them to shape their feelings towards those things. We see that by doing good or harm to them, we can create their love or hatred; when we feed and care for an animal, we quickly earn its affection, while beating and mistreating it always earns us its anger and resentment.
Love in beasts is not caused so much by relation, as in our species; and that because their thoughts are not so active as to trace relations, except in very obvious instances. Yet it is easy to remark, that on some occasions it has a considerable influence upon them. Thus acquaintance, which has the same effect as relation, always produces love in animals either to men or to each other. For the same reason any likeness among them is the source of affection. An ox confined to a park with horses, will naturally join their company, if I may so speak, but always leaves it to enjoy that of his own species, where he has the choice of both.
Love in animals isn't driven by relationships like it is in humans; it's more about their simpler ways of thinking, which only catch connections in obvious cases. However, it’s clear that sometimes this does have a strong effect on them. For example, familiarity, which acts similarly to relationships, often leads animals to form bonds with humans or with each other. Similarly, any resemblance among them can spark affection. An ox kept in a field with horses will naturally want to hang out with them, but it will always choose to be with its own kind when given the option.
The affection of parents to their young proceeds from a peculiar instinct in animals, as well as in our species.
The love that parents have for their young comes from a unique instinct found in animals, as well as in humans.
It is evident, that sympathy, or the communication of passions, takes place among animals, no less than among men. Fear, anger, courage, and other affections are frequently communicated from one animal to another, without their knowledge of that cause, which produced the original passion. Grief likewise is received by sympathy; and produces almost all the same consequences, and excites the same emotions as in our species. The howlings and lamentations of a dog produce a sensible concern in his fellows. And it is remarkable, that though almost all animals use in play the same member, and nearly the same action as in fighting; a lion, a tyger, a cat their paws; an ox his horns; a dog his teeth; a horse his heels: Yet they most carefully avoid harming their companion, even though they have nothing to fear from his resentment; which is an evident proof of the sense brutes have of each other's pain and pleasure.
It's clear that sympathy, or the sharing of emotions, happens among animals just as it does among humans. Fear, anger, bravery, and other feelings are often passed from one animal to another, even when they are unaware of the source of the original emotion. Grief also spreads through sympathy and leads to similar effects, stirring up the same feelings as it does in us. A dog's howling and crying clearly affect its companions. Interestingly, although almost all animals play using the same body parts and similar movements as they do when fighting—like a lion, tiger, or cat using their paws, an ox using its horns, a dog using its teeth, and a horse using its hooves—they are careful not to hurt each other, even when there's no risk of retaliation. This clearly shows that animals are aware of each other’s pain and pleasure.
Every one has observed how much more dogs are animated when they hunt in a pack, than when they pursue their game apart; and it is evident this can proceed from nothing but from sympathy. It is also well known to hunters, that this effect follows in a greater degree, and even in too great a degree, where two packs, that are strangers to each other, are joined together. We might, perhaps, be at a loss to explain this phænomenon, if we had not experience of a similar in ourselves.
Everyone has noticed how much more energetic dogs are when they hunt in a pack compared to when they go after their prey alone; it's clear that this is driven by some kind of camaraderie. Hunters are also aware that this effect is even more pronounced—and sometimes excessively so—when two unfamiliar packs come together. We might struggle to explain this phenomenon if we didn’t have a similar experience ourselves.
Envy and malice are passions very remarkable in animals. They are perhaps more common than pity; as requiring less effort of thought and imagination.
Envy and malice are noteworthy emotions in animals. They may be more prevalent than pity since they require less thought and imagination.
SECT. I OF LIBERTY AND NECESSITY
We come now to explain the direct passions, or the impressions, which arise immediately from good or evil, from pain or pleasure. Of this kind are, desire and aversion, grief and joy, hope and fear.
We now explain the direct passions, or the impressions, that arise right away from good or bad, from pain or pleasure. These include desire and aversion, grief and joy, hope and fear.
Of all the immediate effects of pain and pleasure, there is none more remarkable than the WILL; and though properly speaking, it be not comprehended among the passions, yet as the full understanding of its nature and properties, is necessary to the explanation of them, we shall here make it the subject of our enquiry. I desire it may be observed, that by the will, I mean nothing but the internal impression we feel and are conscious of, when we knowingly give rise to any new motion of our body, or new perception of our mind. This impression, like the preceding ones of pride and humility, love and hatred, it is impossible to define, and needless to describe any farther; for which reason we shall cut off all those definitions and distinctions, with which philosophers are wont to perplex rather than dear up this question; and entering at first upon the subject, shall examine that long disputed question concerning liberty and necessity; which occurs so naturally in treating of the will.
Of all the immediate effects of pain and pleasure, none is more notable than the WILL. Although it's not strictly considered one of the passions, understanding its nature and properties is essential for explaining them, so we'll focus on it here. I want to clarify that when I talk about the will, I mean the internal sensation we experience and are aware of when we consciously initiate any new movement of our body or new thought in our mind. This sensation, similar to those of pride and humility, love and hatred, is hard to define and doesn’t need further description. For this reason, we’ll avoid the definitions and distinctions that philosophers often use to confuse rather than clarify this issue. We’ll start by examining the long-debated question of liberty and necessity, which naturally arises when discussing the will.
It is universally acknowledged, that the operations of external bodies are necessary, and that in the communication of their motion, in their attraction, and mutual cohesion, there are nor the least traces of indifference or liberty. Every object is determined by an absolute fate to a certain degree and direction of its motion, and can no more depart from that precise line, in which it moves, than it can convert itself into an angel, or spirit, or any superior substance. The actions, therefore, of matter are to be regarded as instances of necessary actions; and whatever is in this respect on the same footing with matter, must be acknowledged to be necessary. That we may know whether this be the case with the actions of the mind, we shall begin with examining matter, and considering on what the idea of a necessity in its operations are founded, and why we conclude one body or action to be the infallible cause of another.
It is widely accepted that the actions of external forces are essential, and in how they communicate motion, attract, and bond with each other, there is no sign of indifference or freedom. Every object is governed by a definitive fate that dictates a specific degree and direction of its motion, and it cannot stray from that exact path any more than it can transform into an angel, spirit, or any higher being. Thus, the actions of matter should be seen as examples of necessary actions; anything similar to matter in this regard must also be considered necessary. To determine if this is true for the actions of the mind, we will start by examining matter and exploring the basis of the idea of necessity in its actions and why we conclude that one body or action is the unavoidable cause of another.
It has been observed already, that in no single instance the ultimate connexion of any objects is discoverable, either by our senses or reason, and that we can never penetrate so far into the essence and construction of bodies, as to perceive the principle, on which their mutual influence depends. It is their constant union alone, with which we are acquainted; and it is from the constant union the necessity arises. If objects had nor an uniform and regular conjunction with each other, we should never arrive at any idea of cause and effect; and even after all, the necessity, which enters into that idea, is nothing but a determination of the mind to pass from one object to its usual attendant, and infer the existence of one from that of the other. Here then are two particulars, which we are to consider as essential to necessity, viz, the constant union and the inference of the mind; and wherever we discover these we must acknowledge a necessity. As the actions of matter have no necessity, but what is derived from these circumstances, and it is not by any insight into the essence of bodies we discover their connexion, the absence of this insight, while the union and inference remain, will never, in any case, remove the necessity. It is the observation of the union, which produces the inference; for which reason it might be thought sufficient, if we prove a constant union in the actions of the mind, in order to establish the inference, along with the necessity of these actions. But that I may bestow a greater force on my reasoning, I shall examine these particulars apart, and shall first prove from experience that our actions have a constant union with our motives, tempers, and circumstances, before I consider the inferences we draw from it.
It's already been noted that, in no instance can we find the ultimate connection of any objects through our senses or reasoning. We can never delve deeply enough into the essence and structure of things to understand the principles behind their mutual influence. We only know their constant association, and from this constant association arises necessity. If objects didn't have a consistent and regular relationship, we would never form any ideas of cause and effect. Even then, the necessity involved in that idea is simply a mental determination to move from one object to its usual associate, inferring the existence of one from the other. Here are two key points to consider as essential to necessity: the constant association and the inference of the mind; wherever we find these, we must recognize a necessity. Since the actions of matter have no necessity outside of these factors, and we discover their connections not through insight into the essence of bodies but through their union and inference, the lack of that insight—while the union and inference persist—will never eliminate necessity. It's the observation of the union that leads to the inference. For this reason, one might think it's enough to prove a constant connection in the mind's actions to establish the inference and necessity of those actions. However, to strengthen my argument, I'll examine these points separately and first demonstrate through experience that our actions have a constant connection with our motives, moods, and circumstances before considering the inferences we draw from them.
To this end a very slight and general view of the common course of human affairs will be sufficient. There is no light, in which we can take them, that does nor confirm this principle. Whether we consider mankind according to the difference of sexes, ages, governments, conditions, or methods of education; the same uniformity and regular operation of natural principles are discernible. Like causes still produce like effects; in the same manner as in the mutual action of the elements and powers of nature.
To achieve this, a brief overview of the usual course of human events will suffice. There is no perspective from which we can view them that doesn't support this principle. Whether we look at humanity by gender, age, government, social status, or education methods, the same consistent patterns and operations of natural principles are evident. Similar causes continue to produce similar effects, much like the interactions among the elements and forces of nature.
There are different trees, which regularly produce fruit, whose relish is different from each other; and this regularity will be admitted as an instance of necessity and causes in external bodies. But are the products of Guienne and of Champagne more regularly different than the sentiments, actions, and passions of the two sexes, of which the one are distinguished by their force and maturity, the other by their delicacy and softness?
There are different trees that consistently bear fruit, and the taste of each is distinct; this consistency is seen as a result of necessity and causes in external things. But are the products of Guienne and Champagne more consistently different than the feelings, actions, and passions of the two sexes? One is characterized by strength and maturity, while the other is marked by delicacy and gentleness.
Are the changes of our body from infancy to old age more regular and certain than those of our mind and conduct? And would a man be more ridiculous, who would expect that an infant of four years old will raise a weight of three hundred pound, than one, who from a person of the same age would look for a philosophical reasoning, or a prudent and well-concerted action?
Are the changes in our bodies from infancy to old age more predictable and certain than those in our minds and behavior? And would it be more absurd for someone to expect that a four-year-old will lift a three hundred-pound weight than for someone to expect philosophical reasoning or careful planning from a person of the same age?
We must certainly allow, that the cohesion of the parts of matter arises from natural and necessary principles, whatever difficulty we may find in explaining them: And for a reason we must allow, that human society is founded on like principles; and our reason in the latter case, is better than even that in the former; because we not only observe, that men always seek society, but can also explain the principles, on which this universal propensity is founded. For is it more certain, that two flat pieces of marble will unite together, than that two young savages of different sexes will copulate? Do the children arise from this copulation more uniformly, than does the parents care for their safety and preservation? And after they have arrived at years of discretion by the care of their parents, are the inconveniencies attending their separation more certain than their foresight of these inconveniencies and their care of avoiding them by a close union and confederacy?
We must definitely acknowledge that the connection between the parts of matter comes from natural and necessary principles, no matter how hard it is to explain them. And for a good reason, we must recognize that human society is based on similar principles; in this case, our reasoning is even stronger than in the former, because we not only see that people naturally seek out social connections, but we can also explain the principles behind this universal tendency. Is it any more certain that two flat pieces of marble will stick together than that two young people of different sexes will mate? Do children come from this mating more consistently than parents care for their safety and well-being? And once they reach maturity with their parents' care, are the problems that come from their separation more certain than their ability to anticipate these issues and their efforts to avoid them through close bonds and alliances?
The skin, pores, muscles, and nerves of a day-labourer are different from those of a man of quality: So are his sentiments, actions and manners. The different stations of life influence the whole fabric, external and internal; and different stations arise necessarily, because uniformly, from the necessary and uniform principles of human nature. Men cannot live without society, and cannot be associated without government. Government makes a distinction of property, and establishes the different ranks of men. This produces industry, traffic, manufactures, law-suits, war, leagues, alliances, voyages, travels, cities, fleets, ports, and all those other actions and objects, which cause such a diversity, and at the same time maintain such an uniformity in human life.
The skin, pores, muscles, and nerves of a laborer are different from those of an elite individual. So are their feelings, actions, and behaviors. The various social classes affect the entire structure, both outwardly and inwardly, and these different classes arise inevitably from the consistent and universal principles of human nature. People cannot live without society, and they cannot form associations without government. Government creates distinctions in property and establishes different ranks of people. This leads to industry, trade, manufacturing, lawsuits, wars, alliances, journeys, travels, cities, fleets, ports, and all those other activities and aspects that create such variety while also maintaining a certain uniformity in human life.
Should a traveller, returning from a far country, tell us, that he had seen a climate in the fiftieth degree of northern latitude, where all the fruits ripen and come to perfection in the winter, and decay in the summer, after the same manner as in England they are produced and decay in the contrary seasons, he would find few so credulous as to believe him. I am apt to think a travellar would meet with as little credit, who should inform us of people exactly of the same character with those in Plato's republic on the one hand, or those in Hobbes's Leviathan on the other. There is a general course of nature in human actions, as well as in the operations of the sun and the climate. There are also characters peculiar to different nations and particular persons, as well as common to mankind. The knowledge of these characters is founded on the observation of an uniformity in the actions, that flow from them; and this uniformity forms the very essence of necessity.
If a traveler came back from a distant land and claimed he saw a place at the fiftieth degree of northern latitude where all the fruits ripen and thrive in winter, but wither in summer—opposite to how they grow and decay in England—he would find few who would believe him. I would imagine a traveler would receive just as much skepticism if they told us about people similar to those in Plato's Republic on one side, or those in Hobbes's Leviathan on the other. There's a general pattern in human behavior, just like there is with the sun and climate. Certain traits are unique to different cultures and individuals, but some are shared by all of humanity. Understanding these traits is based on observing the consistency in the actions they cause, and this consistency is the very essence of necessity.
I can imagine only one way of eluding this argument, which is by denying that uniformity of human actions, on which it is founded. As long as actions have a constant union and connexion with the situation and temper of the agent, however we may in words refuse to acknowledge the necessity, we really allow the thing. Now some may, perhaps, find a pretext to deny this regular union and connexion. For what is more capricious than human actions? What more inconstant than the desires of man? And what creature departs more widely, not only from right reason, but from his own character and disposition? An hour, a moment is sufficient to make him change from one extreme to another, and overturn what cost the greatest pain and labour to establish. Necessity is regular and certain. Human conduct is irregular and uncertain. The one, therefore, proceeds not from the other.
I can only think of one way to dodge this argument, which is by denying the uniformity of human actions that it relies on. As long as actions are consistently connected to the circumstances and mindset of the person acting, no matter how much we may verbally deny it, we actually accept it. Some might find a way to argue against this consistent connection. After all, what can be more unpredictable than human actions? What is more inconsistent than our desires? And who strays further from reason and their own character than humans do? Just an hour or a moment can be enough for someone to swing from one extreme to another, completely reversing what took them a lot of effort and pain to establish. Necessity is regular and certain, while human behavior is irregular and uncertain. Therefore, the two do not come from the same source.
To this I reply, that in judging of the actions of men we must proceed upon the same maxims, as when we reason concerning external objects. When any phaenomena are constantly and invariably conjoined together, they acquire such a connexion in the imagination, that it passes from one to the other, without any doubt or hesitation. But below this there are many inferior degrees of evidence and probability, nor does one single contrariety of experiment entirely destroy all our reasoning. The mind ballances the contrary experiments, and deducting the inferior from the superior, proceeds with that degree of assurance or evidence, which remains. Even when these contrary experiments are entirely equal, we remove not the notion of causes and necessity; but supposing that the usual contrariety proceeds from the operation of contrary and concealed causes, we conclude, that the chance or indifference lies only in our judgment on account of our imperfect knowledge, not in the things themselves, which are in every case equally necessary, though to appearance not equally constant or certain. No union can be more constant and certain, than that of some actions with some motives and characters; and if in other cases the union is uncertain, it is no more than what happens in the operations of body, nor can we conclude any thing from the one irregularity, which will not follow equally from the other.
In response to this, I would say that when judging people's actions, we should apply the same principles as when we think about external objects. When any phenomena are consistently linked together, they form such a connection in our minds that we move from one to the other without any doubt or hesitation. However, there are many lower levels of evidence and probability, and one conflicting experiment does not completely invalidate all our reasoning. The mind weighs the opposing experiments and, by subtracting the lesser from the greater, continues with the level of certainty or evidence that remains. Even when these conflicting experiments are perfectly balanced, it doesn't eliminate the idea of causes and necessity. We assume that the usual opposition comes from the influence of hidden and opposing causes, leading us to conclude that the randomness or indifference is merely in our judgment due to our limited understanding, not in the actual things themselves, which are equally necessary, even if they don't always seem consistent or certain. No connection can be more constant and certain than that of some actions with specific motives and traits; if in other situations the connection is uncertain, it is similar to what occurs in physical operations, and we can't draw any conclusions from one irregularity that wouldn't also apply to the other.
It is commonly allowed that mad-men have no liberty. But were we to judge by their actions, these have less regularity and constancy than the actions of wise-men, and consequently are farther removed from necessity. Our way of thinking in this particular is, therefore, absolutely inconsistent; but is a natural consequence of these confused ideas and undefined terms, which we so commonly make use of in our reasonings, especially on the present subject.
It’s generally accepted that crazy people have no freedom. But if we were to judge by their actions, those actions are less regular and consistent than those of wise people, and therefore are further from necessity. Our thinking on this issue is, therefore, completely inconsistent; but it’s a natural result of the muddled ideas and unclear terms we often use in our reasoning, especially on this topic.
We must now shew, that as the union betwixt motives and actions has the same constancy, as that in any natural operations, so its influence on the understanding is also the same, in determining us to infer the existence of one from that of another. If this shall appear, there is no known circumstance, that enters into the connexion and production of the actions of matter, that is not to be found in all the operations of the mind; and consequently we cannot, without a manifest absurdity, attribute necessity to the one, and refuse into the other.
We must now show that the connection between motives and actions is just as consistent as that in any natural processes, and their effect on our understanding is also the same, leading us to conclude the existence of one based on the other. If this is true, then there is no known factor involved in the connection and production of physical actions that isn't present in all mental operations; therefore, it would be clearly absurd to attribute necessity to one while denying it to the other.
There is no philosopher, whose judgment is so riveted to this fantastical system of liberty, as not to acknowledge the force of moral evidence, and both in speculation and practice proceed upon it, as upon a reasonable foundation. Now moral evidence is nothing but a conclusion concerning the actions of men, derived from the consideration of their motives, temper and situation. Thus when we see certain characters or figures described upon paper, we infer that the person, who produced them, would affirm such facts, the death of Caesar, the success of Augustus, the cruelty of Nero; and remembering many other concurrent testimonies we conclude, that those facts were once really existant, and that so many men, without any interest, would never conspire to deceive us; especially since they must, in the attempt, expose themselves to the derision of all their contemporaries, when these facts were asserted to be recent and universally known. The same kind of reasoning runs through politics, war, commerce, economy, and indeed mixes itself so entirely in human life, that it is impossible to act or subsist a moment without having recourse to it. A prince, who imposes a tax upon his subjects, expects their compliance. A general, who conducts an army, makes account of a certain degree of courage. A merchant looks for fidelity and skill in his factor or super-cargo. A man, who gives orders for his dinner, doubts not of the obedience of his servants. In short, as nothing more nearly interests us than our own actions and those of others, the greatest part of our reasonings is employed in judgments concerning them. Now I assert, that whoever reasons after this manner, does ipso facto believe the actions of the will to arise from necessity, and that he knows not what he means, when he denies it.
There’s no philosopher who’s so committed to this elaborate idea of freedom that they don’t recognize the power of moral evidence. In both theory and practice, they build on it as if it were a solid foundation. Moral evidence is simply a conclusion about people’s actions, based on the understanding of their motives, character, and circumstances. So, when we see certain characters or situations described on paper, we can deduce that the person who created them would affirm such facts, like the death of Caesar, the success of Augustus, or the cruelty of Nero. Remembering various other supporting accounts, we conclude that those events actually happened, and that so many people, without any personal gain, wouldn’t conspire to deceive us—especially since they would have to endure mockery from their peers if these events were claimed to be recent and widely known. This same reasoning applies to politics, war, business, and economics, and it’s so deeply woven into human life that it’s impossible to act or survive for even a moment without relying on it. A ruler who imposes a tax on their subjects expects them to comply. A general leading an army anticipates a certain level of bravery. A merchant expects honesty and skill from their manager or trader. A person ordering dinner has no doubt about their servants following instructions. In conclusion, since nothing concerns us more than our own actions and those of others, most of our reasoning is focused on judgments about them. I assert that anyone who reasons this way inherently believes that the choices we make come from necessity, and they don’t truly understand what they mean when they deny it.
All those objects, of which we call the one cause and the other effect, considered in themselves, are as distinct and separate from each other, as any two things in nature, nor can we ever, by the most accurate survey of them, infer the existence of the one from that of the other. It is only from experience and the observation of their constant union, that we are able to form this inference; and even after all, the inference is nothing but the effects of custom on the imagination. We must not here be content with saying, that the idea of cause and effect arises from objects constantly united; but must affirm, that it is the very same with the idea of those objects, and that the necessary connexion is not discovered by a conclusion of the understanding, but is merely a perception of the mind. Wherever, therefore, we observe the same union, and wherever the union operates in the same manner upon the belief and opinion, we have the idea of causes and necessity, though perhaps we may avoid those expressions. Motion in one body in all past instances, that have fallen under our observation, is followed upon impulse by motion in another. It is impossible for the mind to penetrate farther. From this constant union it forms the idea of cause and effect, and by its influence feels the necessity. As there is the same constancy, and the same influence in what we call moral evidence, I ask no more. What remains can only be a dispute of words.
All the things we refer to as cause and effect, when considered individually, are as different and separate from each other as any two things in nature. No matter how carefully we examine them, we can never deduce the existence of one from the other. We can only make this conclusion based on experience and the observation of their constant connection. Even then, this conclusion is just a result of habit on our imagination. We can't just say that the idea of cause and effect comes from objects that are always linked; we must assert that it's directly tied to our understanding of those objects, and that the necessary connection isn't revealed through reasoning but is simply a perception of the mind. Therefore, wherever we notice the same connection and wherever that connection influences our beliefs and opinions, we have the idea of causes and necessity, even if we might use different terms for it. In all past instances we've observed, when one object moves, it causes motion in another. The mind cannot go beyond this. From this repeated connection, it forms the idea of cause and effect and feels the necessity of it. Since there's the same consistency and influence in what we call moral evidence, I ask for nothing more. What’s left can only be a matter of semantics.
And indeed, when we consider how aptly natural and moral evidence cement together, and form only one chain of argument betwixt them, we shall make no scruple to allow, that they are of the same nature, and derived from the same principles. A prisoner, who has neither money nor interest, discovers the impossibility of his escape, as well from the obstinacy of the goaler, as from the walls and bars with which he is surrounded; and in all attempts for his freedom chuses rather to work upon the stone and iron of the one, than upon the inflexible nature of the other. The same prisoner, when conducted to the scaffold, foresees his death as certainly from the constancy and fidelity of his guards as from the operation of the ax or wheel. His mind runs along a certain train of ideas: The refusal of the soldiers to consent to his escape, the action of the executioner; the separation of the head and body; bleeding, convulsive motions, and death. Here is a connected chain of natural causes and voluntary actions; but the mind feels no difference betwixt them in passing from one link to another; nor is less certain of the future event than if it were connected with the present impressions of the memory and senses by a train of causes cemented together by what we are pleased to call a physical necessity. The same experienced union has the same effect on the mind, whether the united objects be motives, volitions and actions; or figure and motion. We may change the names of things; but their nature and their operation on the understanding never change.
And indeed, when we think about how effectively natural and moral evidence come together to form one cohesive argument, we can confidently say that they are fundamentally similar and come from the same principles. A prisoner, who has no money or connections, realizes that escaping is impossible due to both the stubbornness of the jailer and the walls and bars surrounding him; in trying to gain his freedom, he prefers to focus on the stone and iron of the jailer rather than the unyielding nature of his situation. That same prisoner, when taken to the scaffold, knows he will die because of the unwavering loyalty of his guards as much as from the executioner's ax or the wheel. His thoughts follow a clear line: the soldiers’ refusal to let him escape, the action of the executioner, the separation of his head and body, bleeding, convulsions, and death. This forms a connected chain of natural causes and voluntary actions, but the mind sees no difference as it moves from one link to another; it feels just as certain about the future outcome as if it were linked to current memories and sensory experiences by what we refer to as physical necessity. This established connection has the same effect on the mind, whether the connected elements are motives, decisions, and actions, or shapes and movements. We might change the names of things, but their essence and how they affect our understanding never change.
I dare be positive no one will ever endeavour to refute these reasonings otherwise than by altering my definitions, and assigning a different meaning to the terms of cause, and effect, and necessity, and liberty, and chance. According to my definitions, necessity makes an essential part of causation; and consequently liberty, by removing necessity, removes also causes, and is the very same thing with chance. As chance is commonly thought to imply a contradiction, and is at least directly contrary to experience, there are always the same arguments against liberty or free-will. If any one alters the definitions, I cannot pretend to argue with him, until I know the meaning he assigns to these terms.
I’m pretty sure no one will ever try to argue against these ideas without changing my definitions and giving different meanings to the terms cause, effect, necessity, liberty, and chance. According to my definitions, necessity is a key part of causation; therefore, liberty, by eliminating necessity, also removes causes and is essentially the same as chance. Since chance is usually seen as contradictory and directly opposed to experience, the same arguments against liberty or free will always apply. If someone changes the definitions, I can't really argue with them until I understand the meaning they give to these terms.
SECT. II THE SAME SUBJECT CONTINUED
I believe we may assign the three following reasons for the prevalance of the doctrine of liberty, however absurd it may be in one sense, and unintelligible in any other. First, After we have performed any action; though we confess we were influenced by particular views and motives; it is difficult for us to persuade ourselves we were governed by necessity, and that it was utterly impossible for us to have acted otherwise; the idea of necessity seeming to imply something of force, and violence, and constraint, of which we are not sensible. Few are capable of distinguishing betwixt the liberty of spontaniety, as it is called in the schools, and the liberty of indifference; betwixt that which is opposed to violence, and that which means a negation of necessity and causes. The first is even the most common sense of the word; and as it is only that species of liberty, which it concerns us to preserve, our thoughts have been principally turned towards it, and have almost universally confounded it with the other.
I think we can identify three main reasons for the widespread belief in the idea of liberty, even if it seems absurd and confusing in some ways. First, after we’ve done something, even if we admit we were influenced by specific thoughts and motivations, it’s hard for us to accept that we were forced to do it and that there was no way we could have acted differently. The notion of being forced implies something harsh, violent, and constraining, which we don’t experience. Few people can clearly differentiate between the freedom of spontaneity, as it’s called in academic circles, and the freedom of indifference; between what opposes coercion and what means a lack of necessity and causes. The first is actually the most common interpretation of the term, and since this is the type of liberty we really need to defend, our focus has mainly been on it, often mixing it up with the other concept.
Secondly, There is a false sensation or experience even of the liberty of indifference; which is regarded as an argument for its real existence. The necessity of any action, whether of matter or of the mind, is not properly a quality in the agent, but in any thinking or intelligent being, who may consider the action, and consists in the determination of his thought to infer its existence from some preceding objects: As liberty or chance, on the other hand, is nothing but the want of that determination, and a certain looseness, which we feel in passing or not passing from the idea of one to that of the other. Now we may observe, that though in reflecting on human actions we seldom feel such a looseness or indifference, yet it very commonly happens, that in performing the actions themselves we are sensible of something like it: And as all related or resembling objects are readily taken for each other, this has been employed as a demonstrative or even an intuitive proof of human liberty. We feel that our actions are subject to our will on most occasions, and imagine we feel that the will itself is subject to nothing; because when by a denial of it we are provoked to try, we feel that it moves easily every way, and produces an image of itself even on that side, on which it did not settle. This image or faint motion, we persuade ourselves, could have been compleated into the thing itself; because, should that be denyed, we find, upon a second trial, that it can. But these efforts are all in vain; and whatever capricious and irregular actions we may perform; as the desire of showing our liberty is the sole motive of our actions; we can never free ourselves from the bonds of necessity. We may imagine we feel a liberty within ourselves; but a spectator can commonly infer our actions from our motives and character; and even where he cannot, he concludes in general, that he might, were he perfectly acquainted with every circumstance of our situation and temper, and the most secret springs of our complexion and disposition. Now this is the very essence of necessity, according to the foregoing doctrine.
Secondly, there’s a misleading feeling or experience of the freedom of indifference, which is seen as evidence of its actual existence. The necessity of any action, whether physical or mental, isn’t truly a characteristic of the agent, but rather of any thinking or intelligent being that might consider the action. It comes from their decision to infer its existence from prior objects. On the other hand, freedom or chance is simply the lack of that determination and a certain looseness we experience when switching from one idea to another. We can notice that, while reflecting on human actions, we rarely feel that looseness or indifference, yet it often happens that when we actually perform those actions, we sense something similar. Since all related or similar objects are easily mistaken for each other, this has been used as clear or even intuitive proof of human freedom. We feel that our actions usually align with our will, and we think that the will itself isn’t subject to anything; because when we try to deny it, we feel that it can easily move in any direction, even creating an impression of itself in the direction where it didn’t settle. We convince ourselves that this impression or slight movement could have become the actual action; and if we deny that possibility, we find, upon trying again, that it indeed can. But these attempts are all in vain; and no matter how whimsical and unpredictable our actions may seem, since the desire to show our freedom is the only motive behind our actions, we can never truly escape the bonds of necessity. We might think we feel freedom within ourselves, but an observer can usually deduce our actions from our motives and character. Even when they can’t make those deductions, they generally conclude that they could if they were fully aware of every detail of our situation, temperament, and the most hidden aspects of our nature and disposition. This idea embodies the very essence of necessity, according to the earlier arguments.
A third reason why the doctrine of liberty has generally been better received in the world, than its antagonist, proceeds from religion, which has been very unnecessarily interested in this question. There is no method of reasoning more common, and yet none more blameable, than in philosophical debates to endeavour to refute any hypothesis by a pretext of its dangerous consequences to religion and morality. When any opinion leads us into absurdities, it is certainly false; but it is not certain an opinion is false, because it is of dangerous consequence. Such topics, therefore, ought entirely to be foreborn, as serving nothing to the discovery of truth, but only to make the person of an antagonist odious. This I observe in general, without pretending to draw any advantage from it. I submit myself frankly to an examination of this kind, and dare venture to affirm, that the doctrine of necessity, according to my explication of it, is not only innocent, but even advantageous to religion and morality.
A third reason why the idea of liberty is generally more accepted in the world than its opposition is due to religion, which has unnecessarily influenced this issue. In philosophical debates, it's all too common—and very wrong—to try to disprove a theory by claiming it has dangerous consequences for religion and morality. Just because a belief leads to absurd outcomes, it doesn't automatically mean it's false; an opinion isn’t proven false simply because it could lead to harmful results. Therefore, these discussions should be avoided completely, as they do nothing to uncover the truth and only serve to make an opponent look bad. I'm stating this generally without trying to gain anything from it. I'm open to this kind of scrutiny and confidently assert that the idea of necessity, as I explain it, is not only harmless but actually beneficial to religion and morality.
I define necessity two ways, conformable to the two definitions of cause, of which it makes an essential part. I place it either in the constant union and conjunction of like objects, or in the inference of the mind from the one to the other. Now necessity, in both these senses, has universally, though tacitly, in the schools, in the pulpit, and in common life, been allowed to belong to the will of man, and no one has ever pretended to deny, that we can draw inferences concerning human actions, and that those inferences are founded on the experienced union of like actions with like motives and circumstances. The only particular in which any one can differ from me, is either, that perhaps he will refuse to call this necessity. But as long as the meaning is understood, I hope the word can do no harm. Or that he will maintain there is something else in the operations of matter. Now whether it be so or not is of no consequence to religion, whatever it may be to natural philosophy. I may be mistaken in asserting, that we have no idea of any other connexion in the actions of body, and shall be glad to be farther instructed on that head: But sure I am, I ascribe nothing to the actions of the mind, but what must readily be allowed of. Let no one, therefore, put an invidious construction on my words, by saying simply, that I assert the necessity of human actions, and place them on the same footing with the operations of senseless matter. I do not ascribe to the will that unintelligible necessity, which is supposed to lie in matter. But I ascribe to matter, that intelligible quality, call it necessity or not, which the most rigorous orthodoxy does or must allow to belong to the will. I change, therefore, nothing in the received systems, with regard to the will, but only with regard to material objects.
I define necessity in two ways, based on the two definitions of cause that it fundamentally involves. I see it either as the constant connection and association of similar objects, or as the reasoning of the mind that connects one to the other. Now, necessity, in both these meanings, has been generally accepted, though subtly, in schools, in sermons, and in everyday life, as part of human will, and no one has ever claimed that we can't make inferences about human actions, based on the observed correlation of similar actions with similar motives and circumstances. The only difference someone might have with me is that they might refuse to call this necessity. But as long as the meaning is clear, I hope the term doesn't cause any issues. Or they might argue that there’s something else in the behavior of matter. Whether that’s true or not doesn’t matter for religion, even if it does for natural science. I could be wrong in saying that we don’t have any idea of a different connection in physical actions, and I’d welcome more insight on that topic. But I am confident that I attribute nothing to the actions of the mind that wouldn’t be readily accepted. So, let no one misinterpret my words by simply stating that I claim the necessity of human actions, equating them with the behavior of lifeless matter. I don’t attribute to the will that unclear necessity that is believed to reside in matter. Instead, I attribute to matter that clear quality, whether you call it necessity or something else, that the strictest orthodoxy recognizes as belonging to the will. Therefore, I change nothing in the accepted systems regarding the will, only in relation to material objects.
Nay I shall go farther, and assert, that this kind of necessity is so essential to religion and morality, that without it there must ensue an absolute subversion of both, and that every other supposition is entirely destructive to all laws both divine and human. It is indeed certain, that as all human laws are founded on rewards and punishments, it is supposed as a fundamental principle, that these motives have an influence on the mind, and both produce the good and prevent the evil actions. We may give to this influence what name we please; but as it is usually conjoined with the action, common sense requires it should be esteemed a cause, and be booked upon as an instance of that necessity, which I would establish.
No, I will go even further and say that this type of necessity is so crucial to religion and morality that without it, both would completely collapse, and any other viewpoint is completely harmful to all laws, both divine and human. It is certainly true that since all human laws are based on rewards and punishments, it is assumed as a fundamental principle that these incentives have an effect on the mind, motivating good actions and preventing bad ones. We can call this influence whatever we want; however, since it usually accompanies the action, common sense dictates that it should be regarded as a cause and seen as an example of the necessity I want to establish.
This reasoning is equally solid, when applied to divine laws, so far as the deity is considered as a legislator, and is supposed to inflict punishment and bestow rewards with a design to produce obedience. But I also maintain, that even where he acts not in his magisterial capacity, but is regarded as the avenger of crimes merely on account of their odiousness and deformity, not only it is impossible, without the necessary connexion of cause and effect in human actions, that punishments could be inflicted compatible with justice and moral equity; but also that it could ever enter into the thoughts of any reasonable being to inflict them. The constant and universal object of hatred or anger is a person or creature endowed with thought and consciousness; and when any criminal or injurious actions excite that passion, it is only by their relation to the person or connexion with him. But according to the doctrine of liberty or chance, this connexion is reduced to nothing, nor are men more accountable for those actions, which are designed and premeditated, than for such as are the most casual and accidental. Actions are by their very nature temporary and perishing; and where they proceed not from some cause in the characters and disposition of the person, who performed them, they infix not themselves upon him, and can neither redound to his honour, if good, nor infamy, if evil. The action itself may be blameable; it may be contrary to all the rules of morality and religion: But the person is not responsible for it; and as it proceeded from nothing in him, that is durable or constant, and leaves nothing of that nature behind it, it is impossible he can, upon its account, become the object of punishment or vengeance. According to the hypothesis of liberty, therefore, a man is as pure and untainted, after having committed the most horrid crimes, as at the first moment of his birth, nor is his character any way concerned in his actions; since they are not derived from it, and the wickedness of the one can never be used as a proof of the depravity of the other. It is only upon the principles of necessity, that a person acquires any merit or demerit from his actions, however the common opinion may incline to the contrary.
This reasoning also holds true when we consider divine laws, particularly when we think of the deity as a lawmaker who punishes and rewards to promote obedience. However, I argue that even when the deity is viewed as merely an avenger of crimes due to their ugliness and immorality, it is still impossible for punishments to be inflicted justly and fairly without a necessary connection between cause and effect in human actions. Moreover, it wouldn't even occur to any rational being to inflict such punishments. The constant object of hatred or anger is a person or being that can think and feel; when criminal or harmful actions trigger that emotion, it’s only because of their relation to the person involved. But if we accept the idea of freedom or chance, this connection evaporates, making people no more accountable for premeditated actions than for those that happen by chance. Actions are inherently temporary and fleeting; and when they don’t stem from something inherent in the character and disposition of the person who performs them, they don’t define that person and have no lasting impact. A good action might be blameworthy, contrary to all moral and religious standards, but the person isn’t held responsible for it; since it didn’t come from anything within him that is enduring or stable and doesn’t leave behind anything of that sort, it’s impossible for him to be subjected to punishment or retribution because of it. Therefore, according to the idea of freedom, a person remains as innocent and unblemished after committing the most horrific crimes as they were at birth, and his character isn't connected to his actions since those actions don’t originate from it, and the evil of one can never be used as evidence of the corrupt nature of the other. Only under the notion of necessity can a person gain any merit or demerit from their actions, regardless of what common belief might suggest.
But so inconsistent are men with themselves, that though they often assert, that necessity utterly destroys all merit and demerit either towards mankind or superior powers, yet they continue still to reason upon these very principles of necessity in all their judgments concerning this matter. Men are not blamed for such evil actions as they perform ignorantly and casually, whatever may be their consequences. Why? but because the causes of these actions are only momentary, and terminate in them alone. Men are less blamed for such evil actions, as they perform hastily and unpremeditately, than for such as proceed from thought and deliberation. For what reason? but because a hasty temper, though a constant cause in the mind, operates only by intervals, and infects not the whole character. Again, repentance wipes off every crime, especially if attended with an evident reformation of life and manners. How is this to be accounted for? But by asserting that actions render a person criminal, merely as they are proofs of criminal passions or principles in the mind; and when by any alteration of these principles they cease to be just proofs, they likewise cease to be criminal. But according to the doctrine of liberty or chance they never were just proofs, and consequently never were criminal.
But people are so inconsistent with themselves that even though they often claim that necessity completely eliminates any merit or blame towards others or higher powers, they still rely on these same ideas of necessity in their judgments about this issue. People aren’t held accountable for bad actions they commit accidentally or without awareness, no matter what the outcomes are. Why? Because the reasons for these actions are only temporary and affect them alone. People are less blamed for bad actions done quickly and without thought than for those that come from careful consideration. Why is that? Because a quick temper, though a consistent factor in someone's mind, only influences them occasionally and doesn’t define their entire character. Moreover, remorse can clear away any wrongdoing, especially if it comes with a clear change in behavior and attitude. How do we explain this? By saying that actions make someone criminal only if they reflect criminal feelings or principles in the mind; and when these principles change, they stop being valid evidence and thus stop being considered criminal. However, according to the idea of free will or chance, they were never valid evidence in the first place, and therefore were never criminal.
Here then I turn to my adversary, and desire him to free his own system from these odious consequences before he charge them upon others. Or if he rather chuses, that this question should be decided by fair arguments before philosophers, than by declamations before the people, let him return to what I have advanced to prove that liberty and chance are synonimous; and concerning the nature of moral evidence and the regularity of human actions. Upon a review of these reasonings, I cannot doubt of an entire victory; and therefore having proved, that all actions of the will have particular causes, I proceed to explain what these causes are, and how they operate.
Here, I turn to my opponent and ask him to clear his own system of these unpleasant consequences before he blames others. Or, if he prefers that this question be settled with solid arguments among philosophers instead of with rhetoric in front of the public, let him revisit what I’ve put forward to show that liberty and chance are the same; and also about the nature of moral evidence and the regularity of human actions. After reviewing these arguments, I have no doubt that I will emerge completely victorious; thus, having demonstrated that all actions of the will have specific causes, I will now explain what these causes are and how they work.
SECT. III OF THE INFLUENCING MOTIVES OF THE WILL
Nothing is more usual in philosophy, and even in common life, than to talk of the combat of passion and reason, to give the preference to reason, and assert that men are only so far virtuous as they conform themselves to its dictates. Every rational creature, it is said, is obliged to regulate his actions by reason; and if any other motive or principle challenge the direction of his conduct, he ought to oppose it, till it be entirely subdued, or at least brought to a conformity with that superior principle. On this method of thinking the greatest part of moral philosophy, antient and modern, seems to be founded; nor is there an ampler field, as well for metaphysical arguments, as popular declamations, than this supposed pre-eminence of reason above passion. The eternity, invariableness, and divine origin of the former have been displayed to the best advantage: The blindness, unconstancy, and deceitfulness of the latter have been as strongly insisted on. In order to shew the fallacy of all this philosophy, I shall endeavour to prove first, that reason alone can never be a motive to any action of the will; and secondly, that it can never oppose passion in the direction of the will.
Nothing is more common in philosophy, and even in everyday life, than discussing the struggle between passion and reason, favoring reason, and claiming that people are only virtuous to the extent that they follow its guidance. It is said that every rational being must regulate their actions according to reason; if any other motive or principle attempts to guide their behavior, they should resist it until it is completely conquered, or at least brought into alignment with that higher principle. Most of moral philosophy, both ancient and modern, seems to be based on this way of thinking; there is no broader topic for both metaphysical arguments and public debates than this supposed superiority of reason over passion. The eternity, consistency, and divine origin of reason have been highlighted to the fullest extent; while the blindness, inconsistency, and deceitfulness of passion have been emphasized just as strongly. To demonstrate the fallacy of this entire philosophical stance, I will first try to prove that reason alone can never motivate any action of the will; and secondly, that it can never stand against passion in guiding the will.
The understanding exerts itself after two different ways, as it judges from demonstration or probability; as it regards the abstract relations of our ideas, or those relations of objects, of which experience only gives us information. I believe it scarce will be asserted, that the first species of reasoning alone is ever the cause of any action. As its proper province is the world of ideas, and as the will always places us in that of realities, demonstration and volition seem, upon that account, to be totally removed, from each other. Mathematics, indeed, are useful in all mechanical operations, and arithmetic in almost every art and profession: But it is not of themselves they have any influence: Mechanics are the art of regulating the motions of bodies to some designed end or purpose; and the reason why we employ arithmetic in fixing the proportions of numbers, is only that we may discover the proportions of their influence and operation. A merchant is desirous of knowing the sum total of his accounts with any person: Why? but that he may learn what sum will have the same effects in paying his debt, and going to market, as all the particular articles taken together. Abstract or demonstrative reasoning, therefore, never influences any of our actions, but only as it directs our judgment concerning causes and effects; which leads us to the second operation of the understanding.
The understanding operates in two different ways: it judges from demonstration or probability, and it looks at the abstract relationships of our ideas or the relationships of objects that experience teaches us. It's hard to say that the first type of reasoning alone causes any action. Since its main focus is the world of ideas, and the will always places us in the realm of reality, demonstration and will seem to be completely separate from each other. Mathematics is indeed useful in all mechanical tasks, and arithmetic in almost every trade and profession. However, they don’t have any influence by themselves. Mechanics is about controlling the movements of objects for a specific goal or purpose, and we use arithmetic to determine the proportions of numbers only to understand their effects and functions. A merchant wants to know the total of their accounts with someone—why? So they can find out what amount will have the same impact on paying off their debt and shopping as all the individual items combined. Therefore, abstract or demonstrative reasoning doesn’t influence our actions directly, but it does guide our judgment about causes and effects, which leads us to the second function of the understanding.
It is obvious, that when we have the prospect of pain or pleasure from any object, we feel a consequent emotion of aversion or propensity, and are carryed to avoid or embrace what will give us this uneasines or satisfaction. It is also obvious, that this emotion rests not here, but making us cast our view on every side, comprehends whatever objects are connected with its original one by the relation of cause and effect. Here then reasoning takes place to discover this relation; and according as our reasoning varies, our actions receive a subsequent variation. But it is evident in this case that the impulse arises not from reason, but is only directed by it. It is from the prospect of pain or pleasure that the aversion or propensity arises towards any object: And these emotions extend themselves to the causes and effects of that object, as they are pointed out to us by reason and experience. It can never in the least concern us to know, that such objects are causes, and such others effects, if both the causes and effects be indifferent to us. Where the objects themselves do not affect us, their connexion can never give them any influence; and it is plain, that as reason is nothing but the discovery of this connexion, it cannot be by its means that the objects are able to affect us.
It’s clear that when we anticipate pain or pleasure from something, we feel a strong emotion of dislike or desire, which leads us to avoid or seek out what will cause us discomfort or happiness. It's also obvious that this emotion doesn't stop there; it prompts us to consider all related objects that are linked to the original one by the connection of cause and effect. This is where reasoning comes into play to uncover this connection; and as our reasoning changes, our actions change accordingly. However, it's evident that the initial impulse doesn’t come from reason; it is only guided by it. The dislike or desire we feel towards any object arises from the expectation of pain or pleasure. These emotions also extend to the causes and effects related to that object, as indicated by reason and experience. It doesn’t really matter to us to know that some objects are causes and others are effects if we have no interest in either. If the objects themselves don’t impact us, their connection will never give them any influence; and it’s clear that since reason is just the discovery of this connection, it can't be the reason that these objects influence us.
Since reason alone can never produce any action, or give rise to volition, I infer, that the same faculty is as incapable of preventing volition, or of disputing the preference with any passion or emotion. This consequence is necessary. It is impossible reason could have the latter effect of preventing volition, but by giving an impulse in a contrary direction to our passion; and that impulse, had it operated alone, would have been able to produce volition. Nothing can oppose or retard the impulse of passion, but a contrary impulse; and if this contrary impulse ever arises from reason, that latter faculty must have an original influence on the will, and must be able to cause, as well as hinder any act of volition. But if reason has no original influence, it is impossible it can withstand any principle, which has such an efficacy, or ever keep the mind in suspence a moment. Thus it appears, that the principle, which opposes our passion, cannot be the same with reason, and is only called so in an improper sense. We speak not strictly and philosophically when we talk of the combat of passion and of reason. Reason is, and ought only to be the slave of the passions, and can never pretend to any other office than to serve and obey them. As this opinion may appear somewhat extraordinary, it may not be improper to confirm it by some other considerations.
Since reason alone can never lead to any action or drive desire, I conclude that it’s equally unable to prevent desire or compete with any passion or emotion. This outcome is necessary. It’s impossible for reason to prevent desire unless it provides a counter impulse to our passion, and that impulse, if it acted alone, would be able to create desire. Nothing can oppose or slow down the drive of passion except a conflicting impulse; if that contradictory impulse comes from reason, then reason must have some original influence on the will, capable of both producing and hindering any act of desire. But if reason has no original influence, it’s impossible for it to resist any principle that has such power or keep the mind in suspense for even a moment. Thus, it seems that the principle opposing our passion cannot be the same as reason and is only referred to as such in a loose sense. We don’t speak strictly or philosophically when we discuss the struggle between passion and reason. Reason is, and should only be, the servant of the passions, and can never claim any other role than to support and obey them. Since this view might seem a bit unusual, it may be helpful to back it up with some other points.
A passion is an original existence, or, if you will, modification of existence, and contains not any representative quality, which renders it a copy of any other existence or modification. When I am angry, I am actually possest with the passion, and in that emotion have no more a reference to any other object, than when I am thirsty, or sick, or more than five foot high. It is impossible, therefore, that this passion can be opposed by, or be contradictory to truth and reason; since this contradiction consists in the disagreement of ideas, considered as copies, with those objects, which they represent.
A passion is a unique state of being, or, if you prefer, a variation of existence, and doesn’t have any representative quality that makes it a copy of any other state or variation. When I’m angry, I’m truly filled with that passion, and in that state, I have no reference to anything else, just like when I’m thirsty, sick, or taller than five feet. Therefore, it’s impossible for this passion to contradict truth and reason because that contradiction is about the mismatch of ideas, viewed as copies, with the objects they represent.
What may at first occur on this head, is, that as nothing can be contrary to truth or reason, except what has a reference to it, and as the judgments of our understanding only have this reference, it must follow, that passions can be contrary to reason only so far as they are accompanyed with some judgment or opinion. According to this principle, which is so obvious and natural, it is only in two senses, that any affection can be called unreasonable. First, When a passion, such as hope or fear, grief or joy, despair or security, is founded on the supposition or the existence of objects, which really do not exist. Secondly, When in exerting any passion in action, we chuse means insufficient for the designed end, and deceive ourselves in our judgment of causes and effects. Where a passion is neither founded on false suppositions, nor chuses means insufficient for the end, the understanding can neither justify nor condemn it. It is not contrary to reason to prefer the destruction of the whole world to the scratching of my finger. It is not contrary to reason for me to chuse my total ruin, to prevent the least uneasiness of an Indian or person wholly unknown to me. It is as little contrary to reason to prefer even my own acknowledgeed lesser good to my greater, and have a more ardent affection for the former than the latter. A trivial good may, from certain circumstances, produce a desire superior to what arises from the greatest and most valuable enjoyment; nor is there any thing more extraordinary in this, than in mechanics to see one pound weight raise up a hundred by the advantage of its situation. In short, a passion must be accompanyed with some false judgment in order to its being unreasonable; and even then it is not the passion, properly speaking, which is unreasonable, but the judgment.
What might first come to mind on this topic is that nothing can be against truth or reason, except for things that relate to them, and since our understanding's judgments only relate to these, it follows that emotions can only contradict reason when they are accompanied by some judgment or opinion. Following this clear and natural principle, an emotion can be considered unreasonable in two ways. First, when an emotion, like hope or fear, sadness or joy, despair or security, is based on the assumption or existence of things that do not really exist. Second, when we act on any emotion using means that are inadequate for achieving the intended outcome, and we misjudge the causes and effects involved. When an emotion is neither based on false assumptions nor uses inadequate means, reason cannot justify or condemn it. It is not unreasonable to prefer the destruction of the entire world over a minor injury to my finger. It is not unreasonable for me to choose my complete downfall to avoid causing the slightest discomfort to an Indian or someone I don’t know at all. It’s also not unreasonable to prefer a recognized lesser good over a greater one and have stronger feelings for the former. A minor benefit may, under certain circumstances, create a desire that surpasses that which comes from the greatest and most valuable enjoyment; and there’s nothing more extraordinary in this than seeing one pound of weight lift a hundred by virtue of its position. In short, an emotion must be accompanied by some false judgment to be considered unreasonable; and even then, it’s not the emotion itself that is unreasonable, but the judgment.
The consequences are evident. Since a passion can never, in any sense, be called unreasonable, but when founded on a false supposition or when it chuses means insufficient for the designed end, it is impossible, that reason and passion can ever oppose each other, or dispute for the government of the will and actions. The moment we perceive the falshood of any supposition, or the insufficiency of any means our passions yield to our reason without any opposition. I may desire any fruit as of an excellent relish; but whenever you convince me of my mistake, my longing ceases. I may will the performance of certain actions as means of obtaining any desired good; but as my willing of these actions is only secondary, and founded on the supposition, that they are causes of the proposed effect; as soon as I discover the falshood of that supposition, they must become indifferent to me.
The consequences are clear. A passion can never truly be considered unreasonable; it only becomes an issue when it's based on a false assumption or when it uses inadequate means to achieve its goal. It's impossible for reason and passion to truly conflict or argue over control of our will and actions. The moment we recognize the falsehood of any assumption or the inadequacy of any means, our passions submit to our reason without any resistance. I might crave a fruit because it seems delicious, but once you show me I'm wrong, my craving disappears. I may want to perform certain actions to gain something I desire, but since my willingness to take those actions is only secondary and based on the belief that they will lead to the desired outcome, once I realize that belief is false, those actions become irrelevant to me.
It is natural for one, that does not examine objects with a strict philosophic eye, to imagine, that those actions of the mind are entirely the same, which produce not a different sensation, and are not immediately distinguishable to the feeling and perception. Reason, for instance, exerts itself without producing any sensible emotion; and except in the more sublime disquisitions of philosophy, or in the frivolous subtilties of the school, scarce ever conveys any pleasure or uneasiness. Hence it proceeds, that every action of the mind, which operates with the same calmness and tranquillity, is confounded with reason by all those, who judge of things from the first view and appearance. Now it is certain, there are certain calm desires and tendencies, which, though they be real passions, produce little emotion in the mind, and are more known by their effects than by the immediate feeling or sensation. These desires are of two kinds; either certain instincts originally implanted in our natures, such as benevolence and resentment, the love of life, and kindness to children; or the general appetite to good, and aversion to evil, considered merely as such. When any of these passions are calm, and cause no disorder in the soul, they are very readily taken for the determinations of reason, and are supposed to proceed from the same faculty, with that, which judges of truth and falshood. Their nature and principles have been supposed the same, because their sensations are not evidently different.
It's natural for someone who doesn't look at things with a careful philosophical perspective to think that mental processes that don't create different feelings are completely the same and aren't immediately distinguishable by emotion or perception. Reason, for example, works without causing any noticeable emotion; and aside from the more profound discussions in philosophy or the trivial subtleties of academia, it rarely brings any pleasure or discomfort. This leads to the conclusion that every mental action that operates with the same calmness and peace is confused with reason by those who judge based on initial appearances. Now, it's clear that there are certain calm desires and inclinations, which, although they are genuine passions, produce little emotion in the mind and are known more by their effects than by immediate feelings or sensations. These desires can be categorized into two types: either certain instincts rooted in human nature, like kindness and resentment, the love of life, and care for children; or a general desire for good and a dislike for evil, seen merely as such. When any of these passions are calm and don't disturb the soul, they are easily mistaken for the decisions of reason and are thought to arise from the same faculty that judges truth and falsehood. Their nature and principles are assumed to be the same because their sensations are not clearly different.
Beside these calm passions, which often determine the will, there are certain violent emotions of the same kind, which have likewise a great influence on that faculty. When I receive any injury from another, I often feel a violent passion of resentment, which makes me desire his evil and punishment, independent of all considerations of pleasure and advantage to myself. When I am immediately threatened with any grievous ill, my fears, apprehensions, and aversions rise to a great height, and produce a sensible emotion.
Alongside these peaceful feelings that often guide our choices, there are also intense emotions of a similar nature that significantly impact our decision-making. When someone wrongs me, I frequently experience a strong sense of resentment, which drives me to wish for their downfall and punishment, regardless of any potential pleasure or benefit to myself. When I face an immediate threat of serious harm, my fears, anxieties, and aversions surge to a high level, creating a noticeable emotional response.
The common error of metaphysicians has lain in ascribing the direction of the will entirely to one of these principles, and supposing the other to have no influence. Men often act knowingly against their interest: For which reason the view of the greatest possible good does not always influence them. Men often counter-act a violent passion in prosecution of their interests and designs: It is not therefore the present uneasiness alone, which determines them. In general we may observe, that both these principles operate on the will; and where they are contrary, that either of them prevails, according to the general character or present disposition of the person. What we call strength of mind, implies the prevalence of the calm passions above the violent; though we may easily observe, there is no man so constantly possessed of this virtue, as never on any occasion to yield to the sollicitations of passion and desire. From these variations of temper proceeds the great difficulty of deciding concerning the actions and resolutions of men, where there is any contrariety of motives and passions.
The common mistake of philosophers has been to attribute the direction of the will entirely to one of these principles, assuming the other has no impact. People often knowingly act against their own interests, which is why the idea of achieving the greatest good doesn't always guide their actions. Individuals frequently resist strong emotions in pursuit of their interests and goals, so it's not just their current discomfort that drives their decisions. In general, we can see that both principles influence the will; when they conflict, one will dominate based on the person's overall character or current mood. What we refer to as strength of mind means that calm emotions outweigh strong desires, although it’s clear that no one consistently possesses this virtue to the point of never giving in to the urges of passion and desire. This variability in temperament leads to the significant challenge of understanding people's actions and decisions when they have conflicting motivations and emotions.
SECT. IV OF THE CAUSES OF THE VIOLENT PASSIONS
There is not in philosophy a subject of more nice speculation than this of the different causes and effects of the calm and violent passions. It is evident passions influence not the will in proportion to their violence, or the disorder they occasion in the temper; but on the contrary, that when a passion has once become a settled principle of action, and is the predominant inclination of the soul, it commonly produces no longer any sensible agitation. As repeated custom and its own force have made every thing yield to it, it directs the actions and conduct without that opposition and emotion, which so naturally attend every momentary gust of passion. We must, therefore, distinguish betwixt a calm and a weak passion; betwixt a violent and a strong one. But notwithstanding this, it is certain, that when we would govern a man, and push him to any action, it will commonly be better policy to work upon the violent than the calm passions, and rather take him by his inclination, than what is vulgarly called his reason. We ought to place the object in such particular situations as are proper to encrease the violence of the passion. For we may observe, that all depends upon the situation of the object, and that a variation in this particular will be able to change the calm and the violent passions into each other. Both these kinds of passions pursue good, and avoid evil; and both of them are encreased or diminished by the encrease or diminution of the good or evil. But herein lies the difference betwixt them: The same good, when near, will cause a violent passion, which, when remote, produces only a calm one. As this subject belongs very properly to the present question concerning the will, we shall here examine it to the bottom, and shall consider some of those circumstances and situations of objects, which render a passion either calm or violent.
There isn't a topic in philosophy that invites more careful thought than the different causes and effects of calm and intense emotions. It's clear that emotions don't influence the will based only on their intensity or the chaos they create in someone's mood. Instead, when an emotion becomes a consistent drive for action and is the main inclination of someone's mind, it usually results in little noticeable turmoil. As repeated habits and their own strength have made everything submit to them, such emotions guide actions and behavior without the resistance and turmoil that often come with temporary bursts of emotion. Therefore, we need to differentiate between a calm and a weak emotion, and between a violent and a strong one. However, it’s true that when we want to influence someone and encourage them to take action, it’s generally more effective to tap into intense emotions rather than calm ones and to appeal to their inclinations rather than what is commonly called their reason. We should present the object in specific circumstances that will heighten the intensity of the emotion. We can see that everything hinges on the context of the object, and a change in this aspect can transform calm emotions into intense ones, and vice versa. Both types of emotions seek good and steer clear of evil, and both can grow or shrink in response to increasing or decreasing good or evil. The key difference lies here: the same good, when close, will spark an intense emotion, while when it's distant, it only evokes a calm one. Since this topic relates directly to our current discussion about the will, we will examine it thoroughly and look at some of the circumstances and situations of objects that make an emotion either calm or intense.
It is a remarkable property of human nature, that any emotion, which attends a passion, is easily converted into it, though in their natures they be originally different from, and even contrary to each other. It is true; in order to make a perfect union among passions, there is always required a double relation of impressions and ideas; nor is one relation sufficient for that purpose. But though this be confirmed by undoubted experience, we must understand it with its proper limitations, and must regard the double relation, as requisite only to make one passion produce another. When two passions are already produced by their separate causes, and are both present in the mind, they readily mingle and unite, though they have but one relation, and sometimes without any. The predominant passion swallows up the inferior, and converts it into itself. The spirits, when once excited, easily receive a change in their direction; and it is natural to imagine this change will come from the prevailing affection. The connexion is in many respects closer betwixt any two passions, than betwixt any passion and indifference.
It's a fascinating aspect of human nature that any emotion associated with a passion can easily turn into that passion, even if they are originally different or even opposing. To achieve a perfect blend of passions, a double connection between impressions and ideas is usually needed; a single connection isn't enough for that. However, while this is supported by clear experience, we need to understand it within its proper limits and see that the double connection is only necessary for one passion to trigger another. When two passions already arise from their own causes and are both present in the mind, they can easily mix and combine, even if there’s just one connection or sometimes none at all. The stronger passion tends to dominate and absorb the weaker one. Once the spirits are stirred, they can easily change direction; it's natural to assume this change will come from the strongest feeling. The relationship between any two passions is often stronger than the relationship between a passion and indifference.
When a person is once heartily in love, the little faults and caprices of his mistress, the jealousies and quarrels, to which that commerce is so subject; however unpleasant and related to anger and hatred; are yet found to give additional force to the prevailing passion. It is a common artifice of politicians, when they would affect any person very much by a matter of fact, of which they intend to inform him, first to excite his curiosity; delay as long as possible the satisfying it; and by that means raise his anxiety and impatience to the utmost, before they give him a full insight into the business. They know that his curiosity will precipitate him into the passion they design to raise, and assist the object in its influence on the mind. A soldier advancing to the battle, is naturally inspired with courage and confidence, when he thinks on his friends and fellow-soldiers; and is struck with fear and terror, when he reflects on the enemy. Whatever new emotion, therefore, proceeds from the former naturally encreases the courage; as the same emotion, proceeding from the latter, augments the fear; by the relation of ideas, and the conversion of the inferior emotion into the predominant. Hence it is that in martial discipline, the uniformity and lustre of our habit, the regularity of our figures and motions, with all the pomp and majesty of war, encourage ourselves and allies; while the same objects in the enemy strike terror into us, though agreeable and beautiful in themselves.
When someone is truly in love, the little flaws and quirks of their partner, along with the jealousy and arguments that often come with it—no matter how unpleasant and related to anger and hatred—actually end up intensifying the main feeling. Politicians often use a tactic where, if they want to deeply influence someone with some fact they plan to reveal, they first pique their curiosity; they hold off on satisfying that curiosity for as long as possible, which maximizes the person’s anxiety and impatience before revealing the full story. They understand that this curiosity will pull the person into the emotion they want to provoke and enhance its impact on the mind. A soldier heading into battle naturally feels brave and confident when thinking about friends and fellow soldiers but feels fear and dread when considering the enemy. Any new emotion tied to the former boosts courage, while the latter heightens fear due to the connection of ideas and the transformation of lesser feelings into the dominant ones. That’s why, in military training, the uniformity and shine of our uniforms, the orderliness of our formations and movements, along with all the pageantry and glory of war, uplift us and our allies; meanwhile, the same aspects in the enemy scare us, even if they are appealing and beautiful on their own.
Since passions, however independent, are naturally transfused into each other, if they are both present at the same time; it follows, that when good or evil is placed in such a situation, as to cause any particular emotion, beside its direct passion of desire or aversion, that latter passion must acquire new force and violence.
Since passions, although independent, naturally influence each other when they coexist; it follows that when good or evil is in a situation that triggers a specific emotion, alongside its direct feeling of desire or aversion, that feeling must gain new strength and intensity.
This happens, among other cases, whenever any object excites contrary passions. For it is observable that an opposition of passions commonly causes a new emotion in the spirits, and produces more disorder, than the concurrence of any two affections of equal force. This new emotion is easily converted into the predominant passion, and encreases its violence, beyond the pitch it would have arrived at had it met with no opposition. Hence we naturally desire what is forbid, and take a pleasure in performing actions, merely because they are unlawful. The notion of duty, when opposite to the passions, is seldom able to overcome them; and when it fails of that effect, is apt rather to encrease them, by producing an opposition in our motives and principles. The same effect follows whether the opposition arises from internal motives or external obstacles. The passion commonly acquires new force and violence in both cases.
This happens, among other situations, whenever an object stirs up conflicting emotions. It's noticeable that when passions oppose each other, it usually creates a new feeling within us and leads to more disorder than if two feelings of equal strength were working together. This new emotion can easily be transformed into the dominant passion, increasing its intensity beyond what it would have reached without any conflict. As a result, we naturally desire what is forbidden and find pleasure in doing things simply because they’re illegal. The idea of duty, when it clashes with our emotions, rarely manages to overcome them; and when it fails, it often just amplifies them by creating a conflict in our motives and principles. The same result occurs whether the conflict comes from internal motivations or external obstacles. In both cases, the passion tends to gain new strength and intensity.
The efforts, which the mind makes to surmount the obstacle, excite the spirits and inliven the passion.
The effort that the mind puts in to overcome obstacles boosts energy and ignites passion.
Uncertainty has the same influence as opposition. The agitation of the thought; the quick turns it makes from one view to another; the variety of passions, which succeed each other, according to the different views; All these produce an agitation in the mind, and transfuse themselves into the predominant passion.
Uncertainty has the same effect as opposition. The turmoil of thought, the rapid shifts from one perspective to another, the different emotions that follow one after the other based on these perspectives—all create a disturbance in the mind and blend into the main emotion.
There is not in my opinion any other natural cause, why security diminishes the passions, than because it removes that uncertainty, which encreases them. The mind, when left to itself, immediately languishes; and in order to preserve its ardour, must be every moment supported by a new flow of passion. For the same reason, despair, though contrary to security, has a like influence.
In my view, there’s no other natural reason why security lessens our feelings than because it eliminates the uncertainty that increases them. When the mind is left alone, it quickly loses its energy; to keep its enthusiasm alive, it needs a constant surge of new passions. Similarly, despair, even though it goes against security, has a similar effect.
It is certain nothing more powerfully animates any affection, than to conceal some part of its object by throwing it into a kind of shade, which at the same time that it chews enough to pre-possess us in favour of the object, leaves still some work for the imagination. Besides that obscurity is always attended with a kind of uncertainty; the effort, which the fancy makes to compleat the idea, rouzes the spirits, and gives an additional force to the passion.
Nothing fuels our feelings more than hiding part of what we desire in a way that intrigues us. This approach not only gives us a glimpse that makes us favor the object but also leaves room for our imagination to fill in the gaps. Additionally, this sense of mystery brings a level of uncertainty; the effort our mind puts in to complete the idea energizes us and intensifies our emotions.
As despair and security, though contrary to each other, produce the same effects; so absence is observed to have contrary effects, and in different circumstances either encreases or diminishes our affections. The Duc de La Rochefoucault has very well observed, that absence destroys weak passions, but encreases strong; as the wind extinguishes a candle, but blows up a fire. Long absence naturally weakens our idea, and diminishes the passion: But where the idea is so strong and lively as to support itself, the uneasiness, arising from absence, encreases the passion and gives it new force and violence.
As despair and security, even though they are opposites, produce similar effects; absence is noted to have opposite effects and, depending on the situation, can either increase or decrease our emotions. The Duc de La Rochefoucauld pointed out that absence weakens weak passions but strengthens strong ones; like how the wind puts out a candle but fuels a fire. Prolonged absence naturally weakens our perception and lessens the passion. However, when the idea is strong and vivid enough to stand on its own, the discomfort from being apart can increase the passion and give it new intensity and force.
SECT. V OF THE EFFECTS OF CUSTOM
But nothing has a greater effect both to encrease and diminish our passions, to convert pleasure into pain, and pain into pleasure, than custom and repetition. Custom has two original effects upon the mind, in bestowing a facility in the performance of any action or the conception of any object; and afterwards a tendency or inclination towards it; and from these we may account for all its other effects, however extraordinary.
But nothing has a greater impact on increasing or decreasing our emotions, turning pleasure into pain and pain into pleasure, than habit and repetition. Habit has two main effects on the mind: it makes it easier to perform any action or understand any concept, and it creates a tendency or inclination toward it. From these effects, we can explain all its other influences, no matter how unusual.
When the soul applies itself to the performance of any action, or the conception of any object, to which it is not accustomed, there is a certain unpliableness in the faculties, and a difficulty of the spirit's moving in their new direction. As this difficulty excites the spirits, it is the source of wonder, surprize, and of all the emotions, which arise from novelty; and is in itself very agreeable, like every thing, which inlivens the mind to a moderate degree. But though surprize be agreeable in itself, yet as it puts the spirits in agitation, it not only augments our agreeable affections, but also our painful, according to the foregoing principle, that every emotion, which precedes or attends a passion, is easily converted into it. Hence every thing, that is new, is most affecting, and gives us either more pleasure or pain, than what, strictly speaking, naturally belongs to it. When it often returns upon us, the novelty wears off; the passions subside; the hurry of the spirits is over; and we survey the objects with greater tranquillity.
When the soul engages in any action or thinks about any idea it's not used to, there's a certain stiffness in its abilities, and the spirit finds it difficult to move in this new direction. This difficulty stirs up our emotions, leading to feelings of wonder, surprise, and all the emotions that come from new experiences; it's quite enjoyable, similar to anything that stimulates the mind in moderation. However, even though surprise is enjoyable on its own, it causes agitation, which not only increases our pleasant feelings but can also heighten our unpleasant ones, based on the idea that any emotion that comes before or alongside a feeling can easily turn into that feeling. Therefore, everything new can have a stronger impact on us, bringing either more pleasure or pain than what would normally be expected. When these new experiences happen repeatedly, the novelty fades; our emotions settle down; the rush settles; and we look at things with greater calm.
By degrees the repetition produces a facility of the human mind, and an infallible source of pleasure, where the facility goes not beyond a certain degree. And here it is remarkable that the pleasure, which arises from a moderate facility, has not the same tendency with that which arises from novelty, to augment the painful, as well as the agreeable affections. The pleasure of facility does not so much consist in any ferment of the spirits, as in their orderly motion; which will sometimes be so powerful as even to convert pain into pleasure, and give us a relish in time what at first was most harsh and disagreeable.
Over time, repetition creates an ease in the human mind and an undeniable source of pleasure, as long as this ease doesn't exceed a certain limit. It's interesting to note that the pleasure from a balanced ease doesn't have the same effect as the pleasure from novelty, which can increase both our joyful and painful feelings. The pleasure from ease isn't really about a surge of emotions, but rather about their smooth flow; this smoothness can be so strong that it turns pain into pleasure, allowing us to eventually enjoy what once seemed harsh and unpleasant.
But again, as facility converts pain into pleasure, so it often converts pleasure into pain, when it is too great, and renders the actions of the mind so faint and languid, that they are no longer able to interest and support it. And indeed, scarce any other objects become disagreeable through custom; but such as are naturally attended with some emotion or affection, which is destroyed by the too frequent repetition. One can consider the clouds, and heavens, and trees, and stones, however frequently repeated, without ever feeling any aversion. But when the fair sex, or music, or good cheer, or any thing, that naturally ought to be agreeable, becomes indifferent, it easily produces the opposite affection.
But just as our comfort can turn pain into pleasure, it can also turn pleasure into pain when it's too much, causing our minds to feel dull and weak, making it hard to stay engaged or motivated. In fact, not many things become unpleasant from being repeated; usually, it's those that evoke some kind of emotion or feeling that lose their appeal through overexposure. You can look at clouds, the sky, trees, or rocks as often as you want without gaining any dislike for them. But when it comes to things that should be enjoyable, like women, music, or good food, if they become bland due to repetition, they can easily start to feel unpleasant.
But custom not only gives a facility to perform any action, but likewise an inclination and tendency towards it, where it is not entirely disagreeable, and can never be the object of inclination. And this is the reason why custom encreases all active habits, but diminishes passive, according to the observation of a late eminent philosopher. The facility takes off from the force of the passive habits by rendering the motion of the spirits faint and languid. But as in the active, the spirits are sufficiently supported of themselves, the tendency of the mind gives them new force, and bends them more strongly to the action.
But habit not only makes it easier to do something, but also creates a desire and tendency towards it when it's not completely unpleasant, and can never be the focus of desire. This is why habit strengthens all active behaviors but weakens passive ones, according to a recent notable philosopher. The ease diminishes the power of passive habits by making the movement of the mind dull and sluggish. However, in active behaviors, the mind is adequately energized on its own, so the inclination gives it new strength and pushes it more strongly towards the action.
SECT. VI OF THE INFLUENCE OF THE IMAGINATION ON THE PASSIONS
It is remarkable, that the imagination and affections have close union together, and that nothing, which affects the former, can be entirely indifferent to the latter. Wherever our ideas of good or evil acquire a new vivacity, the passions become more violent; and keep pace with the imagination in all its variations. Whether this proceeds from the principle above-mentioned, that any attendant emotion is easily converted into the predominant, I shall not determine. It is sufficient for my present purpose, that we have many instances to confirm this influence of the imagination upon the passions.
It’s remarkable how closely connected imagination and emotions are, and that nothing affecting one can be completely indifferent to the other. Whenever our ideas of good or evil become more intense, our passions grow stronger and match the fluctuations of our imagination. I won’t decide whether this comes from the principle mentioned above, that any accompanying emotion can easily turn into the dominant one. For my current purpose, it’s enough to say that we have many examples that confirm this influence of imagination on our passions.
Any pleasure, with which we are acquainted, affects us more than any other, which we own to be superior, but of whose nature we are wholly ignorant. Of the one we can form a particular and determinate idea: The other we conceive under the general notion of pleasure; and it is certain, that the more general and universal any of our ideas are, the less influence they have upon the imagination. A general idea, though it be nothing but a particular one considered in a certain view, is commonly more obscure; and that because no particular idea, by which we represent a general one, is ever fixed or determinate, but may easily be changed for other particular ones, which will serve equally in the representation.
Any pleasure we know affects us more than any other pleasure we acknowledge as better, but of which we understand nothing. We can form a specific and clear idea of the first one: The other is just understood as pleasure in general; and it's true that the more general and universal our ideas are, the less impact they have on our imagination. A general idea, even if it’s just a particular one viewed in a certain way, tends to be more unclear; this is because no specific idea used to describe a general one is ever fixed or clear, but can easily be swapped for other specific ones that serve just as well in the description.
There is a noted passage in the history of Greece, which may serve for our present purpose. Themistocles told the Athenians, that he had formed a design, which would be highly useful to the public, but which it was impossible for him to communicate to them without ruining the execution, since its success depended entirely on the secrecy with which it should be conducted. The Athenians, instead of granting him full power to act as he thought fitting, ordered him to communicate his design to Aristides, in whose prudence they had an entire confidence, and whose opinion they were resolved blindly to submit to. The design of Themistocles was secretly to set fire to the fleet of all the Grecian commonwealths, which was assembled in a neighbouring port, and which being once destroyed would give the Athenians the empire of the sea without any rival Aristides returned to the assembly, and told them, that nothing could be more advantageous than the design of Themistocles but at the same time that nothing could be more unjust: Upon which the people unanimously rejected the project.
There's a notable moment in Greek history that can illustrate our point. Themistocles informed the Athenians that he had come up with a plan that would greatly benefit the public, but he couldn't share it with them without jeopardizing its execution, as its success relied completely on keeping it secret. Instead of giving him full authority to act as he deemed necessary, the Athenians insisted that he share his plan with Aristides, someone they fully trusted and whose judgment they were determined to follow without question. Themistocles's plan was to secretly set fire to the fleet of all the Greek city-states gathered in a nearby port, which, if destroyed, would allow the Athenians to dominate the sea without competition. Aristides returned to the assembly and stated that nothing could be more beneficial than Themistocles's plan, but at the same time, nothing could be more unjust. As a result, the people unanimously rejected the idea.
A late celebrated historian[1] admires this passage of antient history, as one of the most singular that is any where to be met.
A well-known historian[1] admires this passage from ancient history as one of the most unique found anywhere.
[1] Mons. Rollin {Charles Rollin, HISTOIRE ANCIENNE.(Paris 1730-38)}.
[1] Mons. Rollin {Charles Rollin, HISTOIRE ANCIENNE.(Paris 1730-38)}.
"Here," says he, "they are not philosophers, to whom it is easy in their schools to establish the finest maxims and most sublime rules of morality, who decide that interest ought never to prevail above justice. It is a whole people interested in the proposal which is made to them, who consider it as of importance to the public good, and who notwithstanding reject it unanimously, and without hesitation, merely because it is contrary to justice."
"Here," he says, "they're not philosophers who can easily come up with the best maxims and the highest moral guidelines in their classrooms. They argue that self-interest should never take precedence over justice. It's an entire population that's invested in the proposal put before them, viewing it as important for the public good, and yet they reject it collectively and without doubt, simply because it goes against justice."
For my part I see nothing so extraordinary in this proceeding of the Athenians. The same reasons, which render it so easy for philosophers to establish these sublime maxims, tend, in part, to diminish the merit of such a conduct in that people. Philosophers never ballance betwixt profit and honesty, because their decisions are general, and neither their passions nor imaginations are interested in the objects. And though in the present case the advantage was immediate to the Athenians, yet as it was known only under the general notion of advantage, without being conceived by any particular idea, it must have had a less considerable influence on their imaginations, and have been a less violent temptation, than if they had been acquainted with all its circumstances: Otherwise it is difficult to conceive, that a whole people, unjust and violent as men commonly are, should so unanimously have adhered to justice, and rejected any considerable advantage.
I don’t find anything particularly extraordinary about what the Athenians did. The same reasons that make it easy for philosophers to establish these profound principles also somewhat lessen the merit of the Athenians' actions. Philosophers don’t weigh profit against honesty because their judgments are broad, and their emotions or imaginations aren’t tied to specific outcomes. Although the advantage was immediate for the Athenians, it was only understood in a general sense of benefit, without any specific details in mind. This likely made it less impactful on their imaginations and a weaker temptation than if they had been aware of all the details. Otherwise, it’s hard to believe that an entire people, as unjust and violent as people typically are, would have so unanimously stuck to justice while turning down a significant advantage.
Any satisfaction, which we lately enjoyed, and of which the memory is fresh and recent, operates on the will with more violence, than another of which the traces are decayed, and almost obliterated. From whence does this proceed, but that the memory in the first case assists the fancy and gives an additional force and vigour to its conceptions? The image of the past pleasure being strong and violent, bestows these qualities on the idea of the future pleasure, which is connected with it by the relation of resemblance.
Any satisfaction we recently enjoyed, and whose memory is still fresh, affects our will more intensely than one whose traces have faded and are nearly forgotten. Where does this come from, if not from the fact that the memory in the first situation supports the imagination and adds extra strength and energy to its ideas? The vivid and intense image of past pleasure lends those qualities to the idea of future pleasure, which is linked to it through the resemblance.
A pleasure, which is suitable to the way of life, in which we are engaged, excites more our desires and appetites than another, which is foreign to it. This phænomenon may be explained from the same principle.
A pleasure that fits our way of life sparks our desires and appetites more than one that is unrelated to it. This phenomenon can be explained by the same principle.
Nothing is more capable of infusing any passion into the mind, than eloquence, by which objects are represented in their strongest and most lively colours. We may of ourselves acknowledge, that such an object is valuable, and such another odious; but until an orator excites the imagination, and gives force to these ideas, they may have but a feeble influence either on the will or the affections.
Nothing is better at igniting passion in the mind than eloquence, which presents things in their most vivid and powerful way. We can recognize that one thing is valuable and another is repulsive, but until a speaker stirs the imagination and strengthens these ideas, they have little impact on our will or feelings.
But eloquence is not always necessary. The bare opinion of another, especially when inforced with passion, will cause an idea of good or evil to have an influence upon us, which would otherwise have been entirely neglected. This proceeds from the principle of sympathy or communication; and sympathy, as I have already observed, is nothing but the conversion of an idea into an impression by the force of imagination.
But eloquence isn’t always needed. Someone’s straightforward opinion, especially when delivered with passion, can make a good or bad idea affect us in ways we would have completely overlooked otherwise. This comes from the principle of sympathy or communication; and sympathy, as I’ve mentioned before, is simply turning an idea into a feeling through the power of imagination.
It is remarkable, that lively passions commonly attend a lively imagination. In this respect, as well as others, the force of the passion depends as much on the temper of the person, as the nature or situation of the object.
It's interesting that strong emotions often come with a vibrant imagination. In this way, just like in other respects, the intensity of the emotion relies as much on the person's temperament as it does on the nature or circumstances of the object.
I have already observed, that belief is nothing but a lively idea related to a present impression. This vivacity is a requisite circumstance to the exciting all our passions, the calm as well as the violent; nor has a mere fiction of the imagination any considerable influence upon either of them. It is too weak to take hold of the mind, or be attended with emotion.
I've already noticed that belief is just a vivid idea connected to a current impression. This vividness is essential to triggering all our emotions, both calm and intense; a mere fabrication of the imagination has little impact on either. It's too weak to grasp the mind or evoke any feelings.
SECT. VII OF CONTIGUITY AND DISTANCE IN SPACE AND TIME
There is an easy reason, why every thing contiguous to us, either in space or time, should be conceived with a peculiar force and vivacity, and excel every other object, in its influence on the imagination. Ourself is intimately present to us, and whatever is related to self must partake of that quality. But where an object is so far removed as to have lost the advantage of this relation, why, as it is farther removed, its idea becomes still fainter and more obscure, would, perhaps, require a more particular examination.
There’s a simple reason why everything close to us, whether in space or time, is thought of with a unique intensity and clarity, making it more impactful on our imagination than anything else. Our own self is always right here with us, so anything connected to us shares that quality. However, when an object is far enough away that it’s lost that connection, the farther it is, the more its idea fades and becomes unclear; this might need a deeper look.
It is obvious, that the imagination can never totally forget the points of space and time, in which we are existent; but receives such frequent advertisements of them from the passions and senses, that however it may turn its attention to foreign and remote objects, it is necessitated every moment to reflect on the present. It is also remarkable, that in the conception of those objects, which we regard as real and existent, we take them in their proper order and situation, and never leap from one object to another, which is distant from it, without running over, at least in a cursory manner, all those objects, which are interposed betwixt them. When we reflect, therefore, on any object distant from ourselves, we are obliged not only to reach it at first by passing through all the intermediate space betwixt ourselves and the object, but also to renew our progress every moment; being every moment recalled to the consideration of ourselves and our present situation. It is easily conceived, that this interruption must weaken the idea by breaking the action of the mind, and hindering the conception from being so intense and continued, as when we reflect on a nearer object. The fewer steps we make to arrive at the object, and the smoother the road is, this diminution of vivacity is less sensibly felt, but still may be observed more or less in proportion to the degrees of distance and difficulty.
It's clear that the imagination can never completely forget the points of space and time we exist in; it gets frequent reminders from our emotions and senses. So, no matter how much we focus on distant or unrelated things, we are compelled to think about the present all the time. It's also interesting that when we think of things we consider real and present, we perceive them in their correct order and place, never jumping from one object to another far away without briefly acknowledging everything in between. Therefore, when we reflect on something far from us, we must first navigate through all the space between us and that object, and we have to keep doing this every moment, continually brought back to considerations of ourselves and our current situation. It's easy to understand that this interruption weakens the idea by disrupting our thought process, making it less intense and continuous compared to when we focus on something closer. The fewer steps we take to reach the object and the smoother the path, the less we notice this decrease in intensity, though it can still be observed to varying degrees based on distance and difficulty.
Here then we are to consider two kinds of objects, the contiguous and remote; of which the former, by means of their relation to ourselves, approach an impression in force and vivacity; the latter by reason of the interruption in our manner of conceiving them, appear in a weaker and more imperfect light. This is their effect on the imagination. If my reasoning be just, they must have a proportionable effect on the will and passions. Contiguous objects must have an influence much superior to the distant and remote. Accordingly we find in common life, that men are principally concerned about those objects, which are not much removed either in space or time, enjoying the present, and leaving what is afar off to the care of chance and fortune. Talk to a man of his condition thirty years hence, and he will not regard you. Speak of what is to happen tomorrow, and he will lend you attention. The breaking of a mirror gives us more concern when at home, than the burning of a house, when abroad, and some hundred leagues distant.
Here, we need to think about two types of objects: those that are nearby and those that are far away. The first type, because of how they relate to us, create a strong and vivid impression. The second type, due to the break in how we perceive them, seem weaker and less complete. This is the effect they have on our imagination. If my reasoning is correct, they also must have a corresponding effect on our will and emotions. Nearby objects must have a much greater influence compared to distant ones. In everyday life, we see that people mainly focus on things that are not far away in either space or time, enjoying what's happening now and leaving distant matters to chance and fate. If you talk to someone about their situation thirty years from now, they probably won't pay much attention. But if you mention what will happen tomorrow, they'll definitely listen. We care more about breaking a mirror at home than about a house burning down miles away.
But farther; though distance both in space and time has a considerable effect on the imagination, and by that means on the will and passions, yet the consequence of a removal in space are much inferior to those of a removal in time. Twenty years are certainly but a small distance of time in comparison of what history and even the memory of some may inform them of, and yet I doubt if a thousand leagues, or even the greatest distance of place this globe can admit of, will so remarkably weaken our ideas, and diminish our passions. A West-Indian merchant will tell you, that he is not without concern about what passes in Jamaica; though few extend their views so far into futurity, as to dread very remote accidents.
But further; although distance in both space and time significantly affects our imagination, which in turn influences our will and emotions, the impact of moving through space is much less than that of moving through time. Twenty years is definitely a short span of time compared to what history—and even the memories of some people—can tell us. Yet, I doubt that a thousand leagues, or even the farthest distance this planet can offer, will weaken our thoughts and lessen our feelings as much. A merchant from the West Indies will tell you that he’s still worried about what’s happening in Jamaica, even though few people think far enough ahead to fear very distant events.
The cause of this phænomenon must evidently lie in the different properties of space and time. Without having recourse to metaphysics, any one may easily observe, that space or extension consists of a number of co-existent parts disposed in a certain order, and capable of being at once present to the sight or feeling. On the contrary, time or succession, though it consists likewise of parts, never presents to us more than one at once; nor is it possible for any two of them ever to be co-existent. These qualities of the objects have a suitable effect on the imagination. The parts of extension being susceptible of an union to the senses, acquire an union in the fancy; and as the appearance of one part excludes not another, the transition or passage of the thought through the contiguous parts is by that means rendered more smooth and easy. On the other hand, the incompatibility of the parts of time in their real existence separates them in the imagination, and makes it more difficult for that faculty to trace any long succession or series of events. Every part must appear single and alone, nor can regularly have entrance into the fancy without banishing what is supposed to have been immediately precedent. By this means any distance in time causes a greater interruption in the thought than an equal distance in space, and consequently weakens more considerably the idea, and consequently the passions; which depend in a great measure, on the imagination, according to my system.
The reason for this phenomenon clearly lies in the different properties of space and time. Without diving into metaphysics, anyone can easily see that space, or extension, consists of several coexisting parts arranged in a certain order, and they can all be perceived at the same time. In contrast, time, or succession, also consists of parts, but we can only perceive one at a time; and no two parts can coexist. These qualities of objects have a specific effect on our imagination. The parts of extension can come together to be sensed, and they also connect in our minds. Since seeing one part doesn’t exclude another, the flow of thought through neighboring parts is made smoother and easier. On the other hand, the incompatibility of the parts of time in their actual existence separates them in our imagination, making it harder to follow a long series of events. Each part appears isolated, and it can't smoothly enter our thoughts without pushing aside whatever came right before it. As a result, any gap in time creates a bigger interruption in our thinking than an equal gap in space, weakening the idea and, consequently, the emotions, which, according to my system, rely heavily on the imagination.
There is another phænomenon of a like nature with the foregoing, viz, the superior effects of the same distance in futurity above that in the past. This difference with respect to the will is easily accounted for. As none of our actions can alter the past, it is not strange it should never determine the will. But with respect to the passions the question is yet entire, and well worth the examining.
There’s another phenomenon similar to the one mentioned before: the stronger effects of the same distance in the future compared to the past. This difference regarding will is easy to explain. Since none of our actions can change the past, it makes sense that the past never influences our will. However, when it comes to emotions, the question remains open and is worth looking into.
Besides the propensity to a gradual progression through the points of space and time, we have another peculiarity in our method of thinking, which concurs in producing this phænomenon. We always follow the succession of time in placing our ideas, and from the consideration of any object pass more easily to that, which follows immediately after it, than to that which went before it. We may learn this, among other instances, from the order, which is always observed in historical narrations. Nothing but an absolute necessity can oblige an historian to break the order of time, and in his narration give the precedence to an event, which was in reality posterior to another.
In addition to our tendency for a gradual progression through space and time, we have another characteristic in our way of thinking that contributes to this phenomenon. We always align our ideas with the flow of time, and we find it easier to move from one object to what comes immediately after it than to what came before it. This can be observed, among other examples, in the consistent order seen in historical narratives. Only an absolute necessity can force a historian to disrupt the chronological order and present an event that actually happened later as if it occurred earlier.
This will easily be applied to the question in hand, if we reflect on what I have before observed, that the present situation of the person is always that of the imagination, and that it is from thence we proceed to the conception of any distant object. When the object is past, the progression of the thought in passing to it from the present is contrary to nature, as proceeding from one point of time to that which is preceding, and from that to another preceding, in opposition to the natural course of the succession. On the other hand, when we turn our thought to a future object, our fancy flows along the stream of time, and arrives at the object by an order, which seems most natural, passing always from one point of time to that which is immediately posterior to it. This easy progression of ideas favours the imagination, and makes it conceive its object in a stronger and fuller light, than when we are continually opposed in our passage, and are obliged to overcome the difficulties arising from the natural propensity of the fancy. A small degree of distance in the past has, therefore, a greater effect, in interupting and weakening the conception, than a much greater in the future. From this effect of it on the imagination is derived its influence on the will and passions.
This can easily be related to the current issue at hand if we consider what I've mentioned before: that a person's present situation is always shaped by their imagination, and it’s from there that we envision any distant object. When the object is in the past, our thought process moving toward it from the present goes against nature, as it moves from one point in time to an earlier one, and then to another earlier one, contrary to the natural order of succession. However, when we focus our thoughts on a future object, our imagination flows along the timeline and reaches that object in an order that feels most natural, moving from one point in time to the next one that follows. This smooth flow of ideas supports the imagination and allows it to perceive its object more vividly and completely than when we face constant opposition in our journey, having to overcome the challenges that arise from our natural inclination. A slight distance in the past, therefore, has a stronger impact in interrupting and diluting our conception than a much greater distance in the future. The effect it has on the imagination, consequently, influences the will and emotions.
There is another cause, which both contributes to the same effect, and proceeds from the same quality of the fancy, by which we are determined to trace the succession of time by a similar succession of ideas. When from the present instant we consider two points of time equally distant in the future and in the past, it is evident, that, abstractedly considered, their relation to the present is almost equal. For as the future will sometime be present, so the past was once present. If we could, therefore, remove this quality of the imagination, an equal distance in the past and in the future, would have a similar influence. Nor is this only true, when the fancy remains fixed, and from the present instant surveys the future and the past; but also when it changes its situation, and places us in different periods of time. For as on the one hand, in supposing ourselves existent in a point of time interposed betwixt the present instant and the future object, we find the future object approach to us, and the past retire, and become more distant: so on the other hand, in supposing ourselves existent in a point of time interposed betwixt the present and the past, the past approaches to us, and the future becomes more distant. But from the property of the fancy above-mentioned we rather chuse to fix our thought on the point of time interposed betwixt the present and the future, than on that betwixt the present and the past. We advance, rather than retard our existence; and following what seems the natural succession of time, proceed from past to present, and from present to future. By which means we conceive the future as flowing every moment nearer us, and the past as retiring. An equal distance, therefore, in the past and in the future, has not the same effect on the imagination; and that because we consider the one as continually encreasing, and the other as continually diminishing. The fancy anticipates the course of things, and surveys the object in that condition, to which it tends, as well as in that, which is regarded as the present.
There’s another reason that both contributes to the same outcome and stems from the same quality of imagination, which leads us to track the passage of time through a similar sequence of thoughts. When we look at two moments in time that are equally far in the future and the past from this very moment, it’s clear that, when considered abstractly, their relationship to the present is nearly the same. Just as what is in the future will eventually be present, what is in the past was once present. If we could remove this quality of imagination, an equal distance in the past and the future would have a similar impact. This holds true not only when our imagination remains fixed, surveying the future and the past from the present moment, but also when it shifts, placing us in different time periods. For instance, if we imagine ourselves existing at a moment between the present and the future, we see the future drawing closer and the past receding. On the flip side, if we picture ourselves existing at a point between the present and the past, the past seems to move closer and the future appears more distant. However, because of the previously mentioned quality of imagination, we tend to focus our thoughts on the point of time between the present and the future more than on the one between the present and the past. We prefer to advance rather than hold back our existence, following what seems to be the natural order of time, moving from the past to the present and then from the present to the future. This way, we perceive the future as coming closer to us with each moment, while the past feels like it is fading away. Therefore, equal distances in the past and future do not have the same effect on our imagination; this is because we view one as continuously increasing and the other as continuously decreasing. The imagination anticipates the unfolding of events and observes the object in the state it’s heading toward, as well as in the state we consider present.
SECT. VIII THE SAME SUBJECT CONTINUED
Thus we have accounted for three phaenomena, which seem pretty remarkable. Why distance weakens the conception and passion: Why distance in time has a greater effect than that in space: And why distance in past time has still a greater effect than that in future. We must now consider three phaenomena, which seem to be, in a manner, the reverse of these: Why a very great distance encreases our esteem and admiration for an object; Why such a distance in time encreases it more than that in space: And a distance in past time more than that in future. The curiousness of the subject will, I hope, excuse my dwelling on it for some time.
So, we've looked at three phenomena that are quite striking. First, why distance diminishes our understanding and passion; second, why the passage of time impacts us more than physical distance; and third, why reflecting on the past affects us even more than thinking about the future. Now we need to examine three more phenomena that seem to somewhat reverse these: why a significant distance boosts our appreciation and admiration for something; why that distance in time increases our admiration more than distance in space; and why a distance in the past increases it more than a distance in the future. I hope the intriguing nature of this topic will justify my spending some time on it.
To begin with the first phænomenon, why a great distance encreases our esteem and admiration for an object; it is evident that the mere view and contemplation of any greatness, whether successive or extended, enlarges the soul, and give it a sensible delight and pleasure. A wide plain, the ocean, eternity, a succession of several ages; all these are entertaining objects, and excel every thing, however beautiful, which accompanies not its beauty with a suitable greatness. Now when any very distant object is presented to the imagination, we naturally reflect on the interposed distance, and by that means, conceiving something great and magnificent, receive the usual satisfaction. But as the fancy passes easily from one idea to another related to it, and transports to the second all the passions excited by the first, the admiration, which is directed to the distance, naturally diffuses itself over the distant object. Accordingly we find, that it is not necessary the object should be actually distant from us, in order to cause our admiration; but that it is sufficient, if, by the natural association of ideas, it conveys our view to any considerable distance. A great traveller, though in the same chamber, will pass for a very extraordinary person; as a Greek medal, even in our cabinet, is always esteemed a valuable curiosity. Here the object, by a natural transition, conveys our views to the distance; and the admiration, which arises from that distance, by another natural transition, returns back to the object.
To start with the first phenomenon, why a great distance increases our esteem and admiration for an object; it's clear that simply seeing and contemplating anything great, whether it's sequential or stretched out, expands our minds and gives us a tangible sense of delight and pleasure. A vast plain, the ocean, eternity, a series of ages; all these are captivating sights and surpass everything, no matter how beautiful, that doesn’t pair its beauty with a suitable sense of grandeur. When we see a very distant object in our minds, we naturally think about the distance in between, and by that, we imagine something great and magnificent, giving us the usual satisfaction. As our imagination easily moves from one related idea to another, it carries over all the emotions stirred by the first idea, so the admiration we feel for the distance naturally spreads to the distant object. Thus, we find that an object doesn’t need to actually be far away from us to inspire admiration; it’s enough if it naturally associates our thoughts with any considerable distance. A great traveler, even when in the same room, will seem like a truly extraordinary person; just like a Greek coin, even in our collection, is always regarded as a valuable curiosity. Here, the object, through a natural transition, leads our thoughts to the distance; and the admiration that arises from that distance, through another natural transition, comes back to the object.
But though every great distance produces an admiration for the distant object, a distance in time has a more considerable effect than that in space. Antient busts and inscriptions are more valued than Japan tables: And not to mention the Greeks and Romans, it is certain we regard with more veneration the old Chaldeans and Egyptians, than the modern Chinese and Persians, and bestow more fruitless pains to dear up the history and chronology of the former, than it would cost us to make a voyage, and be certainly informed of the character, learning and government of the latter. I shall be obliged to make a digression in order to explain this phænomenon.
But while every great distance creates admiration for the faraway object, a distance in time has an even greater impact than one in space. Ancient busts and inscriptions are valued more than Japanese tables. Not to mention the Greeks and Romans, it's clear that we hold the ancient Chaldeans and Egyptians in higher regard than modern Chinese and Persians, and we spend more effort trying to uncover the history and chronology of the former than it would take to travel there and learn firsthand about the character, knowledge, and governance of the latter. I will need to digress to explain this phenomenon.
It is a quality very observable in human nature, that any opposition, which does not entirely discourage and intimidate us, has rather a contrary effect, and inspires us with a more than ordinary grandeur and magnanimity. In collecting our force to overcome the opposition, we invigorate the soul, and give it an elevation with which otherwise it would never have been acquainted. Compliance, by rendering our strength useless, makes us insensible of it: but opposition awakens and employs it.
It's a well-known aspect of human nature that any resistance that doesn't completely discourage or intimidate us tends to have the opposite effect, inspiring us with a greater sense of greatness and generosity. In gathering our strength to overcome challenges, we energize our spirit and experience a level of elevation we wouldn't have encountered otherwise. Compliance, by making our strength ineffective, renders us unaware of it: but resistance stirs and activates it.
This is also true in the universe. Opposition not only enlarges the soul; but the soul, when full of courage and magnanimity, in a manner seeks opposition.
This is also true in the universe. Opposition not only expands the soul; but the soul, when filled with courage and generosity, in a way seeks out opposition.
Spumantemque dari pecora inter inertia votis
Optat aprum, aut fulvum descendere monte leonem.
Spumantemque dari pecora inter inertia votis
Optat aprum, aut fulvum descendere monte leonem.
[And, among the tamer beasts, [he] longs to be granted, in answer to his prayers,
a slavering boar, or to have a tawny lion come down from the mountain.]
[And, among the gentler animals, [he] hopes to be given, in response to his prayers,
a drooling boar, or to have a golden lion come down from the mountain.]
Whatever supports and fills the passions is agreeable to us; as on the contrary, what weakens and infeebles them is uneasy. As opposition has the first effect, and facility the second, no wonder the mind, in certain dispositions, desires the former, and is averse to the latter.
Whatever fuels and satisfies our passions is pleasing to us; while, on the other hand, anything that weakens or diminishes them is uncomfortable. Since opposition has the first effect and ease the second, it's no surprise that the mind, in certain moods, craves the former and dislikes the latter.
These principles have an effect on the imagination as well as on the passions. To be convinced of this we need only consider the influence of heights and depths on that faculty. Any great elevation of place communicates a kind of pride or sublimity of imagination, and gives a fancyed superiority over those that lie below; and, vice versa, a sublime and strong imagination conveys the idea of ascent and elevation. Hence it proceeds, that we associate, in a manner, the idea of whatever is good with that of height, and evil with lowness. Heaven is supposed to be above, and hell below. A noble genius is called an elevate and sublime one. ATQUE UDAM SPERNIT HUMUM FUGIENTE PENNA. [Spurns the dank soil in winged flight.] On the contrary, a vulgar and trivial conception is stiled indifferently low or mean. Prosperity is denominated ascent, and adversity descent. Kings and princes are supposed to be placed at the top of human affairs; as peasants and day-labourers are said to be in the lowest stations. These methods of thinking, and of expressing ourselves, are not of so little consequence as they may appear at first sight.
These principles affect both imagination and emotions. To see this, we only need to look at how heights and depths influence our thinking. Being at a high place brings about a sense of pride or elevated imagination, giving a sense of superiority over those below; conversely, a powerful and lofty imagination conveys the idea of rising and being elevated. Thus, we tend to associate goodness with height and evil with lowness. Heaven is thought to be above, and hell below. A noble character is often described as elevated and sublime. ATQUE UDAM SPERNIT HUMUM FUGIENTE PENNA. [Spurns the dank soil in winged flight.] On the other hand, a common and trivial idea is called low or mean. Prosperity is referred to as ascent, while adversity is seen as descent. Kings and princes are thought to occupy the top of society, while peasants and laborers are said to be at the bottom. These ways of thinking and expressing ourselves are not as trivial as they might seem at first glance.
It is evident to common sense, as well as philosophy, that there is no natural nor essential difference betwixt high and low, and that this distinction arises only from the gravitation of matter, which produces a motion from the one to the other. The very same direction, which in this part of the globe is called ascent, is denominated descent in our antipodes; which can proceed from nothing but the contrary tendency of bodies. Now it is certain, that the tendency of bodies, continually operating upon our senses, must produce, from custom, a like tendency in the fancy, and that when we consider any object situated in an ascent, the idea of its weight gives us a propensity to transport it from the place, in which it is situated, to the place immediately below it, and so on, until we come to the ground, which equally stops the body and our imagination. For a like reason we feel a difficulty in mounting, and pass not without a kind of reluctance from the inferior to that which is situated above it; as if our ideas acquired a kind of gravity from their objects. As a proof of this, do we not find, that the facility, which is so much studyed in music and poetry, is called the fail or cadency of the harmony or period; the idea of facility communicating to us that of descent, in the same manner as descent produces a facility?
It’s clear to common sense, as well as philosophy, that there’s no natural or essential difference between high and low, and that this distinction only comes from the way matter moves, creating a shift from one to the other. The same direction that we call ascent in this part of the world is referred to as descent in our antipodes, which can only result from the opposing tendencies of objects. Now, it’s certain that the consistent influence of these tendencies on our senses must, through habit, create a similar tendency in our imagination. When we think about something positioned on an incline, the thought of its weight makes us inclined to move it from where it is to the spot directly below it, and so on, until we reach the ground, which stops both the object and our thoughts. For the same reason, we find it difficult to climb, and we feel a sort of reluctance when moving from something lower to something higher, as if our ideas gain weight from their objects. As proof of this, don’t we see that the ease sought in music and poetry is called the flow or cadence of the harmony or verse? The idea of ease gives us the notion of descent, just like descent creates a sense of ease.
Since the imagination, therefore, in running from low to high, finds an opposition in its internal qualities and principles, and since the soul, when elevated with joy and courage, in a manner seeks opposition, and throws itself with alacrity into any scene of thought or action, where its courage meets with matter to nourish and employ it; it follows, that everything, which invigorates and inlivens the soul, whether by touching the passions or imagination naturally conveys to the fancy this inclination for ascent, and determines it to run against the natural stream of its thoughts and conceptions. This aspiring progress of the imagination suits the present disposition of the mind; and the difficulty, instead of extinguishing its vigour and alacrity, has the contrary affect, of sustaining and encreasing it. Virtue, genius, power, and riches are for this reason associated with height and sublimity; as poverty, slavery, and folly are conjoined with descent and lowness. Were the case the same with us as Milton represents it to be with the angels, to whom descent is adverse, and who cannot sink without labour and compulsion, this order of things would be entirely inverted; as appears hence, that the very nature of ascent and descent is derived from the difficulty and propensity, and consequently every one of their effects proceeds from that origin.
Since the imagination, when moving from low to high, encounters conflict within its own qualities and principles, and since the soul, when filled with joy and courage, actively seeks out challenges, eagerly immersing itself in any situation that stimulates and energizes its bravery; it follows that everything that invigorates and enlivens the soul, whether it appeals to feelings or imagination, naturally fosters this desire for elevation and encourages it to go against the natural flow of its thoughts and ideas. This upward movement of the imagination aligns with the mind's current state, and rather than diminishing its energy and enthusiasm, difficulty instead supports and enhances it. For this reason, virtue, creativity, power, and wealth are associated with height and greatness, while poverty, bondage, and ignorance are linked to decline and lowliness. If our situation were the same as Milton describes for the angels, who find descent to be adverse and cannot fall without effort and resistance, then the order of things would be completely reversed; as is evident from the fact that the very essence of ascent and descent originates from challenge and inclination, and therefore every effect related to them stems from that source.
All this is easily applied to the present question, why a considerable distance in time produces a greater veneration for the distant objects than a like removal in space. The imagination moves with more difficulty in passing from one portion of time to another, than in a transition through the parts of space; and that because space or extension appears united to our senses, while time or succession is always broken and divided. This difficulty, when joined with a small distance, interrupts and weakens the fancy: But has a contrary effect in a great removal. The mind, elevated by the vastness of its object, is still farther elevated by the difficulty of the conception; and being obliged every moment to renew its efforts in the transition from one part of time to another, feels a more vigorous and sublime disposition, than in a transition through the parts of space, where the ideas flow along with easiness and facility. In this disposition, the imagination, passing, as is usual, from the consideration of the distance to the view of the distant objects, gives us a proportionable veneration for it; and this is the reason why all the relicts of antiquity are so precious in our eyes, and appear more valuable than what is brought even from the remotest parts of the world.
All of this easily relates to the current question about why a significant amount of time creates a greater respect for distant objects than a similar distance in space. Our imagination struggles more when moving from one point in time to another than it does when transitioning through physical space. This is because space feels connected to our senses, while time always seems fragmented and divided. This challenge, combined with a short distance, disrupts and weakens our imagination. However, it has the opposite effect when the distance is great. The mind, uplifted by the enormity of what it's considering, is further enhanced by the difficulty of understanding it; and since it has to constantly refocus as it moves from one moment in time to the next, it experiences a more intense and elevated state than when navigating through space, where ideas flow easily. In this state, as is typical, the imagination moves from contemplating the distance to viewing the remote objects, giving us a corresponding sense of respect for them. This is why all remnants of the past are so treasured by us and seem more valuable than things brought from even the farthest places in the world.
The third phænomenon I have remarked will be a full confirmation of this. It is not every removal in time, which has the effect of producing veneration and esteem. We are not apt to imagine our posterity will excel us, or equal our ancestors. This phænomenon is the more remarkable, because any distance in futurity weakens not our ideas so much as an equal removal in the past. Though a removal in the past, when very great, encreases our passions beyond a like removal in the future, yet a small removal has a greater influence in diminishing them.
The third phenomenon I’ve noticed will fully confirm this. It’s not every distance in time that leads to respect and admiration. We don’t usually think that future generations will surpass us or match our ancestors. This phenomenon is especially interesting because any distance in the future doesn’t weaken our ideas as much as an equal distance in the past. Although a significant distance in the past amplifies our emotions more than a similar distance in the future, a small distance has a stronger effect in reducing those emotions.
In our common way of thinking we are placed in a kind of middle station betwixt the past and future; and as our imagination finds a kind of difficulty in running along the former, and a facility in following the course of the latter, the difficulty conveys the notion of ascent, and the facility of the contrary. Hence we imagine our ancestors to be, in a manner, mounted above us, and our posterity to lie below us. Our fancy arrives not at the one without effort, but easily reaches the other: Which effort weakens the conception, where the distance is small; but enlarges and elevates the imagination, when attended with a suitable object. As on the other hand, the facility assists the fancy in a small removal, but takes off from its force when it contemplates any considerable distance.
In our usual way of thinking, we find ourselves in a sort of middle ground between the past and the future. While our imagination struggles to grasp the past, it easily follows the future. This struggle gives us a sense of rising upward, while the ease of imagining the future feels like a downward slide. As a result, we picture our ancestors as being somewhat above us and our descendants as being below us. It takes effort to envision the past, but the future seems easily reachable. This effort weakens our understanding when the past is close, but it expands and elevates our imagination when there's a suitable subject to focus on. On the other hand, this ease helps our imagination when thinking about something small in the past, but it diminishes its impact when we consider something significantly far away.
It may not be improper, before we leave this subject of the will, to resume, in a few words, all that has been said concerning it, in order to set the whole more distinctly before the eyes of the reader. What we commonly understand by passion is a violent and sensible emotion of mind, when any good or evil is presented, or any object, which, by the original formation of our faculties, is fitted to excite an appetite. By reason we mean affections of the very same kind with the former; but such as operate more calmly, and cause no disorder in the temper: Which tranquillity leads us into a mistake concerning them, and causes us to regard them as conclusions only of our intellectual faculties. Both the causes and effects of these violent and calm passions are pretty variable, and depend, in a great measure, on the peculiar temper and disposition of every individual. Generally speaking, the violent passions have a more powerful influence on the will; though it is often found, that the calm ones, when corroborated by reflection, and seconded by resolution, are able to controul them in their most furious movements. What makes this whole affair more uncertain, is, that a calm passion may easily be changed into a violent one, either by a change of temper, or of the circumstances and situation of the object, as by the borrowing of force from any attendant passion, by custom, or by exciting the imagination. Upon the whole, this struggle of passion and of reason, as it is called, diversifies human life, and makes men so different not only from each other, but also from themselves in different times. Philosophy can only account for a few of the greater and more sensible events of this war; but must leave all the smaller and more delicate revolutions, as dependent on principles too fine and minute for her comprehension.
Before we wrap up our discussion on wills, it might be helpful to summarize, in a few words, everything that has been said about them to give the reader a clearer picture. When we talk about passion, we usually mean a strong and noticeable emotional response that arises when something good or bad is present, or when something triggers our innate desires. Reason, on the other hand, relates to feelings similar to those of passion but operate more steadily and don’t disturb our temperament: this calmness can mislead us into thinking they’re just conclusions drawn from our thinking processes. Both the causes and effects of these intense and calm passions can vary significantly and largely reflect the individual’s unique temperament and disposition. Generally, intense passions tend to have a stronger influence on our will; however, calm passions can also take charge when reinforced by thought and supported by determination, effectively controlling even the most intense reactions. What complicates matters is that a calm passion can quickly become intense due to changes in mood or the circumstances surrounding the object of desire, sometimes fueled by other feelings, habits, or by stimulating our imagination. Ultimately, this ongoing battle between passion and reason makes human life diverse and leads people to be different not only from one another but also from themselves at different times. Philosophy can explain a few of the major and noticeable occurrences in this ongoing conflict; however, it has to leave the smaller and subtler changes as dependent on principles that are too complex and delicate for its grasp.
SECT. IX OF THE DIRECT PASSIONS
It is easy to observe, that the passions, both direct and indirect, are founded on pain and pleasure, and that in order to produce an affection of any kind, it is only requisite to present some good or evil. Upon the removal of pain and pleasure there immediately follows a removal of love and hatred, pride and humility, desire and aversion, and of most of our reflective or secondary impressions.
It's easy to see that our emotions, both direct and indirect, are based on pain and pleasure, and that to create any kind of feeling, you just need to show some good or bad. When pain and pleasure are taken away, love and hate, pride and humility, desire and dislike, along with most of our thoughtful or secondary impressions, quickly disappear.
The impressions, which arise from good and evil most naturally, and with the least preparation are the direct passions of desire and aversion, grief and joy, hope and fear, along with volition. The mind by an original instinct tends to unite itself with the good, and to avoid the evil, though they be conceived merely in idea, and be considered as to exist in any future period of time.
The feelings that come from good and bad, often without much thought, are the basic emotions of wanting and rejecting, sadness and happiness, hope and fear, along with the will to act. The mind, by its natural instinct, seeks to connect with what is good and steer clear of what is bad, even if those concepts are just ideas and are thought to exist in the future.
But supposing that there is an immediate impression of pain or pleasure, and that arising from an object related to ourselves or others, this does not prevent the propensity or aversion, with the consequent emotions, but by concurring with certain dormant principles of the human mind, excites the new impressions of pride or humility, love or hatred. That propensity, which unites us to the object, or separates us from it, still continues to operate, but in conjunction with the indirect passions, which arise from a double relation of impressions and ideas.
But let's say that there's an immediate feeling of pain or pleasure connected to something related to us or others; this doesn’t stop our attraction or avoidance, along with the resulting emotions. Instead, it works alongside certain hidden principles of the human mind, triggering new feelings of pride or humility, love or hatred. That attraction, which brings us closer to the object or pushes us away from it, continues to influence us, but it does so alongside the secondary emotions that come from a mix of impressions and ideas.
These indirect passions, being always agreeable or uneasy, give in their turn additional force to the direct passions, and encrease our desire and aversion to the object. Thus a suit of fine cloaths produces pleasure from their beauty; and this pleasure produces the direct passions, or the impressions of volition and desire. Again, when these cloaths are considered as belonging to ourself, the double relation conveys to us the sentiment of pride, which is an indirect passion; and the pleasure, which attends that passion, returns back to the direct affections, and gives new force to our desire or volition, joy or hope.
These indirect feelings, always pleasant or uncomfortable, in turn add more intensity to our direct feelings, increasing our desire or dislike for the object. For example, wearing nice clothes brings us joy from their beauty; this joy fuels our direct feelings, like the impulses of wanting and will. Moreover, when we see these clothes as belonging to us, this connection generates a sense of pride, which is an indirect feeling; the joy that comes from this feeling feeds back into our direct emotions, giving more strength to our desire, will, happiness, or hope.
When good is certain or probable, it produces joy. When evil is in the same situation there arises GRIEF or SORROW.
When good is assured or likely, it brings happiness. When evil is in the same situation, it leads to grief or sorrow.
When either good or evil is uncertain, it gives rise to FEAR or HOPE, according to the degrees of uncertainty on the one side or the other.
When good or evil is uncertain, it leads to FEAR or HOPE, depending on how uncertain things are on either side.
DESIRE arises from good considered simply, and AVERSION is derived from evil. The WILL exerts itself, when either the good or the absence of the evil may be attained by any action of the mind or body.
DESIRE comes from good taken at face value, while AVERSION comes from evil. The WILL is activated when either good or the absence of evil can be achieved through any mental or physical action.
Beside good and evil, or in other words, pain and pleasure, the direct passions frequently arise from a natural impulse or instinct, which is perfectly unaccountable. Of this kind is the desire of punishment to our enemies, and of happiness to our friends; hunger, lust, and a few other bodily appetites. These passions, properly speaking, produce good and evil, and proceed not from them, like the other affections.
Next to good and evil, or in simpler terms, pain and pleasure, our direct emotions often come from a natural impulse or instinct that we can't really explain. An example of this is our desire to punish our enemies and to bring happiness to our friends; there's also hunger, lust, and a few other basic needs. These feelings, in essence, create good and evil and do not stem from them like other emotions do.
None of the direct affections seem to merit our particular attention, except hope and fear, which we shall here endeavour to account for. It is evident that the very same event, which by its certainty would produce grief or joy, gives always rise to fear or hope, when only probable and uncertain. In order, therefore, to understand the reason why this circumstance makes such a considerable difference, we must reflect on what I have already advanced in the preceding book concerning the nature of probability.
None of the direct emotions really seem to deserve our special attention, except for hope and fear, which we will try to explain here. It's clear that the same event, which with certainty would cause grief or joy, always leads to fear or hope when it's just probable and uncertain. So, to understand why this situation makes such a big difference, we need to think about what I discussed in the previous book regarding the nature of probability.
Probability arises from an opposition of contrary chances or causes, by which the mind is not allowed to fix on either side, but is incessantly tost from one to another, and at one moment is determined to consider an object as existent, and at another moment as the contrary. The imagination or understanding, call it which you please, fluctuates betwixt the opposite views; and though perhaps it may be oftener turned to the one side than the other, it is impossible for it, by reason of the opposition of causes or chances, to rest on either. The pro and con of the question alternately prevail; and the mind, surveying the object in its opposite principles, finds such a contrariety as utterly destroys all certainty and established opinion.
Probability comes from the clash of opposing chances or reasons, making it impossible for the mind to settle on either side. Instead, it is constantly tossed back and forth, sometimes convinced that something exists and at other times seeing it as the opposite. The imagination or understanding—whichever you prefer—alternates between these conflicting perspectives. Even if it leans more toward one side than the other, it can't rest on either due to the opposing causes or chances. The arguments for and against the issue take turns dominating, and as the mind examines the object through its conflicting principles, it encounters such a contradiction that it completely undermines all certainty and established beliefs.
Suppose, then, that the object, concerning whose reality we are doubtful, is an object either of desire or aversion, it is evident, that, according as the mind turns itself either to the one side or the other, it must feel a momentary impression of joy or sorrow. An object, whose existence we desire, gives satisfaction, when we reflect on those causes, which produce it; and for the same reason excites grief or uneasiness from the opposite consideration: So that as the understanding, in all probable questions, is divided betwixt the contrary points of view, the affections must in the same manner be divided betwixt opposite emotions.
Suppose we’re uncertain about the reality of an object that either attracts or repels us. It's clear that depending on whether our mind focuses on one side or the other, we will feel a brief rush of joy or sadness. An object we desire brings us satisfaction when we think about the reasons that lead to its existence; conversely, it can cause grief or discomfort when we consider the opposite. So, as our understanding weighs both sides of any likely question, our feelings will similarly be split between conflicting emotions.
Now if we consider the human mind, we shall find, that with regard to the passions, it is not the nature of a wind-instrument of music, which in running over all the notes immediately loses the sound after the breath ceases; but rather resembles a string-instrument, where after each stroke the vibrations still retain some sound, which gradually and insensibly decays. The imagination is extreme quick and agile; but the passions are slow and restive: For which reason, when any object is presented, that affords a variety of views to the one, and emotions to the other; though the fancy may change its views with great celerity; each stroke will not produce a clear and distinct note of passion, but the one passion will always be mixt and confounded with the other. According as the probability inclines to good or evil, the passion of joy or sorrow predominates in the composition: Because the nature of probability is to cast a superior number of views or chances on one side; or, which is the same thing, a superior number of returns of one passion; or since the dispersed passions are collected into one, a superior degree of that passion. That is, in other words, the grief and joy being intermingled with each other, by means of the contrary views of the imagination, produce by their union the passions of hope and fear.
If we think about the human mind, we'll see that when it comes to our emotions, it's not like a wind instrument that quickly loses sound once you stop blowing into it; instead, it's more like a string instrument, where each pluck continues to resonate softly until it fades away. The imagination is incredibly quick and nimble, but our emotions tend to be slow and stubborn. So when we encounter something that offers different perspectives to the imagination and evokes emotions, even though our thoughts might shift rapidly, each emotional response doesn't come out clearly or distinctly. Instead, one emotion often mixes and gets confused with another. Depending on whether the situation seems more likely to lead to something good or bad, feelings of joy or sorrow will dominate. This is because probability tends to favor one side with more possibilities, or in other words, leans toward more emotional responses from one feeling; and since conflicting emotions unite into one, it heightens that feeling. In simpler terms, when sadness and happiness intertwine due to the contrasting thoughts in our imagination, their combination creates feelings of hope and fear.
Upon this head there may be started a very curious question concerning that contrariety of passions, which is our present subject. It is observable, that where the objects of contrary passions are presented at once, beside the encrease of the predominant passion (which has been already explained, and commonly arises at their first shock or rencounter) it sometimes happens, that both the passions exist successively, and by short intervals; sometimes, that they destroy each other, and neither of them takes place; and sometimes that both of them remain united in the mind. It may, therefore, be asked, by what theory we can explain these variations, and to what general principle we can reduce them.
There’s an interesting question to consider regarding the conflicting emotions we're discussing. It's noticeable that when we encounter things that evoke conflicting feelings at the same time, along with the increase of the stronger emotion (which we've already talked about and often occurs during their initial confrontation), it can sometimes happen that both emotions happen one after the other in quick succession; sometimes they cancel each other out and neither emotion is felt; and sometimes both emotions coexist in the mind. So, we can ask how we can explain these differences and what general principle we can apply to understand them.
When the contrary passions arise from objects entirely different, they take place alternately, the want of relation in the ideas separating the impressions from each other, and preventing their opposition. Thus when a man is afflicted for the loss of a law-suit, and joyful for the birth of a son, the mind running from the agreeable to the calamitous object, with whatever celerity it may perform this motion, can scarcely temper the one affection with the other, and remain betwixt them in a state of indifference.
When opposing emotions come from completely different situations, they occur one after the other. The lack of connection between the ideas keeps the feelings apart and stops them from conflicting. For example, when a man is upset about losing a lawsuit but happy about the birth of his son, his mind hops back and forth between the good and the bad feelings. No matter how quickly he shifts his focus, he can barely balance one emotion with the other and stay neutral between them.
It more easily attains that calm situation, when the same event is of a mixt nature, and contains something adverse and something prosperous in its different circumstances. For in that case, both the passions, mingling with each other by means of the relation, become mutually destructive, and leave the mind in perfect tranquility.
It more easily achieves a calm state when the same event has a mixed nature, containing both something negative and something positive in its different circumstances. In that case, both emotions, blending together due to their connection, end up neutralizing each other and leaving the mind in perfect peace.
But suppose, in the third place, that the object is not a compound of good or evil, but is considered as probable or improbable in any degree; in that case I assert, that the contrary passions will both of them be present at once in the soul, and instead of destroying and tempering each other, will subsist together, and produce a third impression or affection by their union. Contrary passions are not capable of destroying each other, except when their contrary movements exactly rencounter, and are opposite in their direction, as well as in the sensation they produce. This exact rencounter depends upon the relations of those ideas, from which they are derived, and is more or less perfect, according to the degrees of the relation. In the case of probability the contrary chances are so far related, that they determine concerning the existence or non-existence of the same object. But this relation is far from being perfect; since some of the chances lie on the side of existence, and others on that of non-existence; which are objects altogether incompatible. It is impossible by one steady view to survey the opposite chances, and the events dependent on them; but it is necessary, that the imagination should run alternately from the one to the other. Each view of the imagination produces its peculiar passion, which decays away by degrees, and is followed by a sensible vibration after the stroke. The incompatibility of the views keeps the passions from shocking in a direct line, if that expression may be allowed; and yet their relation is sufficient to mingle their fainter emotions. It is after this manner that hope and fear arise from the different mixture of these opposite passions of grief and joy, and from their imperfect union and conjunction.
But let's say, on the third point, that the issue isn't simply good or bad, but is seen as likely or unlikely to some extent; in that case, I argue that both opposing emotions will be present at the same time in the mind, and instead of canceling each other out or balancing each other, they will coexist and create a new feeling or response together. Opposing emotions can't completely eliminate each other unless their opposing movements perfectly collide and are opposite in both direction and the feelings they create. This precise collision relies on the connections of the ideas they stem from, and it is more or less perfect depending on the strength of those connections. In the context of probability, the opposing possibilities are related enough that they pertain to the existence or non-existence of the same thing. However, this connection is far from perfect; some of the possibilities lean towards existence, while others lean towards non-existence, which are completely incompatible. It's impossible to view the opposing possibilities and the outcomes tied to them at the same time; instead, the imagination must jump back and forth between them. Each focus of the imagination generates its specific emotion, which gradually fades and is followed by a noticeable shift afterward. The incompatibility of these views prevents the emotions from clashing directly, if that phrase can be used; yet their connection is enough to blend their subtler feelings. This is how hope and fear emerge from the different combinations of these opposing emotions of sadness and happiness, and from their imperfect blending and interaction.
Upon the whole, contrary passions succeed each other alternately, when they arise from different objects: They mutually destroy each other, when they proceed from different parts of the same: And they subsist both of them and mingle together, when they are derived from the contrary and incompatible chances or possibilities, on which any one object depends. The influence of the relations of ideas is plainly seen in this whole affair. If the objects of the contrary passions be totally different, the passions are like two opposite liquors in different bottles, which have no influence on each other. If the objects be intimately connected, the passions are like an alcali and an acid, which, being mingled, destroy each other. If the relation be more imperfect, and consists in the contradictory views of the same object, the passions are like oil and vinegar, which, however mingled, never perfectly unite and incorporate.
Overall, opposing feelings come in turns when they come from different sources: they cancel each other out when they come from different aspects of the same source. They can coexist and blend together when they stem from opposing and incompatible possibilities related to the same object. The impact of the relationships between ideas is clearly evident in this situation. If the sources of the opposing feelings are completely different, the feelings are like two opposing liquids in separate bottles that don’t affect each other. If the sources are closely linked, the feelings are like an alkaline substance and an acid that, when mixed, neutralize each other. If the connection is less strong and consists of contradictory perspectives on the same object, the feelings are like oil and vinegar, which, even when mixed, never fully combine or merge together.
As the hypothesis concerning hope and fear carries its own evidence along with it, we shall be the more concise in our proofs. A few strong arguments are better than many weak ones.
As the idea about hope and fear comes with its own evidence, we’ll be more concise in our arguments. A few strong points are better than many weak ones.
The passions of fear and hope may arise when the chances are equal on both sides, and no superiority can be discovered in the one above the other. Nay, in this situation the passions are rather the strongest, as the mind has then the least foundation to rest upon, and is tossed with the greatest uncertainty. Throw in a superior degree of probability to the side of grief, you immediately see that passion diffuse itself over the composition, and tincture it into fear. Encrease the probability, and by that means the grief, the fear prevails still more and more, till at last it runs insensibly, as the joy continually diminishes, into pure grief. After you have brought it to this situation, diminish the grief, after the same manner that you encreased it; by diminishing the probability on that side, and you'll see the passion clear every moment, until it changes insensibly into hope; which again runs, after the same manner, by slow degrees, into joy, as you encrease that part of the composition by the encrease of the probability. Are not these as plain proofs, that the passions of fear and hope are mixtures of grief and joy, as in optics it is a proof, that a coloured ray of the sun passing through a prism, is a composition of two others, when, as you diminish or encrease the quantity of either, you find it prevail proportionably more or less in the composition? I am sure neither natural nor moral philosophy admits of stronger proofs.
The feelings of fear and hope can come up when the chances are equal on both sides, and there's no obvious advantage to one over the other. In fact, in this scenario, the feelings are often the strongest because the mind has the least solid ground to stand on and is tossed around with the greatest uncertainty. If you introduce a higher probability of sadness, you’ll instantly see that feeling spread throughout the mix and turn into fear. Increase the probability—and thus the sadness—and the fear continues to grow until, eventually, it seamlessly transitions, as the joy gradually fades, into pure grief. After reaching this point, if you reduce the sadness in the same way you increased it—by lowering the probability on that side—you'll notice the feeling clearing up little by little until it transforms into hope; which then, likewise, shifts slowly into joy as you boost that part of the mix by raising the probability. Aren't these clear examples that the feelings of fear and hope are blends of sadness and joy, just like in optics where you can prove that a colored ray of sunlight passing through a prism is made up of two others? As you adjust the amount of either, you see them prevail more or less in the combination. I’m certain that neither natural nor moral philosophy offers stronger evidence.
Probability is of two kinds, either when the object is really in itself uncertain, and to be determined by chance; or when, though the object be already certain, yet it is uncertain to our judgment, which finds a number of proofs on each side of the question. Both these kinds of probabilities cause fear and hope; which can only proceed from that property, in which they agree, viz, the uncertainty and fluctuation they bestow on the imagination by that contrariety of views, which is common to both.
Probability comes in two types: one where the outcome is genuinely uncertain and determined by chance, and the other where the outcome is already certain but remains uncertain to us because our judgment sees multiple arguments on both sides of the issue. Both types of probability evoke fear and hope, stemming from their shared characteristic—namely, the uncertainty and unpredictability they introduce to our imagination due to the conflicting perspectives inherent in both.
It is a probable good or evil, that commonly produces hope or fear; because probability, being a wavering and unconstant method of surveying an object, causes naturally a like mixture and uncertainty of passion. But we may observe, that wherever from other causes this mixture can be produced, the passions of fear and hope will arise, even though there be no probability; which must be allowed to be a convincing proof of the present hypothesis. We find that an evil, barely conceived as possible, does sometimes produce fear; especially if the evil be very great. A man cannot think of excessive pains and tortures without trembling, if he be in the least danger of suffering them. The smallness of the probability is compensated by the greatness of the evil; and the sensation is equally lively, as if the evil were more probable. One view or glimpse of the former, has the same effect as several of the latter.
It's likely that certain situations bring about hope or fear; because probability, being an inconsistent and unreliable way of looking at something, naturally creates a mix of feelings and uncertainties. However, we can see that whenever this mix is created by other factors, the feelings of fear and hope can still emerge, even if there's no actual probability involved, which supports the current argument. We notice that even a potential evil, just imagined as possible, can sometimes instill fear, especially if the evil is particularly severe. A person can’t think about extreme pain and torture without getting anxious, especially if there's even a slight chance of experiencing them. The low likelihood is offset by the severity of the evil; the feeling is just as intense as if the evil were more likely. Just one thought or glimpse of the former has the same impact as several thoughts of the latter.
But they are not only possible evils, that cause fear, but even some allowed to be impossible; as when we tremble on the brink of a precipice, though we know ourselves to be in perfect security, and have it in our choice whether we will advance a step farther. This proceeds from the immediate presence of the evil, which influences the imagination in the same manner as the certainty of it would do; but being encountered by the reflection on our security, is immediately retracted, and causes the same kind of passion, as when from a contrariety of chances contrary passions are produced.
But they aren’t just possible dangers that make us fearful; there are even some that we know are impossible. For instance, we might feel afraid standing at the edge of a cliff, even though we know we’re completely safe and can choose not to take another step forward. This fear comes from being close to the danger, which affects our imagination just like a real threat would. However, once we remind ourselves that we’re safe, that fear quickly fades, creating the same kind of emotional response as when conflicting possibilities stir up different feelings.
Evils, that are certain, have sometimes the same effect in producing fear, as the possible or impossible. Thus a man in a strong prison well-guarded, without the least means of escape, trembles at the thought of the rack, to which he is sentenced. This happens only when the certain evil is terrible and confounding; in which case the mind continually rejects it with horror, while it continually presses in upon the thought. The evil is there fixed and established, but the mind cannot endure to fix upon it; from which fluctuation and uncertainty there arises a passion of much the same appearance with fear.
Certain evils can sometimes cause fear just like possible or impossible ones. For example, a man locked in a secure prison cell, with no way to escape, trembles at the thought of the torture he’s been sentenced to. This occurs only when the certain evil is both terrible and overwhelming; in this situation, the mind constantly tries to push it away with horror while it keeps creeping back into thought. The evil is established and unchangeable, but the mind can’t stand to focus on it; from this confusion and uncertainty grows a feeling that looks a lot like fear.
But it is not only where good or evil is uncertain, as to its existence, but also as to its kind, that fear or hope arises. Let one be told by a person, whose veracity he cannot doubt of, that one of his sons is suddenly killed, it is evident the passion this event would occasion, would not settle into pure grief, till he got certain information, which of his sons he had lost. Here there is an evil certain, but the kind of it uncertain. Consequently the fear we feel on this occasion is without the least mixture of joy, and arises merely from the fluctuation of the fancy betwixt its objects. And though each side of the question produces here the same passion, yet that passion cannot settle, but receives from the imagination a tremulous and unsteady motion, resembling in its cause, as well as in its sensation, the mixture and contention of grief and joy.
But it's not just when it's unclear if something is good or evil that fear or hope comes up; it also happens when it's uncertain what kind it is. If someone you trust tells you that one of your sons has been suddenly killed, it’s clear that the emotion this news would cause wouldn't turn into pure grief until you find out which son you lost. In this case, there's a definite evil, but its nature is uncertain. So, the fear we feel here is purely negative, stemming from the back-and-forth of our thoughts about the situation. Even though both sides of the issue create the same emotion, that emotion can't settle and instead gets a shaky and uncertain movement from our imagination, similar to the mix of grief and joy.
From these principles we may account for a phænomenon in the passions, which at first sight seems very extraordinary, viz, that surprize is apt to change into fear, and every thing that is unexpected affrights us. The most obvious conclusion from this is, that human nature is in general pusillanimous; since upon the sudden appearance of any object. we immediately conclude it to be an evil, and without waiting till we can examine its nature, whether it be good or bad, are at first affected with fear. This I say is the most obvious conclusion; but upon farther examination we shall find that the phænomenon is otherwise to be accounted for. The suddenness and strangeness of an appearance naturally excite a commotion in the mind, like every thing for which we are not prepared, and to which we are not accustomed. This commotion, again, naturally produces a curiosity or inquisitiveness, which being very violent, from the strong and sudden impulse of the object, becomes uneasy, and resembles in its fluctuation and uncertainty, the sensation of fear or the mixed passions of grief and joy. This image of fear naturally converts into the thing itself, and gives us a real apprehension of evil, as the mind always forms its judgments more from its present disposition than from the nature of its objects.
From these principles, we can explain a phenomenon in our emotions that seems quite extraordinary at first: surprise often turns into fear, and anything unexpected frightens us. The most straightforward conclusion from this is that human nature, in general, tends to be timid; when something suddenly appears, we automatically assume it's a threat. Without taking the time to assess whether it's good or bad, we are initially hit with fear. I say this is the most obvious conclusion, but upon further examination, we find that the phenomenon can be explained differently. The suddenness and strangeness of an appearance naturally stir chaos in the mind, just like anything we're not prepared for and not used to. This turmoil naturally sparks curiosity or inquisitiveness, which, because of the intense and sudden impact of the object, becomes uncomfortable and resembles the feeling of fear or the mixed emotions of grief and joy. This sensation of fear easily transforms into the real thing, leading us to genuinely perceive a threat, as our minds tend to judge more based on their current state than on the true nature of the object.
Thus all kinds of uncertainty have a strong connexion with fear, even though they do not cause any opposition of passions by the opposite views and considerations they present to us. A person, who has left his friend in any malady, will feel more anxiety upon his account, than if he were present, though perhaps he is not only incapable of giving him assistance, but likewise of judging of the event of his sickness. In this case, though the principal object of the passion, viz, the life or death of his friend, be to him equally uncertain when present as when absent; yet there are a thousand little circumstances of his friend's situation and condition, the knowledge of which fixes the idea, and prevents that fluctuation and uncertainty so near allyed to fear. Uncertainty is, indeed, in one respect as near allyed to hope as to fear, since it makes an essential part in the composition of the former passion; but the reason, why it inclines not to that side, is, that uncertainty alone is uneasy, and has a relation of impressions to the uneasy passions.
All kinds of uncertainty are closely linked to fear, even though they don't create opposing feelings due to the different perspectives and considerations they present to us. A person who has left a friend dealing with an illness will feel more anxious about them than if they were there, even though they might not be able to help or assess the situation. In this case, while the main focus of their concern—life or death of their friend—remains just as uncertain whether they are present or absent, there are countless small details about their friend's situation that provide clarity and help prevent the fluctuation and uncertainty that closely relate to fear. Uncertainty is, in some ways, just as connected to hope as it is to fear, since it plays a fundamental role in the makeup of hope. However, the reason it doesn't lean toward hope is that uncertainty alone is uncomfortable and relates more to uneasy emotions.
It is thus our uncertainty concerning any minute circumstance relating to a person encreases our apprehensions of his death or misfortune. Horace has remarked this phænomenon.
It’s our uncertainty about any small detail regarding a person that increases our fears of their death or misfortune. Horace pointed out this phenomenon.
Ut assidens implumibus pullis avis
Serpentium allapsus timet,
Magis relictis; non, ut adsit, auxilî
Latura plus præsentibus.
Ut assidens implumibus pullis avis
Serpentium allapsus timet,
Magis relictis; non, ut adsit, auxilî
Latura plus præsentibus.
[As a bird, watching over her fledgelings, is more afraid of their being attacked by snakes if she were to leave them even though, were she to stay, she would not be any more capable of helping them, when they were with her.]
[Like a bird watching over her chicks, she fears they might be attacked by snakes if she leaves them, even though staying wouldn't make her any more able to help them when they're with her.]
But this principle of the connexion of fear with uncertainty I carry farther, and observe that any doubt produces that passion, even though it presents nothing to us on any side but what is good and desireable. A virgin, on her bridalnight goes to bed full of fears and apprehensions, though she expects nothing but pleasure of the highest kind, and what she has long wished for. The newness and greatness of the event, the confusion of wishes and joys so embarrass the mind, that it knows not on what passion to fix itself; from whence arises a fluttering or unsettledness of the spirits which being, in some degree, uneasy, very naturally degenerates into fear.
But I take this idea about the connection between fear and uncertainty even further, and I notice that any doubt can spark that feeling, even if everything around us seems good and desirable. A bride on her wedding night goes to bed full of fears and worries, even though she anticipates nothing but the greatest pleasure and what she has wished for a long time. The newness and significance of the occasion, along with the mix of wishes and joys, can confuse the mind, making it unsure about which emotion to focus on; this leads to a restlessness or unsettled feeling, which can, to some extent, turn into fear.
Thus we still find, that whatever causes any fluctuation or mixture of passions, with any degree of uneasiness, always produces fear, or at least a passion so like it, that they are scarcely to be distinguished.
Thus we still find that any fluctuation or mix of emotions that causes any level of discomfort always produces fear, or at least an emotion so similar to it that they are hard to tell apart.
I have here confined myself to the examination of hope and fear in their most simple and natural situation, without considering all the variations they may receive from the mixture of different views and reflections. Terror, consternation, astonishment, anxiety, and other passions of that kind, are nothing but different species and degrees of fear. It is easy to imagine how a different situation of the object, or a different turn of thought, may change even the sensation of a passion; and this may in general account for all the particular sub-divisions of the other affections, as well as of fear. Love may shew itself in the shape of tenderness, friendship, intimacy, esteem, good-will, and in many other appearances; which at the bottom are the same affections; and arise from the same causes, though with a small variation, which it is not necessary to give any particular account of. It is for this reason I have all along confined myself to the principal passion.
I have focused here on exploring hope and fear in their most basic and natural state, without delving into all the different ways they can manifest due to various perspectives and reflections. Terror, panic, shock, anxiety, and other similar emotions are just different types and levels of fear. It’s easy to see how a change in the situation or a different line of thinking can alter the feeling associated with an emotion; this generally explains all the specific subcategories of other feelings, as well as fear. Love can express itself as tenderness, friendship, closeness, respect, goodwill, and many other forms, which fundamentally are the same emotions stemming from the same causes, even if there are minor differences that don't need detailed explanation. That’s why I have consistently focused on the main emotion.
The same care of avoiding prolixity is the reason why I wave the examination of the will and direct passions, as they appear in animals; since nothing is more evident, than that they are of the same nature, and excited by the same causes as in human creatures. I leave this to the reader's own observation; desiring him at the same time to consider the additional force this bestows on the present system.
The same care in avoiding excessive detail is why I skip the examination of will and direct passions as they appear in animals; because it's clear that they are of the same nature and triggered by the same causes as in humans. I leave this for the reader to observe, while also asking them to consider the added strength this gives to the current system.
SECT. X OF CURIOSITY, OR THE LOVE OF TRUTH
But methinks we have been not a little inattentive to run over so many different parts of the human mind, and examine so many passions, without taking once into the consideration that love of truth, which was the first source of all our enquiries. Twill therefore be proper, before we leave this subject, to bestow a few reflections on that passion, and shew its origin in human nature. It is an affection of so peculiar a kind, that it would have been impossible to have treated of it under any of those heads, which we have examined, without danger of obscurity and confusion.
But I think we have been quite inattentive to go through so many different aspects of the human mind and explore so many emotions without once considering our love for truth, which is the original source of all our inquiries. Therefore, it’s fitting that before we move on from this topic, we take a moment to reflect on that feeling and show its origins in human nature. It’s such a unique emotion that discussing it alongside any of the topics we've covered would have likely led to confusion and ambiguity.
Truth is of two kinds, consisting either in the discovery of the proportions of ideas, considered as such, or in the conformity of our ideas of objects to their real existence. It is certain, that the former species of truth, is not desired merely as truth, and that it is not the justness of our conclusions, which alone gives the pleasure. For these conclusions are equally just, when we discover the equality of two bodies by a pair of compasses, as when we learn it by a mathematical demonstration; and though in the one case the proofs be demonstrative, and in the other only sensible, yet generally speaking, the mind acquiesces with equal assurance in the one as in the other. And in an arithmetical operation, where both the truth and the assurance are of the same nature, as in the most profound algebraical problem, the pleasure is very inconsiderable, if rather it does not degenerate into pain: Which is an evident proof, that the satisfaction, which we sometimes receive from the discovery of truth, proceeds not from it, merely as such, but only as endowed with certain qualities.
Truth comes in two forms: one is the understanding of the relationships between ideas, and the other is the alignment of our perceptions of objects with their actual existence. It's clear that the first kind of truth isn't sought after just for the sake of being truth, and it's not simply the accuracy of our conclusions that brings pleasure. Our conclusions can be equally correct whether we find that two bodies are equal using a compass or through a mathematical proof. Although one method is clear-cut and the other based on observation, generally, the mind feels equally confident in both types. In an arithmetic operation, where both the truth and confidence are consistent, like in advanced algebra, the pleasure we derive can be quite minimal, or it may even feel more like a burden. This clearly shows that the satisfaction we sometimes feel from discovering truth doesn't come solely from the truth itself, but rather from the specific qualities it possesses.
The first and most considerable circumstance requisite to render truth agreeable, is the genius and capacity, which is employed in its invention and discovery. What is easy and obvious is never valued; and even what is in itself difficult, if we come to the knowledge of it without difficulty, and without any stretch of thought or judgment, is but little regarded. We love to trace the demonstrations of mathematicians; but should receive small entertainment from a person, who should barely inform us of the proportions of lines and angles, though we reposed the utmost confidence both in his judgment and veracity. In this case it is sufficient to have ears to learn the truth. We never are obliged to fix our attention or exert our genius; which of all other exercises of the mind is the most pleasant and agreeable.
The first and most important factor that makes truth appealing is the creativity and ability involved in its creation and discovery. What’s easy and obvious is rarely valued, and even difficult things don't hold much importance if we learn about them without effort or deep thinking. We enjoy following the work of mathematicians, but we wouldn't find much enjoyment from someone who simply told us the ratios of lines and angles, even if we completely trusted their judgment and honesty. In that case, it’s enough just to listen to hear the truth. We don’t have to focus our attention or tap into our creativity, which is the most enjoyable exercise of the mind.
But though the exercise of genius be the principal source of that satisfaction we receive from the sciences, yet I doubt, if it be alone sufficient to give us any considerable enjoyment. The truth we discover must also be of some importance. It is easy to multiply algebraical problems to infinity, nor is there any end in the discovery of the proportions of conic sections; though few mathematicians take any pleasure in these researches, but turn their thoughts to what is more useful and important. Now the question is, after what manner this utility and importance operate upon us? The difficulty on this head arises from hence, that many philosophers have consumed their time, have destroyed their health, and neglected their fortune, in the search of such truths, as they esteemed important and useful to the world, though it appeared from their whole conduct and behaviour, that they were not endowed with any share of public spirit, nor had any concern for the interests of mankind. Were they convinced, that their discoveries were of no consequence, they would entirely lose all relish for their studies, and that though the consequences be entirely indifferent to them; which seems to be a contradiction.
Even though the exercise of genius is the main source of the satisfaction we get from the sciences, I wonder if it’s really enough to give us significant enjoyment on its own. The truths we discover also have to be important. It’s easy to create endless algebra problems, and you can keep finding the proportions of conic sections forever; however, few mathematicians actually enjoy these pursuits and instead focus on what’s more useful and significant. The question is, how does this utility and importance affect us? The challenge here is that many philosophers have spent years, ruined their health, and ignored their finances in search of truths they believed to be important and useful to the world, even though their actions made it clear they lacked any sense of public spirit or concern for humanity’s interests. If they were convinced that their discoveries didn’t matter, they would completely lose interest in their studies, even if the results were entirely irrelevant to them, which seems contradictory.
To remove this contradiction, we must consider, that there are certain desires and inclinations, which go no farther than the imagination, and are rather the faint shadows and images of passions, than any real affections. Thus, suppose a man, who takes a survey of the fortifications of any city; considers their strength and advantages, natural or acquired; observes the disposition and contrivance of the bastions, ramparts, mines, and other military works; it is plain, that in proportion as all these are fitted to attain their ends he will receive a suitable pleasure and satisfaction. This pleasure, as it arises from the utility, not the form of the objects, can be no other than a sympathy with the inhabitants, for whose security all this art is employed; though it is possible, that this person, as a stranger or an enemy, may in his heart have no kindness for them, or may even entertain a hatred against them.
To resolve this contradiction, we need to consider that there are certain desires and inclinations that only exist in our imagination, and are more like faint shadows and images of real feelings than actual affections. For example, imagine a person surveying the fortifications of a city; assessing their strength and benefits, whether natural or man-made; observing the layout and design of the bastions, walls, tunnels, and other military structures. It’s clear that the more effective these structures are at achieving their purpose, the more pleasure and satisfaction he will feel. This pleasure, arising from the usefulness rather than the appearance of the objects, can only be understood as a connection with the people who depend on this fortification for their safety. However, it's also possible that this person, being a stranger or an enemy, might not genuinely care for them, or even harbor feelings of hatred.
It may indeed be objected, that such a remote sympathy is a very slight foundation for a passion, and that so much industry and application, as we frequently observe in philosophers, can never be derived from so inconsiderable an original. But here I return to what I have already remarked, that the pleasure of study conflicts chiefly in the action of the mind, and the exercise of the genius and understanding in the discovery or comprehension of any truth. If the importance of the truth be requisite to compleat the pleasure, it is not on account of any considerable addition, which of itself it brings to our enjoyment, but only because it is, in some measure, requisite to fix our attention. When we are careless and inattentive, the same action of the understanding has no effect upon us, nor is able to convey any of that satisfaction, which arises from it, when we are in another disposition.
It might be argued that such a distant connection is a weak basis for passion, and that the level of effort and dedication we often see in philosophers can’t come from such a negligible source. But I want to emphasize what I’ve mentioned before: the joy of studying mainly comes from the activity of the mind and the use of our intellect and understanding to discover or make sense of any truth. While the significance of the truth is necessary to complete the pleasure, it’s not because it adds a meaningful boost to our enjoyment. Instead, it’s only because it helps to grab our attention. When we are careless and not paying attention, the same mental activity doesn’t have any impact on us and can’t provide the satisfaction that comes from it when we’re in a different mindset.
But beside the action of the mind, which is the principal foundation of the pleasure, there is likewise required a degree of success in the attainment of the end, or the discovery of that truth we examine. Upon this head I shall make a general remark, which may be useful on many occasions, viz, that where the mind pursues any end with passion; though that passion be not derived originally from the end, but merely from the action and pursuit; yet by the natural course of the affections, we acquire a concern for the end itself, and are uneasy under any disappointment we meet with in the pursuit of it. This proceeds from the relation and parallel direction of the passions above-mentioned.
But alongside the activity of the mind, which is the main source of pleasure, a certain level of success in achieving our goal or discovering the truth we’re examining is also necessary. I’d like to make a general observation here that might be helpful in many situations: when the mind pursues a goal with passion, even if that passion doesn’t originally come from the goal itself but just from the act of pursuing it, we naturally develop an interest in the goal. This makes us feel uneasy whenever we face setbacks in our pursuit. This happens because of the relationship and similar direction of the passions mentioned above.
To illustrate all this by a similar instance, I shall observe, that there cannot be two passions more nearly resembling each other, than those of hunting and philosophy, whatever disproportion may at first sight appear betwixt them. It is evident, that the pleasure of hunting conflicts in the action of the mind and body; the motion, the attention, the difficulty, and the uncertainty. It is evident likewise, that these actions must be attended with an idea of utility, in order to their having any effect upon us. A man of the greatest fortune, and the farthest removed from avarice, though he takes a pleasure in hunting after patridges and pheasants, feels no satisfaction in shooting crows and magpies; and that because he considers the first as fit for the table, and the other as entirely useless. Here it is certain, that the utility or importance of itself causes no real passion, but is only requisite to support the imagination; and the same person, who over-looks a ten times greater profit in any other subject, is pleased to bring home half a dozen woodcocks or plovers, after having employed several hours in hunting after them. To make the parallel betwixt hunting and philosophy more compleat, we may observe, that though in both cases the end of our action may in itself be despised, yet in the heat of the action we acquire such an attention to this end, that we are very uneasy under any disappointments, and are sorry when we either miss our game, or fall into any error in our reasoning.
To illustrate this with a similar example, I’d like to point out that there are two passions that closely resemble each other: hunting and philosophy, despite the apparent differences at first glance. It’s clear that the pleasure of hunting involves both mental and physical engagement; the movement, the focus, the challenges, and the unpredictability all play a part. It’s also evident that these activities have to be linked to a sense of usefulness to have any real impact on us. A wealthy person, who isn’t greedy, might enjoy hunting for partridges and pheasants but finds no satisfaction in shooting crows and magpies because he sees the first as suitable for the table while viewing the latter as completely useless. Here, it’s certain that the usefulness or value alone doesn’t spark real passion but is needed to stimulate the imagination. The same person who overlooks a much greater benefit in other pursuits feels pleased when he brings home a few woodcocks or plovers after spending hours hunting for them. To further the comparison between hunting and philosophy, we can observe that while the ultimate goal of both activities might be deemed insignificant, in the midst of pursuing them, we become so focused on that goal that we feel frustration when we face disappointments, and we regret it when we either miss our target or make mistakes in our reasoning.
If we want another parallel to these affections, we may consider the passion of gaming, which affords a pleasure from the same principles as hunting and philosophy. It has been remarked, that the pleasure of gaming arises not from interest alone; since many leave a sure gain for this entertainment: Neither is it derived from the game alone; since the same persons have no satisfaction, when they play for nothing: But proceeds from both these causes united, though separately they have no effect. It is here, as in certain chymical preparations, where the mixture of two clear and transparent liquids produces a third, which is opaque and coloured..
If we want another example of these feelings, we can think about the passion for gaming, which brings enjoyment based on the same principles as hunting and philosophy. It's been pointed out that the pleasure of gaming doesn't come solely from the stakes; many people turn away from guaranteed winnings for this entertainment. It's also not just about the game itself; the same individuals feel no satisfaction when playing for free. Instead, the enjoyment comes from the combination of both factors, even though they don't work separately. It's like certain chemical reactions, where mixing two clear liquids results in a third that is opaque and colored.
The interest, which we have in any game, engages our attention, without which we can have no enjoyment, either in that or in any other action. Our attention being once engaged, the difficulty, variety, and sudden reverses of fortune, still farther interest us; and it is from that concern our satisfaction arises. Human life is so tiresome a scene, and men generally are of such indolent dispositions, that whatever amuses them, though by a passion mixt with pain, does in the main give them a sensible pleasure. And this pleasure is here encreased by the nature of the objects, which being sensible, and of a narrow compass, are entered into with facility, and are agreeable to the imagination.
The interest we have in any game grabs our attention, and without that, we can't enjoy it or anything else. Once our attention is caught, the challenges, variety, and unexpected ups and downs further engage us, and it’s from that involvement that our satisfaction comes. Life can be so boring, and people are usually so lazy that anything that entertains them, even if it’s mixed with some pain, ultimately gives them real pleasure. This pleasure is heightened here because the objects involved are tangible and straightforward, making them easy to engage with and pleasing to the imagination.
The same theory, that accounts for the love of truth in mathematics and algebra may be extended to morals, politics, natural philosophy, and other studies, where we consider not the other abstract relations of ideas, but their real connexions and existence. But beside the love of knowledge, which displays itself in the sciences, there is a certain curiosity implanted in human nature, which is a passion derived from a quite different principle. Some people have an insatiable desire of knowing the actions and circumstances of their neighbours, though their interest be no way concerned in them, and they must entirely depend on others for their information; in which case there is no room for study or application. Let us search for the reason of this phænomenon.
The same idea that explains the passion for truth in math and algebra can also apply to ethics, politics, natural philosophy, and other fields, where we look at the real connections and existence of ideas rather than just their abstract relationships. But in addition to the love of knowledge found in the sciences, there’s a certain curiosity rooted in human nature that comes from a completely different source. Some people have an unquenchable thirst for knowing the actions and circumstances of their neighbors, even when it doesn’t affect them at all, and they rely entirely on others for their information; in these cases, there’s no opportunity for study or effort. Let’s explore the reason behind this phenomenon.
It has been proved at large, that the influence of belief is at once to inliven and infix any idea in the imagination, and prevent all kind of hesitation and uncertainty about it. Both these circumstances are advantageous. By the vivacity of the idea we interest the fancy, and produce, though in a lesser degree, the same pleasure, which arises from a moderate passion. As the vivacity of the idea gives pleasure, so its certainty prevents uneasiness, by fixing one particular idea in the mind, and keeping it from wavering in the choice of its objects. It is a quality of human nature, which is conspicuous on many occasions, and is common both to the mind and body, that too sudden and violent a change is unpleasant to us, and that however any objects may in themselves be indifferent, yet their alteration gives uneasiness. As it is the nature of doubt to cause a variation in the thought, and transport us suddenly from one idea to another, it must of consequence be the occasion of pain. This pain chiefly takes place, where interest, relation, or the greatness and novelty of any event interests us in it. It is not every matter of fact, of which we have a curiosity to be informed; neither are they such only as we have an interest to know. It is sufficient if the idea strikes on us with such force, and concerns us so nearly, as to give us an uneasiness in its instability and inconstancy. A stranger, when he arrives first at any town, may be entirely indifferent about knowing the history and adventures of the inhabitants; but as he becomes farther acquainted with them, and has lived any considerable time among them, he acquires the same curiosity as the natives. When we are reading the history of a nation, we may have an ardent desire of clearing up any doubt or difficulty, that occurs in it; but become careless in such researches, when the ideas of these events are, in a great measure, obliterated.
It has been widely shown that belief can both energize and embed an idea in our minds, eliminating any hesitation or uncertainty about it. Both of these factors are beneficial. The vibrancy of the idea captures our imagination and generates, although to a lesser extent, the same enjoyment that comes from a moderate passion. Just as the vibrancy of an idea brings joy, its certainty eases discomfort by anchoring one specific thought in our minds and preventing it from wavering in its choices. It's a well-known aspect of human nature that too sudden or drastic changes are unpleasant for us, and that even if certain things are inherently neutral, their change can cause discomfort. Because doubt creates shifts in our thoughts, moving us abruptly from one idea to another, it inevitably leads to pain. This discomfort is most prominent when interest, relationships, or the magnitude and novelty of an event draw us in. Not every fact sparks our curiosity or matters to us, but it’s enough for an idea to hit us with such intensity and relevance that it causes us unease due to its instability and unpredictability. A newcomer arriving in a town might initially be indifferent to learning about the locals' history and experiences. However, as they get to know them better and spend significant time there, they develop the same curiosity as the locals. When we read about a nation’s history, we may feel a strong desire to resolve any questions or difficulties that arise, but we often become indifferent to such inquiries when the memories of these events have largely faded.
SECT. I MORAL DISTINCTIONS NOT DERIVED FROM REASON
There is an inconvenience which attends all abstruse reasoning that it may silence, without convincing an antagonist, and requires the same intense study to make us sensible of its force, that was at first requisite for its invention. When we leave our closet, and engage in the common affairs of life, its conclusions seem to vanish, like the phantoms of the night on the appearance of the morning; and it is difficult for us to retain even that conviction, which we had attained with difficulty. This is still more conspicuous in a long chain of reasoning, where we must preserve to the end the evidence of the first propositions, and where we often lose sight of all the most received maxims, either of philosophy or common life. I am not, however, without hopes, that the present system of philosophy will acquire new force as it advances; and that our reasonings concerning morals will corroborate whatever has been said concerning the UNDERSTANDING and the PASSIONS. Morality is a subject that interests us above all others: We fancy the peace of society to be at stake in every decision concerning it; and it is evident, that this concern must make our speculations appear more real and solid, than where the subject is, in a great measure, indifferent to us. What affects us, we conclude can never be a chimera; and as our passion is engaged on the one side or the other, we naturally think that the question lies within human comprehension; which, in other cases of this nature, we are apt to entertain some doubt of. Without this advantage I never should have ventured upon a third volume of such abstruse philosophy, in an age, wherein the greatest part of men seem agreed to convert reading into an amusement, and to reject every thing that requires any considerable degree of attention to be comprehended.
There’s an issue that comes with deep reasoning: it can quiet an opponent without actually convincing them, and understanding its power requires as much intense focus as was needed to create it in the first place. When we step away from our study and dive into everyday life, its conclusions seem to disappear like nighttime shadows when morning arrives; it's tough to hold on to even the beliefs we struggled to reach. This is even more evident in a long sequence of reasoning, where we must maintain the evidence of the initial points until the end, often losing sight of commonly accepted principles, whether in philosophy or daily life. However, I remain hopeful that the current philosophical framework will gain strength as it evolves, and that our discussions about morality will support what has been said about UNDERSTANDING and PASSIONS. Morality is a topic that captivates us more than any other: we believe society's peace hinges on every moral decision, and it's clear that this concern makes our theories seem more real and substantial than topics that don’t matter as much to us. What impacts us, we assume, cannot be mere illusion; and since our feelings lean one way or the other, we naturally believe that the issue is within human understanding, even when we might doubt that regarding other subjects. Without this edge, I wouldn’t have dared to write a third volume of such complex philosophy in an era where most people seem to agree on turning reading into a pastime and dismissing anything that requires significant attention to grasp.
It has been observed, that nothing is ever present to the mind but its perceptions; and that all the actions of seeing, hearing, judging, loving, hating, and thinking, fall under this denomination. The mind can never exert itself in any action, which we may not comprehend under the term of perception; and consequently that term is no less applicable to those judgments, by which we distinguish moral good and evil, than to every other operation of the mind. To approve of one character, to condemn another, are only so many different perceptions.
It has been observed that nothing is ever in the mind except its perceptions, and that all actions like seeing, hearing, judging, loving, hating, and thinking fall under this label. The mind can never engage in any action that we can't understand as perception; therefore, this term applies just as much to the judgments we make to distinguish moral good from evil as it does to any other mental activity. To approve of one character and condemn another are just different perceptions.
Now as perceptions resolve themselves into two kinds, viz. impressions and ideas, this distinction gives rise to a question, with which we shall open up our present enquiry concerning morals. WHETHER IT IS BY MEANS OF OUR IDEAS OR IMPRESSIONS WE DISTINGUISH BETWIXT VICE AND VIRTUE, AND PRONOUNCE AN ACTION BLAMEABLE OR PRAISEWORTHY? This will immediately cut off all loose discourses and declamations, and reduce us to something precise and exact on the present subject.
Now that perceptions can be categorized into two types, namely impressions and ideas, this distinction raises a question that will guide our current exploration of morality. WHETHER WE DISTINGUISH BETWEEN VICE AND VIRTUE AND JUDGE AN ACTION AS BLAMEWORTHY OR PRAISEWORTHY THROUGH OUR IDEAS OR IMPRESSIONS? This will quickly eliminate any vague discussions and focus us on something clear and specific regarding the topic at hand.
Those who affirm that virtue is nothing but a conformity to reason; that there are eternal fitnesses and unfitnesses of things, which are the same to every rational being that considers them; that the immutable measures of right and wrong impose an obligation, not only on human creatures, but also on the Deity himself: All these systems concur in the opinion, that morality, like truth, is discerned merely by ideas, and by their juxta-position and comparison. In order, therefore, to judge of these systems, we need only consider, whether it be possible, from reason alone, to distinguish betwixt moral good and evil, or whether there must concur some other principles to enable us to make that distinction.
Those who believe that virtue is simply following reason; that there are eternal qualities of right and wrong that apply to every rational being that considers them; that the unchanging standards of right and wrong create an obligation not only for humans but also for the Deity itself: All these perspectives agree that morality, like truth, is recognized only through ideas and their comparison with one another. Therefore, to evaluate these perspectives, we only need to consider whether it's possible, using reason alone, to tell the difference between moral good and evil, or if we need additional principles to make that distinction.
If morality had naturally no influence on human passions and actions, it were in vain to take such pains to inculcate it; and nothing would be more fruitless than that multitude of rules and precepts, with which all moralists abound. Philosophy is commonly divided into speculative and practical; and as morality is always comprehended under the latter division, it is supposed to influence our passions and actions, and to go beyond the calm and indolent judgments of the understanding. And this is confirmed by common experience, which informs us, that men are often governed by their duties, and are detered from some actions by the opinion of injustice, and impelled to others by that of obligation.
If morality didn’t naturally influence human feelings and actions, it would be pointless to try so hard to teach it; and nothing would be more useless than all the numerous rules and guidelines that moralists provide. Philosophy is usually divided into theoretical and practical; since morality falls under the practical category, it is expected to impact our feelings and actions, extending beyond the calm and relaxed judgments of the mind. This is supported by common experience, which shows us that people are often guided by their responsibilities, held back from certain actions by the perception of wrongdoing, and motivated to others by the sense of obligation.
Since morals, therefore, have an influence on the actions and affections, it follows, that they cannot be derived from reason; and that because reason alone, as we have already proved, can never have any such influence. Morals excite passions, and produce or prevent actions. Reason of itself is utterly impotent in this particular. The rules of morality therefore, are not conclusions of our reason.
Since morals influence our actions and feelings, it's clear that they can't come from reason. We've already shown that reason alone has no such power. Morals stir up emotions and either lead to or stop actions. Reason, by itself, is completely powerless in this regard. Therefore, the rules of morality aren't conclusions reached by our reason.
No one, I believe, will deny the justness of this inference; nor is there any other means of evading it, than by denying that principle, on which it is founded. As long as it is allowed, that reason has no influence on our passions and action, it is in vain to pretend, that morality is discovered only by a deduction of reason. An active principle can never be founded on an inactive; and if reason be inactive in itself, it must remain so in all its shapes and appearances, whether it exerts itself in natural or moral subjects, whether it considers the powers of external bodies, or the actions of rational beings.
No one, I think, will argue against the validity of this conclusion; there’s no way to avoid it except by denying the principle it's based on. As long as we accept that reason doesn’t affect our feelings and actions, it’s pointless to claim that morality is only figured out through reasoning. An active principle can’t come from an inactive one; and if reason is inactive by nature, it will stay that way in every form and context, whether it deals with natural phenomena or moral issues, or whether it looks at the powers of external objects or the actions of rational beings.
It would be tedious to repeat all the arguments, by which I have proved,[1] that reason is perfectly inert, and can never either prevent or produce any action or affection, it will be easy to recollect what has been said upon that subject. I shall only recall on this occasion one of these arguments, which I shall endeavour to render still more conclusive, and more applicable to the present subject.
It would be boring to go over all the arguments I’ve used to show that reason is totally inactive and can never stop or cause any action or emotion; it’s easy to remember what’s been discussed on that topic. I’ll just highlight one of these arguments this time, which I will try to make even more convincing and relevant to the current topic.
Reason is the discovery of truth or falshood. Truth or falshood consists in an agreement or disagreement either to the real relations of ideas, or to real existence and matter of fact. Whatever, therefore, is not susceptible of this agreement or disagreement, is incapable of being true or false, and can never be an object of our reason. Now it is evident our passions, volitions, and actions, are not susceptible of any such agreement or disagreement; being original facts and realities, compleat in themselves, and implying no reference to other passions, volitions, and actions. It is impossible, therefore, they can be pronounced either true or false, and be either contrary or conformable to reason.
Reason is the discovery of truth or falsehood. Truth or falsehood is based on whether there's agreement or disagreement with the actual relationships between ideas or with real existence and facts. So, whatever cannot have this kind of agreement or disagreement cannot be considered true or false and can't be a subject of our reasoning. Clearly, our feelings, decisions, and actions don't fit into that framework; they are original facts and realities, complete in themselves, and don’t reference other feelings, decisions, or actions. Therefore, it’s impossible for them to be labeled as either true or false in relation to reason.
This argument is of double advantage to our present purpose. For it proves DIRECTLY, that actions do not derive their merit from a conformity to reason, nor their blame from a contrariety to it; and it proves the same truth more INDIRECTLY, by shewing us, that as reason can never immediately prevent or produce any action by contradicting or approving of it, it cannot be the source of moral good and evil, which are found to have that influence. Actions may be laudable or blameable; but they cannot be reasonable: Laudable or blameable, therefore, are not the same with reasonable or unreasonable. The merit and demerit of actions frequently contradict, and sometimes controul our natural propensities. But reason has no such influence. Moral distinctions, therefore, are not the offspring of reason. Reason is wholly inactive, and can never be the source of so active a principle as conscience, or a sense of morals.
This argument is doubly beneficial for our current discussion. It directly shows that actions don’t gain their value from aligning with reason, nor do they deserve blame for going against it. It also indirectly supports this idea by demonstrating that since reason can never directly cause or prevent an action by opposing or approving of it, it can't be the source of moral good and evil, which have that kind of influence. Actions can be praiseworthy or blameworthy, but they can’t be labeled as reasonable. Thus, being praiseworthy or blameworthy is not the same as being reasonable or unreasonable. The value and faults of actions often clash and can sometimes override our natural instincts. However, reason doesn't have that kind of power. Therefore, moral distinctions do not originate from reason. Reason is completely inactive and can never be the source of something as dynamic as conscience or a sense of morality.
But perhaps it may be said, that though no will or action can be immediately contradictory to reason, yet we may find such a contradiction in some of the attendants of the action, that is, in its causes or effects. The action may cause a judgment, or may be obliquely caused by one, when the judgment concurs with a passion; and by an abusive way of speaking, which philosophy will scarce allow of, the same contrariety may, upon that account, be ascribed to the action. How far this truth or falsehood may be the source of morals, it will now be proper to consider.
But maybe we can say that although no choice or action can directly contradict reason, we might find such a contradiction in some aspects of the action, specifically in its causes or effects. The action could lead to a judgment, or it might be influenced by one, especially when that judgment aligns with an emotion. In a somewhat misleading way of speaking that philosophy would hardly accept, the same contradiction can be attributed to the action for that reason. Now, it’s important to consider how this truth or falsehood might be the foundation of morals.
It has been observed, that reason, in a strict and philosophical sense, can have influence on our conduct only after two ways: Either when it excites a passion by informing us of the existence of something which is a proper object of it; or when it discovers the connexion of causes and effects, so as to afford us means of exerting any passion. These are the only kinds of judgment, which can accompany our actions, or can be said to produce them in any manner; and it must be allowed, that these judgments may often be false and erroneous. A person may be affected with passion, by supposing a pain or pleasure to lie in an object, which has no tendency to produce either of these sensations, or which produces the contrary to what is imagined. A person may also take false measures for the attaining his end, and may retard, by his foolish conduct, instead of forwarding the execution of any project. These false judgments may be thought to affect the passions and actions, which are connected with them, and may be said to render them unreasonable, in a figurative and improper way of speaking. But though this be acknowledged, it is easy to observe, that these errors are so far from being the source of all immorality, that they are commonly very innocent, and draw no manner of guilt upon the person who is so unfortunate as to fail into them. They extend not beyond a mistake of fact, which moralists have not generally supposed criminal, as being perfectly involuntary. I am more to be lamented than blamed, if I am mistaken with regard to the influence of objects in producing pain or pleasure, or if I know not the proper means of satisfying my desires. No one can ever regard such errors as a defect in my moral character. A fruit, for instance, that is really disagreeable, appears to me at a distance, and through mistake I fancy it to be pleasant and delicious. Here is one error. I choose certain means of reaching this fruit, which are not proper for my end. Here is a second error; nor is there any third one, which can ever possibly enter into our reasonings concerning actions. I ask, therefore, if a man, in this situation, and guilty of these two errors, is to be regarded as vicious and criminal, however unavoidable they might have been? Or if it be possible to imagine, that such errors are the sources of all immorality?
It has been observed that reason, in a strict and philosophical sense, can influence our actions in two ways: either by stirring a passion by making us aware of something that is a suitable object of it, or by revealing the connection of causes and effects, allowing us to act on any passion. These are the only types of judgments that can accompany our actions or can be said to produce them in any way; and it's true that these judgments can often be wrong and misleading. A person might experience passion by thinking that a certain object brings pain or pleasure when it doesn't lead to either sensation or even causes the opposite of what is expected. A person might also take the wrong steps to achieve a goal and, by acting foolishly, delay rather than advance the completion of any project. These incorrect judgments can be thought to influence the passions and actions linked to them, and can be described as making them unreasonable in a figurative and improper way. However, even though this is acknowledged, it’s easy to see that these mistakes are far from being the root of all immorality; in fact, they are usually quite innocent and don’t bring any guilt to the person who is unfortunate enough to make them. They only reflect a mistake of fact, which ethicists generally do not consider criminal, viewing them as entirely involuntary. I deserve more sympathy than blame if I’m mistaken about how objects influence pain or pleasure, or if I don’t know the right ways to satisfy my desires. No one could see such errors as a flaw in my moral character. For example, a fruit that is genuinely unpleasant might look appealing to me from afar, and I mistakenly believe it to be sweet and delicious. That’s one mistake. I choose certain approaches to get this fruit that aren't suitable for my goal. That’s a second mistake; and there isn’t any third possible error in our reasoning about actions. So, I ask, if a person in this situation, who has made these two mistakes, should be regarded as vicious and criminal, no matter how unavoidable those mistakes may have been? Or could we imagine that such mistakes are the root of all immorality?
And here it may be proper to observe, that if moral distinctions be derived from the truth or falshood of those judgments, they must take place wherever we form the judgments; nor will there be any difference, whether the question be concerning an apple or a kingdom, or whether the error be avoidable or unavoidable. For as the very essence of morality is supposed to consist in an agreement or disagreement to reason, the other circumstances are entirely arbitrary, and can never either bestow on any action the character of virtuous or vicious, or deprive it of that character. To which we may add, that this agreement or disagreement, not admitting of degrees, all virtues and vices would of course be equal.
And here it’s important to point out that if moral distinctions come from the truth or falsehood of those judgments, they should apply wherever we make those judgments; it won’t matter whether the issue is about an apple or a kingdom, or if the mistake is avoidable or unavoidable. The very essence of morality is believed to depend on alignment or misalignment with reason, so the other factors are completely arbitrary and can never give any action the quality of being virtuous or vicious, nor take that quality away. Additionally, since this alignment or misalignment does not allow for degrees, all virtues and vices would inherently be equal.
Should it be pretended, that though a mistake of fact be not criminal, yet a mistake of right often is; and that this may be the source of immorality: I would answer, that it is impossible such a mistake can ever be the original source of immorality, since it supposes a real right and wrong; that is, a real distinction in morals, independent of these judgments. A mistake, therefore, of right may become a species of immorality; but it is only a secondary one, and is founded on some other, antecedent to it.
If we pretend that a factual mistake isn't criminal but a mistake about what’s right often is, and that this might lead to immorality, I would respond that it’s impossible for such a mistake to be the original source of immorality because it assumes a genuine distinction between right and wrong. In other words, there is an actual difference in morals that exists independent of these judgments. Therefore, a mistake about what’s right can be a form of immorality, but it’s only a secondary one and is based on something else that came before it.
As to those judgments which are the effects of our actions, and which, when false, give occasion to pronounce the actions contrary to truth and reason; we may observe, that our actions never cause any judgment, either true or false, in ourselves, and that it is only on others they have such an influence. It is certain, that an action, on many occasions, may give rise to false conclusions in others; and that a person, who through a window sees any lewd behaviour of mine with my neighbour's wife, may be so simple as to imagine she is certainly my own. In this respect my action resembles somewhat a lye or falshood; only with this difference, which is material, that I perform not the action with any intention of giving rise to a false judgment in another, but merely to satisfy my lust and passion. It causes, however, a mistake and false judgment by accident; and the falshood of its effects may be ascribed, by some odd figurative way of speaking, to the action itself. But still I can see no pretext of reason for asserting, that the tendency to cause such an error is the first spring or original source of all immorality.[2]
Regarding judgments that result from our actions, which, when incorrect, lead people to deem those actions as untrue and unreasonable; we can note that our actions do not create judgments, true or false, within ourselves, and their influence only extends to others. It’s clear that an action can sometimes lead others to draw incorrect conclusions; for instance, someone who sees inappropriate behavior of mine with my neighbor's wife through a window might naively assume she is my wife. In this way, my action is somewhat like a lie or falsehood; however, the significant difference is that I don't act with the intention to mislead anyone, but simply to satisfy my own desires. Nevertheless, it can cause misunderstandings and incorrect judgments inadvertently, and the falsehood of its results may be, in a somewhat figurative manner, attributed to the action itself. However, I find no valid reason to claim that the potential to create such errors is the primary cause or source of all immorality.[2]
[2]
One might think it were entirely superfluous to prove this, if a late author
[William Wollaston, THE RELIGION OF NATURE DELINEATED (London 1722)], who has
had the good fortune to obtain some reputation, had not seriously affirmed,
that such a falshood is the foundation of all guilt and moral deformity. That
we may discover the fallacy of his hypothesis, we need only consider, that a
false conclusion is drawn from an action, only by means of an obscurity of
natural principles, which makes a cause be secretly interrupted in its
operation, by contrary causes, and renders the connexion betwixt two objects
uncertain and variable. Now, as a like uncertainty and variety of causes take
place, even in natural objects, and produce a like error in our judgment, if
that tendency to produce error were the very essence of vice and immorality, it
should follow, that even inanimate objects might be vicious and immoral.
It is in vain to urge, that inanimate objects act without liberty and
choice. For as liberty and choice are not necessary to make an action produce
in us an erroneous conclusion, they can be, in no respect, essential to
morality; and I do not readily perceive, upon this system, how they can ever
come to be regarded by it. If the tendency to cause error be the origin of
immorality, that tendency and immorality would in every case be
inseparable.
Add to this, that if I had used the precaution of shutting the windows,
while I indulged myself in those liberties with my neighbour's wife, I should
have been guilty of no immorality; and that because my action, being perfectly
concealed, would have had no tendency to produce any false conclusion.
For the same reason, a thief, who steals in by a ladder at a window, and
takes all imaginable care to cause no disturbance, is in no respect criminal.
For either he will not be perceived, or if he be, it is impossible he can
produce any error, nor will any one, from these circumstances, take him to be
other than what he really is.
It is well known, that those who are squint-sighted, do very readily cause
mistakes in others, and that we imagine they salute or are talking to one
person, while they address themselves to another. Are they therefore, upon that
account, immoral?
Besides, we may easily observe, that in all those arguments there is an
evident reasoning in a circle. A person who takes possession of another's
goods, and uses them as his own, in a manner declares them to be his own; and
this falshood is the source of the immorality of injustice. But is property, or
right, or obligation, intelligible, without an antecedent morality?
A man that is ungrateful to his benefactor, in a manner affirms, that he
never received any favours from him. But in what manner? Is it because it is
his duty to be grateful? But this supposes, that there is some antecedent rule
of duty and morals. Is it because human nature is generally grateful, and makes
us conclude, that a man who does any harm never received any favour from the
person he harmed? But human nature is not so generally grateful, as to justify
such a conclusion. Or if it were, is an exception to a general rule in every
case criminal, for no other reason than because it is an exception?
But what may suffice entirely to destroy this whimsical system is, that it
leaves us under the same difficulty to give a reason why truth is virtuous and
falshood vicious, as to account for the merit or turpitude of any other action.
I shall allow, if you please, that all immorality is derived from this supposed
falshood in action, provided you can give me any plausible reason, why such a
falshood is immoral. If you consider rightly of the matter, you will find
yourself in the same difficulty as at the beginning.
This last argument is very conclusive; because, if there be not an evident
merit or turpitude annexed to this species of truth or falahood, It can never
have any influence upon our actions. For, who ever thought of forbearing any
action, because others might possibly draw false conclusions from it? Or, who
ever performed any, that he might give rise to true conclusions?
[2] One might think it unnecessary to prove this, if a recent author [William Wollaston, THE RELIGION OF NATURE DELINEATED (London 1722)] hadn’t seriously claimed that such a falsehood is the basis of all guilt and moral wrongness. To uncover the flaw in his argument, we only need to consider that a false conclusion is drawn from an action due to the obscurity of natural principles, which can cause a cause to be subtly interrupted by opposing causes and makes the connection between two objects uncertain and variable. Since a similar uncertainty and variety of causes also occur in natural objects and lead to a comparable mistake in our judgment, if the tendency to cause error were the essence of vice and immorality, it would mean that even inanimate objects could be considered vicious and immoral.
It’s pointless to claim that inanimate objects act without freedom and choice. Since freedom and choice are not necessary for an action to lead us to an erroneous conclusion, they cannot be essential to morality; and I don't see how, under this system, they could ever be valued by it. If causing error is the source of immorality, then that tendency and immorality would be inseparable in every case.
Add to this the fact that if I had taken the precaution of shutting the windows while engaging in those liberties with my neighbor's wife, I would have committed no immorality because my action, being entirely concealed, would not have led to any false conclusion.
For the same reason, a thief who sneaks in through a window with a ladder and takes all possible care to avoid making a disturbance is not guilty in any way. Either he won't be noticed, or if he is, it's impossible for him to cause any error, and no one would think of him as anything other than what he really is.
It’s well known that people who are cross-eyed often cause misunderstandings in others, leading us to think they’re greeting or talking to one person when they’re actually addressing another. Are they immoral for this reason?
Furthermore, it's easy to spot the circular reasoning in all of these arguments. A person who takes someone else's belongings and uses them as their own effectively claims them as their own; and this falsehood is the source of the immorality of injustice. But can property, or rights, or obligations be understood without a prior sense of morality?
A person who is ungrateful to their benefactor effectively denies having received any help from them. But how so? Is it because they’re obliged to be grateful? That presupposes an existing rule of duty and morals. Is it because human nature is generally grateful, leading us to conclude that a person who does any harm has never received a favor from the person they wronged? But human nature isn’t so universally grateful as to support that conclusion. Or if it were, is an exception to a general rule in every case immoral just because it’s an exception?
What really breaks down this peculiar system is that it leaves us with the same difficulty in explaining why truth is virtuous and falsehood is vicious, as we have in explaining the merit or depravity of any other action. I'll concede, if you'd like, that all immorality comes from this supposed falsehood in action, as long as you can provide a convincing reason as to why such a falsehood is immoral. If you think about it properly, you’ll find yourself in the same predicament as you were at the start.
This final argument is very compelling because if there isn’t an obvious merit or depravity attached to this type of truth or falsehood, it can never influence our actions. After all, who has ever thought about holding back from an action because others might draw false conclusions from it? Or who has ever performed an action just to lead to true conclusions?
Thus upon the whole, it is impossible, that the distinction betwixt moral good and evil, can be made to reason; since that distinction has an influence upon our actions, of which reason alone is incapable. Reason and judgment may, indeed, be the mediate cause of an action, by prompting, or by directing a passion: But it is not pretended, that a judgment of this kind, either in its truth or falshood, is attended with virtue or vice. And as to the judgments, which are caused by our judgments, they can still less bestow those moral qualities on the actions, which are their causes.
Overall, it's impossible to reduce the difference between moral good and evil to reason alone, as that distinction influences our actions in a way that reason by itself cannot. Reason and judgment can serve as indirect causes of an action by either prompting or directing a passion. However, it’s not claimed that such judgments, whether true or false, are associated with virtue or vice. Moreover, the judgments that stem from our decisions are even less capable of assigning those moral qualities to the actions that caused them.
But to be more particular, and to shew, that those eternal immutable fitnesses and unfitnesses of things cannot be defended by sound philosophy, we may weigh the following considerations.
But to be more specific, and to show that those eternal, unchanging qualities of things can't be defended by sound philosophy, we can consider the following points.
If the thought and understanding were alone capable of fixing the boundaries of right and wrong, the character of virtuous and vicious either must lie in some relations of objects, or must be a matter of fact, which is discovered by our reasoning. This consequence is evident. As the operations of human understanding divide themselves into two kinds, the comparing of ideas, and the inferring of matter of fact; were virtue discovered by the understanding; it must be an object of one of these operations, nor is there any third operation of the understanding. which can discover it. There has been an opinion very industriously propagated by certain philosophers, that morality is susceptible of demonstration; and though no one has ever been able to advance a single step in those demonstrations; yet it is taken for granted, that this science may be brought to an equal certainty with geometry or algebra. Upon this supposition vice and virtue must consist in some relations; since it is allowed on all hands, that no matter of fact is capable of being demonstrated. Let us, therefore, begin with examining this hypothesis, and endeavour, if possible, to fix those moral qualities, which have been so long the objects of our fruitless researches. Point out distinctly the relations, which constitute morality or obligation, that we may know wherein they consist, and after what manner we must judge of them.
If thinking and understanding were solely responsible for defining right and wrong, then the nature of good and bad would either depend on the relationships between things or would be a factual matter revealed through our reasoning. This conclusion is clear. Since human understanding operates in two ways—comparing ideas and drawing conclusions about facts—if virtue were revealed through understanding, it would have to fall under one of these processes, as there is no third way for understanding to uncover it. Some philosophers have actively promoted the idea that morality can be demonstrated, and while no one has managed to make any progress in these demonstrations, it is assumed that this area of study could achieve the same level of certainty as geometry or algebra. Based on this assumption, good and bad must involve certain relationships, since it is generally accepted that no factual matter can be demonstrated. Let’s start by examining this assumption and try to identify the moral qualities we have long sought without success. Clearly outline the relationships that define morality or obligation so that we can understand their essence and determine how we should evaluate them.
If you assert, that vice and virtue consist in relations susceptible of certainty and demonstration, you must confine yourself to those four relations, which alone admit of that degree of evidence; and in that case you run into absurdities, from which you will never be able to extricate yourself. For as you make the very essence of morality to lie in the relations, and as there is no one of these relations but what is applicable, not only to an irrational, but also to an inanimate object; it follows, that even such objects must be susceptible of merit or demerit. RESEMBLANCE, CONTRARIETY, DEGREES IN QUALITY, and PROPORTIONS IN QUANTITY AND NUMBER; all these relations belong as properly to matter, as to our actions, passions, and volitions. It is unquestionable, therefore, that morality lies not in any of these relations, nor the sense of it in their discovery.[3]
If you claim that vice and virtue are based on relationships that can be clearly defined and demonstrated, you have to limit yourself to those four relationships that allow for that level of evidence; otherwise, you'll end up in absurd situations that you won’t be able to escape. By making the very foundation of morality depend on these relationships, and since each of these relationships can apply not just to living beings but also to non-living things, it follows that even those objects must have some kind of merit or lack thereof. RESEMBLANCE, CONTRADICTION, DIFFERENCES IN QUALITY, and RATIOS IN QUANTITY AND NUMBER all apply just as much to physical matter as they do to our actions, feelings, and intentions. Therefore, it's clear that morality doesn't actually exist in any of these relationships, nor is the understanding of it found in discovering them. [3]
[3] As a proof, how confused our way of thinking on this subject commonly is, we may observe, that those who assert, that morality is demonstrable, do not say, that morality lies in the relations, and that the relations are distinguishable by reason. They only say, that reason can discover such an action, in such relations, to be virtuous, and such another vicious. It seems they thought it sufficient, if they could bring the word, Relation, into the proposition, without troubling themselves whether it was to the purpose or not. But here, I think, is plain argument. Demonstrative reason discovers only relations. But that reason, according to this hypothesis, discovers also vice and virtue. These moral qualities, therefore, must be relations. When we blame any action, in any situation, the whole complicated object, of action and situation, must form certain relations, wherein the essence of vice consists. This hypothesis is not otherwise intelligible. For what does reason discover, when it pronounces any action vicious? Does it discover a relation or a matter of fact? These questions are decisive, and must not be eluded.
[3] As proof of how confused our thinking on this subject often is, we can see that those who claim that morality can be proven don't actually say that morality is based on relationships or that those relationships can be identified by reason. They simply state that reason can determine that one action in a particular context is virtuous and another is vicious. It seems they believe it's enough to include the word "Relation" in their argument without considering whether it's relevant. However, I believe there's a clear point here. Demonstrative reasoning only reveals relationships. Yet, this reasoning, according to their claim, also identifies vice and virtue. Therefore, these moral qualities must be based on relationships. When we criticize an action in a given situation, the entire complex of action and situation must create specific relationships, within which the essence of vice exists. This idea doesn’t make sense otherwise. For what does reason actually discover when it labels an action as vicious? Does it find a relationship or a factual situation? These questions are crucial and cannot be avoided.
Should it be asserted, that the sense of morality consists in the discovery of some relation, distinct from these, and that our enumeration was not compleat, when we comprehended all demonstrable relations under four general heads: To this I know not what to reply, till some one be so good as to point out to me this new relation. It is impossible to refute a system, which has never yet been explained. In such a manner of fighting in the dark, a man loses his blows in the air, and often places them where the enemy is not present.
If someone wants to claim that morality is about discovering a relation beyond what we've covered, and that our list isn't complete with just four general categories, I honestly don't know how to respond until someone can clearly identify this new relation. It's impossible to argue against a system that hasn't been properly explained. In this way of battling in the dark, a person ends up swinging at nothing and often punches where the opponent isn’t even present.
I must, therefore, on this occasion, rest contented with requiring the two following conditions of any one that would undertake to clear up this system. First, As moral good and evil belong only to the actions of the mind, and are derived from our situation with regard to external objects, the relations, from which these moral distinctions arise, must lie only betwixt internal actions, and external objects, and must not be applicable either to internal actions, compared among themselves, or to external objects, when placed in opposition to other external objects. For as morality is supposed to attend certain relations, if these relations could belong to internal actions considered singly, it would follow, that we might be guilty of crimes in ourselves, and independent of our situation, with respect to the universe: And in like manner, if these moral relations could be applied to external objects, it would follow, that even inanimate beings would be susceptible of moral beauty and deformity. Now it seems difficult to imagine, that any relation can be discovered betwixt our passions, volitions and actions, compared to external objects, which relation might not belong either to these passions and volitions, or to these external objects, compared among themselves. But it will be still more difficult to fulfil the second condition, requisite to justify this system. According to the principles of those who maintain an abstract rational difference betwixt moral good and evil, and a natural fitness and unfitness of things, it is not only supposed, that these relations, being eternal and immutable, are the same, when considered by every rational creature, but their effects are also supposed to be necessarily the same; and it is concluded they have no less, or rather a greater, influence in directing the will of the deity, than in governing the rational and virtuous of our own species. These two particulars are evidently distinct. It is one thing to know virtue, and another to conform the will to it. In order, therefore, to prove, that the measures of right and wrong are eternal laws, obligatory on every rational mind, it is not sufficient to shew the relations upon which they are founded: We must also point out the connexion betwixt the relation and the will; and must prove that this connexion is so necessary, that in every well-disposed mind, it must take place and have its influence; though the difference betwixt these minds be in other respects immense and infinite. Now besides what I have already proved, that even in human nature no relation can ever alone produce any action: besides this, I say, it has been shewn, in treating of the understanding, that there is no connexion of cause and effect, such as this is supposed to be, which is discoverable otherwise than by experience, and of which we can pretend to have any security by the simple consideration of the objects. All beings in the universe, considered in themselves, appear entirely loose and independent of each other. It is only by experience we learn their influence and connexion; and this influence we ought never to extend beyond experience.
I must, therefore, at this time, be satisfied with requiring two conditions from anyone who would try to clarify this system. First, since moral good and evil are only tied to the actions of the mind and stem from our relationship to external objects, the connections that create these moral distinctions must only exist between internal actions and external objects. They should not be applicable either to internal actions compared to each other or to external objects when set against other external objects. For morality is said to relate to certain connections; if these connections could apply to internal actions considered on their own, it would mean we could be blamed for crimes within ourselves, independently of our situation in the universe. Similarly, if these moral connections could apply to external objects, it would imply that even inanimate things could possess moral beauty or ugliness. It seems challenging to imagine that any connection can be found between our feelings, will, and actions when compared to external objects that wouldn’t also relate to those feelings and will, or to those external objects, compared among themselves. However, it will be even more challenging to meet the second condition needed to justify this system. According to those who argue for an abstract rational difference between moral good and evil and a natural appropriateness or inappropriateness of things, it's not only assumed that these connections, being eternal and unchanging, are the same when viewed by any rational being, but it is also assumed that their effects are necessarily the same. It is concluded that these connections have as much, if not more, influence on the will of the deity as they do in guiding rational and virtuous humans. These two aspects are clearly separate. It’s one thing to understand virtue, and quite another to align the will with it. Thus, to demonstrate that the concepts of right and wrong are eternal laws that bind every rational mind, it’s not enough to show the connections they are based on; we also need to highlight the link between those connections and the will and prove that this link is essential, so that in every well-ordered mind, it must occur and have its influence, even though the differences between these minds may be vast and infinite. Now, in addition to what I have already shown, that even in human nature no connection can produce any action on its own: aside from this, I say, it has been demonstrated in the study of understanding that there is no cause-and-effect link, as it is assumed, which can be discovered other than through experience, and of which we can claim any certainty just by considering the objects. All beings in the universe, when considered in themselves, appear to be completely loose and independent of each other. We only learn about their influence and connections through experience, and we should never extend this influence beyond what we have experienced.
Thus it will be impossible to fulfil the first condition required to the system of eternal measures of right and wrong; because it is impossible to shew those relations, upon which such a distinction may be founded: And it is as impossible to fulfil the second condition; because we cannot prove A PRIORI, that these relations, if they really existed and were perceived, would be universally forcible and obligatory.
Thus, it will be impossible to meet the first requirement for a system of timeless measures of right and wrong because it’s impossible to demonstrate the relationships on which such a distinction could be based. And it is equally impossible to meet the second requirement, since we cannot prove A PRIORI that these relationships, if they actually existed and were understood, would be universally compelling and binding.
But to make these general reflections more clear and convincing, we may illustrate them by some particular instances, wherein this character of moral good or evil is the most universally acknowledged. Of all crimes that human creatures are capable of committing, the most horrid and unnatural is ingratitude, especially when it is committed against parents, and appears in the more flagrant instances of wounds and death. This is acknowledged by all mankind, philosophers as well as the people; the question only arises among philosophers, whether the guilt or moral deformity of this action be discovered by demonstrative reasoning, or be felt by an internal sense, and by means of some sentiment, which the reflecting on such an action naturally occasions. This question will soon be decided against the former opinion, if we can shew the same relations in other objects, without the notion of any guilt or iniquity attending them. Reason or science is nothing but the comparing of ideas, and the discovery of their relations; and if the same relations have different characters, it must evidently follow, that those characters are not discovered merely by reason. To put the affair, therefore, to this trial, let us chuse any inanimate object, such as an oak or elm; and let us suppose, that by the dropping of its seed, it produces a sapling below it, which springing up by degrees, at last overtops and destroys the parent tree: I ask, if in this instance there be wanting any relation, which is discoverable in parricide or ingratitude? Is not the one tree the cause of the other's existence; and the latter the cause of the destruction of the former, in the same manner as when a child murders his parent? It is not sufficient to reply, that a choice or will is wanting. For in the case of parricide, a will does not give rise to any DIFFERENT relations, but is only the cause from which the action is derived; and consequently produces the same relations, that in the oak or elm arise from some other principles. It is a will or choice, that determines a man to kill his parent; and they are the laws of matter and motion, that determine a sapling to destroy the oak, from which it sprung. Here then the same relations have different causes; but still the relations are the same: And as their discovery is not in both cases attended with a notion of immorality, it follows, that that notion does not arise from such a discovery.
But to clarify and strengthen these general reflections, we can illustrate them with specific examples where the idea of moral good or evil is most widely recognized. Of all the crimes that humans can commit, the most horrific and unnatural is ingratitude, especially when it is directed at parents, particularly when it manifests in extreme forms like violence and murder. This is recognized by everyone, philosophers and the general public alike; the only debate among philosophers is whether the guilt or moral wrongness of this act is revealed through logical reasoning or felt through an internal sense, alongside some sentiment that reflecting on such actions naturally evokes. This debate will quickly favor the latter view if we can demonstrate similar relationships in other scenarios without any notion of guilt or wrongdoing attached. Reason or science is simply about comparing ideas and discovering their connections; if the same connections have different meanings, it clearly follows that those meanings aren't discovered purely through reason. So, to put this to the test, let’s take any inanimate object, like an oak or elm tree; suppose that it drops seeds that grow into a sapling underneath it, which eventually grows tall enough to overshadow and kill the parent tree: I ask, is there a relationship here that isn’t present in parricide or ingratitude? Isn’t one tree the reason for the other’s existence, and isn’t the latter responsible for the former’s destruction, just like when a child kills a parent? It’s not enough to say that a choice or will is missing. In the case of parricide, a will does not create any different relationships; it simply becomes the source of the act, which generates the same relationships that arise from other principles in the case of the oak or elm. It is a will or choice that drives a person to kill their parent; and it is the laws of matter and motion that lead a sapling to destroy the oak from which it came. Here, then, the same relationships have different causes; yet those relationships remain unchanged: and since recognizing them in both cases doesn’t involve a notion of immorality, it follows that this notion does not stem from such recognition.
But to chuse an instance, still more resembling; I would fain ask any one, why incest in the human species is criminal, and why the very same action, and the same relations in animals have not the smallest moral turpitude and deformity? If it be answered, that this action is innocent in animals, because they have not reason sufficient to discover its turpitude; but that man, being endowed with that faculty which ought to restrain him to his duty, the same action instantly becomes criminal to him; should this be said, I would reply, that this is evidently arguing in a circle. For before reason can perceive this turpitude, the turpitude must exist; and consequently is independent of the decisions of our reason, and is their object more properly than their effect. According to this system, then, every animal, that has sense, and appetite, and will; that is, every animal must be susceptible of all the same virtues and vices, for which we ascribe praise and blame to human creatures. All the difference is, that our superior reason may serve to discover the vice or virtue, and by that means may augment the blame or praise: But still this discovery supposes a separate being in these moral distinctions, and a being, which depends only on the will and appetite, and which, both in thought and reality, may be distinguished from the reason. Animals are susceptible of the same relations, with respect to each other, as the human species, and therefore would also be susceptible of the same morality, if the essence of morality consisted in these relations. Their want of a sufficient degree of reason may hinder them from perceiving the duties and obligations of morality, but can never hinder these duties from existing; since they must antecedently exist, in order to their being perceived. Reason must find them, and can never produce them. This argument deserves to be weighed, as being, in my opinion, entirely decisive.
But to choose an example that’s even more similar, I’d like to ask anyone why incest in humans is considered a crime, while the same behavior and relationships among animals don’t carry any moral wrongdoing or deformity. If someone argues that this behavior is innocent in animals because they lack the reasoning ability to recognize its wrongness, but that humans, equipped with a reason meant to guide them to do their duty, find the same behavior to be criminal, I would respond that this reasoning is clearly circular. For reason must first recognize the wrongdoing before it can be perceived; thus, the wrongdoing exists independently of our reasoning and is more of its object than its effect. According to this line of thinking, every animal that has senses, desires, and will—essentially, every animal—should be capable of the same virtues and vices for which we give praise and blame to humans. The difference is that our superior reasoning can identify vice or virtue, and consequently, can amplify blame or praise. However, discovering these distinctions implies a separate existence of morality that relies solely on will and desire, which can be distinguished from reason both in thought and in reality. Animals can form the same relationships with one another as humans do, and therefore would also be capable of the same moral standings if morality were based on those relationships. Their lack of sufficient reasoning might prevent them from understanding moral duties and obligations, but it can never stop those duties from existing. They must exist beforehand for them to be recognized. Reason must discover them but can never create them. This argument is worth considering, as I believe it is entirely conclusive.
Nor does this reasoning only prove, that morality consists not in any relations, that are the objects of science; but if examined, will prove with equal certainty, that it consists not in any matter of fact, which can be discovered by the understanding. This is the second part of our argument; and if it can be made evident, we may conclude, that morality is not an object of reason. But can there be any difficulty in proving, that vice and virtue are not matters of fact, whose existence we can infer by reason? Take any action allowed to be vicious: Wilful murder, for instance. Examine it in all lights, and see if you can find that matter of fact, or real existence, which you call vice. In which-ever way you take it, you find only certain passions, motives, volitions and thoughts. There is no other matter of fact in the case. The vice entirely escapes you, as long as you consider the object. You never can find it, till you turn your reflection into your own breast, and find a sentiment of disapprobation, which arises in you, towards this action. Here is a matter of fact; but it is the object of feeling, not of reason. It lies in yourself, not in the object. So that when you pronounce any action or character to be vicious, you mean nothing, but that from the constitution of your nature you have a feeling or sentiment of blame from the contemplation of it. Vice and virtue, therefore, may be compared to sounds, colours, heat and cold, which, according to modern philosophy, are not qualities in objects, but perceptions in the mind: And this discovery in morals, like that other in physics, is to be regarded as a considerable advancement of the speculative sciences; though, like that too, it has little or no influence on practice. Nothing can be more real, or concern us more, than our own sentiments of pleasure and uneasiness; and if these be favourable to virtue, and unfavourable to vice, no more can be requisite to the regulation of our conduct and behaviour.
This reasoning also shows that morality isn't based on any relationships that science studies; if we dig deeper, it will clearly demonstrate that it isn't about any facts that we can figure out through understanding. This is the second part of our argument, and if we can make this clear, we can say that morality isn't something reason governs. But is it hard to prove that vice and virtue aren’t facts we can deduce through reason? Take any action deemed vicious: for example, premeditated murder. Look at it from all angles and see if you can find that fact, or true existence, that you call vice. No matter how you approach it, you find only certain feelings, motives, choices, and thoughts. There's no other fact in the situation. The vice eludes you as long as you focus on the action itself. You will never find it until you turn your attention inward and discover a feeling of disapproval that arises in you towards this action. This is a fact, but it originates from your feelings, not from reason. It exists within you, not in the action. So when you label any action or trait as vicious, you’re essentially saying that based on your nature, you feel a sense of blame when you contemplate it. Vice and virtue can be likened to sounds, colors, heat, and cold, which, according to modern philosophy, are not inherent qualities of objects but rather perceptions in the mind. This discovery in morals, similar to that in physics, should be seen as a significant advancement in the speculative sciences; although, like that, it has little to no impact on practical matters. Nothing is more real or affects us more than our own feelings of pleasure and discomfort; and if these feelings support virtue and oppose vice, that’s all we need for guiding our conduct and behavior.
I cannot forbear adding to these reasonings an observation, which may, perhaps, be found of some importance. In every system of morality, which I have hitherto met with, I have always remarked, that the author proceeds for some time in the ordinary way of reasoning, and establishes the being of a God, or makes observations concerning human affairs; when of a sudden I am surprized to find, that instead of the usual copulations of propositions, is, and is not, I meet with no proposition that is not connected with an ought, or an ought not. This change is imperceptible; but is, however, of the last consequence. For as this ought, or ought not, expresses some new relation or affirmation, it is necessary that it should be observed and explained; and at the same time that a reason should be given, for what seems altogether inconceivable, how this new relation can be a deduction from others, which are entirely different from it. But as authors do not commonly use this precaution, I shall presume to recommend it to the readers; and am persuaded, that this small attention would subvert all the vulgar systems of morality, and let us see, that the distinction of vice and virtue is not founded merely on the relations of objects, nor is perceived by reason.
I can't help but add an observation to these discussions, which might be important. In every moral system I've come across so far, I've noticed that the author starts with common reasoning and establishes the existence of a God or makes comments about human affairs; then suddenly, I'm surprised to find that instead of the usual “is” and “is not” statements, all the propositions are now tied to an “ought” or “ought not.” This shift is subtle but incredibly important. Since this “ought” or “ought not” shows a new relationship or affirmation, it needs to be recognized and explained, and we also need a reason for what seems impossible: how this new relationship can be derived from others that are completely different. However, since authors usually don't take this step, I will suggest it to readers; I believe that paying attention to this could challenge all the conventional moral systems and reveal that the distinction between vice and virtue isn't just based on the relationships between objects, nor is it recognized by reason.
SECT. II MORAL DISTINCTIONS DERIVED FROM A MORAL SENSE
Thus the course of the argument leads us to conclude, that since vice and virtue are not discoverable merely by reason, or the comparison of ideas, it must be by means of some impression or sentiment they occasion, that we are able to mark the difference betwixt them. Our decisions concerning moral rectitude and depravity are evidently perceptions; and as all perceptions are either impressions or ideas, the exclusion of the one is a convincing argument for the other. Morality, therefore, is more properly felt than judged of; though this feeling or sentiment is commonly so soft and gentle, that we are apt to confound it with an idea, according to our common custom of taking all things for the same, which have any near resemblance to each other.
Therefore, the argument leads us to conclude that since we can't identify vice and virtue solely through reason or comparing ideas, it's through some impression or feeling that we recognize the difference between them. Our judgments about what is morally right or wrong are clearly perceptions; and since all perceptions are either impressions or ideas, the absence of one effectively supports the existence of the other. So, morality is more about feeling than judgment; however, this feeling or sentiment is usually so subtle and gentle that we often mistake it for an idea, due to our tendency to treat similar things as the same.
The next question is, of what nature are these impressions, and after what manner do they operate upon us? Here we cannot remain long in suspense, but must pronounce the impression arising from virtue, to be agreeable, and that proceding from vice to be uneasy. Every moments experience must convince us of this. There is no spectacle so fair and beautiful as a noble and generous action; nor any which gives us more abhorrence than one that is cruel and treacherous. No enjoyment equals the satisfaction we receive from the company of those we love and esteem; as the greatest of all punishments is to be obliged to pass our lives with those we hate or contemn. A very play or romance may afford us instances of this pleasure, which virtue conveys to us; and pain, which arises from vice.
The next question is, what kind of impressions are these, and how do they affect us? We can’t stay in doubt for long; we have to say that the impression from virtue is pleasant, while that from vice is uncomfortable. Every moment of our experience proves this. There's nothing as fair and beautiful as a noble and generous act, nor anything that evokes more disgust than something cruel and treacherous. No joy compares to the satisfaction we get from being with those we love and respect; the worst punishment is having to spend our lives with those we hate or despise. Even a play or a romance can give us examples of the pleasure that virtue brings us and the pain that vice causes.
Now since the distinguishing impressions, by which moral good or evil is known, are nothing but particular pains or pleasures; it follows, that in all enquiries concerning these moral distinctions, it will be sufficient to shew the principles, which make us feel a satisfaction or uneasiness from the survey of any character, in order to satisfy us why the character is laudable or blameable. An action, or sentiment, or character is virtuous or vicious; why? because its view causes a pleasure or uneasiness of a particular kind. In giving a reason, therefore, for the pleasure or uneasiness, we sufficiently explain the vice or virtue. To have the sense of virtue, is nothing but to feel a satisfaction of a particular kind from the contemplation of a character. The very feeling constitutes our praise or admiration. We go no farther; nor do we enquire into the cause of the satisfaction. We do not infer a character to be virtuous, because it pleases: But in feeling that it pleases after such a particular manner, we in effect feel that it is virtuous. The case is the same as in our judgments concerning all kinds of beauty, and tastes, and sensations. Our approbation is implyed in the immediate pleasure they convey to us.
Now, since the unique feelings that tell us what moral good or evil is come down to specific pains or pleasures, it follows that in all discussions about these moral distinctions, it’s enough to show the principles that make us feel satisfaction or unease when looking at any character. This will explain why that character is praiseworthy or blameworthy. An action, sentiment, or character is virtuous or vicious; why? Because seeing it brings us a certain kind of pleasure or uneasiness. Therefore, when we give a reason for that pleasure or uneasiness, we adequately explain the vice or virtue. To have a sense of virtue simply means feeling a specific kind of satisfaction when contemplating a character. That feeling itself makes up our praise or admiration. We don’t go any deeper; we don’t investigate the source of the satisfaction. We don’t conclude that a character is virtuous just because it feels good; rather, by recognizing that it pleases us in a particular way, we essentially acknowledge that it is virtuous. The same applies to our judgments about all types of beauty, taste, and sensations. Our approval is implied in the immediate pleasure they bring us.
I have objected to the system, which establishes eternal rational measures of right and wrong, that it is impossible to shew, in the actions of reasonable creatures, any relations, which are not found in external objects; and therefore, if morality always attended these relations, it were possible for inanimate matter to become virtuous or vicious. Now it may, in like manner, be objected to the present system, that if virtue and vice be determined by pleasure and pain, these qualities must, in every case, arise from the sensations; and consequently any object, whether animate or inanimate, rational or irrational, might become morally good or evil, provided it can excite a satisfaction or uneasiness. But though this objection seems to be the very same, it has by no means the same force, in the one case as in the other. For, first, tis evident, that under the term pleasure, we comprehend sensations, which are very different from each other, and which have only such a distant resemblance, as is requisite to make them be expressed by the same abstract term. A good composition of music and a bottle of good wine equally produce pleasure; and what is more, their goodness is determined merely by the pleasure. But shall we say upon that account, that the wine is harmonious, or the music of a good flavour? In like manner an inanimate object, and the character or sentiments of any person may, both of them, give satisfaction; but as the satisfaction is different, this keeps our sentiments concerning them from being confounded, and makes us ascribe virtue to the one, and not to the other. Nor is every sentiment of pleasure or pain, which arises from characters and actions, of that peculiar kind, which makes us praise or condemn. The good qualities of an enemy are hurtful to us; but may still command our esteem and respect. It is only when a character is considered in general, without reference to our particular interest, that it causes such a feeling or sentiment, as denominates it morally good or evil. It is true, those sentiments, from interest and morals, are apt to be confounded, and naturally run into one another. It seldom happens, that we do not think an enemy vicious, and can distinguish betwixt his opposition to our interest and real villainy or baseness. But this hinders not, but that the sentiments are, in themselves, distinct; and a man of temper and judgment may preserve himself from these illusions. In like manner, though it is certain a musical voice is nothing but one that naturally gives a particular kind of pleasure; yet it is difficult for a man to be sensible, that the voice of an enemy is agreeable, or to allow it to be musical. But a person of a fine ear, who has the command of himself, can separate these feelings, and give praise to what deserves it.
I have criticized the system that establishes permanent standards of right and wrong, arguing that it’s impossible to demonstrate, through the actions of reasonable beings, any connections that aren’t found in external objects. Therefore, if morality always accompanies these connections, it would mean that inanimate objects could be considered virtuous or vicious. Similarly, it can be argued against the current system that if virtue and vice are defined by pleasure and pain, these qualities must arise from sensations in every case. Consequently, any object, whether it is alive or not, rational or irrational, could become morally good or evil, as long as it can produce satisfaction or discomfort. While this objection appears to be the same, it doesn't carry the same weight in both cases. First, it’s clear that the term pleasure encompasses sensations that are very different from one another, only bearing a distant resemblance that justifies using the same abstract term for both. A great piece of music and a good bottle of wine both provide pleasure; however, does this mean the wine is harmonious or the music has a good flavor? Likewise, both an inanimate object and a person's character or feelings can provide satisfaction; but since the nature of that satisfaction differs, it prevents us from confusing our feelings about them and allows us to attribute virtue to one and not the other. Not every feeling of pleasure or pain stemming from characters and actions is of the specific type that leads us to praise or condemn. The positive traits of an enemy can be harmful to us but can still command our respect and esteem. It’s only when a character is viewed in general terms, without reference to our specific interests, that it triggers a feeling or sentiment that labels it morally good or evil. It’s true that feelings related to self-interest and morality can often get mixed up and naturally overlap. It rarely happens that we don’t see an enemy as vicious, easily distinguishing between their opposition to our interests and true villainy or meanness. However, this doesn’t change the fact that the feelings themselves are distinct, and a person with temperament and judgment can protect themselves from these misconceptions. Similarly, while it’s clear that a musical voice is simply one that naturally produces a certain kind of pleasure, it can be hard for someone to acknowledge that the voice of an enemy is pleasant or to accept it as musical. But a person with a refined ear who can control themselves can separate these feelings and give praise where it’s truly deserved.
SECONDLY, We may call to remembrance the preceding system of the passions, in order to remark a still more considerable difference among our pains and pleasures. Pride and humility, love and hatred are excited, when there is any thing presented to us, that both bears a relation to the object of the passion, and produces a separate sensation related to the sensation of the passion. Now virtue and vice are attended with these circumstances. They must necessarily be placed either in ourselves or others, and excite either pleasure or uneasiness; and therefore must give rise to one of these four passions; which clearly distinguishes them from the pleasure and pain arising from inanimate objects, that often bear no relation to us: And this is, perhaps, the most considerable effect that virtue and vice have upon the human mind.
SECONDLY, let’s remember the previous system of emotions to highlight an even bigger difference between our pains and pleasures. Pride and humility, love and hatred are stirred up when something is presented to us that relates to the object of the emotion and creates a separate feeling connected to that emotion. Now, virtue and vice come with these factors. They must be related to either ourselves or others, and they can trigger either pleasure or discomfort; therefore, they lead to one of these four feelings, which clearly sets them apart from the pleasure and pain that come from inanimate objects, which often have no connection to us. This is perhaps the most significant impact that virtue and vice have on the human mind.
It may now be asked in general, concerning this pain or pleasure, that distinguishes moral good and evil, FROM WHAT PRINCIPLES IS IT DERIVED, AND WHENCE DOES IT ARISE IN THE HUMAN MIND? To this I reply, first, that it is absurd to imagine, that in every particular instance, these sentiments are produced by an original quality and primary constitution. For as the number of our duties is, in a manner, infinite, it is impossible that our original instincts should extend to each of them, and from our very first infancy impress on the human mind all that multitude of precepts, which are contained in the compleatest system of ethics. Such a method of proceeding is not conformable to the usual maxims, by which nature is conducted, where a few principles produce all that variety we observe in the universe, and every thing is carryed on in the easiest and most simple manner. It is necessary, therefore, to abridge these primary impulses, and find some more general principles, upon which all our notions of morals are founded.
It’s fair to ask, in general, about this pain or pleasure that differentiates moral good and evil: WHAT PRINCIPLES DOES IT COME FROM, AND WHERE DOES IT EMERGE IN THE HUMAN MIND? My answer is that it’s unreasonable to think these feelings are generated by an inherent quality and fundamental makeup every single time. Since the number of our duties is practically infinite, it’s impossible for our original instincts to cover each of them and for those instincts to impress upon the human mind right from infancy all the various rules found in a complete ethical system. This approach doesn’t align with the common principles that govern nature, where a few key ideas produce the wide variety we see in the universe, and everything operates in the simplest and most straightforward way. Therefore, we need to simplify these basic impulses and identify some broader principles that underpin all our moral ideas.
But in the second place, should it be asked, Whether we ought to search for these principles in nature, or whether we must look for them in some other origin? I would reply, that our answer to this question depends upon the definition of the word, Nature, than which there is none more ambiguous and equivocal. If nature be opposed to miracles, not only the distinction betwixt vice and virtue is natural, but also every event, which has ever happened in the world, EXCEPTING THOSE MIRACLES, ON WHICH OUR RELIGION IS FOUNDED. In saying, then, that the sentiments of vice and virtue are natural in this sense, we make no very extraordinary discovery.
But secondly, if we ask whether we should look for these principles in nature or if we should seek them from another source, my answer depends on how we define the word "nature," which is highly ambiguous and unclear. If nature is seen as opposing miracles, then the distinction between vice and virtue is natural, as is every event that has ever occurred in the world, EXCLUDING THE MIRACLES THAT FORM THE FOUNDATION OF OUR RELIGION. Therefore, when we say that our feelings about vice and virtue are natural in this sense, we aren't making any groundbreaking discovery.
But nature may also be opposed to rare and unusual; and in this sense of the word, which is the common one, there may often arise disputes concerning what is natural or unnatural; and one may in general affirm, that we are not possessed of any very precise standard, by which these disputes can be decided. Frequent and rare depend upon the number of examples we have observed; and as this number may gradually encrease or diminish, it will be impossible to fix any exact boundaries betwixt them. We may only affirm on this head, that if ever there was any thing, which could be called natural in this sense, the sentiments of morality certainly may; since there never was any nation of the world, nor any single person in any nation, who was utterly deprived of them, and who never, in any instance, shewed the least approbation or dislike of manners. These sentiments are so rooted in our constitution and temper, that without entirely confounding the human mind by disease or madness, it is impossible to extirpate and destroy them.
But nature can also be against the rare and unusual; and in this common sense of the term, there can often be disagreements about what is natural or unnatural. Generally, we can say that we don't have a very clear standard to resolve these disputes. Whether something is frequent or rare depends on how many examples we've observed, and since this number can gradually increase or decrease, it's impossible to set exact boundaries between them. We can only assert that if there’s anything that could be called natural in this sense, it would certainly be our moral feelings; because no nation in the world, or even a single person in any nation, has ever been completely devoid of them, nor has anyone ever failed to show at least some approval or disapproval of behaviors. These feelings are so deeply embedded in our nature and temperament that, except in cases where the human mind is thoroughly disrupted by illness or insanity, it's impossible to completely eradicate them.
But nature may also be opposed to artifice, as well as to what is rare and unusual; and in this sense it may be disputed, whether the notions of virtue be natural or not. We readily forget, that the designs, and projects, and views of men are principles as necessary in their operation as heat and cold, moist and dry: But taking them to be free and entirely our own, it is usual for us to set them in opposition to the other principles of nature should it, therefore, be demanded, whether the sense of virtue be natural or artificial, I am of opinion, that it is impossible for me at present to give any precise answer to this question. Perhaps it will appear afterwards, that our sense of some virtues is artificial, and that of others natural. The discussion of this question will be more proper, when we enter upon an exact detail of each particular vice and virtue.[4]
But nature can also stand against artifice, as well as against what is rare and unusual; and in this way, it might be debated whether the ideas of virtue are natural or not. We easily forget that the designs, plans, and goals of people are just as necessary in their effect as heat and cold, wet and dry. However, since we often see these as free and entirely our own, we typically set them against the other principles of nature. If it's then asked whether the sense of virtue is natural or artificial, I believe it's impossible for me to give a clear answer to this question right now. It might become clear later that our understanding of some virtues is artificial, while others are natural. It will be more appropriate to discuss this question thoroughly when we go into the specific details of each vice and virtue.[4]
[4] In the following discourse natural is also opposed sometimes to civil, sometimes to moral. The opposition will always discover the sense, in which it is taken.
[4] In this discussion, "natural" is sometimes contrasted with "civil" and other times with "moral." The context will clarify how it's being used.
Meanwhile it may not be amiss to observe from these definitions of natural and unnatural, that nothing can be more unphilosophical than those systems, which assert, that virtue is the same with what is natural, and vice with what is unnatural. For in the first sense of the word, Nature, as opposed to miracles, both vice and virtue are equally natural; and in the second sense, as opposed to what is unusual, perhaps virtue will be found to be the most unnatural. At least it must be owned, that heroic virtue, being as unusual, is as little natural as the most brutal barbarity. As to the third sense of the word, it is certain, that both vice and virtue are equally artificial, and out of nature. For however it may be disputed, whether the notion of a merit or demerit in certain actions be natural or artificial, it is evident, that the actions themselves are artificial, and are performed with a certain design and intention; otherwise they could never be ranked under any of these denominations. It is impossible, therefore, that the character of natural and unnatural can ever, in any sense, mark the boundaries of vice and virtue.
Meanwhile, it’s worth noting from these definitions of natural and unnatural that nothing is more unphilosophical than the systems that claim virtue is the same as what is natural, and vice is the same as what is unnatural. In the first sense of the term, nature—contrasted with miracles—suggests both vice and virtue are equally natural; and in the second sense, when compared to what is unusual, virtue might actually be seen as the most unnatural. At the very least, it must be acknowledged that heroic virtue, being so rare, is as little natural as the most brutal barbarism. Regarding the third sense of the word, it’s clear that both vice and virtue are equally artificial and outside of nature. Regardless of whether people debate whether the idea of merit or demerit in certain actions is natural or artificial, it’s evident that the actions themselves are artificial, performed with specific intent and purpose; otherwise, they could never be categorized as such. Therefore, it’s impossible for the concepts of natural and unnatural to clearly define the boundaries of vice and virtue in any sense.
Thus we are still brought back to our first position, that virtue is distinguished by the pleasure, and vice by the pain, that any action, sentiment or character gives us by the mere view and contemplation. This decision is very commodious; because it reduces us to this simple question, Why any action or sentiment upon the general view or survey, gives a certain satisfaction or uneasiness, in order to shew the origin of its moral rectitude or depravity, without looking for any incomprehensible relations and qualities, which never did exist in nature, nor even in our imagination, by any clear and distinct conception. I flatter myself I have executed a great part of my present design by a state of the question, which appears to me so free from ambiguity and obscurity.
So we return to our original point, that virtue is defined by the pleasure and vice by the pain that any action, feeling, or character brings us just by looking at it. This conclusion is really useful, because it boils down to this simple question: Why does any action or feeling, when considered as a whole, cause a certain level of satisfaction or discomfort? This helps to reveal the source of its moral goodness or badness, without needing to search for any confusing relationships or qualities that never actually existed in nature or even in our imagination in any clear way. I hope I’ve made significant progress on my current project by framing the question in a way that seems quite clear and straightforward.
SECT. I JUSTICE, WHETHER A NATURAL OR ARTIFICIAL VIRTUE?
I have already hinted, that our sense of every kind of virtue is not natural; but that there are some virtues, that produce pleasure and approbation by means of an artifice or contrivance, which arises from the circumstances and necessity of mankind. Of this kind I assert justice to be; and shall endeavour to defend this opinion by a short, and, I hope, convincing argument, before I examine the nature of the artifice, from which the sense of that virtue is derived.
I've already suggested that our understanding of all virtues isn't natural; instead, some virtues create pleasure and approval through a kind of trickery or arrangement that comes from human circumstances and needs. I claim that justice is one of these virtues and will attempt to support this idea with a brief and, I hope, persuasive argument before I explore the nature of the trickery that gives rise to our perception of that virtue.
It is evident, that when we praise any actions, we regard only the motives that produced them, and consider the actions as signs or indications of certain principles in the mind and temper. The external performance has no merit. We must look within to find the moral quality. This we cannot do directly; and therefore fix our attention on actions, as on external signs. But these actions are still considered as signs; and the ultimate object of our praise and approbation is the motive, that produced them.
It's clear that when we praise someone's actions, we focus on the motivations behind them and see those actions as reflections of certain principles in their thoughts and demeanor. The actual performance itself holds no value. We need to look inside to understand the moral quality. We can't do this directly, so we direct our attention to actions as external indicators. However, these actions are still viewed as signs, and the main thing we are praising and approving is the motive that led to them.
After the same manner, when we require any action, or blame a person for not performing it, we always suppose, that one in that situation should be influenced by the proper motive of that action, and we esteem it vicious in him to be regardless of it. If we find, upon enquiry, that the virtuous motive was still powerful over his breast, though checked in its operation by some circumstances unknown to us, we retract our blame, and have the same esteem for him, as if he had actually performed the action, which we require of him.
Similarly, when we expect someone to take action or criticize them for not doing so, we always assume that someone in that position should be guided by the right motivation for that action. We consider it wrong for them to ignore it. If we discover, upon investigation, that the good motivation was still strong in them, even though it was hindered by circumstances we’re unaware of, we withdraw our criticism and regard them just as highly as if they had actually carried out the action we expected from them.
It appears, therefore, that all virtuous actions derive their merit only from virtuous motives, and are considered merely as signs of those motives. From this principle I conclude, that the first virtuous motive, which bestows a merit on any action, can never be a regard to the virtue of that action, but must be some other natural motive or principle. To suppose, that the mere regard to the virtue of the action may be the first motive, which produced the action, and rendered it virtuous, is to reason in a circle. Before we can have such a regard, the action must be really virtuous; and this virtue must be derived from some virtuous motive: And consequently the virtuous motive must be different from the regard to the virtue of the action. A virtuous motive is requisite to render an action virtuous. An action must be virtuous, before we can have a regard to its virtue. Some virtuous motive, therefore, must be antecedent to that regard.
It seems that all virtuous actions gain their merit solely from virtuous motives and are seen just as indications of those motives. From this idea, I conclude that the primary virtuous motive that gives merit to any action can never just be the consideration of the action's virtue; it must be some other natural motive or principle. To think that simply considering the virtue of the action could be the initial motive that produced the action and made it virtuous is to argue in a circle. Before we can have that consideration, the action must actually be virtuous; and this virtue must come from some virtuous motive. Therefore, the virtuous motive must be distinct from the consideration of the action's virtue. A virtuous motive is necessary to make an action virtuous. An action must be virtuous before we can regard its virtue. So, some virtuous motive must come before that consideration.
Nor is this merely a metaphysical subtilty; but enters into all our reasonings in common life, though perhaps we may not be able to place it in such distinct philosophical terms. We blame a father for neglecting his child. Why? because it shews a want of natural affection, which is the duty of every parent. Were not natural affection a duty, the care of children could not be a duty; and it were impossible we could have the duty in our eye in the attention we give to our offspring. In this case, therefore, all men suppose a motive to the action distinct from a sense of duty.
This isn't just a complicated idea; it influences all our everyday reasoning, even if we can't express it in clear philosophical terms. We criticize a father for ignoring his child. Why? Because it shows a lack of natural affection, which is something every parent should have. If natural affection wasn't a responsibility, then taking care of children wouldn't be either, and we wouldn't be able to recognize our responsibility in how we care for our kids. In this situation, everyone assumes there's a motivation for the action that is separate from a sense of duty.
Here is a man, that does many benevolent actions; relieves the distressed, comforts the afflicted, and extends his bounty even to the greatest strangers. No character can be more amiable and virtuous. We regard these actions as proofs of the greatest humanity. This humanity bestows a merit on the actions. A regard to this merit is, therefore, a secondary consideration, and derived from the antecedent principle of humanity, which is meritorious and laudable.
Here is a man who performs many kind acts; he helps those in need, comforts the suffering, and shares his generosity even with complete strangers. No character could be more friendly and virtuous. We see these actions as evidence of great compassion. This compassion adds value to his actions. Therefore, considering this value is a secondary thought, stemming from the primary principle of humanity, which is praiseworthy and admirable.
In short, it may be established as an undoubted maxim, THAT NO ACTION CAN BE VIRTUOUS, OR MORALLY GOOD, UNLESS THERE BE IN HUMAN NATURE SOME MOTIVE TO PRODUCE IT, DISTINCT FROM THE SENSE OF ITS MORALITY.
In short, it can be firmly established that NO ACTION CAN BE VIRTUOUS, OR MORALLY GOOD, UNLESS THERE IS SOMETHING IN HUMAN NATURE THAT MOTIVATES IT, SEPARATE FROM THE AWARENESS OF ITS MORALITY.
But may not the sense of morality or duty produce an action, without any other motive? I answer, It may: But this is no objection to the present doctrine. When any virtuous motive or principle is common in human nature, a person, who feels his heart devoid of that motive, may hate himself upon that account, and may perform the action without the motive, from a certain sense of duty, in order to acquire by practice, that virtuous principle, or at least, to disguise to himself, as much as possible, his want of it. A man that really feels no gratitude in his temper, is still pleased to perform grateful actions, and thinks he has, by that means, fulfilled his duty. Actions are at first only considered as signs of motives: But it is usual, in this case, as in all others, to fix our attention on the signs, and neglect, in some measure, the thing signifyed. But though, on some occasions, a person may perform an action merely out of regard to its moral obligation, yet still this supposes in human nature some distinct principles, which are capable of producing the action, and whose moral beauty renders the action meritorious.
But can a sense of morality or duty lead to an action without any other motive? I say yes, it can: but this doesn't challenge the current idea. When a virtuous motive or principle is common in human nature, a person who feels lacking in that motive may dislike themselves for it and still take action out of a sense of duty, either to gain that virtuous principle through practice or at least to cover up their lack of it as much as possible. A person who genuinely doesn’t feel gratitude might still enjoy doing grateful things, believing that through those actions, they've fulfilled their duty. Actions are initially seen as indicators of motives: however, it’s common, in this case as in others, to focus on the indicators and somewhat overlook what they signify. Although there are times when someone might act purely out of moral obligation, this still assumes that there are distinct principles in human nature that can produce the action, and whose moral value makes the action commendable.
Now to apply all this to the present case; I suppose a person to have lent me a sum of money, on condition that it be restored in a few days; and also suppose, that after the expiration of the term agreed on, he demands the sum: I ask, What reason or motive have I to restore the money? It will, perhaps, be said, that my regard to justice, and abhorrence of villainy and knavery, are sufficient reasons for me, if I have the least grain of honesty, or sense of duty and obligation. And this answer, no doubt, is just and satisfactory to man in his civilized state, and when trained up according to a certain discipline and education. But in his rude and more natural condition, if you are pleased to call such a condition natural, this answer would be rejected as perfectly unintelligible and sophistical. For one in that situation would immediately ask you, WHEREIN CONSISTS THIS HONESTY AND JUSTICE, WHICH YOU FIND IN RESTORING A LOAN, AND ABSTAINING FROM THE PROPERTY OF OTHERS? It does not surely lie in the external action. It must, therefore be placed in the motive, from which the external action is derived. This motive can never be a regard to the honesty of the action. For it is a plain fallacy to say, that a virtuous motive is requisite to render an action honest, and at the same time that a regard to the honesty is the motive of the action. We can never have a regard to the virtue of an action, unless the action be antecedently virtuous. No action can be virtuous, but so far as it proceeds from a virtuous motive. A virtuous motive, therefore, must precede the regard to the virtue, and it is impossible, that the virtuous motive and the regard to the virtue can be the same.
Now, let's apply all this to the current situation. Imagine someone lent me some money, expecting it to be paid back within a few days. After that time is up, they ask for the money back. I wonder, what reason do I have to return it? Some might say that my sense of justice and dislike for wrongdoing should be enough if I have any integrity or sense of duty. This answer may make sense to someone who has been raised in a civilized society with certain values. However, in a more primitive and natural state—if you want to call it natural—this explanation would seem completely nonsensical. Someone in that mindset would immediately question, WHAT DOES THIS HONESTY AND JUSTICE MEAN WHEN IT COMES TO PAYING BACK A LOAN AND NOT STEALING FROM OTHERS? It certainly doesn't lie in the action itself, so it must be tied to the motivation behind the action. This motivation can’t be based on the idea of the action being honest. It's a clear mistake to argue that a good motive is needed to make an action honest while also claiming that concern for honesty is the motive for the action. We can only care about the virtue of an action if that action is already deemed virtuous. An action can only be virtuous if it comes from a good motive. Thus, a good motive must come before the emphasis on virtue, and it's impossible for the good motive and the focus on virtue to be the same.
It is requisite, then, to find some motive to acts of justice and honesty, distinct from our regard to the honesty; and in this lies the great difficulty. For should we say, that a concern for our private interest or reputation is the legitimate motive to all honest actions; it would follow, that wherever that concern ceases, honesty can no longer have place. But it is certain, that self-love, when it acts at its liberty, instead of engaging us to honest actions, is the source of all injustice and violence; nor can a man ever correct those vices, without correcting and restraining the natural movements of that appetite.
We need to find a reason for acts of justice and honesty that isn't just about our concern for being honest, and that's where the real challenge lies. If we say that wanting to protect our own interests or reputation is the only reason for honest actions, then it would mean that once that concern fades, honesty would no longer apply. But it's clear that self-love, when left unchecked, leads us away from honest behavior and toward injustice and violence; no one can fix those issues without addressing and controlling that basic instinct.
But should it be affirmed, that the reason or motive of such actions is the regard to publick interest, to which nothing is more contrary than examples of injustice and dishonesty; should this be said, I would propose the three following considerations, as worthy of our attention. First, public interest is not naturally attached to the observation of the rules of justice; but is only connected with it, after an artificial convention for the establishment of these rules, as shall be shewn more at large hereafter. Secondly, if we suppose, that the loan was secret, and that it is necessary for the interest of the person, that the money be restored in the same manner (as when the lender would conceal his riches) in that case the example ceases, and the public is no longer interested in the actions of the borrower; though I suppose there is no moralist, who will affirm, that the duty and obligation ceases. Thirdly, experience sufficiently proves, that men, in the ordinary conduct of life, look not so far as the public interest, when they pay their creditors, perform their promises, and abstain from theft, and robbery, and injustice of every kind. That is a motive too remote and too sublime to affect the generality of mankind, and operate with any force in actions so contrary to private interest as are frequently those of justice and common honesty.
But if we claim that the motivation behind such actions is to serve the public interest, which is completely undermined by instances of injustice and dishonesty; if this is said, I would like to present three considerations that deserve our attention. First, public interest isn't inherently linked to following the rules of justice; it only becomes connected after a deliberate agreement to establish these rules, as will be discussed in more detail later. Second, if we assume the loan was kept secret and that it's necessary for the individual’s interest that the money be repaid in the same way (like when the lender wants to hide their wealth), then the example no longer applies, and the public loses interest in the borrower's actions; although I believe no ethicist would argue that the duty and obligation disappears. Third, experience clearly shows that people, in their everyday lives, don't usually think about the public interest when they repay their debts, keep their promises, and refrain from theft, robbery, or any form of injustice. That motivation is too distant and too lofty to influence the majority of people, especially when their actions directly conflict with personal interests, which often happens with justice and basic honesty.
In general, it may be affirmed, that there is no such passion in human minds, as the love of mankind, merely as such, independent of personal qualities, of services, or of relation to ourself. It is true, there is no human, and indeed no sensible, creature, whose happiness or misery does not, in some measure, affect us when brought near to us, and represented in lively colours: But this proceeds merely from sympathy, and is no proof of such an universal affection to mankind, since this concern extends itself beyond our own species. An affection betwixt the sexes is a passion evidently implanted in human nature; and this passion not only appears in its peculiar symptoms, but also in inflaming every other principle of affection, and raising a stronger love from beauty, wit, kindness, than what would otherwise flow from them. Were there an universal love among all human creatures, it would appear after the same manner. Any degree of a good quality would cause a stronger affection than the same degree of a bad quality would cause hatred; contrary to what we find by experience. Men's tempers are different, and some have a propensity to the tender, and others to the rougher, affections: But in the main, we may affirm, that man in general, or human nature, is nothing but the object both of love and hatred, and requires some other cause, which by a double relation of impressions and ideas, may excite these passions. In vain would we endeavour to elude this hypothesis. There are no phaenomena that point out any such kind affection to men, independent of their merit, and every other circumstance. We love company in general; but it is as we love any other amusement. An Englishman in Italy is a friend: A Euro paean in China; and perhaps a man would be beloved as such, were we to meet him in the moon. But this proceeds only from the relation to ourselves; which in these cases gathers force by being confined to a few persons.
In general, we can say that there's no passion in human minds like the love for humanity, simply as a concept, independent of personal qualities, actions, or connections to ourselves. It’s true that there's no human, or even any sensible creature, whose happiness or suffering doesn’t affect us to some degree when we see it up close and vividly represented. But this is just sympathy, and not evidence of a universal love for mankind, since this concern also reaches beyond our own species. There’s a connection between the sexes that’s clearly a part of human nature; this connection not only manifests with its own specific signs, but also intensifies every other feeling of affection, and creates a deeper love from beauty, intellect, and kindness than what we would normally feel. If there were universal love among all humans, it would show up in the same way. Any positive quality would inspire a stronger affection than the same level of a negative quality would inspire hatred, which is contrary to what we actually observe. People have different temperaments, some leaning towards tender feelings and others towards rougher ones: but overall, we can say that humanity, as a whole, is just the target of both love and hate, needing some other reason to stir up these feelings through a mix of impressions and ideas. It’s pointless to try to avoid this idea. There are no signs that suggest any kind of affection for people, independent of their merits and all other factors. We enjoy company in general, but it’s the same way we enjoy any other entertainment. An Englishman in Italy becomes a friend: A European in China; and maybe a person would be liked as such if we were to meet them on the moon. But this is solely due to our self-interest; in these cases, it becomes stronger when it’s focused on a few individuals.
If public benevolence, therefore, or a regard to the interests of mankind, cannot be the original motive to justice, much less can private benevolence, or a regard to the interests of the party concerned, be this motive. For what if he be my enemy, and has given me just cause to hate him? What if he be a vicious man, and deserves the hatred of all mankind? What if he be a miser, and can make no use of what I would deprive him of? What if he be a profligate debauchee, and would rather receive harm than benefit from large possessions? What if I be in necessity, and have urgent motives to acquire something to my family? In all these cases, the original motive to justice would fail; and consequently the justice itself, and along with it all property, tight, and obligation.
If public goodwill, or concern for the well-being of humanity, can't be the primary reason for justice, then even less can personal goodwill, or concern for the interests of the individual involved, be that reason. What if he is my enemy and has given me good reason to hate him? What if he is a morally corrupt person who deserves the disdain of everyone? What if he is a miser who can’t make use of what I want to take from him? What if he is a reckless spendthrift who would prefer to face harm rather than gain from wealth? What if I am in need and have strong reasons to get something for my family? In all these scenarios, the original motive for justice would be lost; and as a result, justice itself, along with all property, rights, and obligations, would vanish.
A rich man lies under a moral obligation to communicate to those in necessity a share of his superfluities. Were private benevolence the original motive to justice, a man would not be obliged to leave others in the possession of more than he is obliged to give them. At least the difference would be very inconsiderable. Men generally fix their affections more on what they are possessed of, than on what they never enjoyed: For this reason, it would be greater cruelty to dispossess a man of any thing, than not to give it him. But who will assert, that this is the only foundation of justice?
A wealthy person has a moral duty to share some of their excess with those in need. If private generosity were the main reason for justice, a person wouldn't have to leave others with more than they are required to give. At least, the difference wouldn’t be significant. People usually care more about what they already have than about what they’ve never had. For this reason, it would be more cruel to take something away from someone than to deny it to them in the first place. But who can claim that this is the sole basis of justice?
Besides, we must consider, that the chief reason, why men attach themselves so much to their possessions is, that they consider them as their property, and as secured to them inviolably by the laws of society. But this is a secondary consideration, and dependent on the preceding notions of justice and property.
Besides, we need to keep in mind that the main reason people are so attached to their belongings is because they see them as their own and believe they are protected by societal laws. However, this is a secondary thought and relies on earlier ideas about justice and ownership.
A man's property is supposed to be fenced against every mortal, in every possible case. But private benevolence is, and ought to be, weaker in some persons, than in others: And in many, or indeed in most persons, must absolutely fail. Private benevolence, therefore, is not the original motive of justice.
A person's property should be protected from everyone, in every situation. However, personal generosity varies from person to person; some are naturally more giving than others, and in many cases, or even for most people, it can completely fall short. Therefore, personal generosity is not the primary reason for justice.
From all this it follows, that we have no real or universal motive for observing the laws of equity, but the very equity and merit of that observance; and as no action can be equitable or meritorious, where it cannot arise from some separate motive, there is here an evident sophistry and reasoning in a circle. Unless, therefore, we will allow, that nature has established a sophistry, and rendered it necessary and unavoidable, we must allow, that the sense of justice and injustice is not derived from nature, but arises artificially, though necessarily from education, and human conventions.
From all this, it follows that we have no true or universal reason to follow the laws of fairness other than the fairness and value of that adherence. Since no action can be fair or valuable if it doesn't stem from some external reason, there's a clear fallacy and circular reasoning here. Unless we accept that nature has created a fallacy and made it necessary and unavoidable, we must recognize that our understanding of justice and injustice doesn't come from nature but is artificially, yet necessarily, shaped by education and social agreements.
I shall add, as a corollary to this reasoning, that since no action can be laudable or blameable, without some motives or impelling passions, distinct from the sense of morals, these distinct passions must have a great influence on that sense. It is according to their general force in human nature, that we blame or praise. In judging of the beauty of animal bodies, we always carry in our eye the economy of a certain species; and where the limbs and features observe that proportion, which is common to the species, we pronounce them handsome and beautiful. In like manner we always consider the natural and usual force of the passions, when we determine concerning vice and virtue; and if the passions depart very much from the common measures on either side, they are always disapproved as vicious. A man naturally loves his children better than his nephews, his nephews better than his cousins, his cousins better than strangers, where every thing else is equal. Hence arise our common measures of duty, in preferring the one to the other. Our sense of duty always follows the common and natural course of our passions.
I want to add, as a point related to this reasoning, that since no action can be seen as good or bad without some motives or driving emotions that are separate from our sense of morals, these specific emotions must greatly influence that sense. It’s based on their overall impact in human nature that we assign blame or praise. When judging the beauty of animals, we always consider the typical characteristics of a certain species, and when their limbs and features align with the proportions common to that species, we call them attractive and beautiful. In the same way, we always take into account the natural and usual intensity of emotions when we assess vice and virtue; if the emotions stray too far from the typical standards on either side, they are generally deemed wrong. A person naturally loves their children more than their nephews, their nephews more than their cousins, and their cousins more than strangers, assuming all else is equal. This is where our common standards of duty come from, in favoring one over the other. Our sense of duty always aligns with the usual and natural flow of our emotions.
To avoid giving offence, I must here observe, that when I deny justice to be a natural virtue, I make use of the word, natural, only as opposed to artificial. In another sense of the word; as no principle of the human mind is more natural than a sense of virtue; so no virtue is more natural than justice. Mankind is an inventive species; and where an invention is obvious and absolutely necessary, it may as properly be said to be natural as any thing that proceeds immediately from original principles, without the intervention of thought or reflection. Though the rules of justice be artificial, they are not arbitrary. Nor is the expression improper to call them Laws of Nature; if by natural we understand what is common to any species, or even if we confine it to mean what is inseparable from the species.
To avoid causing offense, I need to point out that when I say justice isn’t a natural virtue, I’m using the term “natural” only in contrast to “artificial.” In another sense, since no principle of the human mind is more innate than a sense of virtue, it follows that no virtue is more natural than justice. Humans are inventive beings, and when an invention is obvious and completely necessary, it can be considered as natural as anything that comes directly from fundamental principles, without the need for thought or reflection. While the rules of justice are artificial, they aren’t arbitrary. It’s also correct to refer to them as Laws of Nature, if we understand “natural” to mean what is common to any species, or even if we limit it to mean what is essential to the species.
SECT. II OF THE ORIGIN OF JUSTICE AND PROPERTY
We now proceed to examine two questions, viz, CONCERNING THE MANNER, IN WHICH THE RULES OF JUSTICE ARE ESTABLISHED BY THE ARTIFICE OF MEN; and CONCERNING THE REASONS, WHICH DETERMINE US TO ATTRIBUTE TO THE OBSERVANCE OR NEGLECT OF THESE RULES A MORAL BEAUTY AND DEFORMITY. These questions will appear afterwards to be distinct. We shall begin with the former.
We will now look at two questions: FIRST, HOW THE RULES OF JUSTICE ARE CREATED BY HUMAN CRAFTING; and SECOND, THE REASONS THAT LEAD US TO ATTRIBUTE MORAL BEAUTY OR UGLINESS TO THE FOLLOWING OR IGNORING OF THESE RULES. These questions will later seem to be separate. We'll start with the first one.
Of all the animals, with which this globe is peopled, there is none towards whom nature seems, at first sight, to have exercised more cruelty than towards man, in the numberless wants and necessities, with which she has loaded him, and in the slender means, which she affords to the relieving these necessities. In other creatures these two particulars generally compensate each other. If we consider the lion as a voracious and carnivorous animal, we shall easily discover him to be very necessitous; but if we turn our eye to his make and temper, his agility, his courage, his arms, and his force, we shall find, that his advantages hold proportion with his wants. The sheep and ox are deprived of all these advantages; but their appetites are moderate, and their food is of easy purchase. In man alone, this unnatural conjunction of infirmity, and of necessity, may be observed in its greatest perfection. Not only the food, which is required for his sustenance, flies his search and approach, or at least requires his labour to be produced, but he must be possessed of cloaths and lodging, to defend him against the injuries of the weather; though to consider him only in himself, he is provided neither with arms, nor force, nor other natural abilities, which are in any degree answerable to so many necessities.
Of all the animals on this planet, none seem to have faced more cruelty from nature at first glance than humans, given the countless wants and needs we're burdened with and the limited means we have to meet those needs. In other creatures, these aspects generally balance each other out. Take the lion, for instance; while he is a fierce carnivore, he's also quite needy. However, if we look at his physical attributes and temperament—his agility, courage, strength, and weapons—we see that his advantages match his needs. In contrast, sheep and oxen lack these advantages, but their appetites are moderate and their food is easy to find. Only in humans do we see this unnatural combination of weakness and necessity at its peak. Not only does the food we need for survival often elude us or require hard work to obtain, but we also need clothing and shelter to protect us from the elements. Yet, when we consider him alone, a human has no natural weapons, strength, or abilities to adequately address such numerous needs.
It is by society alone he is able to supply his defects, and raise himself up to an equality with his fellow-creatures, and even acquire a superiority above them. By society all his infirmities are compensated; and though in that situation his wants multiply every moment upon him, yet his abilities are still more augmented, and leave him in every respect more satisfied and happy, than it is possible for him, in his savage and solitary condition, ever to become. When every individual person labours apart, and only for himself, his force is too small to execute any considerable work; his labour being employed in supplying all his different necessities, he never attains a perfection in any particular art; and as his force and success are not at all times equal, the least failure in either of these particulars must be attended with inevitable ruin and misery. Society provides a remedy for these three inconveniences. By the conjunction of forces, our power is augmented: By the partition of employments, our ability encreases: And by mutual succour we are less exposed to fortune and accidents. It is by this additional force, ability, and security, that society becomes advantageous.
It’s only through society that a person can address their shortcomings and elevate themselves to be equal with others, or even gain an advantage over them. Society compensates for all their weaknesses; and although their needs increase constantly, their abilities grow even more, making them more satisfied and happier than they could ever be in a wild and isolated state. When each person works alone, just for themselves, their strength is too limited to accomplish anything significant; their efforts go into meeting their various needs, preventing them from mastering any specific skill. Since their strength and success are inconsistent, even a small setback in either can lead to complete failure and hardship. Society offers solutions to these three problems. By combining our efforts, we increase our power; by dividing tasks, we enhance our capabilities; and by supporting each other, we reduce our vulnerability to fate and mishaps. This added strength, skill, and security is what makes society beneficial.
But in order to form society, it is requisite not only that it be advantageous, but also that men be sensible of these advantages; and it is impossible, in their wild uncultivated state, that by study and reflection alone, they should ever be able to attain this knowledge. Most fortunately, therefore, there is conjoined to those necessities, whose remedies are remote and obscure, another necessity, which having a present and more obvious remedy, may justly be regarded as the first and original principle of human society. This necessity is no other than that natural appetite betwixt the sexes, which unites them together, and preserves their union, till a new tye takes place in their concern for their common offspring. This new concern becomes also a principle of union betwixt the parents and offspring, and forms a more numerous society; where the parents govern by the advantage of their superior strength and wisdom, and at the same time are restrained in the exercise of their authority by that natural affection, which they bear their children. In a little time, custom and habit operating on the tender minds of the children, makes them sensible of the advantages, which they may reap from society, as well as fashions them by degrees for it, by rubbing off those rough corners and untoward affections, which prevent their coalition.
To create a society, it's not enough for it to be beneficial; people also need to recognize these benefits. In their raw, undeveloped state, it's unlikely that individuals can gain this awareness just through study and reflection. Thankfully, alongside those distant and unclear necessities, there's a more immediate need that can be addressed, which can rightly be seen as the foundational principle of human society. This need is the natural attraction between the sexes, which brings them together and keeps them united until a new bond is formed through their shared commitment to their children. This new concern for their offspring also serves as a unifying factor between parents and children, creating a larger society where parents lead with their greater strength and wisdom, while also being guided by the love they have for their kids. Over time, as customs and habits shape the young minds of children, they become aware of the advantages of being part of a society, while also gradually adapting to it by smoothing out rough edges and overcoming traits that hinder their connection with others.
For it must be confest, that however the circumstances of human nature may render an union necessary, and however those passions of lust and natural affection may seem to render it unavoidable; yet there are other particulars in our natural temper, and in our outward circumstances, which are very incommodious, and are even contrary to the requisite conjunction. Among the former, we may justly esteem our selfishness to be the most considerable. I am sensible, that generally speaking, the representations of this quality have been carried much too far; and that the descriptions, which certain philosophers delight so much to form of mankind in this particular, are as wide of nature as any accounts of monsters, which we meet with in fables and romances. So far from thinking, that men have no affection for any thing beyond themselves, I am of opinion, that though it be rare to meet with one, who loves any single person better than himself; yet it is as rare to meet with one, in whom all the kind affections, taken together, do not overbalance all the selfish. Consult common experience: Do you not see, that though the whole expence of the family be generally under the direction of the master of it, yet there are few that do not bestow the largest part of their fortunes on the pleasures of their wives, and the education of their children, reserving the smallest portion for their own proper use and entertainment. This is what we may observe concerning such as have those endearing ties; and may presume, that the case would be the same with others, were they placed in a like situation.
For it's important to admit that while the circumstances of human nature may make a partnership necessary and while the passions of desire and natural affection might seem to make it unavoidable, there are other aspects of our nature and our external situations that can be quite inconvenient and even counter to the needed connection. Among those aspects, we can rightfully consider our selfishness to be the most significant. I realize that, in general, the portrayals of this trait have been exaggerated, and that the descriptions certain philosophers enjoy creating about humans in this regard are as far from reality as any tales of monsters found in fables and romances. Far from believing that people have no affection for anything beyond themselves, I believe that while it is rare to find someone who loves one particular person more than themselves, it is equally rare to find someone in whom all the kind affections together do not outweigh all selfish tendencies. Look at common experience: don't you see that while the overall expenses of the household are usually managed by its head, there are few who do not spend the largest part of their fortunes on the pleasures of their wives and the education of their children, keeping only a small portion for their own personal use and enjoyment? This is what we can observe regarding those with such cherished connections, and we can assume that the same would hold true for others if they were in similar situations.
But though this generosity must be acknowledged to the honour of human nature, we may at the same time remark, that so noble an affection, instead of fitting men for large societies, is almost as contrary to them, as the most narrow selfishness. For while each person loves himself better than any other single person, and in his love to others bears the greatest affection to his relations and acquaintance, this must necessarily produce an oppositon of passions, and a consequent opposition of actions; which cannot but be dangerous to the new-established union.
But while we should recognize this generosity as a credit to human nature, we can also point out that such a noble sentiment, instead of preparing people for greater societies, is nearly as opposed to them as the most extreme selfishness. Each individual tends to love themselves more than anyone else and shows greater affection for their family and friends than for others. This inevitably creates conflicting feelings and, as a result, conflicting actions, which can be harmful to the newly formed unity.
It is however worth while to remark, that this contrariety of passions would be attended with but small danger, did it not concur with a peculiarity in our outward circumstances, which affords it an opportunity of exerting itself. There are different species of goods, which we are possessed of; the internal satisfaction of our minds, the external advantages of our body, and the enjoyment of such possessions as we have acquired by our industry and good fortune. We are perfectly secure in the enjoyment of the first. The second may be ravished from us, but can be of no advantage to him who deprives us of them. The last only are both exposed to the violence of others, and may be transferred without suffering any loss or alteration; while at the same time, there is not a sufficient quantity of them to supply every one's desires and necessities. As the improvement, therefore, of these goods is the chief advantage of society, so the instability of their possession, along with their scarcity, is the chief impediment.
It’s important to note that this clash of emotions would pose little risk if it weren't for a specific aspect of our external circumstances that allows it to manifest. We possess different types of goods: the inner satisfaction of our minds, the physical advantages of our bodies, and the enjoyment of the possessions we've gained through hard work and good luck. We are completely secure in enjoying the first. The second can be taken from us, but it holds no value for those who steal them. Only the last group is vulnerable to the actions of others and can be transferred without suffering any loss or change; at the same time, there isn't enough of them to satisfy everyone's wants and needs. Therefore, while the improvement of these goods is the primary benefit of society, their unstable possession, coupled with their scarcity, is the main obstacle.
In vain should we expect to find, in uncultivated nature, a remedy to this inconvenience; or hope for any inartificial principle of the human mind, which might controul those partial affections, and make us overcome the temptations arising from our circumstances. The idea of justice can never serve to this purpose, or be taken for a natural principle, capable of inspiring men with an equitable conduct towards each other. That virtue, as it is now understood, would never have been dreamed of among rude and savage men. For the notion of injury or injustice implies an immorality or vice committed against some other person: And as every immorality is derived from some defect or unsoundness of the passions, and as this defect must be judged of, in a great measure, from the ordinary course of nature in the constitution of the mind; it will be easy to know, whether we be guilty of any immorality, with regard to others, by considering the natural, and usual force of those several affections, which are directed towards them. Now it appears, that in the original frame of our mind, our strongest attention is confined to ourselves; our next is extended to our relations and acquaintance; and it is only the weakest which reaches to strangers and indifferent persons. This partiality, then, and unequal affection, must not only have an influence on our behaviour and conduct in society, but even on our ideas of vice and virtue; so as to make us regard any remarkable transgression of such a degree of partiality, either by too great an enlargement, or contraction of the affections, as vicious and immoral. This we may observe in our common judgments concerning actions, where we blame a person, who either centers all his affections in his family, or is so regardless of them, as, in any opposition of interest, to give the preference to a stranger, or mere chance acquaintance. From all which it follows, that our natural uncultivated ideas of morality, instead of providing a remedy for the partiality of our affections, do rather conform themselves to that partiality, and give it an additional force and influence.
It's pointless to think we can find a solution to this problem in the wildness of nature or hope that any basic principle of the human mind could control our biased feelings and help us resist the temptations that come from our situation. The concept of justice won't help us achieve this and cannot be seen as a natural principle that inspires fair treatment among people. The virtue we understand today would never have even been imagined by rough and primitive people. The idea of injury or injustice suggests a wrongdoing against someone else. Since every wrongdoing stems from some flaw in our emotions, and this flaw must largely be assessed based on the typical patterns of nature in our minds, it becomes clear how we can determine if we are acting immorally towards others by examining the natural and usual strengths of the various feelings we have towards them. It appears that in our original mental makeup, our greatest focus is on ourselves; our next focus extends to our family and friends; and only our weakest attention reaches out to strangers and people we don't know well. This bias, therefore, not only affects our behavior and interactions in society but also shapes our notions of vice and virtue. It leads us to view any significant breach of this bias—by either excessively broadening or narrowing our affections—as immoral. We see this in our common judgments of actions, where we criticize someone who either concentrates all their feelings on their family or neglects them to favor a stranger or a casual acquaintance in matters of conflicting interests. Therefore, it follows that our natural and unrefined sense of morality, rather than addressing the bias in our emotions, actually conforms to it and adds more power and influence to that bias.
The remedy, then, is not derived from nature, but from artifice; or more properly speaking, nature provides a remedy in the judgment and understanding, for what is irregular and incommodious in the affections. For when men, from their early education in society, have become sensible of the infinite advantages that result from it, and have besides acquired a new affection to company and conversation; and when they have observed, that the principal disturbance in society arises from those goods, which we call external, and from their looseness and easy transition from one person to another; they must seek for a remedy by putting these goods, as far as possible, on the same footing with the fixed and constant advantages of the mind and body. This can be done after no other manner, than by a convention entered into by all the members of the society to bestow stability on the possession of those external goods, and leave every one in the peaceable enjoyment of what he may acquire by his fortune and industry. By this means, every one knows what he may safely possess; and the passions ale restrained in their partial and contradictory motions. Nor is such a restraint contrary to these passions; for if so, it could never be entered into, nor maintained; but it is only contrary to their heedless and impetuous movement. Instead of departing from our own interest, or from that of our nearest friends, by abstaining from the possessions of others, we cannot better consult both these interests, than by such a convention; because it is by that means we maintain society, which is so necessary to their well-being and subsistence, as well as to our own.
The solution, then, doesn’t come from nature but from human creation; or more accurately, nature gives us a remedy through our judgment and understanding for what’s irregular and uncomfortable in our feelings. When people, through their early social experiences, recognize the countless benefits that come from being part of a community, and develop a new appreciation for social interactions and conversations; and when they notice that the main disruptions in society come from what we call external goods, and from their ability to easily shift from one person to another; they need to find a way to stabilize these goods, placing them on a similar level as the enduring and stable benefits of the mind and body. This can only be achieved through an agreement made by all members of society to ensure the stability of these external goods, allowing everyone to enjoy peacefully whatever they earn through their luck and hard work. This way, everyone understands what they can securely possess; and our emotions are kept in check against their conflicting urges. Such restraint doesn’t go against our feelings; if it did, it wouldn’t be possible to establish or maintain such an agreement; rather, it conflicts with their reckless and impulsive nature. Instead of abandoning our own interests or those of our closest friends by refraining from taking what belongs to others, we can best serve both interests through this agreement; because that’s how we preserve the society that’s essential for their well-being and survival, as well as our own.
This convention is not of the nature of a promise: For even promises themselves, as we shall see afterwards, arise from human conventions. It is only a general sense of common interest; which sense all the members of the society express to one another, and which induces them to regulate their conduct by certain rules. I observe, that it will be for my interest to leave another in the possession of his goods, provided he will act in the same manner with regard to me. He is sensible of a like interest in the regulation of his conduct. When this common sense of interest is mutually expressed, and is known to both, it produces a suitable resolution and behaviour. And this may properly enough be called a convention or agreement betwixt us, though without the interposition of a promise; since the actions of each of us have a reference to those of the other, and are performed upon the supposition, that something is to be performed on the other part. Two men, who pull the oars of a boat, do it by an agreement or convention, though they have never given promises to each other. Nor is the rule concerning the stability of possession the less derived from human conventions, that it arises gradually, and acquires force by a slow progression, and by our repeated experience of the inconveniences of transgressing it. On the contrary, this experience assures us still more, that the sense of interest has become common to all our fellows, and gives us a confidence of the future regularity of their conduct: And it is only on the expectation of this, that our moderation and abstinence are founded. In like manner are languages gradually established by human conventions without any promise. In like manner do gold and silver become the common measures of exchange, and are esteemed sufficient payment for what is of a hundred times their value.
This agreement isn't really a promise: even promises, as we'll see later, come from human agreements. It's just a general sense of shared interest; this feeling is communicated among all the members of society, encouraging them to follow certain rules. I realize that it benefits me to leave someone with their belongings if they'll do the same for me. That person understands a similar interest in how they act. When this shared sense of interest is openly acknowledged by both parties, it leads to appropriate decisions and actions. This can be rightly called a convention or agreement between us, even without any promises, since our actions refer to each other and are based on the assumption that something will be done by the other. Two people rowing a boat do so through an agreement, even if they haven’t promised anything to each other. Moreover, the principle regarding the stability of possession is still rooted in human conventions, as it develops gradually, gaining strength through consistent experiences with the drawbacks of breaking it. In fact, this experience further reassures us that the sense of interest is common among everyone, which gives us confidence in their future behavior: our restraint and forbearance depend on this expectation. Similarly, languages evolve gradually through human conventions without any promises. Likewise, gold and silver become standard measures of trade, even being considered adequate payment for things worth a hundred times their value.
After this convention, concerning abstinence from the possessions of others, is entered into, and every one has acquired a stability in his possessions, there immediately arise the ideas of justice and injustice; as also those of property, right, and obligation. The latter are altogether unintelligible without first understanding the former. Our property is nothing but those goods, whose constant possession is established by the laws of society; that is, by the laws of justice. Those, therefore, who make use of the words property, or right, or obligation, before they have explained the origin of justice, or even make use of them in that explication, are guilty of a very gross fallacy, and can never reason upon any solid foundation. A man's property is some object related to him. This relation is not natural, but moral, and founded on justice. It is very preposterous, therefore, to imagine, that we can have any idea of property, without fully comprehending the nature of justice, and shewing its origin in the artifice and contrivance of man. The origin of justice explains that of property. The same artifice gives rise to both. As our first and most natural sentiment of morals is founded on the nature of our passions, and gives the preference to ourselves and friends, above strangers; it is impossible there can be naturally any such thing as a fixed right or property, while the opposite passions of men impel them in contrary directions, and are not restrained by any convention or agreement.
Once this agreement about not taking others' belongings is established, and everyone has settled into their own possessions, ideas of justice and injustice start to emerge, along with concepts of property, rights, and obligations. The latter concepts cannot be understood without first grasping the former. Our property consists of those goods we consistently possess, as determined by societal laws, which are essentially the laws of justice. Therefore, those who use terms like property, rights, or obligations without first explaining the source of justice, or incorporate them without clarity in that explanation, are committing a serious fallacy and cannot reason on any solid ground. A person's property is connected to them. This connection is not natural but moral, based on justice. It is quite absurd to think we can understand property without a full grasp of justice and its man-made origins. The origin of justice clarifies the origin of property; both arise from the same human contrivance. Since our initial and most instinctive moral sentiments are rooted in our passions, favoring ourselves and our friends over outsiders, it is impossible for a stable concept of rights or property to exist while people's opposing passions push them in different directions, unless they are held in check by some form of agreement.
No one can doubt, that the convention for the distinction of property, and for the stability of possession, is of all circumstances the most necessary to the establishment of human society, and that after the agreement for the fixing and observing of this rule, there remains little or nothing to be done towards settling a perfect harmony and concord. All the other passions, besides this of interest, are either easily restrained, or are not of such pernicious consequence, when indulged. Vanity is rather to be esteemed a social passion, and a bond of union among men. Pity and love are to be considered in the same light. And as to envy and revenge, though pernicious, they operate only by intervals, and are directed against particular persons, whom we consider as our superiors or enemies. This avidity alone, of acquiring goods and possessions for ourselves and our nearest friends, is insatiable, perpetual, universal, and directly destructive of society. There scarce is any one, who is not actuated by it; and there is no one, who has not reason to fear from it, when it acts without any restraint, and gives way to its first and most natural movements. So that upon the whole, we are to esteem the difficulties in the establishment of society, to be greater or less, according to those we encounter in regulating and restraining this passion.
No one can deny that the rules for distinguishing property and ensuring stable possession are the most essential factors in building human society. Once we agree on these rules and commit to following them, there’s very little left to do to achieve perfect harmony and agreement. All other desires, apart from this drive for self-interest, can either be easily controlled or are not as harmful when expressed. Vanity is more of a social desire, serving as a connection among people. Pity and love should be viewed similarly. As for envy and revenge, although they can be harmful, they tend to arise only occasionally and target specific individuals whom we see as our betters or adversaries. This relentless desire to acquire goods and possessions for ourselves and our closest friends is insatiable, everlasting, and universally destructive to society. Virtually everyone is driven by it, and no one can escape the potential threat it poses when left unchecked and allowed to follow its natural impulses. Therefore, we should view the challenges in establishing society as greater or lesser based on how we manage and control this desire.
It is certain, that no affection of the human mind has both a sufficient force, and a proper direction to counterbalance the love of gain, and render men fit members of society, by making them abstain from the possessions of others. Benevolence to strangers is too weak for this purpose; and as to the other passions, they rather inflame this avidity, when we observe, that the larger our possessions are, the more ability we have of gratifying all our appetites. There is no passion, therefore, capable of controlling the interested affection, but the very affection itself, by an alteration of its direction. Now this alteration must necessarily take place upon the least reflection; since it is evident, that the passion is much better satisfyed by its restraint, than by its liberty, and that in preserving society, we make much greater advances in the acquiring possessions, than in the solitary and forlorn condition, which must follow upon violence and an universal licence. The question, therefore, concerning the wickedness or goodness of human nature, enters not in the least into that other question concerning the origin of society; nor is there any thing to be considered but the degrees of men's sagacity or folly. For whether the passion of self-interest be esteemed vicious or virtuous, it is all a case; since itself alone restrains it: So that if it be virtuous, men become social by their virtue; if vicious, their vice has the same effect.
It's clear that no feeling in the human mind has the strength or the right focus to balance out the love of money and make people function well in society by encouraging them to refrain from taking what belongs to others. Kindness towards strangers isn't strong enough for this purpose; and when we look at other emotions, they actually increase this greed, as we see that the more we own, the better we can satisfy all our desires. Therefore, there's no emotion that can regulate selfish affection except for the affection itself, by changing its focus. This change must occur with the slightest reflection because it's obvious that the emotion is much better fulfilled through restraint than through freedom, and that by maintaining society, we make much greater progress in gaining possessions than in a lonely and despairing state that would result from violence and complete chaos. The question of whether human nature is good or bad doesn't really affect the question of the origin of society; what matters is the level of people’s wisdom or foolishness. Whether self-interest is seen as bad or good doesn't really change things, since it is self-restrained: so if it's viewed as good, people become social through their goodness; if bad, their badness has the same outcome.
Now as it is by establishing the rule for the stability of possession, that this passion restrains itself; if that rule be very abstruse, and of difficult invention; society must be esteemed, in a manner, accidental, and the effect of many ages. But if it be found, that nothing can be more simple and obvious than that rule; that every parent, in order to preserve peace among his children, must establish it; and that these first rudiments of justice must every day be improved, as the society enlarges: If all this appear evident, as it certainly must, we may conclude, that it is utterly impossible for men to remain any considerable time in that savage condition, which precedes society; but that his very first state and situation may justly be esteemed social. This, however, hinders not, but that philosophers may, if they please, extend their reasoning to the supposed state of nature; provided they allow it to be a mere philosophical fiction, which never had, and never could have any reality. Human nature being composed of two principal parts, which are requisite in all its actions, the affections and understanding; it is certain, that the blind motions of the former, without the direction of the latter, incapacitate men for society: And it may be allowed us to consider separately the effects, that result from the separate operations of these two component parts of the mind. The same liberty may be permitted to moral, which is allowed to natural philosophers; and it is very usual with the latter to consider any motion as compounded and consisting of two parts separate from each other, though at the same time they acknowledge it to be in itself uncompounded and inseparable.
Now, as it is by creating a rule for the stability of possession that this passion holds back, if that rule is very obscure and hard to figure out, society must be seen, in a sense, as accidental and the result of many ages. But if it turns out that nothing is simpler and more obvious than that rule—that every parent, to keep peace among their children, must enforce it—and that these basic principles of justice must improve daily as society grows: If all of this seems clear, as it surely does, we can conclude that it is completely impossible for people to stay for any significant time in that savage state that comes before society; instead, their very first state and situation can be rightly considered social. This, however, doesn’t prevent philosophers from extending their reasoning to the imagined state of nature, as long as they treat it as a mere philosophical fiction that never existed and never could. Human nature is made up of two main parts necessary for all its actions: emotions and understanding. It’s clear that the blind impulses of the former, without the guidance of the latter, hinder people from forming societies. We can consider separately the effects that come from the distinct workings of these two components of the mind. The same freedom can be granted to moral philosophy that is given to natural philosophy; and it is quite common for the latter to view any motion as a combination made up of two parts distinct from each other, even while acknowledging that it is, in itself, uncombined and inseparable.
This state of nature, therefore, is to be regarded as a mere fiction, not unlike that of the golden age, which poets have invented; only with this difference, that the former is described as full of war, violence and injustice; whereas the latter is pointed out to us, as the most charming and most peaceable condition, that can possibly be imagined. The seasons, in that first age of nature, were so temperate, if we may believe the poets, that there was no necessity for men to provide themselves with cloaths and houses as a security against the violence of heat and cold. The rivers flowed with wine and milk: The oaks yielded honey; and nature spontaneously produced her greatest delicacies. Nor were these the chief advantages of that happy age. The storms and tempests were not alone removed from nature; but those more furious tempests were unknown to human breasts, which now cause such uproar, and engender such confusion. Avarice, ambition, cruelty, selfishness, were never heard of: Cordial affection, compassion, sympathy, were the only movements, with which the human mind was yet acquainted. Even the distinction of mine and thine was banished from that happy race of mortals, and carryed with them the very notions of property and obligation, justice and injustice.
This state of nature should be seen as a simple fiction, similar to the golden age envisioned by poets; the key difference being that the former is depicted as filled with war, violence, and injustice, while the latter is presented as the most beautiful and peaceful condition imaginable. In that early age of nature, the seasons were so mild, according to the poets, that people didn't need to make clothes or build houses to protect themselves from extreme heat or cold. Rivers flowed with wine and milk; oaks provided honey, and nature effortlessly produced its finest treats. But these weren’t the only benefits of that fortunate time. Not only were storms and tempests absent from nature, but those fierce tempests were also unknown to human hearts, which now create such turmoil and confusion. Greed, ambition, cruelty, and selfishness didn’t exist; only deep affection, compassion, and empathy filled the human mind. Even the concepts of mine and yours were absent from that happy group of humans, along with the very ideas of property and obligation, justice and injustice.
This, no doubt, is to be regarded as an idle fiction; but yet deserves our attention, because nothing can more evidently shew the origin of those virtues, which are the subjects of our present enquiry. I have already observed, that justice takes its rise from human conventions; and that these are intended as a remedy to some inconveniences, which proceed from the concurrence of certain qualities of the human mind with the situation of external objects. The qualities of the mind are selfishness and limited generosity: And the situation of external objects is their easy change, joined to their scarcity in comparison of the wants and desires of men. But however philosophers may have been bewildered in those speculations, poets have been guided more infallibly, by a certain taste or common instinct, which in most kinds of reasoning goes farther than any of that art and philosophy, with which we have been yet acquainted. They easily perceived, if every man had a tender regard for another, or if nature supplied abundantly all our wants and desires, that the jealousy of interest, which justice supposes, could no longer have place; nor would there be any occasion for those distinctions and limits of property and possession, which at present are in use among mankind. Encrease to a sufficient degree the benevolence of men, or the bounty of nature, and you render justice useless, by supplying its place with much nobler virtues, and more valuable blessings. The selfishness of men is animated by the few possessions we have, in proportion to our wants; and it is to restrain this selfishness, that men have been obliged to separate themselves from the community, and to distinguish betwixt their own goods and those of others.
This is definitely seen as a mere fantasy; however, it still warrants our attention because nothing illustrates the origin of the virtues we're currently examining more clearly. I've already noted that justice arises from human agreements, which are meant to address the inconveniences that come from certain tendencies of the human mind interacting with the external world. The mind's tendencies include selfishness and limited generosity, while the external situation is characterized by constant change coupled with scarcity, especially in relation to human wants and desires. Although philosophers might get lost in these theories, poets tend to be guided more reliably by an instinct or sense that often surpasses the art and philosophy we're familiar with. They easily recognize that if everyone genuinely cared for one another, or if nature comfortably fulfilled all our needs, the jealousy of personal interest—which justice relies on—would cease to exist. There would also be no need for the distinctions and boundaries around property and ownership that we currently observe among people. If we significantly increase either people's goodwill or nature's generosity, justice becomes unnecessary, replaced by far nobler virtues and greater blessings. People’s selfishness is fueled by the limited possessions we have relative to our desires, and it is this selfishness that has led individuals to separate themselves from the community and to differentiate between their own belongings and those of others.
Nor need we have recourse to the fictions of poets to learn this; but beside the reason of the thing, may discover the same truth by common experience and observation. It is easy to remark, that a cordial affection renders all things common among friends; and that married people in particular mutually lose their property, and are unacquainted with the mine and thine, which are so necessary, and yet cause such disturbance in human society. The same effect arises from any alteration in the circumstances of mankind; as when there is such a plenty of any thing as satisfies all the desires of men: In which case the distinction of property is entirely lost, and every thing remains in common. This we may observe with regard to air and water, though the most valuable of all external objects; and may easily conclude, that if men were supplied with every thing in the same abundance, or if every one had the same affection and tender regard for every one as for himself; justice and injustice would be equally unknown among mankind.
We don’t need to rely on poets' fictions to understand this; beyond reason, we can find the same truth through common experience and observation. It’s clear that strong affection makes everything shared among friends, and married couples, in particular, end up blending their properties and lose the concept of "mine" and "yours," which are usually essential but cause so much disruption in society. This same effect happens with any changes in people's circumstances, like when there's such an abundance of something that it fulfills everyone's desires. In this situation, the distinction of property disappears completely, and everything becomes shared. We can see this with air and water, even though they are the most valuable resources; we can easily conclude that if people had everything in equal abundance, or if everyone treated others with the same care as they do themselves, concepts of justice and injustice would be completely alien to humanity.
Here then is a proposition, which, I think, may be regarded as certain, that it is only from the selfishness and confined generosity of men, along with the scanty provision nature has made for his wants, that justice derives its origin. If we look backward we shall find, that this proposition bestows an additional force on some of those observations, which we have already made on this subject.
Here’s a proposal that I believe can be considered true: justice originates from people’s selfishness and limited generosity, along with the minimal resources nature has provided for their needs. If we reflect on the past, we will see that this idea reinforces some of the points we've already discussed on this topic.
First, we may conclude from it, that a regard to public interest, or a strong extensive benevolence, is not our first and original motive for the observation of the rules of justice; since it is allowed, that if men were endowed with such a benevolence, these rules would never have been dreamt of.
First, we can conclude from this that concern for the public good, or a deep sense of generosity, is not our primary reason for following the rules of justice; since it is accepted that if people had such a benevolence, these rules would never have been conceived.
Secondly, we may conclude from the same principle, that the sense of justice is not founded on reason, or on the discovery of certain connexions and relations of ideas, which are eternal, immutable, and universally obligatory. For since it is confest, that such an alteration as that above-mentioned, in the temper and circumstances of mankind, would entirely alter our duties and obligations, it is necessary upon the common system, that the sense of virtue is derived from reason, to shew the change which this must produce in the relations and ideas. But it is evident, that the only cause, why the extensive generosity of man, and the perfect abundance of every thing, would destroy the very idea of justice, is because they render it useless; and that, on the other hand, his confined benevolence, and his necessitous condition, give rise to that virtue, only by making it requisite to the publick interest, and to that of every individual. Twas therefore a concern for our own, and the publick interest, which made us establish the laws of justice; and nothing can be more certain, than that it is not any relation of ideas, which gives us this concern, but our impressions and sentiments, without which every thing in nature is perfectly indifferent to us, and can never in the least affect us. The sense of justice, therefore, is not founded on our ideas, but on our impressions.
Secondly, we can conclude from the same principle that our sense of justice isn’t based on reason or on the discovery of certain connections and relationships of ideas that are eternal, unchanging, and universally binding. Since it’s acknowledged that a change in human temperament and circumstances would completely alter our duties and obligations, it’s necessary within the common framework that the sense of virtue, which is derived from reason, must show the change this would cause in relationships and ideas. However, it’s clear that the only reason why the broad generosity of humanity and the complete abundance of everything would eliminate the very idea of justice is that they make it unnecessary. On the flip side, our limited kindness and our needy condition lead to that virtue because they make it essential for the public good and for everyone individually. Thus, it was a concern for our own and the public interest that led us to establish the laws of justice; and nothing could be more certain than that it’s not any relationship of ideas that gives us this concern, but our feelings and impressions. Without those, everything in nature is completely indifferent to us and does not affect us at all. Therefore, our sense of justice isn’t based on our ideas, but on our impressions.
Thirdly, we may farther confirm the foregoing proposition, THAT THOSE IMPRESSIONS, WHICH GIVE RISE TO THIS SENSE OF JUSTICE, ARE NOT NATURAL TO THE MIND OF MAN, BUT ARISE FROM ARTIFICE AND HUMAN CONVENTIONS. For since any considerable alteration of temper and circumstances destroys equally justice and injustice; and since such an alteration has an effect only by changing our own and the publick interest; it follows, that the first establishment of the rules of justice depends on these different interests. But if men pursued the publick interest naturally, and with a hearty affection, they would never have dreamed of restraining each other by these rules; and if they pursued their own interest, without any precaution, they would run head-long into every kind of injustice and violence. These rules, therefore, are artificial, and seek their end in an oblique and indirect manner; nor is the interest, which gives rise to them, of a kind that could be pursued by the natural and inartificial passions of men.
Thirdly, we can further confirm the previous point that the feelings that lead to our sense of justice are not inherent to human nature, but come from social constructs and agreements. Since any significant change in mood and circumstances equally affects both justice and injustice, and since such changes only impact our personal and public interests, it follows that the initial establishment of justice rules relies on these varying interests. If people naturally pursued the public good with genuine care, they would never think of imposing these rules on one another. Likewise, if they chased their own interests recklessly, they would easily fall into all kinds of injustice and violence. Therefore, these rules are artificial and aim to achieve their purpose in a roundabout way; the interests they stem from are not something that could arise from the natural, instinctive feelings of people.
To make this more evident, consider, that though the rules of justice are established merely by interest, their connexion with interest is somewhat singular, and is different from what may be observed on other occasions. A single act of justice is frequently contrary to public interest; and were it to stand alone, without being followed by other acts, may, in itself, be very prejudicial to society. When a man of merit, of a beneficent disposition, restores a great fortune to a miser, or a seditious bigot, he has acted justly and laudably, but the public is a real sufferer. Nor is every single act of justice, considered apart, more conducive to private interest, than to public; and it is easily conceived how a man may impoverish himself by a signal instance of integrity, and have reason to wish, that with regard to that single act, the laws of justice were for a moment suspended in the universe. But however single acts of justice may be contrary, either to public or private interest, it is certain, that the whole plan or scheme is highly conducive, or indeed absolutely requisite, both to the support of society, and the well-being of every individual. It is impossible to separate the good from the ill. Property must be stable, and must be fixed by general rules. Though in one instance the public be a sufferer, this momentary ill is amply compensated by the steady prosecution of the rule, and by the peace and order, which it establishes in society. And even every individual person must find himself a gainer, on ballancing the account; since, without justice society must immediately dissolve, and every one must fall into that savage and solitary condition, which is infinitely worse than the worst situation that can possibly be supposed in society. When therefore men have had experience enough to observe, that whatever may be the consequence of any single act of justice, performed by a single person, yet the whole system of actions, concurred in by the whole society, is infinitely advantageous to the whole, and to every part; it is not long before justice and property take place. Every member of society is sensible of this interest: Every one expresses this sense to his fellows, along with the resolution he has taken of squaring his actions by it, on condition that others will do the same. No more is requisite to induce any one of them to perform an act of justice, who has the first opportunity. This becomes an example to others. And thus justice establishes itself by a kind of convention or agreement; that is, by a sense of interest, supposed to be common to all, and where every single act is performed in expectation that others are to perform the like. Without such a convention, no one would ever have dreamed, that there was such a virtue as justice, or have been induced to conform his actions to it. Taking any single act, my justice may be pernicious in every respect; and it is only upon the supposition that others are to imitate my example, that I can be induced to embrace that virtue; since nothing but this combination can render justice advantageous, or afford me any motives to conform my self to its rules.
To make this clearer, think about how the rules of justice are established mainly by self-interest, yet their relationship to that interest is quite unique and differs from other situations. An individual act of justice can often go against the public interest; if it stands alone and isn’t followed by other actions, it can harm society. For instance, when a person of high moral standing chooses to give a large fortune back to a miser or a divisive fanatic, they are acting justly and commendably, but the public actually suffers as a result. Moreover, not every isolated act of justice is necessarily better for personal interests than for public ones, and it’s easy to see how someone might make themselves worse off by demonstrating such integrity, wishing in that moment that justice could be paused entirely. However, despite how individual acts of justice may conflict with either public or private interests, it’s clear that the overall system is essential for both supporting society and ensuring the well-being of each person. You can't separate the good from the bad. Property rights need to be stable and determined by general rules. Although the public might suffer in one instance, that temporary harm is more than offset by the ongoing enforcement of these rules and the peace and order they create in society. In fact, each individual stands to benefit overall, since without justice, society would collapse, and everyone would revert to a primal and isolated state, which is far worse than any conceivable situation in organized society. Once people have enough experience to recognize that, regardless of the consequences of any single act of justice by one individual, the entire system of actions agreed upon by society is incredibly beneficial for everyone, justice and property will start to take hold. Every member of society is aware of this interest: each one communicates this to others, along with a commitment to align their actions with it, as long as others do the same. This is all that’s needed to motivate anyone to act justly when the opportunity arises. Such actions then set an example for others. In this way, justice creates itself through a sort of social agreement, based on a common understanding of interest, where every individual performance is expected to be mirrored by others. Without this agreement, no one would have considered that justice was a virtue or felt compelled to act in accordance with it. Taking any single action, my sense of justice might be harmful in every way; it’s only under the assumption that others will follow my lead that I would be motivated to adopt that virtue, since only through this collective action can justice become beneficial or give me any reason to adhere to its principles.
We come now to the second question we proposed, viz. Why we annex the idea of virtue to justice, and of vice to injustice. This question will not detain us long after the principles, which we have already established, All we can say of it at present will be dispatched in a few words: And for farther satisfaction, the reader must wait till we come to the third part of this book. The natural obligation to justice, viz, interest, has been fully explained; but as to the moral obligation, or the sentiment of right and wrong, it will first be requisite to examine the natural virtues, before we can give a full and satisfactory account of it. After men have found by experience, that their selfishness and confined generosity, acting at their liberty, totally incapacitate them for society; and at the same time have observed, that society is necessary to the satisfaction of those very passions, they are naturally induced to lay themselves under the restraint of such rules, as may render their commerce more safe and commodious. To the imposition then, and observance of these rules, both in general, and in every particular instance, they are at first induced only by a regard to interest; and this motive, on the first formation of society, is sufficiently strong and forcible. But when society has become numerous, and has encreased to a tribe or nation, this interest is more remote; nor do men so readily perceive, that disorder and confusion follow upon every breach of these rules, as in a more narrow and contracted society. But though in our own actions we may frequently lose sight of that interest, which we have in maintaining order, and may follow a lesser and more present interest, we never fail to observe the prejudice we receive, either mediately or immediately, from the injustice of others; as not being in that case either blinded by passion, or byassed by any contrary temptation. Nay when the injustice is so distant from us, as no way to affect our interest, it still displeases us; because we consider it as prejudicial to human society, and pernicious to every one that approaches the person guilty of it. We partake of their uneasiness by sympathy; and as every thing, which gives uneasiness in human actions, upon the general survey, is called Vice, and whatever produces satisfaction, in the same manner, is denominated Virtue; this is the reason why the sense of moral good and evil follows upon justice and injustice. And though this sense, in the present case, be derived only from contemplating the actions of others, yet we fail not to extend it even to our own actions. The general rule reaches beyond those instances, from which it arose; while at the same time we naturally sympathize with others in the sentiments they entertain of us. Thus self-interest is the original motive to the establishment of justice: but a sympathy with public interest is the source of the moral approbation, which attends that virtue.
We now turn to the second question we raised: Why do we connect the idea of virtue with justice and vice with injustice? This question won't take us long to address, given the principles we've already laid out. We can summarize it in just a few words, and for further understanding, the reader will need to wait until we reach the third part of this book. We’ve fully explained the natural obligation to justice, which is based on self-interest; however, to understand the moral obligation or the sense of right and wrong, we'll need to first examine the natural virtues. Once people realize through experience that their selfishness and limited generosity, when unchecked, completely disable them from participating in society, and at the same time see that society is essential for satisfying those very passions, they are naturally motivated to impose certain rules that make their interactions safer and more convenient. Initially, both the establishment and adherence to these rules are driven solely by self-interest, and this motivation is strong enough at the beginning of a society. But as society grows larger into a tribe or nation, this interest becomes more abstract, and people are less aware that disorder and chaos result from every violation of these rules, as they do in smaller, tighter-knit communities. Even though we may often lose sight of our interest in maintaining order and may pursue a lesser, more immediate interest in our own actions, we always notice the harm we suffer, directly or indirectly, from the injustice of others—since, in these situations, we are neither blinded by passion nor swayed by conflicting temptations. Even when injustice is far removed from us and does not directly impact our interests, it still bothers us because we see it as harmful to society as a whole and detrimental to anyone who comes into contact with the wrongdoer. We empathize with their discomfort through sympathy; thus, anything that causes distress in human actions is labeled as Vice, while anything that brings satisfaction is called Virtue. This is why our sense of moral good and evil is linked to justice and injustice. Although this sense arises from observing the actions of others, we also apply it to our own behavior. The overall principle extends beyond the specific instances from which it derives, as we naturally empathize with others regarding how they perceive us. Therefore, self-interest serves as the initial motivation for establishing justice, but sympathy for the public interest is what generates the moral approval that accompanies that virtue.
Though this progress of the sentiments be natural, and even necessary, it is certain, that it is here forwarded by the artifice of politicians, who, in order to govern men more easily, and preserve peace in human society, have endeavoured to produce an esteem for justice, and an abhorrence of injustice. This, no doubt, must have its effect; but nothing can be more evident, than that the matter has been carryed too far by certain writers on morals, who seem to have employed their utmost efforts to extirpate all sense of virtue from among mankind. Any artifice of politicians may assist nature in the producing of those sentiments, which she suggests to us, and may even on some occasions, produce alone an approbation or esteem for any particular action; but it is impossible it should be the sole cause of the distinction we make betwixt vice and virtue. For if nature did not aid us in this particular, it would be in vain for politicians to talk of honourable or dishonourable, praiseworthy or blameable. These words would be perfectly unintelligible, and would no more have any idea annexed to them, than if they were of a tongue perfectly unknown to us. The utmost politicians can perform, is, to extend the natural sentiments beyond their original bounds; but still nature must furnish the materials, and give us some notion of moral distinctions.
While it's natural, and even necessary, for feelings to evolve, it's clear that politicians exploit this to make governing easier and maintain peace in society. They've aimed to instill a respect for justice and a dislike for injustice. This certainly has an impact, but it's also obvious that some moral writers have taken things too far, working hard to eliminate a sense of virtue from people. Politicians can help shape the feelings that come naturally to us and might even, at times, create approval or respect for certain actions on their own. However, it's impossible for this to be the only reason we differentiate between vice and virtue. If nature didn’t help us in this regard, it would be pointless for politicians to discuss what's honorable or dishonorable, praiseworthy or blameworthy. Those terms would be completely meaningless, like words in a completely foreign language. The best politicians can do is to push natural sentiments beyond their original limits, but nature must still provide the foundation and give us some understanding of moral distinctions.
As publick praise and blame encrease our esteem for justice; so private education and instruction contribute to the same effect. For as parents easily observe, that a man is the more useful, both to himself and others, the greater degree of probity and honour he is endowed with; and that those principles have greater force, when custom and education assist interest and reflection: For these reasons they are induced to inculcate on their children, from their earliest infancy, the principles of probity, and teach them to regard the observance of those rules, by which society is maintained, as worthy and honourable, and their violation as base and infamous. By this means the sentiments of honour may take root in their tender minds, and acquire such firmness and solidity, that they may fall little short of those principles, which are the most essential to our natures, and the most deeply radicated in our internal constitution.
As public praise and criticism increase our respect for justice, so do private education and guidance have the same effect. Parents easily notice that a person is more useful to themselves and others the more integrity and honor they possess; and that these values are stronger when traditions and education support personal interest and reflection. For these reasons, parents feel motivated to instill in their children, from a very young age, the values of integrity, teaching them to see the following of societal rules as noble and the breaking of those rules as shameful. This way, feelings of honor can take root in their young minds and gain enough strength and stability that they come close to the fundamental principles that are essential to our nature and deeply ingrained in our internal makeup.
What farther contributes to encrease their solidity, is the interest of our reputation, after the opinion, that a merit or demerit attends justice or injustice, is once firmly established among mankind. There is nothing, which touches us more nearly than our reputation, and nothing on which our reputation more depends than our conduct, with relation to the property of others. For this reason, every one, who has any regard to his character, or who intends to live on good terms with mankind, must fix an inviolable law to himself, never, by any temptation, to be induced to violate those principles, which are essential to a man of probity and honour.
What further adds to their stability is the importance of our reputation, especially once the belief in the connection between justice and merit or injustice and demerit is firmly established in society. Nothing affects us more directly than our reputation, and nothing impacts our reputation more than how we act regarding other people's property. For this reason, anyone who cares about their character or wants to get along well with others must set a strict personal rule never to be tempted into violating the principles that are essential to being a person of integrity and honor.
I shall make only one observation before I leave this subject, viz, that though I assert, that in the state of nature, or that imaginary state, which preceded society, there be neither justice nor injustice, yet I assert not, that it was allowable, in such a state, to violate the property of others. I only maintain, that there was no such thing as property; and consequently could be no such thing as justice or injustice. I shall have occasion to make a similar reflection with regard to promises, when I come to treat of them; and I hope this reflection, when duly weighed, will suffice to remove all odium from the foregoing opinions, with regard to justice and injustice.
I’ll make just one point before I move on from this topic: while I argue that in the state of nature, or that imaginary time before society existed, there is neither justice nor injustice, I do not claim that it was acceptable to violate others' property in such a state. I simply contend that there was no concept of property; therefore, there could be no notion of justice or injustice. I will have a similar thought about promises when I discuss them, and I hope this reflection, when considered thoughtfully, will help to alleviate any negativity towards my earlier views on justice and injustice.
SECT. III OF THE RULES WHICH DETERMINE PROPERTY
Though the establishment of the rule, concerning the stability of possession, be not only useful, but even absolutely necessary to human society, it can never serve to any purpose, while it remains in such general terms. Some method must be shewn, by which we may distinguish what particular goods are to be assigned to each particular person, while the rest of mankind are excluded from their possession and enjoyment. Our next business, then, must be to discover the reasons which modify this general rule, and fit it to the common use and practice of the world.
Though establishing the rule about the stability of possession is not just helpful but also essential for human society, it won't be effective as long as it stays in such broad terms. We need to find a way to identify which specific goods belong to each individual while ensuring that the rest of society is excluded from possessing or enjoying them. Our next step, then, should be to uncover the reasons that adjust this general rule to fit the everyday use and practices of the world.
It is obvious, that those reasons are not derived from any utility or advantage, which either the particular person or the public may reap from his enjoyment of any particular goods, beyond what would result from the possession of them by any other person. Twere better, no doubt, that every one were possessed of what is most suitable to him, and proper for his use: But besides, that this relation of fitness may be common to several at once, it is liable to so many controversies, and men are so partial and passionate in judging of these controversies, that such a loose and uncertain rule would be absolutely incompatible with the peace of human society. The convention concerning the stability of possession is entered into, in order to cut off all occasions of discord and contention; and this end would never be attained, were we allowed to apply this rule differently in every particular case, according to every particular utility, which might be discovered in such an application. Justice, in her decisions, never regards the fitness or unfitness of objects to particular persons, but conducts herself by more extensive views. Whether a man be generous, or a miser, he is equally well received by her, and obtains with the same facility a decision in his favours, even for what is entirely useless to him.
It's clear that those reasons don't come from any usefulness or benefit that either the individual or society might gain from their enjoyment of specific goods, beyond what anyone else would get from having them. Of course, it would be better if everyone had what suits them best and is right for their needs. However, this idea of suitability can apply to several people at once and is open to so many disputes. People are often biased and emotional when judging these disputes, so such a loose and uncertain standard would be completely incompatible with social peace. The agreement on the stability of possession is made to eliminate any reasons for conflict and disagreement; this goal would never be achieved if we could apply this standard differently in each case, based on each specific utility we might identify. Justice, in her decisions, never considers the suitability or unsuitability of things for particular individuals, but operates with a broader perspective. Whether someone is generous or stingy, they are equally welcomed by her and can easily get a favorable ruling, even for something that is completely useless to them.
It follows therefore, that the general rule, that possession must be stable, is not applied by particular judgments, but by other general rules, which must extend to the whole society, and be inflexible either by spite or favour. To illustrate this, I propose the following instance. I first consider men in their savage and solitary condition; and suppose, that being sensible of the misery of that state, and foreseeing the advantages that would result from society, they seek each other's company, and make an offer of mutual protection and assistance. I also suppose, that they are endowed with such sagacity as immediately to perceive, that the chief impediment to this project of society and partnership lies in the avidity and selfishness of their natural temper; to remedy which, they enter into a convention for the stability of possession, and for mutual restraint and forbearance. I am sensible, that this method of proceeding is not altogether natural; but besides that I here only suppose those reflections to be formed at once, which in fact arise insensibly and by degrees; besides this, I say, it is very possible, that several persons, being by different accidents separated from the societies, to which they formerly belonged, may be obliged to form a new society among themselves; in which case they are entirely in the situation above-mentioned.
It follows that the general rule that possession must be stable is not determined by specific judgments, but by other general rules that apply to everyone in society, and must be applied consistently without bias. To illustrate this, consider the following example. First, imagine people in their primitive and isolated state; recognizing the misery of that condition, and seeing the benefits of forming a society, they seek each other's company and offer mutual protection and support. I also assume they have enough insight to realize that the main obstacle to this idea of society and teamwork lies in their natural greed and selfishness; to address this, they agree to establish rules for stable possession and mutual restraint and patience. I understand that this way of thinking isn't entirely natural; but aside from the fact that I assume these thoughts occur all at once, when in reality they develop gradually over time, it is very possible that several individuals, after being separated by various circumstances from the societies they once belonged to, may need to create a new society among themselves, putting them back in the situation described above.
It is evident, then, that their first difficulty, in this situation, after the general convention for the establishment of society, and for the constancy of possession, is, how to separate their possessions, and assign to each his particular portion, which he must for the future inalterably enjoy. This difficulty will not detain them long; but it must immediately occur to them, as the most natural expedient, that every one continue to enjoy what he is at present master of, and that property or constant possession be conjoined to the immediate possession. Such is the effect of custom, that it not only reconciles us to any thing we have long enjoyed, but even gives us an affection for it, and makes us prefer it to other objects, which may be more valuable, but are less known to us. What has long lain under our eye, and has often been employed to our advantage, that we are always the most unwilling to part with; but can easily live without possessions, which we never have enjoyed, and are not accustomed to. It is evident, therefore, that men would easily acquiesce in this expedient, that every one continue to enjoy what he is at present possessed of; and this is the reason, why they would so naturally agree in preferring it.[1]
It’s clear that their first challenge in this situation, after the general agreement to form a society and maintain ownership, is figuring out how to separate their belongings and assign each person their specific share, which they must be able to enjoy without change in the future. This issue won’t take long to resolve; they will quickly realize that the most straightforward solution is for everyone to keep what they currently own and that ownership or continuous possession should be linked to what they already have. Customs have such a strong effect that not only do we become attached to things we've long enjoyed, but we even prefer them over other items that might be more valuable but are less familiar to us. We are often most reluctant to give up what we have consistently seen and used to our advantage, while we can easily live without possessions we have never enjoyed or gotten used to. Therefore, it’s clear that people would quickly accept this solution of everyone continuing to enjoy what they currently possess, which is why they would naturally agree to prioritize it.
[1]
No questions in philosophy are more difficult, than when a number of causes
present themselves for the same phænomenon, to determine which is the principal
and predominant. There seldom is any very precise argument to fix our choice,
and men must be contented to be guided by a kind of taste or fancy, arising
from analogy, and a comparison of familiar instances. Thus, in the present
case, there are, no doubt, motives of public interest for most of the rules,
which determine property; but still I suspect, that these rules are principally
fixed by the imagination, or the more frivolous properties of our thought and
conception. I shall continue to explain these causes, leaving it to the
reader's choice, whether he will prefer those derived from publick utility, or
those derived from the imagination. We shall begin with the right of the
present possessor.
It is a quality, which I have already observed in human nature, that when
two objects appear in a close relation to each other, the mind is apt to
ascribe to them any additional relation, in order to compleat the union; and
this inclination is so strong, as often to make us run into errors (such as
that of the conjunction of thought and matter) if we find that they can serve
to that purpose. Many of our impressions are incapable of place or local
position; and yet those very impressions we suppose to have a local conjunction
with the impressions of sight and touch, merely because they are conjoined by
causation, and are already united in the imagination. Since, therefore, we can
feign a new relation, and even an absurd one, in order to compleat any union,
it will easily be imagined, that if there be any relations, which depend on the
mind, it will readily conjoin them to any preceding relation, and unite, by a
new bond, such objects as have already an union in the fancy. Thus for
instance, we never fail, in our arrangement of bodies, to place those which are
resembling in contiguity to each other, or at least in correspondent points of
view; because we feel a satisfaction in joining the relation of contiguity to
that of resemblance, or the resemblance of situation to that of qualities. And
this is easily accounted for from the known properties of human nature. When
the mind is determined to join certain objects, but undetermined in its choice
of the particular objects, It naturally turns its eye to such as are related
together. They are already united in the mind: They present themselves at the
same time to the conception; and instead of requiring any new reason for their
conjunction, it would require a very powerful reason to make us over-look this
natural affinity. This we shall have occasion to explain more fully afterwards,
when we come to treat of beauty. In the mean time, we may content ourselves
with observing, that the same love of order and uniformity, which arranges the
books in a library, and the chairs in a parlour, contribute to the formation of
society, and to the well-being of mankind, by modifying the general rule
concerning the stability of possession. And as property forms a relation
betwixt a person and an object, it is natural to found it on some preceding
relation; and as property Is nothing but a constant possession, secured by the
laws of society, it is natural to add it to the present possession, which is a
relation that resembles it. For this also has its influence. If it be natural
to conjoin all sorts of relations, it is more so, to conjoin such relations as
are resembling, and are related together.
[1]
No questions in philosophy are more challenging than when multiple causes arise for the same phenomenon, making it tough to determine which one is the main or most significant. There's rarely any clear argument to guide our decision, so people often rely on a sense of taste or intuition, shaped by analogy and comparisons with familiar examples. In this instance, it's clear that many of the rules governing property are motivated by public interest; however, I suspect that these rules are mainly influenced by imagination or the lighter aspects of our thinking and perception. I will continue to explain these causes, leaving it up to the reader to choose whether they prefer those that come from public utility or those that come from imagination. We will start with the rights of the current possessor.
It’s a trait of human nature that when two objects seem closely related, our minds tend to attribute any additional connections to them to complete that union. This inclination is so strong that it often leads us to errors (like assuming a link between thought and matter) if we find it can fulfill that purpose. Many of our impressions cannot be placed or positioned locally; yet those same impressions are assumed to have a local connection with the impressions of sight and touch, simply because they are causally linked and already combined in our imagination. Therefore, since we can create a new relationship, even an absurd one, to complete any union, it’s easy to imagine that if there are any relations depending on the mind, it will easily connect them to any previous relations, forming a new bond between objects that are already united in thought. For instance, we often arrange similar objects next to each other or at least in related viewpoints because we find satisfaction in linking proximity to resemblance, or the similarities in position to those in qualities. This is easily explained by the known characteristics of human nature. When the mind decides to connect certain objects but isn’t sure which specific ones to choose, it naturally focuses on those that are related. They are already unified in our minds; they appear to us simultaneously in thought, and instead of needing a new reason for their connection, it would take a strong reason to overlook this natural affinity. We will have the opportunity to explore this further when we discuss beauty. In the meantime, we can note that the same desire for order and uniformity that organizes books in a library and chairs in a living room also contributes to the formation of society and the well-being of people by influencing the general principles concerning the stability of possession. Since property establishes a relationship between a person and an object, it makes sense to base it on some previously existing relationship; and because property is simply a consistent possession, secured by societal laws, it’s logical to tie it to current possession, which resembles that relationship. This connection matters, too. If it’s natural to combine all kinds of relationships, it’s even more natural to link similar relations that are already connected.
But we may observe, that though the rule of the assignment of property to the present possessor be natural, and by that means useful, yet its utility extends not beyond the first formation of society; nor would any thing be more pernicious, than the constant observance of it; by which restitution would be excluded, and every injustice would be authorized and rewarded. We must, therefore, seek for some other circumstance, that may give rise to property after society is once established; and of this kind, I find four most considerable, viz. Occupation, Prescription, Accession, and Succession. We shall briefly examine each of these, beginning with Occupation.
But we can see that while the rule of assigning property to the current owner is natural and useful, its usefulness doesn't last beyond the initial establishment of society. Nothing could be more harmful than strictly following this rule, as it would prevent restitution and allow injustices to be legitimized and rewarded. Therefore, we need to look for other factors that can create property once society is in place. I see four major factors: Occupation, Prescription, Accession, and Succession. We will briefly look at each of these, starting with Occupation.
The possession of all external goods is changeable and uncertain; which is one of the most considerable impediments to the establishment of society, and is the reason why, by universal agreement, express or tacite, men restrain themselves by what we now call the rules of justice and equity. The misery of the condition, which precedes this restraint, is the cause why we submit to that remedy as quickly as possible; and this affords us an easy reason, why we annex the idea of property to the first possession, or to occupation. Men are unwilling to leave property in suspense, even for the shortest time, or open the least door to violence and disorder. To which we may add, that the first possession always engages the attention most; and did we neglect it, there would be no colour of reason for assigning property to any succeeding possession.[2]
The ownership of all external goods is unpredictable and uncertain, which is one of the biggest obstacles to creating a society. This is why, by a universal agreement, whether explicit or implicit, people hold themselves back by what we now refer to as the rules of justice and fairness. The misery of the state we experience before this self-restraint is what makes us accept that solution as quickly as possible. This gives us a clear reason for associating the concept of property with initial possession or occupation. People are reluctant to leave property unresolved, even for a moment, or to allow any opportunity for violence and chaos. Additionally, initial possession always captures the most attention, and if we were to ignore it, there would be no valid reason for claiming property for any subsequent possession.[2]
[2] Some philosophers account for the right of occupation, by saying, that every one has a property in his own labour; and when he joins that labour to any thing, it gives him the property of the whole: But, 1. There are several kinds of occupation, where we cannot be said to join our labour to the object we acquire: As when we possess a meadow by grazing our cattle upon it. 2. This accounts for the matter by means of accession; which is taking a needless circuit. 3. We cannot be said to join our labour to any thing but in a figurative sense. Properly speaking, we only make an alteration on it by our labour. This forms a relation betwixt us and the object; and thence arises the property, according to the preceding principles.
[2] Some philosophers explain the right of ownership by saying that everyone has a claim to the work they put in; when they attach that work to something, they own the entire thing. However, 1. There are different types of ownership where we can’t really say we’re combining our work with the thing we acquire, like when we use a meadow by grazing our cattle on it. 2. This explanation relies on the idea of addition, which is unnecessarily complex. 3. We can only say we join our labor to something in a figurative way. To be precise, we only change it through our work. This creates a relationship between us and the object, and based on the earlier principles, that is how property emerges.
There remains nothing, but to determine exactly, what is meant by possession; and this is not so easy as may at first sight be imagined. We are said to be in possession of any thing, not only when we immediately touch it, but also when we are so situated with respect to it, as to have it in our power to use it; and may move, alter, or destroy it, according to our present pleasure or advantage. This relation, then, is a species of cause and effect; and as property is nothing but a stable possession, derived from the rules of justice, or the conventions of men, it is to be considered as the same species of relation. But here we may observe, that as the power of using any object becomes more or less certain, according as the interruptions we may meet with are more or less probable; and as this probability may increase by insensible degrees; it is in many cases impossible to determine when possession begins or ends; nor is there any certain standard, by which we can decide such controversies. A wild boar, that falls into our snares, is deemed to be in our possession, if it be impossible for him to escape. But what do we mean by impossible? How do we separate this impossibility from an improbability? And how distinguish that exactly from a probability? Mark the precise limits of the one and the other, and shew the standard, by which we may decide all disputes that may arise, and, as we find by experience, frequently do arise upon this subject.[3]
There’s nothing left to do but figure out exactly what we mean by possession, and that's not as simple as it might seem at first. We are considered to have possession of something not just when we physically touch it, but also when we’re in a position to use it; we can move, change, or destroy it based on our current desires or benefits. This relationship is a kind of cause and effect; property is simply a stable possession derived from rules of justice or human agreements, so it should be seen as the same type of relationship. However, we should note that the certainty of being able to use any object varies depending on how likely we are to encounter interruptions; this likelihood can gradually increase. Therefore, in many cases, it’s impossible to determine when possession starts or ends, and there isn’t a clear standard to resolve these disputes. For example, a wild boar caught in our traps is considered to be in our possession if it can’t escape. But what do we mean by “can’t”? How do we distinguish this impossibility from simply being unlikely? And how do we clearly separate that from a probability? Identify the exact boundaries of each and provide a standard to resolve any conflicts that arise about this subject, as we often find that disputes do arise.
[3]
If we seek a solution of these difficulties in reason and public interest, we
never shall find satisfaction; and if we look for it in the imagination, it is
evident, that the qualities, which operate upon that faculty, run so insensibly
and gradually into each other, that it is impossible to give them any precise
bounds or termination. The difficulties on this head must encrease, when we
consider, that our judgment alters very sensibly, according to the subject, and
that the same power and proximity will be deemed possession in one case, which
is not esteemed such in another. A person, who has hunted a hare to the last
degree of weariness, would look upon it as an injustice for another to rush in
before him, and seize his prey. But the same person advancing to pluck an
apple, that hangs within his reach, has no reason to complain, if another, more
alert, passes him, and takes possession. What is the reason of this difference,
but that immobility, not being natural to the hare, but the effect of industry,
forms in that case a strong relation with the hunter, which is wanting in the
other?
Here then it appears, that a certain and infallible power of enjoyment,
without touch or some other sensible relation, often produces not property: And
I farther observe, that a sensible relation, without any present power, is
sometimes sufficient to give a title to any object. The sight of a thing is
seldom a considerable relation, and is only regarded as such, when the object
is hidden, or very obscure; in which case we find, that the view alone conveys
a property; according to that maxim, THAT EVEN A WHOLE CONTINENT BELONGS TO THE
NATION, WHICH FIRST DISCOVERED IT. It is however remarkable that both in the
case of discovery and that of possession, the first discoverer and possessor
must join to the relation an intention of rendering himself proprietor,
otherwise the relation will not have its effect; and that because the connexion
in our fancy betwixt the property and the relation is not so great, but that it
requires to be helped by such an intention.
From all these circumstances, it is easy to see how perplexed many
questions may become concerning the acquisition of property by occupation; and
the least effort of thought may present us with instances, which are not
susceptible of any reasonable decision. If we prefer examples, which are real,
to such as are feigned, we may consider the following one, which is to be met
with in almost every writer, that has treated of the laws of nature. Two
Grecian colonies, leaving their native country, in search of new feats, were
informed that a city near them was deserted by its inhabitants. To know the
truth of this report, they dispatched at once two messengers, one from each
colony; who finding on their approach, that their information was true, begun a
race together with an intention to take possession of the city, each of them
for his countrymen. One of these messengers, finding that he was not an equal
match for the other, launched his spear at the gates of the city, and was so
fortunate as to fix it there before the arrival of his companion. This produced
a dispute betwixt the two colonies, which of them was the proprietor of the
empty city and this dispute still subsists among philosophers. For my part I
find the dispute impossible to be decided, and that because the whole question
hangs upon the fancy, which in this case is not possessed of any precise or
determinate standard, upon which it can give sentence. To make this evident,
let us consider, that if these two persons had been simply members of the
colonies, and not messengers or deputies, their actions would not have been of
any consequence; since in that case their relation to the colonies would have
been but feeble and imperfect. Add to this, that nothing determined them to run
to the gates rather than the walls, or any other part of the city, but that the
gates, being the most obvious and remarkable part, satisfy the fancy best in
taking them for the whole; as we find by the poets, who frequently draw their
images and metaphors from them. Besides we may consider, that the touch or
contact of the one messenger is not properly possession, no more than the
piercing the gates with a spear; but only forms a relation; and there is a
relation, in the other case, equally obvious, tho' not, perhaps, of equal
force. Which of these relations, then, conveys a right and property, or whether
any of them be sufficient for that effect, I leave to the decision of such as
are wiser than myself.
[3]
If we try to solve these problems through logic and public interest, we'll never find satisfaction; and if we look for answers in imagination, it's clear that the qualities impacting that ability blend seamlessly and gradually into one another, making it impossible to define any clear boundaries or conclusions. The challenges in this area increase when we consider that our judgment changes noticeably based on the subject, and that the same ability and closeness can be seen as ownership in one situation but not in another. A person who has chased a hare to the point of exhaustion would feel it's unfair for someone else to rush in and take it. But the same person trying to grab an apple that's within reach has no reason to complain if someone quicker comes along and takes it. What explains this difference is that the stillness of the hare, a result of effort, creates a strong connection between it and the hunter, which is absent in the other case.
Thus, it becomes evident that a definite and undeniable power of enjoyment, without contact or some other tangible relation, often does not create property. I also note that a tangible relation, even without immediate power, can sometimes be enough to establish a claim to an object. The sight of something is rarely a significant relation and is only considered such when the object is hidden or very obscure; in those cases, viewing alone conveys property, following the principle that EVEN A WHOLE CONTINENT BELONGS TO THE NATION THAT FIRST DISCOVERS IT. However, it is notable that in both the cases of discovery and possession, the first discoverer and possessor must add an intention to make themselves the owner, or else the relation won't have any effect; and this is because the connection in our imagination between property and relation isn't strong enough on its own and needs to be supported by such intention.
From all these factors, it's easy to see how complicated many questions about acquiring property by occupation can become, and even a small amount of thought can present examples that lack any reasonable resolution. If we prefer real examples over imagined ones, we can look at the following one, which is often found in the writings of those who discuss natural law. Two Greek colonies, leaving their homeland in search of new lands, learned that a nearby city was abandoned by its residents. To verify this information, they quickly sent two messengers, one from each colony; upon finding the report true as they approached, they began a race to take possession of the city, each for their own countrymen. One of these messengers, realizing he couldn't match the other's speed, threw his spear at the city's gates, and was lucky enough to embed it there before his companion arrived. This led to a dispute between the two colonies about which one owned the deserted city, and this debate continues among philosophers. Personally, I find the dispute impossible to resolve, because the entire question depends on imagination, which in this case doesn't have any clear or specific standard on which it can pass judgment. To illustrate this, let's consider that if these two individuals were simply members of the colonies and not messengers or representatives, their actions would have no significance; since in that case, their connection to the colonies would be weak and incomplete. Furthermore, nothing compelled them to run towards the gates rather than the walls or any other part of the city, except that the gates, being the most visible and notable feature, satisfy the imagination best by taking them to represent the whole, as we see in poetry, which often uses them for imagery and metaphors. Additionally, it can be argued that the touch or contact of one messenger doesn't truly signify possession, just as piercing the gates with a spear does not; rather, it simply creates a relation. There is also a relation in the other case, equally evident, though perhaps not of equal strength. So, which of these relations conveys a right and property, or whether either of them is sufficient for that purpose, I leave to the judgment of those wiser than me.
But such disputes may not only arise concerning the real existence of property and possession, but also concerning their extent; and these disputes are often susceptible of no decision, or can be decided by no other faculty than the imagination. A person who lands on the shore of a small island, that is desart and uncultivated, is deemed its possessor from the very first moment, and acquires the property of the whole; because the object is there bounded and circumscribed in the fancy, and at the same time is proportioned to the new possessor. The same person landing on a desart island, as large as Great Britain, extends his property no farther than his immediate possession; though a numerous colony are esteemed the proprietors of the whole from the instant of their debarkment.
But such disputes may not only arise about the actual existence of property and possession, but also about their extent; and these disputes are often impossible to resolve or can be determined only by imagination. A person who arrives on the shore of a small, uninhabited island is considered its possessor from the very first moment and owns the entire thing; because the object is clearly defined and bounded in the mind, and at the same time fits the new possessor. However, the same person landing on a deserted island as large as Great Britain only claims the area they are standing on; even though a large group arriving there is regarded as owning the whole island from the moment they disembark.
But it often happens, that the title of first possession becomes obscure through time; and that it is impossible to determine many controversies, which may arise concerning it. In that case long possession or prescription naturally takes place, and gives a person a sufficient property in any thing he enjoys. The nature of human society admits not of any great accuracy; nor can we always remount to the first origin of things, in order to determine their present condition. Any considerable space of time sets objects at such a distance, that they seem, in a manner, to lose their reality, and have as little influence on the mind, as if they never had been in being. A man's title, that is clear and certain at present, will seem obscure and doubtful fifty years hence, even though the facts, on which it is founded, should be proved with the greatest evidence and certainty. The same facts have not the same influence after so long an interval of time. And this may be received as a convincing argument for our preceding doctrine with regard to property and justice. Possession during a long tract of time conveys a title to any object. But as it is certain, that, however every thing be produced in time, there is nothing real that is produced by time; it follows, that property being produced by time, is not any thing real in the objects, but is the off-spring of the sentiments, on which alone time is found to have any influence.[4]
But it often happens that the title of first possession becomes unclear over time, and it's impossible to resolve many disputes that may arise regarding it. In that situation, long possession or prescription comes into play, giving a person valid ownership of anything they enjoy. The nature of human society doesn't allow for great precision, nor can we always trace back to the original source of things to determine their current state. A significant amount of time creates distance that makes objects seem less real, affecting our perception as if they never existed. A person's title, which is clear and certain now, may seem unclear and questionable fifty years later, even if the facts supporting it are proven with strong evidence. Those same facts don't hold the same weight after such a long period. This serves as a convincing argument for our earlier discussion about property and justice. Possession over a long duration conveys a title to any object. However, it's clear that while everything occurs over time, nothing real is created by time; thus, property, being shaped by time, is not something real within the objects but rather the product of the sentiments that give time any influence.
[4] Present possession is plainly a relation betwixt a person and an object; but is not sufficient to counter-ballance the relation of first possession, unless the former be long and uninterrupted: In which case the relation is encreased on the side of the present possession, by the extent of time, and diminished on that of first possession, by the distance, This change in the relation produces a consequent change in the property.
[4] Present possession is clearly a relationship between a person and an object; however, it isn't enough to outweigh the relationship of first possession unless the former is long-lasting and uninterrupted. In that case, the relationship is strengthened on the side of present possession due to the amount of time, while the first possession is weakened by the distance. This shift in the relationship leads to a corresponding change in property.
We acquire the property of objects by accession, when they are connected in an intimate manner with objects that are already our property, and at the same time are inferior to them. Thus the fruits of our garden, the offspring of our cattle, and the work of our slaves, are all of them esteemed our property, even before possession. Where objects are connected together in the imagination, they are apt to be put on the same footing, and are commonly supposed to be endowed with the same qualities. We readily pass from one to the other, and make no difference in our judgments concerning them; especially if the latter be inferior to the former.[5]
We gain ownership of objects through accession when they are closely connected to things we already own and are of lesser value. For example, the fruits from our garden, the young of our livestock, and the work done by our servants are all considered our property, even before we physically possess them. When objects are linked in our minds, we tend to treat them similarly and assume they share the same qualities. We easily transition from one to the other and don't differentiate in our opinions about them, especially if the latter is of lesser importance than the former. [5]
[5]
This source of property can never be explained but from the imaginations; and
one may affirm, that the causes are here unmixed. We shall proceed to explain
them more particularly, and illustrate them by examples from common life and
experience.
It has been observed above, that the mind has a natural propensity to join
relations, especially resembling ones, and finds a hind of fitness and
uniformity in such an union. From this propensity are derived these laws of
nature, that upon the first formation of society, property always follows the
present possession; and afterwards, that it arises from first or from long
possession. Now we may easily observe, that relation is not confined merely to
one degree; but that from an object, that is related to us, we acquire a
relation to every other object, which is related to it, and so on, till the
thought loses the chain by too long a progress, However the relation may weaken
by each remove, it is not immediately destroyed; but frequently connects two
objects by means of an intermediate one, which is related to both. And this
principle is of such force as to give rise to the right of accession, and
causes us to acquire the property not only of such objects as we are
immediately possessed of; but also of such as are closely connected with
them.
Suppose a German, a Frenchman, and a Spaniard to come into a room, where
there are placed upon the table three bottles of wine, Rhenish, Burgundy and
Port; and suppose they shoued fall a quarrelling about the division of them; a
person, who was chosen for umpire would naturally, to shew his impartiality,
give every one the product of his own country: And this from a principle,
which, in some measure, is the source of those laws of nature, that ascribe
property to occupation, prescription and accession.
In all these Cases, and particularly that of accession, there is first a
natural union betwixt the idea of the person and that of the object, and
afterwards a new and moral union produced by that right or property, which we
ascribe to the person. But here there occurs a difficulty, which merits our
attention, and may afford us an opportunity of putting to tryal that singular
method of reasoning, which has been employed on the present subject. I have
already observed that the imagination passes with greater facility from little
to great, than from great to littie, and that the transition of ideas is always
easier and smoother in the former case than in the latter. Now as the right of
accession arises from the easy transition of ideas, by which related objects
are connected together, it shoued naturally be imagined, that the right of
accession must encrease in strength, in proportion as the transition of ideas
is performed with greater facility. It may, therefore, be thought, that when we
have acquired the property of any small object, we shall readily consider any
great object related to it as an accession, and as belonging to the proprietor
of the small one; since the transition is in that case very easy from the small
object to the great one, and shoued connect them together in the closest
manner. But In fact the case is always found to be otherwise, The empire of
Great Britain seems to draw along with it the dominion of the Orkneys, the
Hebrides, the isle of Man, and the Isle of Wight; but the authority over those
lesser islands does not naturally imply any title to Great Britain. In short, a
small object naturally follows a great one as its accession; but a great one Is
never supposed to belong to the proprietor of a small one related to it, merely
on account of that property and relation. Yet in this latter case the
transition of ideas is smoother from the proprietor to the small object, which
is his property, and from the small object to the great one, than in the former
case from the proprietor to the great object, and from the great one to the
small. It may therefore be thought, that these phaenomena are objections to the
foregoing hypothesis, THAT THE ASCRIBING OF PROPERTY TO ACCESSION IS NOTHING
BUT AN AFFECT OF THE RELATIONS OF IDEAS, AND OF THE SMOOTH TRANSITION OF THE
IMAGINATION.
It will be easy to solve this objection, if we consider the agility and
unsteadiness of the imagination, with the different views, in which it is
continually placing its objects. When we attribute to a person a property in
two objects, we do not always pass from the person to one object, and from that
to the other related to it. The objects being here to be considered as the
property of the person, we are apt to join them together, and place them in the
same light. Suppose, therefore, a great and a small object to be related
together; if a person be strongly related to the great object, he will likewise
be strongly related to both the objects, considered together, because he Is
related to the most considerable part. On the contrary, if he be only related
to the small object, he will not be strongly related to both, considered
together, since his relation lies only with the most trivial part, which is not
apt to strike us in any great degree, when we consider the whole. And this Is
the reason, why small objects become accessions to great ones, and not great to
small.
It is the general opinion of philosophers and civilians, that the sea is
incapable of becoming the property of any nation; and that because it is
impossible to take possession of it, or form any such distinct relation with
it, as may be the foundation of property. Where this reason ceases, property
immediately takes place. Thus the most strenuous advocates for the liberty of
the seas universally allow, that friths and hays naturally belong as an
accession to the proprietors of the surrounding continent. These have properly
no more bond or union with the land, than the pacific ocean would have; but
having an union in the fancy, and being at the same time inferior, they are of
course regarded as an accession.
The property of rivers, by the laws of most nations, and by the natural
turn of our thought, Is attributed to the proprietors of their banks, excepting
such vast rivers as the Rhine or the Danube, which seem too large to the
imagination to follow as an accession the property of the neighbouring fields.
Yet even these rivers are considered as the property of that nation, thro'
whose dominions they run; the idea of a nation being of a suitable bulk to
correspond with them, and bear them such a relation in the fancy.
The accessions, which are made to lands bordering upon rivers, follow the
land, say the civilians, provided it be made by what they call alluvion, that
is, Insensibly and Imperceptibly; which are circumstances that mightily assist
the imagination in the conjunction. Where there Is any considerable portion
torn at once from one bank, and joined to another, it becomes not his property,
whose land it falls on, till it unite with the land, and till the trees or
plants have spread their roots into both. Before that, the imagination does not
sufficiently join them.
There are other cases, which somewhat resemble this of accession, but
which, at the bottom, are considerably different, and merit our attention. Of
this kind Is the conjunction of the properties of different persons, after such
a manner as not to admit of separation. The question is, to whom the united
mass must belong.
Where this conjunction is of such a nature as to admit of division, but not
of separation, the decision is natural and easy. The whole mass must be
supposed to be common betwixt the proprietors of the several parts, and
afterwards must be divided according to the proportions of these parts. But
here I cannot forbear taking notice of a remarkable subtilty of the Roman law,
in distinguishing betwixt confusion and commixtion. Confusion is an union of
two bodies, such as different liquors, where the parts become entirely
undistinguishable. Commixtion is the blending of two bodies, such as two
bushels of corn, where the parts remain separate in an obvious and visible
manner. As in the latter case the imagination discovers not so entire an union
as in the former, but is able to trace and preserve a distinct idea of the
property of each; this is the reason, why the civil law, tho' it established an
entire community in the case of confusion, and after that a proportional
division, yet in the case of commixtion, supposes each of the proprietors to
maintain a distinct right; however necessity may at last force them to submit
to the same division.
QUOD SI FRUMENTUM TITII FRUMENTO TUO MISTUM FUERIT: SIQUIDEM EX VOLUNTATE
VESTRA, COMMUNE EST: QUIA SINGULA CORPORA, ID EST, SINGULA GRANA, QUAE CUJUSQUE
PRO PRIA FUERUNT, EX CONSENSU VESTRO COMMUNICATA SUNT. QUOD SI CASU ID MISTUM
FUERIT, VEL TITIUS ID MISCUERIT SINE TUA VOLUNT ATE, NON VIDETUR ID COMMUNE
ESSE; QUIA SINGULA CORPORA IN SUA SUBSTANTIA DURANT. SED NEC MAGIS ISTIS
CASIBUS COMMUNE SIT FRUMENTUM QUAM GREX INTELLIGITUR ESSE CORN MUNIS, SI PECORA
TITII TUIS PECORIBUS MISTA FUERINT. SED SI AB ALTERUTRO VESTRUM TOTUM ID
FRUMENTUM RETINEATUR, IN REM QUIDEM ACTIO PRO MODO FRUMENTI CUJUSQUE CORN
PETIT. ARBITRIO AUTEM JUDICIS, UT IPSE AESTIMET QUALE CUJUSQUE FRUMENTUM
FUERIT. Inst. Lib. IL Tit. i. Sect 28.
(In the case that your grain was mixed with that of Titius, if it was done
voluntarily on the part of both of you, it is common property, inasmuch as the
individual items, i.e., the single grains, which were the peculiar property of
either of you, were combined with your joint consent. If, however, the mixture
was accidental, or if Titius mixed it without your consent, it does not appear
that it is common property, Inasmuch as the several components retain their
original identity. Rather, in circumstances of this sort the grain does not
become common property, any more than a herd of cattle is regarded as common
property, If Titius beasts should have become mixed up with yours.
However, if all of the aforesaid corn is kept by either of you, this gives
rise to a suit to determine the ownership of property, in respect of the amount
of corn belonging to each. It is in the discretion of the judge to determine
which is the corn belonging to either party.)
Where the properties of two persons are united after such a manner as
neither to admit of division nor separation, as when one builds a house on
another's ground, in that case, the whole must belong to one of the
proprietors: And here I assert, that it naturally is conceived to belong to the
proprietor of the most considerable part. For however the compound object may
have a relation to two different persons, and carry our view at once to both of
them, yet as the most considerable part principally engages our attention, and
by the strict union draws the inferior along it; for this reason, the whole
bears a relation to the proprietor of that part, and is regarded as his
property. The only difficulty is, what we shall be pleased to call the most
considerable part, and most attractive to the imagination.
This quality depends on several different circumstances, which have little
connexion with each other. One part of a compound object may become more
considerable than another, either because it is more constant and durable;
because it is of greater value; because it is more obvious and remarkable;
because it is of greater extent; or because its existence is more separate and
independent. It will be easy to conceive, that, as these circumstances may be
conjoined and opposed in all the different ways, and according to all the
different degrees, which can be imagined, there will result many cases, where
the reasons on both sides are so equally balanced, that it is impossible for us
to give any satisfactory decision. Here then is the proper business of
municipal laws, to fix what the principles of human nature have left
undetermined.
The superficies yields to the soil, says the civil law: The writing to the
paper: The canvas to the picture. These decisions do not well agree together,
and are a proof of the contrariety of those principles, from which they are
derived.
But of all the questions of this kind the most curious is that, which for
so many ages divided the disciples of Proculus and Sabinus. Suppose a person
shoued make a cup from the metal of another, or a ship from his wood, and
suppose the proprietor of the metal or wood shoued demand his goods, the
question is, whether he acquires a title to the cup or ship. Sabinus maintained
the affirmative, and asserted that the substance or matter is the foundation of
all the qualities; that it is incorruptible and immortal, and therefore
superior to the form, which is casual and dependent. On the other hand,
Proculus observed, that the form is the most obvious and remarkable part, and
that from it bodies are denominated of this or that particular species. To
which he might have added, that the matter or substance is in most bodies so
fluctuating and uncertain, that it is utterly impossible to trace it in all its
changes. For my part, I know not from what principles such a controversy can be
certainly determined. I shall therefore content my self with observing, that
the decision of Trebonian seems to me pretty ingenious; that the cup belongs to
the proprietor of the metal, because it can be brought back to its first form:
But that the ship belongs to the author of its form for a contrary reason. But
however ingenious this reason may seem, it plainly depends upon the fancy,
which by the possibility of such a reduction, finds a closer connexion and
relation betwixt a cup and the proprietor of its metal, than betwixt a ship and
the proprietor of its wood, where the substance is more fixed and unalterable.
[5]
The origin of property can only be explained by our imagination; one might argue that the causes are clear-cut here. We'll explain them in more detail and illustrate with examples from everyday life and experience.
It has been noted that the mind has a natural tendency to associate related things, especially those that are similar, and perceives some form of fit and uniformity in such connections. This tendency gives rise to the natural laws that state that when society first forms, property invariably follows current possession; later, it stems from either initial or prolonged possession. We can easily see that relation isn't limited to one degree; from an object related to us, we acquire a relation to every other object associated with it, and so on, until our thoughts lose the connection due to going too far. However, even though the relation may weaken with each step, it isn’t immediately broken; often, it connects two objects through an intermediary one that relates to both. This principle is powerful enough to give rise to the right of accession, allowing us to gain ownership not only of objects we directly possess but also of those closely connected to them.
Imagine a German, a Frenchman, and a Spaniard who enter a room with three bottles of wine on the table: Rhenish, Burgundy, and Port. If they start arguing about how to divide them, a chosen umpire would naturally, to demonstrate impartiality, give each person a bottle from their own country. This is based on a principle that is, in part, the foundation of those natural laws assigning property based on occupation, prescription, and accession.
In all these cases, especially concerning accession, there is first a natural connection between the person’s idea and that of the object, followed by a new moral connection created by the right or property attributed to that person. However, a difficulty arises here that deserves our attention and might give us a chance to test that unique reasoning method applied to this topic. I’ve already pointed out that the imagination moves more easily from small to large than from large to small, and the transition of ideas is always easier and smoother in the former case. Since the right of accession stems from the smooth transition of ideas linking related objects, one might naturally imagine that the right of accession strengthens as such transitions become easier. Therefore, when we acquire property in a small object, we might readily consider a larger object related to it as an accession, belonging to the owner of the small one; since the transition from the small object to the large one is very easy, it should connect them closely. But, in reality, it’s always found to be the opposite. The British Empire seems to include dominion over the Orkneys, the Hebrides, the Isle of Man, and the Isle of Wight; yet authority over these smaller islands does not automatically imply a claim to Great Britain. In summary, a small object naturally follows a larger one as an accession; but a large one is never assumed to belong to the owner of a related small one, solely because of that property and relation. Yet, in the latter case, the transition of ideas is smoother from the owner to the small object they possess, and from the small object to the large one, than in the former case from the owner to the large object and from the large object to the small one. Hence, these phenomena may seem to challenge the previous hypothesis, namely that the assignment of property to accession is merely an effect of the relations of ideas and the smooth transitions of imagination.
This objection can be easily addressed by considering the agility and inconsistency of the imagination, along with the different perspectives in which it continually views its objects. When we attribute property in two objects to a person, we don’t always transition from that person to one object and then to the other related object. Here, the objects are seen as the person's property, and we tend to merge them and view them as a whole. So, suppose a large and a small object are related; if a person has a strong relation to the larger object, they will also feel a strong connection to both objects viewed together, since they are tied to the more significant part. Conversely, if they're only related to the small object, they won't feel as strong a connection to both, since their relation lies only with the less significant part, which doesn't strike us as strongly when considering the whole. This explains why small objects become accessions to larger ones, but not the other way around.
It is widely believed by philosophers and legal experts that the sea cannot belong to any one nation because it is impossible to possess it or form a significant relationship with it as a foundation for property rights. Where this reason fails, property rights immediately apply. Thus, even strong advocates for freedom of the seas universally agree that coastal waters naturally belong as accessions to the owners of the adjacent land. These areas do not have more connection to the land than the peaceful ocean would; however, they are viewed as an accession due to the imaginative ties and their inferior status.
According to the laws of most nations and the instinctive logic of our thinking, rivers' properties are attributed to the owners of their banks, except for major rivers like the Rhine or Danube, which seem too large to be considered an accession to the property of adjacent fields. Yet, even these rivers are regarded as the property of the nation through whose territory they flow; as the concept of a nation is reasonably sized to correspond with them, bearing such a relationship in our imagination.
The additions made to lands next to rivers are considered as part of that land, say the legal experts, provided they occur through what they call alluvion, meaning gradually and imperceptibly; this greatly facilitates the imaginative connection. If a significant portion of land is suddenly torn from one bank and attached to another, it doesn’t belong to the owner of the land it falls on until it merges with the land and until the trees or plants have established their roots in both sides. Until then, the imagination does not sufficiently combine them.
There are other situations that resemble this accession case somewhat, but are fundamentally different and deserve attention. One such case is the combination of properties of different people in a way that does not allow for separation. The question arises as to whom the united mass belongs.
When this union can be divided yet not separated, the solution is clear and simple. The entire mass is presumed to be shared among the owners of the various parts and must later be split according to the proportion of these parts. Here, I must note an interesting subtlety in Roman law distinguishing between confusion and commixtion. Confusion is a union of two bodies, like different liquids, where the parts become entirely indistinguishable. Commixtion is the blending of two bodies, like two bushels of grain, where the parts remain clearly separate and visible. In the latter case, since the imagination does not perceive such a complete union as in the former, but can trace and maintain a distinct idea of each property, this is why civil law, while establishing a total community in confusion and later a proportional division, assumes that in commixtion, each owner retains a distinct right, although necessity may ultimately compel them to agree on the same division.
QUOD SI FRUMENTUM TITII FRUMENTO TUO MISTUM FUERIT: SIQUIDEM EX VOLUNTATE VESTRA, COMMUNE EST: QUIA SINGULA CORPORA, ID EST, SINGULA GRANA, QUAE CUJUSQUE PRO PRIA FUERUNT, EX CONSENSU VESTRO COMMUNICATA SUNT. QUOD SI CASU ID MISTUM FUERIT, VEL TITIUS ID MISCUERIT SINE TUA VOLUNT ATE, NON VIDETUR ID COMMUNE ESSE; QUIA SINGULA CORPORA IN SUA SUBSTANTIA DURANT. SED NEC MAGIS ISTIS CASIBUS COMMUNE SIT FRUMENTUM QUAM GREX INTELLIGITUR ESSE CORN MUNIS, SI PECORA TITII TUIS PECORIBUS MISTA FUERINT. SED SI AB ALTERUTRO VESTRUM TOTUM ID FRUMENTUM RETINEATUR, IN REM QUIDEM ACTIO PRO MODO FRUMENTI CUJUSQUE CORN PETIT. ARBITRIO AUTEM JUDICIS, UT IPSE AESTIMET QUALE CUJUSQUE FRUMENTUM FUERIT. Inst. Lib. IL Tit. i. Sect 28.
(In the case that your grain was mixed with that of Titius, if it was done voluntarily by both of you, it is common property, as the individual items, that is, the single grains, which were each of your property, were combined with your joint consent. If, however, the mixing was accidental or if Titius mixed it without your consent, it does not appear to be common property, since the several components retain their original identity. Thus, in circumstances like this, the grain does not benefit from common ownership, just as a herd of cattle is not considered common property if Titius's livestock were to become mixed in with yours.
However, if all of the above grains are kept by either of you, this gives rise to a suit to determine ownership concerning the amount of corn each is entitled to. The judge has the discretion to decide which is the grain belonging to each party.)
When the properties of two people are united in such a way that neither division nor separation is possible, such as when someone builds a house on someone else's land, then the whole must belong to one of the owners. I assert that it is naturally understood to belong to the owner of the most significant part. For although the combined object relates to two different people and draws our attention to both, the most significant part primarily engages our attention, tying the lesser part to it; for this reason, the whole is related to the owner of that part and is regarded as their property. The only question is what we should consider the most significant part that captures our imagination.
This quality depends on various circumstances that don’t have much connection to each other. One part of a composite object might be more significant than another either because it's more constant and durable, more valuable, more visible and remarkable, larger, or because its existence is more distinct and independent. It’s easy to see that, since these circumstances can be combined and contrasted in various ways, many cases will arise where the arguments on both sides are so evenly matched that it becomes impossible to reach a satisfactory conclusion. Here then lies the true work of municipal laws: to establish what the principles of human nature leave indeterminate.
The law states that the surface yields to the soil, writing yields to paper, and the canvas yields to the painting. These rulings do not cohere well and illustrate the conflict in the principles from which they derive.
However, of all the questions of this nature, the most intriguing is the one that has divided the followers of Proculus and Sabinus for many ages. Imagine someone made a cup from another person's metal, or a ship from someone's wood; if the owner of the metal or wood demands their goods, the question arises whether they gain ownership of the cup or the ship. Sabinus maintained that they should, arguing that the substance or material is the foundation of all qualities; it is eternal and unchanging, thus superior to the form, which is incidental and dependent. Conversely, Proculus claimed that the form is the most evident and notable aspect, and it is this that defines objects as belonging to one species or another. He might have added that the material or substance in most objects is so variable and uncertain that it is impossible to trace it through all its changes. For my part, I don't know on what grounds such a debate can be satisfactorily resolved. I will simply note that Trebonian's decision seems quite clever; the cup belongs to the owner of the metal because it can be reverted to its original form, while the ship belongs to its creator for the opposite reason. However, no matter how clever this reasoning may seem, it clearly relies on the imagination, which, due to the possibility of such a restoration, finds a closer connection and link between a cup and the owner of its metal than between a ship and the owner of its wood, where the substance is more stable and unchanging.
The right of succession is a very natural one, from the presumed consent of the parent or near relation, and from the general interest of mankind, which requires, that men's possessions should pass to those, who are dearest to them, in order to render them more industrious and frugal. Perhaps these causes are seconded by the influence of relation, or the association of ideas, by which we are naturally directed to consider the son after the parent's decease, and ascribe to him a title to his father's possessions. Those goods must become the property of some body: But of whom is the question. Here it is evident the persons children naturally present themselves to the mind; and being already. connected to those possessions by means of their deceased parent, we are apt to connect them still farther by the relation of property. Of this there are many parallel instances.[6]
The right of succession is a very natural one, based on the presumed consent of the parent or close relative, and the general interest of humanity, which suggests that people's possessions should go to those who are closest to them to encourage them to work harder and be more responsible. These reasons are likely supported by the bonds of family and the way we naturally think about inheritance, where we consider the son after the parent's death and feel he has a claim to his father's belongings. Those assets must belong to someone: but to whom? It’s clear that children come to mind, and since they are already connected to those possessions through their deceased parent, we tend to further associate them with the ownership of those assets. There are many similar examples. [6]
[6] In examining the different titles to authority in government, we shall meet with many reasons to convince us, that the right of succession depends, in a great measure on the imagination. Mean while I shall rest contented with observing one example, which belongs to the present subject. Suppose that a person die without children, and that a dispute arises among his relations concerning his inheritance; it is evident, that if his riches be deriv'd partly from his father, partly from his mother, the most natural way of determining such a dispute, is, to divide his possessions, and assign each part to the family, from whence it is deriv'd. Now as the person is suppos'd to have been once the full and entire proprietor of those goods; I ask, what is it makes us find a certain equity and natural reason in this partition, except it be the imagination? His affection to these families does not depend upon his possessions; for which reason his consent can never be presum'd precisely for such a partition. And as to the public interest, it seems not to be in the least concern'd on the one side or the other.
[6] In looking at the different claims to authority in government, we'll find many reasons that suggest the right of succession is largely based on perception. For now, I’ll focus on one example that relates to this topic. Imagine a person dies without children, and a dispute arises among their relatives over the inheritance; it's clear that if their wealth comes partly from their father and partly from their mother, the most straightforward way to resolve the dispute is to split their assets and give each part to the family from which it originated. Since the person is thought to have been the sole owner of those goods, I ask, what gives us the sense of fairness and reason in this division, if not our imagination? Their attachment to these families isn’t tied to their wealth; therefore, we can’t assume their consent for such a division. And regarding the public interest, it seems completely unaffected either way.
SECT. IV OF THE TRANSFERENCE OF PROPERTY BY CONSENT
However useful, or even necessary, the stability of possession may be to human society, it is attended with very considerable inconveniences. The relation of fitness or suitableness ought never to enter into consideration, in distributing the properties of mankind; but we must govern ourselves by rules, which are more general in their application, and more free from doubt and uncertainty. Of this kind is present possession upon the first establishment of society; and afterwards occupation, prescription, accession, and succession. As these depend very much on chance, they must frequently prove contradictory both to men's wants and desires; and persons and possessions must often be very ill adjusted. This is a grand inconvenience, which calls for a remedy. To apply one directly, and allow every man to seize by violence what he judges to be fit for him, would destroy society; and therefore the rules of justice seek some medium betwixt a rigid stability, and this changeable and uncertain adjustment. But there is no medium better than that obvious one, that possession and property should always be stable, except when the proprietor consents to bestow them on some other person. This rule can have no ill consequence, in occasioning wars and dissentions; since the proprietor's consent, who alone is concerned, is taken along in the alienation: And it may serve to many good purposes in adjusting property to persons. Different parts of the earth produce different commodities; and not only so, but different men both are by nature fitted for different employments, and attain to greater perfection in any one, when they confine themselves to it alone. All this requires a mutual exchange and commerce; for which reason the translation of property by consent is founded on a law of nature, as well as its stability without such a consent.
While the stability of ownership is beneficial, or even essential, for society, it comes with significant drawbacks. The idea of what is suitable or appropriate should never factor into how we distribute property among people; instead, we should follow broader and more certain principles. Initially, possession at the founding of society and later forms like occupation, prescription, accession, and succession are examples of these principles. Because these rely heavily on chance, they often conflict with people's needs and desires, leading to mismatches between individuals and theirproperties. This is a major issue that needs to be addressed. If we simply allowed anyone to take by force what they believe they deserve, it would undermine society. Therefore, justice aims to find a balance between strict stability and the unpredictable nature of property distribution. A clear solution is that possession and ownership should remain stable, except when the owner willingly transfers them to someone else. This rule won't lead to wars or conflicts since the owner's consent, which is crucial, is included in the transfer. It can also help align property with individuals effectively. Different regions produce various goods, and people have a natural inclination towards specific jobs and achieve greater expertise by focusing solely on them. This necessitates mutual exchange and interaction, which is why the consensual transfer of property aligns with natural law, just as the stability of property does without consent.
So far is determined by a plain utility and interest. But perhaps it is from more trivial reasons, that delivery, or a sensible transference of the object is commonly required by civil laws, and also by the laws of nature, according to most authors, as a requisite circumstance in the translation of property. The property of an object, when taken for something real, without any reference to morality, or the sentiments of the mind, is a quality perfectly insensible, and even inconceivable; nor can we form any distinct notion, either of its stability or translation. This imperfection of our ideas is less sensibly felt with regard to its stability, as it engages less our attention, and is easily past over by the mind, without any scrupulous examination. But as the translation of property from one person to another is a more remarkable event, the defect of our ideas becomes more sensible on that occasion, and obliges us to turn ourselves on every side in search of some remedy. Now as nothing more enlivens any idea than a present impression, and a relation betwixt that impression and the idea; it is natural for us to seek some false light from this quarter. In order to aid the imagination in conceiving the transference of property, we take the sensible object, and actually transfer its possession to the person, on whom we would bestow the property. The supposed resemblance of the actions, and the presence of this sensible delivery, deceive the mind, and make it fancy, that it conceives the mysterious transition of the property. And that this explication of the matter is just, appears hence, that men have invented a symbolical delivery, to satisfy the fancy, where the real one is impracticable. Thus the giving the keys of a granary is understood to be the delivery of the corn contained in it: The giving of stone and earth represents the delivery of a manor. This is a kind of superstitious practice in civil laws, and in the laws of nature, resembling the Roman catholic superstitions in religion. As the Roman catholics represent the inconceivable mysteries of the Christian religion, and render them more present to the mind, by a taper, or habit, or grimace, which is supposed to resemble them; so lawyers and moralists have run into like inventions for the same reason, and have endeavoured by those means to satisfy themselves concerning the transference of property by consent.
So far, this is determined by basic utility and interest. But maybe it’s for more trivial reasons that the transfer or a clear act of giving the object is usually required by civil laws, and also by natural laws, according to most authors, as a necessary part of transferring property. The ownership of an object, when seen as something real, without any connection to morality or feelings, is a quality that is completely unnoticeable and even hard to grasp; we can’t form a clear understanding of its stability or transfer. This limitation in our understanding is less noticeable regarding its stability, as it catches our attention less and is easily overlooked by the mind without any deep investigation. However, since the transfer of property from one person to another is a more noticeable event, the flaws in our understanding become more apparent then and push us to look around for some solution. Since nothing enlivens an idea more than a current impression and a connection between that impression and the idea, it's natural for us to seek some misleading clarity from this direction. To help our imagination understand the transfer of property, we take the actual object and physically give its possession to the person we want to grant the property to. The supposed similarity of the actions and the presence of this physical transfer trick the mind and make it think that it understands the mysterious change of ownership. This explanation seems valid since people have created symbolic acts of delivery to satisfy the imagination when the real ones are impractical. For example, giving the keys to a granary is understood as delivering the grain inside it; giving stone and dirt represents the transfer of a manor. This is a kind of superstitious practice in civil laws and natural laws, similar to Roman Catholic superstitions in religion. Just as Roman Catholics represent the incomprehensible mysteries of Christianity and make them more tangible with candles, clothing, or gestures believed to resemble them, lawyers and moralists have come up with similar inventions for the same reasons, striving to satisfy themselves regarding the transfer of property through consent.
SECT. V OF THE OBLIGATION OF PROMISES
That the rule of morality, which enjoins the performance of promises, is not natural, will sufficiently appear from these two propositions, which I proceed to prove, viz, that a promise would not be intelligible, before human conventions had established it; and that even if it were intelligible, it would not be attended with any moral obligation.
That the rule of morality that requires us to keep our promises isn’t natural becomes clear from these two points, which I’m about to prove: first, that a promise wouldn’t make sense before human agreements established it; and second, that even if it did make sense, it wouldn’t carry any moral obligation.
I say, first, that a promise is not intelligible naturally, nor antecedent to human conventions; and that a man, unacquainted with society, could never enter into any engagements with another, even though they could perceive each other's thoughts by intuition. If promises be natural and intelligible, there must be some act of the mind attending these words, I promise; and on this act of the mind must the obligation depend. Let us, therefore, run over all the faculties of the soul, and see which of them is exerted in our promises.
I first want to say that a promise isn’t something that’s naturally understood or exists before human agreements; a person who doesn’t know society wouldn’t be able to make any commitments with someone else, even if they could instinctively understand each other’s thoughts. If promises were natural and clear, there would have to be some mental process behind the words, “I promise,” and that mental process is what the obligation is based on. So, let's go through all the mental faculties and see which one is involved when we make promises.
The act of the mind, exprest by a promise, is not a resolution to perform any thing: For that alone never imposes any obligation. Nor is it a desire of such a performance: For we may bind ourselves without such a desire, or even with an aversion, declared and avowed. Neither is it the willing of that action, which we promise to perform: For a promise always regards some future time, and the will has an influence only on present actions. It follows, therefore, that since the act of the mind, which enters into a promise, and produces its obligation, is neither the resolving, desiring, nor willing any particular performance, it must necessarily be the willing of that obligation, which arises from the promise. Nor is this only a conclusion of philosophy; but is entirely conformable to our common ways of thinking and of expressing ourselves, when we say that we are bound by our own consent, and that the obligation arises from our mere will and pleasure. The only question then is, whether there be not a manifest absurdity in supposing this act of the mind, and such an absurdity as no man could fall into, whose ideas are not confounded with prejudice and the fallacious use of language.
The act of the mind expressed by a promise isn’t just a decision to do something because that alone doesn't create any obligation. It's also not a desire for that action since we can commit to things without wanting to or even when we actively dislike them. It isn't simply wanting to do what we promise either because a promise always refers to the future, while our will only affects what we do in the present. Therefore, since the act of the mind involved in a promise that creates an obligation isn't just deciding, desiring, or wanting a specific action, it must be the willingness to accept the obligation that comes from the promise. This isn't just a philosophical idea; it aligns perfectly with how we usually think and speak when we say that we are obliged by our own consent, and that the obligation comes from our own will and choice. The only real question is whether it's absurd to think this way, and that kind of absurdity seems impossible for anyone whose ideas aren’t clouded by bias and misleading language.
All morality depends upon our sentiments; and when any action, or quality of the mind, pleases us after a certain manner, we say it is virtuous; and when the neglect, or nonperformance of it, displeases us after a like manner, we say that we lie under an obligation to perform it. A change of the obligation supposes a change of the sentiment; and a creation of a new obligation supposes some new sentiment to arise. But it is certain we can naturally no more change our own sentiments, than the motions of the heavens; nor by a single act of our will, that is, by a promise, render any action agreeable or disagreeable, moral or immoral; which, without that act, would have produced contrary impressions, or have been endowed with different qualities. It would be absurd, therefore, to will any new obligation, that is, any new sentiment of pain or pleasure; nor is it possible, that men could naturally fall into so gross an absurdity. A promise, therefore, is naturally something altogether unintelligible, nor is there any act of the mind belonging to it.[7]
All morality is based on our feelings; when an action or a certain quality of the mind makes us feel good in a particular way, we call it virtuous. When failing to do it or neglecting it makes us feel bad in a similar way, we say we have a duty to do it. Changing that duty means changing how we feel about it, and creating a new duty means a new feeling must arise. However, it's clear that we can't naturally change our own feelings any more than we can change the movements of the heavens. Nor can we, with a simple act of will, like making a promise, make an action feel good or bad, moral or immoral, if without that act it would have elicited opposite feelings or had different traits. So, it would be unreasonable to create any new duty, meaning any new feeling of pleasure or pain; and it's impossible for people to naturally fall into such a blatant absurdity. Therefore, a promise is inherently something completely unintelligible, and there’s no mental act associated with it.[7]
[7]
Were morality discoverable by reason, and not by sentiment, it would be still
more evident, that promises cou'd make no alteration upon it. Morality is
suppos'd to consist in relation. Every new imposition of morality, therefore,
must arise from some new relation of objects; and consequently the will could
not produce immediately any change in morals, but cou'd have that effect only
by producing a change upon the objects. But as the moral obligation of a
promise is the pure effect of the will, without the least change in any part of
the universe; it follows, that promises have no natural obligation.
Shou'd it be said, that this act of the will being in effect a new object,
produces new relations and new duties; I wou'd answer, that this is a pure
sophism, which may be detected by a very moderate share of accuracy and
exactness. To will a new obligation, is to will a new relation of objects; and
therefore, if this new relation of objects were form'd by the volition itself,
we should in effect will the volition; which is plainly absurd and impossible.
The will has here no object to which it cou'd tend; but must return upon itself
in infinitum. The new obligation depends upon new relations. The new relations
depend upon a new volition. The new volition has for object a new obligation,
and consequently new relations, and consequently a new volition; which volition
again has in view a new obligation, relation and volition, without any
termination. It is impossible, therefore, we cou'd ever will a new obligation;
and consequently it is impossible the will cou'd ever accompany a promise, or
produce a new obligation of morality.
[7]
If morality could be understood through reason instead of sentiment, it would be even clearer that promises wouldn’t change it at all. Morality is thought to be based on relationships. Therefore, any new imposition of morality must come from a new relationship between objects; as a result, the will cannot directly change morals, but can only do so by changing the objects involved. However, since the moral obligation of a promise is solely the result of the will, without any change in the universe, it follows that promises lack any natural obligation.
If someone argues that this act of will, being a new object, creates new relationships and new duties, I would respond that this is simply a fallacy that can be uncovered with a bit of accuracy and precision. To will a new obligation means to will a new relationship of objects; therefore, if this new relationship were created by the will itself, we would essentially be willing the will, which is clearly absurd and impossible. The will lacks any object to which it could direct itself and must turn back on itself endlessly. The new obligation depends on new relationships. The new relationships depend on a new will. The new will has as its object a new obligation, which results in new relationships, and then in a new will; this new will then aims at a new obligation, relationship, and will, without any end. It is therefore impossible for us to will a new obligation; consequently, it is impossible for the will to ever accompany a promise or create a new moral obligation.
But, secondly, if there was any act of the mind belonging to it, it could not naturally produce any obligation. This appears evidently from the foregoing reasoning. A promise creates a new obligation. A new obligation supposes new sentiments to arise. The will never creates new sentiments. There could not naturally, therefore, arise any obligation from a promise, even supposing the mind could fall into the absurdity of willing that obligation.
But, secondly, if there was any mental action involved, it couldn’t naturally create any obligation. This is clear from the reasoning above. A promise creates a new obligation. A new obligation assumes that new feelings emerge. The will doesn’t create new feelings. Therefore, no obligation could naturally arise from a promise, even if the mind could absurdly will that obligation.
The same truth may be proved still more evidently by that reasoning, which proved justice in general to be an artificial virtue. No action can be required of us as our duty, unless there be implanted in human nature some actuating passion or motive, capable of producing the action. This motive cannot be the sense of duty. A sense of duty supposes an antecedent obligation: And where an action is not required by any natural passion, it cannot be required by any natural obligation; since it may be omitted without proving any defect or imperfection in the mind and temper, and consequently without any vice. Now it is evident we have no motive leading us to the performance of promises, distinct from a sense of duty. If we thought, that promises had no moral obligation, we never should feel any inclination to observe them. This is not the case with the natural virtues. Though there was no obligation to relieve the miserable, our humanity would lead us to it; and when we omit that duty, the immorality of the omission arises from its being a proof, that we want the natural sentiments of humanity. A father knows it to be his duty to take care of his children: But he has also a natural inclination to it. And if no human creature had that inclination, no one could lie under any such obligation. But as there is naturally no inclination to observe promises, distinct from a sense of their obligation; it follows, that fidelity is no natural virtue, and that promises have no force, antecedent to human conventions.
The same truth can be demonstrated even more clearly through the reasoning that established justice as an artificial virtue. No action can be required of us as our duty unless there is a passion or motive embedded in human nature that can drive us to take that action. This motive cannot be a sense of duty. A sense of duty assumes an existing obligation: and if an action isn't required by any natural passion, it can't be mandated by any natural obligation, since we could skip it without indicating any flaw or imperfection in our mind and temperament, and therefore without any vice. It is clear that we have no motive that pushes us to fulfill promises apart from a sense of duty. If we believed that promises had no moral obligation, we would never feel inclined to keep them. This isn't the case with natural virtues. Even if there were no obligation to help the suffering, our humanity would still lead us to do so; and when we fail in that duty, the immorality of that failure comes from the fact that we lack the natural feelings of humanity. A father knows it’s his duty to care for his children, but he also has a natural inclination to do so. If no human had that inclination, no one would be under any such obligation. But since there is no natural inclination to keep promises distinct from a sense of their obligation, it follows that fidelity is not a natural virtue, and that promises have no power other than what is established by human agreements.
If any one dissent from this, he must give a regular proof of these two propositions, viz. THAT THERE IS A PECULIAR ACT OF THE MIND, ANNEXT TO PROMISES; AND THAT CONSEQUENT TO THIS ACT OF THE MIND, THERE ARISES AN INCLINATION TO PERFORM, DISTINCT FROM A SENSE OF DUTY. I presume, that it is impossible to prove either of these two points; and therefore I venture to conclude that promises are human inventions, founded on the necessities and interests of society.
If anyone disagrees with this, they need to provide clear evidence for these two claims: FIRST, THAT THERE IS A UNIQUE MENTAL ACT LINKED TO PROMISES; AND SECOND, THAT FOLLOWING THIS MENTAL ACT, THERE IS A DESIRE TO FULFILL IT, SEPARATE FROM A SENSE OF DUTY. I believe it’s impossible to prove either of these points; thus, I conclude that promises are human creations based on the needs and interests of society.
In order to discover these necessities and interests, we must consider the same qualities of human nature, which we have already found to give rise to the preceding laws of society. Men being naturally selfish, or endowed only with a confined generosity, they are not easily induced to perform any action for the interest of strangers, except with a view to some reciprocal advantage, which they had no hope of obtaining but by such a performance. Now as it frequently happens, that these mutual performances cannot be finished at the same instant, it is necessary, that one party be contented to remain in uncertainty, and depend upon the gratitude of the other for a return of kindness. But so much corruption is there among men, that, generally speaking, this becomes but a slender security; and as the benefactor is here supposed to bestow his favours with a view to self-interest, this both takes off from the obligation, and sets an example to selfishness, which is the true mother of ingratitude. Were we, therefore, to follow the natural course of our passions and inclinations, we should perform but few actions for the advantage of others, from distinterested views; because we are naturally very limited in our kindness and affection: And we should perform as few of that kind, out of a regard to interest; because we cannot depend upon their gratitude. Here then is the mutual commerce of good offices in a manner lost among mankind, and every one reduced to his own skill and industry for his well-being and subsistence. The invention of the law of nature, concerning the stability of possession, has already rendered men tolerable to each other; that of the transference of property and possession by consent has begun to render them mutually advantageous: But still these laws of nature, however strictly observed, are not sufficient to render them so serviceable to each other, as by nature they are fitted to become. Though possession be stable, men may often reap but small advantage from it, while they are possessed of a greater quantity of any species of goods than they have occasion for, and at the same time suffer by the want of others. The transference of property, which is the proper remedy for this inconvenience, cannot remedy it entirely; because it can only take place with regard to such objects as are present and individual, but not to such as are absent or general. One cannot transfer the property of a particular house, twenty leagues distant; because the consent cannot be attended with delivery, which is a requisite circumstance. Neither can one transfer the property of ten bushels of corn, or five hogsheads of wine, by the mere expression and consent; because these are only general terms, and have no direct relation to any particular heap of corn, or barrels of wine. Besides, the commerce of mankind is not confined to the barter of commodities, but may extend to services and actions, which we may exchange to our mutual interest and advantage. Your corn is ripe to-day; mine will be so tomorrow. It is profitable for us both, that I should labour with you to-day, and that you should aid me to-morrow. I have no kindness for you, and know you have as little for me. I will not, therefore, take any pains upon your account; and should I labour with you upon my own account, in expectation of a return, I know I should be disappointed, and that I should in vain depend upon your gratitude. Here then I leave you to labour alone: You treat me in the same manner. The seasons change; and both of us lose our harvests for want of mutual confidence and security.
To find these necessities and interests, we need to look at the same aspects of human nature that have led to the laws of society we've discussed before. Since people are naturally selfish or have limited generosity, they aren't easily motivated to do good for strangers unless they expect some benefit in return, which they can only gain by taking such actions. Often, these mutual actions can't happen at the same time, so one party has to accept uncertainty and rely on the other's gratitude for a return favor. However, human nature is so flawed that this often provides little security; if the person helping is acting out of self-interest, it reduces the obligation to return that kindness and promotes the selfishness that leads to ingratitude. If we were to follow our natural inclinations, we'd do very few things for others' benefit without expecting something in return, since our kindness and affection are inherently limited. And we'd do just as few for self-interested reasons because we can’t count on their gratitude. This is where the exchange of good deeds breaks down among people, leaving everyone to rely on their own skills and efforts for their own well-being. The idea of natural law regarding the stability of possession has made people somewhat bearable to each other; the law of transferring property and possessions by consent has started to make exchanges mutually beneficial. However, even with these natural laws in place, they aren’t enough to make people as helpful to each other as they could be. While possession might be stable, individuals often gain little from it when they have more goods than they actually need and simultaneously lack other important items. The transfer of property, which could fix this issue, can't completely solve it because it can only happen with specific items that are present but not with those that are absent or general. You can't transfer the ownership of a specific house that's twenty leagues away because the necessary delivery can’t occur. You also can't transfer ownership of ten bushels of corn or five hogsheads of wine just by saying so, since those are general terms and don’t relate directly to any specific items. Moreover, human exchange isn’t just about trading goods; it can also involve services and actions that benefit both parties. For example, your corn is ready today, and mine will be ready tomorrow. It's in our mutual interest for me to help you today, and for you to help me tomorrow. I don’t have any affection for you, and I know you feel the same way about me. Therefore, I have no motivation to work for your benefit. If I do work for my benefit in hopes of getting something in return, I know I’ll be let down and that depending on your gratitude is pointless. So, I’ll leave you to work alone, and you’ll do the same to me. As the seasons change, we both lose our harvests due to a lack of mutual trust and security.
All this is the effect of the natural and inherent principles and passions of human nature; and as these passions and principles are inalterable, it may be thought, that our conduct, which depends on them, must be so too, and that it would be in vain, either for moralists or politicians, to tamper with us, or attempt to change the usual course of our actions, with a view to public interest. And indeed, did the success of their designs depend upon their success in correcting the selfishness and ingratitude of men, they would never make any progress, unless aided by omnipotence, which is alone able to new-mould the human mind, and change its character in such fundamental articles. All they can pretend to, is, to give a new direction to those natural passions, and teach us that we can better satisfy our appetites in an oblique and artificial manner, than by their headlong and impetuous motion. Hence I learn to do a service to another, without bearing him any real kindness; because I forsee, that he will return my service, in expectation of another of the same kind, and in order to maintain the same correspondence of good offices with me or with others. And accordingly, after I have served him, and he is in possession of the advantage arising from my action, he is induced to perform his part, as foreseeing the consequences of his refusal.
All of this stems from the natural and inherent principles and emotions of human nature. Since these emotions and principles don’t change, it can be assumed that our behavior, which relies on them, won’t change either. It would be pointless for moralists or politicians to try to mess with us or change the usual way we act for the sake of the public good. In fact, if their success depended on changing the selfishness and ingratitude of people, they’d never make any headway unless helped by an omnipotent force that alone can reshape the human mind and alter its core traits. All they can hope to do is redirect these natural emotions and show us that we can better satisfy our desires in an indirect and artificial way instead of in a reckless and impulsive manner. This is why I learn to do someone a favor without actually caring for them, because I know they’ll return the favor, expecting me to do the same thing again, and to keep that exchange of good deeds going. So, after I’ve helped them and they benefit from my action, they feel compelled to reciprocate, knowing what will happen if they don’t.
But though this self-interested commerce of man begins to take place, and to predominate in society, it does not entirely abolish the more generous and noble intercourse of friendship and good offices. I may still do services to such persons as I love, and am more particularly acquainted with, without any prospect of advantage; and they may make me a return in the same manner, without any view but that of recompensing my past services. In order, therefore, to distinguish those two different sorts of commerce, the interested and the disinterested, there is a certain form of words invented for the former, by which we bind ourselves to the performance of any action. This form of words constitutes what we call a promise, which is the sanction of the interested commerce of mankind. When a man says he promises any thing, he in effect expresses a resolution of performing it; and along with that, by making use of this form of words, subjects himself to the penalty of never being trusted again in case of failure. A resolution is the natural act of the mind, which promises express: But were there no more than a resolution in the case, promises would only declare our former motives, and would not create any new motive or obligation. They are the conventions of men, which create a new motive, when experience has taught us, that human affairs would be conducted much more for mutual advantage, were there certain symbols or signs instituted, by which we might give each, other security of our conduct in any particular incident, After these signs are instituted, whoever uses them is immediately bound by his interest to execute his engagements, and must never expect to be trusted any more, if he refuse to perform what he promised.
But even though this self-serving trade among people is starting to happen and become dominant in society, it doesn't completely eliminate the more generous and noble exchanges of friendship and goodwill. I can still do favors for people I care about and know well, without expecting anything in return; and they can return the favor in the same way, with no intention other than to repay my previous kindnesses. To differentiate these two types of exchanges—the self-interested and the selfless—there's a specific phrase created for the former, which binds us to the performance of an action. This phrase is what we call a promise, which acts as the foundation for the self-interested interactions among people. When someone says they promise something, they're essentially stating their intention to follow through, and by using this phrase, they make themselves liable to the consequence of losing trust if they fail. An intention is a natural mental act, which promises express: but if it were only an intention, promises would simply reflect our past motivations and wouldn't create any new motives or obligations. They are agreements among people that generate a new motive when experience has shown us that human affairs would be managed much better for everyone's benefit if we had certain symbols or signs that assured us of each other's reliability in specific situations. Once these signs are established, anyone who uses them is immediately compelled by their own interests to fulfill their commitments and can never expect to be trusted again if they fail to deliver on what they promised.
Nor is that knowledge, which is requisite to make mankind sensible of this interest in the institution and observance of promises, to be esteemed superior to the capacity of human nature, however savage and uncultivated. There needs but a very little practice of the world, to make us perceive all these consequences and advantages. The shortest experience of society discovers them to every mortal; and when each individual perceives the same sense of interest in all his fellows, he immediately performs his part of any contract, as being assured, that they will not be wanting in theirs. All of them, by concert, enter into a scheme of actions, calculated for common benefit, and agree to be true to their word; nor is there any thing requisite to form this concert or convention, but that every one have a sense of interest in the faithful fulfilling of engagements, and express that sense to other members of the society. This immediately causes that interest to operate upon them; and interest is the first obligation to the performance of promises.
Also, the understanding needed for people to realize the importance of making and keeping promises isn't beyond human nature, no matter how rough or unrefined. It only takes a little bit of real-world experience for us to recognize all these outcomes and benefits. Just a brief experience in society reveals them to everyone; and when individuals see the same sense of interest in all those around them, they naturally fulfill their part of any agreement, confident that others will do the same. Together, they engage in a plan of actions aimed at mutual benefit and agree to keep their word; all that's needed to establish this agreement is that each person understands the importance of fulfilling their commitments and communicates that understanding to others in the community. This immediately prompts that interest to take effect on them; and interest is the primary reason for honoring promises.
Afterwards a sentiment of morals concurs with interest, and becomes a new obligation upon mankind. This sentiment of morality, in the performance of promises, arises from the same principles as that in the abstinence from the property of others. Public interest, education, and the artifices of politicians, have the same effect in both cases. The difficulties, that occur to us, in supposing a moral obligation to attend promises, we either surmount or elude. For instance; the expression of a resolution is not commonly supposed to be obligatory; and we cannot readily conceive how the making use of a certain form of words should be able to cause any material difference. Here, therefore, we feign a new act of the mind, which we call the willing an obligation; and on this we suppose the morality to depend. But we have proved already, that there is no such act of the mind, and consequently that promises impose no natural obligation.
Afterward, a sense of morals aligns with self-interest, creating a new obligation for humanity. This sense of morality in keeping promises comes from the same principles as refraining from taking what's not ours. Public interest, education, and political tactics have the same influence in both situations. The challenges we face in thinking of a moral obligation to keep promises are ones we either overcome or sidestep. For example, the statement of intent is usually not seen as binding, and we can't easily understand how using a specific set of words could make any real difference. So, we pretend there’s a new mental act we call the willing of an obligation, and on that, we think the morality depends. However, we have already shown that there is no such mental act, and therefore promises don't create any natural obligation.
To confirm this, we may subjoin some other reflections concerning that will, which is supposed to enter into a promise, and to cause its obligation. It is evident, that the will alone is never supposed to cause the obligation, but must be expressed by words or signs, in order to impose a tye upon any man. The expression being once brought in as subservient to the will, soon becomes the principal part of the promise; nor will a man be less bound by his word, though he secretly give a different direction to his intention, and with-hold himself both from a resolution, and from willing an obligation. But though the expression makes on most occasions the whole of the promise, yet it does not always so; and one, who should make use of any expression, of which he knows not the meaning, and which he uses without any intention of binding himself, would not certainly be bound by it. Nay, though he knows its meaning, yet if he uses it in jest only, and with such signs as shew evidently he has no serious intention of binding himself, he would not lie under any obligation of performance; but it is necessary, that the words be a perfect expression of the will, without any contrary signs. Nay, even this we must not carry so far as to imagine, that one, whom, by our quickness of understanding, we conjecture, from certain signs, to have an intention of deceiving us, is not bound by his expression or verbal promise, if we accept of it; but must limit this conclusion to those cases, where the signs are of a different kind from those of deceit. All these contradictions are easily accounted for, if the obligation of promises be merely a human invention for the convenience of society; but will never be explained, if it be something real and natural, arising from any action of the mind or body.
To confirm this, we can add some thoughts about the will, which is believed to be involved in a promise and creates its obligation. It's clear that the will alone doesn't create the obligation; it needs to be communicated through words or signs to impose a requirement on anyone. Once the expression is introduced as a way to convey the will, it quickly becomes the core of the promise; a person is still bound by their word, even if they secretly intend something different and refrain from making a definite decision or feeling obliged. However, while the expression usually forms the entire promise, that's not always the case. Someone who uses an expression they don't understand and without any intention of being bound by it definitely wouldn't be obligated. Moreover, even if they do understand its meaning but use it just as a joke, signaling clearly that they have no serious intent to commit, they wouldn't be under any obligation to follow through. The words must perfectly reflect the will without any contradictory signs. But we shouldn't stretch this too far and assume that someone we suspect has a deceptive intention will not be bound by their words or promise, as long as we accept it; this conclusion should only apply to situations where the signs differ from those associated with deceit. All these contradictions can be easily explained if the obligation of promises is merely a human concept for the sake of society, but they won't be clear if it's something real and natural stemming from any mental or physical action.
I shall farther observe, that since every new promise imposes a new obligation of morality on the person who promises, and since this new obligation arises from his will; it is one of the most mysterious and incomprehensible operations that can possibly be imagined, and may even be compared to TRANSUBSTANTIATION, or HOLY ORDERS,[8] where a certain form of words, along with a certain intention, changes entirely the nature of an external object, and even of a human nature. But though these mysteries be so far alike, it is very remarkable, that they differ widely in other particulars, and that this difference may be regarded as a strong proof of the difference of their origins. As the obligation of promises is an invention for the interest of society, it is warped into as many different forms as that interest requires, and even runs into direct contradictions, rather than lose sight of its object. But as those other monstrous doctines are mere priestly inventions, and have no public interest in view, they are less disturbed in their progress by new obstacles; and it must be owned, that, after the first absurdity, they follow more directly the current of reason and good sense. Theologians clearly perceived, that the external form of words, being mere sound, require an intention to make them have any efficacy; and that this intention being once considered as a requisite circumstance, its absence must equally prevent the effect, whether avowed or concealed, whether sincere or deceitful. Accordingly they have commonly determined, that the intention of the priest makes the sacrament, and that when he secretly withdraws his intention, he is highly criminal in himself; but still destroys the baptism, or communion, or holy orders. The terrible consequences of this doctrine were not able to hinder its taking place; as the inconvenience of a similar doctrine, with regard to promises, have prevented that doctrine from establishing itself. Men are always more concerned about the present life than the future; and are apt to think the smallest evil, which regards the former, more important than the greatest, which regards the latter.
I will also note that since every new promise creates a new moral obligation for the person making the promise, and since this new obligation comes from their will, it's one of the most mysterious and incomprehensible processes imaginable. It can even be compared to TRANSUBSTANTIATION or HOLY ORDERS, where a specific set of words, along with a certain intention, completely changes the nature of an external object, and even of a human being. However, while these mysteries are somewhat similar, it's quite remarkable that they differ significantly in other ways, and this difference can be seen as strong evidence of their different origins. The obligation of promises is designed for the benefit of society; therefore, it takes on various forms depending on that interest and may even lead to direct contradictions rather than losing sight of its purpose. In contrast, the other bizarre doctrines are purely priestly inventions with no public interest in mind, so they are less affected by new obstacles. It must be acknowledged that, after the initial absurdity, these doctrines tend to align more closely with reason and common sense. Theologians recognized that the external form of words, being just sounds, need intention to carry any weight; and if that intention is absent, it will prevent the effect, whether it's disclosed or hidden, sincere or deceitful. Thus, they typically concluded that the priest’s intention is what makes a sacrament valid, and if he secretly withdraws his intention, he is highly culpable; however, he still invalidates the baptism, communion, or holy orders. The serious consequences of this doctrine didn't stop it from being adopted, just as the drawbacks of a similar doctrine regarding promises have prevented that doctrine from being fully established. People tend to care more about their present life than the future and often view even the smallest trouble regarding the former as more significant than the greatest concerning the latter.
[8] I mean so far, as holy orders are suppos'd to produce the indelible character. In other respects they are only a legal qualification.
[8] I mean, so far, as holy orders are believed to create an indelible character. In other ways, they are just a legal requirement.
We may draw the same conclusion, concerning the origin of promises, from the force, which is supposed to invalidate all contracts, and to free us from their obligation. Such a principle is a proof, that promises have no natural obligation, and are mere artificial contrivances for the convenience and advantage of society. If we consider aright of the matter, force is not essentially different from any other motive of hope or fear, which may induce us to engage our word, and lay ourselves under any obligation. A man, dangerously wounded, who promises a competent sum to a surgeon to cure him, would certainly be bound to performance; though the case be not so much different from that of one, who promises a sum to a robber, as to produce so great a difference in our sentiments of morality, if these sentiments were not built entirely on public interest and convenience.
We can reach the same conclusion about the origin of promises based on the idea that force can invalidate all contracts and free us from their obligations. This principle shows that promises don’t have a natural obligation and are just social constructs created for the convenience and benefit of society. If we think about it carefully, force is not fundamentally different from any other motivation driven by hope or fear that might lead us to give our word and take on obligations. A man who is seriously injured and offers a surgeon a decent amount of money to treat him would definitely be obligated to follow through, even though this situation is not so different from someone promising money to a robber. The difference in our moral views in these cases is only significant because our sentiments are based entirely on public interest and convenience.
SECT. VI SOME FARTHER REFLECTIONS CONCERNING JUSTICE AND INJUSTICE
We have now run over the three fundamental laws of nature, that of the stability of possession, of its transference by consent, and of the performance of promises. It is on the strict observance of those three laws, that the peace and security of human society entirely depend; nor is there any possibility of establishing a good correspondence among men, where these are neglected. Society is absolutely necessary for the well-being of men; and these are as necessary to the support of society. Whatever restraint they may impose on the passions of men, they are the real offspring of those passions, and are only a more artful and more refined way of satisfying them. Nothing is more vigilant and inventive than our passions; and nothing is more obvious, than the convention for the observance of these rules. Nature has, therefore, trusted this affair entirely to the conduct of men, and has not placed in the mind any peculiar original principles, to determine us to a set of actions, into which the other principles of our frame and constitution were sufficient to lead us. And to convince us the more fully of this truth, we may here stop a moment, and from a review of the preceding reasonings may draw some new arguments, to prove that those laws, however necessary, are entirely artificial, and of human invention; and consequently that justice is an artificial, and not a natural virtue.
We have now covered the three fundamental laws of nature: the stability of possession, the transfer of possession through consent, and the fulfillment of promises. The peace and security of human society rely completely on strictly following these three laws; without them, it's impossible to establish good relationships among people. Society is essential for the well-being of individuals, and these laws are vital for supporting society. Regardless of the restrictions they place on human passions, they are a true product of those passions, serving as a more clever and refined way to fulfill them. Nothing is more alert and inventive than our passions, and it's clear that a convention exists for adhering to these rules. Therefore, nature has completely entrusted this matter to human conduct and hasn’t provided any specific original principles to guide us towards a set of actions that the other principles of our nature could lead us to. To further convince ourselves of this truth, we can take a moment to review the earlier arguments and draw new points to show that, while these laws are necessary, they are entirely artificial creations of humanity; thus, justice is an artificial, not a natural, virtue.
(1) The first argument I shall make use of is derived from the vulgar definition of justice. Justice is commonly defined to be a constant and perpetual will of giving every one his due. In this definition it is supposed, that there are such things as right and property, independent of justice, and antecedent to it; and that they would have subsisted, though men had never dreamt of practising such a virtue. I have already observed, in a cursory manner, the fallacy of this opinion, and shall here continue to open up a little more distinctly my sentiments on that subject.
(1) The first argument I’m going to use comes from the common definition of justice. Justice is usually defined as a constant and ongoing intention to give everyone what they deserve. This definition assumes that things like rights and property exist independently of justice and would still exist even if people never thought about practicing such a virtue. I’ve already pointed out the flaws in this belief briefly, and here I'll elaborate on my thoughts regarding this topic.
I shall begin with observing, that this quality, which we shall call property, is like many of the imaginary qualities of the peripatetic philosophy, and vanishes upon a more accurate inspection into the subject, when considered a-part from our moral sentiments. It is evident property does not consist in any of the sensible qualities of the object. For these may continue invariably the same, while the property changes. Property, therefore, must consist in some relation of the object. But it is not in its relation with regard to other external and inanimate objects. For these may also continue invariably the same, while the property changes. This quality, therefore, consists in the relations of objects to intelligent and rational beings. But it is not the external and corporeal relation, which forms the essence of property. For that relation may be the same betwixt inanimate objects, or with regard to brute creatures; though in those cases it forms no property. It is, therefore, in some internal relation, that the property consists; that is, in some influence, which the external relations of the object have on the mind and actions. Thus the external relation, which we call occupation or first possession, is not of itself imagined to be the property of the object, but only to cause its property. Now it is evident, this external relation causes nothing in external objects, and has only an influence on the mind, by giving us a sense of duty in abstaining from that object, and in restoring it to the first possessor. These actions are properly what we call justice; and consequently it is on that virtue that the nature of property depends, and not the virtue on the property.
I’ll start by noting that this quality, which we’ll call property, is similar to many of the made-up qualities in the philosophy of peripatetics, and it disappears under closer examination of the subject when viewed separately from our moral feelings. It’s clear that property doesn’t rely on any of the visible qualities of the object. These can remain exactly the same while the property changes. Therefore, property must be based on some relationship of the object. However, it’s not in relation to other external and inanimate objects, since those can also stay the same while the property changes. This quality exists in the relations between objects and intelligent, rational beings. But it’s not the external, physical relationship that defines property. That relationship may be the same between inanimate objects or with animals, yet, in those situations, it doesn’t constitute property. Thus, property lies in some internal relationship, meaning it comes from some effect that the object’s external relationships have on our minds and actions. The external relationship we call occupation or first possession isn’t, by itself, considered the property of the object but merely leads to it. Clearly, this external relationship doesn’t cause anything in the external objects; it only influences our minds by creating a sense of duty to avoid that object and to return it to the first possessor. These actions are what we properly refer to as justice; therefore, the nature of property relies on that virtue, not the virtue on the property.
If any one, therefore, would assert, that justice is a natural virtue, and injustice a natural vice, he must assert, that abstracting from the nations of property, and right and obligation, a certain conduct and train of actions, in certain external relations of objects, has naturally a moral beauty or deformity, and causes an original pleasure or uneasiness. Thus the restoring a man's goods to him is considered as virtuous, not because nature has annexed a certain sentiment of pleasure to such a conduct, with regard to the property of others, but because she has annexed that sentiment to such a conduct, with regard to those external objects, of which others have had the first or long possession, or which they have received by the consent of those, who have had first or long possession. If nature has given us no such sentiment, there is not, naturally, nor antecedent to human conventions, any such thing as property. Now, though it seems sufficiently evident, in this dry and accurate consideration of the present subject, that nature has annexed no pleasure or sentiment of approbation to such a conduct; yet that I may leave as little room for doubt as possible, I shall subjoin a few more arguments to confirm my opinion.
If anyone wants to claim that justice is a natural virtue and injustice is a natural vice, they must argue that, apart from concepts of property, rights, and obligations, certain behaviors and actions in specific external relationships have an inherent moral beauty or ugliness and evoke original feelings of pleasure or discomfort. For instance, returning someone's belongings to them is seen as virtuous, not because nature has linked a specific feeling of pleasure to this behavior concerning others' property, but because it has linked that feeling to this behavior regarding external objects that others have had for a long time or received with the consent of those who originally possessed them. If nature hasn't provided us with such feelings, then there’s nothing inherently like property, independent of human agreements. Now, while it seems quite clear, through this straightforward and precise examination of the topic, that nature hasn’t connected any pleasure or sense of approval to such behaviors, I will add a few more arguments to eliminate any doubt about my view.
First, If nature had given us a pleasure of this kind, it would have been as evident and discernible as on every other occasion; nor should we have found any difficulty to perceive, that the consideration of such actions, in such a situation, gives a certain pleasure and sentiment of approbation. We should not have been obliged to have recourse to notions of property in the definition of justice, and at the same time make use of the notions of justice in the definition of property. This deceitful method of reasoning is a plain proof, that there are contained in the subject some obscurities and difficulties, which we are not able to surmount, and which we desire to evade by this artifice.
First, if nature had given us a pleasure like this, it would be as clear and noticeable as it is on any other occasion; we wouldn’t have struggled to see that thinking about such actions in such a context brings a certain pleasure and sense of approval. We wouldn’t have had to rely on ideas about property to define justice while simultaneously using the concepts of justice to define property. This misleading way of reasoning clearly shows that there are some complexities and challenges in the subject that we can't overcome, and we try to avoid them with this trick.
Secondly, Those rules, by which properties, rights, and obligations are determined, have in them no marks of a natural origin but many of artifice and contrivance. They are too numerous to have proceeded from nature: They are changeable by human laws: And have all of them a direct and evident tendency to public good, and the support, of civil society. This last circumstance is remarkable upon two accounts. First, because, though the cause of the establishment of these laws had been a regard for the public good, as much as the public good is their natural tendency, they would still have been artificial, as being purposely contrived and directed to a certain end. Secondly, because, if men had been endowed with such a strong regard for public good, they would never have restrained themselves by these rules; so that the laws of justice arise from natural principles in a manner still more oblique and artificial. It is self-love which is their real origin; and as the self-love of one person is naturally contrary to that of another, these several interested passions are obliged to adjust themselves after such a manner as to concur in some system of conduct and behaviour. This system, therefore, comprehending the interest of each individual, is of course advantageous to the public; though it be not intended for that purpose by die inventors.
Secondly, the rules that define properties, rights, and obligations don't show any signs of a natural origin, but rather many indications of being made up and designed. There are too many of them to have come from nature: they're changeable by human laws and all have a clear and direct purpose of promoting the public good and supporting civil society. This last point is notable for two reasons. First, even though these laws were created with a focus on the public good, which is also their natural outcome, they would still be artificial because they were intentionally designed to achieve a specific goal. Second, if people truly cared so much about the public good, they wouldn't have limited themselves with these rules; thus, the laws of justice come from natural principles in a way that’s even more indirect and constructed. The real source of these laws is self-interest; and since one person's self-interest often conflicts with another's, these various competing interests need to find a way to align themselves in some system of conduct and behavior. This system, which reflects the interests of each individual, ultimately benefits the public, even if that wasn't the original intention of those who created it.
(2) In the second place we may observe, that all kinds of vice and virtue run insensibly into each other, and may approach by such imperceptible degrees as will make it very difficult, if not absolutely impossible, to determine when the one ends, and the other begins; and from this observation we may derive a new argument for the foregoing principle. For whatever may be the case, with regard to all kinds of vice and virtue, it is certain, that rights, and obligations, and property, admit of no such insensible gradation, but that a man either has a full and perfect property, or none at all; and is either entirely obliged to perform any action, or lies under no manner of obligation. However civil laws may talk of a perfect dominion, and of an imperfect, it is easy to observe, that this arises from a fiction, which has no foundation in reason, and can never enter into our notions of natural justice and equity. A man that hires a horse, though but for a day, has as full a right to make use of it for that time, as he whom we call its proprietor has to make use of it any other day; and it was evident, that however the use may be bounded in time or degree, the right itself is not susceptible of any such gradation, but is absolute and entire, so far as it extends. Accordingly we may observe, that this right both arises and perishes in an instant; and that a man entirely acquires the property of any object by occupation, or the consent of the proprietor; and loses it by his own consent; without any of that insensible gradation, which is remarkable in other qualities and relations, Since, therefore, this is die case with regard to property, and rights, and obligations, I ask, how it stands with regard to justice and injustice? After whatever manner you answer this question, you run into inextricable difficulties. If you reply, that justice and injustice admit of degree, and run insensibly into each other, you expressly contradict the foregoing position, that obligation and property are not susceptible of such a gradation. These depend entirely upon justice and injustice, and follow them in all their variations. Where the justice is entire, the property is also entire: Where the justice is imperfect, the property must also be imperfect And vice versa, if the property admit of no such variations, they must also be incompatible with justice. If you assent, therefore, to this last proposition, and assert, that justice and injustice are not susceptible of degrees, you in effect assert, that they are not naturally either vicious or virtuous; since vice and virtue, moral good and evil, and indeed all natural qualities, run insensibly into each other, and are, on many occasions, undistinguishable.
(2) Secondly, we can notice that all types of vice and virtue blend into each other seamlessly, making it very difficult, if not impossible, to pinpoint where one ends and the other begins. This observation gives us a new argument for the earlier principle. Whatever the situation may be regarding all forms of vice and virtue, it's clear that rights, obligations, and property do not allow for such subtle gradations. A person either has full and complete ownership, or they have none at all; they are either fully obligated to perform an action, or they are under no obligation whatsoever. Although civil laws may talk about perfect and imperfect ownership, it's easy to see that this is based on a fiction that lacks a rational foundation and doesn't fit into our understanding of natural justice and fairness. A person who rents a horse, even for just a day, has the same right to use it for that time as its owner does to use it any other day. It's clear that, regardless of how the use is restricted in time or degree, the right itself doesn't allow for any such gradation—it's absolute and complete as far as it extends. Thus, we can see that this right both comes into existence and ceases to exist instantly; a person fully acquires ownership of something by taking possession or with the owner's consent, and loses it through their own consent, without any of the subtle gradations that are noticeable in other qualities and relationships. So, since this is how it is with property, rights, and obligations, I ask how it relates to justice and injustice? However you answer this question, you will face unresolvable challenges. If you say that justice and injustice allow for degrees and blend into each other, you directly contradict the previous assertion that obligations and property do not allow for such gradation. Those depend entirely on justice and injustice and vary with them. Where justice is complete, property is also complete; where justice is imperfect, the property must likewise be imperfect. And conversely, if property does not allow for such variations, then it cannot be compatible with justice. Therefore, if you agree with this last statement and claim that justice and injustice do not permit degrees, you are essentially saying that they are not naturally virtuous or vicious; since vice and virtue, moral good and evil, and indeed all natural qualities, blend into each other and are often indistinguishable.
And here it may be worth while to observe, that though abstract reasoning, and the general maxims of philosophy and law establish this position, that property, and right, and obligation admit not of degrees, yet in our common and negligent way of thinking, we find great difficulty to entertain that opinion, and do even secretly embrace the contrary principle. An object must either be in the possession of one person or another. An action must either be performed or not. The necessity there is of choosing one side in these dilemmas, and the impossibility there often is of finding any just medium, oblige us, when we reflect on the matter, to acknowledge, that all property and obligations are entire. But on the other hand, when we consider the origin of property and obligation, and find that they depend on public utility, and sometimes on the propensities of the imagination, which are seldom entire on any side; we are naturally inclined to imagine, that these moral relations admit of an insensible gradation. Hence it is, that in references, where the consent of the parties leave the referees entire masters of the subject, they commonly discover so much equity and justice on both sides, as induces them to strike a medium, and divide the difference betwixt the parties. Civil judges, who have not this liberty, but are obliged to give a decisive sentence on some one side, are often at a loss how to determine, and are necessitated to proceed on the most frivolous reasons in the world. Half rights and obligations, which seem so natural in common life, are perfect absurdities in their tribunal; for which reason they are often obliged to take half arguments for whole ones, in order to terminate the affair one way or other.
It’s worth noting that, although abstract reasoning and the general principles of philosophy and law make it clear that property, rights, and obligations don’t come in degrees, we often struggle to accept this idea in our everyday thinking and even secretly lean toward the opposite belief. An object must either belong to one person or another. An action must either be done or not done. The need to choose one side in these dilemmas, along with the frequent difficulty of finding a fair middle ground, leads us to realize, upon reflection, that all property and obligations are absolute. However, when we look at the origins of property and obligation, we see that they rely on public utility and sometimes on our imaginations, which are rarely definitive. This makes us naturally inclined to think that these moral relationships allow for subtle gradations. As a result, in situations where the parties involved agree to let the mediators have full authority, they often find enough fairness and justice on both sides to propose a compromise and split the difference. Civil judges, on the other hand, who don’t have that flexibility and must make a definitive ruling on one side, often struggle to decide and end up relying on the most trivial reasons. The concept of half rights and obligations, which seems so natural in everyday life, is completely absurd in their court; for this reason, they often have to treat partial arguments as complete ones to resolve the matter one way or another.
(3) The third argument of this kind I shall make use of may be explained thus. If we consider the ordinary course of human actions, we shall find, that the mind restrains not itself by any general and universal rules; but acts on most occasions as it is determined by its present motives and inclination. As each action is a particular individual event, it must proceed from particular principles, and from our immediate situation within ourselves, and with respect to the rest of the universe. If on some occasions we extend our motives beyond those very circumstances, which gave rise to them, and form something like general rules for our conduct, it is easy to observe, that these rules are not perfectly inflexible, but allow of many exceptions. Since, therefore, this is the ordinary course of human actions, we may conclude, that the laws of justice, being universal and perfectly inflexible, can never be derived from nature, nor be the immediate offspring of any natural motive or inclination. No action can be either morally good or evil, unless there be some natural passion or motive to impel us to it, or deter us from it; and it is evident, that die morality must be susceptible of all the same variations, which are natural to the passion. Here are two persons, who dispute for an estate; of whom one is rich, a fool, and a batchelor; the other poor, a man of sense, and has a numerous family: The first is my enemy; the second my friend. Whether I be actuated in this affair by a view to public or private interest, by friendship or enmity, I must be induced to do my utmost to procure the estate to the latter. Nor would any consideration of the right and property of the persons be able to restrain me, were I actuated only by natural motives, without any combination or convention with others. For as all property depends on morality; and as all morality depends on the ordinary course of our passions and actions; and as these again are only directed by particular motives; it is evident, such a partial conduct must be suitable to the strictest morality, and could never be a violation of property. Were men, therefore, to take the liberty of acting with regard to the laws of society, as they do in every other affair, they would conduct themselves, on most occasions, by particular judgments, and would take into consideration the characters and circumstances of the persons, as well as the general nature of the question. But it is easy to observe, that this would produce an infinite confusion in human society, and that the avidity and partiality of men would quickly bring disorder into the world, if not restrained by some general and inflexible principles. Twas, therefore, with a view to this inconvenience, that men have established those principles, and have agreed to restrain themselves by general rules, which are unchangeable by spite and favour, and by particular views of private or public interest. These rules, then, are artificially invented for a certain purpose, and are contrary to the common principles of human nature, which accommodate themselves to circumstances, and have no stated invariable method of operation.
(3) The third argument I’m going to use can be explained like this. If we look at how people usually act, we’ll see that the mind doesn’t restrain itself with any universal principles; instead, it usually acts based on its current motives and desires. Since every action is a unique event, it has to come from specific principles and our immediate situation both internally and in relation to the rest of the world. Sometimes, we may try to extend our motives beyond the circumstances that created them and come up with something like general rules for our behavior, but it’s easy to see these rules aren’t completely rigid; they allow for many exceptions. Thus, since this is the typical way people behave, we can conclude that the laws of justice, which are universal and entirely rigid, cannot come from nature or be directly linked to any natural motive or inclination. No action can be deemed morally good or bad unless there’s some natural passion or motive driving us toward it or keeping us away from it; it's clear that morality must be able to change just like the passions do. For example, here are two people fighting over an estate; one is wealthy, foolish, and single, while the other is poor, sensible, and has a large family: the first is my enemy, and the second is my friend. Whether I’m motivated by public or private interest, friendship or hostility, I would be compelled to do everything I can to get the estate for the latter. No consideration of the rights or property of these individuals would hold me back if I’m only driven by these natural motives, without any involvement with others. Since all property relies on morality, and all morality depends on the usual patterns of our passions and actions, which in turn are guided by specific motives, it’s clear that such biased behavior could conform to the strictest morality and wouldn’t violate property rights. If people acted according to the laws of society as they do in other situations, they would generally make judgments based on specific circumstances and take into account the characters and situations of the individuals involved, as well as the overall nature of the issue. However, it’s easy to see that this would lead to immense confusion in society, and the greed and partiality of humans would quickly disrupt the world if not kept in check by some general and unyielding principles. Therefore, to avoid this problem, people have created those principles and agreed to limit themselves with general rules that can’t be changed by spite, favoritism, or personal or public interest. These rules are invented for a specific reason and go against the common principles of human nature, which adapt to circumstances and don’t operate according to any fixed, unchanging method.
Nor do I perceive how I can easily be mistaken in this matter. I see evidently, that when any man imposes on himself general inflexible rules in his conduct with others, he considers certain objects as their property, which he supposes to be sacred and inviolable. But no proposition can be more evident, than that property is perfectly unintelligible without first supposing justice and injustice; and that these virtues and vices are as unintelligible, unless we have motives, independent of the morality, to impel us to just actions, and deter us from unjust ones. Let those motives, therefore, be what they will, they must accommodate themselves to circumstances, and must admit of all the variations, which human affairs, in their incessant revolutions, are susceptible of. They are consequently a very improper foundation for such rigid inflexible rules as the laws of nature; and it is evident these laws can only be derived from human conventions, when men have perceived the disorders that result from following their natural and variable principles.
I don't see how I can easily be wrong about this. It’s clear to me that when someone sets strict, unchanging rules for how they interact with others, they regard certain things as their property, which they think are sacred and untouchable. However, it’s obvious that property doesn’t make sense without first acknowledging justice and injustice; and these qualities are also confusing unless we have motives, separate from morality, that drive us to do the right thing and keep us from doing the wrong one. Whatever those motives may be, they need to adapt to circumstances and allow for all the changes that human situations constantly go through. Therefore, they are a really poor basis for unyielding rules like the laws of nature; it's clear these laws can only come from social agreements, once people recognize the chaos that comes from following their natural and inconsistent instincts.
Upon the whole, then, we are to consider this distinction betwixt justice and injustice, as having two different foundations, viz, that of interest, when men observe, that it is impossible to live in society without restraining themselves by certain rules; and that of morality, when this interest is once observed and men receive a pleasure from the view of such actions as tend to the peace of society, and an uneasiness from such as are contrary to it. It is the voluntary convention and artifice of men, which makes the first interest take place; and therefore those laws of justice are so far to be considered as artificial. After that interest is once established and acknowledged, the sense of morality in the observance of these rules follows naturally, and of itself; though it is certain, that it is also augmented by a new artifice, and that the public instructions of politicians, and the private education of parents, contribute to the giving us a sense of honour and duty in the strict regulation of our actions with regard to the properties of others.
Overall, we should view the difference between justice and injustice as having two distinct foundations: one based on self-interest, when people recognize that it's impossible to live in society without sticking to certain rules; and the other rooted in morality, when this self-interest is acknowledged, and people take pleasure in actions that promote societal peace and feel discomfort with those that do not. The initial concept of interest is created through the voluntary agreements of individuals, which makes these laws of justice somewhat artificial. Once self-interest is established and recognized, the sense of morality in following these rules emerges naturally on its own; however, it’s clear that this sense is also strengthened by a new layer of social influence, including the public teachings of politicians and the private upbringing from parents, which help instill in us a sense of honor and duty regarding how we treat other people's property.
SECT. VII OF THE ORIGIN OF GOVERNMENT
Nothing is more certain, than that men are, in a great measure, governed by interest, and that even when they extend their concern beyond themselves, it is not to any great distance; nor is it usual for them, in common life, to look farther than their nearest friends and acquaintance. It is no less certain, that it is impossible for men to consult, their interest in so effectual a manner, as by an universal and inflexible observance of the rules of justice, by which alone they can preserve society, and keep themselves from falling into that wretched and savage condition, which is commonly represented as the state of nature. And as this interest, which all men have in the upholding of society, and the observation of the rules of justice, is great, so is it palpable and evident, even to the most rude and uncultivated of human race; and it is almost impossible for any one, who has had experience of society, to be mistaken in this particular. Since, therefore, men are so sincerely attached to their interest, and their interest is so much concerned in the observance of justice, and this interest is so certain and avowed; it may be asked, how any disorder can ever arise in society, and what principle there is in human nature so powerful as to overcome so strong a passion, or so violent as to obscure so clear a knowledge?
Nothing is more certain than that people are largely driven by self-interest, and even when they care about others, it's usually not far beyond their closest friends and acquaintances. It's also clear that it's impossible for people to effectively pursue their own interests without universally and rigidly following the rules of fairness, which are the only way to maintain society and prevent themselves from descending into that miserable and savage state often referred to as the state of nature. The interest everyone has in supporting society and adhering to the rules of fairness is significant, even obvious, to the most uncivilized of humans; it's nearly impossible for anyone who's experienced society to be mistaken about this. Given that people are so genuinely committed to their own interests, which are closely tied to upholding fairness, and that this interest is so clear and recognized, one might wonder how any disorder could ever arise in society and what principle in human nature could be so powerful as to overcome such a strong desire or so overwhelming as to cloud such clear understanding.
It has been observed, in treating of the passions, that men are mightily governed by the imagination, and proportion their affections more to the light, under which any object appears to them, than to its real and intrinsic value. What strikes upon them with a strong and lively idea commonly prevails above what lies in a more obscure light; and it must be a great superiority of value, that is able to compensate this advantage. Now as every thing, that is contiguous to us, either in space or time, strikes upon us with such an idea, it has a proportional effect on the will and passions, and commonly operates with more force than any object, that lies in a more distant and obscure light. Though we may be fully convinced, that the latter object excels the former, we are not able to regulate our actions by this judgment; but yield to the sollicitations of our passions, which always plead in favour of whatever is near and contiguous.
It has been noted that when it comes to emotions, people are heavily influenced by their imagination and tend to value their feelings based on how things appear rather than their actual worth. What hits them with a strong and vivid impression often takes precedence over what is less clear and defined; only a significant degree of actual value can make up for this advantage. Since everything that is close to us, whether in time or space, affects us with such an impression, it often influences our desires and emotions more powerfully than things that are farther away and less clear. Even if we are fully convinced that the latter is superior to the former, we struggle to act according to that judgment; instead, we give in to the urges of our emotions, which always advocate for what is near and immediate.
This is the reason why men so often act in contradiction to their known interest; and in particular why they prefer any trivial advantage, that is present, to the maintenance of order in society, which so much depends on the observance of justice. The consequences of every breach of equity seem to lie very remote, and are not able to counter-ballance any immediate advantage, that may be reaped from it. They are, however, never the less real for being remote; and as all men are, in some degree, subject to the same weakness, it necessarily happens, that the violations of equity must become very frequent in society, and the commerce of men, by that means, be rendered very dangerous and uncertain. You have the same propension, that I have, in favour of what is contiguous above what is remote. You are, therefore, naturally carried to commit acts of injustice as well as me. Your example both pushes me forward in this way by imitation, and also affords me a new reason for any breach of equity, by shewing me, that I should be the cully of my integrity, if I alone should impose on myself a severe restraint amidst the licentiousness of others.
This is why men often act against their own best interests; specifically, they tend to choose any small immediate gain over the stability of society, which heavily relies on maintaining justice. The effects of any injustice seem far off and are not enough to outweigh any instant benefit that can come from it. However, just because these consequences are distant doesn’t mean they’re not real; since everyone is somewhat vulnerable to this same weakness, violations of justice become frequent in society, making interactions among people risky and unpredictable. You share the same tendency that I do to value what’s immediate over what’s distant. Therefore, you’re naturally inclined to act unjustly just like me. Your behavior encourages me to do the same by showing that if I am the only one who holds back while others indulge, I would be the fool for sticking to my integrity.
This quality, therefore, of human nature, not only is very dangerous to society, but also seems, on a cursory view, to be incapable of any remedy. The remedy can only come from the consent of men; and if men be incapable of themselves to prefer remote to contiguous, they will never consent to any thing, which would oblige them to such a choice, and contradict, in so sensible a manner, their natural principles and propensities. Whoever chuses the means, chuses also the end; and if it be impossible for us to prefer what is remote, it is equally impossible for us to submit to any necessity, which would oblige us to such a method of acting.
This aspect of human nature is not only very harmful to society, but also seems, at first glance, to be beyond any solution. The solution can only arise from people’s agreement; and if people cannot choose long-term benefits over immediate ones, they will never agree to anything that forces them to make such a choice, which goes against their natural instincts and tendencies. Whoever chooses the means also chooses the end; and if it's impossible for us to prioritize what is distant, it is equally impossible for us to accept any necessity that would require us to act in that way.
But here it is observable, that this infirmity of human nature becomes a remedy to itself, and that we provide against our negligence about remote objects, merely because we are naturally inclined to that negligence. When we consider any objects at a distance, all their minute distinctions vanish, and we always give the preference to whatever is in itself preferable, without considering its situation and circumstances. This gives rise to what in an improper sense we call reason, which is a principle, that is often contradictory to those propensities that display themselves upon the approach of the object. In reflecting on any action, which I am to perform a twelve-month hence, I always resolve to prefer the greater good, whether at that time it will be more contiguous or remote; nor does any difference in that particular make a difference in my present intentions and resolutions. My distance from the final determination makes all those minute differences vanish, nor am I affected by any thing, but the general and more discernible qualities of good and evil. But on my nearer approach, those circumstances, which I at first over-looked, begin to appear, and have an influence on my conduct and affections. A new inclination to the present good springs up, and makes it difficult for me to adhere inflexibly to my first purpose and resolution. This natural infirmity I may very much regret, and I may endeavour, by all possible means, to free my self from it. I may have recourse to study and reflection within myself; to the advice of friends; to frequent meditation, and repeated resolution: And having experienced how ineffectual all these are, I may embrace with pleasure any other expedient, by which I may impose a restraint upon myself, and guard against this weakness.
But here it’s clear that this weakness of human nature ends up being a remedy in itself, and we take steps to avoid being careless about distant things simply because we are naturally prone to that carelessness. When we think about things that are far away, all their small differences fade away, and we always favor what is objectively better, without taking into account its situation and context. This leads to what we incorrectly call reason, a principle that often contradicts the instincts that show themselves as we get closer to the object. When contemplating any action I’m going to take a year from now, I always decide to choose the greater good, whether it’s closer or farther away at that time; and the difference in its timing doesn’t affect my current intentions and decisions. My distance from the final choice makes all those small differences disappear, and I’m only influenced by the general and more obvious qualities of good and evil. But as I get closer, those factors I initially overlooked begin to surface and start to impact my behavior and feelings. A new urge for the immediate good emerges, making it hard for me to stick firmly to my initial goal and resolution. I may regret this natural weakness greatly, and I might try everything I can to free myself from it. I could turn to study and self-reflection, seek advice from friends, engage in frequent meditation, and repeat my resolutions: And after realizing how ineffective all these are, I might gladly turn to any other solution that allows me to restrain myself and protect myself against this weakness.
The only difficulty, therefore, is to find out this expedient, by which men cure their natural weakness, and lay themselves under the necessity of observing the laws of justice and equity, notwithstanding their violent propension to prefer contiguous to remote. It is evident such a remedy can never be effectual without correcting this propensity; and as it is impossible to change or correct any thing material in our nature, the utmost we can do is to change our circumstances and situation, and render the observance of the laws of justice our nearest interest, and their violation our most remote. But this being impracticable with respect to all mankind, it can only take place with respect to a few, whom we thus immediately interest in the execution of justice. There are the persons, whom we call civil magistrates, kings and their ministers, our governors and rulers, who being indifferent persons to the greatest part of the state, have no interest, or but a remote one, in any act of injustice; and being satisfied with their present condition, and with their part in society, have an immediate interest in every execution of justice, which is so necessary to the upholding of society. Here then is the origin of civil government and society. Men are not able radically to cure, either in themselves or others, that narrowness of soul, which makes them prefer the present to the remote. They cannot change their natures. All they can do is to change their situation, and render the observance of justice the immediate interest of some particular persons, and its violation their more remote. These persons, then, are not only induced to observe those rules in their own conduct, but also to constrain others to a like regularity, and inforce the dictates of equity through the whole society. And if it be necessary, they may also interest others more immediately in the execution of justice, and create a number of officers, civil and military, to assist them in their government.
The only challenge, then, is to figure out how people can overcome their natural weaknesses and feel compelled to follow the laws of fairness and justice, even though they tend to favor what is nearby over what is distant. It’s clear that such a solution can’t work effectively without addressing this tendency; and since it’s impossible to change or fix anything significant in our nature, the best we can do is alter our circumstances and make following the laws of justice our immediate concern while making their violation seem more distant. However, this isn't feasible for everyone, so it can only apply to a few individuals who we then directly involve in enforcing justice. These are the civil magistrates, kings, and their ministers—our governors and leaders—who, being neutral in relation to most of society, have no strong personal stake in any acts of injustice. Content with their current roles and status in society, they have a direct interest in the enforcement of justice, which is vital for maintaining social order. This is the foundation of civil government and society. People cannot completely change that shortsightedness which makes them prioritize the present over the future, and they can't change their nature. All they can do is modify their circumstances to ensure that upholding justice benefits specific individuals directly, while its breach affects them less immediately. These individuals are not only motivated to follow those standards in their own behavior but are also compelled to ensure that others do the same, enforcing fairness throughout society. If necessary, they can also involve others more directly in carrying out justice and establish a range of civil and military officers to help them govern.
But this execution of justice, though the principal, is not the only advantage of government. As violent passion hinder men from seeing distinctly the interest they have in an equitable behaviour towards others; so it hinders them from seeing that equity itself, and gives them a remarkable partiality in their own favours. This inconvenience is corrected in the same manner as that above-mentioned. The same persons, who execute the laws of justice, will also decide all controversies concerning them; and being indifferent to the greatest part of the society, will decide them more equitably than every one would in his own case.
But while enforcing justice is the main benefit of government, it's not the only one. Just as strong emotions can cloud people's judgment about the importance of treating others fairly, they can also prevent them from recognizing fairness itself, leading to a notable bias in their own favor. This issue is resolved in the same way as described above. The same individuals who enforce the laws of justice will also resolve any disputes related to them; and since they are impartial to most of society, they will adjudicate these matters more fairly than individuals would in their own situations.
By means of these two advantages, in the execution and decision of justice, men acquire a security against each others weakness and passion, as well as against their own, and under the shelter of their governors, begin to taste at ease the sweets of society and mutual assistance. But government extends farther its beneficial influence; and not contented to protect men in those conventions they make for their mutual interest, it often obliges them to make such conventions, and forces them to seek their own advantage, by a concurrence in some common end or purpose. There is no quality in human nature, which causes more fatal errors in our conduct, than that which leads us to prefer whatever is present to the distant and remote, and makes us desire objects more according to their situation than their intrinsic value. Two neighbours may agree to drain a meadow, which they possess in common; because it is easy for them to know each others mind; and each must perceive, that the immediate consequence of his failing in his part, is, the abandoning the whole project. But it is very difficult, and indeed impossible, that a thousand persons should agree in any such action; it being difficult for them to concert so complicated a design, and still more difficult for them to execute it; while each seeks a pretext to free himself of the trouble and expence, and would lay the whole burden on others. Political society easily remedies both these inconveniences. Magistrates find an immediate interest in the interest of any considerable part of their subjects. They need consult no body but themselves to form any scheme for the promoting of that interest. And as the failure of any one piece in the execution is connected, though not immediately, with the failure of the whole, they prevent that failure, because they find no interest in it, either immediate or remote. Thus bridges are built; harbours opened; ramparts raised; canals formed; fleets equiped; and armies disciplined every where, by the care of government, which, though composed of men subject to all human infirmities, becomes, by one of the finest and most subtle inventions imaginable, a composition, which is, in some measure, exempted from all these infirmities.
With these two advantages, in carrying out and deciding justice, people gain security against each other's weaknesses and emotions, as well as their own. Under the protection of their government, they start to enjoy the benefits of society and mutual support. But the government goes further with its positive influence; not only does it protect people in the agreements they make for their common good, but it often also requires them to make these agreements and compels them to pursue their own interests by agreeing on a shared goal or purpose. There’s no trait in human nature that leads to more significant mistakes in our actions than the tendency to favor what is immediate over what is further away, which makes us value things more based on their accessibility than their actual worth. Two neighbors might decide to drain a shared meadow because it’s easy for them to understand each other's intentions, and each realizes that if one of them fails to do their part, they jeopardize the entire project. However, it's very challenging, even impossible, for a thousand people to agree on a similar action; coordinating such a complex plan is tough and executing it is even harder, as each person looks for a way to avoid the hassle and cost and wants to offload the entire burden onto others. Political society effectively addresses both of these issues. Officials have a vested interest in the welfare of a significant part of their community. They only need to consult themselves to come up with strategies to promote that interest. And since the failure of any single part in the execution is linked, though not directly, to the failure of the whole, they work to prevent that failure, as they have no vested interest in it, whether immediate or remote. This is how bridges are built, ports are opened, fortifications are raised, canals are created, fleets are outfitted, and armies are trained everywhere, all thanks to the efforts of the government, which, although made up of people subject to human flaws, becomes, through one of the most brilliant and sophisticated inventions imaginable, a system that is somewhat free from those flaws.
SECT. VIII OF THE SOURCE OF ALLEGIANCE
Though government be an invention very advantageous, and even in some circumstances absolutely necessary to mankind; it is not necessary in all circumstances, nor is it impossible for men to preserve society for some time, without having recourse to such an invention. Men, it is true, are always much inclined to prefer present interest to distant and remote; nor is it easy for them to resist the temptation of any advantage, that they may immediately enjoy, in apprehension of an evil that lies at a distance from them: But still this weakness is less conspicuous where the possessions, and the pleasures of life are few, and of little value, as they always are in the infancy of society. An Indian is but little tempted to dispossess another of his hut, or to steal his bow, as being already provided of the same advantages; and as to any superior fortune, which may attend one above another in hunting and fishing, it is only casual and temporary, and will have but small tendency to disturb society. And so far am I from thinking with some philosophers, that men are utterly incapable of society without government, that I assert the first rudiments of government to arise from quarrels, not among men of the same society, but among those of different societies. A less degree of riches will suffice to this latter effect, than is requisite for the former. Men fear nothing from public war and violence but the resistance they meet with, which, because they share it in common, seems less terrible; and because it comes from strangers, seems less pernicious in its consequences, than when they are exposed singly against one whose commerce is advantageous to them, and without whose society it is impossible they can subsist. Now foreign war to a society without government necessarily produces civil war. Throw any considerable goods among men, they instantly fall a quarrelling, while each strives to get possession of what pleases him, without regard to the consequences. In a foreign war the most considerable of all goods, life and limbs, are at stake; and as every one shuns dangerous ports, seizes the best arms, seeks excuse for the slightest wounds, the laws, which may be well enough observed while men were calm, can now no longer take place, when they are in such commotion.
Even though government is a very useful invention, and in some situations absolutely necessary for humanity, it’s not essential in every circumstance. It’s also possible for people to maintain society for a period of time without resorting to such an invention. It’s true that people often prefer immediate interests over distant ones, and it’s not easy for them to ignore the temptation of any advantage they can enjoy right now, especially when confronted with a distant threat. However, this weakness is less noticeable when the possessions and pleasures of life are few and not very valuable, which is usually the case in the early stages of society. A Native American is not very tempted to take another person's hut or steal their bow since they usually have the same resources; any temporary advantage in hunting or fishing is generally casual and won't significantly disrupt society. I strongly disagree with some philosophers who argue that people are completely incapable of forming societies without government. I believe that the earliest forms of government stem from conflicts not among individuals from the same society, but between those from different societies. Less wealth is needed to create this kind of conflict than is required for maintaining order within a society. People fear public war and violence only for the resistance they face, which seems less intense because it’s shared by everyone and appears less harmful since it comes from outsiders rather than someone they depend on for survival. In a society without government, foreign wars inevitably lead to civil wars. When valuable items are distributed among people, they immediately start fighting, each trying to claim what they desire without thinking about the consequences. In foreign conflicts, the most valuable assets—life and health—are at risk; and since everyone avoids danger, grabs the best weapons, and seeks justification for even the smallest injuries, the laws that might have been respected when people were calm can no longer be enforced when they are in turmoil.
This we find verified in the American tribes, where men live in concord and amity among themselves without any established government and never pay submission to any of their fellows, except in time of war, when their captain enjoys a shadow of authority, which he loses after their return from the field, and the establishment of peace with the neighbouring tribes. This authority, however, instructs them in the advantages of government, and teaches them to have recourse to it, when either by the pillage of war, by commerce, or by any fortuitous inventions, their riches and possessions have become so considerable as to make them forget, on every emergence, the interest they have in the preservation of peace and justice. Hence we may give a plausible reason, among others, why all governments are at first monarchical, without any mixture and variety; and why republics arise only from the abuses of monarchy and despotic power. Camps are the true mothers of cities; and as war cannot be administered, by reason of the suddenness of every exigency, without some authority in a single person, the same kind of authority naturally takes place in that civil government, which succeeds the military. And this reason I take to be more natural, than the common one derived from patriarchal government, or the authority of a father, which is said first to take place in one family, and to accustom the members of it to the government of a single person. The state of society without government is one of the most natural states of men, and must submit with the conjunction of many families, and long after the first generation. Nothing but an encrease of riches and possessions could oblige men to quit it; and so barbarous and uninstructed are all societies on their first formation, that many years must elapse before these can encrease to such a degree, as to disturb men in the enjoyment of peace and concord. But though it be possible for men to maintain a small uncultivated society without government, it is impossible they should maintain a society of any kind without justice, and the observance of those three fundamental laws concerning the stability of possession, its translation by consent, and the performance of promises. These are, therefore, antecedent to government, and are supposed to impose an obligation before the duty of allegiance to civil magistrates has once been thought of. Nay, I shall go farther, and assert, that government, upon its first establishment, would naturally be supposed. to derive its obligation from those laws of nature, and, in particular, from that concerning the performance of promises. When men have once perceived the necessity of government to maintain peace, and execute justice, they would naturally assemble together, would chuse magistrates, determine power, and promise them obedience. As a promise is supposed to be a bond or security already in use, and attended with a moral obligation, it is to be considered as the original sanction of government, and as the source of the first obligation to obedience. This reasoning appears so natural, that it has become the foundation of our fashionable system of politics, and is in a manner the creed of a party amongst us, who pride themselves, with reason, on the soundness of their philosophy, and their liberty of thought. All men, say they, are born free and equal: Government and superiority can only be established by consent: The consent of men, in establishing government, imposes on them a new obligation, unknown to the laws of nature. Men, therefore, are bound to obey their magistrates, only because they promise it; and if they had not given their word, either expressly or tacitly, to preserve allegiance, it would never have become a part of their moral duty. This conclusion, however, when carried so far as to comprehend government in all its ages and situations, is entirely erroneous; and I maintain, that though the duty of allegiance be at first grafted on the obligation of promises, and be for some time supported by that obligation, yet it quickly takes root of itself, and has an original obligation and authority, independent of all contracts. This is a principle of moment, which we must examine with care and attention, before we proceed any farther.
This is evident in the American tribes, where men live in harmony and friendship with each other without any formal government and only submit to a leader during wartime. The leader holds a temporary authority that disappears once they return from battle and peace is restored with neighboring tribes. However, this authority shows them the benefits of having a government and teaches them to seek it when their wealth and possessions, gained through war, trade, or random luck, become significant enough that they forget the importance of maintaining peace and justice. This gives us a plausible reason, among others, why all governments initially tend to be monarchies, without any mix or variation, and why republics emerge only from the failures of monarchy and tyrannical power. Military camps are the true origin of cities; and since war cannot be conducted due to the unpredictability of emergencies without some authority in a single leader, this kind of authority naturally carries over into the civil government that follows the military. I believe this reason is more natural than the commonly accepted idea that authority derives from patriarchal rule, or the authority of a father, which is said to originate within a single family and familiarize its members with the rule of one person. A society without government is one of the most natural states for humans and must unite many families, lasting long after the first generation. It takes a significant increase in wealth and possessions to drive people away from this state; and so primitive and uneducated are all societies in their initial formation that many years must pass before they gather enough riches to disrupt the enjoyment of peace and harmony. While it's possible for people to maintain a small, uncultivated society without government, it is impossible to maintain any society without justice and adherence to three fundamental laws regarding property stability, consensual property transfer, and promise-keeping. These laws, therefore, precede government and are assumed to impose obligations before the duty of allegiance to civil authorities is even considered. Furthermore, I assert that when government is first established, it would naturally be considered to derive its authority from these natural laws, particularly from the obligation to keep promises. Once people recognize the need for government to uphold peace and administer justice, they would come together, elect officials, define power, and promise to obey. Since a promise is seen as a bond or security already in practice, and comes with a moral obligation, it is regarded as the original basis of government and the source of the initial obligation to obey. This reasoning is so intuitive that it has become the foundation of our popular political system, and it is almost the manifesto of a group among us who justifiably take pride in their solid philosophy and freedom of thought. They claim that all humans are born free and equal: government and dominance can only be founded on consent: the consent of individuals in establishing government imposes a new obligation on them, one that is not covered by the laws of nature. Thus, individuals are bound to obey their officials solely because they have promised to do so; if they had not clearly or implicitly committed to uphold their allegiance, it would never have become part of their moral duty. However, this conclusion, when extended to include government across all times and circumstances, is entirely flawed. I argue that while the duty of allegiance initially grows from the obligation of promises and is supported by that obligation for a time, it quickly establishes its own roots and possesses an inherent authority, independent of any contracts. This is an important principle that we must examine closely before moving on further.
It is reasonable for those philosophers, who assert justice to be a natural virtue, and antecedent to human conventions, to resolve all civil allegiance into the obligation of a promise, and assert that it is our own consent alone, which binds us to any submission to magistracy. For as all government is plainly an invention of men, and the origin of most governments is known in history, it is necessary to mount higher, in order to find the source of our political duties, if we would assert them to have any natural obligation of morality. These philosophers, therefore, quickly observe, that society is as antient as the human species, and those three fundamental laws of nature as antient as society: So that taking advantage of the antiquity, and obscure origin of these laws, they first deny them to be artificial and voluntary inventions of men, and then seek to ingraft on them those other duties, which are more plainly artificial. But being once undeceived in this particular, and having found that natural, as well as civil justice, derives its origin from human conventions, we shall quickly perceive, how fruitless it is to resolve the one into the other, and seek, in the laws of nature, a stronger foundation for our political duties than interest, and human conventions; while these laws themselves are built on the very same foundation. On which ever side we turn this subject, we shall find, that these two kinds of duty are exactly on the same footing, and have the same source both of their first invention and moral obligation. They are contrived to remedy like inconveniences, and acquire their moral sanction in the same manner, from their remedying those inconveniences. These are two points, which we shall endeavour to prove as distinctly as possible.
It's reasonable for philosophers who claim that justice is a natural virtue, existing before human agreements, to say that all civil loyalty comes down to the obligation of a promise. They argue that it is our own consent that binds us to follow any authority. Since all government is clearly a human invention, and we know the history of most governments, we need to look further back to find the source of our political duties if we want to claim they have any natural moral obligation. These philosophers quickly note that society is as old as humanity itself, and the three fundamental laws of nature are just as ancient as society. Taking advantage of the age and unclear origin of these laws, they first deny that they are artificial and voluntary inventions of people, and then they try to attach to them other duties that are clearly artificial. However, once we realize that both natural and civil justice come from human agreements, we will see how pointless it is to try to connect the two and to seek in the laws of nature a stronger basis for our political duties than interest and human conventions, especially since these laws are built on the same foundation. No matter which angle we consider this topic, we will find that these two kinds of duty are exactly equal in status and share the same source for both their initial creation and moral obligation. They are designed to address similar issues and gain their moral authority in the same way by addressing those issues. These are two points we will aim to prove as clearly as possible.
We have already shewn, that men invented the three fundamental laws of nature, when they observed the necessity of society to their mutual subsistance, and found, that it was impossible to maintain any correspondence together, without some restraint on their natural appetites. The same self-love, therefore, which renders men so incommodious to each other, taking a new and more convenient direction, produces the rules of justice, and is the first motive of their observance. But when men have observed, that though the rules of justice be sufficient to maintain any society, yet it is impossible for them, of themselves, to observe those rules, in large and polished societies; they establish government, as a new invention to attain their ends, and preserve the old, or procure new advantages, by a more strict execution of justice. So far, therefore, our civil duties are connected with our natural, that the former are invented chiefly for the sake of the latter; and that the principal object of government is to constrain men to observe the laws of nature. In this respect, however, that law of nature, concerning the performance of promises, is only comprized along with the rest; and its exact observance is to be considered as an effect of the institution of government, and not the obedience to government as an effect of the obligation of a promise. Though the object of our civil duties be the enforcing of our natural, yet the first[9] motive of the invention, as well as performance of both, is nothing but self-interest: and since there is a separate interest in the obedience to government, from that in the performance of promises, we must also allow of a separate obligation. To obey the civil magistrate is requisite to preserve order and concord in society. To perform promises is requisite to beget mutual trust and confidence in the common offices of life. The ends, as well as the means, are perfectly distinct; nor is the one subordinate to the other.
We have already shown that people invented the three fundamental laws of nature when they recognized the need for society to support their mutual survival and realized that it was impossible to maintain any communication without some limits on their natural desires. The same self-interest that makes people inconvenient to one another, when redirected in a more practical way, leads to the development of justice, which is the primary motivation for following these rules. However, when people notice that while the rules of justice are enough to maintain any society, it's impossible for them to uphold those rules on their own in large, sophisticated societies, they create a government as a new way to achieve their goals and ensure the enforcement of justice, either maintaining the old benefits or gaining new ones through stricter implementation. Thus, our civic duties are intertwined with our natural ones, as the former exist mainly for the sake of the latter, and the main purpose of government is to compel people to follow the laws of nature. In this regard, the natural law concerning the keeping of promises is included along with the others, and its exact adherence should be viewed as a result of government institutions, not the other way around. While the goal of our civic duties is to uphold our natural ones, the main motivation for both their invention and fulfillment is self-interest. Since there is a distinct interest in obeying the government separate from that of keeping promises, we also need to recognize a separate obligation. Obeying the civil authorities is essential for maintaining order and harmony in society. Keeping promises is necessary for fostering mutual trust and confidence in everyday interactions. The goals and means are completely separate; neither one is subordinate to the other.
To make this more evident, let us consider, that men will often bind themselves by promises to the performance of what it would have been their interest to perform, independent of these promises; as when they would give others a fuller security, by super-adding a new obligation of interest to that which they formerly lay under. The interest in the performance of promises, besides its moral obligation, is general, avowed, and of the last consequence in life. Other interests may be more particular and doubtful; and we are apt to entertain a greater suspicion, that men may indulge their humour, or passion, in acting contrary to them. Here, therefore, promises come naturally in play, and are often required for fuller satisfaction and security. But supposing those other interests to be as general and avowed as the interest in the performance of a promise, they will be regarded as on the same footing, and men will begin to repose the same confidence in them. Now this is exactly the case with regard to our civil duties, or obedience to the magistrate; without which no government could subsist, nor any peace or order be maintained in large societies, where there are so many possessions on the one hand, and so many wants, real or imaginary, on the other. Our civil duties, therefore, must soon detach themselves from our promises, and acquire a separate force and influence. The interest in both is of the very same kind: It is general, avowed, and prevails in all times and places. There is, then, no pretext of reason for founding the one upon the other; while each of them has a foundation peculiar to itself. We might as well resolve the obligation to abstain from the possessions of others, into the obligation of a promise, as that of allegiance. The interests are not more distinct in the one case than the other. A regard to property is not more necessary to natural society, than obedience is to civil society or government; nor is the former society more necessary to the being of mankind, than the latter to their well-being and happiness. In short, if the performance of promises be advantageous, so is obedience to government: If the former interest be general, so is the latter: If the one interest be obvious and avowed, so is the other. And as these two rules are founded on like obligations of interest, each of them must have a peculiar authority, independent of the other.
To make this clearer, let's consider that people often tie themselves to promises to do things they would have been inclined to do anyway. This happens when they want to provide others with more security by adding a new obligation to what they were already committed to. The interest in keeping promises, in addition to its moral duty, is widely recognized and extremely important in life. Other interests may be more specific and uncertain, and we tend to be more suspicious that people might follow their whims or emotions instead of those interests. In this context, promises naturally come into play, and people often seek them for greater satisfaction and security. However, if those other interests were as widely recognized and important as the interest in keeping promises, they would be seen as equal, and people would start to trust them just as much. This is exactly the case regarding our civic duties or obedience to authority; without these, no government could exist, nor could peace or order be maintained in large societies filled with possessions on one side and various real or imagined needs on the other. Therefore, our civic duties must soon separate themselves from our promises and gain their own force and influence. The interest in both is fundamentally the same: it is widespread, acknowledged, and holds true at all times and places. There is no good reason to base one on the other since each has its own foundation. We might as well say the obligation to refrain from taking others' property comes from the obligation of a promise as we would with allegiance. The interests are just as distinct in both cases. Concern for property is not more essential to natural society than obedience is to civil society or government; neither is the former society more crucial for human existence than the latter is for human well-being and happiness. In short, if keeping promises is beneficial, so is obedience to government. If one interest is general, so is the other. If one interest is clear and acknowledged, so is the other. And since these two principles are based on similar obligations of interest, each must hold its own authority, independent of the other.
But it is not only the natural obligations of interest, which are distinct in promises and allegiance; but also the moral obligations of honour and conscience: Nor does the merit or demerit of the one depend in the least upon that of the other. And indeed, if we consider the close connexion there is betwixt the natural and moral obligations, we shall find this conclusion to be entirely unavoidable. Our interest is always engaged on the side of obedience to magistracy; and there is nothing but a great present advantage, that can lead us to rebellion, by making us over-look the remote interest, which we have in the preserving of peace and order in society. But though a present interest may thus blind us with regard to our own actions, it takes not place with regard to those of others; nor hinders them from appearing in their true colours, as highly prejudicial to public interest, and to our own in particular. This naturally gives us an uneasiness, in considering such seditious and disloyal actions, and makes us attach to them the idea of vice and moral deformity. It is the same principle, which causes us to disapprove of all kinds of private injustice, and in particular of the breach of promises. We blame all treachery and breach of faith; because we consider, that the freedom and extent of human commerce depend entirely on a fidelity with regard to promises. We blame all disloyalty to magistrates; because we perceive, that the execution of justice, in the stability of possession, its translation by consent, and the performance of promises, is impossible, without submission to government. As there are here two interests entirely distinct from each other, they must give rise to two moral obligations, equally separate and independent. Though there was no such thing as a promise in the world, government would still be necessary in all large and civilized societies; and if promises had only their own proper obligation, without the separate sanction of government, they would have but little efficacy in such societies. This separates the boundaries of our public and private duties, and shews that the latter are more dependant on the former, than the former on the latter. Education, and the artifice of politicians, concur to bestow a farther morality on loyalty, and to brand all rebellion with a greater degree of guilt and infamy. Nor is it a wonder, that politicians should be very industrious in inculcating such notions, where their interest is so particularly concerned.
But it's not just the natural responsibilities of self-interest that differentiate promises and loyalty; it's also the moral responsibilities of honor and conscience. The value or lack of value in one doesn’t depend at all on the other. In fact, if we look at the close connection between natural and moral obligations, we’ll see that this conclusion is unavoidable. Our self-interest is always aligned with obeying authority; only a significant immediate benefit can push us toward rebellion by distracting us from the long-term benefits of maintaining peace and order in society. While a present interest might cloud our judgment regarding our own actions, it doesn’t apply to the actions of others, nor does it stop them from being seen clearly as harmful to the public good and to our own interests. This naturally creates discomfort when we consider such rebellious and disloyal actions, leading us to view them as morally wrong. The same principle causes us to disapprove of all forms of private injustice, especially breaking promises. We condemn all betrayal and broken trust because we believe that the freedom and scope of human relationships rely entirely on fidelity to promises. We criticize all disloyalty to authorities because we recognize that the enforcement of justice, the stability of ownership, its transfer by consent, and the fulfillment of promises cannot exist without submission to government. Since these two interests are completely distinct, they must lead to two moral obligations that are equally separate and independent. Even if promises didn’t exist, government would still be necessary in all large and civilized societies; and if promises only had their own intrinsic obligation without the separate authority of government, they would have little impact in such societies. This clarifies the boundaries between our public and private responsibilities, showing that the latter depend more on the former than vice versa. Education and the manipulation by politicians work together to impose a greater morality on loyalty and to label all rebellion with a higher degree of guilt and shame. It’s no surprise that politicians are keen to promote such ideas, especially when their interests are at stake.
Lest those arguments should not appear entirely conclusive (as I think they are) I shall have recourse to authority, and shall prove, from the universal consent of mankind, that the obligation of submission to government is not derived from any promise of the subjects. Nor need any one wonder, that though I have all along endeavoured to establish my system on pure reason, and have scarce ever cited the judgment even of philosophers or historians on any article, I should now appeal to popular authority, and oppose the sentiments of the rabble to any philosophical reasoning. For it must be observed, that the opinions of men, in this case, carry with them a peculiar authority, and are, in a great measure, infallible. The distinction of moral good and evil is founded on the pleasure or pain, which results from the view of any sentiment, or character; and as that pleasure or pain cannot be unknown to the person who feels it, it follows,[10] that there is just so much vice or virtue in any character, as every one places in it, and that it is impossible in this particular we can ever be mistaken. And though our judgments concerning the origin of any vice or virtue, be not so certain as those concerning their degrees; yet, since the question in this case regards not any philosophical origin of an obligation, but a plain matter of fact, it is not easily conceived how we can fall into an error. A man, who acknowledges himself to be bound to another, for a certain sum, must certainly know whether it be by his own bond, or that of his father; whether it be of his mere good-will, or for money lent him; and under what conditions, and for what purposes he has bound himself. In like manner, it being certain, that there is a moral obligation to submit to government, because every one thinks so; it must be as certain, that this obligation arises not from a promise; since no one, whose judgment has not been led astray by too strict adherence to a system of philosophy, has ever yet dreamt of ascribing it to that origin. Neither magistrates nor subjects have formed this idea of our civil duties.
To ensure that these arguments seem wholly conclusive (as I believe they are), I'll turn to authority and show, based on the universal agreement of people, that the duty to obey the government doesn't come from any promise made by the people. It's also not surprising that although I have consistently tried to base my system on pure reason and rarely referenced even the opinions of philosophers or historians, I now call on popular authority and contrast the views of the masses against philosophical reasoning. This is because, in this case, the beliefs of the people carry a special kind of authority and are, to a large extent, infallible. The distinction between moral good and evil is based on the pleasure or pain resulting from how any sentiment or character is viewed. Since that pleasure or pain cannot be unknown to the person experiencing it, it follows that there is exactly as much vice or virtue in a character as each person perceives, making it impossible for us to be mistaken on this point. Although our judgments about the origins of any vice or virtue may not be as clear-cut as those concerning their degrees, since this question is about the straightforward fact of an obligation and not its philosophical origins, it’s hard to see how we could be wrong. A person who admits they owe another for a certain amount must clearly understand whether it's based on their own bond or that of their father, whether it's from their goodwill or money lent, and under what conditions and purposes they have tied themselves. Similarly, since it's clear that there is a moral obligation to obey the government, because everyone believes so, it must also be clear that this obligation doesn't come from a promise; no one who hasn’t been misguided by a strict adherence to a philosophical system has ever thought to attribute it to that origin. Neither officials nor citizens have created this idea of our civil duties.
[10] This proposition must hold strictly true, with regard to every quality, that is determin'd merely by sentiment. In what sense we can talk either of a right or a wrong taste in morals, eloquence, or beauty, shall be considerd afterwards. In the mean time, it may be observ'd, that there is such an uniformity in the GENERAL sentiments of mankind, as to render such questions of but small importance.
[10] This statement must be completely accurate regarding every quality determined solely by feelings. We'll discuss how we can talk about right or wrong tastes in morals, eloquence, or beauty later. Meanwhile, it can be noted that there is a significant uniformity in people's general sentiments, making such questions relatively unimportant.
We find, that magistrates are so far from deriving their authority, and the obligation to obedience in their subjects, from the foundation of a promise or original contract, that they conceal, as far as possible, from their people, especially from the vulgar, that they have their origin from thence. Were this the sanction of government, our rulers would never receive it tacitly, which is the utmost that can be pretended; since what is given tacitly and insensibly can never have such influence on mankind, as what is performed expressly and openly. A tacit promise is, where the will is signified by other more diffuse signs than those of speech; but a will there must certainly be in the case, and that can never escape the person's notice, who exerted it, however silent or tacit. But were you to ask the far greatest part of the nation, whether they had ever consented to the authority of their rulers, or promised to obey them, they would be inclined to think very strangely of you; and would certainly reply, that the affair depended not on their consent, but that they were born to such an obedience. In consequence of this opinion, we frequently see them imagine such persons to be their natural rulers, as are at that time deprived of all power and authority, and whom no man, however foolish, would voluntarily chuse; and this merely because they are in that line, which ruled before, and in that degree of it, which used to succeed; though perhaps in so distant a period, that scarce any man alive could ever have given any promise of obedience. Has a government, then, no authority over such as these, because they never consented to it, and would esteem the very attempt of such a free choice a piece of arrogance and impiety? We find by experience, that it punishes them very freely for what it calls treason and rebellion, which, it seems, according to this system, reduces itself to common injustice. If you say, that by dwelling in its dominions, they in effect consented to the established government; I answer, that this can only be, where they think the affair depends on their choice, which few or none, beside those philosophers, have ever yet imagined. It never was pleaded as an excuse for a rebel, that the first act he performed, after he came to years of discretion, was to levy war against the sovereign of the state; and that while he was a child he could not bind himself by his own consent, and having become a man, showed plainly, by the first act he performed, that he had no design to impose on himself any obligation to obedience. We find, on the contrary, that civil laws punish this crime at the same age as any other, which is criminal, of itself, without our consent; that is, when the person is come to the full use of reason: Whereas to this crime they ought in justice to allow some intermediate time, in which a tacit consent at least might be supposed. To which we may add, that a man living under an absolute government, would owe it no allegiance; since, by its very nature, it depends not on consent. But as that is as natural and common a government as any, it must certainly occasion some obligation; and it is plain from experience, that men, who are subjected to it, do always think so. This is a clear proof, that we do not commonly esteem our allegiance to be derived from our consent or promise; and a farther proof is, that when our promise is upon any account expressly engaged, we always distinguish exactly betwixt the two obligations, and believe the one to add more force to the other, than in a repetition of the same promise. Where no promise is given, a man looks not on his faith as broken in private matters, upon account of rebellion; but keeps those two duties of honour and allegiance perfectly distinct and separate. As the uniting of them was thought by these philosophers a very subtile invention, this is a convincing proof, that it is not a true one; since no man can either give a promise, or be restrained by its sanction and obligation unknown to himself.
We find that magistrates do not get their authority or the obligation for their subjects to obey them from a promise or original contract. They try to keep from their people, especially the common folk, that their authority comes from such sources. If this were the basis of government, our leaders wouldn’t accept it quietly, which is the most that can be claimed; since what is accepted quietly can never have the same impact on people as what is done openly and clearly. A silent promise is where the intention is shown through other, less direct signs than speech; but there must be a will behind it, and that will can never be completely unnoticed by the person who expressed it, no matter how silent or informal it was. If you were to ask most people in the nation if they ever agreed to their rulers' authority or promised to obey them, they would likely think you were strange and would definitely respond that the issue doesn’t rely on their consent, but rather that they were born into this obedience. Because of this belief, we often see them considering some individuals to be their natural rulers, even when those individuals lack any power or authority, and whom no person, however foolish, would willingly choose; simply because they are in the lineage that ruled before, and in the position that used to follow; even if it was so long ago that very few people alive could have ever given any promise of obedience. Does a government have no authority over those who never consented to it, and would view the very idea of such free choice as arrogance and impiety? We see from experience that it punishes them quite readily for what it calls treason and rebellion, which, according to this perspective, amounts to plain injustice. If you argue that by living in its territory, they effectively consented to the established government; I respond that this can only happen when they believe the matter depends on their choice, a view held by few, if any, besides those philosophers. It’s never been claimed as a valid excuse for a rebel that the first act they took as an adult was to wage war against the state’s sovereign; and that while they were a child, they couldn’t bind themselves by their own consent and, upon becoming an adult, clearly demonstrated, by their very first act, that they had no intention of committing to any obligation of obedience. On the contrary, we see that civil laws penalize this offense at the same age as any other crime, which is criminal in itself, regardless of our consent; that is, when the person is fully rational. Whereas for this crime, justice should allow some time in which at least a silent consent could be presumed. Additionally, a person living under an absolute government wouldn’t owe it any allegiance; because, by its nature, it doesn’t rely on consent. But since that is just as natural and common a form of government as any, it must certainly create some obligation; and our experiences clearly show that those subjected to it always think so. This is clear evidence that we don’t usually see our allegiance as stemming from our consent or promise; and further proof is that when our promise is explicitly made for any reason, we always clearly differentiate between the two obligations, believing that one strengthens the other more than repeating the same promise. When no promise is made, a person doesn’t view their faith as broken in private matters due to rebellion; but keeps the duties of honor and allegiance entirely separate. Given that philosophers thought combining these two was a clever concept, it convincingly shows that this idea isn’t accurate; since no one can make a promise or be bound by its sanction and obligation without being aware of it.
SECT. IX OF THE MEASURES OF ALLEGIANCE
Those political writers, who have had recourse to a promise, or original contract, as the source of our allegiance to government, intended to establish a principle, which is perfectly just and reasonable; though the reasoning, upon which they endeavoured to establish it, was fallacious and sophistical. They would prove, that our submission to government admits of exceptions, and that an egregious tyranny in the rulers is sufficient to free the subjects from all ties of allegiance. Since men enter into society, say they, and submit themselves to government, by their free and voluntary consent, they must have in view certain advantages, which they propose to reap from it, and for which they are contented to resign their native liberty. There is, therefore, something mutual engaged on the part of the magistrate, viz, protection and security; and it is only by the hopes he affords of these advantages, that he can ever persuade men to submit to him. But when instead of protection and security, they meet with tyranny and oppression, they are freed from their promises, (as happens in all conditional contracts) and return to that state of liberty, which preceded the institution of government. Men would never be so foolish as to enter into such engagements as should turn entirely to the advantage of others, without any view of bettering their own condition. Whoever proposes to draw any profit from our submission, must engage himself, either expressly or tacitly, to make us reap some advantage from his authority; nor ought he to expect, that without the performance of his part we will ever continue in obedience.
Those political writers who have relied on a promise or an original contract as the basis for our loyalty to government aimed to establish a principle that is completely just and reasonable. However, the reasoning they used to support it was misleading and deceptive. They argue that our obedience to government has limits, and that extreme tyranny from those in power is enough to free the people from all allegiance. They claim that people join society and agree to be governed by their own free will, with the expectation of gaining certain benefits in return for giving up their natural liberty. Hence, there is a mutual obligation on the part of the ruler, which includes protection and security; it's only by offering these benefits that a ruler can get people to submit. But when instead of protection and security, people face tyranny and oppression, they are released from their promises (as is the case with all conditional contracts) and can return to the state of liberty that existed before the government was formed. People wouldn’t be foolish enough to enter into agreements that solely benefit others without expecting to improve their own situation. Anyone who intends to gain from our submission must commit, either explicitly or implicitly, to ensuring we gain some benefit from their authority; they shouldn’t expect that we will remain obedient without them fulfilling their part.
I repeat it: This conclusion is just, though the principles be erroneous; and I flatter myself, that I can establish the same conclusion on more reasonable principles. I shall not take such a compass, in establishing our political duties, as to assert, that men perceive the advantages of government; that they institute government with a view to those advantages; that this institution requires a promise of obedience; which imposes a moral obligation to a certain degree, but being conditional, ceases to be binding, whenever the other contracting party performs not his part of the engagement. I perceive, that a promise itself arises entirely from human conventions, and is invented with a view to a certain interest. I seek, therefore, some such interest more immediately connected with government, and which may be at once the original motive to its institution, and the source of our obedience to it. This interest I find to consist in the security and protection, which we enjoy in political society, and which we can never attain, when perfectly free and independent. As interest, therefore, is the immediate sanction of government, the one can have no longer being than the other; and whenever the civil magistrate carries his oppression so far as to render his authority perfectly intolerable, we are no longer bound to submit to it. The cause ceases; the effect must cease also.
I say it again: This conclusion is fair, even if the principles are flawed; and I believe that I can support the same conclusion with more reasonable principles. I will not take a broad approach in defining our political duties by claiming that people see the benefits of government; that they create government to pursue those benefits; that this creation demands a promise of obedience; which imposes a moral duty to some extent, but being conditional, it no longer applies if the other party fails to fulfill their part of the agreement. I understand that a promise itself stems entirely from human agreements and is created with a specific interest in mind. Therefore, I look for some interest that is directly related to government, which can serve as both the initial motivation for its creation and the reason for our obedience to it. I find that this interest lies in the security and protection we receive in political society, which we can never achieve when completely free and independent. Thus, since interest is the immediate basis of government, one cannot exist without the other; and whenever the civil authority becomes so oppressive that it makes its rule completely unbearable, we are no longer obligated to obey it. The cause ends; the effect must end as well.
So far the conclusion is immediate and direct, concerning the natural obligation which we have to allegiance. As to the moral obligation, we may observe, that the maxim would here be false, that when the cause ceases, the effect must cease also. For there is a principle of human nature, which we have frequently taken notice of, that men are mightily addicted to general rules, and that we often carry our maxims beyond those reasons, which first induced us to establish them. Where cases are similar in many circumstances, we are apt to put them on the same footing, without considering, that they differ in the most material circumstances, and that the resemblance is more apparent than real. It may, therefore, be thought, that in the case of allegiance our moral obligation of duty will not cease, even though the natural obligation of interest, which is its cause, has ceased; and that men may be bound by conscience to submit to a tyrannical government against their own and the public interest. And indeed, to the force of this argument I so far submit, as to acknowledge, that general rules commonly extend beyond the principles, on which they are founded; and that we seldom make any exception to them, unless that exception have the qualities of a general rule, and be founded on very numerous and common instances. Now this I assert to be entirely the present case. When men submit to the authority of others, it is to procure themselves some security against the wickedness and injustice of men, who are perpetually carried, by their unruly passions, and by their present and immediate interest, to the violation of all the laws of society. But as this imperfection is inherent in human nature, we know that it must attend men in all their states and conditions; and that these, whom we chuse for rulers, do not immediately become of a superior nature to the rest of mankind, upon account of their superior power and authority. What we expect from them depends not on a change of their nature but of their situation, when they acquire a more immediate interest in the preservation of order and the execution of justice. But besides that this interest is only more immediate in the execution of justice among their subjects; besides this, I say, we may often expect, from the irregularity of human nature, that they will neglect even this immediate interest, and be transported by their passions into all the excesses of cruelty and ambition.. Our general knowledge of human nature, our observation of the past history of mankind, our experience of present times; all these causes must induce us to open the door to exceptions, and must make us conclude, that we may resist the more violent effects of supreme power, without any crime or injustice.
So far, the conclusion is clear and straightforward regarding our natural obligation to loyalty. As for the moral obligation, we can see that it would be incorrect to say that when the cause ends, the effect must also end. There’s a basic principle of human nature that we’ve often noted: people are strongly inclined toward general rules, and we tend to apply our maxims beyond the reasons that originally led us to create them. When situations share many similarities, we're likely to treat them as the same without recognizing that they vary in crucial ways, making the resemblance more superficial than genuine. Therefore, it could be argued that in the case of loyalty, our moral duty won't end even if the natural obligation of interest, which causes it, has ended; and that individuals might feel a moral obligation to submit to a tyrannical government even when it's against their own and the public's interest. In fact, I acknowledge that general rules typically go beyond the principles they’re based on, and we rarely make exceptions unless those exceptions exhibit the characteristics of general rules and are based on many common instances. I assert that this is exactly the situation we’re facing. When people submit to the authority of others, it’s to protect themselves from the wrongdoing and injustice of those who are driven by their uncontrollable passions and immediate interests to break all societal laws. However, because this flaw is inherent in human nature, we must accept that it will affect people in every state and circumstance; and those we choose as rulers don’t transform into superior beings simply due to their greater power and authority. What we expect from them isn’t based on a change in their nature but rather on a change in their situation when they have a more direct interest in maintaining order and administering justice. Additionally, while this interest is only more immediate in the enforcement of justice among their subjects, we can often expect that, due to the unpredictability of human nature, they might neglect even this immediate interest and be swept away by their passions into acts of cruelty and ambition. Our general understanding of human nature, our observations of the history of mankind, and our experiences in the present all lead us to allow for exceptions and conclude that we can resist the more extreme abuses of authority without committing any crime or injustice.
Accordingly we may observe, that this is both the general practice and principle of mankind, and that no nation, that could find any remedy, ever yet suffered the cruel ravages of a tyrant, or were blamed for their resistance. Those who took up arms against Dionysius or Nero, or Philip the second, have the favour of every reader in the perusal of their history: and nothing but the most violent perversion of common sense can ever lead us to condemn them. It is certain, therefore, that in all our notions of morals we never entertain such an absurdity as that of passive obedience, but make allowances for resistance in the more flagrant instances of tyranny and oppression. The general opinion of mankind has some authority in all cases; but in this of morals it is perfectly infallible. Nor is it less infallible, because men cannot distinctly explain the principles, on which it is founded. Few persons can carry on this train of reasoning:
Therefore, we can see that this is both the common practice and fundamental principle of humanity, and that no nation that could find any solution has ever suffered the brutal attacks of a tyrant or been criticized for resisting. Those who fought against Dionysius, Nero, or Philip II are looked upon favorably by every reader of their history. Only the most extreme twisting of common sense would lead us to judge them harshly. It is clear, then, that in all our ideas about morals, we never entertain the absurdity of passive obedience, but rather allow for resistance in the most outrageous cases of tyranny and oppression. The general opinion of humanity holds some weight in all matters, but in the realm of morals, it is completely reliable. It remains just as reliable, even though people may not clearly articulate the principles it is based on. Few people can follow this line of reasoning:
Government is a mere human invention for the interest of society. Where the tyranny of the governor removes this interest, it also removes the natural obligation to obedience. The moral obligation is founded on the natural, and therefore must cease where that ceases; especially where the subject is such as makes us foresee very many occasions wherein the natural obligation may cease, and causes us to form a kind of general rule for the regulation of our conduct in such occurrences.
Government is simply a human creation meant to serve society's interests. When the governor's tyranny undermines these interests, it also eliminates the natural obligation to obey. The moral obligation is based on the natural one, so it must end when the natural one does; especially in cases where we can anticipate numerous situations in which the natural obligation might end, leading us to establish a general guideline for how we should act in those situations.
But though this train of reasoning be too subtile for the vulgar, it is certain, that all men have an implicit notion of it, and are sensible, that they owe obedience to government merely on account of the public interest; and at the same time, that human nature is so subject to frailties and passions, as may easily pervert this institution, and change their governors into tyrants and public enemies. If the sense of common interest were not our original motive to obedience, I would fain ask, what other principle is there in human nature capable of subduing the natural ambition of men, and forcing them to such a submission? Imitation and custom are not sufficient. For the question still recurs, what motive first produces those instances of submission, which we imitate, and that train of actions, which produces the custom? There evidently is no other principle than public interest; and if interest first produces obedience to government, the obligation to obedience must cease, whenever the interest ceases, in any great degree, and in a considerable number of instances.
But even though this line of reasoning might be too subtle for the average person, it's clear that everyone has an inherent understanding of it and recognizes that they owe loyalty to the government primarily because of the common good. At the same time, human nature is prone to weaknesses and emotions that can easily distort this system, turning their leaders into tyrants and enemies of the people. If the feeling of shared interest wasn't our primary reason for obedience, I would love to know what other principle in human nature can tame people's natural ambition and compel them to submit. Mimicking others and tradition aren't enough. The question still remains: what motivates those initial acts of submission that we copy, and the sequence of actions that creates that tradition? Clearly, there is no other principle than public interest; and if interest is what leads to obedience to government, then the obligation to obey must end whenever that interest fades significantly in a considerable number of cases.
SECT. X OF THE OBJECTS OF ALLEGIANCE
But though, on some occasions, it may be justifiable, both in sound politics and morality, to resist supreme power, it is certain, that in the ordinary course of human affairs nothing can be more pernicious and criminal; and that besides the convulsions, which always attend revolutions, such a practice tends directly to the subversion of all government, and the causing an universal anarchy and confusion among mankind. As numerous and civilized societies cannot subsist without government, so government is entirely useless without an exact obedience. We ought always to weigh the advantages, which we reap from authority, against the disadvantages; and by this means we shall become more scrupulous of putting in practice the doctrine of resistance. The common rule requires submission; and it is only in cases of grievous tyranny and oppression, that the exception can take place.
But while it may sometimes be justified, both politically and morally, to resist those in power, it’s clear that, in most situations, nothing is more harmful and wrong. Along with the turmoil that always comes with revolutions, such actions directly undermine all governments and lead to widespread chaos and disorder among people. Just as many civilized societies cannot survive without government, government is completely ineffective without strict obedience. We should always consider the benefits we get from authority against the downsides; by doing so, we will be more careful about practicing the idea of resistance. The general rule demands submission, and only in cases of severe tyranny and oppression should there be any exceptions.
Since then such a blind submission is commonly due to magistracy, the next question is, to whom it is due, and whom we are to regard as our lawful magistrates? In order to answer this question, let us recollect what we have already established concerning the origin of government and political society. When men have once experienced the impossibility of preserving any steady order in society, while every one is his own master, and violates or observes the laws of society, according to his present interest or pleasure, they naturally run into the invention of government, and put it out of their own power, as far as possible, to transgress the laws of society. Government, therefore, arises from the same voluntary conversation of men; and it is evident, that the same convention, which establishes government, will also determine the persons who are to govern, and will remove all doubt and ambiguity in this particular. And the voluntary consent of men must here have the greater efficacy, that the authority of the magistrate does at first stand upon the foundation of a promise of the subjects, by which they bind themselves to obedience; as in every other contract or engagement. The same promise, then, which binds them to obedience, ties them down to a particular person, and makes him the object of their allegiance.
Since then, this kind of blind submission is often due to authority, the next question is, to whom is it due, and who should we consider our rightful authorities? To answer this, let’s remember what we’ve established about the origins of government and political society. When people realize they can’t maintain any kind of order in society while everyone acts as their own master, following or breaking societal laws based on their immediate interests or desires, they naturally turn to creating a government, giving up as much of their ability to break the laws as possible. Therefore, government comes from the same voluntary agreement among people; it's clear that the same agreement that creates the government will also identify who is meant to govern and resolve any confusion about this. Moreover, the voluntary consent of individuals is crucial here, as the authority of the magistrate initially rests on a promise from the subjects to obey, just like in any other contract or commitment. Thus, the same promise that obligates them to obey also ties them to a specific individual, making that person the focus of their loyalty.
But when government has been established on this footing for some considerable time, and the separate interest, which we have in submission, has produced a separate sentiment of morality, the case is entirely altered, and a promise is no longer able to determine the particular magistrate since it is no longer considered as the foundation of government. We naturally suppose ourselves born to submission; and imagine, that such particular persons have a right to command, as we on our part are bound to obey. These notions of right and obligation are derived from nothing but the advantage we reap from government, which gives us a repugnance to practise resistance ourselves, and makes us displeased with any instance of it in others. But here it is remarkable, that in this new state of affairs, the original sanction of government, which is interest, is not admitted to determine the persons, whom we are to obey, as the original sanction did at first, when affairs were on the footing of a promise. A promise fixes and determines the persons, without any uncertainty: But it is evident, that if men were to regulate their conduct in this particular, by the view of a peculiar interest, either public or private, they would involve themselves in endless confusion, and would render all government, in a great measure, ineffectual. The private interest of every one is different; and though the public interest in itself be always one and the same, yet it becomes the source of as great dissentions, by reason of the different opinions of particular persons concerning it. The same interest, therefore, which causes us to submit to magistracy, makes us renounce itself in the choice of our magistrates, and binds us down to a certain form of government, and to particular persons, without allowing us to aspire to the utmost perfection in either. The case is here the same as in that law of nature concerning the stability of possession. It is highly advantageous, and even absolutely necessary to society, that possession should be stable; and this leads us to the establishment of such a rule: But we find, that were we to follow the same advantage, in assigning particular possessions to particular persons, we should disappoint our end, and perpetuate the confusion, which that rule is intended to prevent. We must, therefore, proceed by general rules, and regulate ourselves by general interests, in modifying the law of nature concerning the stability of possession. Nor need we fear, that our attachment to this law will diminish upon account of the seeming frivolousness of those interests, by which it is determined. The impulse of the mind is derived from a very strong interest; and those other more minute interests serve only to direct the motion, without adding any thing to it, or diminishing from it. It is the same case with government. Nothing is more advantageous to society than such an invention; and this interest is sufficient to make us embrace it with ardour and alacrity; though we are obliged afterwards to regulate and direct our devotion to government by several considerations, which are not of the same importance, and to chuse our magistrates without having in view any particular advantage from the choice.
But when government has been set up like this for a significant amount of time, and the individual interest we have in obeying has created a distinct sense of morality, everything changes, and a promise can no longer define who the particular authority is, since it is no longer seen as the basis of government. We naturally assume we are born to submit and believe that certain people have the right to command, while we are obligated to obey. These ideas of rights and obligations come solely from the benefits we get from government, which makes us resistant to resisting ourselves and makes us uncomfortable with any acts of resistance in others. It’s worth noting that in this new situation, the original basis of government, which is interest, no longer dictates who we should obey, as it did at first when things were based on promises. A promise clearly identifies who is in charge, without any ambiguity. However, if people started to govern their behavior based on particular interests, whether public or private, they would end up in endless confusion and make government largely ineffective. Each person's private interest is different, and while public interest itself is always the same, it leads to significant disagreements because of differing individual opinions about it. Therefore, the same interest that causes us to obey magistrates also makes us reject that interest when choosing our magistrates, binding us to a specific form of government and certain individuals while preventing us from striving for the highest ideals in either. The situation here mirrors the natural law regarding the stability of possession. It's very beneficial, and even essential for society, that possession remains stable, which leads us to establish such a rule. However, if we were to pursue that same benefit by assigning specific possessions to specific people, we would undermine our goal and continue the confusion that the rule is meant to avoid. We must, therefore, apply general rules and align ourselves with general interests when adapting the natural law regarding the stability of possession. We shouldn't worry that our commitment to this law will lessen because of the seemingly trivial interests that underlie it. The drive of the mind comes from a strong interest, and those other smaller interests merely help guide the motion without adding to it or taking away from it. The same is true for government. Nothing is more beneficial to society than this system; and this interest is enough to make us embrace it eagerly and energetically, even though we later need to manage our commitment to government by various considerations that aren't as significant, and choose our officials without aiming for specific personal gain from that choice.
The first of those principles I shall take notice of, as a foundation of the right of magistracy, is that which gives authority to all the most established governments of the world without exception: I mean, long possession in any one form of government, or succession of princes. It is certain, that if we remount to the first origin of every nation, we shall find, that there scarce is any race of kings, or form of a commonwealth, that is not primarily founded on usurpation and rebellion, and whose title is not at first worse than doubtful and uncertain. Time alone gives solidity to their right; and operating gradually on the minds of men, reconciles them to any authority, and makes it seem just and reasonable. Nothing causes any sentiment to have a greater influence upon us than custom, or turns our imagination more strongly to any object. When we have been long accustomed to obey any set of men, that general instinct or tendency, which we have to suppose a moral obligation attending loyalty, takes easily this direction, and chuses that set of men for its objects. It is interest which gives the general instinct; but it is custom which gives the particular direction.
The first principle I want to highlight, which forms the basis of governmental authority, is the one that grants power to all the established governments in the world without exception: long-standing possession in any form of government or succession of rulers. It's clear that if we trace back to the origins of every nation, we will find that hardly any royal lineage or form of government isn't initially rooted in usurpation and rebellion. Their legitimacy is often questionable from the start. Only time gives them solid legitimacy; it gradually influences people's minds, making them accept any authority and perceive it as just and reasonable. Nothing shapes our feelings more profoundly than custom, nor does anything direct our thoughts more strongly toward a particular authority. When we grow used to obeying a specific group of people, our instinct to view loyalty as a moral obligation easily follows that group and chooses them as its object. It's self-interest that generates the general instinct, but it's custom that provides the specific direction.
And here it is observable, that the same length of time has a different influence on our sentiments of morality, according to its different influence on the mind. We naturally judge of every thing by comparison; and since in considering the fate of kingdoms and republics, we embrace a long extent of time, a small duration has not in this case a like influence on our sentiments, as when we consider any other object. One thinks he acquires a right to a horse, or a suit of cloaths, in a very short time; but a century is scarce sufficient to establish any new government, or remove all scruples in the minds of the subjects concerning it. Add to this, that a shorter period of time will suffice to give a prince a title to any additional power he may usurp, than will serve to fix his right, where the whole is an usurpation. The kings of France have not been possessed of absolute power for above two reigns; and yet nothing will appear more extravagant to Frenchmen than to talk of their liberties. If we consider what has been said concerning accession, we shall easily account for this phænomenon.
And here it’s clear that the same amount of time affects our feelings about morality differently, depending on how it impacts the mind. We naturally judge everything through comparison; and since we look at the fate of kingdoms and republics, we consider a long period of time, which means a short duration doesn’t affect our feelings in the same way as it does with other things. One might feel they acquire the right to a horse or a set of clothes in no time, but it takes almost a century to establish a new government or resolve all doubts in the minds of the people about it. Additionally, a shorter amount of time is enough for a ruler to claim any extra power they take, compared to what it takes to secure their right when the whole situation is an usurpation. The kings of France haven’t held absolute power for more than two reigns, and yet nothing seems more outrageous to the French than talking about their liberties. If we reflect on what has been said about accession, we can easily explain this phenomenon.
When there is no form of government established by long possession, the present possession is sufficient to supply its place, and may be regarded as the second source of all public authority. Right to authority is nothing but the constant possession of authority, maintained by the laws of society and the interests of mankind; and nothing can be more natural than to join this constant possession to the present one, according to the principles above-mentioned. If the same principles did not take place with regard to the property of private persons, it was because these principles were counter-ballanced by very strong considerations of interest; when we observed, that all restitution would by that means be prevented, and every violence be authorized and protected. And though the same motives may seem to have force, with regard to public authority, yet they are opposed by a contrary interest; which consists in the preservation of peace, and the avoiding of all changes, which, however they may be easily produced in private affairs, are unavoidably attended with bloodshed and confusion, where the public is interested.
When there isn’t an established government from long-term possession, the current possession is enough to fill that role and can be seen as the second source of all public authority. The right to authority is simply the ongoing possession of that authority, upheld by social laws and the needs of humanity; and it makes sense to link this ongoing possession to the current one, based on the principles mentioned earlier. If these same principles did not apply to private property, it was because they were balanced by strong considerations of interest; we noticed that any restitution would be blocked and any violence would be justified and protected. Although the same motivations might seem relevant concerning public authority, they are countered by a different interest, which is the maintenance of peace and the avoidance of changes, which, while easily made in personal matters, inevitably lead to violence and chaos when public interests are involved.
Any one, who finding the impossibility of accounting for the right of the present possessor, by any received system of ethics, should resolve to deny absolutely that right, and assert, that it is not authorized by morality, would be justly thought to maintain a very extravagant paradox, and to shock the common sense and judgment of mankind. No maxim is more conformable, both to prudence and morals, than to submit quietly to the government, which we find established in the country where we happen to live, without enquiring too curiously into its origin and first establishment. Few governments will bear being examined so rigorously. How many kingdoms are there at present in the world, and how many more do we find in history, whose governors have no better foundation for their authority than that of present possession? To confine ourselves to the Roman and Grecian empire; is it not evident, that the long succession of emperors, from the dissolution of the Roman liberty, to the final extinction of that empire by the Turks, could not so much as pretend to any other title to the empire? The election of the senate was a mere form, which always followed the choice of the legions; and these were almost always divided in the different provinces, and nothing but the sword was able to terminate the difference. It was by the sword, therefore, that every emperor acquired, as well as defended his right; and we must either say, that all the known world, for so many ages, had no government, and owed no allegiance to any one, or must allow, that the right of the stronger, in public affairs, is to be received as legitimate, and authorized by morality, when not opposed by any other title.
Anyone who finds it impossible to justify the right of the current possessor using any accepted ethical system and decides to completely deny that right, claiming it isn’t supported by morality, would rightly be seen as holding a very extreme view that goes against common sense and the judgment of people. No principle aligns more closely with both wisdom and morality than to peacefully accept the government that exists in the country where we live, without probing too deeply into how it started or was established. Few governments can withstand such close scrutiny. How many kingdoms exist today, and how many more have existed in history, where their leaders have no better claim to authority than their current possession? If we focus on the Roman and Greek empires, isn’t it clear that the long line of emperors, from the fall of Roman liberty until the final end of that empire by the Turks, could not even pretend to have any other claim to power? The election of the Senate was merely a formality that always followed the choice of the legions, which were often divided across different provinces, and only the sword could settle these disputes. Therefore, every emperor gained and upheld his right through force; we must either concede that the entire known world, for so many ages, had no government and owed allegiance to no one, or accept that the right of the stronger in public matters should be regarded as legitimate and morally supported when no other claim stands against it.
The right of conquest may be considered as a third source of the title of sovereigns. This right resembles very much that of present possession; but has rather a superior force, being seconded by the notions of glory and honour, which we ascribe to conquerors, instead of the sentiments of hatred and detestation, which attend usurpers. Men naturally favour those they love; and therefore are more apt to ascribe a right to successful violence, betwixt one sovereign and another, than to the successful rebellion of a subject against his sovereign.[11]
The right of conquest can be seen as a third source of sovereign authority. This right is quite similar to the idea of current ownership, but it carries a stronger weight, supported by the ideas of glory and honor associated with conquerors, rather than the feelings of hatred and disgust that accompany usurpers. People naturally support those they admire; therefore, they are more likely to recognize a right to the successful violence between sovereigns than to the successful rebellion of a subject against their ruler.[11]
[11] It is not here asserted, that present possession or conquest are sufficient to give a title against long possession and positive laws but only that they have some force, and will be able to call the ballance where the titles are otherwise equal, and will even be sufficient sometimes to sanctify the weaker title. What degree of force they have is difficult to determine. I believe all moderate men will allow, that they have great force in all disputes concerning the rights of princes.
[11] It’s not claimed here that current possession or conquest alone are enough to establish a title against long-standing possession and established laws, but rather that they hold some weight and can tip the scales when titles are otherwise equal, and can sometimes even legitimize a weaker title. Determining how much weight they actually carry is challenging. I think most reasonable people would agree that they have significant influence in all discussions regarding the rights of rulers.
When neither long possession, nor present possession, nor conquest take place, as when the first sovereign, who founded any monarchy, dies; in that case, the right of succession naturally prevails in their stead, and men are commonly induced to place the son of their late monarch on the throne, and suppose him to inherit his father's authority. The presumed consent of the father, the imitation of the succession to private families, the interest, which the state has in chusing the person, who is most powerful, and has the most numerous followers; all these reasons lead men to prefer the son of their late monarch to any other person.[12]
When there's no long possession, current possession, or conquest—like when the first ruler who established a monarchy dies—the right of succession naturally takes over. People are usually inclined to place the late monarch’s son on the throne, believing he inherits his father's authority. The assumed consent of the father, the tradition of succession in private families, and the interest the state has in choosing the most capable and supported individual all lead people to favor the son of the late monarch over anyone else.[12]
[12] To prevent mistakes I must observe, that this case of succession is not the same with that of hereditary monarchies, where custom has fix'd the right of succession. These depend upon the principle of long possession above explain'd.
[12] To avoid confusion, I must point out that this situation of succession is different from hereditary monarchies, where tradition has established the right of succession. These rely on the principle of long-term possession mentioned earlier.
These reasons have some weight; but I am persuaded, that to one, who considers impartially of the matter, it will appear, that there concur some principles of the imagination, along with those views of interest. The royal authority seems to be connected with the young prince even in his father's life-time, by the natural transition of the thought; and still more after his death: So that nothing is more natural than to compleat this union by a new relation, and by putting him actually in possession of what seems so naturally to belong to him.
These reasons hold some weight, but I believe that for anyone who looks at the situation fairly, it will be clear that there are also some imaginative principles at play, alongside those considerations of interest. The royal authority seems linked to the young prince even while his father is alive, and even more so after his death. Therefore, it's completely natural to solidify this connection through a new relationship and by giving him actual control over what seems like it rightfully belongs to him.
To confirm this we may weigh the following phaenomena, which are pretty curious in their kind. In elective monarchies the right of succession has no place by the laws and settled custom; and yet its influence is so natural, that it is impossible entirely to exclude it from the imagination, and render the subjects indifferent to the son of their deceased monarch. Hence in some governments of this kind, the choice commonly falls on one or other of the royal family; and in some governments they are all excluded. Those contrary phaenomena proceed from the same principle. Where the royal family is excluded, it is from a refinement in politics, which makes people sensible of their propensity to chuse a sovereign in that family, and gives them a jealousy of their liberty, lest their new monarch, aided by this propensity, should establish his family, and destroy the freedom of elections for the future.
To confirm this, we can look at some interesting phenomena. In elective monarchies, the right of succession isn't established by laws or customs, yet its influence is so natural that it's impossible to completely ignore it or make people indifferent to the son of their deceased monarch. As a result, in some governments like these, the choice usually falls on someone from the royal family, while in others, they are all excluded. These opposing phenomena stem from the same principle. When the royal family is excluded, it’s a political strategy that makes people aware of their tendency to choose a ruler from that family, leading to concerns about their freedom. They worry that their new monarch might use this tendency to establish their dynasty and undermine the freedom of elections in the future.
The history of Artaxerxes, and the younger Cyrus, may furnish us with some reflections to the same purpose. Cyrus pretended a right to the throne above his elder brother, because he was born after his father's accession. I do not pretend, that this reason was valid. I would only infer from it, that he would never have made use of such a pretext, were it not for the qualities of the imagination above-mentioned, by which we are naturally inclined to unite by a new relation whatever objects we find already united. Artaxerxes had an advantage above his brother, as being the eldest son, and the first in succession: But Cyrus was more closely related to the royal authority, as being begot after his father was invested with it.
The story of Artaxerxes and his younger brother Cyrus can give us some insights on this topic. Cyrus claimed a right to the throne over his older brother because he was born after their father became king. I’m not saying this reasoning was valid. I only want to point out that he wouldn’t have used such an excuse if it weren’t for the imaginative tendencies I mentioned earlier, which lead us to connect whatever things we find already related. Artaxerxes had the advantage of being the oldest son and the first in line for the throne, but Cyrus felt more closely tied to royal power since he was born after their father assumed his role as king.
Should it here be pretended, that the view of convenience may be the source of all the right of succession, and that men gladly take advantage of any rule, by which they can fix the successor of their late sovereign, and prevent that anarchy and confusion, which attends all new elections? To this I would answer, that I readily allow, that this motive may contribute something to the effect; but at the same time I assert, that without another principle, it is impossible such a motive should take place. The interest of a nation requires, that the succession to the crown should be fixed one way or other; but it is the same thing to its interest in what way it be fixed: So that if the relation of blood had not an effect independent of public interest, it would never have been regarded, without a positive law; and it would have been impossible, that so many positive laws of different nations could ever have concured precisely in the same views and intentions.
If someone claims that the desire for convenience is the main reason for succession rights, and that people eagerly take advantage of any rule that allows them to name the successor of their deceased leader to avoid the chaos of new elections, I'd respond that while I agree this motivation may play a role, I also maintain that without another principle, such a motivation couldn't exist. The interests of a nation demand that the line of succession for the crown be established in one way or another, and the nation's interests don't depend on how it's established. Therefore, if the bloodline didn't have significance beyond public interest, it wouldn't have been considered without a formal law. Moreover, it would have been impossible for so many laws across different nations to align so precisely in their aims and intentions.
This leads us to consider the fifth source of authority, viz. positive laws; when the legislature establishes a certain form of government and succession of princes. At first sight it may be thought, that this must resolve into some of the preceding titles of authority. The legislative power, whence the positive law is derived, must either be established by original contract, long possession, present possession, conquest, or succession; and consequently the positive law must derive its force from some of those principles. But here it is remarkable, that though a positive law can only derive its force from these principles, yet it acquires not all the force of the principle from whence it is derived, but loses considerably in the transition; as it is natural to imagine. For instance; a government is established for many centuries on a certain system of laws, forms, and methods of succession. The legislative power, established by this long succession, changes all on a sudden the whole system of government, and introduces a new constitution in its stead. I believe few of the subjects will think themselves bound to comply with this alteration, unless it have an evident tendency to the public good: But men think themselves still at liberty to return to the antient government. Hence the notion of fundamental laws; which are supposed to be inalterable by the will of the sovereign: And of this nature the Salic law is understood to be in France. How far these fundamental laws extend is not determined in any government; nor is it possible it ever should. There is such an indefensible gradation from the most material laws to the most trivial, and from the most ancient laws to the most modern, that it will be impossible to set bounds to the legislative power, and determine how far it may innovate in the principles of government. That is the work more of imagination and passion than of reason.
This brings us to the fifth source of authority, which is positive laws; when the legislature establishes a specific form of government and a succession of leaders. At first glance, it might seem that this must connect to some of the previous types of authority. The legislative power, from which positive law comes, must be based on original agreement, long-standing possession, current possession, conquest, or succession; therefore, the positive law must derive its strength from one of those principles. However, it's important to note that while a positive law can only gain its strength from these principles, it doesn’t retain all the power of its source but significantly loses it in the process, as one might expect. For example, if a government has been established for many centuries under a specific system of laws, forms, and methods of succession, and then the legislative power suddenly changes the entire government system and introduces a new constitution, I believe few citizens will feel obliged to accept this change unless it clearly benefits the public good. People tend to think they can revert to the old government. This leads to the idea of fundamental laws, which are believed to be unchangeable by the will of the ruler; the Salic law in France is an example of this. The extent of these fundamental laws isn't clearly defined in any government, nor is it likely it ever will be. There is such an unresolvable range from the most significant laws to the most minor, and from ancient laws to the most recent, that it's impossible to limit the legislative power and decide how far it can innovate in the principles of government. This task relies more on imagination and emotion than on reason.
Whoever considers the history of the several nations of the world; their revolutions, conquests, increase, and diminution; the manner in which their particular governments are established, and the successive right transmitted from one person to another, will soon learn to treat very lightly all disputes concerning the rights of princes, and will be convinced, that a strict adherence to any general rules, and the rigid loyalty to particular persons and families, on which some people set so high a value, are virtues that hold less of reason, than of bigotry and superstition. In this particular, the study of history confirms the reasonings of true philosophy; which, shewing us the original qualities of human nature, teaches us to regard the controversies in politics as incapable of any decision in most cases, and as entirely subordinate to the interests of peace and liberty. Where the public good does not evidently demand a change; it is certain, that the concurrence of all those titles, original contract, long possession, present possession, succession, and positive laws, forms the strongest title to sovereignty, and is justly regarded as sacred and inviolable. But when these titles are mingled and opposed in different degrees, they often occasion perplexity; and are less capable of solution from the arguments of lawyers and philosophers, than from the swords of the soldiery. Who shall tell me, for instance, whether Germanicus, or Drufus, ought to have succeeded Tiberius, had he died while they were both alive, without naming any of them for his successor? Ought the right of adoption to be received as equivalent to that of blood in a nation, where it had the same effect in private families, and had already, in two instances, taken place in the public? Ought Germanicus to be esteemed the eldest son, because he was born before Drufus; or the younger, because he was adopted after the birth of his brother? Ought the right of the elder to be regarded in a nation, where the eldest brother had no advantage in the succession to private families? Ought the Roman empire at that time to be esteemed hereditary, because of two examples; or ought it, even so early, to be regarded as belonging to the stronger, or the present possessor, as being founded on so recent an usurpation? Upon whatever principles we may pretend to answer these and such like questions, I am afraid we shall never be able to satisfy an impartial enquirer, who adopts no party in political controversies, and will be satisfied with nothing but sound reason and philosophy.
Whoever looks at the history of different nations; their revolutions, conquests, growth, and decline; how their specific governments are set up, and the rights passed from one person to another, will soon realize that all debates about the rights of leaders should be taken lightly. They will come to understand that strict loyalty to any general rules, or rigid allegiance to specific individuals and families, which some people value highly, are more about bigotry and superstition than reason. In this respect, studying history supports the arguments of real philosophy, which shows us the basic qualities of human nature and teaches us to see political disputes as often unsolvable and ultimately subordinate to the needs for peace and freedom. When the public good does not clearly require a change, it's clear that the combination of all those titles—original contract, long possession, current possession, succession, and positive laws—forms the strongest claim to sovereignty and should be considered sacred and untouchable. However, when these titles are mixed and opposed in various ways, they often lead to confusion, and are less likely to be resolved by the arguments of lawyers and philosophers than by the swords of soldiers. Who can tell me, for example, whether Germanicus or Drufus should have succeeded Tiberius if he had died while both were alive and had not named a successor? Should the right of adoption be seen as equal to that of blood in a society where it had the same effect in private families and had already occurred publicly in two cases? Should Germanicus be considered the older son because he was born before Drufus, or the younger one because he was adopted after his brother's birth? Should the right of the older brother matter in a society where the eldest brother has no advantage in cashing in on family succession? Should the Roman Empire at that time be seen as hereditary based on two examples, or should it instead, even at that early stage, be treated as belonging to the stronger or current possessor, given that it was founded on such recent usurpation? Regardless of the principles we might claim to use to answer these questions, I fear we may never satisfy an unbiased inquirer who takes no side in political disputes and seeks only solid reason and philosophy.
But here an English reader will be apt to enquire concerning that famous revolution, which has had such a happy influence on our constitution, and has been attended with such mighty consequences. We have already remarked, that in the case of enormous tyranny and oppression, it is lawful to take arms even against supreme power; and that as government is a mere human invention for mutual advantage and security, it no longer imposes any obligation, either natural or moral, when once it ceases to have that tendency. But though this general principle be authorized by common sense, and the practice of all ages, it is certainly impossible for the laws, or even for philosophy, to establish any particular rules, by which we may know when resistance is lawful; and decide all controversies, which may arise on that subject. This may not only happen with regard to supreme power; but it is possible, even in some constitutions, where the legislative authority is not lodged in one person, that there may be a magistrate so eminent and powerful, as to oblige the laws to keep silence in this particular. Nor would this silence be an effect only of their respect, but also of their prudence; since it is certain, that in the vast variety of circumstances, which occur in all governments, an exercise of power, in so great a magistrate, may at one time be beneficial to the public, which at another time would be pernicious and tyrannical. But notwithstanding this silence of the laws in limited monarchies, it is certain, that the people still retain the right of resistance; since it is impossible, even in the most despotic governments, to deprive them of it. The same necessity of self-preservation, and the same motive of public good, give them the same liberty in the one case as in the other. And we may farther observe, that in such mixed governments, the cases, wherein resistance is lawful, must occur much oftener, and greater indulgence be given to the subjects to defend themselves by force of arms, than in arbitrary governments. Not only where the chief magistrate enters into measures, in themselves, extremely pernicious to the public, but even when he would encroach on the other parts of the constitution, and extend his power beyond the legal bounds, it is allowable to resist and dethrone him; though such resistance and violence may, in the general tenor of the laws, be deemed unlawful and rebellious. For besides that nothing is more essential to public interest, than the preservation of public liberty; it is evident, that if such a mixed government be once supposed to be established, every part or member of the constitution must have a right of self-defence, and of maintaining its ancient bounds against the encroachment of every other authority. As matter would have been created in vain, were it deprived of a power of resistance, without which no part of it could preserve a distinct existence, and the whole might be crowded up into a single point: So it is a gross absurdity to suppose, in any government, a right without a remedy, or allow, that the supreme power is shared with the people, without allowing, that it is lawful for them to defend their share against every invader. Those, therefore, who would seem to respect our free government, and yet deny the right of resistance, have renounced all pretensions to common sense, and do not merit a serious answer.
But here, an English reader might wonder about that famous revolution, which has positively impacted our constitution and led to significant consequences. We've noted that in cases of extreme tyranny and oppression, it's acceptable to take up arms against even the highest power; and since government is just a human invention for mutual benefit and security, it no longer has any natural or moral obligation when it stops serving that purpose. However, while this general principle is supported by common sense and the practices throughout history, it’s impossible for laws or even philosophy to create specific rules to determine when resistance is lawful or to resolve all disputes on that issue. This can happen not just regarding supreme power, but it’s also possible in some constitutions where legislative authority isn’t held by one person, that there may be a magistrate so significant and powerful that the laws become silent on this matter. That silence wouldn’t just show respect; it would also be a matter of prudence since, in the countless situations that arise in all governments, the exercise of power by such a magistrate could be beneficial to the public at one point and harmful and tyrannical at another. Yet, despite this silence of the laws in limited monarchies, the people still have the right to resist; after all, it’s impossible, even in the most oppressive governments, to strip them of this right. The same need for self-preservation and the same concern for public good grant them the same freedom in both situations. Furthermore, in mixed governments, the instances where resistance is justified are likely to occur much more frequently, and subjects are given greater leeway to defend themselves with force than in arbitrary governments. Not only where the chief magistrate engages in actions that are severely damaging to the public, but even when he tries to overstep his authority and expand his power beyond legal limits, it's acceptable to resist and remove him; even if such resistance might be deemed unlawful and rebellious by the laws as a whole. Since nothing is more crucial to the public interest than maintaining public liberty, it’s clear that if such a mixed government is assumed to be established, every part or member of the constitution has a right to self-defense and to uphold its original boundaries against any encroachment by other authorities. Just as matter would have been created in vain if it lacked the power of resistance, without which no part of it could exist separately, leading to the entire thing collapsing into a single point; it’s absurd to suggest that any government could have rights without remedies, or allow that supreme power is shared with the people without recognizing that it’s lawful for them to defend their portion against any invader. Therefore, those who claim to respect our free government while denying the right of resistance have abandoned all pretense of common sense and don’t deserve a serious response.
It does not belong to my present purpose to shew, that these general principles are applicable to the late revolution; and that all the rights and privileges, which ought to be sacred to a free nation, were at that time threatened with the utmost danger. I am better pleased to leave this controverted subject, if it really admits of controversy; and to indulge myself in some philosophical reflections, which naturally arise from that important event.
It’s not my goal right now to demonstrate that these general principles apply to the recent revolution, or that all the rights and privileges that should be protected for a free nation were in serious jeopardy at that time. I prefer to step away from this debated topic, if it even deserves to be debated, and instead allow myself to contemplate some philosophical thoughts that naturally emerge from such a significant event.
First, We may observe, that should the lords and commons in our constitution, without any reason from public interest, either depose the king in being, or after his death exclude the prince, who, by laws and settled custom, ought to succeed, no one would esteem their proceedings legal, or think themselves bound to comply with them. But should the king, by his unjust practices, or his attempts for a tyrannical and despotic power, justly forfeit his legal, it then not only becomes morally lawful and suitable to the nature of political society to dethrone him; but what is more, we are apt likewise to think, that the remaining members of the constitution acquire a right of excluding his next heir, and of chusing whom they please for his successor. This is founded on a very singular quality of our thought and imagination. When a king forfeits his authority, his heir ought naturally to remain in the same situation, as if the king were removed by death; unless by mixing himself in the tyranny, he forfeit it for himself. But though this may seem reasonable, we easily comply with the contrary opinion. The deposition of a king, in such a government as ours, is certainly an act beyond all common authority, and an illegal assuming a power for public good, which, in the ordinary course of government, can belong to no member of the constitution. When the public good is so great and so evident as to justify the action, the commendable use of this licence causes us naturally to attribute to the parliament a right of using farther licences; and the antient bounds of the laws being once transgressed with approbation, we are not apt to be so strict in confining ourselves precisely within their limits. The mind naturally runs on with any train of action, which it has begun; nor do we commonly make any scruple concerning our duty, after the first action of any kind, which we perform. Thus at the revolution, no one who thought the deposition of the father justifiable, esteemed themselves to be confined to his infant son; though had that unhappy monarch died innocent at that time, and had his son, by any accident, been conveyed beyond seas, there is no doubt but a regency would have been appointed till he should come to age, and could be restored to his dominions. As the slightest properties of the imagination have an effect on the judgments of the people, it shews the wisdom of the laws and of the parliament to take advantage of such properties, and to chuse the magistrates either in or out of a line, according as the vulgar will most naturally attribute authority and right to them.
First, we can see that if the lords and commons in our constitution were to depose the current king or exclude the rightful prince who is supposed to succeed him, without any valid reason related to public interest, no one would consider their actions legal or feel obligated to follow them. However, if the king unjustly loses his authority through tyrannical or despotic actions, it becomes not only morally acceptable but also fitting for the nature of political society to dethrone him. What's more, we might also believe that the remaining members of the constitution have the right to exclude his next heir and choose anyone they see fit as his successor. This belief is rooted in a unique aspect of our thinking and imagination. When a king loses his authority, his heir should naturally find himself in the same position as if the king had died, unless he has involved himself in his father’s tyranny, in which case he loses that right as well. Although this might seem reasonable, we often accept the opposite view. Dethroning a king in our type of government is undoubtedly an act beyond ordinary authority, and it assumes a power for public good that no member of the constitution should normally possess. When the public good is so significant and clear that it justifies such an action, the legitimate use of this power leads us to attribute to Parliament a right to exercise further powers. Once the traditional limits of the laws are crossed with approval, we aren't usually strict about sticking to those limits. The mind tends to follow any course of action once it has started, and we typically don't question our duty after the first action we take. Thus, during the revolution, no one who believed in the justification of deposing the father felt restricted by the presence of his infant son. If that unfortunate monarch had died innocent during that time and his son had been taken abroad, it’s certain that a regency would have been established until he came of age and could reclaim his throne. Since even minor elements of imagination can influence public judgment, it shows the wisdom of the laws and Parliament to take advantage of these elements and choose magistrates either within or outside a lineage, based on how the general public most naturally attributes authority and legitimacy to them.
Secondly, Though the accession of the Prince of Orange to the throne might at first give occasion to many disputes, and his title be contested, it ought not now to appear doubtful, but must have acquired a sufficient authority from those three princes, who have succeeded him upon the same title. Nothing is more usual, though nothing may, at first sight, appear more unreasonable, than this way of thinking. Princes often seem to acquire a right from their successors, as well as from their ancestors; and a king, who during his life-time might justly be deemed an usurper, will be regarded by posterity as a lawful prince, because he has had the good fortune to settle his family on the throne, and entirely change the antient form of government. Julius Caesar is regarded as the first Roman emperor; while Sylla and Marius, whose titles were really the same as his, are treated as tyrants and usurpers. Time and custom give authority to all forms of government, and all successions of princes; and that power, which at first was founded only on injustice and violence, becomes in time legal and obligatory. Nor does the mind rest there; but returning back upon its footsteps, transfers to their predecessors and ancestors that right, which it naturally ascribes to the posterity, as being related together, and united in the imagination. The present king of France makes Hugh Capet a more lawful prince than Cromwell; as the established liberty of the Dutch is no inconsiderable apology for their obstinate resistance to Philip the second.
Secondly, although the Prince of Orange’s rise to the throne may initially spark many disputes and his claim might be challenged, it shouldn’t seem uncertain now; he must have gained enough legitimacy from the three princes who followed him under the same title. It's quite common, even if it appears unreasonable at first glance, to think this way. Rulers often seem to gain legitimacy from their successors just as much as from their ancestors; a king who might have been seen as an usurper during his lifetime can be viewed by future generations as a rightful monarch, simply because he managed to establish his family on the throne and completely transform the old system of government. Julius Caesar is seen as the first Roman emperor, while Sylla and Marius, who had similar claims, are considered tyrants and usurpers. Time and tradition lend legitimacy to all forms of government and all lines of rulers; what initially arises from injustice and force can eventually become legal and obligatory. Moreover, the mind goes further back, transferring to their predecessors and ancestors the legitimacy that it naturally attributes to their descendants, as they are perceived to be connected and unified in thought. The current king of France regards Hugh Capet as a more legitimate ruler than Cromwell; similarly, the established freedom of the Dutch serves as a significant justification for their stubborn resistance against Philip the Second.
SECT. XI OF THE LAWS OF NATIONS
When civil government has been established over the greatest part of mankind, and different societies have been formed contiguous to each other, there arises a new set of duties among the neighbouring states, suitable to the nature of that commerce, which they carry on with each other. Political writers tell us, that in every kind of intercourse, a body politic is to be considered as one person; and indeed this assertion is so far just, that different nations, as well as private persons, require mutual assistance; at the same time that their selfishness and ambition are perpetual sources of war and discord. But though nations in this particular resemble individuals, yet as they are very different in other respects, no wonder they regulate themselves by different maxims, and give rise to a new set of rules, which we call the laws of nations. Under this head we may comprize the sacredness of the persons of ambassadors, the declaration of war, the abstaining from poisoned arms, with other duties of that kind, which are evidently calculated for the commerce, that is peculiar to different societies.
When civil government has been established over most of humanity, and different societies have formed next to each other, a new set of responsibilities arises among neighboring states, reflecting the nature of their commerce with one another. Political writers tell us that in every type of interaction, a political entity should be seen as a single person; and this idea is somewhat accurate, as different nations, like individuals, need mutual support, while their selfishness and ambition are constant sources of conflict and discord. However, even though nations are comparable to individuals in this way, they are very different in other aspects, so it’s no surprise they follow different principles and create a new set of rules that we call international law. This includes the inviolability of diplomats, the declaration of war, the prohibition of poisoned weapons, and other similar duties that are clearly designed for the unique interactions between different societies.
But though these rules be super-added to the laws of nature, the former do not entirely abolish the latter; and one may safely affirm, that the three fundamental rules of justice, the stability of possession, its transference by consent, and the performance of promises, are duties of princes, as well as of subjects. The same interest produces the same effect in both cases. Where possession has no stability, there must be perpetual war. Where property is not transferred by consent, there can be no commerce. Where promises are not observed, there can be no leagues nor alliances. The advantages, therefore, of peace, commerce, and mutual succour, make us extend to different kingdoms the same notions of justice, which take place among individuals.
But even though these rules are added to the laws of nature, they don’t completely replace them; we can confidently say that the three basic rules of justice—the stability of possession, its transfer by consent, and keeping promises—are responsibilities of both leaders and citizens. The same interests lead to the same outcomes in both situations. When possession isn’t stable, there will always be conflict. When property isn’t transferred with agreement, trade cannot happen. When promises aren’t kept, there can be no treaties or alliances. The benefits of peace, trade, and mutual support encourage us to apply the same ideas of justice across different kingdoms that we use among individuals.
There is a maxim very current in the world, which few politicians are willing to avow, but which has been authorized by the practice of all ages, that there is a system of morals calculated for princes, much more free than that which ought to govern private persons. It is evident this is not to be understood of the lesser extent of public duties and obligations; nor will any one be so extravagant as to assert, that the most solemn treaties ought to have no force among princes. For as princes do actually form treaties among themselves, they must propose some advantage from the execution of them; and the prospect of such advantage for the future must engage them to perform their part, and must establish that law of nature. The meaning, therefore, of this political maxim is, that though the morality of princes has the same extent, yet it has not the same force as that of private persons, and may lawfully be trangressed from a more trivial motive. However shocking such a proposition may appear to certain philosophers, it will be easy to defend it upon those principles, by which we have accounted for the origin of justice and equity.
There’s a commonly accepted saying in the world that few politicians are willing to admit, but has been validated through history, that there’s a set of morals meant for rulers that is much looser than what should guide private individuals. It’s clear that this doesn’t mean a lesser scope of public duties and obligations; nor would anyone be foolish enough to claim that the most important treaties should have no value among rulers. Since rulers actually create treaties with one another, they must expect some benefit from fulfilling them; and the promise of such benefit in the future should motivate them to uphold their end, establishing that law of nature. Therefore, the meaning of this political saying is that while the morality for rulers covers the same ground, it doesn’t carry the same weight as that for individuals, and may be lawfully violated for more trivial reasons. Although this idea may seem shocking to some philosophers, it can be easily defended using the principles we’ve established for the origins of justice and fairness.
When men have found by experience, that it is impossible to subsist without society, and that it is impossible to maintain society, while they give free course to their appetites; so urgent an interest quickly restrains their actions, and imposes an obligation to observe those rules, which we call the laws of justice. This obligation of interest rests nor here; but by the necessary course of the passions and sentiments, gives rise to the moral obligation of duty; while we approve of such actions as tend to the peace of society, and disapprove of such as tend to its disturbance. The same natural obligation of interest takes place among independent kingdoms, and gives rise to the same morality; so that no one of ever so corrupt morals will approve of a prince, who voluntarily, and of his own accord, breaks his word, or violates any treaty. But here we may observe, that though the intercourse of different states be advantageous, and even sometimes necessary, yet it is nor so necessary nor advantageous as that among individuals, without which it is utterly impossible for human nature ever to subsist. Since, therefore, the natural obligation to justice, among different states, is not so strong as among individuals, the moral obligation, which arises from it, must partake of its weakness; and we must necessarily give a greater indulgence to a prince or minister, who deceives another; than to a private gentleman, who breaks his word of honour.
When people have realized through experience that it’s impossible to survive without society, and that society can’t function if everyone acts on their desires, they quickly learn to control their behavior and feel compelled to follow the rules we call the laws of justice. This self-interest doesn’t stop there; through our feelings and emotions, it leads to the moral duty we feel to do the right thing. We support actions that promote peace in society and disapprove of those that disrupt it. The same natural obligation of self-interest exists among independent nations, creating similar moral standards, meaning no one, regardless of their morals, will support a ruler who intentionally breaks their promises or violates a treaty. However, we should note that while interaction between different states can be beneficial and sometimes necessary, it’s not as crucial or beneficial as the relationships among individuals, without which human nature cannot survive. Thus, since the natural obligation to justice among nations is weaker than among individuals, the moral obligation that comes from it will also be weaker; we are generally more forgiving of a prince or official who deceives someone else than we would be of a private citizen who breaks their word.
Should it be asked, what proportion these two species of morality bear to each other? I would answer, that this is a question, to which we can never give any precise answer; nor is it possible to reduce to numbers the proportion, which we ought to fix betwixt them. One may safely affirm, that this proportion finds itself, without any art or study of men; as we may observe on many other occasions. The practice of the world goes farther in teaching us the degrees of our duty, than the most subtile philosophy, which was ever yet invented. And this may serve as a convincing proof, that all men have an implicit notion of the foundation of those moral rules concerning natural and civil justice, and are sensible, that they arise merely from human conventions, and from the interest, which we have in the preservation of peace and order. For otherwise the diminution of the interest would never produce a relaxation of the morality, and reconcile us more easily to any transgression of justice among princes and republics, than in the private commerce of one subject with another.
If we were to ask what the relationship is between these two types of morality, I would say that it’s a question without a clear answer. It's impossible to quantify the ratio we should establish between them. We can confidently say that this ratio exists naturally, without any need for complex thinking or study, as we can observe in many other situations. Real-life experiences teach us about the degrees of our responsibilities more effectively than even the most sophisticated philosophy ever created. This evidence suggests that everyone has an inherent understanding of the basis of moral rules regarding natural and civil justice, recognizing that these rules stem from human agreements and the necessity of maintaining peace and order. Otherwise, a decrease in interest would never lead to a more relaxed view of morality, nor would it make us more accepting of violations of justice among rulers and states compared to the personal interactions between individuals.
SECT. XII OF CHASTITY AND MODESTY
If any difficulty attend this system concerning the laws of nature and nations, it will be with regard to the universal approbation or blame, which follows their observance or transgression, and which some may not think sufficiently explained from the general interests of society. To remove, as far as possible, all scruples of this kind, I shall here consider another set of duties, viz, the modesty and chastity which belong to the fair sex: And I doubt not but these virtues will be found to be still more conspicuous instances of the operation of those principles, which I have insisted on.
If there are any challenges with this system regarding the laws of nature and nations, it will likely relate to the overall approval or disapproval that comes from observing or breaking them, which some might not think is fully explained by the general interests of society. To address any concerns like this, I will now examine another set of duties, specifically the modesty and chastity that are associated with women. I am confident that these virtues will serve as even clearer examples of the principles I have discussed.
There are some philosophers, who attack the female virtues with great vehemence, and fancy they have gone very far in detecting popular errors, when they can show, that there is no foundation in nature for all that exterior modesty, which we require in the expressions, and dress, and behaviour of the fair sex. I believe I may spare myself the trouble of insisting on so obvious a subject, and may proceed, without farther preparation, to examine after what manner such notions arise from education, from the voluntary conventions of men, and from the interest of society.
Some philosophers argue against female virtues very passionately and think they've accomplished a lot by pointing out that there's no natural basis for all the outward modesty we expect in the expressions, clothing, and behavior of women. I believe it's unnecessary for me to dwell on such an obvious topic, and I can move forward, without further ado, to explore how these ideas come from education, from the voluntary agreements of men, and from societal interests.
Whoever considers the length and feebleness of human infancy, with the concern which both sexes naturally have for their offspring, will easily perceive, that there must be an union of male and female for the education of the young, and that this union must be of considerable duration. But in order to induce the men to impose on themselves this restraint, and undergo chearfully all the fatigues and expences, to which it subjects them, they must believe, that the children are their own, and that their natural instinct is not directed to a wrong object, when they give a loose to love and tenderness. Now if we examine the structure of the human body, we shall find, that this security is very difficult to be attained on our part; and that since, in the copulation of the sexes, the principle of generation goes from the man to the woman, an error may easily take place on the side of the former, though it be utterly impossible with regard to the latter. From this trivial and anatomical observation is derived that vast difference betwixt the education and duties of the two sexes.
Whoever thinks about the long and vulnerable period of human infancy, along with the natural concern that both men and women have for their children, will easily see that there needs to be a partnership between males and females for raising the young, and this partnership must last a significant amount of time. To encourage men to voluntarily accept this responsibility and deal with all the challenges and expenses that come with it, they must believe that the children are theirs and that their natural instincts are not misdirected when they express love and care. However, if we look closely at the human body's structure, we'll find that this sense of security is hard to achieve for men; since in the sexual act, the generative principle moves from the man to the woman, a mistake can easily occur on the man's side, while it is completely impossible on the woman's side. This simple anatomical observation leads to the substantial differences in the upbringing and responsibilities of the two sexes.
Were a philosopher to examine the matter a priori, he would reason after the following manner. Men are induced to labour for the maintenance and education of their children, by the persuasion that they are really their own; and therefore it is reasonable, and even necessary, to give them some security in this particular. This security cannot consist entirely in the imposing of severe punishments on any transgressions of conjugal fidelity on the part of the wife; since these public punishments cannot be inflicted without legal proof, which it is difficult to meet with in this subject. What restraint, therefore, shall we impose on women, in order to counter-balance so strong a temptation as they have to infidelity? There seems to be no restraint possible, but in the punishment of bad fame or reputation; a punishment, which has a mighty influence on the human mind, and at the same time is inflicted by the world upon surmizes, and conjectures, and proofs, that would never be received in any court of judicature. In order, therefore, to impose a due restraint on the female sex, we must attach a peculiar degree of shame to their infidelity, above what arises merely from its injustice, and must bestow proportionable praises on their chastity.
If a philosopher were to consider this issue from a theoretical perspective, he would reason like this: People are motivated to work for the support and upbringing of their children because they believe those children truly belong to them. Therefore, it makes sense and is even essential to provide them with some security in this regard. This security can't only be about imposing harsh penalties for any violations of marital fidelity by the wife, since such public punishments require legal proof, which is hard to obtain in this situation. So, what kind of restrictions should we impose on women to counterbalance the strong temptation they may have toward infidelity? It seems that the only possible restraint is the punishment of a tarnished reputation—a punishment that has a significant impact on the human psyche and is often applied by society based on suspicions, assumptions, and evidence that would never be accepted in a court of law. Thus, to properly restrain women, we need to attach a particular level of shame to their unfaithfulness, beyond just its unfairness, and we should also give appropriate recognition to their fidelity.
But though this be a very strong motive to fidelity, our philosopher would quickly discover, that it would not alone be sufficient to that purpose. All human creatures, especially of the female sex, are apt to over-look remote motives in favour of any present temptation: The temptation is here the strongest imaginable: Its approaches are insensible and seducing: And a woman easily finds, or flatters herself she shall find, certain means of securing her reputation, and preventing all the pernicious consequences of her pleasures. It is necessary, therefore, that, beside the infamy attending such licences, there should be some preceding backwardness or dread, which may prevent their first approaches, and may give the female sex a repugnance to all expressions, and postures, and liberties, that have an immediate relation to that enjoyment.
But even though this is a really strong reason to be faithful, our philosopher would soon realize that it's not enough on its own. All human beings, especially women, tend to overlook distant motivations in favor of immediate temptations. Here, the temptation is incredibly strong: its advances are subtle and enticing. A woman often believes she can find ways to protect her reputation and avoid any negative consequences of her pleasures. Therefore, it's important that, besides the shame associated with such freedoms, there should be some initial hesitation or fear that can stop these temptations from taking hold and make women resist any actions, gestures, or liberties that are directly connected to that pleasure.
Such would be the reasonings of our speculative philosopher: But I am persuaded, that if he had not a perfect knowledge of human nature, he would be apt to regard them as mere chimerical speculations, and would consider the infamy attending infidelity, and backwardness to all its approaches, as principles that were rather to be wished than hoped for in the world. For what means, would he say, of persuading mankind, that the transgressions of conjugal duty are more infamous than any other kind of injustice, when it is evident they are more excusable, upon account of the greatness of the temptation? And what possibility of giving a backwardness to the approaches of a pleasure, to which nature has inspired so strong a propensity; and a propensity that it is absolutely necessary in the end to comply with, for the support of the species?
Such would be the thoughts of our thoughtful philosopher: But I believe that if he didn't fully understand human nature, he would tend to see these ideas as just fanciful notions, viewing the shame associated with infidelity and reluctance to engage in it as ideals that are more desirable than realistic in society. For what would he say as a way to convince people that breaking marital commitments is more shameful than any other form of wrongdoing, when it’s clear that such actions are more forgivable due to the intensity of the temptation? And how could one possibly create a reluctance toward engaging in a pleasure that nature has driven us to desire so strongly, a desire that ultimately must be fulfilled for the survival of the species?
But speculative reasonings, which cost so much pains to philosophers, are often formed by the world naturally, and without reflection: As difficulties, which seem unsurmountable in theory, are easily got over in practice. Those, who have an interest in the fidelity of women, naturally disapprove of their infidelity, and all the approaches to it. Those, who have no interest, are carried along with the stream. Education takes possession of the ductile minds of the fair sex in their infancy. And when a general rule of this kind is once established, men are apt to extend it beyond those principles, from which it first arose. Thus batchelors, however debauched, cannot chuse but be shocked with any instance of lewdness or impudence in women. And though all these maxims have a plain reference to generation, yet women past child-bearing have no more privilege in this respect, than those who are in the flower of their youth and beauty. Men have undoubtedly an implicit notion, that all those ideas of modesty and decency have a regard to generation; since they impose not the same laws, with the same force, on the male sex, where that reason takes not place. The exception is there obvious and extensive, and founded on a remarkable difference, which produces a clear separation and disjunction of ideas. But as the case is not the same with regard to the different ages of women, for this reason, though men know, that these notions are founded on the public interest, yet the general rule carries us beyond the original principle, and makes us extend the notions of modesty over the whole sex, from their earliest infancy to their extremest old-age and infirmity.
But speculative reasoning, which takes so much effort for philosophers, often comes naturally to people in the world, without thought: Difficulties that seem insurmountable in theory are easily overcome in practice. Those who have a stake in the loyalty of women naturally disapprove of their disloyalty and all the ways to it. Those who have no stake just go along with the crowd. Education influences the impressionable minds of young women from a very early age. Once a general rule like this is established, men tend to apply it beyond the principles from which it started. Thus, bachelors, no matter how debauched, can't help but be shocked by any instance of immorality or rudeness in women. While all these maxims clearly relate to procreation, women past childbearing age are subject to the same standards in this regard as those who are young and beautiful. Men undoubtedly have an underlying belief that all these ideas of modesty and decency relate to procreation, since they don't impose the same rules with the same force on men, where that reasoning doesn't apply. The exception is clear and significant, creating a clear separation of ideas. However, since the same doesn't apply to the different ages of women, even though men know these ideas are based on public interest, the general rule leads us to extend the notions of modesty across the entire female population, from their earliest childhood to their oldest age and frailty.
Courage, which is the point of honour among men, derives its merit, in a great measure, from artifice, as well as the chastity of women; though it has also some foundation in nature, as we shall see afterwards.
Courage, which is a point of pride among men, gets much of its value from skill and strategy, just like the purity of women; although it also has some basis in nature, as we will discuss later.
As to the obligations which the male sex lie under, with regard to chastity, we may observe, that according to the general notions of the world, they bear nearly the same proportion to the obligations of women, as the obligations of the law of nations do to those of the law of nature. It is contrary to the interest of civil society, that men should have an entire liberty of indulging their appetites in venereal enjoyment: But as this interest is weaker than in the case of the female sex, the moral obligation, arising from it, must be proportionably weaker. And to prove this we need only appeal to the practice and sentiments of all nations and ages.
Regarding the obligations that men have concerning chastity, we can see that, according to common beliefs, these obligations are almost equal in importance to those of women, much like the obligations of international law compared to those of natural law. It goes against the interests of society for men to have complete freedom to indulge in sexual pleasure. However, since this societal interest is less significant than it is for women, the moral obligation stemming from it is also correspondingly weaker. To demonstrate this, we only need to look at the practices and attitudes of all cultures and throughout history.
SECT. I OF THE ORIGIN OF THE NATURAL VIRTUES AND VICES
We come now to the examination of such virtues and vices as are entirely natural, and have no dependance on the artifice and contrivance of men. The examination of these will conclude this system of morals.
We now turn to exploring virtues and vices that are completely natural and don't rely on human trickery or manipulation. This exploration will wrap up this moral framework.
The chief spring or actuating principle of the human mind is pleasure or pain; and when these sensations are removed, both from our thought and feeling, we are, in a great measure, incapable of passion or action, of desire or volition. The most immediate effects of pleasure and pain are the propense and averse motions of the mind; which are diversified into volition, into desire and aversion, grief and joy, hope and fear, according as the pleasure or pain changes its situation, and becomes probable or improbable, certain or uncertain, or is considered as out of our power for the present moment. But when along with this, the objects, that cause pleasure or pain, acquire a relation to ourselves or others; they still continue to excite desire and aversion, grief and joy: But cause, at the same time, the indirect passions of pride or humility, love or hatred, which in this case have a double relation of impressions and ideas to the pain or pleasure.
The main driving force of the human mind is pleasure or pain. When we remove these sensations from our thoughts and feelings, we become largely incapable of passion or action, desire or will. The immediate effects of pleasure and pain lead to the attraction and aversion of the mind, which manifest as will, desire and aversion, sadness and happiness, hope and fear, depending on how the pleasure or pain shifts, becoming likely or unlikely, certain or uncertain, or is seen as out of our control in the moment. However, when the objects that bring pleasure or pain become connected to ourselves or others, they continue to provoke desire and aversion, happiness and sadness, but also give rise to indirect feelings like pride or humility, love or hatred. In this case, these emotions have a dual connection to the impression and ideas related to the pain or pleasure.
We have already observed, that moral distinctions depend entirely on certain peculiar sentiments of pain and pleasure, and that whatever mental quality in ourselves or others gives us a satisfaction, by the survey or reflection, is of course virtuous; as every thing of this nature, that gives uneasiness, is vicious. Now since every quality in ourselves or others, which gives pleasure, always causes pride or love; as every one, that produces uneasiness, excites humility or hatred: It follows, that these two particulars are to be considered as equivalent, with regard to our mental qualities, virtue and the power of producing love or pride, vice and the power of producing humility or hatred. In every case, therefore, we must judge of the one by the other; and may pronounce any quality of the mind virtuous, which causes love or pride; and any one vicious, which causes hatred or humility.
We’ve already noted that moral distinctions are based solely on specific feelings of pain and pleasure, and that any mental quality in ourselves or others that gives us satisfaction upon reflection is virtuous; conversely, anything that causes discomfort is considered vicious. Since every quality in ourselves or others that brings us pleasure tends to evoke pride or love, while any that causes discomfort tends to stimulate humility or hatred, it follows that these two aspects should be seen as equivalent regarding our mental qualities: virtue relates to the ability to produce love or pride, and vice relates to the ability to produce humility or hatred. Therefore, we must evaluate one in relation to the other; we can categorize any mindset that fosters love or pride as virtuous, and any mindset that incites hatred or humility as vicious.
If any action be either virtuous or vicious, it is only as a sign of some quality or character. It must depend upon durable principles of the mind, which extend over the whole conduct, and enter into the personal character. Actions themselves, not proceeding from any constant principle, have no influence on love or hatred, pride or humility; and consequently are never considered in morality.
If any action is either good or bad, it only reflects some quality or trait. It must be based on enduring principles of the mind that influence overall behavior and contribute to personal character. Actions that don't stem from any consistent principle have no effect on feelings of love or hate, pride or humility; therefore, they are never considered in moral judgments.
This reflection is self-evident, and deserves to be attended to, as being of the utmost importance in the present subject. We are never to consider any single action in our enquiries concerning the origin of morals; but only the quality or character from which the action proceeded. These alone are durable enough to affect our sentiments concerning the person. Actions are, indeed, better indications of a character than words, or even wishes and sentiments; but it is only so far as they are such indications, that they are attended with love or hatred, praise or blame.
This reflection is obvious and deserves our attention because it’s crucial to the topic at hand. We should never look at any single action when we explore the origins of morals; instead, we should focus on the quality or character that led to that action. Only these qualities are lasting enough to influence our feelings about the individual. Actions are indeed better indicators of character than words, wishes, or feelings; however, it's only to the extent that they serve as indicators that they provoke love or hatred, praise or blame.
To discover the true origin of morals, and of that love or hatred, which arises from mental qualities, we must take the matter pretty deep, and compare some principles, which have been already examined and explained.
To uncover the real source of morals and the love or hate that comes from our mental traits, we need to dig deeper and compare some principles that have already been looked into and explained.
We may begin with considering a-new the nature and force of sympathy. The minds of all men are similar in their feelings and operations; nor can any one be actuated by any affection, of which all others are not, in some degree, susceptible. As in strings equally wound up, the motion of one communicates itself to the rest; so all the affections readily pass from one person to another, and beget correspondent movements in every human creature. When I see the effects of passion in the voice and gesture of any person, my mind immediately passes from these effects to their causes, and forms such a lively idea of the passion, as is presently converted into the passion itself. In like manner, when I perceive the causes of any emotion, my mind is conveyed to the effects, and is actuated with a like emotion. Were I present at any of the more terrible operations of surgery, it is certain, that even before it begun, the preparation of the instruments, the laying of the bandages in order, the heating of the irons, with all the signs of anxiety and concern in the patient and assistants, would have a great effect upon my mind, and excite the strongest sentiments of pity and terror. No passion of another discovers itself immediately to the mind. We are only sensible of its causes or effects. From these we infer the passion: And consequently these give rise to our sympathy.
Let's start by rethinking the nature and impact of sympathy. The feelings and thoughts of all people are alike; no one can be moved by an emotion that others cannot also feel to some extent. Just like how the vibration of one tightly strung instrument affects the others, emotions easily transfer from one person to another, sparking similar reactions in everyone. When I notice the signs of emotion in someone's voice or body language, my mind quickly jumps from those signs to their underlying causes, creating a vivid picture of the emotion that converts into my own feeling. Similarly, when I recognize the causes of an emotion, my mind shifts to the effects and I feel a similar emotion. If I were in the room for any intense surgical procedure, I know that even before it started, seeing the instruments being prepared, the bandages being laid out, the heating of tools, along with the anxiety of the patient and the medical staff, would deeply affect me, stirring up strong feelings of compassion and fear. No emotion of another person reveals itself to the mind directly. We can only sense its causes or effects. From those, we infer the emotion, which in turn sparks our sympathy.
Our sense of beauty depends very much on this principle; and where any object has atendency to produce pleasure in its possessor, it is always regarded as beautiful; as every object, that has a tendency to produce pain, is disagreeable and deformed. Thus the conveniency of a house, the fertility of a field, the strength of a horse, the capacity, security, and swift-sailing of a vessel, form the principal beauty of these several objects. Here the object, which is denominated beautiful, pleases only by its tendency to produce a certain effect. That effect is the pleasure or advantage of some other person. Now the pleasure of a stranger, for whom we have no friendship, pleases us only by sympathy. To this principle, therefore, is owing the beauty, which we find in every thing that is useful. How considerable a part this is of beauty can easily appear upon reflection. Wherever an object has a tendency to produce pleasure in the possessor, or in other words, is the proper cause of pleasure, it is sure to please the spectator, by a delicate sympathy with the possessor. Most of the works of art are esteemed beautiful, in proportion to their fitness for the use of man, and even many of the productions of nature derive their beauty from that source. Handsome and beautiful, on most occasions, is nor an absolute but a relative quality, and pleases us by nothing but its tendency to produce an end that is agreeable.[1]
Our sense of beauty largely relies on this principle; when an object tends to bring pleasure to its owner, it is considered beautiful, while anything that tends to cause pain is seen as unpleasant and ugly. Thus, the usefulness of a house, the richness of a field, the strength of a horse, and the capacity, safety, and speed of a boat represent the main aspects of beauty in these objects. Here, what we call beautiful pleases us only by its ability to produce a specific effect, that effect being the pleasure or benefit to someone else. The pleasure of a stranger, whom we have no connection with, is pleasing to us only through empathy. Therefore, the beauty we find in anything useful is attributed to this principle. It becomes clear upon reflection how significant this aspect is to beauty. Whenever an object has the potential to bring pleasure to its owner, or in other words, is a true source of pleasure, it will surely please the observer through a subtle empathy with the owner. Most artistic works are considered beautiful based on their suitability for human use, and many natural creations also derive their beauty from this source. Beautiful and attractive are often not absolute qualities but rather relative ones, and they please us only because of their potential to lead to a desirable outcome.[1]
[1] Decentior equus cujus astricta sunt ilia; sed idem velocior. Pulcher aspectu sit athieta, cujus lacertos exercitatio expressit; idem certamini paratior. Nunquam vero species ab utilitate dividitur. Sed hoc quidem discernere, modici judicii est. Quinct. lib. 8. (A horse with narrow flanks looks more comely; It also moves faster. An athlete whose muscles have been developed by training presents a handsome appearance; he is also better prepared for the contest. Attractive appearance is invariably associated with efficient functioning. Yet it takes no outstanding powers of judgement to wake this distinction.)
[1] A horse with narrow flanks looks better; it also runs faster. An athlete whose muscles have been built up from training looks great; he’s also better prepared for competition. Good looks are always linked to effective performance. However, it doesn’t take exceptional judgment to notice this difference.
The same principle produces, in many instances, our sentiments of morals, as well as those of beauty. No virtue is more esteemed than justice, and no vice more detested than injustice; nor are there any qualities, which go farther to the fixing the character, either as amiable or odious. Now justice is a moral virtue, merely because it has that tendency to the good of mankind; and, indeed, is nothing but an artificial invention to that purpose. The same may be said of allegiance, of the laws of nations, of modesty, and of good-manners. All these are mere human contrivances for the interest of society. And since there is a very strong sentiment of morals, which in all nations, and all ages, has attended them, we must allow, that the reflecting on the tendency of characters and mental qualities, is sufficient to give us the sentiments of approbation and blame. Now as the means to an end can only be agreeable, where the end is agreeable; and as the good of society, where our own interest is not concerned, or that of our friends, pleases only by sympathy: It follows, that sympathy is the source of the esteem, which we pay to all the artificial virtues.
The same principle often shapes our feelings about morals and beauty. No virtue is more highly valued than justice, and no vice is more hated than injustice; likewise, no traits play a greater role in defining a person's character as good or bad. Justice is deemed a moral virtue simply because it promotes the well-being of humanity, and actually, it's just a human-made concept for that purpose. The same applies to loyalty, international laws, modesty, and good manners. All of these are just human inventions aimed at benefiting society. And since a strong sense of morality has existed across all cultures and eras, we have to acknowledge that reflecting on the impact of character traits and mental qualities is enough to form our feelings of approval and disapproval. Now, since a means to an end can only be appreciated if the end is desirable, and since the well-being of society pleases us only through empathy—especially when our own interests or those of our friends are not at stake—it follows that empathy is the root of the respect we give to all these socially constructed virtues.
Thus it appears, that sympathy is a very powerful principle in human nature, that it has a great influence on our taste of beauty, and that it produces our sentiment of morals in all the artificial virtues. From thence we may presume, that it also gives rise to many of the other virtues; and that qualities acquire our approbation, because of their tendency to the good of mankind. This presumption must become a certainty, when we find that most of those qualities, which we naturally approve of, have actually that tendency, and render a man a proper member of society: While the qualities, which we naturally disapprove of, have a contrary tendency, and render any intercourse with the person dangerous or disagreeable. For having found, that such tendencies have force enough to produce the strongest sentiment of morals, we can never reasonably, in these cases, look for any other cause of approbation or blame; it being an inviolable maxim in philosophy, that where any particular cause is sufficient for an effect, we ought to rest satisfied with it, and ought not to multiply causes without necessity. We have happily attained experiments in the artificial virtues, where the tendency of qualities to the good of society, is the sole cause of our approbation, without any suspicion of the concurrence of another principle. From thence we learn the force of that principle. And where that principle may take place, and the quality approved of is really beneficial to society, a true philosopher will never require any other principle to account for the strongest approbation and esteem.
It seems that sympathy is a very powerful part of human nature. It greatly influences our sense of beauty and shapes our moral sentiments regarding all artificial virtues. From this, we can assume that it also plays a role in many other virtues; qualities gain our approval because they contribute to the well-being of humanity. This assumption becomes a certainty when we see that most qualities we naturally admire actually have that positive influence and make someone a valuable member of society. In contrast, qualities we instinctively disapprove of have the opposite effect, making interactions with those individuals risky or unpleasant. Since we've observed that such tendencies are strong enough to create our most profound moral sentiments, we shouldn’t reasonably expect any other cause for approval or disapproval in these situations. It's an unbreakable rule in philosophy that when a specific cause is sufficient for an effect, we should accept it and not complicate matters by introducing unnecessary causes. We have successfully conducted experiments on artificial virtues, where the inclination of qualities to benefit society is the only reason for our approval, without any indication of another principle at play. From this, we understand the power of that principle. Where that principle applies, and the quality in question genuinely benefits society, a true philosopher won’t seek any further principle to explain strong approval and respect.
That many of the natural virtues have this tendency to the good of society, no one can doubt of. Meekness, beneficence, charity, generosity, clemency, moderation, equity bear the greatest figure among the moral qualities, and are commonly denominated the social virtues, to mark their tendency to the good of society. This goes so far, that some philosophers have represented all moral distinctions as the effect of artifice and education, when skilful politicians endeavoured to restrain the turbulent passions of men, and make them operate to the public good, by the notions of honour and shame. This system, however, is nor consistent with experience. For, first, there are other virtues and vices beside those which have this tendency to the public advantage and loss. Secondly, had not men a natural sentiment of approbation and blame, it could never be excited by politicians; nor would the words laudable and praise-worthy, blameable and odious be any more intelligible, than if they were a language perfectly known to us, as we have already observed. But though this system be erroneous, it may teach us, that moral distinctions arise, in a great measure, from the tendency of qualities and characters to the interests of society, and that it is our concern for that interest, which makes us approve or disapprove of them. Now we have no such extensive concern for society but from sympathy; and consequently it is that principle, which takes us so far out of ourselves, as to give us the same pleasure or uneasiness in the characters of others, as if they had a tendency to our own advantage or loss.
It's undeniable that many natural virtues benefit society. Qualities like meekness, kindness, charity, generosity, mercy, moderation, and fairness stand out as moral qualities, often referred to as social virtues due to their positive impact on society. Some philosophers have even suggested that all moral distinctions are merely products of manipulation and education, created when clever politicians tried to control people's unruly passions and steer them towards the common good by instilling ideas of honor and shame. However, this idea doesn't hold up against real-life experiences. First, there are other virtues and vices that do not necessarily serve the public good or harm. Second, if people didn't have a natural sense of approval or disapproval, politicians could never instill those feelings; terms like commendable and praiseworthy, or blameworthy and detestable wouldn't make any sense, just as if they were in a completely unfamiliar language. While this theory is flawed, it highlights that moral distinctions largely stem from how qualities and characters impact society's interests, and it’s our concern for these interests that influences our approval or disapproval of them. Our deep concern for society arises primarily from empathy; this empathy pulls us beyond our own self-interest, allowing us to feel joy or discomfort regarding the qualities of others, as if they directly affect our own well-being.
The only difference betwixt the natural virtues and justice lies in this, that the good, which results from the former, arises from every single act, and is the object of some natural passion: Whereas a single act of justice, considered in itself, may often be contrary to the public good; and it is only the concurrence of mankind, in a general scheme or system of action, which is advantageous. When I relieve persons in distress, my natural humanity is my motive; and so far as my succour extends, so far have I promoted the happiness of my fellow-creatures. But if we examine all the questions, that come before any tribunal of justice, we shall find, that, considering each case apart, it would as often be an instance of humanity to decide contrary to the laws of justice as conformable them. Judges take from a poor man to give to a rich; they bestow on the dissolute the labour of the industrious; and put into the hands of the vicious the means of harming both themselves and others. The whole scheme, however, of law and justice is advantageous to the society; and it was with a view to this advantage, that men, by their voluntary conventions, established it. After it is once established by these conventions, it is naturally attended with a strong sentiment of morals; which can proceed from nothing but our sympathy with the interests of society. We need no other explication of that esteem, which attends such of the natural virtues, as have a tendency to the public good. I must farther add, that there are several circumstances, which render this hypothesis much more probable with regard to the natural than the artificial virtues. It is certain that the imagination is more affected by what is particular, than by what is general; and that the sentiments are always moved with difficulty, where their objects are, in any degree, loose and undetermined: Now every particular act of justice is not beneficial to society, but the whole scheme or system: And it may not, perhaps, be any individual person for whom we are concerned, who receives benefit from justice, but the whole society alike. On the contrary, every particular act of generosity, or relief of the industrious and indigent, is beneficial; and is beneficial to a particular person, who is not undeserving of it. It is more natural, therefore, to think, that the tendencies of the latter virtue will affect our sentiments, and command our approbation, than those of the former; and therefore, since we find, that the approbation of the former arises from their tendencies, we may ascribe, with better reason, the same cause to the approbation of the latter. In any number of similar effects, if a cause can be discovered for one, we ought to extend that cause to all the other effects, which can be accounted for by it: But much more, if these other effects be attended with peculiar circumstances, which facilitate the operation of that cause.
The only difference between natural virtues and justice is that the good coming from natural virtues arises from each individual act and is driven by some natural feeling. In contrast, a single act of justice can often go against the public good; it's only when people work together in a broader plan or system that it becomes beneficial. When I help those in need, my natural compassion is my motivation; the extent to which I help corresponds to how much I contribute to the happiness of others. However, if we look at all the cases that come before any court, we'll find that examining each case individually, it can sometimes be more humane to rule against the laws of justice rather than in favor of them. Judges might take from a poor person to give to a rich one, reward the lazy with the effort of the hardworking, and give the immoral the power to harm themselves and others. Nevertheless, the overall framework of law and justice is beneficial to society, and it was with this benefit in mind that people voluntarily created it. Once it's established through these agreements, it naturally comes with a strong moral sentiment, which can only come from our sympathy for societal interests. We don't need any other explanation for the esteem that surrounds those natural virtues that benefit the public good. Furthermore, several factors make this idea more likely regarding natural virtues than artificial ones. It's clear that our imagination is more influenced by specifics than by generalities, and our feelings are hard to stir when their objects are somewhat vague and undefined: Each individual act of justice may not benefit society as a whole, but the entire system does. It might not even be a specific individual who benefits from justice, but rather all of society. On the other hand, every single act of kindness or assistance to the hardworking and needy is beneficial and specifically helps someone who deserves it. Therefore, it's more instinctive to think that the effects of the latter virtue will touch our feelings and earn our approval more than those of the former; thus, since we observe that the approval of the former comes from their effects, we can reasonably assign the same cause to the approval of the latter. In a series of similar outcomes, if we can identify a cause for one, we should apply that cause to all other outcomes it can explain; this is even more applicable if those other outcomes come with specific circumstances that make the cause more effective.
Before I proceed farther, I must observe two remarkable circumstances in this affair, which may seem objections to the present system. The first may be thus explained. When any quality, or character, has a tendency to the good of mankind, we are pleased with it, and approve of it; because it presents the lively idea of pleasure; which idea affects us by sympathy, and is itself a kind of pleasure. But as this sympathy is very variable, it may be thought that our sentiments of morals must admit of all the same variations. We sympathize more with persons contiguous to us, than with persons remote from us: With our acquaintance, than with strangers: With our countrymen, than with foreigners. But notwithstanding this variation of our sympathy, we give the same approbation to the same moral qualities in China as in England. They appear equally virtuous, and recommend themselves equally to the esteem of a judicious spectator. The sympathy varies without a variation in our esteem. Our esteem, therefore, proceeds not from sympathy.
Before I go any further, I need to point out two noteworthy aspects of this situation that might seem like objections to the current system. The first can be explained like this: When a quality or character benefits humanity, we appreciate it and approve of it because it brings to mind the idea of pleasure, which influences us through sympathy and is, in itself, a form of pleasure. However, since this sympathy can change a lot, it could be thought that our moral sentiments must vary in the same way. We tend to sympathize more with those close to us than with those far away: with our friends rather than strangers, and with our fellow countrymen rather than foreigners. But despite this change in our sympathy, we give the same approval to the same moral qualities in China as we do in England. They appear equally virtuous and earn the same respect from an observant person. The sympathy changes without causing any change in our esteem. Therefore, our esteem doesn’t come from sympathy.
To this I answer: The approbation of moral qualities most certainly is not derived from reason, or any comparison of ideas; but proceeds entirely from a moral taste, and from certain sentiments of pleasure or disgust, which arise upon the contemplation and view of particular qualities or characters. Now it is evident, that those sentiments, whence-ever they are derived, must vary according to the distance or contiguity of the objects; nor can I feel the same lively pleasure from the virtues of a person, who lived in Greece two thousand years ago, that I feel from the virtues of a familiar friend and acquaintance. Yet I do not say, that I esteem the one more than the other: And therefore, if the variation of the sentiment, without a variation of the esteem, be an objection, it must have equal force against every other system, as against that of sympathy. But to consider the matter a-right, it has no force at all; and it is the easiest matter in the world to account for it. Our situation, with regard both to persons and things, is in continual fluctuation; and a man, that lies at a distance from us, may, in a little time, become a familiar acquaintance. Besides, every particular man has a peculiar position with regard to others; and it is impossible we could ever converse together on any reasonable terms, were each of us to consider characters and persons, only as they appear from his peculiar point of view. In order, therefore, to prevent those continual contradictions, and arrive at a more stable judgment of things, we fix on some steady and general points of view; and always, in our thoughts, place ourselves in them, whatever may be our present situation. In like manner, external beauty is determined merely by pleasure; and it is evident, a beautiful countenance cannot give so much pleasure, when seen at the distance of twenty paces, as when it is brought nearer us. We say not, however, that it appears to us less beautiful: Because we know what effect it will have in such a position, and by that reflection we correct its momentary appearance.
To this I reply: The approval of moral qualities definitely doesn’t come from reason or comparing ideas; rather, it comes entirely from a moral sense and from certain feelings of pleasure or disgust that arise when we contemplate specific qualities or characters. It's clear that those feelings, regardless of their source, must change depending on how far away or close the objects are to us; I can’t feel the same intense pleasure from the virtues of someone who lived in Greece two thousand years ago as I do from the virtues of a close friend. However, I’m not saying I value one more than the other. Therefore, if the change in feeling, without a change in esteem, is a problem, it would apply equally to every other system, just like it does for the system of sympathy. But looking at it correctly, it’s not a problem at all; it’s very easy to explain. Our situation, in relation to both people and things, is constantly changing; a person who is far away from us can become a close friend in no time. Also, every individual has a unique position in relation to others, and it would be impossible for us to have any reasonable conversation if we all only considered characters and people from our own individual viewpoints. Therefore, to avoid constant contradictions and reach a more stable judgment of things, we focus on some steady and general perspectives; and we always place ourselves in those perspectives, no matter what our current situation is. Similarly, external beauty is determined solely by pleasure; and it’s clear that a beautiful face doesn’t give as much pleasure when seen from twenty paces away as it does when it’s closer to us. However, we don’t say it appears less beautiful to us: We know what effect it will have in that position, and through that reflection, we adjust its momentary appearance.
In general, all sentiments of blame or praise are variable, according to our situation of nearness or remoteness, with regard to the person blamed or praised, and according to the present disposition of our mind. But these variations we regard not in our general decision, but still apply the terms expressive of our liking or dislike, in the same manner, as if we remained in one point of view. Experience soon teaches us this method of correcting our sentiments, or at least, of correcting our language, where the sentiments are more stubborn and inalterable. Our servant, if diligent and faithful, may excite stronger sentiments of love and kindness than Marcus Brutus, as represented in history; but we say not upon that account, that the former character is more laudable than the latter. We know, that were we to approach equally near to that renowned patriot, he would command a much higher degree of affection and admiration. Such corrections are common with regard to all the senses; and indeed it were impossible we could ever make use of language, or communicate our sentiments to one another, did we not correct the momentary appearances of things, and overlook our present situation.
In general, our feelings of blame or praise change depending on how close or far we are from the person we're judging, and also based on our current state of mind. However, we don’t let these changes affect our overall judgment; we still use words that show our approval or disapproval as if we’re sticking to one perspective. Experience quickly teaches us how to adjust our feelings or at least adjust our words when our feelings are more stubborn and unchangeable. Our servant, if they are hardworking and loyal, may inspire stronger feelings of love and kindness than Marcus Brutus as depicted in history; but we don’t say that the former is more admirable than the latter. We know that if we were to get as close to that famous patriot, we would feel much greater affection and admiration for him. Such adjustments are common for all our senses; in fact, it would be impossible for us to use language or share our feelings with each other if we didn’t adjust for the momentary impressions of things and overlook our current situation.
It is therefore from the influence of characters and qualities, upon those who have an intercourse with any person, that we blame or praise him. We consider not whether the persons, affected by the qualities, be our acquaintance or strangers, countrymen or foreigners. Nay, we over-look our own interest in those general judgments; and blame not a man for opposing us in any of our pretensions, when his own interest is particularly concerned. We make allowance for a certain degree of selfishness in men; because we know it to be inseparable from human nature, and inherent in our frame and constitution. By this reflection we correct those sentiments of blame, which so naturally arise upon any opposition.
It’s because of the impact of people’s traits and qualities on those who interact with them that we either criticize or commend them. We don’t take into account whether the individuals affected by these qualities are our friends or strangers, fellow citizens or foreigners. In fact, we often overlook our own interests in these general judgments and don’t blame someone for opposing us in our claims when their own interests are at stake. We allow for a certain level of selfishness in people because we understand it’s part of human nature and built into our makeup. With this understanding, we adjust our feelings of blame that naturally arise when we face opposition.
But however the general principle of our blame or praise may be corrected by those other principles, it is certain, they are not altogether efficacious, nor do our passions often correspond entirely to the present theory. It is seldom men heartily love what lies at a distance from them, and what no way redounds to their particular benefit; as it is no less rare to meet with persons, who can pardon another any opposition he makes to their interest, however justifiable that opposition may be by the general rules of morality. Here we are contented with saying, that reason requires such an Impartial conduct, but that it is seldom we can bring ourselves to it, and that our passions do not readily follow the determination of our judgment. This language will be easily understood, if we consider what we formerly said concerning that reason, which is able to oppose our passion; and which we have found to be nothing but a general calm determination of the passions, founded on some distant view or reflection. When we form our judgments of persons, merely from the tendency of their characters to our own benefit, or to that of our friends, we find so many contradictions to our sentiments in society and conversation, and such an uncertainty from the incessant changes of our situation, that we seek some other standard of merit and demerit, which may not admit of so great variation. Being thus loosened from our first station, we cannot afterwards fix ourselves so commodiously by any means as by a sympathy with those, who have any commerce with the person we consider. This is far from being as lively as when our own interest is concerned, or that of our particular friends; nor has it such an influence on our love and hatred: But being equally conformable to our calm and general principles, it is said to have an equal authority over our reason, and to command our judgment and opinion. We blame equally a bad action, which we read of in history, with one performed in our neighbourhood the other day: The meaning of which is, that we know from reflection, that the former action would excite as strong sentiments of disapprobation as the latter, were it placed in the same position.
But although the general idea of our blame or praise can be adjusted by other principles, it's clear that these principles aren't completely effective, and our feelings often don't completely align with current theories. People rarely genuinely care about things that are far away from them or that don’t directly benefit them; it's also quite uncommon to find people who can forgive others for standing against their interests, no matter how justifiable that opposition is by the general rules of morality. Here, we often say that reason demands such impartial behavior, but we find it difficult to achieve it, and our feelings don’t easily follow what our judgment decides. This will be clear if we think about what we mentioned before regarding reason, which can counter our feelings; we’ve found that it’s really just a calm determination of feelings based on some distant thought or consideration. When we judge people solely based on how their character benefits us or our friends, we encounter so many contradictions in society and conversation and face such uncertainty due to our constantly changing situations that we look for another standard of right and wrong that doesn’t change as much. Being disconnected from our original position, we can't easily settle on anything as well as we can by feeling sympathy for those who interact with the person we're considering. This sympathy isn’t as intense as when our own interests or those of our close friends are involved, nor does it have as much influence on our love or hate; but since it aligns with our calm and general principles, it’s said to have equal authority over our reason and to govern our judgment and opinions. We equally criticize a bad action we read about in history as we do one that happened in our neighborhood the other day: the implication is that we know from contemplation that the former action would provoke just as strong feelings of disapproval as the latter if it were in the same context.
I now proceed to the second remarkable circumstance, which I proposed to take notice of. Where a person is possessed of a character, that in its natural tendency is beneficial to society, we esteem him virtuous, and are delighted with the view of his character, even though particular accidents prevent its operation, and incapacitate him from being serviceable to his friends and country. Virtue in rags is still virtue; and the love, which it procures, attends a man into a dungeon or desart, where the virtue can no longer be exerted in action, and is lost to all the world. Now this may be esteemed an objection to the present system. Sympathy interests us in the good of mankind; and if sympathy were the source of our esteem for virtue, that sentiment of approbation could only take place, where the virtue actually attained its end, and was beneficial to mankind. Where it fails of its end, it is only an imperfect means; and therefore can never acquire any merit from that end. The goodness of an end can bestow a merit on such means alone as are compleat, and actually produce the end.
I now move on to the second notable point that I wanted to discuss. When someone has a character that naturally benefits society, we consider them virtuous and appreciate the view of their character, even if certain circumstances prevent them from being helpful to their friends and country. Virtue in rags is still virtue; the love it brings follows a person into a dungeon or desert, where the virtue can no longer be acted upon and is lost to everyone. This might be seen as a critique of the current system. Sympathy makes us care about the well-being of others; if sympathy were the source of our appreciation for virtue, then that feeling of approval would only occur where virtue actually achieves its purpose and benefits society. When it fails to do so, it’s merely an incomplete means; thus, it can never earn any merit from that purpose. The goodness of an end can only give merit to those means that are complete and truly achieve the end.
To this we may reply, that where any object, in all its parts, is fitted to attain any agreeable end, it naturally gives us pleasure, and is esteemed beautiful, even though some external circumstances be wanting to render it altogether effectual. It is sufficient if every thing be compleat in the object itself. A house, that is contrived with great judgment for all the commodities of life, pleases us upon that account; though perhaps we are sensible, that no one will ever dwell in it. A fertile soil, and a happy climate, delight us by a reflection on the happiness which they would afford the inhabitants, though at present the country be desart and uninhabited. A man, whose limbs and shape promise strength and activity, is esteemed handsome, though condemned to perpetual imprisonment. The imagination has a set of passions belonging to it, upon which our sentiments of beauty much depend. These passions are moved by degrees of liveliness and strength, which are inferior to belief, and independent of the real existence of their objects. Where a character is, in every respect, fitted to be beneficial to society, the imagination passes easily from the cause to the effect, without considering that there are some circumstances wanting to render the cause a complete one. General rules create a species of probability, which sometimes influences the judgment, and always the imagination.
In response to this, we can say that when an object is perfectly designed in all its parts to achieve a pleasing result, it naturally brings us joy and is considered beautiful, even if some external factors are missing to make it fully effective. It's enough for everything to be complete within the object itself. A house that's designed thoughtfully for all the comforts of life pleases us for that reason, even if we know no one will ever live in it. A rich, fertile land with a great climate brings us joy by making us think of the happiness it would offer its inhabitants, even if the area is currently empty and uninhabited. A person whose physique suggests strength and agility is seen as attractive, even if they are stuck in prison for life. Our feelings about beauty are influenced by a set of emotions connected to our imagination. These emotions can be stirred by varying degrees of intensity and liveliness that are less than beliefs and independent of the actual existence of their subjects. When a character is well-suited to benefit society in every way, the imagination easily links the cause to the effect, overlooking the fact that some elements are missing to make the cause fully complete. General principles create a kind of likelihood that can sometimes sway our judgment and always affects our imagination.
It is true, when the cause is compleat, and a good disposition is attended with good fortune, which renders it really beneficial to society, it gives a stronger pleasure to the spectator, and is attended with a more lively sympathy. We are more affected by it; and yet we do not say that it is more virtuous, or that we esteem it more. We know, that an alteration of fortune may render the benevolent disposition entirely impotent; and therefore we separate, as much as possible, the fortune from the disposition. The case is the same, as when we correct the different sentiments of virtue, which proceed from its different distances from ourselves. The passions do not always follow our corrections; but these corrections serve sufficiently to regulate our abstract notions, and are alone regarded, when we pronounce in general concerning the degrees of vice and virtue.
It’s true that when a cause is complete and a good attitude is paired with good luck, making it genuinely beneficial to society, it brings a stronger pleasure to the observer and creates a more vivid sense of sympathy. We are more moved by it; still, we don’t claim it’s more virtuous or that we value it more. We understand that a change in luck can make a kind disposition completely ineffective; that’s why we try to separate fortune from disposition as much as possible. The situation is similar when we adjust the different feelings we have about virtue, which arise from how close or distant it is to us. Our emotions don’t always align with our adjustments, but these corrections are enough to shape our abstract ideas and are what we focus on when we make broad statements about the levels of vice and virtue.
It is observed by critics, that all words or sentences, which are difficult to the pronunciation, are disagreeable to the ear. There is no difference, whether a man hear them pronounced, or read them silently to himself. When I run over a book with my eye, I imagine I hear it all; and also, by the force of imagination, enter into the uneasiness, which the delivery of it would give the speaker. The uneasiness is not real; but as such a composition of words has a natural tendency to produce it, this is sufficient to affect the mind with a painful sentiment, and render the discourse harsh and disagreeable. It is a similar case, where any real quality is, by accidental circumstances, rendered impotent, and is deprived of its natural influence on society.
Critics observe that any words or sentences that are hard to pronounce sound unpleasant to the ear. It doesn't matter whether a person hears them spoken or reads them silently to themselves. When I skim through a book, I feel like I'm hearing all of it; and through the power of imagination, I also experience the discomfort that the speaker would feel while delivering it. The discomfort isn't real, but the way those words are put together naturally tends to create it, which is enough to make the mind feel a painful sentiment and make the speech seem harsh and unappealing. It’s a similar situation when any real quality becomes ineffective due to accidental circumstances, losing its natural impact on society.
Upon these principles we may easily remove any contradiction, which may appear to be betwixt the extensive sympathy, on which our sentiments of virtue depend, and that limited generosity which I have frequently observed to be natural to men, and which justice and property suppose, according to the precedent reasoning. My sympathy with another may give me the sentiment of pain and disapprobation, when any object is presented, that has a tendency to give him uneasiness; though I may not be willing to sacrifice any thing of my own interest, or cross any of my passions, for his satisfaction. A house may displease me by being ill-contrived for the convenience of the owner; and yet I may refuse to give a shilling towards the rebuilding of it. Sentiments must touch the heart, to make them controul our passions: But they need not extend beyond the imagination, to make them influence our taste. When a building seems clumsy and tottering to the eye, it is ugly and disagreeable; though we be fully assured of the solidity of the workmanship. It is a kind of fear, which causes this sentiment of disapprobation; but the passion is not the same with that which we feel, when obliged to stand under a wall, that we really think tottering and insecure. The seeming tendencies of objects affect the mind: And the emotions they excite are of a like species with those, which proceed from the real consequences of objects, but their feeling is different. Nay, these emotions are so different in their feeling, that they may often be contrary, without destroying each other; as when the fortifications of a city belonging to an enemy are esteemed beautiful upon account of their strength, though we could wish that they were entirely destroyed. The imagination adheres to the general views of things, and distinguishes the feelings they produce, from those which arise from our particular and momentary situation.
Based on these principles, we can easily resolve any conflicts that may seem to exist between the broad sympathy on which our feelings about virtue rely and the limited generosity that I often notice is natural to people, which is assumed by justice and property according to previous reasoning. My sympathy for someone else might make me feel pain and disapproval when I encounter something that could cause them distress; however, I might not be willing to give up anything from my own interests or compromise my desires for their happiness. For example, a house might bother me because it’s poorly designed for the owner's convenience, but I may still refuse to contribute even a penny towards its reconstruction. Feelings must resonate emotionally to control our desires, but they don’t need to go beyond our imagination to impact our preferences. When a building appears awkward and unstable to the eye, it seems ugly and unpleasant, even if we are completely confident in its solid construction. This distaste stems from a kind of fear, but it differs from the anxiety we feel when we actually have to stand beneath a wall that we genuinely believe is unstable and unsafe. The perceived characteristics of objects affect our minds, and the feelings they provoke are similar to those arising from the actual consequences of objects, but the sensations are distinct. In fact, these feelings can be so different that they can often be opposed to each other without negating one another; for instance, we may find the defensive walls of an enemy city beautiful because of their strength, even though we would prefer they were completely destroyed. The imagination focuses on the broader characteristics of things and separates the feelings they generate from those that come from our specific and immediate circumstances.
If we examine the panegyrics that are commonly made of great men, we shall find, that most of the qualities, which are attributed to them, may be divided into two kinds, viz. such as make them perform their part in society; and such as render them serviceable to themselves, and enable them to promote their own interest. Their prudence, temperance, frugality, industry, assiduity, enterprize, dexterity, are celebrated, as well as their generosity and humanity. If we ever give an indulgence to any quality, that disables a man from making a figure in life, it is to that of indolence, which is not supposed to deprive one of his parts and capacity, but only suspends their exercise; and that without any inconvenience to the person himself, since it is, in some measure, from his own choice. Yet indolence is always allowed to be a fault, and a very great one, if extreme: Nor do a man's friends ever acknowledge him to be subject to it, but in order to save his character in more material articles. He could make a figure, say they, if he pleased to give application: His understanding is sound, his conception quick, and his memory tenacious; but he hates business, and is indifferent about his fortune. And this a man sometimes may make even a subject of vanity; though with the air of confessing a fault: Because he may think, that his incapacity for business implies much more noble qualities; such as a philosophical spirit, a fine taste, a delicate wit, or a relish for pleasure and society. But take any other case: Suppose a quality, that without being an indication of any other good qualities, incapacitates a man always for business, and is destructive to his interest; such as a blundering understanding, and a wrong judgment of every thing in life; inconstancy and irresolution; or a want of address in the management of men and business: These are all allowed to be imperfections in a character; and many men would rather acknowledge the greatest crimes, than have it suspected, that they are, in any degree, subject to them.
If we look at the praise often given to great people, we’ll find that most qualities attributed to them can be split into two categories: those that help them play their role in society, and those that serve their own interests. Their traits like wisdom, self-control, thriftiness, hard work, diligence, initiative, and skill are celebrated alongside their generosity and compassion. If we ever excuse a quality that prevents someone from standing out in life, it’s laziness, which isn’t seen as taking away someone’s abilities but only hindering their use; and this doesn’t really harm the person, since it’s somewhat of their own choice. However, laziness is always considered a flaw, especially when it’s excessive. A person’s friends usually only admit to it in order to protect their reputation regarding more serious issues. They might say he could succeed if he decided to apply himself: his mind is sharp, his ideas come quickly, and he has a good memory; yet he dislikes work and is indifferent about his future. Sometimes, a person might even take pride in this, though it sounds more like acknowledging a fault. They might believe that their lack of interest in work signifies more noble traits, like a philosophical mindset, a fine taste, a sharp wit, or an enjoyment of pleasure and companionship. But in a different scenario: if we consider a trait that doesn’t demonstrate any positive qualities and always makes a person unfit for work, harming their interests—like a confused mind and poor judgment, indecisiveness, or lack of skill in dealing with people and tasks—these are universally seen as flaws in character. Many people would prefer to admit to serious crimes than have it suggested that they might, in any way, suffer from such issues.
It is very happy, in our philosophical researches, when we find the same phænomenon diversified by a variety of circumstances; and by discovering what is common among them, can the better assure ourselves of the truth of any hypothesis we may make use of to explain it. Were nothing esteemed virtue but what were beneficial to society, I am persuaded, that the foregoing explication of the moral sense ought still to be received, and that upon sufficient evidence: But this evidence must grow upon us, when we find other kinds of virtue, which will not admit of any explication except from that hypothesis. Here is a man, who is not remarkably defective in his social qualities; but what principally recommends him is his dexterity in business, by which he has extricated himself from the greatest difficulties, and conducted the most delicate affairs with a singular address and prudence. I find an esteem for him immediately to arise in me: His company is a satisfaction to me; and before I have any farther acquaintance with him, I would rather do him a service than another, whose character is in every other respect equal, but is deficient in that particular. In this case, the qualities that please me are all considered as useful to the person, and as having a tendency to promote his interest and satisfaction. They are only regarded as means to an end, and please me in proportion to their fitness for that end. The end, therefore, must be agreeable to me. But what makes the end agreeable? The person is a stranger: I am no way interested in him, nor lie under any obligation to him: His happiness concerns not me, farther than the happiness of every human, and indeed of every sensible creature: That is, it affects me only by sympathy. From that principle, whenever I discover his happiness and good, whether in its causes or effects, I enter so deeply into it, that it gives me a sensible emotion. The appearance of qualities, that have a tendency to promote it, have an agreeable effect upon my imagination, and command my love and esteem.
It’s really exciting in our philosophical studies when we find the same phenomenon affected by various circumstances; by uncovering what they have in common, we can more confidently affirm the truth of any hypothesis we use to explain it. If nothing is considered virtuous except what benefits society, I believe that the previous explanation of the moral sense should still be accepted, and it should be based on solid evidence. But this evidence must become clear to us when we find other types of virtue that can only be explained by that hypothesis. Here’s a guy who isn’t particularly lacking in social skills, but what stands out about him is his knack for business, which has helped him overcome major challenges and handle delicate matters with remarkable skill and wisdom. I immediately feel a respect for him: being around him is enjoyable to me; and even before getting to know him better, I would rather do something for him than for someone else who is otherwise just as capable but lacks that particular skill. In this case, the qualities I admire are all seen as beneficial to him and are aimed at promoting his well-being and satisfaction. They’re only viewed as tools to achieve an end and please me based on how effective they are for that goal. Therefore, the end must be something I find appealing. But what makes that end appealing? The person is a stranger: I have no personal interest in him, nor am I obligated to him: His happiness doesn’t concern me beyond the way it concerns all humans and indeed every sentient being: it affects me only through empathy. Based on that principle, whenever I notice his happiness and good fortune, whether through its causes or effects, I become so involved that it stirs a strong emotional response in me. The presence of qualities that promote his happiness has a pleasant effect on my imagination and earns my love and admiration.
This theory may serve to explain, why the same qualities, in all cases, produce both pride and love, humility and hatred; and the same man is always virtuous or vicious, accomplished or despicable to others, who is so to himself. A person, in whom we discover any passion or habit, which originally is only incommodious to himself, becomes always disagreeable to us, merely on its account; as on the other hand, one whose character is only dangerous and disagreeable to others, can never be satisfied with himself, as long as he is sensible of that disadvantage. Nor is this observable only with regard to characters and manners, but may be remarked even in the most minute circumstances. A violent cough in another gives us uneasiness; though in itself it does not in the least affect us. A man will be mortified, if you tell him he has a stinking breath; though it is evidently no annoyance to himself. Our fancy easily changes its situation; and either surveying ourselves as we appear to others, or considering others as they feel themselves, we enter, by that means, into sentiments, which no way belong to us, and in which nothing but sympathy is able to interest us. And this sympathy we sometimes carry so far, as even to be displeased with a quality commodious to us, merely because it displeases others, and makes us disagreeable in their eyes; though perhaps we never can have any interest in rendering ourselves agreeable to them.
This theory might explain why the same qualities can lead to both pride and love, as well as humility and hatred; the same person is always seen as virtuous or vicious, admirable or despicable to others, just as they are to themselves. When we notice someone has a passion or habit that only harms themselves, they become off-putting to us for that reason. On the flip side, someone whose character is dangerous and unpleasant to others will never feel at ease with themselves as long as they are aware of that flaw. This isn't just true for personalities and behaviors; it can even be seen in the smallest details. A severe cough from someone else bothers us, even though it doesn’t affect us directly. A person feels humiliated if you mention they have bad breath, even though it clearly doesn’t bother them. Our imagination can easily switch perspectives; by looking at ourselves as others see us, or viewing others as they perceive themselves, we adopt feelings that don't truly belong to us, where only sympathy can engage us. Sometimes, we take this sympathy so far that we become annoyed by a trait that benefits us simply because it annoys others and makes us look bad in their eyes, even if we have no real interest in winning their approval.
There have been many systems of morality advanced by philosophers in all ages; but if they are strictly examined, they may be reduced to two, which alone merit our attention. Moral good and evil are certainly distinguished by our sentiments, not by reason: But these sentiments may arise either from the mere species or appearance of characters and passions, or from reflections on their tendency to the happiness of mankind, and of particular persons. My opinion is, that both these causes are intermixed in our judgments of morals; after the same manner as they are in our decisions concerning most kinds of external beauty: Though I am also of opinion, that reflections on the tendencies of actions have by far the greatest influence, and determine all the great lines of our duty. There are, however, instances, in cases of less moment, wherein this immediate taste or sentiment produces our approbation. Wit, and a certain easy and disengaged behaviour, are qualities immediately agreeable to others, and command their love and esteem. Some of these qualities produce satisfaction in others by particular original principles of human nature, which cannot be accounted for: Others may be resolved into principles, which are more general. This will best appear upon a particular enquiry.
Many moral systems have been proposed by philosophers throughout history, but when closely examined, they can be boiled down to two that truly deserve our focus. We certainly differentiate between moral good and evil based on our feelings, not on reason. However, these feelings can come either from the simple nature or appearance of traits and emotions, or from thoughts about how they affect the happiness of humanity and individual people. I believe that both factors are mixed together in our moral judgments, similar to how we decide on most types of external beauty. Still, I also think that contemplating the effects of actions has a much stronger influence and shapes all the key aspects of our duties. There are, however, cases of lesser importance where this immediate taste or feeling leads to our approval. Wit and a certain relaxed and approachable demeanor are traits that people find immediately appealing and earn their affection and respect. Some of these traits bring satisfaction to others based on specific innate principles of human nature that can’t be fully explained, while others can be traced back to more general principles. This will become clearer through a deeper investigation.
As some qualities acquire their merit from their being immediately agreeable to others, without any tendency to public interest; so some are denominated virtuous from their being immediately agreeable to the person himself, who possesses them. Each of the passions and operations of the mind has a particular feeling, which must be either agreeable or disagreeable. The first is virtuous, the second vicious. This particular feeling constitutes the very nature of the passion; and therefore needs not be accounted for.
As some qualities gain their value simply because they're pleasing to others, without benefiting the public good; similarly, some are called virtuous because they're directly pleasing to the individual who has them. Each passion and mental action evokes a specific feeling, which can be either pleasant or unpleasant. The pleasant feelings are considered virtuous, while the unpleasant ones are seen as vicious. This specific feeling is inherent to the passion itself and doesn’t require further explanation.
But however directly the distinction of vice and virtue may seem to flow from the immediate pleasure or uneasiness, which particular qualities cause to ourselves or others; it is easy to observe, that it has also a considerable dependence on the principle of sympathy so often insisted on. We approve of a person, who is possessed of qualities immediately agreeable to those, with whom he has any commerce; though perhaps we ourselves never reaped any pleasure from them. We also approve of one, who is possessed of qualities, that are immediately agreeable to himself; though they be of no service to any mortal. To account for this we must have recourse to the foregoing principles.
But no matter how directly the difference between vice and virtue seems to stem from the immediate pleasure or discomfort caused by certain qualities to ourselves or others, it's clear that it also heavily relies on the principle of sympathy that’s been emphasized. We tend to approve of someone who has qualities that are immediately pleasing to those they interact with, even if we personally don’t gain any pleasure from them. We also approve of someone who possesses qualities that make them happy, even if those qualities aren’t beneficial to anyone else. To understand this, we need to refer back to the earlier principles.
Thus, to take a general review of the present hypothesis: Every quality of the mind is denominated virtuous, which gives pleasure by the mere survey; as every quality, which produces pain, is called vicious. This pleasure and this pain may arise from four different sources. For we reap a pleasure from the view of a character, which is naturally fitted to be useful to others, or to the person himself, or which is agreeable to others, or to the person himself. One may, perhaps, be surprized. that amidst all these interests and pleasures, we should forget our own, which touch us so nearly on every other occasion. But we shall easily satisfy ourselves on this head, when we consider, that every particular person’s pleasure and interest being different, it is impossible men could ever agree in their sentiments and judgments, unless they chose some common point of view, from which they might survey their object, and which might cause it to appear the same to all of them. Now in judging of characters, the only interest or pleasure, which appears the same to every spectator, is that of the person himself, whose character is examined; or that of persons, who have a connexion with him. And though such interests and pleasures touch us more faintly than our own, yet being more constant and universal, they counter-ballance the latter even in practice, and are alone admitted in speculation as the standard of virtue and morality. They alone produce that particular feeling or sentiment, on which moral distinctions depend.
So, to take a general look at the current hypothesis: Every quality of the mind that brings pleasure just by being observed is considered virtuous, while any quality that causes pain is labeled vicious. This pleasure and pain can come from four different sources. We gain pleasure from observing a character that is naturally useful to others or to that person themselves, or that is pleasing to others or to that person. One might be surprised that amid all these interests and pleasures, we would forget our own, which usually affect us so closely. But we can easily clarify this when we think about how each person's pleasure and interest are different; it's impossible for people to agree on their feelings and judgments unless they choose a common point of view from which they can evaluate their object, making it appear the same to everyone. When judging characters, the only shared interest or pleasure apparent to every observer is that of the person being evaluated or those who have a connection to them. And although these interests and pleasures may affect us less intensely than our own, they are more constant and universal, balancing out our personal interests in practice and serving as the standard for virtue and morality in theory. They are what produce the specific feeling or sentiment on which moral distinctions rely.
As to the good or ill desert of virtue or vice, it is an evident consequence of the sentiments of pleasure or uneasiness. These sentiments produce love or hatred; and love or hatred, by the original constitution of human passion, is attended with benevolence or anger; that is, with a desire of making happy the person we love, and miserable the person we hate. We have treated of this more fully on another occasion.
Regarding the merits or shortcomings of virtue or vice, it’s clear that they stem from feelings of pleasure or discomfort. These feelings lead to love or hatred; and love or hatred, according to the original makeup of human emotions, come with kindness or anger; that is, a desire to make the person we love happy and the person we hate miserable. We have discussed this in more detail elsewhere.
SECT. II OF GREATNESS OF MIND
It may now be proper to illustrate this general system of morals, by applying it to particular instances of virtue and vice, and shewing how their merit or demerit arises from the four sources here explained. We shall begin with examining the passions of pride and humility, and shall consider the vice or virtue that lies in their excesses or just proportion. An excessive pride or overweaning conceit of ourselves is always esteemed vicious, and is universally hated; as modesty, or a just sense of our weakness, is esteemed virtuous, and procures the good-will of every-one. Of the four sources of moral distinctions, this is to be ascribed to the third; viz, the immediate agreeableness and disagreeableness of a quality to others, without any reflections on the tendency of that quality.
It’s now appropriate to illustrate this general moral system by applying it to specific examples of virtue and vice, showing how their value or lack thereof comes from the four sources explained here. We will start by examining the emotions of pride and humility and consider the vice or virtue that exists in their extremes or proper balance. Excessive pride or an arrogant opinion of ourselves is always seen as negative and is universally disliked, while modesty or a realistic understanding of our limitations is seen as virtuous and earns everyone’s goodwill. Among the four sources of moral distinctions, this can be attributed to the third; that is, the immediate attractiveness or unattractiveness of a quality to others, without considering the implications of that quality.
In order to prove this, we must have recourse to two principles, which are very conspicuous in human nature. The first of these is the sympathy, and communication of sentiments and passions above-mentioned. So close and intimate is the correspondence of human souls, that no sooner any person approaches me, than he diffuses on me all his opinions, and draws along my judgment in a greater or lesser degree. And though, on many occasions, my sympathy with him goes not so far as entirely to change my sentiments, and way of thinking; yet it seldom is so weak as not to disturb the easy course of my thought, and give an authority to that opinion, which is recommended to me by his assent and approbation. Nor is it any way material upon what subject he and I employ our thoughts. Whether we judge of an indifferent person, or of my own character, my sympathy gives equal force to his decision: And even his sentiments of his own merit make me consider him in the same light, in which he regards himself.
To prove this, we need to refer to two principles that are very evident in human nature. The first is the sympathy and sharing of feelings and emotions mentioned earlier. The connection between human souls is so close that as soon as someone approaches me, they pass on their opinions and influence my judgment to some extent. While my sympathy for them doesn't always completely change my views or way of thinking, it’s rarely weak enough not to disrupt my train of thought and lend authority to the opinion being shared with me through their agreement and approval. It doesn’t really matter what topic we’re discussing. Whether we’re evaluating a neutral person or my own character, my sympathy gives equal weight to their decision. Even their feelings about their own worth lead me to see them the way they see themselves.
This principle of sympathy is of so powerful and insinuating a nature, that it enters into most of our sentiments and passions, and often takes place under the appearance of its contrary. For it is remarkable, that when a person opposes me in any thing, which I am strongly bent upon, and rouzes up my passion by contradiction, I have always a degree of sympathy with him, nor does my commotion proceed from any other origin. We may here observe an evident conflict or rencounter of opposite principles and passions. On the one side there is that passion or sentiment, which is natural to me; and it is observable, that the stronger this passion is, the greater is the commotion. There must also be some passion or sentiment on the other side; and this passion can proceed from nothing but sympathy. The sentiments of others can never affect us, but by becoming, in some measure, our own; in which case they operate upon us, by opposing and encreasing our passions, in the very same manner, as if they had been originally derived from our own temper and disposition. While they remain concealed in the minds of others, they can never have an influence upon us: And even when they are known, if they went no farther than the imagination, or conception; that faculty is so accustomed to objects of every different kind, that a mere idea, though contrary to our sentiments and inclinations, would never alone be able to affect us.
This principle of sympathy is so powerful and sneaky that it influences most of our feelings and passions, often appearing as its opposite. It's interesting that when someone challenges me on something I really care about and stirs up my emotions through disagreement, I always feel some level of sympathy for them; my reaction actually comes from that sympathy. We can see a clear clash of conflicting principles and emotions. On one side, there's my natural feeling or sentiment, and the stronger this feeling is, the more intense my reaction becomes. There must also be some feeling on the other side, which can only arise from sympathy. The feelings of others can’t affect us unless they somehow become part of our own experience; in this case, they act on us by challenging and amplifying our feelings, just as if they originated from our own nature and temperament. As long as these feelings are hidden in someone else's mind, they can't influence us. Even when they are known, if they only exist as thoughts or concepts, our mind is so used to dealing with various kinds of objects that merely imagining something, even if it contradicts our feelings and preferences, wouldn’t be enough to impact us.
The second principle I shall take notice of is that of comparison, or the variation of our judgments concerning objects, according to the proportion they bear to those with which we compare them. We judge more, of objects by comparison, than by their intrinsic worth and value; and regard every thing as mean, when set in opposition to what is superior of the same kind. But no comparison is more obvious than that with ourselves; and hence it is that on all occasions it takes place, and mixes with most of our passions. This kind of comparison is directly contrary to sympathy in its operation, as we have observed in treating of compassion and malice.[2] IN ALL KINDS OF COMPARISON AN OBJECT MAKES US ALWAYS RECEIVE FROM ANOTHER, TO WHICH IT IS COMPARED, A SENSATION CONTRARY TO WHAT ARISES FROM ITSELF IN ITS DIRECT AND IMMEDIATE SURVEY. THE DIRECT SURVEY OF ANOTHER'S PLEASURE NATURALLY GIVES US PLEASURE; AND THEREFORE PRODUCES PAIN, WHEN COMPARED WITH OUR OWN. HIS PAIN, CONSIDERED IN ITSELF, IS PAINFUL; BUT AUGMENTS THE IDEA OF OUR OWN HAPPINESS, AND GIVES US PLEASURE.
The second principle I want to talk about is comparison, or how our judgments about things change based on what we compare them to. We tend to judge things more by comparing them than by their own inherent value. We see everything as inferior when we place it next to something better of the same kind. However, the most obvious comparison is with ourselves; that’s why it happens in many situations and influences most of our emotions. This kind of comparison works in direct opposition to sympathy, as we've noted when discussing compassion and malice. In all kinds of comparisons, an object always prompts us to feel something opposite to what we feel from it directly. Seeing someone else's pleasure typically brings us joy, which can lead to pain when we compare it with our own situation. When we view another person's pain by itself, it is distressing; however, it enhances our sense of our own happiness and gives us pleasure.
Since then those principles of sympathy, and a comparison with ourselves, are directly contrary, it may be worth while to consider, what general rules can be formed, beside the particular temper of the person, for the prevalence of the one or the other. Suppose I am now in safety at land, and would willingly reap some pleasure from this consideration: I must think on the miserable condition of those who are at sea in a storm, and must endeavour to render this idea as strong and lively as possible, in order to make me more sensible of my own happiness. But whatever pains I may take, the comparison will never have an equal efficacy, as if I were really on the shore,[3] and saw a ship at a distance tossed by a tempest, and in danger every moment of perishing on a rock or sand-bank. But suppose this idea to become still more lively. Suppose the ship to be driven so near me, that I can perceive distinctly the horror, painted on the countenance of the seamen and passengers, hear their lamentable cries, see the dearest friends give their last adieu, or embrace with a resolution to perish in each others arms: No man has so savage a heart as to reap any pleasure from such a spectacle, or withstand the motions of the tenderest compassion and sympathy. It is evident, therefore, there is a medium in this case; and that if the idea be too feint, it has no influence by comparison; and on the other hand, if it be too strong, it operates on us entirely by sympathy, which is the contrary to comparison. Sympathy being the conversion of an idea into an impression, demands a greater force and vivacity in the idea than is requisite to comparison.
Since then, the principles of sympathy and self-comparison are completely opposite, it may be worth considering what general rules can be formed, beyond the individual temperament, for one or the other to prevail. Imagine I’m now safely on land and want to enjoy this moment: I need to think about the unfortunate situation of those at sea in a storm and try to make that idea as vivid and intense as possible to appreciate my own happiness. But no matter how hard I try, the comparison will never be as effective as if I were actually standing on the shore, seeing a ship in the distance tossed by a storm, at risk of crashing on a rock or sandbank. Now, imagine this idea becomes even more vivid. What if the ship is driven so close that I can clearly see the fear on the faces of the sailors and passengers, hear their desperate cries, and watch loved ones say their last goodbyes or hold each other tightly as they accept their fate? No one has such a cruel heart that they would take pleasure from such a scene, or resist the strongest feelings of compassion and sympathy. So it’s clear there’s a balance in this situation: if the idea is too faint, it has no impact through comparison; on the other hand, if it’s too intense, it affects us solely through sympathy, which is the opposite of comparison. Sympathy transforms an idea into an impression, requiring a greater intensity and liveliness in the idea than what’s needed for comparison.
[3]
Suave mari magno turbantibus aequora ventis E terra magnum alterius spectare
laborem; Non quia vexari quenquam eat jucunda voluptas, Sed quibus ipse malls
caress qula cernere sauv' est. LUCRET.
(There is something pleasant in watching, from dry land, the great difficulties
another man is undergoing out on the high sea, with the winds lashing the
waters. This is not because one derives delight from any man's distress, but
because it is pleasurable to perceive from what troubles one is oneself free.)
[3]
There’s something enjoyable about watching, from dry land, the major struggles another person is facing out at sea, with the winds whipping the waves. This isn't because one finds joy in someone else's suffering, but because it's satisfying to see what problems one is free from. LUCRET.
All this is easily applied to the present subject. We sink very much in our own eyes, when in the presence of a great man, or one of a superior genius; and this humility makes a considerable ingredient in that respect, which we pay our superiors, according to our foregoing reasonings on that passion.[4] Sometimes even envy and hatred arise from the comparison; but in the greatest part of men, it rests at respect and esteem. As sympathy has such a powerful influence on the human mind, it causes pride to have, in some measure, the same effect as merit; and by making us enter into those elevated sentiments, which the proud man entertains of himself, presents that comparison, which is so mortifying and disagreeable. Our judgment does not entirely accompany him in the flattering conceit, in which he pleases himself; but still is so shaken as to receive the idea it presents, and to give it an influence above the loose conceptions of the imagination. A man, who, in an idle humour, would form a notion of a person of a merit very much superior to his own, would not be mortified by that fiction: But when a man, whom we are really persuaded to be of inferior merit, is presented to us; if we observe in him any extraordinary degree of pride and self-conceit; the firm persuasion he has of his own merit, takes hold of the imagination, and diminishes us in our own eyes, in the same manner, as if he were really possessed of all the good qualities which he so liberally attributes to himself. Our idea is here precisely in that medium, which is requisite to make it operate on us by comparison. Were it accompanied with belief, and did the person appear to have the same merit, which he assumes to himself, it would have a contrary effect, and would operate on us by sympathy. The influence of that principle would then be superior to that of comparison, contrary to what happens where the person's merit seems below his pretensions.
All this easily applies to the current topic. We tend to feel diminished in our own eyes when we are around a great person or someone with exceptional talent; this humility plays a significant role in the respect we show our superiors, as we've already discussed regarding this emotion. Sometimes, envy and hatred arise from comparison, but for most people, it stays at respect and esteem. Because sympathy has such a strong effect on the human mind, it makes pride somewhat have the same impact as merit; it leads us to engage in the elevated feelings that a proud person has about themselves, presenting us with that mortifying and unpleasant comparison. Our judgment doesn’t fully align with the flattering self-image that pleases them, but it’s still shaken enough to accept the image they present, giving it more influence than the vague notions from our imagination. A person who, in a casual mood, imagines someone with far greater merit than their own wouldn’t feel hurt by that thought. However, when someone we genuinely believe to be less meritorious is in front of us, if we notice any extraordinary pride and self-importance in them, the strong belief they have in their own merit grabs hold of our imagination and makes us feel smaller, just as if they actually had all the qualities they boast about. Our perception is exactly at the level necessary for this to affect us through comparison. If it were accompanied by genuine belief, and the person actually had the same merit they claim to possess, it would have an opposite effect and would impact us through sympathy. The influence of that principle would then outweigh that of comparison, unlike what happens when someone’s merit seems below their claims.
The necessary consequence of these principles is, that pride, or an over-weaning conceit of ourselves, must be vicious; since it causes uneasiness in all men, and presents them every moment with a disagreeable comparison. It is a trite observation in philosophy, and even in common life and conversation, that it is our own pride, which makes us so much displeased with the pride of other people; and that vanity becomes insupportable to us merely because we are vain. The gay naturally associate themselves with the gay, and the amorous with the amorous: But the proud never can endure the proud, and rather seek the company of those who are of an opposite disposition. As we are, all of us, proud in some degree, pride is universally blamed and condemned by all mankind; as having a natural tendency to cause uneasiness in others by means of comparison. And this effect must follow the more naturally, that those, who have an ill-grounded conceit of themselves, are for ever making those comparisons, nor have they any other method of supporting their vanity. A man of sense and merit is pleased with himself, independent of all foreign considerations: But a fool must always find some person, that is more foolish, in order to keep himself in good humour with his own parts and understanding.
The unavoidable outcome of these principles is that pride, or an excessive self-importance, must be harmful; since it creates discomfort for everyone and consistently presents them with an unflattering comparison. It's a common saying in philosophy, and in everyday life and conversation, that our own pride makes us particularly annoyed by the pride of others, and that vanity becomes unbearable to us simply because we are vain. Those who are carefree naturally flock together, and the romantic tend to group with the romantic: But the proud can never stand the proud and would rather seek out the company of those who are different. Since we all possess some level of pride, it is universally criticized and condemned by everyone, as it tends to cause discomfort in others through comparison. This effect is even more pronounced because those with an unfounded sense of superiority are always making those comparisons, as they have no other way to sustain their vanity. A person of intelligence and worth appreciates themselves without relying on external validation: But a fool always needs to find someone even more foolish to feel good about their own intellect and abilities.
But though an over-weaning conceit of our own merit be vicious and disagreeable, nothing can be more laudable, than to have a value for ourselves, where we really have qualities that are valuable. The utility and advantage of any quality to ourselves is a source of virtue, as well as its agreeableness to others; and it is certain, that nothing is more useful to us in the conduct of life, than a due degree of pride, which makes us sensible of our own merit, and gives us a confidence and assurance in all our projects and enterprizes. Whatever capacity any one may be endowed with, it is entirely useless to him, if he be not acquainted with it, and form not designs suitable to it. It is requisite on all occasions to know our own force; and were it allowable to err on either side, it would be more advantageous to over-rate our merit, than to form ideas of it, below its just standard. Fortune commonly favours the bold and enterprizing; and nothing inspires us with more boldness than a good opinion of ourselves.
While an excessive belief in our own worth can be problematic and off-putting, it’s completely commendable to value ourselves when we genuinely possess valuable qualities. The usefulness and benefits of any quality we have contribute to our virtue, as well as its appeal to others. It’s clear that nothing is more beneficial in navigating life than having a healthy level of pride, which makes us aware of our own worth and provides us with confidence in all our projects and endeavors. No matter what abilities someone may have, they are useless if that person isn’t aware of them and doesn’t pursue goals that align with those abilities. It’s essential to recognize our own strengths, and if we are to make a mistake, it’s better to overestimate our worth than to underestimate it. Luck often favors those who are bold and adventurous, and nothing boosts our courage more than a positive self-image.
Add to this, that though pride, or self-applause, be sometimes disagreeable to others, it is always agreeable to ourselves; as on the other hand, modesty, though it gives pleasure to every one, who observes it, produces often uneasiness in the person endowed with it. Now it has been observed, that our own sensations determine the vice and virtue of any quality, as well as those sensations, which it may excite in others.
Additionally, while pride or self-satisfaction can sometimes annoy others, it always feels good to us; conversely, modesty, while pleasing to everyone who sees it, often causes discomfort for the person exhibiting it. It has been noted that our own feelings shape the morality of any trait, as well as the feelings it may evoke in others.
Thus self-satisfaction and vanity may not only be allowable, but requisite in a character. It is, however, certain, that good-breeding and decency require that we should avoid all signs and expressions, which tend directly to show that passion. We have, all of us, a wonderful partiality for ourselves, and were we always to give vent to our sentiments in this particular, we should mutually cause the greatest indignation in each other, not only by the immediate presence of so disagreeable a subject of comparison, but also by the contrariety of our judgments. In like manner, therefore, as we establish the laws of nature, in order to secure property in society, and prevent the opposition of self-interest; we establish the rules of good-breeding, in order to prevent the opposition of men's pride, and render conversation agreeable and inoffensive. Nothing is more disagreeable than a man's over-weaning conceit of himself: Every one almost has a strong propensity to this vice: No one can well distinguish in himself betwixt the vice and virtue, or be certain, that his esteem of his own merit is well-founded: For these reasons, all direct expressions of this passion are condemned; nor do we make any exception to this rule in favour of men of sense and merit. They are not allowed to do themselves justice openly, in words, no more than other people; and even if they show a reserve and secret doubt in doing themselves justice in their own thoughts, they will be more applauded. That impertinent, and almost universal propensity of men, to over-value themselves, has given us such a prejudice against self-applause, that we are apt to condemn it, by a general rule, wherever we meet with it; and it is with some difficulty we give a privilege to men of sense, even in their most secret thoughts. At least, it must be owned, that some disguise in this particular is absolutely requisite; and that if we harbour pride in our breasts, we must carry a fair outside, and have the appearance of modesty and mutual deference in all our conduct and behaviour. We must, on every occasion, be ready to prefer others to ourselves; to treat them with a kind of deference, even though they be our equals; to seem always the lowest and least in the company, where we are not very much distinguished above them: And if we observe these rules in our conduct, men will have more indulgence for our secret sentiments, when we discover them in an oblique manner.
Self-satisfaction and vanity can be not just acceptable, but necessary in a person’s character. However, it's certainly true that good manners and decency require us to avoid any overt signs or expressions of that feeling. We all have a natural bias in favor of ourselves, and if we always expressed our feelings about this, we would end up making each other extremely upset, not only because of the unpleasant comparisons but also due to differing opinions. Just as we create laws of nature to secure property in society and avoid conflicts of self-interest, we establish rules of good manners to prevent clashes of pride and make conversations pleasant and non-offensive. Nothing is more off-putting than a person’s overwhelming arrogance about themselves. Almost everyone tends to be susceptible to this vice. It's hard for anyone to clearly distinguish between their own virtues and flaws or to be certain that their self-esteem is justified. For these reasons, all direct expressions of this feeling are frowned upon; we don’t make exceptions for sensible or accomplished people either. They aren’t permitted to openly praise themselves with words any more than anyone else is, and even if they show restraint and doubt when thinking about their own worth, they will win more admiration for it. That annoying and almost universal tendency of people to overrate themselves has led us to have a strong prejudice against self-praise, so much so that we tend to condemn it as a rule whenever we encounter it; and it’s difficult for us to grant an exception to sensible people, even in their most private thoughts. At the very least, it must be acknowledged that some level of disguise in this matter is absolutely necessary, and if we have pride in our hearts, we must present a humble exterior and show modesty and respect toward others in all our actions and behaviors. We should always be ready to put others before ourselves, to treat them with a kind of respect, even if they are our equals, and to appear the least important in a group unless we are significantly more distinguished than them. If we follow these guidelines in our behavior, people will be more forgiving of our true feelings when we reveal them subtly.
I believe no one, who has any practice of the world, and can penetrate into the inward sentiments of men, will assert, that the humility, which good-breeding and decency require of us, goes beyond the outside, or that a thorough sincerity in this particular is esteemed a real part of our duty. On the contrary, we may observe, that a genuine and hearty pride, or self-esteem, if well concealed and well founded, is essential to the character of a man of honour, and that there is no quality of the mind, which is more indispensibly requisite to procure the esteem and approbation of mankind. There are certain deferences and mutual submissions, which custom requires of the different ranks of men towards each other; and whoever exceeds in this particular, if through interest, is accused of meanness; if through ignorance, of simplicity. It is necessary, therefore, to know our rank and station in the world, whether it be fixed by our birth, fortune, employments, talents or reputation. It is necessary to feel the sentiment and passion of pride in conformity to it, and to regulate our actions accordingly. And should it be said, that prudence may suffice to regulate our actions in this particular, without any real pride, I would observe, that here the object of prudence is to conform our actions to the general usage and custom; and, that it is impossible those tacit airs of superiority should ever have been established and authorized by custom, unless men were generally proud, and unless that passion were generally approved, when well-grounded.
I believe that anyone who has experience in the world and can understand the true feelings of people will not claim that the humility required by good manners and decency goes any deeper than appearances, or that complete honesty in this matter is considered a real part of our responsibilities. On the contrary, we can see that genuine and strong pride, or self-respect, if well-hidden and based on solid reasons, is essential to the character of an honorable person. There is no mental quality more necessary to earn the respect and approval of others. There are certain levels of respect and mutual submission that custom dictates between different social ranks, and anyone who goes too far in this regard, either out of self-interest, is seen as lowly, or out of ignorance, is seen as naïve. Therefore, it is essential to understand our rank and position in the world, whether determined by birth, wealth, job, talents, or reputation. It’s important to experience pride in alignment with that rank and adjust our actions accordingly. And if someone suggests that prudence alone can guide our behavior in this matter without any genuine pride, I would point out that prudence here aims to align our actions with social norms and customs. It’s impossible for those subtle displays of superiority to become established and accepted customs unless people were generally proud and unless that feeling was widely regarded as acceptable when justified.
If we pass from common life and conversation to history, this reasoning acquires new force, when we observe, that all those great actions and sentiments, which have become the admiration of mankind, are founded on nothing but pride and self-esteem. Go, says Alexander the Great to his soldiers, when they refused to follow him to the Indies, go tell your countrymen, that you left Alexander corn pleating the conquest of the world. This passage was always particularly admired by the prince of Conde, as we learn from St Evremond.
If we shift from everyday life and conversation to history, this reasoning gains even more weight when we notice that all those remarkable actions and feelings, which have captured the awe of humanity, are based solely on pride and self-worth. "Go," Alexander the Great tells his soldiers when they refused to join him on his expedition to the Indies, "go tell your fellow countrymen that you left Alexander in the middle of conquering the world." This statement has always been especially admired by the Prince of Condé, as noted by St Evremond.
"ALEXANDER," said that prince, "abandoned by his soldiers, among barbarians, not yet fully subdued, felt in himself such a dignity of right and of empire, that he could not believe it possible any one could refuse to obey him. Whether in Europe or in Asia, among Greeks or Persians, all was indifferent to him: Wherever he found men, he fancied he found subjects."
"ALEXANDER," said that prince, "left behind by his soldiers, surrounded by barbarians who were not yet fully conquered, felt a sense of dignity in his right to rule and his empire that made it hard for him to believe anyone would refuse to obey him. Whether in Europe or Asia, among Greeks or Persians, it didn't matter to him: wherever he encountered people, he believed he found subjects."
In general we may observe, that whatever we call heroic virtue, and admire under the character of greatness and elevation of mind, is either nothing but a steady and well-established pride and self-esteem, or partakes largely of that passion. Courage, intrepidity, ambition, love of glory, magnanimity, and all the other shining virtues of that kind, have plainly a strong mixture of self-esteem in them, and derive a great part of their merit from that origin. Accordingly we find, that many religious declaimers decry those virtues as purely pagan and natural, and represent to us the excellency of the Christian religion, which places humility in the rank of virtues, and corrects the judgment of the world, and even of philosophers, who so generally admire all the efforts of pride and ambition. Whether this virtue of humility has been rightly understood, I shall not pretend to determine. I am content with the concession, that the world naturally esteems a well-regulated pride, which secretly animates our conduct, without breaking out into such indecent expressions of vanity, as many offend the vanity of others.
In general, we can see that what we call heroic virtue, and admire as greatness and elevation of mind, is either just a steady and well-established pride and self-esteem, or it largely includes that feeling. Courage, boldness, ambition, love of glory, nobility, and all those other impressive virtues obviously have a strong mix of self-esteem in them and get much of their value from that source. Consequently, we find that many religious speakers criticize those virtues as purely pagan and natural, and they show us the excellence of the Christian religion, which places humility among the virtues and corrects the judgment of the world and even philosophers, who usually admire all the displays of pride and ambition. Whether this virtue of humility has been properly understood, I won’t claim to decide. I’m fine with the acknowledgment that the world naturally values well-regulated pride, which quietly drives our behavior without breaking into the kind of indecent displays of vanity that bother the pride of others.
The merit of pride or self-esteem is derived from two circumstances, viz, its utility and its agreeableness to ourselves; by which it capacitates us for business, and, at the same time, gives us an immediate satisfaction. When it goes beyond its just bounds, it loses the first advantage, and even becomes prejudicial; which is the reason why we condemn an extravagant pride and ambition, however regulated by the decorums of good-breeding and politeness. But as such a passion is still agreeable, and conveys an elevated and sublime sensation to the person, who is actuated by it, the sympathy with that satisfaction diminishes considerably the blame, which naturally attends its dangerous influence on his conduct and behaviour. Accordingly we may observe, that an excessive courage and magnanimity, especially when it displays itself under the frowns of fortune, contributes in a great measure, to the character of a hero, and will render a person the admiration of posterity; at the same time, that it ruins his affairs, and leads him into dangers and difficulties, with which otherwise he would never have been acquainted.
The value of pride or self-esteem comes from two factors: its usefulness and how good it makes us feel. It enables us to take care of business while also providing immediate satisfaction. However, when it exceeds reasonable limits, it loses its benefits and can even be harmful; that’s why we criticize excessive pride and ambition, no matter how much they are tempered by good manners and politeness. But since such feelings can still be enjoyable and give a sense of elevation and grandeur to those who experience them, our sympathy for that satisfaction greatly lessens the blame that usually accompanies its negative impact on a person’s actions and behavior. Thus, we can see that excessive courage and nobility, especially when faced with hardship, significantly contribute to a person’s heroic character and can earn them admiration from future generations, even as it jeopardizes their affairs and subjects them to challenges they otherwise wouldn’t have faced.
Heroism, or military glory, is much admired by the generality of mankind. They consider it as the most sublime kind of merit. Men of cool reflection are not so sanguine in their praises of it. The infinite confusions and disorder, which it has caused in the world, diminish much of its merit in their eyes. When they would oppose the popular notions on this head, they always paint out the evils, which this supposed virtue has produced in human society; the subversion of empires, the devastation of provinces, the sack of cities. As long as these are present to us, we are more inclined to hate than admire the ambition of heroes. But when we fix our view on the person himself, who is the author of all this mischief, there is something so dazzling in his character, the mere contemplation of it so elevates the mind, that we cannot refuse it our admiration. The pain, which we receive from its tendency to the prejudice of society, is over-powered by a stronger and more immediate sympathy.
Heroism, or military glory, is widely admired by most people. They see it as the highest form of merit. However, those who think things through are not so quick to praise it. The endless chaos and disorder it has caused in the world greatly diminish its value in their eyes. When they challenge popular beliefs about this, they always highlight the harms that this so-called virtue has brought to society: the downfall of empires, the destruction of regions, the looting of cities. As long as these realities are in our minds, we are more likely to dislike than admire the ambitions of heroes. But when we focus on the individual responsible for all this trouble, there is something so captivating about their character that just thinking about it lifts our spirits, making it hard for us not to admire them. The pain we feel from its negative impact on society is overshadowed by a stronger, more immediate sense of empathy.
Thus our explication of the merit or demerit, which attends the degrees of pride or self-esteem, may serve as a strong argument for the preceding hypothesis, by shewing the effects of those principles above explained in all the variations of our judgments concerning that passion. Nor will this reasoning be advantageous to us only by shewing, that the distinction of vice and virtue arises from the four principles of the advantage and of the pleasure of the person himself, and of others: But may also afford us a strong proof of some under-parts of that hypothesis.
Thus, our explanation of the value or lack of value that comes with different levels of pride or self-esteem can strongly support the previous idea by demonstrating the effects of those principles discussed earlier in all the variations of our judgments about that emotion. This reasoning will not only benefit us by showing that the distinction between vice and virtue comes from the four principles concerning the advantage and pleasure of both the individual and others, but it may also provide solid evidence for certain aspects of that hypothesis.
No one, who duly considers of this matter, will make any scruple of allowing, that any piece of in-breeding, or any expression of pride and haughtiness, is displeasing to us, merely because it shocks our own pride, and leads us by sympathy into a comparison, which causes the disagreeable passion of humility. Now as an insolence of this kind is blamed even in a person who has always been civil to ourselves in particular; nay, in one, whose name is only known to us in history; it follows, that our disapprobation proceeds from a sympathy with others, and from the reflection, that such a character is highly displeasing and odious to every one, who converses or has any intercourse with the person possest of it. We sympathize with those people in their uneasiness; and as their uneasiness proceeds in part from a sympathy with the person who insults them, we may here observe a double rebound of the sympathy; which is a principle very similar to what we have observed.[5]
Anyone who thinks about this matter will have no hesitation in agreeing that any form of in-breeding or any display of pride and arrogance is off-putting to us, simply because it offends our own sense of pride and leads us, through empathy, to a comparison that triggers the uncomfortable feeling of humility. This kind of arrogance is criticized even in someone who has always been polite to us, or even in someone whose name we only recognize from history. This shows that our disapproval comes from sympathy with others and the realization that such a character is very unappealing and loathsome to anyone who interacts with that person. We empathize with those who are uncomfortable, and since their discomfort partly comes from sympathy with the person who is being rude to them, we can note a double reaction of sympathy here, which is a principle quite similar to what we have observed.[5]
SECT. III OF GOODNESS AND BENEVOLENCE
Having thus explained the origin of that praise and approbation, which attends every thing we call great in human affections; we now proceed to give an account of their goodness, and shew whence its merit is derived.
Having explained where the praise and approval that comes with everything we call great in human emotions comes from, we now move on to discuss their goodness and show where their value originates.
When experience has once given us a competent knowledge of human affairs, and has taught us the proportion they bear to human passion, we perceive, that the generosity of men is very limited, and that it seldom extends beyond their friends and family, or, at most, beyond their native country. Being thus acquainted with the nature of man, we expect not any impossibilities from him; but confine our view to that narrow circle, in which any person moves, in order to form a judgment of his moral character. When the natural tendency of his passions leads him to be serviceable and useful within his sphere, we approve of his character, and love his person, by a sympathy with the sentiments of those, who have a more particular connexion with him. We are quickly obliged to forget our own interest in our judgments of this kind, by reason of the perpetual contradictions, we meet with in society and conversation, from persons that are not placed in the same situation, and have not the same interest with ourselves. The only point of view, in which our sentiments concur with those of others, is, when we consider the tendency of any passion to the advantage or harm of those, who have any immediate connexion or intercourse with the person possessed of it. And though this advantage or harm be often very remote from ourselves, yet sometimes it is very near us, and interests us strongly by sympathy. This concern we readily extend to other cases, that are resembling; and when these are very remote, our sympathy is proportionably weaker, and our praise or blame fainter and more doubtful. The case is here the same as in our judgments concerning external bodies. All objects seem to diminish by their distance: But though the appearance of objects to our senses be the original standard, by which we judge of them, yet we do not say, that they actually diminish by the distance; but correcting the appearance by reflection, arrive at a more constant and established judgment concerning them. In like manner, though sympathy be much fainter than our concern for ourselves, and a sympathy with persons remote from us much fainter than that with persons near and contiguous; yet we neglect all these differences in our calm judgments concerning the characters of men. Besides, that we ourselves often change our situation in this particular, we every day meet with persons, who are in a different situation from ourselves, and who could never converse with us on any reasonable terms, were we to remain constantly in that situation and point of view, which is peculiar to us. The intercourse of sentiments, therefore, in society and conversation, makes us form some general inalterable standard, by which we may approve or disapprove of characters and manners. And though the heart does not always take part with those general notions, or regulate its love and hatred by them, yet are they sufficient for discourse, and serve all our purposes in company, in the pulpit, on the theatre, and in the schools.
When we've gained a solid understanding of human affairs through experience, and learned how they relate to human emotions, we realize that people's generosity is quite limited, usually extending only to their friends and family, or at most, their country. Having this understanding of human nature, we don't expect the impossible from anyone; instead, we focus on the small circle where each person operates to judge their moral character. When someone's natural emotions drive them to be helpful and useful within their sphere, we approve of their character and like them because we share feelings with those who are more closely connected to them. We often have to set aside our own interests when making these judgments due to the constant contradictions we encounter in society and conversation with people who have different perspectives and interests. Our views align with others primarily when we consider how someone's emotions affect those who have immediate connections or interactions with them. Even though these effects can often be distant from us, there are times when they hit close to home and resonate strongly with us. We readily extend our concern to similar cases; however, when these cases are very distant, our sympathy weakens, and our praise or criticism becomes less certain and more hesitant. The situation here is akin to how we judge external objects: everything seems smaller the further away it is. While our sensory perception serves as the initial standard for judgment, we don't claim that objects actually shrink with distance; instead, we refine our impressions through reflection to reach a more reliable assessment. Similarly, while our sympathy for ourselves is much stronger than for others and sympathy for distant people is weaker than for those close to us, we overlook these differences when calmly judging people's characters. Moreover, we often find ourselves in different situations, meeting people who are in situations unlike our own, and we couldn't have reasonable conversations if we stayed fixed in our own unique perspective. Thus, the exchange of sentiments in society and conversation leads us to establish some general, unchanging standards for approving or disapproving of people’s characters and behaviors. Although our emotions don't always align with these general notions or dictate our feelings of love and hate, they are adequate for discussion and serve our purposes in social settings, in preaching, on stage, and in classrooms.
From these principles we may easily account for that merit, which is commonly ascribed to generosity, humanity, compassion, gratitude, friendship, fidelity, zeal, disinterestedness, liberality, and all those other qualities, which form the character of good and benevolent. A propensity to the tender passions makes a man agreeable and useful in all the parts of life; and gives a just direction to all his other quailties, which otherwise may become prejudicial to society. Courage and ambition, when not regulated by benevolence, are fit only to make a tyrant and public robber. It is the same case with judgment and capacity, and all the qualities of that kind. They are indifferent in themselves to the interests of society, and have a tendency to the good or ill of mankind, according as they are directed by these other passions.
From these principles, we can easily explain the value that is often attributed to generosity, kindness, compassion, gratitude, friendship, loyalty, enthusiasm, selflessness, openness, and all those other qualities that define a good and caring person. A natural inclination towards tender feelings makes a person pleasant and helpful in all areas of life, and it guides all their other qualities, which could otherwise become harmful to society. Without the guidance of kindness, courage and ambition are only suited to create a tyrant and a public thief. The same applies to judgment, skill, and similar qualities. They are neutral in themselves regarding society's interests and can lead to either positive or negative outcomes for humanity, depending on how they are influenced by these other emotions.
As Love is immediately agreeable to the person, who is actuated by it, and hatred immediately disagreeable; this may also be a considerable reason, why we praise all the passions that partake of the former, and blame all those that have any considerable share of the latter. It is certain we are infinitely touched with a tender sentiment, as well as with a great one. The tears naturally start in our eyes at the conception of it; nor can we forbear giving a loose to the same tenderness towards the person who exerts it. All this seems to me a proof, that our approbation has, in those cases, an origin different from the prospect of utility and advantage, either to ourselves or others. To which we may add, that men naturally, without reflection, approve of that character, which is most like their own. The man of a mild disposition and tender affections, in forming a notion of the most perfect virtue, mixes in it more of benevolence and humanity, than the man of courage and enterprize, who naturally looks upon a certain elevation of mind as the most accomplished character. This must evidently proceed from an immediate sympathy, which men have with characters similar to their own. They enter with more warmth into such sentiments, and feel more sensibly the pleasure, which arises from them.
Since love is instantly pleasing to the person who feels it, and hatred is immediately off-putting, this may explain why we praise all the emotions associated with love and criticize those that involve hatred. It’s clear that we’re deeply moved by both tender feelings and powerful ones. Tears naturally spring to our eyes when we think of it, and we can’t help but express the same kind of tenderness toward the person who shows it. All of this seems to show that our approval in these cases comes from somewhere other than just the prospect of usefulness or benefit to ourselves or others. Additionally, people tend to, without even thinking about it, approve of characters that resemble their own. A person with a gentle nature and caring feelings, when imagining the ideal virtue, includes more kindness and compassion than someone who is bold and adventurous, who naturally views a certain level of ambition as the ultimate character. This clearly comes from a natural empathy people have for characters similar to theirs. They connect more passionately with such feelings and experience the pleasure they bring more intensely.
It is remarkable, that nothing touches a man of humanity more than any instance of extraordinary delicacy in love or friendship, where a person is attentive to the smallest concerns of his friend, and is willing to sacrifice to them the most considerable interest of his own. Such delicacies have little influence on society; because they make us regard the greatest trifles: But they are the more engaging, the more minute the concern is, and are a proof of the highest merit in any one, who is capable of them. The passions are so contagious, that they pass with the greatest facility from one person to another, and produce correspondent movements in all human breasts. Where friendship appears in very signal instances, my heart catches the same passion, and is warmed by those warm sentiments, that display themselves before me. Such agreeable movements must give me an affection to every one that excites them. This is the case with every thing that is agreeable in any person. The transition from pleasure to love is easy: But the transition must here be still more easy; since the agreeable sentiment, which is excited by sympathy, is love itself; and there is nothing required but to change the object.
It's amazing how nothing moves a compassionate person more than moments of exceptional tenderness in love or friendship, where someone pays attention to even the smallest worries of their friend and is willing to sacrifice their own significant interests for them. These acts of kindness have little impact on society because they prompt us to focus on the tiniest details. However, they become even more charming the more minor the issue is, and they demonstrate the highest virtue in anyone capable of such kindness. Emotions are so infectious that they easily transfer from one person to another, creating similar feelings in everyone. When friendship shows itself in remarkable ways, my heart feels the same emotions and is warmed by the heartfelt sentiments displayed before me. Such pleasant feelings naturally make me care for everyone who inspires them. This is true for anything enjoyable about any person. The shift from pleasure to love is simple: but in this case, it should be even simpler, since the enjoyable feeling triggered by empathy is love itself; all that’s needed is to change the object of that emotion.
Hence the peculiar merit of benevolence in all its shapes and appearances. Hence even its weaknesses are virtuous and amiable; and a person, whose grief upon the loss of a friend were excessive, would be esteemed upon that account. His tenderness bestows a merit, as it does a pleasure, on his melancholy.
Therefore, the unique value of kindness in all its forms and expressions. Even its flaws are seen as virtuous and likable; a person whose grief over losing a friend is intense would be regarded positively for it. Their sensitivity adds worth and pleasure to their sadness.
We are not, however, to imagine, that all the angry passions are vicious, though they are disagreeable. There is a certain indulgence due to human nature in this respect. Anger and hatred are passions inherent in Our very frame and constitutions. The want of them, on some occasions, may even be a proof of weakness and imbecillity. And where they appear only in a low degree, we not only excuse them because they are natural; but even bestow our applauses on them, because they are inferior to what appears in the greatest part of mankind.
We shouldn't think that all angry emotions are bad, even though they can be unpleasant. There's a certain allowance we should give to human nature in this regard. Anger and hatred are feelings that are part of our very being. Lacking them at certain times might even show weakness or fragility. When they show up only at a low level, we not only forgive them because they are natural, but we also praise them because they are less intense than what we see in most people.
Where these angry passions rise up to cruelty, they form the most detested of all vices. All the pity and concern which we have for the miserable sufferers by this vice, turns against the person guilty of it, and produces a stronger hatred than we are sensible of on any other occasion. Even when the vice of inhumanity rises not to this extreme degree, our sentiments concerning it are very much influenced by reflections on the harm that results from it. And we may observe in general, that if we can find any quality in a person, which renders him incommodious to those, who live and converse with him, we always allow it to be a fault or blemish, without any farther examination. On the other hand, when we enumerate the good qualities of any person, we always mention those parts of his character, which render him a safe companion, an easy friend, a gentle master, an agreeable husband, or an indulgent father. We consider him with all his relations in society; and love or hate him, according as he affects those, who have any immediate intercourse with him. And it is a most certain rule, that if there be no relation of life, in which I could not wish to stand to a particular person, his character must so far be allowed to be perfect. If he be as little wanting to himself as to others, his character is entirely perfect. This is the ultimate test of merit and virtue.
When these intense emotions escalate to cruelty, they become the most hated of all vices. All the sympathy and concern we feel for the unfortunate victims of this vice turns against the person responsible, creating a deeper hatred than we experience in any other situation. Even when the vice of inhumanity doesn't reach such an extreme, our feelings about it are heavily shaped by the harm it causes. Generally, we notice that if we find any quality in someone that makes them difficult for those around them, we instantly consider it a flaw or defect without further thought. In contrast, when we highlight someone's good qualities, we always point out aspects of their character that make them a reliable companion, a supportive friend, a kind master, a pleasant spouse, or a caring parent. We think of them in relation to their role in society and form our feelings of love or hate based on how they affect those who interact with them. It's a clear rule that if there is no aspect of life in which I wouldn't want to have a relationship with a particular person, their character can be considered perfect to that extent. If they are as considerate of themselves as they are of others, their character is completely flawless. This is the ultimate measure of merit and virtue.
SECT. IV OF NATURAL ABILITIES
No distinction is more usual in all systems of ethics, than that betwixt natural abilities and moral virtues; where the former are placed on the same footing with bodily endowments, and are supposed to have no merit or moral worth annexed to them. Whoever considers the matter accurately, will find, that a dispute upon this head would be merely a dispute of words, and that though these qualities are not altogether of the same kind, yet they agree in the most material circumstances. They are both of them equally mental qualities: And both of them equally produce pleasure; and have of course an equal tendency to procure the love and esteem of mankind. There are few, who are not as jealous of their character, with regard to sense and knowledge, as to honour and courage; and much more than with regard to temperance and sobriety. Men are even afraid of passing for goodnatured; lest that should be taken for want of understanding: And often boast of more debauches than they have been really engaged in, to give themselves airs of fire and spirit. In short, the figure a man makes in the world, the reception he meets with in company, the esteem paid him by his acquaintance; all these advantages depend almost as much upon his good sense and judgment, as upon any other part of his character. Let a man have the best intentions in the world, and be the farthest from all injustice and violence, he will never be able to make himself be much regarded without a moderate share, at least, of parts and understanding. Since then natural abilities, though, perhaps, inferior, yet are on the same footing, both as to their causes and effects, with those qualities which we call moral virtues, why should we make any distinction betwixt them?
No distinction is more common in all systems of ethics than the one between natural abilities and moral virtues. The former are treated similarly to physical talents and are thought to have no merit or moral worth attached to them. Anyone who examines this closely will see that a debate on this issue would just be a dispute over words. Although these qualities are not entirely the same, they share important similarities. Both are mental qualities and both can create pleasure, which in turn leads to gaining the love and respect of others. Few people are not as protective of their reputation regarding intelligence and knowledge as they are about honor and bravery, and even more so than about self-control and sobriety. People are often wary of being seen as too nice, fearing it might imply a lack of intelligence, and they might exaggerate their wildness to appear passionate and spirited. Ultimately, how a person is perceived in the world, the reception they receive in social settings, and the regard held by their peers—all of these factors depend nearly as much on their good judgment and sense as on any other aspect of their character. Even if someone has the best intentions and is far from unjust or violent, they won’t gain much recognition without at least a moderate level of intelligence and understanding. Since natural abilities, though perhaps less esteemed, are comparable in their causes and effects to what we call moral virtues, why should we draw any distinction between them?
Though we refuse to natural abilities the title of virtues, we must allow, that they procure the love and esteem of mankind; that they give a new lustre to the other virtues; and that a man possessed of them is much more intitled to our good-will and services, than one entirely void of them. It may, indeed, be pretended that the sentiment of approbation, which those qualities produce, besides its being inferior, is also somewhat different from that, which attends the other virtues. But this, in my opinion, is not a sufficient reason for excluding them from the catalogue of virtues. Each of the virtues, even benevolence, justice, gratitude, integrity, excites a different sentiment or feeling in the spectator. The characters of Caesar and Cato, as drawn by Sallust, are both of them virtuous, in the strictest sense of the word; but in a different way: Nor are the sentiments entirely the same, which arise from them. The one produces love; the other esteem: The one is amiable; the other awful: We could wish to meet with the one character in a friend; the other character we would be ambitious of in ourselves. In like manner, the approbation which attends natural abilities, may be somewhat different to the feeling from that, which arises from the other virtues, without making them entirely of a different species. And indeed we may observe, that the natural abilities, no more than the other virtues, produce not, all of them, the same kind of approbation. Good sense and genius beget esteem: Wit and humour excite love.[6]
Although we don't consider natural abilities to be virtues, we must acknowledge that they earn people’s love and respect; they enhance the other virtues, and a person who possesses them is much more deserving of our goodwill and assistance than someone who lacks them completely. It might be argued that the approval generated by these qualities is not only inferior but also somewhat different from that which accompanies other virtues. However, I believe this is not a valid reason to exclude them from the list of virtues. Each virtue, even kindness, fairness, gratitude, and honesty, elicits a different feeling in the observer. The characters of Caesar and Cato, as portrayed by Sallust, are both virtuous in the strictest sense, but in different ways: the feelings they evoke are not entirely the same. One inspires love; the other inspires respect. We would want to see one character in a friend, while we would aspire to embody the other character ourselves. Similarly, the approval that comes with natural abilities may differ from the feelings that arise from other virtues without making them completely different categories. In fact, we can also see that natural abilities, just like other virtues, do not all produce the same kind of approval. Common sense and talent generate respect; wit and humor inspire love.
[6] Love and esteem are at the bottom the same passions, and arise from like causes. The qualities, that produce both, are agreeable, and give pleasure. But where this pleasure is severe and serious; or where its object is great, and makes a strong impression; or where it produces any degree of humility and awe: In all these cases, the passion, which arises from the pleasure, is more properly denominated esteem than love. Benevolence attends both: But is connected with love in a more eminent degree.
[6] Love and respect are basically the same feelings, stemming from similar reasons. The traits that lead to both are pleasing and enjoyable. However, when this pleasure is intense and serious; or when its object is significant and leaves a strong impact; or when it evokes a sense of humility and awe: In all these situations, the feeling that arises from the pleasure is more accurately called esteem rather than love. Kindness is present in both, but it’s more closely associated with love.
Those, who represent the distinction betwixt natural abilities and moral virtues as very material, may say, that the former are entirely involuntary, and have therefore no merit attending them, as having no dependance on liberty and free-will. But to this I answer, first, that many of those qualities, which all moralists, especially the antients, comprehend under the title of moral virtues, are equally involuntary and necessary, with the qualities of the judgment and imagination. Of this nature are constancy, fortitude, magnanimity; and, in short, all the qualities which form the great man. I might say the same, in some degree, of the others; it being almost impossible for the mind to change its character in any considerable article, or cure itself of a passionate or splenetic temper, when they are natural to it. The greater degree there is of these blameable qualities, the more vicious they become, and yet they are the less voluntary. Secondly, I would have anyone give me a reason, why virtue and vice may not be involuntary, as well as beauty and deformity. These moral distinctions arise from the natural distinctions of pain and pleasure; and when we receive those feelings from the general consideration of any quality or character, we denominate it vicious or virtuous. Now I believe no one will assert, that a quality can never produce pleasure or pain to the person who considers it, unless it be perfectly voluntary in the person who possesses it. Thirdly, As to free-will, we have shewn that it has no place with regard to the actions, no more than the qualities of men. It is not a just consequence, that what is voluntary is free. Our actions are more voluntary than our judgments; but we have not more liberty in the one than in the other.
Those who highlight the difference between natural abilities and moral virtues as significant might argue that natural abilities are completely involuntary and, therefore, lack merit since they don't depend on freedom and free will. In response, I would point out that many qualities that all moralists, especially the ancients, classify as moral virtues are just as involuntary and necessary as the qualities of judgment and imagination. Qualities like constancy, courage, and nobility fall into this category, encompassing all the traits that define a great person. I could also say the same to some extent about other qualities; it's nearly impossible for someone to change their character significantly or to rid themselves of a passionate or moody temperament if those traits are natural to them. The more prominent these undesirable qualities are, the more harmful they become, yet they remain less voluntary. Secondly, I challenge anyone to explain why virtue and vice cannot be involuntary just like beauty and ugliness. These moral distinctions come from our natural experiences of pain and pleasure; when we perceive certain qualities or characters, we label them as vicious or virtuous. I doubt anyone would argue that a quality can never produce pleasure or pain for the observer unless it is entirely voluntary in the person who possesses it. Thirdly, regarding free will, we have shown that it does not apply to actions any more than it does to human qualities. It is not a valid assumption that what is voluntary is free. Our actions are more voluntary than our judgments, but we do not have any more freedom in one than the other.
But though this distinction betwixt voluntary and involuntary be not sufficient to justify the distinction betwixt natural abilities and moral virtues, yet the former distinction will afford us a plausible reason, why moralists have invented the latter. Men have observed, that though natural abilities and moral qualities be in the main on the same footing, there is, however, this difference betwixt them, that the former are almost invariable by any art or industry; while the latter, or at least, the actions, that proceed from them, may be changed by the motives of rewards and punishments, praise and blame. Hence legislators, and divines, and moralists, have principally applied themselves to the regulating these voluntary actions, and have endeavoured to produce additional motives, for being virtuous in that particular. They knew, that to punish a man for folly, or exhort him to be prudent and sagacious, would have but little effect; though the same punishments and exhortations, with regard to justice and injustice, might have a considerable influence. But as men, in common life and conversation, do not carry those ends in view, but naturally praise or blame whatever pleases or displeases them, they do not seem much to regard this distinction, but consider prudence under the character of virtue as well as benevolence, and penetration as well as justice. Nay, we find, that all moralists, whose judgment is not perverted by a strict adherence to a system, enter into the same way of thinking; and that the antient moralists in particular made no scruple of placing prudence at the head of the cardinal virtues. There is a sentiment of esteem and approbation, which may be excited, in some degree, by any faculty of the mind, in its perfect state and condition; and to account for this sentiment is the business of Philosophers. It belongs to Grammarians to examine what qualities are entitled to the denomination of virtue; nor will they find, upon trial, that this is so easy a task, as at first sight they may be apt to imagine.
But even though the difference between voluntary and involuntary actions isn’t enough to justify separating natural abilities from moral virtues, this distinction does give us a reasonable explanation for why moralists have created the latter. People have noticed that while natural abilities and moral qualities are generally treated the same, there’s a clear difference: natural abilities usually can’t be changed by effort or hard work, whereas moral qualities—or at least the actions that come from them—can be influenced by rewards and punishments, praise and criticism. Because of this, lawmakers, religious leaders, and moralists have focused primarily on regulating these voluntary actions and have tried to create more reasons for being virtuous in that respect. They understood that punishing someone for foolishness or urging them to be wise and discerning usually wouldn’t have much effect, while the same punishments and encouragements concerning justice might have a significant impact. However, in everyday life and conversations, people don’t usually think in those terms; instead, they naturally praise or criticize whatever they find pleasing or displeasing. Because of this, they don’t pay much attention to this distinction and see prudence as a virtue just like benevolence, and insight as well as justice. In fact, we see that all moralists, whose judgment isn’t clouded by a rigid commitment to a system, think in this way; the ancient moralists especially had no hesitation in placing prudence at the top of the cardinal virtues. There is a feeling of respect and approval that can be triggered, to some extent, by any mental ability in its ideal state; explaining this feeling is the task of philosophers. It is up to grammarians to determine which qualities deserve the title of virtue, and they will find, upon investigation, that this task is not as straightforward as they might initially believe.
The principal reason why natural abilities are esteemed, is because of their tendency to be useful to the person, who is possessed of them. It is impossible to execute any design with success, where it is not conducted with prudence and discretion; nor will the goodness of our intentions alone suffice to procure us a happy issue to our enterprizes. Men are superior to beasts principally by the superiority of their reason; and they are the degrees of the same faculty, which set such an infinite difference betwixt one man and another. All the advantages of art are owing to human reason; and where fortune is not very capricious, the most considerable part of these advantages must fall to the share of the prudent and sagacious.
The main reason natural talents are valued is because they tend to be useful to the people who have them. It's impossible to successfully carry out any plan without being careful and sensible; good intentions alone won't guarantee a positive outcome for our efforts. Humans are superior to animals mainly because of their greater reasoning ability, and the different levels of this ability create a huge gap between one person and another. All the benefits of skill come from human reasoning, and when luck isn’t too unpredictable, most of these benefits will go to those who are wise and thoughtful.
When it is asked, whether a quick or a slow apprehension be most valuable? whether one, that at first view penetrates into a subject, but can perform nothing upon study; or a contrary character, which must work out every thing by dint of application? whether a clear head, or a copious invention? whether a profound genius, or a sure judgment? in short, what character, or peculiar understanding, is more excellent than another? It is evident we can answer none of these questions, without considering which of those qualities capacitates a man best for the world, and carries him farthest in any of his undertakings.
When we ask whether a quick or slow understanding is more valuable—whether someone who grasps a subject immediately but struggles with deeper study, or someone who needs to work hard for everything—whether a clear mind or a rich imagination is better, or a deep intellect versus good judgment—we need to figure out which quality is truly superior. Ultimately, we can’t answer these questions without looking at which of these traits best prepares a person for the world and helps them succeed in their endeavors.
There are many other qualities of the mind, whose merit is derived from the same origin, industry, perseverance, patience, activity, vigilance, application, constancy, with other virtues of that kind, which it will be easy to recollect, are esteemed valuable upon no other account, than their advantage in the conduct of life. It is the same case with temperance, frugality, economy, resolution: As on the other hand, prodigality, luxury, irresolution, uncertainty, are vicious, merely because they draw ruin upon us, and incapacitate us for business and action.
There are many other qualities of the mind that come from the same source: hard work, perseverance, patience, activity, alertness, focus, consistency, and other similar virtues that we easily recognize as valuable mainly because they help us navigate life effectively. The same goes for traits like self-control, thriftiness, financial savvy, and determination. On the flip side, extravagance, indulgence, lack of resolve, and indecisiveness are seen as negative simply because they lead to our downfall and hinder our ability to be productive and take action.
As wisdom and good-sense are valued, because they are useful to the person possessed of them; so wit and eloquence are valued, because they are immediately agreeable to others. On the other hand, good humour is loved and esteemed, because it is immediately agreeable to the person himself. It is evident, that the conversation of a man of wit is very satisfactory; as a chearful good-humoured companion diffuses a joy over the whole company, from a sympathy with his gaiety. These qualities, therefore, being agreeable, they naturally beget love and esteem, and answer to all the characters of virtue.
As wisdom and common sense are appreciated because they benefit the person who has them, wit and eloquence are valued because they are instantly enjoyable for others. In contrast, good humor is loved and respected because it brings immediate joy to the person themselves. It’s clear that talking with a witty person is very satisfying; a cheerful and good-humored friend spreads happiness throughout the entire group through their shared joy. These traits are therefore pleasing, naturally generating love and respect, aligning with all the attributes of virtue.
It is difficult to tell, on many occasions, what it is that renders one man's conversation so agreeable and entertaining, and another's so insipid and distasteful. As conversation is a transcript of the mind as well as books, the same qualities, which render the one valuable, must give us an esteem for the other. This we shall consider afterwards. In the mean time it may be affirmed in general, that all the merit a man may derive from his conversation (which, no doubt, may be very considerable) arises from nothing but the pleasure it conveys to those who are present.
It's often hard to say why one person's conversation is so enjoyable and engaging while another's is boring and unpleasant. Just like books, conversation reflects the mind, and the same qualities that make one valuable should also enhance our appreciation for the other. We'll look into that later. For now, it's safe to say that all the value someone might gain from their conversation (which can definitely be significant) comes purely from the enjoyment it brings to those who are listening.
In this view, cleanliness is also to be regarded as a virtue; since it naturally renders us agreeable to others, and is a very considerable source of love and affection. No one will deny, that a negligence in this particular is a fault; and as faults are nothing but smaller vices, and this fault can have no other origin than the uneasy sensation, which it excites in others, we may in this instance, seemingly so trivial, dearly discover the origin of the moral distinction of vice and virtue in other instances.
In this perspective, cleanliness is seen as a virtue because it naturally makes us more pleasant to others and is a significant source of love and affection. No one can deny that neglecting this aspect is a flaw; and since flaws are just lesser vices, and this particular flaw stems from the discomfort it causes in others, we can, in this seemingly trivial case, uncover the root of the moral distinction between vice and virtue in other situations.
Besides all those qualities, which render a person lovely or valuable, there is also a certain JE-NE-SAIS-QUOI of agreeable and handsome, that concurs to the same effect. In this case, as well as in that of wit and eloquence, we must have recourse to a certain sense, which acts without reflection, and regards not the tendencies of qualities and characters. Some moralists account for all the sentiments of virtue by this sense. Their hypothesis is very plausible. Nothing but a particular enquiry can give the preference to any other hypothesis. When we find, that almost all the virtues have such particular tendencies; and also find, that these tendencies are sufficient alone to give a strong sentiment of approbation: We cannot doubt, after this, that qualities are approved of, in proportion to the advantage, which results from them.
Along with all those qualities that make a person charming or valuable, there's also a certain indescribable appeal that contributes to the same effect. In this situation, just like with wit and eloquence, we need to rely on a certain instinct that functions without conscious thought and doesn't consider the underlying tendencies of qualities and traits. Some moral philosophers explain all feelings of virtue through this instinct. Their idea is quite convincing. Only a detailed investigation can favor one explanation over another. When we notice that almost all virtues have specific tendencies, and that these tendencies alone can evoke a strong feeling of approval, we can be confident that qualities are valued in proportion to the benefits they bring.
The decorum or indecorum of a quality, with regard to the age, or character, or station, contributes also to its praise or blame. This decorum depends, in a great measure, upon experience. It is usual to see men lose their levity, as they advance in years. Such a degree of gravity, therefore, and such years, are connected together in our thoughts. When we observe them separated in any person's character, this imposes a kind of violence on our imagination, and is disagreeable.
The appropriateness or inappropriateness of a quality, considering someone's age, character, or position, also plays a role in how we praise or blame them. This appropriateness largely depends on experience. It's common to see people become more serious as they get older. So, this level of seriousness and age are linked in our minds. When we see these traits separated in someone's character, it feels jarring to our imagination and is unpleasant.
That faculty of the soul, which, of all others, is of the least consequence to the character, and has the least virtue or vice in its several degrees, at the same time, that it admits of a great variety of degrees, is the memory. Unless it rise up to that stupendous height as to surprize us, or sink so low as, in some measure, to affect the judgment, we commonly take no notice of its variations, nor ever mention them to the praise or dispraise of any person. It is so far from being a virtue to have a good memory, that men generally affect to complain of a bad one; and endeavouring to persuade the world, that what they say is entirely of their own invention, sacrifice it to the praise of genius and judgment. Yet to consider the matter abstractedly, it would be difficult to give a reason, why the faculty of recalling past ideas with truth and clearness, should not have as much merit in it, as the faculty of placing our present ideas, in such an order, as to form true propositions and opinions. The reason of the difference certainly must be, that the memory is exerted without any sensation of pleasure or pain; and in all its middling degrees serves almost equally well in business and affairs. But the least variations in the judgment are sensibly felt in their consequences; while at the same time that faculty is never exerted in any eminent degree, without an extraordinary delight and satisfaction. The sympathy with this utility and pleasure bestows a merit on the understanding; and the absence of it makes us consider the memory as a faculty very indifferent to blame or praise.
The part of the mind that matters the least when it comes to someone's character, and has the least value or moral weight in its various forms, while also allowing for a wide range of levels, is memory. Unless it reaches such an impressive level that it astonishes us, or drops so low that it somewhat affects our judgment, we usually overlook its differences and don’t mention them when talking about someone’s strengths or weaknesses. Having a good memory isn’t even considered a virtue; people often complain about having a poor one and try to convince others that their ideas come entirely from their own creativity, which they then attribute to talent and good judgment. However, if we think about it objectively, it’s hard to understand why the ability to recall past ideas clearly and accurately shouldn't have as much value as the ability to organize our current thoughts to create true statements and beliefs. The difference likely comes from the fact that we use memory without feeling any pleasure or pain, and it serves almost equally well in tasks and activities in its average forms. But small changes in judgment have noticeable effects, and using that ability to a high degree always comes with great joy and satisfaction. This connection to usefulness and pleasure gives value to understanding, while the lack of it leads us to view memory as a faculty that's not really subject to blame or praise.
Before I leave this subject of natural abilities, I must observe, that, perhaps, one source of the esteem and affection, which attends them, is derived from the importance and weight, which they bestow on the person possessed of them. He becomes of greater consequence in life. His resolutions and actions affect a greater number of his fellow-creatures. Both his friendship and enmity are of moment. And it is easy to observe, that whoever is elevated, after this manner, above the rest of mankind, must excite in us the sentiments of esteem and approbation. Whatever is important engages our attention, fixes our thought, and is contemplated with satisfaction. The histories of kingdoms are more interesting than domestic stories: The histories of great empires more than those of small cities and principalities: And the histories of wars and revolutions more than those of peace and order. We sympathize with the persons that suffer, in all the various sentiments which belong to their fortunes. The mind is occupied by the multitude of the objects, and by the strong passions, that display themselves. And this occupation or agitation of the mind is commonly agreeable and amusing. The same theory accounts for the esteem and regard we pay to men of extraordinary parts and abilities. The good and ill of multitudes are connected with their actions. Whatever they undertake is important, and challenges our attention. Nothing is to be over-looked and despised, that regards them. And where any person can excite these sentiments, he soon acquires our esteem; unless other circumstances of his character render him odious and disagreeable.
Before I move on from the topic of natural abilities, I want to point out that one reason we hold them in such high regard is because they add significance to the person who possesses them. They become more important in life. Their choices and actions impact more people. Both their friendships and rivalries matter. It’s easy to see that whoever stands out like this among others tends to evoke feelings of respect and approval in us. Anything significant grabs our attention, engages our thoughts, and is viewed with satisfaction. The stories of kingdoms are more captivating than family tales: the stories of great empires are more interesting than those of small towns and regions: and the narratives of wars and revolutions are more compelling than those of peace and stability. We empathize with those who suffer, experiencing all the various emotions tied to their fortunes. Our minds are filled with numerous objects and the intense emotions that unfold. This engagement or excitement of the mind is generally enjoyable and entertaining. The same idea explains the respect and admiration we show toward individuals with extraordinary talents and abilities. The fortunes of many are tied to their actions. Anything they do is important and grabs our focus. Nothing about them should be overlooked or regarded as insignificant. When someone can evoke these feelings, they quickly earn our respect, unless other aspects of their character make them unpleasant or unlikable.
SECT. V SOME FARTHER REFLECTIONS CONCERNING THE NATURAL VIRTUES
It has been observed, in treating of the passions, that pride and humility, love and hatred, are excited by any advantages or disadvantages of the mind, body, or fortune; and that these advantages or disadvantages have that effect by producing a separate impression of pain or pleasure. The pain or pleasure, which arises from the general survey or view of any action or quality of the mind, constitutes its vice or virtue, and gives rise to our approbation or blame, which is nothing but a fainter and more imperceptible love or hatred. We have assigned four different sources of this pain and pleasure; and in order to justify more fully that hypothesis, it may here be proper to observe, that the advantages or disadvantages of the body and of fortune, produce a pain or pleasure from the very same principles. The tendency of any object to be useful to the person possessed of it, or to others; to convey pleasure to him or to others; all these circumstances convey an immediate pleasure to the person, who considers the object, and command his love and approbation.
It has been noted that when discussing emotions, pride and humility, love and hate, are triggered by any advantages or disadvantages related to the mind, body, or circumstances; and that these advantages or disadvantages create a distinct feeling of pain or pleasure. The pain or pleasure that comes from our overall assessment of any action or mental quality forms its vice or virtue, leading to our approval or disapproval, which is essentially a weaker and less noticeable form of love or hate. We have identified four different sources of this pain and pleasure, and to further support that idea, it's worth mentioning that the advantages or disadvantages of the body and circumstances also produce pain or pleasure based on the same principles. The way an object tends to be useful to the person who has it, or to others; the pleasure it brings to them or others; all of these factors provide immediate pleasure to the individual considering the object, and inspire their love and approval.
To begin with the advantages of the body; we may observe a phænomenon, which might appear somewhat trivial and ludicrous, if any thing could be trivial, which fortified a conclusion of such importance, or ludicrous, which was employed in a philosophical reasoning. It is a general remark, that those we call good women's men, who have either signalized themselves by their amorous exploits, or whose make of body promises any extraordinary vigour of that kind, are well received by the fair sex, and naturally engage the affections even of those, whose virtue prevents any design of ever giving employment to those talents. Here it is evident, that the ability of such a person to give enjoyment, is the real source of that love and esteem he meets with among the females; at the same time that the women, who love and esteem him, have no prospect of receiving that enjoyment themselves, and can only be affected by means of their sympathy with one, that has a commerce of love with him. This instance is singular, and merits our attention.
To start with the benefits of the body, we can notice a phenomenon that may seem somewhat trivial and silly, even if nothing can truly be trivial when it supports such an important conclusion, or silly when it's used in philosophical reasoning. Generally speaking, we notice that those men we call "good with women," who have either distinguished themselves through their romantic exploits or whose physical appearance suggests extraordinary vigor in that regard, are well-received by women. They easily capture the affection of even those whose virtues would prevent them from ever engaging those talents. Here, it's clear that the ability of such a man to provide enjoyment is the real reason for the love and admiration he receives from women, even though the women who love and admire him have no chance of experiencing that enjoyment themselves and are only moved through their sympathy for someone else who has a romantic connection with him. This example is unique and deserves our attention.
Another source of the pleasure we receive from considering bodily advantages, is their utility to the person himself, who is possessed of them. It is certain, that a considerable part of the beauty of men, as well as of other animals, consists in such a conformation of members, as we find by experience to be attended with strength and agility, and to capacitate the creature for any action or exercise. Broad shoulders, a lank belly, firm joints, taper legs; all these are beautiful in our species because they are signs of force and vigour, which being advantages we naturally sympathize with, they convey to the beholder a share of that satisfaction they produce in the possessor.
Another source of the pleasure we get from thinking about physical advantages is their usefulness to the person who has them. It's clear that a significant part of what we consider attractive in men, as well as in other animals, comes from a body shape that we know through experience is associated with strength and agility, enabling the creature to engage in various activities. Broad shoulders, a flat stomach, strong joints, and slender legs; all these traits are considered beautiful in our species because they symbolize power and vitality. Since these are qualities we naturally admire, they also give the viewer a sense of the satisfaction that the person possessing them experiences.
So far as to the utility, which may attend any quality of the body. As to the immediate pleasure, it is certain, that an air of health, as well as of strength and agility, makes a considerable part of beauty; and that a sickly air in another is always disagreeable, upon account of that idea of pain and uneasiness, which it conveys to us. On the other hand, we are pleased with the regularity of our own features, though it be neither useful to ourselves nor others; and it is necessary at a distance, to make it convey to us any satisfaction. We commonly consider ourselves as we appear in the eyes of others, and sympathize with the advantageous sentiments they entertain with regard to us.
When it comes to the usefulness of any physical trait, it’s clear that having a healthy appearance, along with strength and agility, significantly contributes to beauty. Meanwhile, a sickly look in someone else is always off-putting because it reminds us of pain and discomfort. On the flip side, we appreciate the symmetry of our own features, even if it doesn’t benefit us or anyone else; it has to be seen from a distance to bring us any joy. We often see ourselves through how others perceive us, and we resonate with the positive thoughts they have about us.
How far the advantages of fortune produce esteem and approbation from the same principles, we may satisfy ourselves by reflecting on our precedent reasoning on that subject. We have observed, that our approbation of those, who are possessed of the advantages of fortune, may be ascribed to three different causes. First, To that immediate pleasure, which a rich man gives us, by the view of the beautiful cloaths, equipage, gardens, or houses, which he possesses. Secondly, To the advantage, which we hope to reap from him by his generosity and liberality. Thirdly, To the pleasure and advantage, which he himself reaps from his possessions, and which produce an agreeable sympathy in us. Whether we ascribe our esteem of the rich and great to one or all of these causes, we may clearly see the traces of those principles, which give rise to the sense of vice and virtue. I believe most people, at first sight, will be inclined to ascribe our esteem of the rich to self-interest, and the prospect of advantage. But as it is certain, that our esteem or deference extends beyond any prospect of advantage to ourselves, it is evident, that that sentiment must proceed from a sympathy with those, who are dependent on the person we esteem and respect, and who have an immediate connexion with him. We consider him as a person capable of contributing to the happiness or enjoyment of his fellow-creatures, whose sentiments, with regard to him, we naturally embrace. And this consideration will serve to justify my hypothesis in preferring the third principle to the other two, and ascribing our esteem of the rich to a sympathy with the pleasure and advantage, which they themselves receive from their possessions. For as even the other two principles cannot operate to a due extent, or account for all the phaenomena, without having recourse to a sympathy of one kind or other; it is much more natural to chuse that sympathy, which is immediate and direct, than that which is remote and indirect. To which we may add, that where the riches or power are very great, and render the person considerable and important in the world, the esteem attending them, may, in part, be ascribed to another source, distinct from these three, viz. their interesting the mind by a prospect of the multitude, and importance of their consequences: Though, in order to account for the operation of this principle, we must also have recourse to sympathy; as we have observed in the preceding section.
How much do the benefits of wealth lead to respect and approval based on the same ideas? We can understand this by reflecting on our earlier discussions on the topic. We've noticed that our respect for those with wealth can be attributed to three main reasons. First, the immediate pleasure a wealthy person brings us through their beautiful clothes, fancy cars, gardens, or homes. Second, the benefits we hope to gain from their generosity and kindness. Third, the happiness and advantages they experience from their possessions, which we find appealing. Whether we attribute our admiration for the rich and powerful to one or all of these reasons, we can clearly see the underlying principles that give rise to our sense of right and wrong. I believe most people, at first glance, will tend to think our admiration for the rich comes from self-interest and potential benefits to ourselves. However, since our admiration and respect often extend beyond any personal gain, it’s clear that this feeling must come from a connection with those who depend on the person we admire and who have a close relationship with them. We see them as someone who can enhance the happiness or enjoyment of others, whose opinions we naturally align with. This viewpoint supports my argument for favoring the third reason over the other two, as it connects our admiration for the wealthy to a shared pleasure and benefit that they derive from their possessions. Even the first two reasons wouldn’t fully explain the phenomena without appealing to some form of sympathy; therefore, it makes more sense to choose the sympathy that is direct and immediate rather than that which is far-reaching and indirect. Additionally, when wealth or power is substantial enough to make someone significant and influential in society, the respect that comes with it can also stem from a different source—specifically, the intrigue created by the number of people involved and the significance of the consequences. However, to explain how this principle works, we must revert to the idea of sympathy, as we indicated in the previous section.
It may not be amiss, on this occasion, to remark the flexibility of our sentiments, and the several changes they so readily receive from the objects, with which they are conjoined. All the sentiments of approbation, which attend any particular species of objects, have a great resemblance to each other, though derived from different sources; and, on the other hand, those sentiments, when directed to different objects, are different to the feeling, though derived from the same source. Thus the beauty of all visible objects causes a pleasure pretty much the same, though it be sometimes derived from the mere species and appearance of the objects; sometimes from sympathy, and an idea of their utility. In like manner, whenever we survey the actions and characters of men, without any particular interest in them, the pleasure, or pain, which arises from the survey (with some minute differences) is, in the main, of the same kind, though perhaps there be a great diversity in the causes, from which it is derived. On the other hand, a convenient house, and a virtuous character, cause not the same feeling of approbation; even though the source of our approbation be the same, and flow from sympathy and an idea of their utility. There is something very inexplicable in this variation of our feelings; but it is what we have experience of with regard to all our passions and sentiments.
It might be worth noting, on this occasion, the flexibility of our feelings and how easily they change based on the things we associate with them. All the feelings of approval we have toward specific types of objects are quite similar, even if they come from different sources; on the flip side, those feelings, when focused on different objects, feel different, even if they come from the same source. For example, the beauty of all visually pleasing objects brings about a similar pleasure, although it might stem from just the type and appearance of the objects sometimes, or from empathy and their perceived usefulness other times. Similarly, when we look at the actions and characters of people without any particular personal stake in them, the pleasure or pain we feel from that observation (with some slight differences) is generally of the same category, even though the reasons behind it may vary significantly. However, a comfortable home and a virtuous character do not produce the same feeling of approval; even if our approval comes from the same source and is rooted in empathy and a sense of their utility. There’s something quite puzzling about this shift in our feelings, but it’s something we experience with all our emotions and sentiments.
SECT. VI CONCLUSION OF THIS BOOK
Thus upon the whole I am hopeful, that nothing is wanting to an accurate proof of this system of ethics. We are certain, that sympathy is a very powerful principle in human nature. We are also certain, that it has a great influence on our sense of beauty, when we regard external objects, as well as when we judge of morals. We find, that it has force sufficient to give us the strongest sentiments of approbation, when it operates alone, without the concurrence of any other principle; as in the cases of justice, allegiance, chastity, and good-manners. We may observe, that all the circumstances requisite for its operation are found in most of the virtues; which have, for the most part, a tendency to the good of society, or to that of the person possessed of them. If we compare all these circumstances, we shall not doubt, that sympathy is the chief source of moral distinctions; especially when we reflect, that no objection can be raised against this hypothesis in one case, which will not extend to all cases. Justice is certainly approved of for no other reason, than because it has a tendency to the public good: And the public good is indifferent to us, except so far as sympathy interests us in it. We may presume the like with regard to all the other virtues, which have a like tendency to the public good. They must derive all their merit from our sympathy with those, who reap any advantage from them: As the virtues, which have a tendency to the good of the person possessed of them, derive their merit from our sympathy with him.
Overall, I'm hopeful that we have everything needed for a solid proof of this ethical system. We're sure that sympathy is a powerful driver in human nature. We also know it significantly impacts our sense of beauty when we look at the outside world, as well as when we evaluate morals. We see that it has enough power to evoke our strongest feelings of approval when it acts on its own, without needing any other principle to support it, as in the cases of justice, loyalty, chastity, and good manners. We can notice that all the necessary circumstances for its operation are present in most virtues, which generally aim for the good of society or the benefit of the person who embodies them. When we compare all these circumstances, we can't doubt that sympathy is the primary source of moral distinctions; especially when we consider that any objection to this idea in one situation can apply to all others. Justice is clearly approved solely because it tends toward the public good, and the public good means little to us unless sympathy engages us with it. We can make the same assumption regarding all other virtues that also lean toward the public good. They must get all their worth from our sympathy with those who benefit from them, just as the virtues that promote the well-being of the individual gain their value from our sympathy for that person.
Most people will readily allow, that the useful qualities of the mind are virtuous, because of their utility. This way of thinking is so natural, and occurs on so many occasions, that few will make any scruple of admitting it. Now this being once admitted, the force of sympathy must necessarily be acknowledged. Virtue is considered as means to an end. Means to an end are only valued so far as the end is valued. But the happiness of strangers affects us by sympathy alone. To that principle, therefore, we are to ascribe the sentiment of approbation, which arises from the survey of all those virtues, that are useful to society, or to the person possessed of them. These form the most considerable part of morality.
Most people easily agree that the positive traits of the mind are virtuous because they are useful. This way of thinking is so natural and happens so often that few will question it. Once accepted, the importance of sympathy must also be recognized. Virtue is seen as a means to an end. Means to an end are valued only to the extent that the end itself is valued. However, the happiness of others affects us through sympathy alone. Therefore, we can attribute the feeling of approval to this principle, which comes from observing all those virtues that benefit society or the individuals who possess them. These make up the most significant part of morality.
Were it proper in such a subject to bribe the reader's assent, or employ any thing but solid argument, we are here abundantly supplied with topics to engage the affections. All lovers of virtue (and such we all are in speculation, however we may degenerate in practice) must certainly be pleased to see moral distinctions derived from so noble a source, which gives us a just notion both of the generosity and capacity of human nature. It requires but very little knowledge of human affairs to perceive, that a sense of morals is a principle inherent in the soul, and one of the most powerful that enters into the composition. But this sense must certainly acquire new force, when reflecting on itself, it approves of those principles, from whence it is derived, and finds nothing but what is great and good in its rise and origin. Those who resolve the sense of morals into original instincts of the human mind, may defend the cause of virtue with sufficient authority; but want the advantage, which those possess, who account for that sense by an extensive sympathy with mankind. According to their system, not only virtue must be approved of, but also the sense of virtue: And not only that sense, but also the principles, from whence it is derived. So that nothing is presented on any side, but what is laudable and good.
If it were appropriate to persuade the reader in such a topic or to use anything other than solid arguments, we have plenty of points to stir the emotions. All lovers of virtue (which we all claim to be in theory, even if we fall short in practice) must definitely take pleasure in seeing moral distinctions come from such a noble source, giving us a true understanding of both the generosity and potential of human nature. It doesn't take much insight into human affairs to recognize that a sense of morality is a principle embedded in the soul, and it’s one of the most influential aspects of our being. This sense certainly gains even more strength when it reflects on itself, endorsing the principles from which it originates and discovering only greatness and goodness in its beginnings. Those who attribute the sense of morality to basic instincts of the human mind can defend the cause of virtue with adequate authority, but they lack the advantage of those who explain that sense through a deep empathy for humanity. According to their view, not only must virtue be recognized, but so must the sense of virtue; and not only that sense, but also the principles that underpin it. Therefore, what is offered from any angle is solely commendable and good.
This observation may be extended to justice, and the other virtues of that kind. Though justice be artificial, the sense of its morality is natural. It is the combination of men, in a system of conduct, which renders any act of justice beneficial to society. But when once it has that tendency, we naturally approve of it; and if we did not so, it is impossible any combination or convention could ever produce that sentiment.
This observation can also apply to justice and other similar virtues. Although justice is a construct, our understanding of its morality is instinctive. It's the way people interact within a set of guidelines that makes any act of justice beneficial to society. Once it has that positive impact, we instinctively support it; if we didn't, no agreement or social arrangement could ever create that feeling.
Most of the inventions of men are subject to change. They depend upon humour and caprice. They have a vogue for a time, and then sink into oblivion. It may, perhaps, be apprehended, that if justice were allowed to be a human invention, it must be placed on the same footing. But the cases are widely different. The interest, on which justice is founded, is the greatest imaginable, and extends to all times and places. It cannot possibly be served by any other invention. It is obvious, and discovers itself on the very first formation of society. All these causes render the rules of justice stedfast and immutable; at least, as immutable as human nature. And if they were founded on original instincts, could they have any greater stability?
Most inventions by humans are subject to change. They rely on trends and whims. They become popular for a while and then fade into obscurity. One might worry that if justice were seen as a human invention, it would be treated the same way. But the situations are very different. The interest that justice is based on is the most significant imaginable, reaching across all times and places. No other invention could satisfy it. It is clear and reveals itself from the very beginning of society. All these factors make the rules of justice steadfast and unchangeable; at least, as unchangeable as human nature. And if they were based on fundamental instincts, could they be any more stable?
The same system may help us to form a just notion of the happiness, as well as of the dignity of virtue, and may interest every principle of our nature in the embracing and cherishing that noble quality. Who indeed does not feel an accession of alacrity in his pursuits of knowledge and ability of every kind, when he considers, that besides the advantage, which immediately result from these acquisitions, they also give him a new lustre in the eyes of mankind, and are universally attended with esteem and approbation? And who can think any advantages of fortune a sufficient compensation for the least breach of the social virtues, when he considers, that not only his character with regard to others, but also his peace and inward satisfaction entirely depend upon his strict observance of them; and that a mind will never be able to bear its own survey, that has been wanting in its part to mankind and society? But I forbear insisting on this subject. Such reflections require a work apart, very different from the genius of the present. The anatomist ought never to emulate the painter; nor in his accurate dissections and portraitures of the smaller parts of the human body, pretend to give his figures any graceful and engaging attitude or expression. There is even something hideous, or at least minute in the views of things, which he presents; and it is necessary the objects should be set more at a distance, and be more covered up from sight, to make them engaging to the eye and imagination. An anatomist, however, is admirably fitted to give advice to a painter; and it is even impracticable to excel in the latter art, without the assistance of the former. We must have an exact knowledge of the parts, their situation and connexion, before we can design with any elegance or correctness. And thus the most abstract speculations concerning human nature, however cold and unentertaining, become subservient to practical morality; and may render this latter science more correct in its precepts, and more persuasive in its exhortations.
The same system can help us develop a fair understanding of happiness, as well as the value of virtue, and can engage every part of our nature in embracing and valuing that noble quality. Who doesn’t feel a boost of enthusiasm in pursuing knowledge and skills of all kinds when they realize that, in addition to the immediate benefits of these achievements, they also enhance their reputation in the eyes of others and are generally met with respect and approval? And who can consider the advantages of wealth a worthy trade-off for even the smallest violation of social virtues when they recognize that their character concerning others, as well as their peace and inner satisfaction, entirely relies on upholding these virtues? A mind won't be able to handle looking at itself if it has failed in its obligations to humanity and society. But I won’t dwell on this subject. Such thoughts deserve a separate discussion, quite different from the style of the present. An anatomist should never try to imitate a painter; nor should they, in their detailed dissections and representations of the smaller parts of the human body, attempt to show their figures with any graceful or appealing pose or expression. There is often something grotesque, or at least insignificant, in the way they depict things; and it’s necessary for the subjects to be kept at a distance and partially hidden from view to make them more appealing to the eye and imagination. However, an anatomist is perfectly suited to advise a painter; and it's nearly impossible to excel in painting without the guidance of anatomy. We must have a precise understanding of the parts, their placement, and connection before we can design with any elegance or accuracy. Thus, even the most abstract theories about human nature, no matter how cold and uninteresting, become useful for practical morality; and they can make this moral science more accurate in its principles and more compelling in its appeals.
APPENDIX
There is nothing I would more willingly lay hold of, than an opportunity of confessing my errors; and should esteem such a return to truth and reason to be more honourable than the most unerring judgment. A man, who is free from mistakes, can pretend to no praises, except from the justness of his understanding: But a man, who corrects his mistakes, shews at once the justness of his understanding, and the candour and ingenuity of his temper. I have not yet been so fortunate as to discover any very considerable mistakes in the reasonings delivered in the preceding volumes, except on one article: But I have found by experience, that some of my expressions have not been so well chosen, as to guard against all mistakes in the readers; and it is chiefly to remedy this defect, I have subjoined the following appendix.
There’s nothing I would rather do than take the chance to admit my mistakes; I see such a return to truth and reason as more honorable than the most flawless judgment. A person who never makes mistakes can't expect praise except for the accuracy of their understanding. But someone who corrects their errors demonstrates both the clarity of their understanding and the openness and cleverness of their character. I haven't yet been lucky enough to find any major errors in the reasoning presented in the earlier volumes, except for one issue. However, I've realized through experience that some of my wording hasn't been clear enough to prevent misunderstandings among readers, and it's mainly to fix this issue that I've added the following appendix.
We can never be induced to believe any matter of fact, except where its cause, or its effect, is present to us; but what the nature is of that belief, which arises from the relation of cause and effect, few have had the curiosity to ask themselves. In my opinion, this dilemma is inevitable. Either the belief is some new idea, such as that of reality or existence, which we join to the simple conception of an object, or it is merely a peculiar feeling or sentiment. That it is not a new idea, annexed to the simple conception, may be evinced from these two arguments. First, We have no abstract idea of existence, distinguishable and separable from the idea of particular objects. It is impossible, therefore, that this idea of existence can be annexed to the idea of any object, or form the difference betwixt a simple conception and belief. Secondly, The mind has the command over all its ideas, and can separate, unite, mix, and vary them, as it pleases; so that if belief consisted merely in a new idea, annexed to the conception, it would be in a man's power to believe what he pleased. We may, therefore, conclude, that belief consists merely in a certain feeling or sentiment; in something, that depends not on the will, but must arise from certain determinate causes and principles, of which we are not masters. When we are convinced of any matter of fact, we do nothing but conceive it, along with a certain feeling, different from what attends the mere reveries of the imagination. And when we express our incredulity concerning any fact, we mean, that the arguments for the fact produce not that feeling. Did not the belief consist in a sentiment different from our mere conception, whatever objects were presented by the wildest imagination, would be on an equal footing with the most established truths founded on history and experience. There is nothing but the feeling, or sentiment, to distinguish the one from the other.
We can never be convinced to believe anything factual unless we can see its cause or its effect; however, not many have taken the time to question the nature of the belief that arises from the relationship between cause and effect. In my view, this dilemma is unavoidable. Either the belief is a new idea, like reality or existence, which we attach to the simple concept of an object, or it’s just a unique feeling or sentiment. The idea that it isn't a new concept tied to a simple perception can be supported by two arguments. First, we have no abstract idea of existence that is distinct and separable from the idea of specific objects. Therefore, it's impossible for this idea of existence to be attached to the idea of any object or to create a difference between a simple conception and a belief. Second, the mind can control all its ideas and can separate, combine, mix, and alter them however it wants; so if belief were merely a new idea added to a concept, a person could believe anything they wanted. Thus, we can conclude that belief is simply a certain feeling or sentiment—something that doesn’t depend on our will but must arise from specific causes and principles that are beyond our control. When we are convinced of a fact, we simply perceive it along with a specific feeling that is different from the mere fantasies of the imagination. And when we express our disbelief about a fact, we mean that the arguments for the fact don't produce that feeling. If belief were just a sentiment different from our simple conception, then anything presented by the wildest imagination would hold the same weight as the most established truths based on history and experience. The only thing that distinguishes one from the other is the feeling or sentiment.
This, therefore, being regarded as an undoubted truth, that belief is nothing but a peculiar feeling, different from the simple conception, the next question, that naturally occurs, is, what is the nature of this feeling, or sentiment, and whether it be analogous to any other sentiment of the human mind? This question is important. For if it be not analogous to any other sentiment, we must despair of explaining its causes, and must consider it as an original principle of the human mind. If it be analogous, we may hope to explain its causes from analogy, and trace it up to more general principles. Now that there is a greater firmness and solidity in the conceptions, which are the objects of conviction and assurance, than in the loose and indolent reveries of a castle-builder, every one will readily own. They strike upon us with more force; they are more present to us; the mind has a firmer hold of them, and is more actuated and moved by them. It acquiesces in them; and, in a manner, fixes and reposes itself on them. In short, they approach nearer to the impressions, which are immediately present to us; and are therefore analogous to many other operations of the mind.
This is seen as an undeniable truth: belief is a unique feeling, different from just thinking about something. The next question that naturally arises is: what is the nature of this feeling or sentiment, and does it relate to any other feelings in the human mind? This question is crucial. If it doesn’t relate to any other sentiment, we might as well give up trying to explain what causes it and view it as a fundamental aspect of the human mind. However, if it is similar to other feelings, we may be able to explain its causes by relating it to those and connect it to broader principles. It's clear that the ideas we feel convinced and assured about have a stronger and more solid presence than the vague and relaxed daydreams of someone lost in imagination. They hit us harder, are more vivid, and the mind has a better grasp on them, responding and reacting more actively. We accept them and, in a sense, rely on them. In short, they are closer to the impressions that are directly in front of us and therefore share similarities with many other mental processes.
There is not, in my opinion, any possibility of evading this conclusion, but by asserting, that belief, beside the simple conception, consists in some impression or feeling, distinguishable from the conception. It does not modify the conception, and render it more present and intense: It is only annexed to it, after the same manner that will and desire are annexed to particular conceptions of good and pleasure. But the following considerations will, I hope, be sufficient to remove this hypothesis. First, It is directly contrary to experience, and our immediate consciousness. All men have ever allowed reasoning to be merely an operation of our thoughts or ideas; and however those ideas may be varied to the feeling, there is nothing ever enters into our conclusions but ideas, or our fainter conceptions. For instance; I hear at present a person's voice, whom I am acquainted with; and this sound comes from the next room. This impression of my senses immediately conveys my thoughts to the person, along with all the surrounding objects. I paint them out to myself as existent at present, with the same qualities and relations, that I formerly knew them possessed of. These ideas take faster hold of my mind, than the ideas of an inchanted castle. They are different to the feeling; but there is no distinct or separate impression attending them. It is the same case when I recollect the several incidents of a journey, or the events of any history. Every particular fact is there the object of belief. Its idea is modified differently from the loose reveries of a castle-builder: But no distinct impression attends every distinct idea, or conception of matter of fact. This is the subject of plain experience. If ever this experience can be disputed on any occasion, it is when the mind has been agitated with doubts and difficulties; and afterwards, upon taking the object in a new point of view, or being presented with a new argument, fixes and reposes itself in one settled conclusion and belief. In this case there is a feeling distinct and separate from the conception. The passage from doubt and agitation to tranquility and repose, conveys a satisfaction and pleasure to the mind. But take any other case. Suppose I see the legs and thighs of a person in motion, while some interposed object conceals the rest of his body. Here it is certain, the imagination spreads out the whole figure. I give him a head and shoulders, and breast and neck. These members I conceive and believe him to be possessed of. Nothing can be more evident, than that this whole operation is performed by the thought or imagination alone. The transition is immediate. The ideas presently strike us. Their customary connexion with the present impression, varies them and modifies them in a certain manner, but produces no act of the mind, distinct from this peculiarity of conception. Let any one examine his own mind, and he will evidently find this to be the truth.
In my opinion, there's no way to avoid this conclusion without claiming that belief, besides the simple idea, includes some impression or feeling that’s separate from the idea itself. It doesn’t change the idea or make it more vivid; it just gets added on like will and desire are added to specific ideas of what is good and pleasurable. However, I hope the following points will be enough to dismiss this idea. First, it directly contradicts experience and our immediate awareness. Everyone has always felt that reasoning is just a process of our thoughts or ideas; regardless of how those ideas might affect our feelings, nothing that enters our conclusions is anything but ideas or our weaker understandings. For example, I hear the voice of someone I know coming from the next room. This sensory impression immediately directs my thoughts to that person along with everything around them. I envision them as they exist now, with the same qualities and relationships I previously recognized. These ideas connect to my mind more firmly than the ideas of an imagined castle. They feel different, but there’s no distinct or separate impression connected to them. The same happens when I recall various events from a trip or from any history. Each specific fact is the object of belief. Its idea is shaped differently than the loose fantasies of a daydreamer; however, there’s no distinct impression tied to each separate idea or conception of reality. This is a matter of straightforward experience. If this experience can ever be questioned, it’s when the mind is troubled by doubt and uncertainty; later, when looking at the issue from a new perspective or given a new argument, it settles into a single conclusion and belief. In this case, there’s a feeling separate from the idea. The shift from doubt and agitation to calm and certainty brings satisfaction and pleasure to the mind. But consider another situation. Suppose I see someone’s legs and thighs moving while an object hides the rest of their body. Here, it’s clear that my imagination fills in the whole figure. I create a head, shoulders, chest, and neck for them. I conceive and believe them to possess these attributes. Nothing is more obvious than that this entire process is done purely by thought or imagination. The shift happens instantly. The ideas strike us immediately. Their usual connection with the present impression alters and modifies them in a certain way but does not lead to any separate mental action distinct from this particular form of thought. Anyone should examine their own mind, and they will clearly find this to be true.
Secondly, Whatever may be the case, with regard to this distinct impression, it must be allowed, that the mind has a firmer hold, or more steady conception of what it takes to be matter of fact, than of fictions. Why then look any farther, or multiply suppositions without necessity?
Secondly, whatever the situation may be, it's important to acknowledge that the mind has a stronger grasp, or a clearer understanding, of what it considers to be reality than of made-up stories. So why dig deeper or complicate things with unnecessary assumptions?
Thirdly, We can explain the causes of the firm conception, but not those of any separate impression. And not only so, but the causes of the firm conception exhaust the whole subject, and nothing is left to produce any other effect. An inference concerning a matter of fact is nothing but the idea of an object, that is frequently conjoined, or is associated with a present impression. This is the whole of it. Every part is requisite to explain, from analogy, the more steady conception; and nothing remains capable of producing any distinct impression.
Thirdly, we can explain the reasons behind a strong idea, but not those for any individual impression. Furthermore, the reasons for the strong idea cover the entire subject, leaving nothing else to create any other effect. An inference about a factual matter is simply the idea of an object that is often linked or associated with a current impression. That's all there is to it. Every element is necessary to explain, through analogy, the more stable idea; and nothing is left that can produce any clear impression.
Fourthly, The effects of belief, in influencing the passions and imagination, can all be explained from the firm conception; and there is no occasion to have recourse to any other principle. These arguments, with many others, enumerated in the foregoing volumes, sufficiently prove, that belief only modifies the idea or conception; and renders it different to the feeling, without producing any distinct impression. Thus upon a general view of the subject, there appear to be two questions of importance, which we may venture to recommend to the consideration of philosophers, Whether there be any thing to distinguish belief from the simple conception beside the feeling of sentiment? And, Whether this feeling be any thing but a firmer conception, or a faster hold, that we take of the object?
Fourthly, the impact of belief on our emotions and imagination can all be explained by a solid understanding of the concept, and there's no need to turn to any other principle. These arguments, along with many others mentioned in the previous volumes, clearly show that belief only changes the idea or concept and makes it feel different without creating a separate impression. So, when we take a broad look at the topic, there seem to be two important questions we can suggest philosophers consider: Is there anything that distinguishes belief from a simple concept aside from the feeling that comes with it? And is that feeling just a stronger concept or a firmer grip we have on the object?
If, upon impartial enquiry, the same conclusion, that I have formed, be assented to by philosophers, the next business is to examine the analogy, which there is betwixt belief, and other acts of the mind, and find the cause of the firmness and strength of conception: And this I do not esteem a difficult task. The transition from a present impression, always enlivens and strengthens any idea. When any object is presented, the idea of its usual attendant immediately strikes us, as something real and solid. It is felt, rather than conceived, and approaches the impression, from which it is derived, in its force and influence. This I have proved at large. I cannot add any new arguments.
If, after an unbiased investigation, philosophers agree with my conclusion, the next step is to explore the similarities between belief and other mental activities and to find the reason for the strength and stability of our thoughts. I don’t think this is a hard task. The shift from a current impression always enhances and strengthens any idea. When we see an object, the idea of what usually accompanies it immediately comes to mind as something real and solid. It’s felt more than thought about, and it has a similar impact to the impression from which it comes. I've already discussed this in detail. I can’t offer any new arguments.
I had entertained some hopes, that however deficient our theory of the intellectual world might be, it would be free from those contradictions, and absurdities, which seem to attend every explication, that human reason can give of the material world. But upon a more strict review of the section concerning personal identity, I find myself involved in such a labyrinth, that, I must confess, I neither know how to correct my former opinions, nor how to render them consistent. If this be not a good general reason for scepticism, it is at least a sufficient one (if I were not already abundantly supplied) for me to entertain a diffidence and modesty in all my decisions. I shall propose the arguments on both sides, beginning with those that induced me to deny the strict and proper identity and simplicity of a self or thinking being.
I had some hope that, no matter how lacking our understanding of the intellectual world might be, it would be free from the contradictions and absurdities that seem to come with every explanation human reason offers about the material world. However, after taking a closer look at the section on personal identity, I find myself caught in such a maze that I must admit I don’t know how to fix my earlier opinions or make them consistent. If this isn’t a solid reason for skepticism, at the very least, it’s enough (if I didn’t already have plenty) to make me cautious and humble in all my judgments. I will present the arguments on both sides, starting with those that led me to reject the strict identity and simplicity of a self or thinking being.
When we talk of self or substance, we must have an idea annexed to these terms, otherwise they are altogether unintelligible. Every idea is derived from preceding impressions; and we have no impression of self or substance, as something simple and individual. We have, therefore, no idea of them in that sense.
When we discuss self or substance, we need to have an idea connected to these terms; otherwise, they are completely unclear. Every idea comes from earlier impressions, and we don't have an impression of self or substance as something simple and distinct. Therefore, we don't have an idea of them in that way.
Whatever is distinct, is distinguishable; and whatever is distinguishable, is separable by the thought or imagination. All perceptions are distinct. They are, therefore, distinguishable, and separable, and may be conceived as separately existent, and may exist separately, without any contradiction or absurdity.
Whatever is unique can be recognized; and whatever can be recognized can be separated in thought or imagination. All perceptions are unique. They are, therefore, recognizable and separable, and can be understood as existing separately, and can exist separately, without any contradiction or absurdity.
When I view this table and that chimney, nothing is present to me but particular perceptions, which are of a like nature with all the other perceptions. This is the doctrine of philosophers. But this table, which is present to me, and the chimney, may and do exist separately. This is the doctrine of the vulgar, and implies no contradiction. There is no contradiction, therefore, in extending the same doctrine to all the perceptions.
When I look at this table and that chimney, all I see are specific perceptions, which are similar to all my other perceptions. This is what philosophers believe. But this table, which I see, and the chimney can and do exist on their own. This is what most people think, and it makes sense. Therefore, there’s no contradiction in applying the same idea to all perceptions.
In general, the following reasoning seems satisfactory. All ideas are borrowed from preceding perceptions. Our ideas of objects, therefore, are derived from that source. Consequently no proposition can be intelligible or consistent with regard to objects, which is not so with regard to perceptions. But it is intelligible and consistent to say, that objects exist distinct and independent, without any common simple substance or subject of inhesion. This proposition, therefore, can never be absurd with regard to perceptions.
Overall, the reasoning here seems sound. All ideas come from previous experiences. Our understanding of objects is based on that. So, no statement about objects can make sense or be consistent unless it does so for perceptions. However, it is clear and logical to say that objects exist as separate and independent, without relying on any common simple substance or subject. Therefore, this idea can never be unreasonable concerning perceptions.
When I turn my reflection on myself, I never can perceive this self without some one or more perceptions; nor can I ever perceive any thing but the perceptions. It is the composition of these, therefore, which forms the self. We can conceive a thinking being to have either many or few perceptions. Suppose the mind to be reduced even below the life of an oyster. Suppose it to have only one perception, as of thirst or hunger. Consider it in that situation. Do you conceive any thing but merely that perception? Have you any notion of self or substance? If not, the addition of other perceptions can never give you that notion.
When I look at myself, I can never see this self without having one or more perceptions; nor can I perceive anything except for those perceptions. So, it's the combination of these that makes up the self. We can imagine a thinking being having either many or few perceptions. Imagine the mind being reduced even below the life of an oyster. Imagine it having only one perception, like feeling thirsty or hungry. Think about it in that state. Do you think of anything other than that one perception? Do you have any idea of self or substance? If not, then adding more perceptions will never give you that idea.
The annihilation, which some people suppose to follow upon death, and which entirely destroys this self, is nothing but an extinction of all particular perceptions; love and hatred, pain and pleasure, thought and sensation. These therefore must be the same with self; since the one cannot survive the other.
The idea that annihilation follows death, completely erasing the self, is really just the end of all specific perceptions—love and hate, pain and pleasure, thought and feeling. This means they must be tied to the self, since one can't exist without the other.
Is self the same with substance? If it be, how can that question have place, concerning the subsistence of self, under a change of substance? If they be distinct, what is the difference betwixt them? For my part, I have a notion of neither, when conceived distinct from particular perceptions.
Is the self the same as substance? If it is, how can we question the existence of the self when the substance changes? If they are different, what is the distinction between them? Personally, I have no idea what either of them is when thought of separately from specific perceptions.
Philosophers begin to be reconciled to the principle, that we have no idea of external substance, distinct from the ideas of particular qualities. This must pave the way for a like principle with regard to the mind, that we have no notion of it, distinct from the particular perceptions.
Philosophers are starting to accept the idea that we have no concept of external substance separate from the ideas of specific qualities. This should lead to a similar understanding about the mind, that we have no notion of it apart from our specific perceptions.
So far I seem to be attended with sufficient evidence. But having thus loosened all our particular perceptions, when I proceed to explain the principle of connexion, which binds them together, and makes us attribute to them a real simplicity and identity; I am sensible, that my account is very defective, and that nothing but the seeming evidence of the precedent reasonings could have induced me to receive it. If perceptions are distinct existences, they form a whole only by being connected together. But no connexions among distinct existences are ever discoverable by human understanding. We only feel a connexion or determination of the thought, to pass from one object to another. It follows, therefore, that the thought alone finds personal identity, when reflecting on the train of past perceptions, that compose a mind, the ideas of them are felt to be connected together, and naturally introduce each other. However extraordinary this conclusion may seem, it need not surprize us. Most philosophers seem inclined to think, that personal identity arises from consciousness; and consciousness is nothing but a reflected thought or perception. The present philosophy, therefore, has so far a promising aspect. But all my hopes vanish, when I come to explain the principles, that unite our successive perceptions in our thought or consciousness. I cannot discover any theory, which gives me satisfaction on this head.
So far, it seems I have enough evidence. But after breaking down all our specific perceptions, when I try to explain the principle of connection that ties them together and makes us see them as having a real simplicity and identity, I realize my explanation is quite lacking, and only the apparent evidence from my earlier reasoning could have led me to accept it. If perceptions are separate existences, they only form a whole by being linked together. However, no connections between distinct existences can be identified by human understanding. We only sense a connection or impulse of thought to move from one object to another. Therefore, it follows that thought alone finds personal identity when reflecting on the series of past perceptions that make up a mind; the ideas of those perceptions feel connected and naturally lead to one another. This conclusion may seem unusual, but it shouldn't surprise us. Most philosophers tend to believe that personal identity comes from consciousness, and consciousness is just a reflective thought or perception. Therefore, the current philosophy seems promising to some extent. But all my hopes disappear when I try to explain the principles that link our successive perceptions in our thought or consciousness. I can't find any theory that satisfies me on this matter.
In short there are two principles, which I cannot render consistent; nor is it in my power to renounce either of them, viz, that all our distinct perceptions are distinct existences, and that the mind never perceives any real connexion among distinct existences. Did our perceptions either inhere in something simple and individual, or did the mind perceive some real connexion among them, there would be no difficulty in the case. For my part, I must plead the privilege of a sceptic, and confess, that this difficulty is too hard for my understanding. I pretend not, however, to pronounce it absolutely insuperable. Others, perhaps, or myself, upon more mature reflections, may discover some hypothesis, that will reconcile those contradictions.
In short, there are two principles that I can’t reconcile; nor can I give up either of them. The first is that all our separate perceptions are distinct existences, and the second is that the mind never sees any real connection among those distinct existences. If our perceptions either belonged to something simple and individual, or if the mind recognized some real connection among them, there wouldn’t be any difficulty in this situation. For my part, I have to admit the privilege of being a skeptic and confess that this difficulty is too challenging for my understanding. However, I don’t claim that it’s absolutely impossible to solve. Others, or even I with more thought, might discover a hypothesis that reconciles these contradictions.
I shall also take this opportunity of confessing two other errors of less importance, which more mature reflection has discovered to me in my reasoning. The first may be found in Vol. I. page 106. where I say, that the distance betwixt two bodies is known, among other things, by the angles, which the rays of light flowing from the bodies make with each other. It is certain, that these angles are not known to the mind, and consequently can never discover the distance. The second error may be found in Vol. I. page 144 where I say, that two ideas of the same object can only be different by their different degrees of force and vivacity. I believe there are other differences among ideas, which cannot properly be comprehended under these terms. Had I said, that two ideas of the same object can only be different by their different feeling, I should have been nearer the truth.
I’d also like to take this chance to admit two other less important mistakes that I’ve realized in my reasoning after some deeper thought. The first can be found in Vol. I, page 106, where I state that the distance between two bodies is known, among other things, by the angles that the rays of light coming from the bodies make with each other. It’s clear that these angles aren’t known to the mind and therefore can’t reveal the distance. The second mistake is in Vol. I, page 144, where I say that two ideas of the same object can only differ by their varying degrees of intensity and liveliness. I think there are other distinctions among ideas that don’t fit neatly into those categories. If I had said that two ideas of the same object can only be different based on their different feelings, I would have been closer to the truth.
Download ePUB
If you like this ebook, consider a donation!