This is a modern-English version of A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, originally written by Berkeley, George. It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.



A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge


by

George Berkeley (1685-1753)



WHEREIN THE CHIEF CAUSES OF ERROR AND DIFFICULTY IN THE SCIENCES,
WITH THE GROUNDS OF SCEPTICISM, ATHEISM, AND IRRELIGION,
ARE INQUIRED INTO.




DEDICATION


To the Right Honourable
THOMAS, EARL OF PEMBROKE, &C.,
Knight of the most Noble Order of the Garter and one of
the Lords of Her Majesty's most honourable privy council.

My Lord,

My Lord,

You will perhaps wonder that an obscure person, who has not the honour to be known to your lordship, should presume to address you in this manner. But that a man who has written something with a design to promote Useful Knowledge and Religion in the world should make choice of your lordship for his patron, will not be thought strange by any one that is not altogether unacquainted with the present state of the church and learning, and consequently ignorant how great an ornament and support you are to both. Yet, nothing could have induced me to make you this present of my poor endeavours, were I not encouraged by that candour and native goodness which is so bright a part in your lordship's character. I might add, my lord, that the extraordinary favour and bounty you have been pleased to show towards our Society gave me hopes you would not be unwilling to countenance the studies of one of its members. These considerations determined me to lay this treatise at your lordship's feet, and the rather because I was ambitious to have it known that I am with the truest and most profound respect, on account of that learning and virtue which the world so justly admires in your lordship, MY LORD, Your lordship's most humble and most devoted servant,

You might be surprised that someone you don't know would dare to reach out to you like this. However, it's only natural for someone who has written something aimed at promoting Useful Knowledge and Religion to seek your support, and anyone familiar with the current state of the church and education knows how much you contribute to both. Still, I wouldn't have approached you with this gift of my humble efforts if I hadn't been inspired by your kindness and genuine goodness, which are such shining traits of your character. Additionally, my lord, the exceptional kindness and generosity you've shown to our Society made me hopeful that you'd be open to supporting the efforts of one of its members. These thoughts led me to present this treatise to you, especially since I wanted to express my deep and sincere respect for the knowledge and virtues the world rightly admires in you, MY LORD, Your lordship's most humble and devoted servant.

GEORGE BERKELEY

George Berkeley





CONTENTS

PREFACE
INTRODUCTION
OF THE PRINCIPLES OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE





PREFACE

What I here make public has, after a long and scrupulous inquiry, seemed to me evidently true and not unuseful to be known--particularly to those who are tainted with Scepticism, or want a demonstration of the existence and immateriality of God, or the natural immortality of the soul. Whether it be so or no I am content the reader should impartially examine; since I do not think myself any farther concerned for the success of what I have written than as it is agreeable to truth. But, to the end this may not suffer, I make it my request that the reader suspend his judgment till he has once at least read the whole through with that degree of attention and thought which the subject-matter shall seem to deserve. For, as there are some passages that, taken by themselves, are very liable (nor could it be remedied) to gross misinterpretation, and to be charged with most absurd consequences, which, nevertheless, upon an entire perusal will appear not to follow from them; so likewise, though the whole should be read over, yet, if this be done transiently, it is very probable my sense may be mistaken; but to a thinking reader, I flatter myself it will be throughout clear and obvious. As for the characters of novelty and singularity which some of the following notions may seem to bear, it is, I hope, needless to make any apology on that account. He must surely be either very weak, or very little acquainted with the sciences, who shall reject a truth that is capable of demonstration, for no other reason but because it is newly known, and contrary to the prejudices of mankind. Thus much I thought fit to premise, in order to prevent, if possible, the hasty censures of a sort of men who are too apt to condemn an opinion before they rightly comprehend it.

What I'm sharing here is something I've found to be clearly true after thorough investigation, and I believe it’s useful to know—especially for those who are skeptical or looking for proof of God’s existence and immateriality, or the natural immortality of the soul. Whether this is true or not, I encourage readers to examine it without bias; I care only that what I've written aligns with the truth. To ensure this isn’t overlooked, I ask that readers hold off on forming their opinions until they've read the entire piece with the attention and thought it deserves. Some parts may seem misleading when taken alone and could be misinterpreted in the most absurd ways, but after reading everything, those misconceptions will likely disappear. Similarly, if the work is skimmed, it’s easy to misunderstand my meaning. I believe that for thoughtful readers, my intentions will be clear throughout. As for the originality of some ideas, I hope no apology is necessary. It would be foolish or uninformed to dismiss a demonstrable truth just because it’s new and challenges common beliefs. I wanted to include this to hopefully avert hasty judgments from those quick to criticize without fully understanding.




INTRODUCTION

1. Philosophy being nothing else but THE STUDY OF WISDOM AND TRUTH, it may with reason be expected that those who have spent most time and pains in it should enjoy a greater calm and serenity of mind, a greater clearness and evidence of knowledge, and be less disturbed with doubts and difficulties than other men. Yet so it is, we see the illiterate bulk of mankind that walk the high-road of plain common sense, and are governed by the dictates of nature, for the most part easy and undisturbed. To them nothing THAT IS FAMILIAR appears unaccountable or difficult to comprehend. They complain not of any want of evidence in their senses, and are out of all danger of becoming SCEPTICS. But no sooner do we depart from sense and instinct to follow the light of a superior principle, to reason, meditate, and reflect on the nature of things, but a thousand scruples spring up in our minds concerning those things which before we seemed fully to comprehend. Prejudices and errors of sense do from all parts discover themselves to our view; and, endeavouring to correct these by reason, we are insensibly drawn into uncouth paradoxes, difficulties, and inconsistencies, which multiply and grow upon us as we advance in speculation, till at length, having wandered through many intricate mazes, we find ourselves just where we were, or, which is worse, sit down in a forlorn Scepticism.

1. Philosophy is simply the STUDY OF WISDOM AND TRUTH, so it’s reasonable to expect that those who dedicate a lot of time and effort to it should experience more peace of mind, clearer knowledge, and be less troubled by doubts and challenges than others. Yet, it often turns out that the uneducated masses, who follow the straightforward path of common sense and rely on natural instincts, are generally calm and undisturbed. To them, nothing FAMILIAR seems baffling or hard to understand. They don’t complain about lacking evidence from their senses and are free from the risk of becoming SKEPTICS. However, once we stray from instinct and start to follow higher reasoning, meditating and reflecting on the nature of things, countless uncertainties arise in our minds regarding things we once thought we fully understood. Prejudices and sensory errors come to light, and as we try to fix these through reasoning, we unintentionally get caught up in strange paradoxes, complexities, and inconsistencies that grow as we delve deeper into our thoughts. Eventually, after wandering through many confusing paths, we find ourselves right back where we started, or, even worse, stuck in a hopeless form of Scepticism.

2. The cause of this is thought to be the obscurity of things, or the natural weakness and imperfection of our understandings. It is said, the faculties we have are few, and those designed by nature for the SUPPORT and comfort of life, and not to penetrate into the INWARD ESSENCE and constitution of things. Besides, the mind of man being finite, when it treats of things which partake of infinity, it is not to be wondered at if it run into absurdities and contradictions, out of which it is impossible it should ever extricate itself, it being of the nature of infinite not to be comprehended by that which is finite.

2. The reason for this is believed to be the complexity of things, or the natural limitations and imperfections of our understanding. It's said that the abilities we have are limited, and those designed by nature are meant for the SUPPORT and comfort of life, not to explore the INWARD ESSENCE and structure of things. Furthermore, since the human mind is finite, when it deals with things that are infinite, it’s not surprising if it leads to absurdities and contradictions that it can never escape from, because the infinite cannot be fully understood by what is finite.

3. But, perhaps, we may be too partial to ourselves in placing the fault originally in our faculties, and not rather in the wrong use we make of them. IT IS A HARD THING TO SUPPOSE THAT RIGHT DEDUCTIONS FROM TRUE PRINCIPLES SHOULD EVER END IN CONSEQUENCES WHICH CANNOT BE MAINTAINED or made consistent. We should believe that God has dealt more bountifully with the sons of men than to give them a strong desire for that knowledge which he had placed quite out of their reach. This were not agreeable to the wonted indulgent methods of Providence, which, whatever appetites it may have implanted in the creatures, doth usually furnish them with such means as, if rightly made use of, will not fail to satisfy them. Upon the whole, I am inclined to think that the far greater part, if not all, of those difficulties which have hitherto amused philosophers, and blocked up the way to knowledge, are entirely owing to ourselves--that we have first raised a dust and then complain we cannot see.

3. But maybe we are too focused on blaming our own abilities for the fault, rather than the way we use them incorrectly. IT’S HARD TO BELIEVE THAT LOGICAL DEDUCTIONS FROM TRUE PRINCIPLES COULD EVER RESULT IN OUTCOMES THAT CAN’T BE SUPPORTED or made consistent. We should think that God has been more generous with humanity than to give us a strong desire for knowledge that is completely out of our reach. That wouldn’t fit with the usual compassionate ways of Providence, which, no matter what desires it has instilled in creatures, usually provides them with means that, if used correctly, will surely satisfy those desires. Overall, I tend to think that most, if not all, of the challenges that have puzzled philosophers and hindered our pursuit of knowledge are entirely due to us—we create confusion and then complain that we can’t see.

4. My purpose therefore is, to try if I can discover what those Principles are which have introduced all that doubtfulness and uncertainty, those absurdities and contradictions, into the several sects of philosophy; insomuch that the wisest men have thought our ignorance incurable, conceiving it to arise from the natural dulness and limitation of our faculties. And surely it is a work well deserving our pains to make a strict inquiry concerning the First Principles of Human Knowledge, to sift and examine them on all sides, especially since there may be some grounds to suspect that those lets and difficulties, which stay and embarrass the mind in its search after truth, do not spring from any darkness and intricacy in the objects, or natural defect in the understanding, so much as from false Principles which have been insisted on, and might have been avoided.

4. My goal, then, is to see if I can figure out what those principles are that have caused all the confusion and uncertainty, along with the absurdities and contradictions, in the various branches of philosophy. So much so that the wisest individuals have believed our ignorance to be incurable, thinking it results from the natural dullness and limitations of our minds. It is certainly a worthy endeavor to thoroughly investigate the First Principles of Human Knowledge, to analyze and scrutinize them from every angle, especially since there may be reason to suspect that the obstacles and difficulties that hinder and confuse our minds in the pursuit of truth do not arise from any complexity in the objects themselves or from a natural deficiency in understanding, but rather from false principles that have been upheld and could have been avoided.

5. How difficult and discouraging soever this attempt may seem, when I consider how many great and extraordinary men have gone before me in the like designs, yet I am not without some hopes--upon the consideration that the largest views are not always the clearest, and that he who is short--sighted will be obliged to draw the object nearer, and may, perhaps, by a close and narrow survey, discern that which had escaped far better eyes.

5. No matter how hard and discouraging this attempt might seem, especially when I think about all the great and extraordinary people who have tried similar things before me, I still have some hope—considering that the biggest perspectives aren’t always the clearest, and that someone who can’t see far will have to bring the object closer, and maybe, by looking closely and closely, they’ll notice things that even much better eyes missed.

6. A CHIEF SOURCE OF ERROR IN ALL PARTS OF KNOWLEDGE.--In order to prepare the mind of the reader for the easier conceiving what follows, it is proper to premise somewhat, by way of Introduction, concerning the nature and abuse of Language. But the unravelling this matter leads me in some measure to anticipate my design, by taking notice of what seems to have had a chief part in rendering speculation intricate and perplexed, and to have occasioned innumerable errors and difficulties in almost all parts of knowledge. And that is the opinion that the mind has a power of framing ABSTRACT IDEAS or notions of things. He who is not a perfect stranger to the writings and disputes of philosophers must needs acknowledge that no small part of them are spent about abstract ideas. These are in a more especial manner thought to be the object of those sciences which go by the name of LOGIC and METAPHYSICS, and of all that which passes under the notion of the most abstracted and sublime learning, in all which one shall scarce find any question handled in such a manner as does not suppose their existence in the mind, and that it is well acquainted with them.

6. A MAIN SOURCE OF ERROR IN ALL AREAS OF KNOWLEDGE.--To prepare the reader's mind for better understanding of what follows, it's important to start with a brief introduction about the nature and misuse of language. However, discussing this topic partly leads me to reveal my purpose by addressing what seems to be a major factor in making speculation complex and confusing and causing countless errors and difficulties in nearly all fields of knowledge. This factor is the belief that the mind has the ability to create ABSTRACT IDEAS or concepts of things. Anyone familiar with the writings and debates of philosophers must acknowledge that a significant portion of their work revolves around abstract ideas. These ideas are especially considered the focus of fields known as LOGIC and METAPHYSICS, and all that is regarded as the most abstract and advanced knowledge, where you can hardly find any question addressed without assuming their existence in the mind and that the mind is well-acquainted with them.

7. PROPER ACCEPTATION OF ABSTRACTION.--It is agreed on all hands that the qualities or modes of things do never REALLY EXIST EACH OF THEM APART BY ITSELF, and separated from all others, but are mixed, as it were, and blended together, several in the same object. But, we are told, the mind being able to consider each quality singly, or abstracted from those other qualities with which it is united, does by that means frame to itself abstract ideas. For example, there is perceived by sight an object extended, coloured, and moved: this mixed or compound idea the mind resolving into its simple, constituent parts, and viewing each by itself, exclusive of the rest, does frame the abstract ideas of extension, colour, and motion. Not that it is possible for colour or motion to exist without extension; but only that the mind can frame to itself by ABSTRACTION the idea of colour exclusive of extension, and of motion exclusive of both colour and extension.

7. PROPER ACCEPTANCE OF ABSTRACTION.--It is widely agreed that the qualities or characteristics of things never truly exist independently from each other; instead, they are mixed and blended together within the same object. However, we are told that the mind can consider each quality separately or abstracted from the other qualities it is combined with, which allows it to create abstract ideas. For instance, when we see an object that is extended, colored, and in motion, the mind breaks this mixed or composite idea into its simple, individual parts and views each one separately, apart from the others, thus forming the abstract ideas of extension, color, and motion. It’s not that color or motion can exist without extension; rather, it’s that the mind can create the idea of color without considering extension, and the idea of motion without considering both color and extension.

8. OF GENERALIZING [Note].--Again, the mind having observed that in the particular extensions perceived by sense there is something COMMON and alike IN ALL, and some other things peculiar, as this or that figure or magnitude, which distinguish them one from another; it considers apart or singles out by itself that which is common, making thereof a most abstract idea of extension, which is neither line, surface, nor solid, nor has any figure or magnitude, but is an idea entirely prescinded from all these. So likewise the mind, by leaving out of the particular colours perceived by sense that which distinguishes them one from another, and retaining that only which is COMMON TO ALL, makes an idea of colour in abstract which is neither red, nor blue, nor white, nor any other determinate colour. And, in like manner, by considering motion abstractedly not only from the body moved, but likewise from the figure it describes, and all particular directions and velocities, the abstract idea of motion is framed; which equally corresponds to all particular motions whatsoever that may be perceived by sense.

8. OF GENERALIZING [Note].--Again, the mind, having noticed that in the specific extensions perceived by our senses, there is something COMMON and similar IN ALL, along with some unique aspects, like specific shapes or sizes that differentiate them from each other; it separates or highlights what is common, creating a very abstract idea of extension that is neither a line, surface, nor solid, nor does it have any particular shape or size, but is an idea completely detached from all these. Similarly, the mind, by disregarding the specific colors perceived by our senses that set them apart from each other, and retaining only what is COMMON TO ALL, forms an abstract idea of color that is neither red, nor blue, nor white, nor any other specific color. Likewise, by considering motion abstractly not only without the moving body but also apart from the shape it takes, and all specific directions and speeds, the abstract idea of motion is created; which applies equally to all particular motions that can be perceived by our senses.

[Note: Vide Reid, on the Intellectual Powers of Man, Essay V, chap iii. sec. 1, edit. 1843]

[Note: See Reid, on the Intellectual Powers of Man, Essay V, chap iii. sec. 1, edit. 1843]

9. OF COMPOUNDING.--And as the mind frames to itself abstract ideas of qualities or MODES, so does it, by the same precision or mental separation, attain abstract ideas of the more compounded BEINGS which include several coexistent qualities. For example, the mind having observed that Peter, James, and John resemble each other in certain common agreements of shape and other qualities, leaves out of the complex or compounded idea it has of Peter, James, and any other particular man, that which is peculiar to each, retaining only what is common to all, and so makes an abstract idea wherein all the particulars equally partake--abstracting entirely from and cutting off all those circumstances and differences which might determine it to any particular existence. And after this manner it is said we come by the abstract idea of MAN, or, if you please, humanity, or human nature; wherein it is true there is included colour, because there is no man but has some colour, but then it can be neither white, nor black, nor any particular colour, because there is no one particular colour wherein all men partake. So likewise there is included stature, but then it is neither tall stature, nor low stature, nor yet middle stature, but something abstracted from all these. And so of the rest. Moreover, their being a great variety of other creatures that partake in some parts, but not all, of the complex idea of MAN, the mind, leaving out those parts which are peculiar to men, and retaining those only which are common to all the living creatures, frames the idea of ANIMAL, which abstracts not only from all particular men, but also all birds, beasts, fishes, and insects. The constituent parts of the abstract idea of animal are body, life, sense, and spontaneous motion. By BODY is meant body without any particular shape or figure, there being no one shape or figure common to all animals, without covering, either of hair, or feathers, or scales, &c., nor yet naked: hair, feathers, scales, and nakedness being the distinguishing properties of particular animals, and for that reason left out of the ABSTRACT IDEA. Upon the same account the spontaneous motion must be neither walking, nor flying, nor creeping; it is nevertheless a motion, but what that motion is it is not easy to conceive[Note.].

9. OF COMPOUNDING.--Just as the mind creates abstract ideas of qualities or MODES, it also forms abstract ideas of more complex BEINGS that include multiple coexisting qualities. For instance, after noticing that Peter, James, and John share certain common features in shape and other qualities, the mind sets aside the unique aspects of each individual and focuses only on what they all have in common. This results in an abstract idea that all the specifics share equally—completely removing the details and differences that could relate to any specific individual. This is how we arrive at the abstract idea of MAN, or rather, humanity or human nature; in this concept, color is included since no man lacks some color, but it cannot be described as simply white, black, or any specific color because no single color is common to all men. Similarly, stature is included, but it cannot be defined as tall, short, or average; rather, it is something distinct from all these categories. This same logic applies to other qualities as well. Additionally, since there is a wide variety of other creatures that share some aspects but not all of the complex idea of MAN, the mind excludes the features unique to humans and focuses on those that all living creatures share, forming the idea of ANIMAL, which abstractly encompasses all living beings, including birds, beasts, fish, and insects. The main components of the abstract idea of animal are body, life, sense, and spontaneous motion. By BODY, it refers to a body without any specific shape or form, since no single shape or form is shared by all animals, whether covered in hair, feathers, or scales, or even naked. Hair, feathers, and scales are distinctive traits of particular animals and are therefore excluded from the ABSTRACT IDEA. Similarly, spontaneous motion cannot be defined as walking, flying, or crawling; it is still a type of motion, but the exact nature of that motion is not easy to grasp.

[Note: Vide Hobbes' Tripos, ch. v. sect. 6.]

[Note: See Hobbes' Tripos, ch. v. sect. 6.]

10. TWO OBJECTIONS TO THE EXISTENCE OF ABSTRACT IDEAS.--Whether others have this wonderful faculty of ABSTRACTING THEIR IDEAS, they best can tell: for myself, I find indeed I have a faculty of imagining, or representing to myself, the ideas of those particular things I have perceived, and of variously compounding and dividing them. I can imagine a man with two heads, or the upper parts of a man joined to the body of a horse. I can consider the hand, the eye, the nose, each by itself abstracted or separated from the rest of the body. But then whatever hand or eye I imagine, it must have some particular shape and colour. Likewise the idea of man that I frame to myself must be either of a white, or a black, or a tawny, a straight, or a crooked, a tall, or a low, or a middle-sized man. I cannot by any effort of thought conceive the abstract idea above described. And it is equally impossible for me to form the abstract idea of motion distinct from the body moving, and which is neither swift nor slow, curvilinear nor rectilinear; and the like may be said of all other abstract general ideas whatsoever. To be plain, I own myself able to abstract IN ONE SENSE, as when I consider some particular parts or qualities separated from others, with which, though they are united in some object, yet it is possible they may really exist without them. But I deny that I can abstract from one another, or conceive separately, those qualities which it is impossible should exist so separated; or that I can frame a general notion, by abstracting from particulars in the manner aforesaid--which last are the two proper acceptations of ABSTRACTION. And there are grounds to think most men will acknowledge themselves to be in my case. The generality of men which are simple and illiterate never pretend to ABSTRACT NOTIONS. It is said they are difficult and not to be attained without pains and study; we may therefore reasonably conclude that, if such there be, they are confined only to the learned.

10. TWO OBJECTIONS TO THE EXISTENCE OF ABSTRACT IDEAS.--Whether other people have this amazing ability to ABSTRACT THEIR IDEAS, they can say better than I can. For my part, I find that I can imagine, or mentally represent, the ideas of specific things I've perceived, and I can mix and break them down in various ways. I can picture a man with two heads, or the top part of a man connected to the body of a horse. I can think about the hand, the eye, or the nose, each on their own, separated from the rest of the body. However, any hand or eye I imagine has to have a specific shape and color. Similarly, the idea of a man that I create in my mind must be either white, black, or brown, straight or crooked, tall, short, or average. I cannot, no matter how hard I try, conceive the abstract idea mentioned above. It's just as impossible for me to form the abstract idea of motion that is separate from the body that is moving, and which is neither fast nor slow, curvy nor straight; this applies to all other abstract general ideas as well. To be clear, I admit I can abstract IN ONE SENSE, as when I consider certain parts or qualities separately from others, which, although they are combined in an object, could actually exist without them. But I deny that I can abstract from one another, or conceive separately, those qualities that cannot exist apart; nor can I form a general notion by abstracting from specifics in the way described—which are the two main meanings of ABSTRACTION. There are reasons to believe most people would agree with me. The majority of simple and uneducated individuals do not claim to have ABSTRACT NOTIONS. It's said that they are difficult to grasp and require effort and study; therefore, we can reasonably assume that, if they exist at all, they are limited to the educated.

11. I proceed to examine what can be alleged in DEFENCE OF THE DOCTRINE OF ABSTRACTION, and try if I can discover what it is that inclines the men of speculation to embrace an opinion so remote from common sense as that seems to be. There has been a late deservedly esteemed philosopher who, no doubt, has given it very much countenance, by seeming to think the having abstract general ideas is what puts the widest difference in point of understanding betwixt man and beast. "The having of general ideas," saith he, "is that which puts a perfect distinction betwixt man and brutes, and is an excellency which the faculties of brutes do by no means attain unto. For, it is evident we observe no foot-steps in them of making use of general signs for universal ideas; from which we have reason to imagine that they have not the FACULTY OF ABSTRACTING, or making general ideas, since they have no use of words or any other general signs." And a little after: "Therefore, I think, we may suppose that it is in this that the species of brutes are discriminated from men, and it is that proper difference wherein they are wholly separated, and which at last widens to so wide a distance. For, if they have any ideas at all, and are not bare machines (as some would have them), we cannot deny them to have some reason. It seems as evident to me that they do, some of them, in certain instances reason as that they have sense; but it is only in particular ideas, just as they receive them from their senses. They are the best of them tied up within those narrow bounds, and have not (as I think) the faculty to enlarge them by any kind of ABSTRACTION." Essay on Human Understanding, II. xi. 10 and 11. I readily agree with this learned author, that the faculties of brutes can by no means attain to ABSTRACTION. But then if this be made the distinguishing property of that sort of animals, I fear a great many of those that pass for men must be reckoned into their number. The reason that is here assigned why we have no grounds to think brutes have abstract general ideas is, that we observe in them no use of words or any other general signs; which is built on this supposition--that the making use of words implies the having general ideas. From which it follows that men who use language are able to ABSTRACT or GENERALIZE their ideas. That this is the sense and arguing of the author will further appear by his answering the question he in another place puts: "Since all things that exist are only particulars, how come we by general terms?" His answer is: "Words become general by being made the signs of general ideas."--Essay on Human Understanding, IV. iii. 6. But [Note. 1] it seems that a word becomes general by being made the sign, not of an ABSTRACT general idea, but of several particular ideas [Note. 2], any one of which it indifferently suggests to the mind. For example, when it is said "the change of motion is proportional to the impressed force," or that "whatever has extension is divisible," these propositions are to be understood of motion and extension in general; and nevertheless it will not follow that they suggest to my thoughts an idea of motion without a body moved, or any determinate direction and velocity, or that I must conceive an abstract general idea of extension, which is neither line, surface, nor solid, neither great nor small, black, white, nor red, nor of any other determinate colour. It is only implied that whatever particular motion I consider, whether it be swift or slow, perpendicular, horizontal, or oblique, or in whatever object, the axiom concerning it holds equally true. As does the other of every particular extension, it matters not whether line, surface, or solid, whether of this or that magnitude or figure.

11. I will look into the arguments made in DEFENSE OF THE DOCTRINE OF ABSTRACTION and see if I can uncover what leads thinkers to adopt such a viewpoint that seems far removed from common sense. Recently, an esteemed philosopher has given this idea a lot of support by suggesting that having abstract general ideas is what creates the biggest gap in understanding between humans and animals. He states, "Having general ideas is what creates a perfect distinction between humans and animals, and it is a quality that animals do not possess. It is clear that we see no signs of them using general symbols for universal ideas; from this, we reason that they do not have the FACULTY OF ABSTRACTING or creating general ideas, since they don't use words or any other general symbols." He goes on to say, "Therefore, I think we can conclude that this is how animal species are distinguished from humans, and it is the essential difference that completely separates them, ultimately creating a vast divide. Because if they have any ideas at all, and are not mere machines (as some claim), we can't deny that they have some reasoning. It seems clear to me that some of them reason in specific situations just as they perceive with their senses. The best among them are confined within these limited boundaries and do not have (as I believe) the ability to expand them through any form of ABSTRACTION." Essay on Human Understanding, II. xi. 10 and 11. I completely agree with this knowledgeable author that animals cannot reach ABSTRACTION. But if this is seen as the defining trait of those animals, I worry that many who are regarded as humans should be included in that group. The reasoning provided as to why we have no basis to believe animals possess abstract general ideas is based on our observation that they do not use words or any other general symbols; this is grounded in the assumption that the use of words indicates having general ideas. Consequently, it follows that people who use language can ABSTRACT or GENERALIZE their ideas. The author's viewpoint is further clarified by his response to a question he poses elsewhere: "Since everything that exists is just particulars, how do we come to have general terms?" His answer is, "Words become general by being made the signs of general ideas."--Essay on Human Understanding, IV. iii. 6. But [Note. 1] it seems that a word becomes general by being made the sign, not of an ABSTRACT general idea, but of several particular ideas [Note. 2], any of which it can suggest to the mind. For instance, when we say "the change of motion is proportional to the impressed force," or that "whatever has extension is divisible," these statements are meant to be understood about motion and extension in general; yet, it does not follow that they evoke in my mind an idea of motion devoid of a moving body, a specific direction, or speed, or that I need to form an abstract general idea of extension that is neither line, surface, nor solid, neither large nor small, black, white, nor red, nor of any other specific color. It simply implies that whatever particular motion I consider, be it fast or slow, vertical, horizontal, or diagonal, in any object, the axiom applies equally. The same goes for any particular extension, regardless of whether it’s a line, surface, or solid, whether it has this or that size or shape.

[Note 1: "TO THIS I CANNOT ASSENT, BEING OF OPINION," edit of 1710.]

[Note 1: "I CANNOT AGREE WITH THIS, AS I BELIEVE," edit of 1710.]

[Note 2: Of the same sort.]

[Note 2: Of the same sort.]

12. EXISTENCE OF GENERAL IDEAS ADMITTED.--By observing how ideas become general we may the better judge how words are made so. And here it is to be noted that I do not deny absolutely there are general ideas, but only that there are any ABSTRACT GENERAL IDEAS; for, in the passages we have quoted wherein there is mention of general ideas, it is always supposed that they are formed by ABSTRACTION, after the manner set forth in sections 8 and 9. Now, if we will annex a meaning to our words, and speak only of what we can conceive, I believe we shall acknowledge that an idea which, considered in itself, is particular, becomes general by being made to represent or stand for all other particular ideas of the SAME SORT. To make this plain by an example, suppose a geometrician is demonstrating the method of cutting a line in two equal parts. He draws, for instance, a black line of an inch in length: this, which in itself is a particular line, is nevertheless with regard to its signification general, since, as it is there used, it represents all particular lines whatsoever; so that what is demonstrated of it is demonstrated of all lines, or, in other words, of a line in general. And, as that particular line becomes general by being made a sign, so the name LINE, which taken absolutely is PARTICULAR, by being a sign is made GENERAL. And as the former owes its generality not to its being the sign of an abstract or general line, but of ALL PARTICULAR right lines that may possibly exist, so the latter must be thought to derive its generality from the same cause, namely, the VARIOUS PARTICULAR lines which it indifferently denotes. [Note.]

12. EXISTENCE OF GENERAL IDEAS ADMITTED.--By observing how ideas become general, we can better understand how words are created in the same way. It's important to note that I’m not completely denying the existence of general ideas, but I am questioning whether there are any ABSTRACT GENERAL IDEAS. In the passages we have cited that mention general ideas, it's always assumed that they are formed by ABSTRACTION, as explained in sections 8 and 9. Now, if we assign meanings to our words and only talk about what we can conceive, I believe we will recognize that an idea, when considered on its own, is specific but becomes general by representing or standing for all other specific ideas of the SAME KIND. To clarify this with an example, let’s say a mathematician is demonstrating how to divide a line into two equal parts. He draws, for instance, a black line one inch long: this, being a specific line, is still general in its meaning since it represents all specific lines in that context; therefore, what is demonstrated about it applies to all lines, or in other words, to lines in general. Just like that specific line becomes general by being used as a symbol, the term LINE, which by itself is SPECIFIC, is made GENERAL by being a symbol. And just as the specific line gains its generality not from being the sign of an abstract or general line but from ALL SPECIFIC straight lines that might exist, the term LINE must also be understood to derive its generality from the VARIOUS SPECIFIC lines it can represent. [Note.]

[Note: "I look upon this (doctrine) to be one of the greatest and most valuable discoveries that have been made of late years in the republic of letters."--Treatise of Human Nature, book i, part i, sect. 7. Also Stewart's Philosophy of the Mind, part i, chapt. iv. sect. iii. p. 99.]

[Note: "I consider this idea to be one of the greatest and most valuable discoveries made recently in the realm of literature."--Treatise of Human Nature, book i, part i, sect. 7. Also Stewart's Philosophy of the Mind, part i, chapt. iv. sect. iii. p. 99.]

13. ABSTRACT GENERAL IDEAS NECESSARY, ACCORDING TO LOCKE.--To give the reader a yet clearer view of the nature of abstract ideas, and the uses they are thought necessary to, I shall add one more passage out of the Essay on Human Understanding, (IV. vii. 9) which is as follows: "ABSTRACT IDEAS are not so obvious or easy to children or the yet unexercised mind as particular ones. If they seem so to grown men it is only because by constant and familiar use they are made so. For, when we nicely reflect upon them, we shall find that general ideas are fictions and contrivances of the mind, that carry difficulty with them, and do not so easily offer themselves as we are apt to imagine. For example, does it not require some pains and skill to form the general idea of a triangle (which is yet none of the most abstract, comprehensive, and difficult); for it must be neither oblique nor rectangle, neither equilateral, equicrural, nor scalenon, but ALL AND NONE of these at once? In effect, it is something imperfect that cannot exist, an idea wherein some parts of several different and INCONSISTENT ideas are put together. It is true the mind in this imperfect state has need of such ideas, and makes all the haste to them it can, for the CONVENIENCY OF COMMUNICATION AND ENLARGEMENT OF KNOWLEDGE, to both which it is naturally very much inclined. But yet one has reason to suspect such ideas are marks of our imperfection. At least this is enough to show that the most abstract and general ideas are not those that the mind is first and most easily acquainted with, nor such as its earliest knowledge is conversant about."--If any man has the faculty of framing in his mind such an idea of a triangle as is here described, it is in vain to pretend to dispute him out of it, nor would I go about it. All I desire is that the reader would fully and certainly inform himself whether he has such an idea or no. And this, methinks, can be no hard task for anyone to perform. What more easy than for anyone to look a little into his own thoughts, and there try whether he has, or can attain to have, an idea that shall correspond with the description that is here given of the general idea of a triangle, which is NEITHER OBLIQUE NOR RECTANGLE, EQUILATERAL, EQUICRURAL NOR SCALENON, BUT ALL AND NONE OF THESE AT ONCE?

13. ABSTRACT GENERAL IDEAS NECESSARY, ACCORDING TO LOCKE.--To give the reader a clearer understanding of abstract ideas and their perceived importance, I’ll add another excerpt from the Essay on Human Understanding, (IV. vii. 9), which says: "ABSTRACT IDEAS are not as obvious or easy for children or inexperienced minds as specific ones. If they seem easy to adults, it’s only because they’ve become familiar through constant use. However, upon closer reflection, we find that general ideas are inventions of the mind that come with difficulty and don’t present themselves as easily as we think. For instance, forming a general idea of a triangle does require some effort and skill (and it’s not even the most abstract, comprehensive, or challenging concept); it must be neither oblique nor right-angled, neither equilateral, isosceles, nor scalene, but ALL AND NONE of these at once. Essentially, it’s an imperfect idea that cannot exist, consisting of parts from several different and INCONSISTENT ideas combined together. It’s true that the mind, in this imperfect state, needs such ideas and rushes to them out of the CONVENIENCE OF COMMUNICATION AND EXPANSION OF KNOWLEDGE, both of which it naturally seeks. Still, one might reasonably suspect that these ideas reflect our imperfections. This demonstrates that the most abstract and general ideas are not those the mind first encounters or easily grasps, nor those it deals with in its earliest understanding."--If someone has the ability to form in their mind the idea of a triangle as described here, there’s no point in trying to challenge their understanding, nor would I attempt to. All I ask is that the reader honestly and accurately assess whether they have such an idea. I think this is not a difficult task for anyone. What could be simpler than to look into their own thoughts and see if they can attain an idea that matches the description of a general triangle, which is NEITHER OBLIQUE NOR RECTANGLE, EQUILATERAL, ISOSCELES NOR SCALENE, BUT ALL AND NONE OF THESE AT ONCE?

14. BUT THEY ARE NOT NECESSARY FOR COMMUNICATION.--Much is here said of the difficulty that abstract ideas carry with them, and the pains and skill requisite to the forming them. And it is on all hands agreed that there is need of great toil and labour of the mind, to emancipate our thoughts from particular objects, and raise them to those sublime speculations that are conversant about abstract ideas. From all which the natural consequence should seem to be, that so DIFFICULT a thing as the forming abstract ideas was not necessary for COMMUNICATION, which is so EASY and familiar to ALL SORTS OF MEN. But, we are told, if they seem obvious and easy to grown men, IT IS ONLY BECAUSE BY CONSTANT AND FAMILIAR USE THEY ARE MADE SO. Now, I would fain know at what time it is men are employed in surmounting that difficulty, and furnishing themselves with those necessary helps for discourse. It cannot be when they are grown up, for then it seems they are not conscious of any such painstaking; it remains therefore to be the business of their childhood. And surely the great and multiplied labour of framing abstract notions will be found a hard task for that tender age. Is it not a hard thing to imagine that a couple of children cannot prate together of their sugar-plums and rattles and the rest of their little trinkets, till they have first tacked together numberless inconsistencies, and so framed in their minds ABSTRACT GENERAL IDEAS, and annexed them to every common name they make use of?

14. BUT THEY ARE NOT NECESSARY FOR COMMUNICATION.--A lot has been said about the challenges that abstract ideas bring and the effort and skill needed to form them. It's widely accepted that it takes a lot of mental effort to free our thoughts from specific objects and elevate them to those high-level discussions that deal with abstract ideas. From all this, it would seem that creating abstract ideas, which is so challenging, is not necessary for COMMUNICATION, which is EASY and familiar to ALL KINDS OF PEOPLE. However, we are told that if they seem straightforward and simple to adults, IT'S ONLY BECAUSE THEY HAVE BECOME SO THROUGH CONSTANT AND FAMILIAR USE. Now, I would like to know when people actually work to overcome that difficulty and equip themselves with the essential tools for conversation. It can't be when they are adults because then it seems they aren't aware of any such hard work; it must, therefore, be the task of their childhood. And certainly, the extensive and complicated effort of forming abstract ideas will be a tough job for such a young age. Is it not hard to believe that a couple of children cannot chat about their candies and toys until they have first pieced together countless inconsistencies and formed ABSTRACT GENERAL IDEAS in their minds, attaching them to every common word they use?

15. NOR FOR THE ENLARGEMENT OF KNOWLEDGE.--Nor do I think them a whit more needful for the ENLARGEMENT OF KNOWLEDGE than for COMMUNICATION. It is, I know, a point much insisted on, that all knowledge and demonstration are about universal notions, to which I fully agree: but then it doth not appear to me that those notions are formed by ABSTRACTION in the manner PREMISED--UNIVERSALITY, so far as I can comprehend, not consisting in the absolute, POSITIVE nature or conception of anything, but in the RELATION it bears to the particulars signified or represented by it; by virtue whereof it is that things, names, or notions, being in their own nature PARTICULAR, are rendered UNIVERSAL. Thus, when I demonstrate any proposition concerning triangles, it is to be supposed that I have in view the universal idea of a triangle; which ought not to be understood as if I could frame an idea of a triangle which was neither equilateral, nor scalenon, nor equicrural; but only that the particular triangle I consider, whether of this or that sort it matters not, doth equally stand for and represent all rectilinear triangles whatsoever, and is in that sense UNIVERSAL. All which seems very plain and not to include any difficulty in it.

15. NOR FOR THE ENLARGEMENT OF KNOWLEDGE.--I don’t think they are any more necessary for the EXPANSION OF KNOWLEDGE than for COMMUNICATION. I understand that it's often emphasized that all knowledge and proof relate to universal concepts, and I completely agree with that. However, it doesn’t seem to me that those concepts are formed by ABSTRACTION in the way stated—UNIVERSALITY, as far as I see it, doesn’t consist in the absolute, POSITIVE nature or idea of anything, but rather in the RELATION it has to the specifics it signifies or represents. This is why things, names, or concepts, which are inherently PARTICULAR, can be considered UNIVERSAL. So, when I prove something about triangles, it’s assumed that I am referencing the universal idea of a triangle; it's important to clarify that I’m not saying I can come up with an idea of a triangle that isn't equilateral, scalene, or isosceles. Instead, the particular triangle I address, regardless of its type, represents all straight-line triangles in that sense and is therefore UNIVERSAL. All of this seems quite clear and not difficult to understand.

16. OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--But here it will be demanded, HOW WE CAN KNOW ANY PROPOSITION TO BE TRUE OF ALL PARTICULAR TRIANGLES, EXCEPT we have first seen it DEMONSTRATED OF THE ABSTRACT IDEA OF A TRIANGLE which equally agrees to all? For, because a property may be demonstrated to agree to some one particular triangle, it will not thence follow that it equally belongs to any other triangle, which in all respects is not the same with it. For example, having demonstrated that the three angles of an isosceles rectangular triangle are equal to two right ones, I cannot therefore conclude this affection agrees to all other triangles which have neither a right angle nor two equal sides. It seems therefore that, to be certain this proposition is universally true, we must either make a particular demonstration for every particular triangle, which is impossible, or once for all demonstrate it of the ABSTRACT IDEA OF A TRIANGLE, in which all the particulars do indifferently partake and by which they are all equally represented. To which I answer, that, though the idea I have in view whilst I make the demonstration be, for instance, that of an isosceles rectangular triangle whose sides are of a determinate length, I may nevertheless be certain it extends to all other rectilinear triangles, of what sort or bigness soever. And that because neither the right angle, nor the equality, nor determinate length of the sides are at all concerned in the demonstration. It is true the diagram I have in view includes all these particulars, but then there is not the least mention made of them in the proof of the proposition. It is not said the three angles are equal to two right ones, because one of them is a right angle, or because the sides comprehending it are of the same length. Which sufficiently shows that the right angle might have been oblique, and the sides unequal, and for all that the demonstration have held good. And for this reason it is that I conclude that to be true of any obliquangular or scalenon which I had demonstrated of a particular right--angled equicrural triangle, and not because I demonstrated the proposition of the abstract idea of a triangle And here it must be acknowledged that a man may consider a figure merely as triangular, without attending to the particular qualities of the angles, or relations of the sides. So far he may abstract; but this will never prove that he can frame an abstract, general, inconsistent idea of a triangle. In like manner we may consider Peter so far forth as man, or so far forth as animal without framing the fore-mentioned abstract idea, either of man or of animal, inasmuch as all that is perceived is not considered.

16. OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--But here it will be asked, HOW CAN WE KNOW ANY STATEMENT TO BE TRUE FOR ALL SPECIFIC TRIANGLES, UNLESS we have first seen it PROVEN FOR THE ABSTRACT IDEA OF A TRIANGLE that applies to all? Just because a property can be shown to apply to one specific triangle, it doesn't mean it automatically applies to any other triangle that is not identical to it in every way. For example, if I have shown that the three angles of an isosceles right triangle equal two right angles, I can't conclude that this property applies to all other triangles that don't have a right angle or two equal sides. Therefore, to be sure that this assertion is universally true, we would either have to prove it for every single triangle, which is impossible, or demonstrate it once and for all for the ABSTRACT IDEA OF A TRIANGLE, which every specific triangle shares and is represented by. In response, I say that even if the triangle I'm focused on during the demonstration is, for instance, an isosceles right triangle with specific side lengths, I can still be confident that it applies to all other straight-edged triangles, regardless of their type or size. This is because the right angle, the equal lengths, and the specific measurement of the sides are not involved in the proof. It is true that the diagram I’m considering includes all these specifics, but none of them are mentioned in the proposition’s proof. It doesn't say the three angles are equal to two right angles because one of them is a right angle, or because the sides forming it are the same length. This clearly shows that the right angle could have been oblique, and the sides unequal, yet the proof would still hold. For this reason, I conclude that what I demonstrated for a specific right-angled isosceles triangle is also true for any oblique-angled or scalene triangle. This is not because I proved the proposition for the abstract idea of a triangle. Here, it should be noted that a person can view a shape simply as triangular, without focusing on the specific characteristics of the angles or the relationships of the sides. To that extent, one can abstract, but this will never prove that they can create an abstract, general, inconsistent idea of a triangle. Similarly, we can consider Peter as a man or as an animal without forming the aforementioned abstract idea, either of man or animal, since not everything perceived is considered.

17. ADVANTAGE OF INVESTIGATING THE DOCTRINE OF ABSTRACT GENERAL IDEAS.--It were an endless as well as an useless thing to trace the SCHOOLMEN, those great masters of abstraction, through all the manifold inextricable labyrinths of error and dispute which their doctrine of abstract natures and notions seems to have led them into. What bickerings and controversies, and what a learned dust have been raised about those matters, and what mighty advantage has been from thence derived to mankind, are things at this day too clearly known to need being insisted on. And it had been well if the ill effects of that doctrine were confined to those only who make the most avowed profession of it. When men consider the great pains, industry, and parts that have for so many ages been laid out on the cultivation and advancement of the sciences, and that notwithstanding all this the far greater part of them remains full of darkness and uncertainty, and disputes that are like never to have an end, and even those that are thought to be supported by the most clear and cogent demonstrations contain in them paradoxes which are perfectly irreconcilable to the understandings of men, and that, taking all together, a very small portion of them does supply any real benefit to mankind, otherwise than by being an innocent diversion and amusement--I say the consideration of all this is apt to throw them into a despondency and perfect contempt of all study. But this may perhaps cease upon a view of the false principles that have obtained in the world, amongst all which there is none, methinks, has a more wide and extended sway over the thoughts of speculative men than [Note.] this of abstract general ideas.

17. ADVANTAGE OF INVESTIGATING THE DOCTRINE OF ABSTRACT GENERAL IDEAS.--It would be both endless and pointless to follow the SCHOOLMEN, those great masters of abstraction, through the countless complex errors and disputes their doctrine of abstract natures and concepts seems to have led them into. The arguments and controversies, along with the vast amount of scholarly debate stirred up about these topics, as well as the significant benefits derived from them for humanity, are now too well-known to require further emphasis. It would have been better if the negative effects of that doctrine were limited to those who openly practice it. When people consider the tremendous effort, diligence, and talent that has been dedicated over the ages to the development and advancement of the sciences, and that despite all this, most of them still remain shrouded in darkness and uncertainty, with disputes that seem unlikely to ever end, and even the fields that are believed to be backed by the clearest and most convincing evidence contain paradoxes that are completely irreconcilable with human understanding, it becomes evident that very little of it actually provides real benefits to humanity, aside from serving as innocent distractions and entertainment. I say that reflecting on all this can easily lead them to despair and complete disdain for all study. However, this perspective may change when considering the false principles that have taken hold in the world, among which, it seems to me, none has greater influence over the thoughts of speculative thinkers than this idea of abstract general concepts.

[Note: "That we have been endeavouring to overthrow."--Edit 1710.]

[Note: "That we have been trying to overthrow."--Edit 1710.]

18. I come now to consider the SOURCE OF THIS PREVAILING NOTION, and that seems to me to be LANGUAGE. And surely nothing of less extent than reason itself could have been the source of an opinion so universally received. The truth of this appears as from other reasons so also from the plain confession of the ablest patrons of abstract ideas, who acknowledge that they are made in order to naming; from which it is a clear consequence that if there had been no such things as speech or universal signs there never had been any thought of abstraction. See III. vi. 39, and elsewhere of the Essay on Human Understanding. Let us examine the manner wherein words have contributed to the origin of that mistake.--First [Vide sect. xix.] then, it is thought that every name has, or ought to have, ONE ONLY precise and settled signification, which inclines men to think there are certain ABSTRACT, DETERMINATE IDEAS that constitute the true and only immediate signification of each general name; and that it is by the mediation of these abstract ideas that a general name comes to signify any particular thing. Whereas, in truth, there is no such thing as one precise and definite signification annexed to any general name, they all signifying indifferently a great number of particular ideas. All which doth evidently follow from what has been already said, and will clearly appear to anyone by a little reflexion. To this it will be OBJECTED that every name that has a definition is thereby restrained to one certain signification. For example, a TRIANGLE is defined to be A PLAIN SURFACE COMPREHENDED BY THREE RIGHT LINES, by which that name is limited to denote one certain idea and no other. To which I answer, that in the definition it is not said whether the surface be great or small, black or white, nor whether the sides are long or short, equal or unequal, nor with what angles they are inclined to each other; in all which there may be great variety, and consequently there is NO ONE SETTLED IDEA which limits the signification of the word TRIANGLE. It is one thing for to keep a name constantly to the same definition, and another to make it stand everywhere for the same idea; the one is necessary, the other useless and impracticable.

18. Now, let’s look at the SOURCE OF THIS COMMON IDEA, which seems to be LANGUAGE. And nothing less than reason itself could have given rise to such a widely accepted opinion. This is evident not only for various reasons but also from the straightforward admissions of the most knowledgeable supporters of abstract ideas, who recognize that they are created for the purpose of naming. It clearly follows that if there had been no speech or universal signs, there would have been no thoughts of abstraction. See III. vi. 39, and other sections of the Essay on Human Understanding. Let’s examine how words have contributed to the origin of this misunderstanding. First [Vide sect. xix.], people think that every name should have ONLY ONE precise and fixed meaning, which leads them to believe there are certain ABSTRACT, DETERMINATE IDEAS that make up the true and only immediate meaning of each general name; and it's through these abstract ideas that a general name comes to refer to any specific thing. However, in reality, no general name has just one precise and definite meaning attached to it; they all refer to a wide range of specific ideas. This follows clearly from what has already been said and will become obvious to anyone with a bit of reflection. An objection to this would be that every name with a definition is limited to one certain meaning. For example, a TRIANGLE is defined as A PLAIN SURFACE ENCLOSED BY THREE STRAIGHT LINES, limiting that name to represent one specific idea and no other. In response, I would say that the definition doesn't specify whether the surface is large or small, black or white, or whether the sides are long or short, equal or unequal, or the angles of inclination between them; there can be significant variation in all these aspects, and therefore there is NO ONE SETTLING IDEA that limits the meaning of the word TRIANGLE. It's one thing to keep a name consistently to the same definition, and quite another to make it represent the same idea everywhere; the former is necessary, while the latter is unnecessary and impractical.

19. SECONDLY, But, to give a farther account how WORDS came to PRODUCE THE DOCTRINE OF ABSTRACT IDEAS, it must be observed that it is a received opinion that language has NO OTHER END but the communicating our ideas, and that every significant name stands for an idea. This being so, and it being withal certain that names which yet are not thought altogether insignificant do not always mark out PARTICULAR conceivable ideas, it is straightway concluded that THEY STAND FOR ABSTRACT NOTIONS. That there are many names in use amongst speculative men which do not always suggest to others determinate, particular ideas, or in truth anything at all, is what nobody will deny. And a little attention will discover that it is not necessary (even in the strictest reasonings) significant names which stand for ideas should, every time they are used, excite in the understanding the ideas they are made to stand for--in reading and discoursing, names being for the most part used as letters are in ALGEBRA, in which, though a particular quantity be marked by each letter, yet to proceed right it is not requisite that in every step each letter suggest to your thoughts that particular quantity it was appointed to stand for.[Note.]

19. SECONDLY, to explain further how WORDS lead to the DOCTRINE OF ABSTRACT IDEAS, it's important to note that it's a common belief that the only purpose of language is to communicate our ideas, and that every meaningful name represents an idea. Given this, and the fact that names which aren't completely meaningless don't always refer to SPECIFIC, understandable ideas, it's quickly assumed that THEY REPRESENT ABSTRACT NOTIONS. No one would deny that many names used by thoughtful individuals don't always evoke clear, specific ideas, or sometimes anything at all. A bit of attention will reveal that it’s not necessary (even in the most rigorous arguments) for words that represent ideas to always invoke the specific ideas they refer to whenever they are used—in reading and discussing, words are mostly used like letters in ALGEBRA, where, although each letter stands for a particular quantity, it’s not essential for each letter to constantly remind you of that specific quantity at every step.

[Note: Language has become the source or origin of abstract general ideas on account of a twofold error.--(1.) That every word has only one signification. (2.) That the only end of language is the communication of our ideas--Ed.]

[Note: Language has become the source of abstract general ideas because of two main misconceptions.--(1.) That every word has only one meaning. (2.) That the only purpose of language is to communicate our ideas--Ed.]

20. SOME OF THE ENDS OF LANGUAGE.--Besides, the communicating of ideas marked by words is not the chief and only end of language, as is commonly supposed. There are other ends, as the raising of some passion, the exciting to or deterring from an action, the putting the mind in some particular disposition--to which the former is in many cases barely subservient, and sometimes entirely omitted, when these can be obtained without it, as I think does not unfrequently happen in the familiar use of language. I entreat the reader to reflect with himself, and see if it doth not often happen, either in hearing or reading a discourse, that the passions of fear, love, hatred, admiration, disdain, and the like, arise immediately in his mind upon the perception of certain words, without any ideas coming between. At first, indeed, the words might have occasioned ideas that were fitting to produce those emotions; but, if I mistake not, it will be found that, when language is once grown familiar, the hearing of the sounds or sight of the characters is oft immediately attended with those passions which at first were wont to be produced by the intervention of ideas that are now quite omitted. May we not, for example, be affected with the promise of a GOOD THING, though we have not an idea of what it is? Or is not the being threatened with danger sufficient to excite a dread, though we think not of any particular evil likely to befal us, nor yet frame to ourselves an idea of danger in abstract? If any one shall join ever so little reflexion of his own to what has been said, I believe that it will evidently appear to him that general names are often used in the propriety of language without the speaker's designing them for marks of ideas in his own, which he would have them raise in the mind of the hearer. Even proper names themselves do not seem always spoken with a design to bring into our view the ideas of those individuals that are supposed to be marked by them. For example, when a schoolman tells me "Aristotle has said it," all I conceive he means by it is to dispose me to embrace his opinion with the deference and submission which custom has annexed to that name. And this effect is often so instantly produced in the minds of those who are accustomed to resign their judgment to authority of that philosopher, as it is impossible any idea either of his person, writings, or reputation should go before [Note.]. Innumerable examples of this kind may be given, but why should I insist on those things which every one's experience will, I doubt not, plentifully suggest unto him?

20. SOME OF THE PURPOSES OF LANGUAGE.--Moreover, the way we share ideas through words isn't the main and only purpose of language, as is often believed. There are other purposes, such as stirring up emotions, encouraging or discouraging certain actions, or putting us in a specific state of mind—of which the former purpose is often only a minor point and sometimes completely ignored when it can be achieved without it, which frequently happens in everyday language use. I urge the reader to think about whether it doesn't often occur, both when listening to or reading conversations, that feelings of fear, love, hatred, admiration, disdain, and similar emotions arise right away upon hearing certain words, without any ideas coming in between. At first, the words might have sparked ideas that appropriately led to those emotions; however, if I'm not mistaken, it will likely be clear that when language becomes familiar, hearing the sounds or seeing the letters often directly triggers those emotions without the ideas that initially used to precede them. Can we not feel affected by the promise of a GOOD THING, even if we have no idea what it is? Or isn't being threatened with danger enough to trigger fear, even if we don't think about any specific threat to ourselves or form a general idea of danger? If anyone adds even a little personal reflection to what has been said, I believe it will clearly show that general terms are often used correctly in language without the speaker intending for them to bring up ideas in their own mind that they want to evoke in the listener’s mind. Even proper names don’t always seem to be used with the purpose of bringing to our minds the ideas of those specific individuals they represent. For instance, when someone tells me, "Aristotle said this," I think they mainly mean to lead me to accept their opinion with the respect and submission that comes with that name. This effect can often happen so quickly in those who usually defer their judgment to the authority of that philosopher that it's hard for any idea about his personality, writings, or reputation to come to mind first [Note.]. Countless examples of this kind can be given, but why should I dwell on things that I’m sure everyone’s own experience recognizes?

[Note: "So close and immediate a connection may custom establish betwixt the very word ARISTOTLE, and the motions of assent and reverence in the minds of some men."--Edit 1710.]

[Note: "A connection so close and immediate can be established by tradition between the very word ARISTOTLE and the feelings of agreement and respect in the minds of some people."--Edit 1710.]

21. CAUTION IN THE USE OF LANGUAGE NECESSARY.--We have, I think, shown the impossibility of ABSTRACT IDEAS. We have considered what has been said for them by their ablest patrons; and endeavored to show they are of no use for those ends to which they are thought necessary. And lastly, we have traced them to the source from whence they flow, which appears evidently to be language.--It cannot be denied that words are of excellent use, in that by their means all that stock of knowledge which has been purchased by the joint labours of inquisitive men in all ages and nations may be drawn into the view and made the possession of one single person. But at the same time it must be owned that most parts of knowledge have been strangely perplexed and darkened by the abuse of words, and general ways of speech wherein they are delivered.[Note 1.] Since therefore words are so apt to impose on the understanding[Note 2.], whatever ideas I consider, I shall endeavour to take them bare and naked into my view, keeping out of my thoughts so far as I am able, those names which long and constant use has so strictly united with them; from which I may expect to derive the following advantages:

21. CAUTION IN THE USE OF LANGUAGE NECESSARY.--I believe we’ve demonstrated the impossibility of ABSTRACT IDEAS. We’ve looked at what the most skilled supporters have said about them and tried to show that they’re not useful for the purposes we assume they are needed. Finally, we’ve traced them back to their source, which clearly seems to be language. There’s no denying that words are incredibly useful because they allow us to access the wealth of knowledge gathered by curious thinkers throughout history and across cultures. However, we must also acknowledge that many areas of knowledge have been strangely confused and obscured by the misuse of words and the general ways they are expressed. Since words can easily mislead our understanding, whenever I reflect on any ideas, I will strive to examine them in their purest form, keeping out of my thoughts, as much as possible, those labels that long-standing use has so closely linked to them; from this, I expect to gain the following advantages:

[Note 1: "That it may almost be made a question, whether language has contributed more to the hindrance or advancement of the sciences."--Edit 1710.]

[Note 1: "It can almost be questioned whether language has done more to hinder or promote the sciences."--Edit 1710.]

[Note 2: "I am resolved in my inquiries to make as little use of them as possibly I can."--Edit 1710.]

[Note 2: "I'm determined to rely on them as little as I can."--Edit 1710.]

22. FIRST, I shall be sure to get clear of all controversies PURELY VERBAL--the springing up of which weeds in almost all the sciences has been a main hindrance to the growth of true and sound knowledge. SECONDLY, this seems to be a sure way to extricate myself out of that fine and subtle net of ABSTRACT IDEAS which has so miserably perplexed and entangled the minds of men; and that with this peculiar circumstance, that by how much the finer and more curious was the wit of any man, by so much the deeper was he likely to be ensnared and faster held therein. THIRDLY, so long as I confine my thoughts to my own ideas divested of words, I do not see how I can easily be mistaken. The objects I consider, I clearly and adequately know. I cannot be deceived in thinking I have an idea which I have not. It is not possible for me to imagine that any of my own ideas are alike or unlike that are not truly so. To discern the agreements or disagreements there are between my ideas, to see what ideas are included in any compound idea and what not, there is nothing more requisite than an attentive perception of what passes in my own understanding.

22. FIRST, I will make sure to avoid all purely verbal controversies, which often arise and have been a major obstacle to the growth of true and sound knowledge in almost all sciences. SECONDLY, this seems like a reliable way to free myself from the complex and abstract ideas that have confused and entangled people's minds so badly; and notably, the more clever and curious a person is, the more likely they are to get trapped and held fast in those ideas. THIRDLY, as long as I focus on my own thoughts stripped of words, I don't see how I could easily be mistaken. I clearly and adequately understand the objects I consider. I can't be fooled into thinking I have an idea that I don't actually have. It's impossible for me to believe that any of my own ideas could be similar or different if they truly aren't. To recognize the agreements or disagreements between my ideas, and to see which ideas are part of any compound idea and which are not, all I need is to carefully observe what happens in my own understanding.

23. But the attainment of all THESE ADVANTAGES doth PRESUPPOSE AN ENTIRE DELIVERANCE FROM THE DECEPTION OF WORDS, which I dare hardly promise myself; so difficult a thing it is to dissolve an union so early begun, and confirmed by so long a habit as that betwixt words and ideas. Which difficulty seems to have been very much increased by the doctrine of ABSTRACTION. For, so long as men thought abstract ideas were annexed to their words, it doth not seem strange that they should use words for ideas--it being found an impracticable thing to lay aside the word, and RETAIN THE ABSTRACT IDEA IN THE MIND, WHICH IN ITSELF WAS PERFECTLY INCONCEIVABLE. This seems to me the principal cause why those men who have so emphatically recommended to others the laying aside all use of words in their meditations, and contemplating their bare ideas, have yet failed to perform it themselves. Of late many have been very sensible of the absurd opinions and insignificant disputes which grow out of the abuse of words. And, in order to remedy these evils, they advise well, that we attend to the ideas signified, and draw off our attention from the words which signify them. But, how good soever this advice may be they have given others, it is plain they could not have a due regard to it themselves, so long as they thought the only immediate use of words was to signify ideas, and that the immediate signification of every general name was a DETERMINATE ABSTRACT IDEA.

23. But achieving all these advantages assumes a complete escape from the deception of words, which I can scarcely promise myself; it’s so challenging to break a bond that has started early and been reinforced by such a long habit between words and ideas. This difficulty seems to have been greatly worsened by the concept of abstraction. As long as people believed that abstract ideas were tied to their words, it didn’t seem strange for them to use words for ideas—it being an impossible task to set aside the word while keeping the abstract idea in the mind, which was in itself completely inconceivable. This seems to me the main reason why those who have strongly encouraged others to abandon all use of words in their thoughts and focus on their pure ideas have still struggled to do so themselves. Recently, many have become aware of the absurd beliefs and pointless arguments that stem from the misuse of words. To address these issues, they rightly suggest that we focus on the ideas represented and shift our attention away from the words that signify them. However good this advice may be for others, it’s clear that they couldn’t fully apply it themselves as long as they believed the only immediate role of words was to signify ideas, and that the direct meaning of every general name was a specific abstract idea.

24. But, THESE BEING KNOWN TO BE MISTAKES, A MAN MAY with greater ease PREVENT HIS BEING IMPOSED ON BY WORDS. He that knows he has no other than particular ideas, will not puzzle himself in vain to find out and conceive the abstract idea annexed to any name. And he that knows names do not always stand for ideas will spare himself the labour of looking for ideas where there are none to be had. It were, therefore, to be wished that everyone would use his utmost endeavours to obtain a clear view of the ideas he would consider, separating from them all that dress and incumbrance of words which so much contribute to blind the judgment and divide the attention. In vain do we extend our view into the heavens and pry into the entrails of the earth, in vain do we consult the writings of learned men and trace the dark footsteps of antiquity--we need only draw the curtain of words, to hold the fairest tree of knowledge, whose fruit is excellent, and within the reach of our hand.

24. But knowing these are mistakes makes it easier for a person to avoid being misled by words. Someone who understands they only have specific ideas won't bother trying to find or think of an abstract idea connected to any name. And someone who realizes that names don’t always represent ideas will save themselves the effort of searching for ideas where there aren’t any. It would be ideal if everyone worked hard to gain a clear understanding of the ideas they want to consider, stripping away the clutter and complexities of language that often blind judgment and distract attention. There's no point in looking up to the heavens or digging deep into the earth, and it’s pointless to study the works of learned individuals or follow the obscure trails of the past—we just need to pull back the curtain of words to grasp the most beautiful tree of knowledge, whose fruit is excellent and within our reach.

25. Unless we take care TO CLEAR THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF KNOWLEDGE FROM THE embarras and DELUSION OF WORDS, we may make infinite reasonings upon them to no purpose; we may draw consequences from consequences, and be never the wiser. The farther we go, we shall only lose ourselves the more irrecoverably, and be the deeper entangled in difficulties and mistakes. Whoever therefore designs to read the following sheets, I entreat him to make my words the occasion of his own thinking, and endeavour to attain the same train of thoughts in reading that I had in writing them. By this means it will be easy for him to discover the truth or falsity of what I say. He will be out of all danger of being deceived by my words, and I do not see how he can be led into an error by considering his own naked, undisguised ideas.

25. Unless we take the time to clarify the basic principles of knowledge from the confusion and misinterpretation of words, we could spend forever reasoning about them without getting anywhere; we might draw conclusions from conclusions and still not understand. The further we go, the more lost we will become, becoming even more stuck in difficulties and mistakes. Whoever plans to read the following pages, I ask you to use my words as a starting point for your own thoughts and try to follow the same line of reasoning I had while writing them. This way, it will be easy for you to determine the truth or falsehood of what I say. You will avoid the risk of being misled by my words, and I don't see how you could be mistaken by examining your own clear, straightforward ideas.




OF THE PRINCIPLES OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE

1. OBJECTS OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE.--It is evident to any one who takes a survey of the objects of human knowledge, that they are either IDEAS actually imprinted on the senses; or else such as are perceived by attending to the passions and operations of the mind; or lastly, ideas formed by help of memory and imagination--either compounding, dividing, or barely representing those originally perceived in the aforesaid ways. By sight I have the ideas of light and colours, with their several degrees and variations. By touch I perceive hard and soft, heat and cold, motion and resistance, and of all these more and less either as to quantity or degree. Smelling furnishes me with odours; the palate with tastes; and hearing conveys sounds to the mind in all their variety of tone and composition. And as several of these are observed to accompany each other, they come to be marked by one name, and so to be reputed as one thing. Thus, for example a certain colour, taste, smell, figure and consistence having been observed to go together, are accounted one distinct thing, signified by the name APPLE. Other collections of ideas constitute a stone, a tree, a book, and the like sensible things--which as they are pleasing or disagreeable excite the passions of love, hatred, joy, grief, and so forth.

1. OBJECTS OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE.--It's clear to anyone who looks at the objects of human knowledge that they fall into three categories: IDEAS that are directly experienced through the senses, those that arise from reflecting on our feelings and mental processes, and finally, ideas created through memory and imagination—either by combining, breaking down, or simply representing those initially perceived through the above methods. Through sight, I get ideas of light and colors, along with their various shades and differences. Through touch, I sense hardness and softness, heat and cold, movement and resistance, and I can perceive all of these in varying quantities or degrees. Smell gives me different scents; taste provides flavors; and hearing delivers sounds to my mind in all their diverse tones and combinations. As several of these are seen to occur together, they end up being labeled with a single name, thus regarded as one entity. For instance, a specific color, taste, smell, shape, and texture that are observed together are recognized as one distinct item referred to as an APPLE. Other combinations of ideas form a stone, a tree, a book, and similar tangible things—which, whether pleasant or unpleasant, stir up feelings of love, hatred, joy, grief, and so on.

2. MIND--SPIRIT--SOUL.--But, besides all that endless variety of ideas or objects of knowledge, there is likewise something which knows or perceives them, and exercises divers operations, as willing, imagining, remembering, about them. This perceiving, active being is what I call MIND, SPIRIT, SOUL, or MYSELF. By which words I do not denote any one of my ideas, but a thing entirely distinct from them, WHEREIN THEY EXIST, or, which is the same thing, whereby they are perceived--for the existence of an idea consists in being perceived.

2. MIND--SPIRIT--SOUL.--But, beyond all the endless variety of ideas or things to know, there’s also something that knows or perceives them, and carries out different activities like wanting, imagining, and remembering regarding them. This perceiving, active entity is what I refer to as MIND, SPIRIT, SOUL, or MYSELF. These terms don’t refer to any of my ideas, but to something completely separate from them, IN WHICH THEY EXIST, or, in other words, by which they are perceived—because an idea's existence is tied to being perceived.

3. HOW FAR THE ASSENT OF THE VULGAR CONCEDED.--That neither our thoughts, nor passions, nor ideas formed by the imagination, exist WITHOUT the mind, is what EVERYBODY WILL ALLOW. And it seems no less evident that the various sensations or ideas imprinted on the sense, however blended or combined together (that is, whatever objects they compose), cannot exist otherwise than IN a mind perceiving them. I think an intuitive knowledge may be obtained of this by any one that shall attend to WHAT IS MEANT BY THE TERM EXIST, when applied to sensible things. The table I write on I say exists, that is, I see and feel it; and if I were out of my study I should say it existed--meaning thereby that if I was in my study I might perceive it, or that some other spirit actually does perceive it.[Note.] There was an odour, that is, it was smelt; there was a sound, that is, it was heard; a colour or figure, and it was perceived by sight or touch. This is all that I can understand by these and the like expressions. For as to what is said of the absolute existence of unthinking things without any relation to their being perceived, that seems perfectly unintelligible. Their ESSE is PERCIPI, nor is it possible they should have any existence out of the minds or thinking things which perceive them.

3. HOW FAR THE ASSENT OF THE VULGAR CONCEDED.--Everyone agrees that our thoughts, feelings, and imaginings don’t exist without the mind. It also seems clear that various sensations or ideas that we perceive, no matter how they are mixed or combined (that is, whatever objects they form), can only exist in a mind that is experiencing them. I believe anyone who considers what it means for something to EXIST when referring to tangible things can intuitively understand this. The table I’m writing on exists; I can see and feel it. If I were out of my study, I would still say it exists, implying that if I were in my study, I could perceive it, or that some other person actually does perceive it. [Note.] There was an odor, which means it was smelled; there was a sound, which means it was heard; a color or shape, which means it was seen or touched. This is all that I understand from these kinds of statements. As for claims about the absolute existence of things that don’t think, independent of being perceived, that seems completely nonsensical. Their EXISTENCE is to be PERCEIVED, and it’s impossible for them to exist outside the minds or thinking beings that perceive them.

[Note: First argument in support of the author's theory.]

[Note: First argument in support of the author's theory.]

4. THE VULGAR OPINION INVOLVES A CONTRADICTION.--It is indeed an opinion STRANGELY prevailing amongst men, that houses, mountains, rivers, and in a word all sensible objects, have an existence, natural or real, distinct from their being perceived by the understanding. But, with how great an assurance and acquiescence soever this principle may be entertained in the world, yet whoever shall find in his heart to call it in question may, if I mistake not, perceive it to involve a manifest contradiction. For, what are the fore-mentioned objects but the things we perceive by sense? and what do we PERCEIVE BESIDES OUR OWN IDEAS OR SENSATIONS? and is it not plainly repugnant that any one of these, or any combination of them, should exist unperceived?

4. THE COMMON VIEW IS CONTRADICTORY.--There’s a strangely widespread belief among people that houses, mountains, rivers, and basically all tangible things exist in a natural or real way, separate from being perceived by our minds. However confidently this idea may be accepted in society, anyone who dares to question it will likely see that it leads to a clear contradiction. What are these objects, after all, but the things we sense? And what do we PERCEIVE OTHER THAN OUR OWN IDEAS OR SENSATIONS? Isn’t it obviously contradictory for any of these, or any combination of them, to exist without being perceived?

5. CAUSE OF THIS PREVALENT ERROR.--If we thoroughly examine this tenet it will, perhaps, be found at bottom to depend on the doctrine of ABSTRACT IDEAS. For can there be a nicer strain of abstraction than to distinguish the existence of sensible objects from their being perceived, so as to conceive them existing unperceived? Light and colours, heat and cold, extension and figures--in a word the things we see and feel--what are they but so many sensations, notions, ideas, or impressions on the sense? and is it possible to separate, even in thought, any of these from perception? For my part, I might as easily divide a thing from itself. I may, indeed, divide in my thoughts, or conceive apart from each other, those things which, perhaps I never perceived by sense so divided. Thus, I imagine the trunk of a human body without the limbs, or conceive the smell of a rose without thinking on the rose itself. So far, I will not deny, I can abstract--if that may properly be called ABSTRACTION which extends only to the conceiving separately such objects as it is possible may really exist or be actually perceived asunder. But my conceiving or imagining power does not extend beyond the possibility of real existence or perception. Hence, as it is impossible for me to see or feel anything without an actual sensation of that thing, so is it impossible for me to conceive in my thoughts any sensible thing or object distinct from the sensation or perception of it.[Note.]

5. CAUSE OF THIS PREVALENT ERROR.--If we take a close look at this belief, we might find that it fundamentally relies on the idea of ABSTRACT IDEAS. Is there a more refined form of abstraction than distinguishing the existence of physical objects from being perceived, to the point of imagining them existing without being perceived? Light and colors, heat and cold, shapes and sizes—essentially, the things we see and feel—what are they if not a collection of sensations, concepts, ideas, or impressions on our senses? And is it possible to separate any of these from perception, even in thought? For me, that would be as easy as trying to separate something from itself. I can, of course, differentiate in my thoughts or imagine those things that I may never have perceived as separate. For example, I might picture the trunk of a human body without the limbs, or think of the smell of a rose without considering the rose itself. I won’t deny that I can abstract—if we call ABSTRACTION the ability to conceive separately those objects that might really exist or be perceived apart. However, my imagination doesn't reach beyond what could realistically exist or be perceived. Thus, just as it’s impossible for me to see or feel anything without having a real sensation of it, it is also impossible for me to conceive in my thoughts any sensory thing or object that is distinct from the sensation or perception of it.[Note.]

[Note: "In truth the object and the sensation are the same thing, and cannot therefore be abstracted from each other--Edit 1710."]

[Note: "Actually, the object and the sensation are the same thing, and therefore cannot be separated from each other--Edit 1710."]

6. Some truths there are so near and obvious to the mind that a man need only open his eyes to see them. Such I take this important one to be, viz., that all the choir of heaven and furniture of the earth, in a word all those bodies which compose the mighty frame of the world, have not any subsistence without a mind, that their BEING (ESSE) is to be perceived or known; that consequently so long as they are not actually perceived by me, or do not exist in my mind or that of any other CREATED SPIRIT, they must either have no existence at all, OR ELSE SUBSIST IN THE MIND OF SOME ETERNAL SPIRIT--it being perfectly unintelligible, and involving all the absurdity of abstraction, to attribute to any single part of them an existence independent of a spirit [Note.]. To be convinced of which, the reader need only reflect, and try to separate in his own thoughts the being of a sensible thing from its being perceived.

6. Some truths are so obvious that a person just needs to open their eyes to see them. I consider this important one to be that everything in the universe, including the heavenly choir and earthly furniture, all the things that make up the vast structure of the world, cannot exist without a mind. Their BEING (ESSE) comes from being perceived or known; therefore, as long as they are not actually perceived by me or existing in my mind or the mind of any other CREATED SPIRIT, they must either not exist at all or EXIST IN THE MIND OF SOME ETERNAL SPIRIT. It is completely unintelligible and absurd to think of any part of them existing independently of a spirit [Note.]. To understand this, the reader just needs to reflect and try to separate in their own thoughts the existence of a sensible thing from its being perceived.

[Note: "To make this appear with all the light and evidence of an axiom, it seems sufficient if I can but awaken the reflection of the reader, that he may take an impartial view of his own meaning, and in turn his thoughts upon the subject itself, free and disengaged from all embarrass of words and prepossession in favour of received mistakes."--Edit 1710]

[Note: "To make this clear with all the clarity and certainty of a basic truth, I just need to prompt the reader to reflect so they can take an unbiased look at their own understanding and, in turn, their thoughts on the topic itself, free from any confusion of language and preconceived notions about common misconceptions."--Edit 1710]

7. SECOND ARGUMENT.[Note.]--From what has been said it follows there is NOT ANY OTHER SUBSTANCE THAN SPIRIT, or that which perceives. But, for the fuller proof of this point, let it be considered the sensible qualities are colour, figure, motion, smell, taste, etc., i.e. the ideas perceived by sense. Now, for an idea to exist in an unperceiving thing is a manifest contradiction, for TO HAVE AN IDEA IS ALL ONE AS TO PERCEIVE; that therefore wherein colour, figure, and the like qualities exist must perceive them; hence it is clear there can be no UNTHINKING substance or SUBSTRATUM of those ideas.

7. SECOND ARGUMENT.[Note.]--From what has been discussed, it follows that there is NO OTHER SUBSTANCE THAN SPIRIT, or that which perceives. However, to provide stronger evidence for this point, let's consider that the qualities we can sense include color, shape, movement, smell, taste, etc., meaning the ideas we experience through our senses. Now, for an idea to exist in something that doesn't perceive is a clear contradiction, because TO HAVE AN IDEA IS THE SAME AS TO PERCEIVE; therefore, whatever has color, shape, and similar qualities must be capable of perception; thus, it's evident there can be no UNTHINKING substance or UNDERLYING SOURCE of those ideas.

[Note: Vide sect. iii. and xxv.]

[Note: Vide sect. iii. and xxv.]

8. OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--But, say you, though the ideas themselves do not exist without the mind, yet there may be things LIKE them, whereof they are copies or resemblances, which things exist without the mind in an unthinking substance. I ANSWER, an idea can be like nothing but an idea; a colour or figure can be like nothing but another colour or figure. If we look but never so little into our thoughts, we shall find it impossible for us to conceive a likeness except only between our ideas. Again, I ask whether those supposed originals or external things, of which our ideas are the pictures or representations, be themselves perceivable or no? If they are, THEN THEY ARE IDEAS and we have gained our point; but if you say they are not, I appeal to any one whether it be sense to assert a colour is like something which is invisible; hard or soft, like something which is intangible; and so of the rest.

8. OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--But, you might say, even though ideas don’t exist without the mind, there could be things LIKE them, which are copies or resemblances and exist independently in a non-thinking substance. I ANSWER, an idea can only resemble another idea; a color or shape can only be like another color or shape. If we examine our thoughts even a little, we’ll find it impossible to conceive a likeness except between our ideas. Again, I ask whether those supposed originals or external things, of which our ideas are the pictures or representations, are themselves perceivable or not? If they are, THEN THEY ARE IDEAS and we’ve made our point; but if you say they are not, I challenge anyone to claim it makes sense to say a color resembles something that is invisible; that something hard or soft is similar to something that can’t be touched; and so on.

9. THE PHILOSOPHICAL NOTION OF MATTER INVOLVES A CONTRADICTION.--Some there are who make a DISTINCTION betwixt PRIMARY and SECONDARY qualities. By the former they mean extension, figure, motion, rest, solidity or impenetrability, and number; by the latter they denote all other sensible qualities, as colours, sounds, tastes, and so forth. The ideas we have of these they acknowledge not to be the resemblances of anything existing without the mind, or unperceived, but they will have our ideas of the primary qualities to be patterns or images of things which exist without the mind, in an unthinking substance which they call MATTER. By MATTER, therefore, we are to understand an inert, senseless substance, in which extension, figure, and motion DO ACTUALLY SUBSIST. But it is evident from what we have already shown, that extension, figure, and motion are ONLY IDEAS EXISTING IN THE MIND, and that an idea can be like nothing but another idea, and that consequently neither they nor their archetypes can exist in an UNPERCEIVING substance. Hence, it is plain that the very notion of what is called MATTER or CORPOREAL SUBSTANCE, involves a contradiction in it.[Note.]

9. THE PHILOSOPHICAL NOTION OF MATTER INVOLVES A CONTRADICTION.--Some people distinguish between PRIMARY and SECONDARY qualities. The former refers to extension, shape, motion, rest, solidity or impenetrability, and number; the latter includes all other sensory qualities, like colors, sounds, tastes, and so on. They admit that our ideas of these secondary qualities do not resemble anything existing outside of our mind or unperceived, but they insist that our ideas of primary qualities are patterns or images of things that exist independently, in a substance they call MATTER. Thus, we should understand MATTER as an inert, senseless substance in which extension, shape, and motion actually exist. However, it’s clear from what we’ve already demonstrated that extension, shape, and motion are ONLY IDEAS EXISTING IN THE MIND, and an idea can only resemble another idea; consequently, neither they nor their archetypes can exist in an UNPERCEIVING substance. Therefore, it is evident that the very concept of what is called MATTER or CORPOREAL SUBSTANCE involves a contradiction. [Note.]

[Note: "Insomuch that I should not think it necessary to spend more time in exposing its absurdity. But because the tenet of the existence of matter seems to have taken so deep a root in the minds of philosophers, and draws after it so many ill consequences, I choose rather to be thought prolix and tedious, than omit anything that might conduce to the full discovery and extirpation of the prejudice."--Edit 1710.]

[Note: "So much so that I don't think it's necessary to spend more time pointing out its absurdity. But since the belief in the existence of matter seems to be so deeply entrenched in the minds of philosophers and leads to many negative consequences, I would rather be considered lengthy and boring than leave out anything that could help fully uncover and eliminate this bias."--Edit 1710.]

10. ARGUMENTUM AD HOMINEM.--They who assert that figure, motion, and the rest of the primary or original qualities do exist without the mind in unthinking substances, do at the same time acknowledge that colours, sounds, heat cold, and suchlike secondary qualities, do not--which they tell us are sensations existing IN THE MIND ALONE, that depend on and are occasioned by the different size, texture, and motion of the minute particles of matter. This they take for an undoubted truth, which they can demonstrate beyond all exception. Now, if it be certain that those original qualities ARE INSEPARABLY UNITED WITH THE OTHER SENSIBLE QUALITIES, and not, even in thought, capable of being abstracted from them, it plainly follows that they exist only in the mind. But I desire any one to reflect and try whether he can, by any abstraction of thought, conceive the extension and motion of a body without all other sensible qualities. For my own part, I see evidently that it is not in my power to frame an idea of a body extended and moving, but I must withal give it some colour or other sensible quality which is ACKNOWLEDGED to exist only in the mind. In short, extension, figure, and motion, abstracted from all other qualities, are inconceivable. Where therefore the other sensible qualities are, there must these be also, to wit, in the mind and nowhere else.

10. ARGUMENTUM AD HOMINEM.--Those who claim that primary qualities like shape, motion, and the rest exist independently of the mind in non-thinking substances also acknowledge that colors, sounds, heat, cold, and similar secondary qualities do not—these are sensations that exist ONLY IN THE MIND, which depend on and are caused by the varying size, texture, and motion of tiny particles of matter. They consider this an undeniable truth that they can prove without exception. Now, if it’s certain that those original qualities ARE INSEPARABLY LINKED TO OTHER SENSIBLE QUALITIES and cannot even be thought of separately from them, it clearly follows that they exist only in the mind. But I challenge anyone to reflect and see if they can, through any kind of mental abstraction, imagine the extension and motion of an object without all other sensible qualities. As for me, I clearly see that I cannot form an idea of an extended and moving object without also assigning it some color or other sensible quality that is ACKNOWLEDGED to exist only in the mind. In short, extension, shape, and motion, when separated from all other qualities, are unimaginable. Therefore, wherever the other sensible qualities are, these original qualities must also be; specifically, in the mind and nowhere else.

11. A SECOND ARGUMENT AD HOMINEM.--Again, GREAT and SMALL, SWIFT and SLOW, ARE ALLOWED TO EXIST NOWHERE WITHOUT THE MIND, being entirely RELATIVE, and changing as the frame or position of the organs of sense varies. The extension therefore which exists without the mind is neither great nor small, the motion neither swift nor slow, that is, they are nothing at all. But, say you, they are extension in general, and motion in general: thus we see how much the tenet of extended movable substances existing without the mind depends on the strange doctrine of ABSTRACT IDEAS. And here I cannot but remark how nearly the vague and indeterminate description of Matter or corporeal substance, which the modern philosophers are run into by their own principles, resembles that antiquated and so much ridiculed notion of MATERIA PRIMA, to be met with in Aristotle and his followers. Without extension solidity cannot be conceived; since therefore it has been shown that extension exists not in an unthinking substance, the same must also be true of solidity.

11. A SECOND ARGUMENT AD HOMINEM.--Again, BIG and SMALL, FAST and SLOW, CAN ONLY EXIST IN THE MIND, as they are completely RELATIVE and change with the position or function of our senses. Therefore, the extension that exists outside of the mind is neither big nor small, the motion neither fast nor slow; in other words, they are nothing at all. But you argue that they are general extension and general motion: this shows how much the belief in extended movable substances existing outside the mind relies on the strange idea of ABSTRACT IDEAS. I can’t help but point out how closely the vague and unclear descriptions of Matter or physical substance that modern philosophers have fallen into due to their own principles resemble that outdated and often mocked notion of MATERIA PRIMA, found in Aristotle and his followers. Without extension, solidity can't be imagined; thus, since it's been shown that extension doesn't exist in an unthinking substance, the same must apply to solidity.

12. That NUMBER is entirely THE CREATURE OF THE MIND, even though the other qualities be allowed to exist without, will be evident to whoever considers that the same thing bears a different denomination of number as the mind views it with different respects. Thus, the same extension is one, or three, or thirty-six, according as the mind considers it with reference to a yard, a foot, or an inch. Number is so visibly relative, and dependent on men's understanding, that it is strange to think how any one should give it an absolute existence without the mind. We say one book, one page, one line, etc.; all these are equally units, though some contain several of the others. And in each instance, it is plain, the unit relates to some particular combination of ideas arbitrarily put together by the mind.

12. That NUMBER is completely A PRODUCT OF THE MIND, even if other qualities can exist independently, will be clear to anyone who thinks about the fact that the same thing can be assigned different numbers, depending on how the mind views it. So, the same measurement can be one, three, or thirty-six, based on whether the mind is considering it in terms of yards, feet, or inches. Number is clearly relative and relies on human perception, making it surprising that anyone would consider it to have an existence outside of the mind. We say one book, one page, one line, etc.; all these are individual units, even though some contain multiple units of the others. And in each case, it’s obvious that the unit refers to a specific arrangement of ideas that the mind has assembled in a certain way.

13. UNITY I know some will have to be A SIMPLE OR UNCOMPOUNDED IDEA, accompanying all other ideas into the mind. That I have any such idea answering the word UNITY I do not find; and if I had, methinks I could not miss finding it: on the contrary, it should be the most familiar to my understanding, since it is said to accompany all other ideas, and to be perceived by all the ways of sensation and reflexion. To say no more, it is an ABSTRACT IDEA.

13. UNITY I know some will consider it a SIMPLE OR UNCOMPOUNDED IDEA, accompanying all other ideas in the mind. I don’t find that I have any idea that fits the term UNITY; and if I did, I think I wouldn't overlook it: on the contrary, it should be the most familiar concept to me, since it’s said to accompany all other ideas and be perceived through all forms of sensation and reflection. To say no more, it is an ABSTRACT IDEA.

14. A THIRD ARGUMENT AD HOMINEM.--I shall farther add, that, after the same manner as modern philosophers prove certain sensible qualities to have no existence in Matter, or without the mind, the same thing may be likewise proved of all other sensible qualities whatsoever. Thus, for instance, it is said that heat and cold are affections only of the mind, and not at all patterns of real beings, existing in the corporeal substances which excite them, for that the same body which appears cold to one hand seems warm to another. Now, why may we not as well argue that figure and extension are not patterns or resemblances of qualities existing in Matter, because to the same eye at different stations, or eyes of a different texture at the same station, they appear various, and cannot therefore be the images of anything SETTLED AND DETERMINATE WITHOUT THE MIND? Again, it is proved that SWEETNESS is not really in the sapid thing, because the thing remaining unaltered the sweetness is changed into bitter, as in case of a fever or otherwise vitiated palate. Is it not as reasonable to say that MOTION is not without the mind, since if the succession of ideas in the mind become swifter, the motion, it is acknowledged, shall appear slower without any alteration in any external object?

14. A THIRD ARGUMENT AD HOMINEM.--I will add that, just as modern philosophers demonstrate that certain sensible qualities don't exist in Matter or outside the mind, the same can be shown for all other sensible qualities. For example, it’s said that heat and cold are only feelings of the mind and not actual properties of the physical substances that cause them, since the same object might feel cold to one hand and warm to another. So, why can’t we argue that shape and size aren’t actual qualities in Matter, because they can appear different to the same eye from different distances, or to eyes of different textures from the same distance, and therefore can't be the images of anything FIXED AND DEFINITE WITHOUT THE MIND? Furthermore, it's shown that SWEETNESS isn’t actually in the tasty object, because the object remains the same while sweetness can change to bitterness, like during a fever or with a damaged sense of taste. Is it not just as reasonable to say that MOTION doesn’t exist without the mind, since when the flow of ideas in the mind speeds up, motion appears slower without any change to the external object?

15. NOT CONCLUSIVE AS TO EXTENSION.--In short, let any one consider those arguments which are thought manifestly to prove that colours and taste exist only in the mind, and he shall find they may with equal force be brought to prove the same thing of extension, figure, and motion. Though it must be confessed this method of arguing does not so much prove that there is no extension or colour in an outward object, as that we do not know by SENSE which is the TRUE extension or colour of the object. But the arguments foregoing plainly show it to be impossible that any colour or extension at all, or other sensible quality whatsoever, should exist in an UNTHINKING subject without the mind, or in truth, that there should be any such thing as an outward object.

15. NOT CONCLUSIVE AS TO EXTENSION.--In short, anyone who considers the arguments that are clearly meant to prove that colors and tastes exist only in the mind will find that the same arguments can be used with equal strength to prove the same thing about extension, shape, and motion. While it must be admitted that this way of arguing doesn't really prove that there is no extension or color in an outside object, it does show that we cannot know through SENSE what the TRUE extension or color of the object is. However, the previous arguments clearly indicate that it is impossible for any color, extension, or other sensory quality to exist in a UNTHINKING subject without the mind, or in fact, that there could be any such thing as an outside object.

16. But let us examine a little the received opinion.--It is said EXTENSION is a MODE or accident OF MATTER, and that Matter is the SUBSTRATUM that supports it. Now I desire that you would explain to me what is meant by Matter's SUPPORTING extension. Say you, I have no idea of Matter and therefore cannot explain it. I answer, though you have no positive, yet, if you have any meaning at all, you must at least have a relative idea of Matter; though you know not what it is, yet you must be supposed to know what relation it bears to accidents, and what is meant by its supporting them. It is evident SUPPORT cannot here be taken in its usual or literal sense--as when we say that pillars support a building; in what sense therefore must it be taken? [Note.]

16. But let’s take a closer look at the common belief. It's said that EXTENSION is a MODE or characteristic OF MATTER, and that Matter is the FOUNDATION that supports it. Now, I’d like you to explain what it means for Matter to SUPPORT extension. You might say you have no idea what Matter is, so you can’t explain it. I respond that even if you don’t have a clear definition, if you have any understanding at all, you must at least have a relative idea of Matter; even if you don’t know what it is, you are expected to understand its relationship to characteristics and what is meant by it supporting them. Clearly, SUPPORT cannot be understood here in its usual or literal sense—like when we say that pillars support a building; so how should we interpret it? [Note.]

[Note: "For my part, I am not able to discover any sense at all that can be applicable to it."--Edit 1710.]

[Note: "As for me, I can't find any meaning in it at all."--Edit 1710.]

17. PHILOSOPHICAL MEANING OF "MATERIAL SUBSTANCE" DIVISIBLE INTO TWO PARTS.--If we inquire into what the most accurate philosophers declare themselves to mean by MATERIAL SUBSTANCE, we shall find them acknowledge they have no other meaning annexed to those sounds but the idea of BEING IN GENERAL, together WITH THE RELATIVE NOTION OF ITS SUPPORTING ACCIDENTS. The general idea of Being appeareth to me the most abstract and incomprehensible of all other; and as for its supporting accidents, this, as we have just now observed, cannot be understood in the common sense of those words; it must therefore be taken in some other sense, but what that is they do not explain. So that when I consider the TWO PARTS or branches which make the signification of the words MATERIAL SUBSTANCE, I am convinced there is no distinct meaning annexed to them. But why should we trouble ourselves any farther, in discussing this material SUBSTRATUM or support of figure and motion, and other sensible qualities? Does it not suppose they have an existence without the mind? And is not this a direct repugnancy, and altogether inconceivable?

17. PHILOSOPHICAL MEANING OF "MATERIAL SUBSTANCE" DIVISIBLE INTO TWO PARTS.--If we look into what the most precise philosophers say they mean by MATERIAL SUBSTANCE, we will find that they admit they have no other meaning tied to those terms except the idea of BEING IN GENERAL, ALONG WITH THE RELATED NOTION OF ITS SUPPORTING ACCIDENTS. The general idea of Being appears to me to be the most abstract and incomprehensible of all; and regarding its supporting accidents, this, as we just noted, cannot be understood in the usual sense of those words; it must therefore be taken in some other way, but they do not clarify what that is. So when I think about the TWO PARTS or branches that form the meaning of the words MATERIAL SUBSTANCE, I am convinced there is no distinct meaning associated with them. But why should we concern ourselves any further with discussing this material SUBSTRATUM or support of shape, motion, and other tangible qualities? Does it not suggest they exist independently of the mind? And isn't that a direct contradiction and entirely unimaginable?

18. THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL BODIES WANTS PROOF.--But, though it were possible that solid, figured, movable substances may exist without the mind, corresponding to the ideas we have of bodies, yet HOW IS IT POSSIBLE FOR US TO KNOW THIS? Either we must know it by sense or by reason. As for our senses, by them we have the knowledge ONLY OF OUR SENSATIONS, ideas, or those things that are immediately perceived by sense, call them what you will: but they do not inform us that things exist without the mind, or unperceived, like to those which are perceived. This the materialists themselves acknowledge. It remains therefore that if we have any knowledge at all of external things, it must be by REASON, inferring their existence from what is immediately perceived by sense. But what reason can induce us to believe the existence of bodies without the mind, from what we perceive, since the very patrons of Matter themselves do not pretend there is ANY NECESSARY CONNEXION BETWIXT THEM AND OUR IDEAS? I say it is granted on all hands (and what happens in dreams, phrensies, and the like, puts it beyond dispute) that IT IS POSSIBLE WE MIGHT BE AFFECTED WITH ALL THE IDEAS WE HAVE NOW, THOUGH THERE WERE NO BODIES EXISTING WITHOUT RESEMBLING THEM. Hence, it is evident the supposition of external bodies is not necessary for the producing our ideas; since it is granted they are produced sometimes, and might possibly be produced always in the same order, we see them in at present, without their concurrence.

18. THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL BODIES REQUIRES PROOF.--Even if it's possible that solid, shaped, movable substances exist outside of our minds that correspond to our ideas of bodies, HOW CAN WE KNOW THIS? We must know it either through our senses or through reasoning. Our senses only give us knowledge of OUR SENSATIONS, ideas, or those things that we perceive directly: they don’t tell us that things exist outside of our minds or unperceived, like those we can perceive. Even materialists acknowledge this. Therefore, if we have any knowledge of external things at all, it must be through REASON, inferring their existence from what we perceive directly. But what reason can support the belief in the existence of bodies outside the mind based on our perceptions, given that even the advocates of Matter do not claim there is ANY NECESSARY CONNECTION BETWEEN THEM AND OUR IDEAS? It is agreed by everyone (and what happens in dreams, madness, and similar experiences confirms this) that IT IS POSSIBLE FOR US TO HAVE ALL THE IDEAS WE HAVE NOW, EVEN IF THERE WERE NO BODIES EXISTING THAT RESEMBLE THEM. Thus, it is clear that the assumption of external bodies is not necessary for producing our ideas; it is accepted that they are sometimes produced and could potentially be produced always in the same order that we currently observe, without their involvement.

19. THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL BODIES AFFORDS NO EXPLICATION OF THE MANNER IN WHICH OUR IDEAS ARE PRODUCED.--But, though we might possibly have all our sensations without them, yet perhaps it may be thought EASIER to conceive and explain the MANNER of their production, by supposing external bodies in their likeness rather than otherwise; and so it might be at least probable there are such things as bodies that excite their ideas in our minds. But neither can this be said; for, though we give the materialists their external bodies, they by their own confession are never the nearer knowing how our ideas are produced; since they own themselves unable to comprehend in what manner BODY CAN ACT UPON SPIRIT, or how it is possible it should imprint any idea in the mind. Hence it is evident the production of ideas or sensations in our minds can be no reason why we should suppose Matter or corporeal substances, SINCE THAT IS ACKNOWLEDGED TO REMAIN EQUALLY INEXPLICABLE WITH OR WITHOUT THIS SUPPOSITION. If therefore it were possible for bodies to exist without the mind, yet to hold they do so, must needs be a very precarious opinion; since it is to suppose, without any reason at all, that God has created innumerable beings THAT ARE ENTIRELY USELESS, AND SERVE TO NO MANNER OF PURPOSE.

19. THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL OBJECTS DOES NOT EXPLAIN HOW OUR IDEAS ARE GENERATED.--While we might be able to experience all our sensations without them, it may seem EASIER to imagine and explain how they come about by assuming external objects that resemble them rather than the opposite; thus, it might at least seem likely that such things as objects exist that trigger ideas in our minds. However, that can't really be claimed; for even if we accept the materialists' external objects, they admit they still don’t understand how our ideas are formed. They confess they can't grasp how BODY CAN INFLUENCE SPIRIT, or how it could possibly leave any idea in the mind. Thus, it's clear that the creation of ideas or sensations in our minds doesn't justify the assumption of Matter or physical substances, since it’s acknowledged to remain equally UNEXPLAINED whether we keep this assumption or not. Therefore, even if it were possible for objects to exist without the mind, to claim they do would be a very shaky belief; because it would mean suggesting, with no justification at all, that God has created countless beings THAT ARE COMPLETELY USELESS AND SERVE NO PURPOSE WHATSOEVER.

20. DILEMMA.--In short, if there were external bodies, it is impossible we should ever come to know it; and if there were not, we might have the very same reasons to think there were that we have now. Suppose--what no one can deny possible--an intelligence without the help of external bodies, to be affected with the same train of sensations or ideas that you are, imprinted in the same order and with like vividness in his mind. I ask whether that intelligence has not all the reason to believe the existence of corporeal substances, represented by his ideas, and exciting them in his mind, that you can possibly have for believing the same thing? Of this there can be no question--which one consideration were enough to make any reasonable person suspect the strength of whatever arguments be may think himself to have, for the existence of bodies without the mind.

20. DILEMMA.--In short, if there were external things, it's impossible for us to ever know about them; and if there weren't, we might still have the same reasons to believe there were as we do now. Imagine—something no one can deny is possible—an intelligence that, without any external objects, experiences the same sensations or ideas that you do, arranged in the same order and with similar intensity in its mind. I ask whether that intelligence doesn't have just as much reason to believe in the existence of physical substances, represented by its ideas and stimulating them in its mind, as you have for believing the same thing. There’s no doubt about this—which is a point that should make any reasonable person question the strength of whatever arguments they might think they have for the existence of bodies outside the mind.

21. Were it necessary to add any FURTHER PROOF AGAINST THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER after what has been said, I could instance several of those errors and difficulties (not to mention impieties) which have sprung from that tenet. It has occasioned numberless controversies and disputes in philosophy, and not a few of far greater moment in religion. But I shall not enter into the detail of them in this place, as well because I think arguments A POSTERIORI are unnecessary for confirming what has been, if I mistake not, sufficiently demonstrated A PRIORI, as because I shall hereafter find occasion to speak somewhat of them.

21. If I needed to provide any more EVIDENCE AGAINST THE EXISTENCE OF matter after what has already been said, I could point out several errors and issues (not to mention offensive ideas) that have arisen from that belief. It has led to countless debates and arguments in philosophy, along with some even more significant ones in religion. However, I won’t go into detail about them here, both because I believe arguments BASED ON EXPERIENCE are unnecessary to support what has, if I'm not mistaken, been sufficiently proven through REASONING, and because I will have the opportunity to discuss them later.

22. I am afraid I have given cause to think I am needlessly prolix in handling this subject. For, to what purpose is it to dilate on that which may be demonstrated with the utmost evidence in a line or two, to any one that is capable of the least reflexion? It is but looking into your own thoughts, and so trying whether you can conceive it possible for a sound, or figure, or motion, or colour to exist without the mind or unperceived. This easy trial may perhaps make you see that what you contend for is a downright contradiction. Insomuch that I am content to put the whole upon this issue:--If you can but CONCEIVE it possible for one extended movable substance, or, in general, for any one idea, or anything like an idea, to exist otherwise than in a mind perceiving it, I shall readily give up the cause. And, as for all that COMPAGES of external bodies you contend for, I shall grant you its existence, THOUGH (1.) YOU CANNOT EITHER GIVE ME ANY REASON WHY YOU BELIEVE IT EXISTS [Vide sect. lviii.], OR (2.) ASSIGN ANY USE TO IT WHEN IT IS SUPPOSED TO EXIST [Vide sect. lx.]. I say, the bare possibility of your opinions being true shall pass for an argument that it is so. [Note: i.e. although your argument be deficient in the two requisites of an hypothesis.--Ed.]

22. I'm afraid I've given you reason to think I'm being unnecessarily long-winded about this topic. What's the point of going on and on about something that can be clearly demonstrated in a couple of sentences to anyone who is capable of a bit of reflection? You just need to think about your own thoughts and see if you can imagine that a sound, shape, movement, or color can exist without a mind or go unnoticed. This simple test might help you realize that what you're arguing for is a complete contradiction. So, I'm willing to put everything on the line for this: if you can even imagine that one extended movable substance, or any idea at all, could exist without being perceived by a mind, I'll gladly concede the argument. And as for all the external bodies you insist on, I’ll accept their existence, EVEN THOUGH (1.) YOU CANNOT PROVIDE ANY REASON WHY YOU BELIEVE THEY EXIST [See sect. lviii.], OR (2.) GIVE ANY PURPOSE FOR THEM IF THEY ARE SUPPOSED TO EXIST [See sect. lx.]. I mean, the mere possibility of your views being correct is not enough to count as a solid argument. [Note: i.e., although your argument lacks the two essential components of a hypothesis.--Ed.]

23. But, say you, surely there is nothing easier than for me to imagine trees, for instance, in a park, or books existing in a closet, and nobody by to perceive them. I answer, you may so, there is no difficulty in it; but what is all this, I beseech you, more than framing in your mind certain ideas which you call BOOKS and TREES, and the same time omitting to frame the idea of any one that may perceive them? BUT DO NOT YOU YOURSELF PERCEIVE OR THINK OF THEM ALL THE WHILE? This therefore is nothing to the purpose; it only shows you have the power of imagining or forming ideas in your mind: but it does not show that you can conceive it possible the objects of your thought may exist without the mind. To make out this, IT IS NECESSARY THAT YOU CONCEIVE THEM EXISTING UNCONCEIVED OR UNTHOUGHT OF, WHICH IS A MANIFEST REPUGNANCY. When we do our utmost to conceive the existence of external bodies, we are all the while only contemplating our own ideas. But the mind taking no notice of itself, is deluded to think it can and does conceive bodies existing unthought of or without the mind, though at the same time they are apprehended by or exist in itself. A little attention will discover to any one the truth and evidence of what is here said, and make it unnecessary to insist on any other proofs against the existence of material substance.

23. But, you might say, there's nothing easier than imagining trees in a park or books in a closet with no one around to see them. I answer, you can do that, and there’s no difficulty in it; but I ask you, isn’t this just creating certain ideas in your mind that you label BOOKS and TREES while ignoring the idea of someone who could perceive them? BUT DON'T YOU YOURSELF PERCEIVE OR THINK ABOUT THEM ALL ALONG? This doesn’t really address the issue; it just shows you have the ability to imagine or create ideas in your mind, but it doesn’t prove that you can believe these thoughts could exist without a mind. To really support this, YOU MUST CONCEIVE OF THEM EXISTING WITHOUT BEING CONCEIVED OR THOUGHT ABOUT, WHICH IS A CLEAR CONTRADICTION. When we try our hardest to conceive the existence of external objects, we are just reflecting on our own ideas. But since the mind doesn’t notice itself, it gets fooled into thinking it can and does conceive of objects existing without being thought of or without a mind, even though they are still being perceived or exist within it. A little reflection will reveal to anyone the truth and clarity of this statement and make it clear that no further evidence is needed against the existence of material substance.

24. THE ABSOLUTE EXISTENCE OF UNTHINKING THINGS ARE WORDS WITHOUT A MEANING.--It is very obvious, upon the least inquiry into our thoughts, to know whether it is possible for us to understand what is meant by the ABSOLUTE EXISTENCE OF SENSIBLE OBJECTS IN THEMSELVES, OR WITHOUT THE MIND. To me it is evident those words mark out either a direct contradiction, or else nothing at all. And to convince others of this, I know no readier or fairer way than to entreat they would calmly attend to their own thoughts; and if by this attention the emptiness or repugnancy of those expressions does appear, surely nothing more is requisite for the conviction. It is on this therefore that I insist, to wit, that the ABSOLUTE existence of unthinking things are words without a meaning, or which include a contradiction. This is what I repeat and inculcate, and earnestly recommend to the attentive thoughts of the reader.

24. THE ABSOLUTE EXISTENCE OF UNTHINKING THINGS ARE WORDS WITHOUT A MEANING.--It’s quite clear, with just a little reflection on our thoughts, to see whether we can understand what is meant by the ABSOLUTE EXISTENCE OF SENSIBLE OBJECTS IN THEMSELVES, OR WITHOUT THE MIND. To me, it’s obvious that those words either express a direct contradiction or signify nothing at all. To persuade others of this, I know no simpler or fairer way than to kindly ask them to calmly consider their own thoughts; and if, through this consideration, the emptiness or contradiction of those expressions becomes clear, surely nothing more is needed for conviction. This is what I emphasize: that the ABSOLUTE existence of unthinking things are words without a meaning, or which contain a contradiction. This is what I repeatedly stress and earnestly recommend to the thoughtful attention of the reader.

25. THIRD ARGUMENT.[Note: Vide sect. iii. and vii.]--REFUTATION OF LOCKE.--All our ideas, sensations, notions, or the things which we perceive, by whatsoever names they may be distinguished, are visibly inactive--there is nothing of power or agency included in them. So that ONE IDEA or object of thought CANNOT PRODUCE or make ANY ALTERATION IN ANOTHER. To be satisfied of the truth of this, there is nothing else requisite but a bare observation of our ideas. For, since they and every part of them exist only in the mind, it follows that there is nothing in them but what is perceived: but whoever shall attend to his ideas, whether of sense or reflexion, will not perceive in them any power or activity; there is, therefore, no such thing contained in them. A little attention will discover to us that the very being of an idea implies passiveness and inertness in it, insomuch that it is impossible for an idea to do anything, or, strictly speaking, to be the cause of anything: neither can it be the resemblance or pattern of any active being, as is evident from sect. 8. Whence it plainly follows that extension, figure, and motion cannot be the cause of our sensations. To say, therefore, that these are the effects of powers resulting from the configuration, number, motion, and size of corpuscles, must certainly be false. [Note: Vide sect. cii.]

25. THIRD ARGUMENT.[Note: See sections iii. and vii.]--REFUTATION OF LOCKE.--All our ideas, sensations, notions, or the things we perceive, regardless of what they're called, are clearly inactive—there's no power or agency in them. Therefore, ONE IDEA or object of thought CANNOT PRODUCE or cause ANY CHANGE IN ANOTHER. To understand this, all that’s needed is to simply observe our ideas. Since they and every part of them exist only in the mind, it follows that there’s nothing in them except what is perceived. However, anyone who pays attention to their ideas, whether from the senses or reflection, will not find any power or activity in them; thus, there is no such thing contained within them. A little focus will show us that the very nature of an idea implies passiveness and inactivity, making it impossible for an idea to do anything, or to be the cause of anything: neither can it represent or be the model of any active being, as is clear from section 8. Hence, it clearly follows that extension, shape, and motion cannot be the cause of our sensations. Therefore, saying that these are the results of powers arising from the arrangement, number, motion, and size of particles must certainly be incorrect. [Note: See section cii.]

26. CAUSE OF IDEAS.--We perceive a continual succession of ideas, some are anew excited, others are changed or totally disappear. There is therefore some cause of these ideas, whereon they depend, and which produces and changes them. That this cause cannot be any quality or idea or combination of ideas, is clear from the preceding section. It must therefore be a substance; but it has been shown that there is no corporeal or material substance: it remains therefore that the CAUSE OF IDEAS is an incorporeal active substance or Spirit.

26. CAUSE OF IDEAS.--We continually experience a flow of ideas; some are newly sparked, while others change or completely fade away. So, there must be a cause for these ideas, something they rely on that creates and alters them. It's clear from the previous section that this cause can't be any quality, idea, or combination of ideas. Therefore, it must be a substance; however, it has been established that there is no physical or material substance. Hence, the CAUSE OF IDEAS must be an incorporeal active substance or Spirit.

27. NO IDEA OF SPIRIT.--A spirit is one simple, undivided, active being--as it perceives ideas it is called the UNDERSTANDING, and as it produces or otherwise operates about them it is called the WILL. Hence there can be no idea formed of a soul or spirit; for all ideas whatever, being passive and inert (vide sect. 25), they cannot represent unto us, by way of image or LIKENESS, that which acts. A little attention will make it plain to any one, that to have an idea which shall be like that active principle of motion and change of ideas is absolutely impossible. Such is the nature of SPIRIT, or that which acts, that it cannot be of itself perceived, BUT ONLY BY THE EFFECTS WHICH IT PRODUCETH. If any man shall doubt of the truth of what is here delivered, let him but reflect and try if he can frame the idea of any power or active being, and whether he has ideas of two principal powers, marked by the names WILL and UNDERSTANDING, distinct from each other as well as from a third idea of Substance or Being in general, with a relative notion of its supporting or being the subject of the aforesaid powers--which is signified by the name SOUL or SPIRIT. This is what some hold; but, so far as I can see, the words WILL [Note: "Understanding, mind."--Edit 1710.], SOUL, SPIRIT, do not stand for different ideas, or, in truth, for any idea at all, but for something which is very different from ideas, and which, being an agent, cannot be like unto, or represented by, any idea whatsoever. Though it must be owned at the same time that we have some notion of soul, spirit, and the operations of the mind: such as willing, loving, hating--inasmuch as we know or understand the meaning of these words.

27. NO IDEA OF SPIRIT.--A spirit is one simple, indivisible, active being. When it perceives ideas, it's referred to as the UNDERSTANDING, and when it acts or engages with those ideas, it's called the WILL. Therefore, we cannot form an idea of a soul or spirit; all ideas, being passive and inert (see section 25), cannot represent to us, through image or LIKENESS, that which is active. With a little thought, it becomes clear that having an idea that resembles that active principle of motion and change is absolutely impossible. The nature of SPIRIT, or that which acts, is such that it cannot be perceived by itself, BUT ONLY BY THE EFFECTS IT PRODUCES. If anyone doubts the truth of this assertion, let them reflect and see if they can create an idea of any power or active being, and whether they have distinct ideas for the two main powers named WILL and UNDERSTANDING, separate from a third idea of Substance or Being in general, along with a relative notion of it supporting or being the subject of those powers—represented by the name SOUL or SPIRIT. Some hold this view; however, as far as I can tell, the terms WILL [Note: "Understanding, mind."--Edit 1710.], SOUL, SPIRIT, do not represent different ideas or, in reality, any idea at all, but instead signify something very different from ideas, which, being an agent, cannot be represented by any idea whatsoever. Yet, it must be acknowledged that we do have some understanding of the soul, spirit, and the operations of the mind: such as willing, loving, hating—since we know or comprehend the meaning of these terms.

28. I find I can excite ideas in my mind at pleasure, and vary and shift the scene as oft as I think fit. It is no more than willing, and straightway this or that idea arises in my fancy; and by the same power it is obliterated and makes way for another. This making and unmaking of ideas doth very properly denominate the mind active. Thus much is certain and grounded on experience; but when we think of unthinking agents or of exciting ideas exclusive of volition, we only amuse ourselves with words.

28. I find that I can easily generate ideas in my mind and change the scene whenever I want. It's just a matter of willingness, and immediately, this or that idea comes to mind; and with the same ability, it can be erased and replaced by another. This creation and destruction of ideas clearly shows that the mind is active. This is certain and based on experience, but when we consider unthinking agents or generating ideas without any intention, we're just playing with words.

29. IDEAS OF SENSATION DIFFER FROM THOSE OF REFLECTION OR MEMORY.--But, whatever power I may have over MY OWN thoughts, I find the ideas actually perceived by Sense have not a like dependence on my will. When in broad daylight I open my eyes, it is not in my power to choose whether I shall see or no, or to determine what particular objects shall present themselves to my view; and so likewise as to the hearing and other senses; the ideas imprinted on them are not creatures of my will. There is THEREFORE SOME OTHER WILL OR SPIRIT that PRODUCES THEM.

29. IDEAS OF SENSATION DIFFER FROM THOSE OF REFLECTION OR MEMORY.--But, whatever control I may have over my own thoughts, I realize that the ideas I actually perceive through my senses don't depend on my will in the same way. When I open my eyes in broad daylight, I can't choose whether I see or not, nor can I decide which specific objects will come into view; the same goes for hearing and other senses; the ideas formed through them aren't creations of my will. Therefore, there must be some other will or spirit that produces them.

30. LAWS OF NATURE.--The ideas of Sense are more strong, lively, and DISTINCT than those of the imagination; they have likewise a steadiness, order, and coherence, and are not excited at random, as those which are the effects of human wills often are, but in a regular train or series, the admirable connexion whereof sufficiently testifies the wisdom and benevolence of its Author. Now THE SET RULES OR ESTABLISHED METHODS WHEREIN THE MIND WE DEPEND ON EXCITES IN US THE IDEAS OF SENSE, ARE CALLED THE LAWS OF NATURE; and these we learn by experience, which teaches us that such and such ideas are attended with such and such other ideas, in the ordinary course of things.

30. LAWS OF NATURE.--The ideas we get from our senses are stronger, more vivid, and clearer than those from our imagination; they also have a consistency, order, and coherence, and are not triggered randomly like those influenced by human desires often are. Instead, they follow a regular pattern or sequence, the remarkable connection of which clearly shows the wisdom and kindness of its Creator. The RULES OR ESTABLISHED METHODS THAT THE MIND DEPENDS ON TO TRIGGER SENSORY IDEAS ARE KNOWN AS THE LAWS OF NATURE; we learn these through experience, which teaches us that certain ideas are consistently associated with other ideas in the usual course of events.

31. KNOWLEDGE OF THEM NECESSARY FOR THE CONDUCT OF WORLDLY AFFAIRS.--This gives us a sort of foresight which enables us to regulate our actions for the benefit of life. And without this we should be eternally at a loss; we could not know how to act anything that might procure us the least pleasure, or remove the least pain of sense. That food nourishes, sleep refreshes, and fire warms us; that to sow in the seed-time is the way to reap in the harvest; and in general that to obtain such or such ends, such or such means are conducive--all this we know, NOT BY DISCOVERING ANY NECESSARY CONNEXION BETWEEN OUR IDEAS, but only by the observation of the settled laws of nature, without which we should be all in uncertainty and confusion, and a grown man no more know how to manage himself in the affairs of life than an infant just born.

31. KNOWLEDGE OF THEM NECESSARY FOR THE CONDUCT OF WORLDLY AFFAIRS.--This gives us a kind of foresight that enables us to shape our actions for the benefit of our lives. Without this knowledge, we'd be completely lost; we wouldn't know how to do anything that could bring us even a little pleasure or ease our slightest discomfort. We understand that food nourishes, sleep refreshes, and fire keeps us warm; that planting seeds at the right time leads to a good harvest; and generally, that certain means help us achieve specific goals. We know all this NOT BY DISCOVERING ANY NECESSARY CONNECTION BETWEEN OUR IDEAS, but simply by observing the established laws of nature. Without this understanding, we would be left in uncertainty and confusion, with an adult no better equipped to handle life than a newborn baby.

32. And yet THIS consistent UNIFORM WORKING, which so evidently displays the goodness and wisdom of that Governing Spirit whose Will constitutes the laws of nature, is so far from leading our thoughts to Him, that it rather SENDS THEM A WANDERING AFTER SECOND CAUSES. For, when we perceive certain ideas of Sense constantly followed by other ideas and WE KNOW THIS IS NOT OF OUR OWN DOING, we forthwith attribute power and agency to the ideas themselves, and make one the cause of another, than which nothing can be more absurd and unintelligible. Thus, for example, having observed that when we perceive by sight a certain round luminous figure we at the same time perceive by touch the idea or sensation called HEAT, we do from thence conclude the sun to be the cause of heat. And in like manner perceiving the motion and collision of bodies to be attended with sound, we are inclined to think the latter the effect of the former.

32. Yet this consistent and uniform operation, which clearly shows the goodness and wisdom of that governing spirit whose will forms the laws of nature, actually leads our thoughts away from Him and makes us chase after secondary causes. When we notice that certain sensory ideas are regularly followed by other ideas, and we realize this isn’t something we control, we immediately assign power and agency to the ideas themselves, making one the cause of another, which is completely absurd and confusing. For instance, after seeing a certain round, glowing shape, we also feel the sensation called heat, and from this, we conclude that the sun causes heat. Similarly, when we observe the movement and collision of objects accompanied by sound, we are tempted to believe that sound is the result of that movement.

33. OF REAL THINGS AND IDEAS OR CHIMERAS.--The ideas imprinted on the Senses by the Author of nature are called REAL THINGS; and those excited in the imagination being less regular, vivid, and constant, are more properly termed IDEAS, or IMAGES OF THINGS, which they copy and represent. But then our sensations, be they never so vivid and distinct, are nevertheless IDEAS, that is, they exist in the mind, or are perceived by it, as truly as the ideas of its own framing. The ideas of Sense are allowed to have more reality in them, that is, to be more (1)STRONG, (2)ORDERLY, and (3)COHERENT than the creatures of the mind; but this is no argument that they exist without the mind. They are also (4)LESS DEPENDENT ON THE SPIRIT [Note: Vide sect. xxix.--Note.], or thinking substance which perceives them, in that they are excited by the will of another and more powerful spirit; yet still they are IDEAS, and certainly no IDEA, whether faint or strong, can exist otherwise than in a mind perceiving it.

33. OF REAL THINGS AND IDEAS OR CHIMERAS.--The ideas created by the Author of nature that we perceive through our senses are called REAL THINGS; whereas those stirred in our imagination, which are less regular, vivid, and constant, are better described as IDEAS or IMAGES OF THINGS that they imitate and represent. However, our sensations, no matter how vivid and clear, are still IDEAS, meaning they exist in the mind or are perceived by it, just as much as the ideas we create ourselves. Sensory ideas are considered to have more reality in them, that is, to be more (1) STRONG, (2) ORDERLY, and (3) COHERENT than the creations of the mind; but this doesn’t mean they exist independently of the mind. They are also (4) LESS DEPENDENT ON THE SPIRIT [Note: Vide sect. xxix.--Note.], or thinking substance that perceives them, since they are triggered by the will of another, more powerful spirit; yet they are still IDEAS, and certainly no IDEA, whether faint or strong, can exist except in a perceiving mind.

34. FIRST GENERAL OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--Before we proceed any farther it is necessary we spend some time in answering objections which may probably be made against the principles we have hitherto laid down. In doing of which, if I seem too prolix to those of quick apprehensions, I hope it may be pardoned, since all men do not equally apprehend things of this nature, and I am willing to be understood by every one.

34. FIRST GENERAL OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--Before we go any further, we need to take some time to address objections that may be raised against the principles we've outlined so far. If I seem a bit lengthy to those who grasp things quickly, I hope you'll understand, as not everyone comprehends these matters equally, and I want to make sure I’m clear for everyone.

FIRST, then, it will be objected that by the foregoing principles ALL THAT IS REAL AND SUBSTANTIAL IN NATURE IS BANISHED OUT OF THE WORLD, and instead thereof a chimerical scheme of ideas takes place. All things that exist, exist only in the mind, that is, they are purely notional. What therefore becomes of the sun, moon and stars? What must we think of houses, rivers, mountains, trees, stones; nay, even of our own bodies? Are all these but so many chimeras and illusions on the fancy? To all which, and whatever else of the same sort may be objected, I ANSWER, that by the principles premised we are not deprived of any one thing in nature. Whatever we see, feel, hear, or anywise conceive or understand remains as secure as ever, and is as real as ever. There is a RERUM NATURA, and the distinction between realities and chimeras retains its full force. This is evident from sect. 29, 30, and 33, where we have shown what is meant by REAL THINGS in opposition to CHIMERAS or ideas of our own framing; but then they both equally exist in the mind, and in that sense they are alike IDEAS.

FIRST, it will be argued that based on the previous principles, EVERYTHING REAL AND SUBSTANTIAL IN NATURE IS DRIVEN OUT OF THE WORLD, and in its place, a made-up scheme of ideas takes over. Everything that exists does so only in the mind, meaning they are purely notional. So, what happens to the sun, moon, and stars? What should we think about houses, rivers, mountains, trees, and stones; even our own bodies? Are all these just various illusions and fantasies? In response to all such objections, I SAY that the previously mentioned principles do not take away any single thing in nature. Everything we see, feel, hear, or otherwise perceive or understand remains as secure and real as ever. There is a RERUM NATURA, and the difference between what is real and what is imaginary still holds strong. This is clear from sections 29, 30, and 33, where we explain what is meant by REAL THINGS in contrast to CHIMERAS or ideas we've created; yet both equally exist in the mind, and in that way, they are all IDEAS.

35. THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER, AS UNDERSTOOD BY PHILOSOPHERS, DENIED.[Vide sect. lxxxiv.]--I do not argue against the existence of any one thing that we can apprehend either by sense or reflexion. That the things I see with my eyes and touch with my hands do exist, really exist, I make not the least question. The only thing whose existence we deny IS THAT WHICH PHILOSOPHERS CALL MATTER or corporeal substance. And in doing of this there is no damage done to the rest of mankind, who, I dare say, will never miss it. The Atheist indeed will want the colour of an empty name to support his impiety; and the Philosophers may possibly find they have lost a great handle for trifling and disputation.

35. THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER, AS UNDERSTOOD BY PHILOSOPHERS, DENIED. [Vide sect. lxxxiv.] -- I don't argue against the existence of anything that we can perceive through our senses or our thoughts. I have no doubt that the things I see with my eyes and touch with my hands do exist, truly exist. The only thing whose existence we deny is what philosophers call matter or physical substance. And in doing this, no harm is done to the rest of humanity, who, I believe, will never miss it. The atheist may need the superficial label of an empty term to support their beliefs, and the philosophers might find they've lost a significant basis for trivial debates and arguments.

36. READILY EXPLAINED.--If any man thinks this detracts from the existence or reality of things, he is very far from understanding what has been premised in the plainest terms I could think of. Take here an abstract of what has been said:--There are spiritual substances, minds, or human souls, which will or excite ideas in themselves at pleasure; but these are faint, weak, and unsteady in respect of others they perceive by sense--which, being impressed upon them according to certain rules or laws of nature, speak themselves the effects of a mind more powerful and wise than human spirits. These latter are said to have more REALITY in them than the former:--by which is meant that they are more affecting, orderly, and distinct, and that they are not fictions of the mind perceiving them. And in this sense the sun that I see by day is the real sun, and that which I imagine by night is the idea of the former. In the sense here given of REALITY it is evident that every vegetable, star, mineral, and in general each part of the mundane system, is as much a REAL BEING by our principles as by any other. Whether others mean anything by the term REALITY different from what I do, I entreat them to look into their own thoughts and see.

36. EASILY EXPLAINED.--If anyone thinks this takes away from the existence or reality of things, they clearly don't understand what I’ve laid out in the simplest terms I could think of. Here’s a summary of what’s been said: There are spiritual substances, minds, or human souls, which can create or spark ideas internally whenever they choose; however, these are faint, weak, and inconsistent compared to what they observe through their senses—which, being impressed upon them according to specific rules or laws of nature, reflect the effects of a mind that is more powerful and wise than human spirits. These latter are said to have more REALITY than the former, meaning they are more impactful, organized, and clear, and they are not just fabrications of the perceiving mind. In this sense, the sun I see during the day is the real sun, while that which I imagine at night is just an idea of the former. Based on the definition of REALITY given here, it’s clear that every plant, star, mineral, and, in general, every part of the world is just as much a REAL BEING according to our principles as it is by any other measure. If others have a different understanding of the term REALITY than I do, I encourage them to reflect on their own thoughts and see.

37. THE PHILOSOPHIC, NOT THE VULGAR SUBSTANCE, TAKEN AWAY.--I will be urged that thus much at least is true, to wit, that we take away all corporeal substances. To this my answer is, that if the word SUBSTANCE be taken in the vulgar sense--for a combination of sensible qualities, such as extension, solidity, weight, and the like--this we cannot be accused of taking away: but if it be taken in a philosophic sense--for the SUPPORT of accidents or QUALITIES WITHOUT THE MIND--then indeed I acknowledge that we take it away, if one may be said to take away that which never had any existence, not even in the imagination.

37. THE PHILOSOPHICAL, NOT THE COMMON MEANING OF SUBSTANCE, REMOVED.--I will be challenged that it is at least true that we eliminate all physical substances. In response, I say that if the term SUBSTANCE is understood in the common way—as a mix of observable qualities like size, solidity, weight, and so on—then we cannot be accused of removing it. However, if it is understood in a philosophical way—as the SUPPORT of properties or QUALITIES OUTSIDE OF THE MIND—then I admit that we do remove it, if one can be said to remove something that never actually existed, not even in someone's imagination.

38. But, say you, it sounds very harsh to say we eat and drink ideas, and are clothed with ideas. I acknowledge it does so--the word IDEA not being used in common discourse to signify the several combinations of sensible qualities which are called THINGS; and it is certain that any expression which varies from the familiar use of language will seem harsh and ridiculous. But this doth not concern the truth of the proposition, which in other words is no more than to say, we are fed and clothed with those things which we perceive immediately by our senses. The hardness or softness, the colour, taste, warmth, figure, or suchlike qualities, which combined together constitute the several sorts of victuals and apparel, have been shown to exist only in the mind that perceives them; and this is all that is meant by calling them IDEAS; which word if it was as ordinarily used as THING, would sound no harsher nor more ridiculous than it. I am not for disputing about the propriety, but the truth of the expression. If therefore you agree with me that we eat and drink and are clad with the immediate objects of sense, which cannot exist unperceived or without the mind, I shall readily grant it is more proper or conformable to custom that they should be called things rather than ideas.

38. But, you might say, it sounds really harsh to say we eat and drink ideas and are dressed in ideas. I get that—it’s true that we don’t usually use the word IDEA to mean the various combinations of qualities we recognize as THINGS; and any phrase that strays from common language is going to sound off and silly. But that doesn’t change the truth of the statement, which is really just saying that we’re fed and clothed by the things we directly experience with our senses. The hardness or softness, color, taste, warmth, shape, or similar qualities that come together to make up different kinds of food and clothing have been shown to exist only in the mind that perceives them; and that’s all that’s meant by calling them IDEAS. If we used that word as often as we use THING, it wouldn’t sound any more harsh or ridiculous. I’m not arguing about what’s proper, just the truth of the expression. So, if you agree with me that we eat, drink, and wear the immediate things we sense, which can’t exist without being perceived or without the mind, then I’ll readily admit it’s more suitable and customary to call them things instead of ideas.

39. THE TERM IDEA PREFERABLE TO THING.--If it be demanded why I make use of the word IDEA, and do not rather in compliance with custom call them THINGS. I answer, I do it for two reasons:--first, because the term THING in contra-distinction to IDEA, is generally supposed to denote somewhat existing without the mind; secondly, because THING has a more comprehensive signification than IDEA, including SPIRIT or thinking things as well as IDEAS. Since therefore the objects of sense exist only in the mind, and are withal thoughtless and inactive, I chose to mark them by the word IDEA, which implies those properties.

39. THE TERM IDEA PREFERABLE TO THING.--If someone asks why I use the word IDEA instead of calling them THINGS like most people do, I answer for two reasons: first, because the term THING, when contrasted with IDEA, is usually understood to refer to something that exists independently of the mind; second, because THING has a broader meaning than IDEA, including SPIRIT or thinking entities as well as IDEAS. Since the objects of perception exist only in the mind and are inherently thoughtless and inactive, I prefer to refer to them as IDEA, which reflects those characteristics.

40. THE EVIDENCE OF THE SENSES NOT DISCREDITED.--But, say what we can, some one perhaps may be apt to reply, he will still believe his senses, and never suffer any arguments, how plausible soever, to prevail over the certainty of them. Be it so; assert the evidence of sense as high as you please, we are willing to do the same. That what I see, hear, and feel DOTH EXIST, THAT IS to say, IS PERCEIVED BY ME, I no more doubt than I do of my own being. But I do not see how the testimony of sense can be alleged as a proof for the existence of anything which is not perceived by sense. We are not for having any man turn SCEPTIC and disbelieve his senses; on the contrary, we give them all the stress and assurance imaginable; nor are there any principles more opposite to Scepticism than those we have laid down [Note.], as shall be hereafter clearly shown.

40. THE EVIDENCE OF THE SENSES NOT DISCOUNTED.--But, no matter what we say, someone might reply that they will still trust their senses and will not let any argument, no matter how convincing, override the certainty they have in them. That's fine; you can insist on the validity of your senses as much as you want, and we’re willing to do the same. What I see, hear, and feel DOES EXIST, meaning it is PERCEIVED BY ME; I doubt it no more than I doubt my own existence. However, I don’t see how the evidence of the senses can be used to prove the existence of anything that can’t be perceived by the senses. We’re not suggesting that anyone become a SKEPTIC or disbelieve their senses; on the contrary, we give them all the weight and confidence possible. In fact, there are no principles more contrary to Skepticism than those we’ve established [Note.], as will be clearly demonstrated later.

[Note: They extirpate the very root of scepticism, "the fallacy of the senses."--Ed.]

[Note: They eliminate the very foundation of skepticism, "the fallacy of the senses."--Ed.]

41. SECOND OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--Secondly, it will be OBJECTED that there is a great difference betwixt real fire for instance, and the idea of fire, betwixt dreaming or imagining oneself burnt, and actually being so: if you suspect it to be only the idea of fire which you see, do but put your hand into it and you will be convinced with a witness. This and the like may be urged in opposition to our tenets. To all which the ANSWER is evident from what has been already said; and I shall only add in this place, that if real fire be very different from the idea of fire, so also is the real pain that it occasions very different from the idea of the same pain, and yet nobody will pretend that real pain either is, or can possibly be, in an unperceiving thing, or without the mind, any more than its idea.

41. SECOND OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--Secondly, it will be OBJECTED that there is a big difference between real fire, for example, and the idea of fire, between dreaming or imagining oneself getting burned and actually being burned: if you think it’s just the idea of fire that you see, just put your hand in it and you’ll be convinced as a witness. This and similar arguments can be made against our beliefs. The ANSWER to all this is clear from what has already been said; and I will just add here that if real fire is very different from the idea of fire, then the real pain it causes is also very different from the idea of the same pain, and yet no one would claim that real pain can exist in something that doesn’t perceive it, or without the mind, any more than its idea can.

42. THIRD OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--Thirdly, it will be objected that we see things actually without or at distance from us, and which consequently do not exist in the mind; it being absurd that those things which are seen at the distance of several miles should be as near to us as our own thoughts. In answer to this, I desire it may be considered that in a DREAM we do oft perceive things as existing at a great distance off, and yet for all that, those things are acknowledged to have their existence only in the mind.

42. THIRD OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--Thirdly, some might argue that we see things that are outside of us or far away, which therefore do not exist in our minds; it seems ridiculous that things seen several miles away should be as close to us as our own thoughts. In response, I ask you to consider that in a DREAM, we often perceive things as existing far away, yet those things are recognized to exist only in our minds.

43. But, for the fuller clearing of this point, it may be worth while to consider how it is that we perceive distance and things placed at a distance by sight. For, that we should in truth see EXTERNAL space, and bodies actually existing in it, some nearer, others farther off, seems to carry with it some opposition to what has been said of their existing nowhere without the mind. The consideration of this difficulty it was that gave birth to my "Essay towards a New Theory of Vision," which was published not long since, wherein it is shown (1) that DISTANCE or outness is NEITHER IMMEDIATELY of itself PERCEIVED by sight, nor yet apprehended or judged of by lines and angles, or anything that has a necessary connexion with it; but (2) that it is ONLY SUGGESTED to our thoughts by certain visible ideas and sensations attending vision, which in their own nature have no manner of similitude or relation either with distance or things placed at a distance; but, by a connexion taught us BY EXPERIENCE, they come to signify and suggest them to us, after the same manner that WORDS of any language suggest the ideas they are made to stand for; insomuch that a man BORN blind and afterwards made to see, would not, at first sight, think the things he saw to be without his mind, or at any distance from him. See sect. 41 of the fore-mentioned treatise.

43. To further clarify this point, it might be helpful to examine how we perceive distance and objects that are far away through sight. The fact that we can actually see external space, with some objects appearing closer and others further away, seems to contradict what has been said about their existence being nonexistent without the mind. This difficulty led to my "Essay towards a New Theory of Vision," which was published recently. In it, I argue (1) that DISTANCE or outwardness is NEITHER DIRECTLY PERCEIVED by sight NOR understood through lines and angles or any necessary connection; but (2) that it is ONLY SUGGESTED to our thoughts by certain visible ideas and sensations associated with vision, which, in their nature, have no resemblance or relation to either distance or distant objects. Instead, through CONNECTIONS learned from EXPERIENCE, these sensations come to signify and suggest them to us, much like WORDS in any language represent the ideas they stand for. Therefore, a person BORN blind and then given sight would not initially perceive the objects they see as existing outside their mind or at any distance from them. See section 41 of the aforementioned treatise.

44. The ideas of sight and touch make two species entirely distinct and heterogeneous. THE FORMER ARE MARKS AND PROGNOSTICS OF THE LATTER. That the proper objects of sight neither exist without mind, nor are the images of external things, was shown even in that treatise. Though throughout the same the contrary be supposed true of tangible objects--not that to suppose that vulgar error was necessary for establishing the notion therein laid down, but because it was beside my purpose to examine and refute it in a discourse concerning VISION. So that in strict truth the ideas of sight, when we apprehend by them distance and things placed at a distance, do not suggest or mark out to us things ACTUALLY existing at a distance, but only admonish us what ideas of touch will be imprinted in our minds at such and such distances of time, and in consequence of such or such actions. It is, I say, evident from what has been said in the foregoing parts of this Treatise, and in sect. 147 and elsewhere of the Essay concerning Vision, that visible ideas are the Language whereby the governing Spirit on whom we depend informs us what tangible ideas he is about to imprint upon us, in case we excite this or that motion in our own bodies. But for a fuller information in this point I refer to the Essay itself.

44. The concepts of sight and touch represent two completely different categories. SIGHT ACTS AS A SIGN AND A FORECAST FOR TOUCH. It was demonstrated in that earlier work that the true objects of sight do not exist without the mind, nor are they merely images of external things. Although it’s assumed that the opposite is true for what we can touch—this doesn’t mean that the common misconception was necessary for establishing the ideas presented, but rather that it was outside my purpose to analyze and disprove it in a discussion about VISION. Thus, to be precise, the ideas we get from sight, when we perceive distance and distant objects, do not indicate or reveal objects that REALLY exist at a distance; they merely remind us of what ideas of touch will be formed in our minds at certain distances over time and as a result of specific actions. It is clear from what has been discussed in the earlier sections of this Treatise, especially in section 147 and other parts of the Essay on Vision, that visible ideas serve as the language through which the governing Spirit we rely on informs us about the tangible ideas he is about to implant in us, depending on whether we initiate this or that movement in our own bodies. For a more in-depth understanding of this topic, I refer you to the Essay itself.

45. FOURTH OBJECTION, FROM PERPETUAL ANNIHILATION AND CREATION.--ANSWER.--Fourthly, it will be objected that from the foregoing principles it follows things are every moment annihilated and created anew. The objects of sense exist only when they are perceived; the trees therefore are in the garden, or the chairs in the parlour, no longer than while there is somebody by to perceive them. Upon SHUTTING MY EYES all the furniture in the room is reduced to nothing, and barely upon opening them it is again created. In ANSWER to all which, I refer the reader to what has been said in sect. 3, 4, &c., and desire he will consider whether he means anything by the actual existence of an idea distinct from its being perceived. For my part, after the nicest inquiry I could make, I am not able to discover that anything else is meant by those words; and I once more entreat the reader to sound his own thoughts, and not suffer himself to be imposed on by words. If he can conceive it possible either for his ideas or their archetypes to exist without being perceived, then I give up the cause; but if he cannot, he will acknowledge it is unreasonable for him to stand up in defence of he knows not what, and pretend to charge on me as an absurdity the not assenting to those propositions which at bottom have no meaning in them.

45. FOURTH OBJECTION, FROM PERPETUAL ANNIHILATION AND CREATION.--ANSWER.--Fourth, it will be argued that based on the principles mentioned earlier, things are constantly being destroyed and created anew. The things we perceive only exist when they are observed; so the trees in the garden or the chairs in the living room only exist as long as someone is there to see them. When I CLOSE MY EYES, all the furniture in the room disappears, and as soon as I open them, it is created again. In RESPONSE to this, I refer the reader to what was discussed in sections 3, 4, etc., and urge him to think carefully about what he actually means by the existence of an idea that is separate from being perceived. Personally, after thorough investigation, I cannot find that anything else is intended by those words; and I once again ask the reader to reflect on his own thoughts and not be misled by terminology. If he can imagine that his ideas or their underlying forms could exist without being perceived, then I concede the argument; but if he cannot, he should recognize that it is unreasonable for him to defend something he doesn't understand and to accuse me of absurdity for not agreeing with propositions that essentially lack meaning.

46. ARGUMENTUM AD HOMINEM.--It will not be amiss to observe how far the received principles of philosophy are themselves chargeable with those pretended absurdities. (1) It is thought strangely absurd that upon closing my eyelids all the visible objects around me should be reduced to nothing; and yet is not this what philosophers commonly acknowledge, when they agree on all hands that light and colours, which alone are the proper and immediate objects of sight, are mere sensations that exist no longer than they are perceived? (2)Again, it may to some perhaps seem very incredible that things should be every moment creating, yet this very notion is commonly taught in the schools. For the SCHOOLMEN, though they acknowledge the existence of Matter, and that the whole mundane fabric is framed out of it, are nevertheless of opinion that it cannot subsist without the divine conservation, which by them is expounded to be a continual creation.

46. ARGUMENTUM AD HOMINEM.--It’s worth noting how much the accepted principles of philosophy are to blame for these so-called absurdities. (1) It seems strangely ridiculous that when I close my eyes, all the visible things around me vanish; yet isn’t this what philosophers usually agree on, when they universally claim that light and colors, which are the true and immediate objects of sight, are just sensations that only exist while they are being perceived? (2) Additionally, it may seem unbelievable to some that things are created every moment, yet this idea is often taught in schools. The SCHOOLMEN, while they acknowledge the existence of Matter and assert that the entire universe is made from it, also believe that it cannot exist without divine conservation, which they interpret as continuous creation.

47. (3) Further, a little thought will discover to us that though we allow the existence of Matter or corporeal substance, yet it will unavoidably follow, FROM THE PRINCIPLES WHICH ARE NOW GENERALLY ADMITTED, that the PARTICULAR bodies, of what kind soever, do none of them exist whilst they are not perceived. For, it is evident from sect. II and the following sections, that the Matter philosophers contend for is an incomprehensible somewhat, WHICH HAS NONE OF THOSE PARTICULAR QUALITIES WHEREBY THE BODIES FALLING UNDER OUR SENSES ARE DISTINGUISHED ONE FROM ANOTHER. (2) But, to make this more plain, it must be remarked that the infinite divisibility of Matter is now universally allowed, at least by the most approved and considerable philosophers, who on the received principles demonstrate it beyond all exception. Hence, it follows there is an infinite number of parts in each particle of Matter which are not perceived by sense. The reason therefore that any particular body seems to be of a finite magnitude, or exhibits only a finite number of parts to sense, is, not because it contains no more, since in itself it contains an infinite number of parts, BUT BECAUSE THE SENSE IS NOT ACUTE ENOUGH TO DISCERN THEM. In proportion therefore as the sense is rendered more acute, it perceives a greater number of parts in the object, that is, the object appears greater, and its figure varies, those parts in its extremities which were before unperceivable appearing now to bound it in very different lines and angles from those perceived by an obtuser sense. And at length, after various changes of size and shape, when the sense becomes infinitely acute the body shall seem infinite. During all which there is no alteration in the body, but only in the sense. EACH BODY THEREFORE, CONSIDERED IN ITSELF, IS INFINITELY EXTENDED, AND CONSEQUENTLY VOID OF ALL SHAPE OR FIGURE. From which it follows that, though we should grant the existence of Matter to be never so certain, yet it is withal as certain, the materialists themselves are by their own principles forced to acknowledge, that neither the particular bodies perceived by sense, nor anything like them, exists without the mind. Matter, I say, and each particle thereof, is according to them infinite and shapeless, AND IT IS THE MIND THAT FRAMES ALL THAT VARIETY OF BODIES WHICH COMPOSE THE VISIBLE WORLD, ANY ONE WHEREOF DOES NOT EXIST LONGER THAN IT IS PERCEIVED.

47. (3) Furthermore, a little thought will reveal that even though we accept the existence of matter or physical substance, it inevitably follows from the principles that are currently widely accepted that specific bodies, of any kind, do not exist when they are not perceived. It is clear from section II and the sections that follow that the matter philosophers argue for is an incomprehensible something that lacks the specific qualities that distinguish the bodies we sense from one another. (2) To clarify this further, it should be noted that the infinite divisibility of matter is now universally accepted, at least by the most respected philosophers, who demonstrate this beyond any doubt based on established principles. Therefore, it follows that there is an infinite number of parts in every particle of matter that are not perceptible to our senses. The reason a particular body seems to have a finite size or only shows a finite number of parts to our senses is not that it contains no more, since it actually has an infinite number of parts, but because our senses are not sharp enough to detect them. As our senses become more acute, they perceive more parts in the object, making the object appear larger, and its shape changes, with parts on its edges that were previously undetectable now appearing to define it in very different lines and angles than those recognized by a less sensitive sense. Eventually, after various changes in size and shape, when our senses become infinitely acute, the body will seem infinite. Throughout this process, the body itself does not change, only the sense does. Therefore, each body, considered in itself, is infinitely extended and consequently lacks any definite shape or figure. This leads to the conclusion that even if we were to grant the existence of matter as certain, it is equally certain that the materialists themselves, by their own principles, must acknowledge that neither the particular bodies perceived by our senses nor anything similar exists without the mind. Matter, I assert, and each particle of it, is according to them infinite and shapeless, and it is the mind that creates all the different bodies that make up the visible world, each of which does not exist any longer than it is perceived.

48. If we consider it, the objection proposed in sect. 45 will not be found reasonably charged on the principles we have premised, so as in truth to make any objection at all against our notions. For, though we hold indeed the objects of sense to be nothing else but ideas which cannot exist unperceived; yet we may not hence conclude they have no existence except only while they are perceived by US, since THERE MAY BE SOME OTHER SPIRIT THAT PERCEIVES THEM THOUGH WE DO NOT. Wherever bodies are said to have no existence without the mind, I would not be understood to mean this or that particular mind, but ALL MINDS WHATSOEVER. It does not therefore follow from the foregoing principles that bodies are annihilated and created every moment, or exist not at all during the intervals between our perception of them.

48. If we think about it, the objection raised in section 45 isn't really valid based on the principles we've discussed, so it doesn't actually challenge our ideas. Even though we believe that the objects of our senses are just ideas that can’t exist without being perceived, we can't conclude that they only exist when we're perceiving them, since there could be some other spirit that perceives them even if we don’t. When we say that objects don't exist without the mind, I don’t mean this specific mind or that one, but ALL MINDS IN GENERAL. Therefore, it doesn't follow from the principles we outlined that objects are constantly being created and destroyed every moment, or that they don’t exist at all in the time between our perceptions of them.

49. FIFTH OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--Fifthly, it may perhaps be OBJECTED that if extension and figure exist only in the mind, it follows that the mind is extended and figured; since extension is a mode or attribute which (to speak with the schools) is predicated of the subject in which it exists. I ANSWER, (1) Those qualities are in the mind ONLY AS THEY ARE PERCEIVED BY IT--that is, not by way of MODE or ATTRIBUTE, but only by way of IDEA; and it no more follows the soul or mind is extended, because extension exists in it alone, than it does that it is red or blue, because those colours are ON ALL HANDS acknowledged to exist in it, and nowhere else. (2) As to what philosophers say of subject and mode, that seems very groundless and unintelligible. For instance, in this proposition "a die is hard, extended, and square," they will have it that the word die denotes a subject or substance, distinct from the hardness, extension, and figure which are predicated of it, and in which they exist. This I cannot comprehend: to me a die seems to be nothing distinct from those things which are termed its modes or accidents. And, to say a die is hard, extended, and square is not to attribute those qualities to a subject distinct from and supporting them, but only an explication of the meaning of the word DIE.

49. FIFTH OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--Fifthly, someone might argue that if extension and shape exist only in the mind, it means the mind itself is extended and shaped; since extension is a characteristic that, as the scholars say, belongs to the subject in which it exists. I RESPOND, (1) Those qualities exist in the mind ONLY AS THEY ARE PERCEIVED BY IT—that is, not as MODE or ATTRIBUTE, but simply as IDEA; and it does not follow that the soul or mind is extended, just because extension exists only in it, any more than it follows that it is red or blue, since those colors are universally acknowledged to exist in it and nowhere else. (2) Regarding what philosophers say about subject and mode, that seems quite unfounded and confusing. For example, in the statement "a die is hard, extended, and square," they argue that the word die refers to a subject or substance that is separate from the hardness, extension, and shape that are attributed to it, and in which they exist. I cannot understand this: to me, a die seems to be nothing different from what we call its modes or accidents. And saying a die is hard, extended, and square does not attribute those qualities to a separate subject that supports them, but is merely an explanation of the meaning of the word DIE.

50. SIXTH OBJECTION, FROM NATURAL PHILOSOPHY.--ANSWER.--Sixthly, you will say there have been a great many things explained by matter and motion; take away these and you destroy the whole corpuscular philosophy, and undermine those mechanical principles which have been applied with so much success to account for the PHENOMENA. In short, whatever advances have been made, either by ancient or modern philosophers, in the study of nature do all proceed on the supposition that corporeal substance or Matter doth really exist. To this I ANSWER that there is not any one PHENOMENON explained on that supposition which may not as well be explained without it, as might easily be made appear by an INDUCTION OF PARTICULARS. To explain the PHENOMENA, is all one as to show why, upon such and such occasions, we are affected with such and such ideas. But (1) how Matter should operate on a Spirit, or produce any idea in it, is what no philosopher will pretend to explain; it is therefore evident there can be no use of Matter in natural philosophy. Besides, (2) they who attempt to account for things do it not by CORPOREAL SUBSTANCE, but by figure, motion, and other qualities, which are in truth no more than mere ideas, and, therefore, cannot be the cause of anything, as has been already shown. See sect. 25.

50. SIXTH OBJECTION, FROM NATURAL PHILOSOPHY.--ANSWER.--Sixthly, you might say there are many things explained by matter and motion; remove these, and you destroy the entire corpuscular philosophy and challenge the mechanical principles that have been successfully applied to explain the PHENOMENA. Essentially, any progress made by ancient or modern philosophers in understanding nature is based on the assumption that physical substance or Matter truly exists. To this I RESPOND that there isn’t a single PHENOMENON explained based on that assumption which couldn’t also be explained without it, as could easily be demonstrated through an INDUCTION OF PARTICULARS. Explaining the PHENOMENA is the same as showing why, in particular situations, we are affected by specific ideas. But (1) how Matter can influence a Spirit or generate any idea within it is something no philosopher will attempt to explain; therefore, it’s clear there’s no necessity for Matter in natural philosophy. Furthermore, (2) those who try to explain things do so not through CORPOREAL SUBSTANCE, but through shape, motion, and other qualities, which are essentially just ideas, and therefore cannot be the cause of anything, as has already been demonstrated. See sect. 25.

51. SEVENTH OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--Seventhly, it will upon this be demanded whether it does not seem ABSURD TO TAKE AWAY NATURAL CAUSES, AND ASCRIBE EVERYTHING TO THE IMMEDIATE OPERATION OF SPIRITS? We must no longer say upon these principles that fire heats, or water cools, but that a Spirit heats, and so forth. Would not a man be deservedly laughed at, who should talk after this manner? I ANSWER, he would so; in such things we ought to THINK WITH THE LEARNED, AND SPEAK WITH THE VULGAR. They who to demonstration are convinced of the truth of the Copernican system do nevertheless say "the sun rises," "the sun sets," or "comes to the meridian"; and if they affected a contrary style in common talk it would without doubt appear very ridiculous. A little reflexion on what is here said will make it manifest that the common use of language would receive no manner of alteration or disturbance from the admission of our tenets.

51. SEVENTH OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--Seventh, it will be asked whether it doesn't seem ABSURD TO REMOVE NATURAL CAUSES AND ATTRIBUTE EVERYTHING TO THE DIRECT ACTION OF SPIRITS? We shouldn't say, based on these principles, that fire heats or water cools; instead, we should say that a Spirit heats, and so on. Wouldn't someone be justifiably mocked for talking this way? I ANSWER, yes, they would; in such matters, we should THINK LIKE THE EDUCATED AND SPEAK LIKE THE COMMON PEOPLE. Those who are convinced of the truth of the Copernican system still say "the sun rises," "the sun sets," or "reaches its highest point"; and if they tried to change their speech in everyday conversation, it would undoubtedly seem very silly. A little reflection on what has been said will make it clear that the everyday use of language would not change or be disturbed by accepting our beliefs.

52. IN THE ORDINARY AFFAIRS OF LIFE, ANY PHRASES MAY BE RETAINED, so long as they excite in us proper sentiments, or dispositions to act in such a manner as is necessary for our WELL-BEING, how false soever they may be if taken in a strict and SPECULATIVE SENSE. Nay, this is unavoidable, since, propriety being regulated by CUSTOM, language is suited to the RECEIVED opinions, which are not always the truest. Hence it is impossible, even in the most rigid, philosophic reasonings, so far to alter the bent and genius of the tongue we speak, as never to give a handle for cavillers to pretend difficulties and inconsistencies. But, a fair and ingenuous reader will collect the sense from the scope and tenor and connexion of a discourse, making allowances for those inaccurate modes of speech which use has made inevitable.

52. IN THE EVERYDAY MATTERS OF LIFE, ANY PHRASES CAN BE KEPT, as long as they inspire in us the right feelings or motivations to act in ways that are necessary for our WELL-BEING, no matter how misleading they may be if taken literally and ANALYTICALLY. In fact, this is unavoidable, because propriety is influenced by CUSTOM, and language reflects the ACCEPTED opinions, which aren’t always the most accurate. Therefore, it’s impossible, even in the strictest philosophical arguments, to change the nature and style of the language we use so thoroughly that there’s never a chance for critics to claim they see difficulties and contradictions. However, a fair and open-minded reader will understand the meaning from the overall intent, structure, and connection of a discussion, allowing for those inaccurate phrases that usage has made inevitable.

53. As to the OPINION THAT THERE ARE NO CORPOREAL CAUSES, this has been heretofore maintained by some of the Schoolmen, as it is of late by others among the modern philosophers, who though they allow Matter to exist, yet will have God alone to be the immediate efficient cause of all things. These men saw that amongst all the objects of sense there was none which had any power or activity included in it; and that by consequence this was likewise true of whatever bodies they supposed to exist without the mind, like unto the immediate objects of sense. But then, that they should suppose an innumerable multitude of created beings, which they acknowledge are not capable of producing any one effect in nature, and which therefore are made to no manner of purpose, since God might have done everything as well without them: this I say, though we should allow it possible, must yet be a very unaccountable and extravagant supposition.

53. Regarding the OPINION THAT THERE ARE NO PHYSICAL CAUSES, some scholars have maintained this in the past, and modern philosophers have recently adopted similar views. They admit that matter exists but claim that God is the only direct cause of everything. These thinkers observed that none of the tangible objects we perceive have any inherent power or activity. Consequently, this also applies to any physical entities they believe exist outside of our perception, like the immediate sensory objects. However, it’s perplexing that they would suggest there are countless created beings that they recognize cannot produce any effects in nature, making them pointless since God could have accomplished everything without them. I argue that even if we consider it possible, it remains a very unreasonable and far-fetched belief.

54. EIGHTH OBJECTION.--TWOFOLD ANSWER.--In the eighth place, the universal concurrent assent of mankind may be thought by some an invincible argument in behalf of Matter, or the existence of external things. Must we suppose the whole world to be mistaken? And if so, what cause can be assigned of so widespread and predominant an error? I answer, FIRST, that, upon a narrow inquiry, it will not perhaps be found so many as is imagined do really believe the existence of Matter or things without the mind. Strictly speaking, to believe that which involves a contradiction, or has no meaning in it, is impossible; and whether the foregoing expressions are not of that sort, I refer it to the impartial examination of the reader. In one sense, indeed, men may be said to believe that Matter exists, that is, they ACT as if the immediate cause of their sensations, which affects them every moment, and is so nearly present to them, were some senseless unthinking being. But, that they should clearly apprehend any meaning marked by those words, and form thereof a settled SPECULATIVE opinion, is what I am not able to conceive. This is not the only instance wherein men impose upon themselves, by imagining they believe those propositions which they have often heard, though at bottom they have no meaning in them.

54. EIGHTH OBJECTION.--TWOFOLD ANSWER.--In the eighth place, some might argue that the universal agreement of humanity is a strong argument for the existence of Matter or external things. Do we really have to assume that everyone in the world is wrong? And if that's the case, what could explain such a widespread and dominant mistake? I respond, FIRST, that upon closer examination, it may not actually be true that as many people as is thought really believe in the existence of Matter or things outside of the mind. Strictly speaking, believing in something that involves a contradiction or has no real meaning is impossible; whether the previous statements fall into that category, I leave for the reader to consider impartially. In one way, it could be said that people believe Matter exists, meaning they behave as if the immediate source of their sensations, which impacts them constantly and is so present to them, is some thoughtless, unfeeling entity. However, that they should fully understand any meaning behind those words and form a consistent SPECULATIVE opinion from it is something I cannot grasp. This is not the only instance where people deceive themselves by thinking they believe in propositions they've often heard, even when those propositions actually lack real meaning.

55. But SECONDLY, though we should grant a notion to be never so universally and steadfastly adhered to, yet this is weak argument of its truth to whoever considers what a vast number of prejudices and false opinions are everywhere embraced with the utmost tenaciousness, by the unreflecting (which are the far greater) part of mankind. There was a time when the antipodes and motion of the earth were looked upon as monstrous absurdities even by men of learning: and if it be considered what a small proportion they bear to the rest of mankind, we shall find that at this day those notions have gained but a very inconsiderable footing in the world.

55. But SECONDLY, even if we accept a belief that is widely and firmly held, this is a weak argument for its truth to anyone who thinks about the countless prejudices and false beliefs that many people cling to very tightly, especially the unreflective majority. There was a time when educated people considered the idea of antipodes and the Earth's motion to be complete nonsense. And when we look at how few people actually supported those ideas compared to everyone else, we see that today those beliefs have gained only a very small foothold in the world.

56. NINTH OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--But it is demanded that we assign A CAUSE OF THIS PREJUDICE, and account for its obtaining in the world. To this I ANSWER, that men knowing they perceived several ideas, WHEREOF THEY THEMSELVES WERE NOT THE AUTHORS--as not being excited from within nor depending on the operation of their wills--this made them maintain those ideas, or objects of perception had an EXISTENCE INDEPENDENT OF AND WITHOUT THE MIND, without ever dreaming that a contradiction was involved in those words. But, philosophers having plainly seen that the immediate objects of perception do not exist without the mind, THEY IN SOME DEGREE CORRECTED the mistake of the vulgar; but at the same time run into another which seems no less absurd, to wit, that there are certain objects really existing without the mind, or having a subsistence distinct from being perceived, OF WHICH OUR IDEAS ARE ONLY IMAGES or resemblances, imprinted by those objects on the mind. And this notion of the philosophers owes its origin to the same cause with the former, namely, their being conscious that they were not the authors of their own sensations, which they evidently knew were imprinted from without, and which therefore must have some cause distinct from the minds on which they are imprinted.

56. NINTH OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--However, it is asked that we explain the REASON for this prejudice and how it came to exist in the world. To this, I ANSWER that people, realizing they perceived various ideas that they themselves did not create—since these ideas weren't generated from within or controlled by their own will—came to believe that those ideas or objects of perception had an EXISTENCE INDEPENDENT OF AND OUTSIDE THE MIND, without ever considering that those words contain a contradiction. Yet, philosophers have clearly recognized that the immediate objects of perception do not exist without the mind; THEY HAVE PARTIALLY CORRECTED the common people's misunderstanding. However, they fell into another mistake that seems just as absurd, which is the idea that there are certain objects genuinely existing outside the mind, or having a reality separate from being perceived, OF WHICH OUR IDEAS ARE ONLY IMAGES or copies, imprinted by those objects onto the mind. This philosophical idea arises from the same reason as the former, namely, their awareness that they were not the creators of their own sensations, which they clearly understood were imprinted from outside, and therefore must have some cause distinct from the minds onto which they are imprinted.

57. BUT WHY THEY SHOULD SUPPOSE THE IDEAS OF SENSE TO BE EXCITED IN US BY THINGS IN THEIR LIKENESS, and not rather have recourse to SPIRIT which alone can act, may be accounted for, FIRST, because they were not aware of the repugnancy there is, (1) as well in supposing things like unto our ideas existing without, as in (2) attributing to them POWER OR ACTIVITY. SECONDLY, because the Supreme Spirit which excites those ideas in our minds, is not marked out and limited to our view by any particular finite collection of sensible ideas, as human agents are by their size, complexion, limbs, and motions. And thirdly, because His operations are regular and uniform. Whenever the course of nature is interrupted by a miracle, men are ready to own the presence of a superior agent. But, when we see things go on in the ordinary course they do not excite in us any reflexion; their order and concatenation, though it be an argument of the greatest wisdom, power, and goodness in their creator, is yet so constant and familiar to us that we do not think them the immediate effects of a Free Spirit; especially since inconsistency and mutability in acting, though it be an imperfection, is looked on as a mark of freedom.

57. BUT WHY DO THEY THINK THAT OUR SENSES ARE TRIGGERED BY THINGS THAT ARE SIMILAR TO OUR IDEAS, rather than considering the SPIRIT that can actually act? This can be explained, FIRST, because they didn’t recognize the inconsistency in (1) assuming that things similar to our ideas exist outside of us, as well as in (2) attributing POWER OR ACTIVITY to them. SECOND, because the Supreme Spirit that triggers those ideas in our minds isn’t defined or limited to our perception by any specific finite set of sensory ideas, unlike human beings who are defined by their size, appearance, limbs, and movements. Third, because His actions are consistent and uniform. Whenever nature's usual course is interrupted by a miracle, people readily acknowledge a higher agent at work. But when we see things happen as they normally do, they don’t provoke any reflection from us; their order and connection, although they demonstrate great wisdom, power, and goodness in their creator, are so consistent and familiar to us that we don’t see them as the immediate results of a Free Spirit, especially since inconsistency and changeability in action, while being a flaw, are viewed as signs of freedom.

58. TENTH OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--Tenthly, it will be objected that the notions we advance are inconsistent with several sound truths in philosophy and mathematics. For example, the motion of the earth is now universally admitted by astronomers as a truth grounded on the clearest and most convincing reasons. But, on the foregoing principles, there can be no such thing. For, motion being only an idea, it follows that if it be not perceived it exists not; but the motion of the earth is not perceived by sense. I answer, that tenet, if rightly understood, will be found to agree with the principles we have premised; for, the question whether the earth moves or no amounts in reality to no more than this, to wit, whether we have reason to conclude, from what has been observed by astronomers, that if we were placed in such and such circumstances, and such or such a position and distance both from the earth and sun, we should perceive the former to move among the choir of the planets, and appearing in all respects like one of them; and this, by the established rules of nature which we have no reason to mistrust, is reasonably collected from the phenomena.

58. TENTH OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--Tenthly, it will be argued that the ideas we present contradict some well-established truths in philosophy and mathematics. For instance, the motion of the earth is now widely accepted by astronomers as a fact based on clear and convincing evidence. However, according to the principles mentioned earlier, there can be no such motion. Since motion is just an idea, it follows that if it’s not perceived, it doesn’t exist; but the motion of the earth cannot be perceived through the senses. I respond that this belief, if properly understood, will actually align with the principles we've laid out. The question of whether the earth moves or not essentially comes down to whether we have enough reason to believe, based on astronomers’ observations, that if we were in certain circumstances—at a specific position and distance from both the earth and the sun—we would perceive the earth moving among the planets, appearing just like one of them; and this conclusion is reasonably drawn from the phenomena based on the established rules of nature that we have no reason to doubt.

59. We may, from the experience we have had of the train and succession of ideas in our minds, often make, I will not say uncertain conjectures, but sure and well--grounded predictions concerning the ideas we shall be affected with pursuant to a great train of actions, and be enabled to pass a right judgment of what would have appeared to us, in case we were placed in circumstances very different from those we are in at present. Herein consists the knowledge of nature, which may preserve its use and certainty very consistently with what has been said. It will be easy to apply this to whatever objections of the like sort may be drawn from the magnitude of the stars, or any other discoveries in astronomy or nature.

59. Based on what we’ve experienced with the flow of thoughts in our minds, we can often make not just uncertain guesses, but confident and well-founded predictions about the ideas we will encounter as a result of a series of actions. This allows us to judge accurately what we would have thought if we were in situations very different from our current ones. This is the essence of understanding nature, which can maintain its usefulness and reliability in line with what has been stated. It’s easy to relate this to any similar objections that might come up regarding the size of the stars or other findings in astronomy or nature.

60. ELEVENTH OBJECTION.--In the eleventh place, it will be demanded to what purpose serves that curious organization of plants, and the animal mechanism in the parts of animals; might not vegetables grow, and shoot forth leaves of blossoms, and animals perform all their motions as well without as with all that variety of internal parts so elegantly contrived and put together; which, being ideas, have nothing powerful or operative in them, nor have any necessary connexion with the effects ascribed to them? If it be a Spirit that immediately produces every effect by a fiat or act of his will, we must think all that is fine and artificial in the works, whether of man or nature, to be made in vain. By this doctrine, though an artist has made the spring and wheels, and every movement of a watch, and adjusted them in such a manner as he knew would produce the motions he designed, yet he must think all this done to no purpose, and that it is an Intelligence which directs the index, and points to the hour of the day. If so, why may not the Intelligence do it, without his being at the pains of making the movements and putting them together? Why does not an empty case serve as well as another? And how comes it to pass that whenever there is any fault in the going of a watch, there is some corresponding disorder to be found in the movements, which being mended by a skilful hand all is right again? The like may be said of all the clockwork of nature, great part whereof is so wonderfully fine and subtle as scarce to be discerned by the best microscope. In short, it will be asked, how, upon our principles, any tolerable account can be given, or any final cause assigned of an innumerable multitude of bodies and machines, framed with the most exquisite art, which in the common philosophy have very apposite uses assigned them, and serve to explain abundance of phenomena?

60. ELEVENTH OBJECTION.--In the eleventh place, one might question the purpose of the intricate structure of plants and the mechanical systems in animals; couldn’t plants grow, sprout leaves and flowers, and animals carry out all their movements just fine without all those various internal parts so beautifully designed and assembled? These ideas seem powerless and don’t necessarily connect to the effects attributed to them. If a Spirit is the one producing every effect simply by willing it, we would have to believe that all the fine and intricate things in human or natural works are made in vain. According to this view, even if an artist has crafted the springs and gears of a watch, arranging them in a way that he knows will create the desired movements, he must believe it was all done for no reason, and that it is actually an Intelligence operating the hands, telling the time. If that's the case, why can't the Intelligence just do it without the artist needing to create and assemble those movements? Why wouldn’t an empty case work just as well? And why is it that whenever there’s an issue with a watch, there’s a corresponding problem in the movements, which, when fixed by a skilled hand, makes everything function correctly again? The same can be said for the entire mechanism of nature, a significant part of which is so incredibly fine and delicate that it’s barely visible even with the best microscope. In short, it raises the question of how, based on our principles, we can provide a reasonable explanation or assign any purpose to the countless bodies and machines that are constructed with such exquisite artistry, which in traditional philosophy have very fitting uses assigned to them and help explain many phenomena?

61. ANSWER.--To all which I answer, first, that though there were some difficulties relating to the administration of Providence, and the uses by it assigned to the several parts of nature, which I could not solve by the foregoing principles, yet this objection could be of small weight against the truth and certainty of those things which may be proved a priori, with the utmost evidence and rigor of demonstration. Secondly, but neither are the received principles free from the like difficulties; for, it may still be demanded to what end God should take those roundabout methods of effecting things by instruments and machines, which no one can deny might have been effected by the mere command of His will without all that apparatus; nay, if we narrowly consider it, we shall find the objection may be retorted with greater force on those who hold the existence of those machines without of mind; for it has been made evident that solidity, bulk, figure, motion, and the like have no activity or efficacy in them, so as to be capable of producing any one effect in nature. See sect. 25. Whoever therefore supposes them to exist (allowing the supposition possible) when they are not perceived does it manifestly to no purpose; since the only use that is assigned to them, as they exist unperceived, is that they produce those perceivable effects which in truth cannot be ascribed to anything but Spirit.

61. ANSWER.--To all this, I first respond that, while there are some challenges related to how Providence operates and the roles assigned to different parts of nature that I couldn’t resolve using the previous principles, this objection carries little weight against the truth and certainty of things that can be proven a priori with the highest level of evidence and rigor in demonstration. Secondly, the accepted principles are not free from similar challenges; it can still be questioned why God would use indirect methods to achieve things through instruments and machines, which could have been accomplished simply by His will without all that complexity. Indeed, if we scrutinize it closely, we’ll find that the objection can be strengthened against those who believe in the existence of these machines independent of the mind; for it has been shown that solidity, size, shape, motion, and similar properties have no power or effectiveness in themselves to produce any effect in nature. See sect. 25. Therefore, anyone who assumes they exist (if we assume that possibility) when they are not perceived does so clearly without reason; since the only purpose assigned to them, as they exist unperceived, is to produce perceivable effects that can ultimately be attributed only to Spirit.

62. (FOURTHLY.)--But, to come nigher the difficulty, it must be observed that though the fabrication of all those parts and organs be not absolutely necessary to the producing any effect, yet it is necessary to the producing of things in a constant regular way according to the laws of nature. There are certain general laws that run through the whole chain of natural effects; these are learned by the observation and study of nature, and are by men applied as well to the framing artificial things for the use and ornament of life as to the explaining various phenomena--which explication consists only in showing the conformity any particular phenomenon has to the general laws of nature, or, which is the same thing, in discovering the uniformity there is in the production of natural effects; as will be evident to whoever shall attend to the several instances wherein philosophers pretend to account for appearances. That there is a great and conspicuous use in these regular constant methods of working observed by the Supreme Agent has been shown in sect. 31. And it is no less visible that a particular size, figure, motion, and disposition of parts are necessary, though not absolutely to the producing any effect, yet to the producing it according to the standing mechanical laws of nature. Thus, for instance, it cannot be denied that God, or the Intelligence that sustains and rules the ordinary course of things, might if He were minded to produce a miracle, cause all the motions on the dial-plate of a watch, though nobody had ever made the movements and put them in it: but yet, if He will act agreeably to the rules of mechanism, by Him for wise ends established and maintained in the creation, it is necessary that those actions of the watchmaker, whereby he makes the movements and rightly adjusts them, precede the production of the aforesaid motions; as also that any disorder in them be attended with the perception of some corresponding disorder in the movements, which being once corrected all is right again.

62. (FOURTHLY.)--However, to get to the heart of the issue, it's important to note that while creating all those parts and organs isn’t absolutely necessary to produce any effect, it is essential for consistently generating things in a regular manner according to the laws of nature. There are certain universal laws that apply throughout all natural effects; these laws are understood through observing and studying nature and are used by people both to create artificial items for practical use and decoration, as well as to explain various phenomena. This explanation involves demonstrating how any specific phenomenon aligns with general natural laws, or, in other words, uncovering the uniformity in the production of natural effects; this will be clear to anyone who considers the different instances where philosophers try to clarify appearances. The significant and noticeable benefit of these regular, consistent methods of operation observed by the Supreme Agent has been demonstrated in section 31. It’s also evident that a specific size, shape, motion, and arrangement of parts are necessary—though not absolutely required—for producing an effect, yet they are essential for generating it according to the established mechanical laws of nature. For example, it cannot be denied that God, or the Intelligence sustaining and governing the usual course of events, could if He chose, create a miracle, causing all the motions on a watch's dial-plate without anyone ever having made the movements and set them in place. However, if He acts in accordance with the mechanical rules, which He has wisely established and maintained in creation, it’s necessary that the watchmaker’s actions—whereby he creates and correctly adjusts the movements—precede the production of those motions; and any disorder in them must correspond to some noticeable disorder in the movements, which, once rectified, returns everything to normal.

63. It may indeed on some occasions be necessary that the Author of nature display His overruling power in producing some appearance out of the ordinary series of things. Such exceptions from the general rules of nature are proper to surprise and awe men into an acknowledgement of the Divine Being; but then they are to be used but seldom, otherwise there is a plain reason why they should fail of that effect. Besides, God seems to choose the convincing our reason of His attributes by the works of nature, which discover so much harmony and contrivance in their make, and are such plain indications of wisdom and beneficence in their Author, rather than to astonish us into a belief of His Being by anomalous and surprising events.

63. There are times when the Creator of nature may need to show His powerful influence by creating something unusual that breaks the normal order of things. These exceptions to the usual rules of nature are meant to surprise and impress people into recognizing the Divine Being; however, they should be used sparingly, or there’s a clear reason they might lose their impact. Additionally, it seems that God prefers to convince us of His attributes through the works of nature, which reveal a great harmony and design in their creation, and serve as clear signs of wisdom and kindness from their Creator, rather than trying to shock us into believing in His existence through unusual and startling events.

64. To set this matter in a yet clearer light, I shall observe that what has been objected in sect. 60 amounts in reality to no more than this:--ideas are not anyhow and at random produced, there being a certain order and connexion between them, like to that of cause and effect; there are also several combinations of them made in a very regular and artificial manner, which seem like so many instruments in the hand of nature that, being hid as it were behind the scenes, have a secret operation in producing those appearances which are seen on the theatre of the world, being themselves discernible only to the curious eye of the philosopher. But, since one idea cannot be the cause of another, to what purpose is that connexion? And, since those instruments, being barely inefficacious perceptions in the mind, are not subservient to the production of natural effects, it is demanded why they are made; or, in other words, what reason can be assigned why God should make us, upon a close inspection into His works, behold so great variety of ideas so artfully laid together, and so much according to rule; it not being credible that He would be at the expense (if one may so speak) of all that art and regularity to no purpose.

64. To clarify this matter even more, I want to point out that what was raised in section 60 really amounts to this: ideas aren't just randomly created; there's a certain order and connection between them, similar to cause and effect. There are also several combinations of these ideas made in a very structured and artificial way, which act like tools in nature's hands that, while hidden behind the scenes, secretly influence the appearances we see in the world, being noticeable only to the keen eye of a philosopher. However, since one idea cannot cause another, what's the point of that connection? And since these tools are simply ineffective perceptions in the mind and do not contribute to producing natural effects, it raises the question of why they exist at all. In other words, what reason can we find for God showing us, upon closer examination of His works, such a vast variety of ideas carefully arranged and so orderly? It's hard to believe that He would invest (if I can put it that way) all that artistry and structure for no reason.

65. To all which my answer is, first, that the connexion of ideas does not imply the relation of cause and effect, but only of a mark or sign with the thing signified. The fire which I see is not the cause of the pain I suffer upon my approaching it, but the mark that forewarns me of it. In like manner the noise that I hear is not the effect of this or that motion or collision of the ambient bodies, but the sign thereof. Secondly, the reason why ideas are formed into machines, that is, artificial and regular combinations, is the same with that for combining letters into words. That a few original ideas may be made to signify a great number of effects and actions, it is necessary they be variously combined together. And, to the end their use be permanent and universal, these combinations must be made by rule, and with wise contrivance. By this means abundance of information is conveyed unto us, concerning what we are to expect from such and such actions and what methods are proper to be taken for the exciting such and such ideas; which in effect is all that I conceive to be distinctly meant when it is said that, by discerning a figure, texture, and mechanism of the inward parts of bodies, whether natural or artificial, we may attain to know the several uses and properties depending thereon, or the nature of the thing.

65. My response to all of this is, first, that the connection of ideas doesn't imply a cause-and-effect relationship, but rather just a relationship between a sign and what it represents. The fire I see isn’t the cause of the pain I feel when I get close to it; it’s a warning sign. Similarly, the noise I hear isn’t caused by any specific movement or collision of nearby objects, but is just a sign of it. Secondly, the reason ideas are formed into systems, or artificial and organized combinations, is the same reason letters are combined into words. In order for a few original ideas to represent a wide range of effects and actions, they need to be combined in different ways. Additionally, for their use to be lasting and universal, these combinations should be crafted according to rules and with careful planning. This way, we receive a wealth of information about what to expect from certain actions and what methods are suitable for triggering specific ideas; essentially, this is what I believe is clearly meant when it’s said that by recognizing the shape, texture, and structure of the internal parts of objects, whether natural or man-made, we can understand their various uses and properties, or the essence of the object.

66. PROPER EMPLOYMENT OF THE NATURAL PHILOSOPHER.--Hence, it is evident that those things which, under the notion of a cause co-operating or concurring to the production of effects, are altogether inexplicable, and run us into great absurdities, may be very naturally explained, and have a proper and obvious use assigned to them, when they are considered only as marks or signs for our information. And it is the searching after and endeavouring to understand those signs instituted by the Author of Nature, that ought to be the employment of the natural philosopher; and not the pretending to explain things by corporeal causes, which doctrine seems to have too much estranged the minds of men from that active principle, that supreme and wise Spirit "in whom we live, move, and have our being."

66. PROPER EMPLOYMENT OF THE NATURAL PHILOSOPHER.--Therefore, it’s clear that those things we think of as causes working together to produce effects can be completely baffling and lead us to absurd conclusions. However, they can be easily explained and assigned a clear purpose when we view them simply as signs or indicators for our understanding. The pursuit of understanding these signs established by the Creator of Nature should be the focus of the natural philosopher; rather than trying to explain things through physical causes, a viewpoint that has likely distracted people from that active principle, that supreme and wise Spirit "in whom we live, move, and have our being."

67. TWELFTH OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--In the twelfth place, it may perhaps be objected that--though it be clear from what has been said that there can be no such thing as an inert, senseless, extended, solid, figured, movable substance existing without the mind, such as philosophers describe Matter--yet, if any man shall leave out of his idea of matter the positive ideas of extension, figure, solidity and motion, and say that he means only by that word an inert, senseless substance, that exists without the mind or unperceived, which is the occasion of our ideas, or at the presence whereof God is pleased to excite ideas in us: it doth not appear but that Matter taken in this sense may possibly exist. In answer to which I say, first, that it seems no less absurd to suppose a substance without accidents, than it is to suppose accidents without a substance. But secondly, though we should grant this unknown substance may possibly exist, yet where can it be supposed to be? That it exists not in the mind is agreed; and that it exists not in place is no less certain--since all place or extension exists only in the mind, as has been already proved. It remains therefore that it exists nowhere at all.

67. TWELFTH OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--In the twelfth point, someone might argue that, even though it’s clear from what has been said that there can’t be an inert, mindless, extended, solid, shaped, movable substance existing outside of the mind, like philosophers describe Matter, if anyone excludes the positive ideas of extension, shape, solidity, and motion from their definition of matter and means only an inert, mindless substance that exists independently or is unobserved, which causes our ideas or prompts God to create ideas in us, then it seems possible that Matter, understood this way, could exist. In response, I first say that it seems just as unreasonable to imagine a substance without properties as it is to imagine properties without a substance. Secondly, even if we accept that this unknown substance might possibly exist, where could it be? It is agreed that it doesn’t exist in the mind, and it’s also certain that it doesn’t exist in space since all space or extension exists only in the mind, as already proven. Therefore, it follows that it exists nowhere at all.

68. MATTER SUPPORTS NOTHING, AN ARGUMENT AGAINST ITS EXISTENCE.--Let us examine a little the description that is here given us of matter. It neither acts, nor perceives, nor is perceived; for this is all that is meant by saying it is an inert, senseless, unknown substance; which is a definition entirely made up of negatives, excepting only the relative notion of its standing under or supporting. But then it must be observed that it supports nothing at all, and how nearly this comes to the description of a nonentity I desire may be considered. But, say you, it is the unknown occasion, at the presence of which ideas are excited in us by the will of God. Now, I would fain know how anything can be present to us, which is neither perceivable by sense nor reflexion, nor capable of producing any idea in our minds, nor is at all extended, nor has any form, nor exists in any place. The words "to be present," when thus applied, must needs be taken in some abstract and strange meaning, and which I am not able to comprehend.

68. MATTER SUPPORTS NOTHING, AN ARGUMENT AGAINST ITS EXISTENCE.--Let’s take a closer look at the description of matter given here. It doesn’t act, perceive, or get perceived; this is what is meant by saying it is an inert, senseless, unknown substance. This definition is entirely made up of negatives, except for the vague idea of it supporting something. However, it must be noted that it supports nothing at all, and we should consider how closely this resembles the description of a nonentity. But you might say it is the unknown cause that triggers ideas in us through the will of God. Now, I’d like to know how anything can be present to us if it can’t be sensed, reflected upon, or cause any ideas in our minds, is not extended, has no form, and doesn’t exist in any specific place. The phrase "to be present," when used in this way, must be taken to mean something abstract and strange, which I cannot grasp.

69. Again, let us examine what is meant by occasion. So far as I can gather from the common use of language, that word signifies either the agent which produces any effect, or else something that is observed to accompany or go before it in the ordinary course of things. But when it is applied to Matter as above described, it can be taken in neither of those senses; for Matter is said to be passive and inert, and so cannot be an agent or efficient cause. It is also unperceivable, as being devoid of all sensible qualities, and so cannot be the occasion of our perceptions in the latter sense: as when the burning my finger is said to be the occasion of the pain that attends it. What therefore can be meant by calling matter an occasion? The term is either used in no sense at all, or else in some very distant from its received signification.

69. Once again, let’s look at what is meant by "occasion." From what I can gather in everyday language, that word refers either to the agent that produces an effect or to something that is usually observed alongside or before it. However, when it comes to Matter as described above, it doesn't fit either of those meanings; Matter is considered passive and inert, and therefore cannot be an agent or effective cause. It's also unobservable because it lacks any sensory qualities, so it can't be the cause of our perceptions in that sense, like when burning my finger is said to be the cause of the pain that comes with it. So what does it mean to call matter an occasion? The term is either not used in any meaningful way, or it is used in a way that is very different from its usual meaning.

70. You will Perhaps say that Matter, though it be not perceived by us, is nevertheless perceived by God, to whom it is the occasion of exciting ideas in our minds. For, say you, since we observe our sensations to be imprinted in an orderly and constant manner, it is but reasonable to suppose there are certain constant and regular occasions of their being produced. That is to say, that there are certain permanent and distinct parcels of Matter, corresponding to our ideas, which, though they do not excite them in our minds, or anywise immediately affect us, as being altogether passive and unperceivable to us, they are nevertheless to God, by whom they art perceived, as it were so many occasions to remind Him when and what ideas to imprint on our minds; that so things may go on in a constant uniform manner.

70. You might say that matter, even if we don't perceive it, is still seen by God, who uses it to trigger ideas in our minds. You argue that because we notice our sensations being recorded in an orderly and consistent way, it makes sense to think there are some constant and regular causes for them. In other words, there are certain permanent and distinct pieces of matter that correspond to our ideas. Although these pieces don't directly trigger our thoughts or affect us in any way since they're entirely passive and unnoticeable to us, they are nonetheless perceived by God. For Him, they serve as reminders of when and what ideas to impress upon our minds, so that things continue in a consistent and uniform way.

71. In answer to this, I observe that, as the notion of Matter is here stated, the question is no longer concerning the existence of a thing distinct from Spirit and idea, from perceiving and being perceived; but whether there are not certain ideas of I know not what sort, in the mind of God which are so many marks or notes that direct Him how to produce sensations in our minds in a constant and regular method--much after the same manner as a musician is directed by the notes of music to produce that harmonious train and composition of sound which is called a tune, though they who hear the music do not perceive the notes, and may be entirely ignorant of them. But, this notion of Matter seems too extravagant to deserve a confutation. Besides, it is in effect no objection against what we have advanced, viz. that there is no senseless unperceived substance.

71. In response to this, I note that, as the idea of Matter is presented here, the issue isn't about the existence of something separate from Spirit and idea, from perceiving and being perceived; rather, it's about whether there are certain ideas of an unknown nature in the mind of God that serve as guides for how to create sensations in our minds in a consistent and orderly way—similar to how a musician follows musical notes to create the harmonious sequence of sound known as a tune, even though those listening to the music do not perceive the notes and may be completely unaware of them. However, this concept of Matter seems too far-fetched to warrant a rebuttal. Furthermore, it effectively poses no challenge to what we've put forward, namely, that there is no mindless, unperceived substance.

72. THE ORDER OF OUR PERCEPTIONS SHOWS THE GOODNESS OF GOD, BUT AFFORDS NO PROOF OF THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER.--If we follow the light of reason, we shall, from the constant uniform method of our sensations, collect the goodness and wisdom of the Spirit who excites them in our minds; but this is all that I can see reasonably concluded from thence. To me, I say, it is evident that the being of a spirit infinitely wise, good, and powerful is abundantly sufficient to explain all the appearances of nature. But, as for inert, senseless Matter, nothing that I perceive has any the least connexion with it, or leads to the thoughts of it. And I would fain see any one explain any the meanest phenomenon in nature by it, or show any manner of reason, though in the lowest rank of probability, that he can have for its existence, or even make any tolerable sense or meaning of that supposition. For, as to its being an occasion, we have, I think, evidently shown that with regard to us it is no occasion. It remains therefore that it must be, if at all, the occasion to God of exciting ideas in us; and what this amounts to we have just now seen.

72. THE ORDER OF OUR PERCEPTIONS SHOWS THE GOODNESS OF GOD, BUT AFFORDS NO PROOF OF THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER.--If we follow reason, we can see that the consistent way our sensations happen reflects the goodness and wisdom of the Spirit that inspires them in our minds; however, that’s all I think we can reasonably conclude. It seems clear to me that the existence of a spirit that is infinitely wise, good, and powerful is more than enough to explain everything we see in nature. But when it comes to lifeless, unfeeling Matter, I see no connection between what I perceive and it, nor do I have any thoughts about it. I would like to see anyone explain even the simplest phenomenon in nature using it or show any kind of reasoning, even the slightest hint of probability, for its existence, or make any reasonable sense of that assumption. As for it being a cause, I believe we’ve clearly shown that it isn’t a cause for us. Therefore, if it exists at all, it must be a cause to God for generating ideas in us; and what that means we’ve just reviewed.

73. It is worth while to reflect a little on the motives which induced men to suppose the existence of material substance; that so having observed the gradual ceasing and expiration of those motives or reasons, we may proportionably withdraw the assent that was grounded on them. First, therefore, it was thought that colour, figure, motion, and the rest of the sensible qualities or accidents, did really exist without the mind; and for this reason it seemed needful to suppose some unthinking substratum or substance wherein they did exist, since they could not be conceived to exist by themselves. Afterwards, in process of time, men being convinced that colours, sounds, and the rest of the sensible, secondary qualities had no existence without the mind, they stripped this substratum or material substance of those qualities, leaving only the primary ones, figure, motion, and suchlike, which they still conceived to exist without the mind, and consequently to stand in need of a material support. But, it having been shown that none even of these can possibly exist otherwise than in a Spirit or Mind which perceives them it follows that we have no longer any reason to suppose the being of Matter; nay, that it is utterly impossible there should be any such thing, so long as that word is taken to denote an unthinking substratum of qualities or accidents wherein they exist without the mind.

73. It's worth taking a moment to think about why people believed in the existence of material substance; by observing the gradual disappearance of those reasons, we can also retract our agreement based on them. First, people thought that color, shape, movement, and other sensory qualities really existed outside of the mind. For this reason, it seemed necessary to assume some unthinking foundation or substance where they existed, since it was hard to imagine them existing on their own. Over time, however, people became convinced that colors, sounds, and other secondary qualities didn’t exist without the mind, so they removed these qualities from the idea of material substance, leaving only the primary qualities like shape and movement, which they still believed existed independently of the mind and needed a material support. But since it has been demonstrated that not even these can exist except within a Spirit or Mind that perceives them, it follows that we have no reason to assume the existence of Matter. In fact, it's completely impossible for such a thing to exist, as long as we understand that term to mean an unthinking foundation of qualities or accidents existing apart from the mind.

74. But though it be allowed by the materialists themselves that Matter was thought of only for the sake of supporting accidents, and, the reason entirely ceasing, one might expect the mind should naturally, and without any reluctance at all, quit the belief of what was solely grounded thereon; yet the prejudice is riveted so deeply in our thoughts, that we can scarce tell how to part with it, and are therefore inclined, since the thing itself is indefensible, at least to retain the name, which we apply to I know not what abstracted and indefinite notions of being, or occasion, though without any show of reason, at least so far as I can see. For, what is there on our part, or what do we perceive, amongst all the ideas, sensations, notions which are imprinted on our minds, either by sense or reflexion, from whence may be inferred the existence of an inert, thoughtless, unperceived occasion? and, on the other hand, on the part of an All-sufficient Spirit, what can there be that should make us believe or even suspect He is directed by an inert occasion to excite ideas in our minds?

74. Even though materialists themselves agree that Matter was thought of mainly to support accidents, and that if the reasoning behind it vanished, we should naturally and easily let go of the belief based solely on that, the bias is so ingrained in our thoughts that we can barely imagine letting it go. Because of this, we tend to keep the term, even though it refers to abstract and vague ideas of being or cause, without much reasoning, at least as far as I can see. So, what evidence do we have, or what do we perceive among all the ideas, sensations, and notions imprinted on our minds by our senses or reflection, that might suggest the existence of an inactive, thoughtless, unrecognized cause? And on the flip side, what could possibly lead us to believe or even suspect that an All-sufficient Spirit is influenced by an inactive cause to generate ideas in our minds?

75. ABSURDITY OF CONTENDING FOR THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER AS THE OCCASION OF IDEAS.--It is a very extraordinary instance of the force of prejudice, and much to be lamented, that the mind of man retains so great a fondness, against all the evidence of reason, for a stupid thoughtless somewhat, by the interposition whereof it would as it were screen itself from the Providence of God, and remove it farther off from the affairs of the world. But, though we do the utmost we can to secure the belief of Matter, though, when reason forsakes us, we endeavour to support our opinion on the bare possibility of the thing, and though we indulge ourselves in the full scope of an imagination not regulated by reason to make out that poor possibility, yet the upshot of all is, that there are certain unknown Ideas in the mind of God; for this, if anything, is all that I conceive to be meant by occasion with regard to God. And this at the bottom is no longer contending for the thing, but for the name.

75. ABSURDITY OF CLAIMING THAT MATTER EXISTS AS THE CAUSE OF IDEAS.--It is truly remarkable how strong our biases can be, and it's unfortunate that people hold onto the idea of a mindless substance, despite all evidence to the contrary. They seem to think that by doing so, they can shield themselves from God’s influence and distance themselves from worldly matters. Yet, even when we try our hardest to believe in Matter, when reason abandons us, we cling to the mere possibility of it. We allow our imaginations to run wild, unchecked by reason, to justify that flimsy possibility. Still, the conclusion is that there are certain unknown Ideas in God’s mind; this is really what I believe is meant by “occasion” in relation to God. Ultimately, this isn’t about defending the concept itself, but rather just the term.

76. Whether therefore there are such Ideas in the mind of God, and whether they may be called by the name Matter, I shall not dispute. But, if you stick to the notion of an unthinking substance or support of extension, motion, and other sensible qualities, then to me it is most evidently impossible there should be any such thing, since it is a plain repugnancy that those qualities should exist in or be supported by an unperceiving substance.

76. Whether there are such ideas in the mind of God and whether we can call them Matter is not something I will contest. However, if you cling to the idea of a mindless substance or a basis for extension, motion, and other observable qualities, then I find it completely impossible for such a thing to exist. It’s clearly contradictory for those qualities to exist in or be supported by a substance that doesn’t perceive.

77. THAT A SUBSTRATUM NOT PERCEIVED, MAY EXIST, UNIMPORTANT.--But, say you, though it be granted that there is no thoughtless support of extension and the other qualities or accidents which we perceive, yet there may perhaps be some inert, unperceiving substance or substratum of some other qualities, as incomprehensible to us as colours are to a man born blind, because we have not a sense adapted to them. But, if we had a new sense, we should possibly no more doubt of their existence than a blind man made to see does of the existence of light and colours. I answer, first, if what you mean by the word Matter be only the unknown support of unknown qualities, it is no matter whether there is such a thing or no, since it no way concerns us; and I do not see the advantage there is in disputing about what we know not what, and we know not why.

77. THAT AN UNSEEN FOUNDATION MAY EXIST, BUT IT DOESN'T MATTER.--However, you might say, even if we agree that there’s no thoughtless support for the extension and the other qualities or features we perceive, there could still be some inert, unobserved substance or foundation of other qualities, as incomprehensible to us as colors are to someone born blind, because we don’t have a sense tuned to them. But if we had a new sense, we might not doubt their existence any more than a blind person who gains sight would doubt the existence of light and colors. My response is, first, if by "Matter" you mean only the unknown support of unknown qualities, then it doesn’t really matter whether such a thing exists or not, since it doesn’t concern us. I don’t see the point in arguing about what we can't define or understand.

78. But, secondly, if we had a new sense it could only furnish us with new ideas or sensations; and then we should have the same reason against their existing in an unperceiving substance that has been already offered with relation to figure, motion, colour and the like. Qualities, as has been shown, are nothing else but sensations or ideas, which exist only in a mind perceiving them; and this is true not only of the ideas we are acquainted with at present, but likewise of all possible ideas whatsoever.

78. But, secondly, if we had a new sense, it could only give us new ideas or sensations; and we would have the same argument against their existing in a non-perceiving substance that has already been presented regarding shape, movement, color, and similar qualities. As has been shown, qualities are nothing more than sensations or ideas that exist only in a mind that perceives them; and this is true not only of the ideas we currently know, but also of all possible ideas in general.

79. But, you will insist, what if I have no reason to believe the existence of Matter? what if I cannot assign any use to it or explain anything by it, or even conceive what is meant by that word? yet still it is no contradiction to say that Matter exists, and that this Matter is in general a substance, or occasion of ideas; though indeed to go about to unfold the meaning or adhere to any particular explication of those words may be attended with great difficulties. I answer, when words are used without a meaning, you may put them together as you please without danger of running into a contradiction. You may say, for example, that twice two is equal to seven, so long as you declare you do not take the words of that proposition in their usual acceptation but for marks of you know not what. And, by the same reason, you may say there is an inert thoughtless substance without accidents which is the occasion of our ideas. And we shall understand just as much by one proposition as the other.

79. But you'll ask, what if I have no reason to believe in the existence of Matter? What if I can't find any use for it or explain anything through it, or even grasp what that word means? Still, it doesn't contradict to say that Matter exists, and that this Matter is generally a substance or a source of ideas; although trying to explain or stick to any specific meaning of those words can be quite challenging. I respond that when words are used without meaning, you can put them together however you want without the risk of contradicting yourself. For instance, you could say that two plus two equals seven, as long as you make it clear that you aren’t using those words in their usual sense but as symbols for something you can’t define. By the same logic, you could say there is a lifeless, thoughtless substance without properties that causes our ideas. And we would understand just as much from one statement as we would from the other.

80. In the last place, you will say, what if we give up the cause of material Substance, and stand to it that Matter is an unknown somewhat--neither substance nor accident, spirit nor idea, inert, thoughtless, indivisible, immovable, unextended, existing in no place. For, say you, whatever may be urged against substance or occasion, or any other positive or relative notion of Matter, has no place at all, so long as this negative definition of Matter is adhered to. I answer, you may, if so it shall seem good, use the word "Matter" in the same sense as other men use "nothing," and so make those terms convertible in your style. For, after all, this is what appears to me to be the result of that definition, the parts whereof when I consider with attention, either collectively or separate from each other, I do not find that there is any kind of effect or impression made on my mind different from what is excited by the term nothing.

80. Lastly, you might ask, what if we abandon the idea of material substance and insist that matter is something unknown—neither substance nor accident, spirit nor idea, lifeless, thoughtless, indivisible, unmovable, not extended, and existing nowhere? Because, you say, no arguments against substance, occasion, or any other positive or relative concept of matter hold any weight as long as we stick to this negative definition of matter. In response, you can, if it seems appropriate, use the word "matter" just like other people use "nothing," making those terms interchangeable in your writing. Ultimately, this seems to me to be the outcome of that definition; when I consider its parts, whether together or individually, I don't find any effect or impression on my mind that differs from what is evoked by the term nothing.

81. You will reply, perhaps, that in the fore-said definition is included what doth sufficiently distinguish it from nothing--the positive abstract idea of quiddity, entity, or existence. I own, indeed, that those who pretend to the faculty of framing abstract general ideas do talk as if they had such an idea, which is, say they, the most abstract and general notion of all; that is, to me, the most incomprehensible of all others. That there are a great variety of spirits of different orders and capacities, whose faculties both in number and extent are far exceeding those the Author of my being has bestowed on me, I see no reason to deny. And for me to pretend to determine by my own few, stinted narrow inlets of perception, what ideas the inexhaustible power of the Supreme Spirit may imprint upon them were certainly the utmost folly and presumption--since there may be, for aught that I know, innumerable sorts of ideas or sensations, as different from one another, and from all that I have perceived, as colours are from sounds. But, how ready soever I may be to acknowledge the scantiness of my comprehension with regard to the endless variety of spirits and ideas that may possibly exist, yet for any one to pretend to a notion of Entity or Existence, abstracted from spirit and idea, from perceived and being perceived, is, I suspect, a downright repugnancy and trifling with words.--It remains that we consider the objections which may possibly be made on the part of Religion.

81. You might respond that the definition mentioned above includes what clearly sets it apart from nothing—the positive abstract idea of essence, being, or existence. I admit that those who claim to have the ability to create abstract general ideas often speak as if they possess such a concept, which they say is the most abstract and general of all; to me, it's the most incomprehensible of them all. I see no reason to deny that there are many different kinds of beings with various abilities, far beyond what the Creator has given me. It would be the height of folly and arrogance for me to think I could determine what ideas the limitless power of the Supreme Spirit might impress on them, since there could be, for all I know, countless kinds of ideas or sensations that are as different from each other and from everything I’ve experienced as colors are from sounds. However willing I am to acknowledge the limits of my understanding regarding the endless variety of spirits and ideas that might exist, I suspect that anyone claiming to have a notion of Being or Existence, separate from spirit and ideas, from what is perceived and what perceives, is simply being contradictory and playing with words. —Now, let's consider the objections that might arise from the perspective of Religion.

82. OBJECTIONS DERIVED FROM THE SCRIPTURES ANSWERED.--Some there are who think that, though the arguments for the real existence of bodies which are drawn from Reason be allowed not to amount to demonstration, yet the Holy Scriptures are so clear in the point as will sufficiently convince every good Christian that bodies do really exist, and are something more than mere ideas; there being in Holy Writ innumerable facts related which evidently suppose the reality of timber and stone, mountains and rivers, and cities, and human bodies. To which I answer that no sort of writings whatever, sacred or profane, which use those and the like words in the vulgar acceptation, or so as to have a meaning in them, are in danger of having their truth called in question by our doctrine. That all those things do really exist, that there are bodies, even corporeal substances, when taken in the vulgar sense, has been shown to be agreeable to our principles; and the difference betwixt things and ideas, realities and chimeras, has been distinctly explained. See sect. 29, 30, 33, 36, &c. And I do not think that either what philosophers call Matter, or the existence of objects without the mind, is anywhere mentioned in Scripture.

82. OBJECTIONS DERIVED FROM THE SCRIPTURES ANSWERED.--Some people believe that, even if the arguments for the real existence of objects based on Reason don't fully convince, the Holy Scriptures make it clear enough to convince any good Christian that bodies truly exist and are more than just ideas. The Bible contains countless accounts that clearly imply the reality of wood and stone, mountains and rivers, cities, and human bodies. In response, I argue that no type of writing, whether sacred or secular, that uses those words in their common meaning or in a way that conveys meaning, is at risk of having its truth challenged by our beliefs. It has been demonstrated that all these things do indeed exist and that there are bodies, even physical substances, in the everyday sense, which aligns with our principles. The distinction between things and ideas, realities and fantasies, has been clearly explained. See sect. 29, 30, 33, 36, &c. Additionally, I don't believe that what philosophers refer to as Matter or the existence of objects outside the mind is mentioned anywhere in Scripture.

83. NO OBJECTION AS TO LANGUAGE TENABLE.--Again, whether there can be or be not external things, it is agreed on all hands that the proper use of words is the marking our conceptions, or things only as they are known and perceived by us; whence it plainly follows that in the tenets we have laid down there is nothing inconsistent with the right use and significancy of language, and that discourse, of what kind soever, so far as it is intelligible, remains undisturbed. But all this seems so manifest, from what has been largely set forth in the premises, that it is needless to insist any farther on it.

83. NO OBJECTION AS TO LANGUAGE TENABLE.--Again, whether or not there are external things, everyone agrees that the proper use of words marks our ideas or things only as we know and perceive them; thus, it clearly follows that the principles we've established are consistent with the correct use and meaning of language, and that any form of discourse, as long as it's understandable, remains unaffected. But all of this seems so obvious, based on what has already been discussed, that it’s unnecessary to dwell on it any further.

84. But, secondly it will be urged that miracles do, at least, lose much of their stress and import by our principles. What must we think of Moses' rod? was it not really turned into a serpent; or was there only a change of ideas in the minds of the spectators? And, can it be supposed that our Saviour did no more at the marriage-feast in Cana than impose on the sight, and smell, and taste of the guests, so as to create in them the appearance or idea only of wine? The same may be said of all other miracles; which, in consequence of the foregoing principles, must be looked upon only as so many cheats, or illusions of fancy. To this I reply, that the rod was changed into a real serpent, and the water into real wine. That this does not in the least contradict what I have elsewhere said will be evident from sect. 34 and 35. But this business of real and imaginary has been already so plainly and fully explained, and so often referred to, and the difficulties about it are so easily answered from what has gone before, that it were an affront to the reader's understanding to resume the explication of it in its place. I shall only observe that if at table all who were present should see, and smell, and taste, and drink wine, and find the effects of it, with me there could be no doubt of its reality; so that at bottom the scruple concerning real miracles has no place at all on ours, but only on the received principles, and consequently makes rather for than against what has been said.

84. But, secondly, some might argue that miracles lose a lot of their significance and importance because of our beliefs. What should we think of Moses' rod? Was it actually turned into a serpent, or was it just a change in perception for the people watching? And can we really believe that our Savior did no more at the wedding in Cana than to fool the guests' sight, smell, and taste into thinking they had wine? The same could be said about all other miracles, which, based on the previous principles, would just be seen as tricks or illusions. I respond by saying that the rod was transformed into a real serpent, and the water became real wine. This doesn’t contradict what I've previously stated, as will be clear from sections 34 and 35. The distinction between what is real and what is imaginary has already been explained quite clearly and thoroughly, and the issues surrounding it can be easily resolved based on earlier discussions, so it would be an insult to the reader's intelligence to revisit it here. I will just point out that if everyone at the table could see, smell, taste, and drink the wine, experiencing its effects, there could be no doubt about its reality; therefore, the concern about real miracles doesn’t really apply to us, but only to accepted principles, and actually supports what has been said rather than contradicts it.

85. CONSEQUENCES OF THE PRECEDING TENETS.--Having done with the Objections, which I endeavoured to propose in the clearest light, and gave them all the force and weight I could, we proceed in the next place to take a view of our tenets in their Consequences. Some of these appear at first sight--as that several difficult and obscure questions, on which abundance of speculation has been thrown away, are entirely banished from philosophy. "Whether corporeal substance can think," "whether Matter be infinitely divisible," and "how it operates on spirit"--these and like inquiries have given infinite amusement to philosophers in all ages; but depending on the existence of Matter, they have no longer any place on our principles. Many other advantages there are, as well with regard to religion as the sciences, which it is easy for any one to deduce from what has been premised; but this will appear more plainly in the sequel.

85. CONSEQUENCES OF THE PRECEDING TENETS.--Now that we've dealt with the objections, which I tried to present as clearly as possible and gave all the weight I could, we will next look at our tenets and their consequences. Some of these become obvious right away—like how several complex and unclear questions that have sparked endless speculation are completely removed from philosophy. "Can physical substance think?" "Is matter infinitely divisible?" and "How does it interact with the mind?"—these and similar questions have entertained philosophers throughout history; however, since they depend on the existence of matter, they no longer fit within our principles. There are many other benefits, both for religion and the sciences, that anyone can easily deduce from what we've discussed; but this will be clearer as we continue.

86. THE REMOVAL OF MATTER GIVES CERTAINTY TO KNOWLEDGE.--From the principles we have laid down it follows human knowledge may naturally be reduced to two heads--that of ideas and that of spirits. Of each of these I shall treat in order.

86. THE REMOVAL OF MATTER GIVES CERTAINTY TO KNOWLEDGE.--Based on the principles we've established, human knowledge can naturally be categorized into two main areas: the realm of ideas and the realm of spirits. I will discuss each of these in turn.

And first as to ideas or unthinking things. Our knowledge of these has been very much obscured and confounded, and we have been led into very dangerous errors, by supposing a twofold existence of the objects of sense--the one intelligible or in the mind, the other real and without the mind; whereby unthinking things are thought to have a natural subsistence of their own distinct from being perceived by spirits. This, which, if I mistake not, has been shown to be a most groundless and absurd notion, is the very root of Scepticism; for, so long as men thought that real things subsisted without the mind, and that their knowledge was only so far forth real as it was conformable to real things, it follows they could not be certain they had any real knowledge at all. For how can it be known that the things which are perceived are conformable to those which are not perceived, or exist without the mind?

And first, regarding ideas or things that don't think. Our understanding of these has been greatly obscured and confused, leading us into dangerous mistakes by assuming there are two types of existence for the objects we sense—one that’s understandable or in our mind, and another that’s real and outside of our mind. This idea, which I believe has been shown to be completely unfounded and ridiculous, is the very root of skepticism; for as long as people believed that real things existed independently of the mind, and that their knowledge was only valid if it matched these real things, it follows that they could never be sure they had any real knowledge at all. How can we know that the things we perceive correspond to those that we don’t perceive, or that exist outside of our mind?

87. Colour, figure, motion, extension, and the like, considered only as so many sensations in the mind, are perfectly known, there being nothing in them which is not perceived. But, if they are looked on as notes or images, referred to things or archetypes existing without the mind, then are we involved all in scepticism. We see only the appearances, and not the real qualities of things. What may be the extension, figure, or motion of anything really and absolutely, or in itself, it is impossible for us to know, but only the proportion or relation they bear to our senses. Things remaining the same, our ideas vary, and which of them, or even whether any of them at all, represent the true quality really existing in the thing, it is out of our reach to determine. So that, for aught we know, all we see, hear, and feel may be only phantom and vain chimera, and not at all agree with the real things existing in rerum natura. All this scepticism follows from our supposing a difference between things and ideas, and that the former have a subsistence without the mind or unperceived. It were easy to dilate on this subject, and show how the arguments urged by sceptics in all ages depend on the supposition of external objects.

87. Colors, shapes, movement, size, and similar things, when considered solely as sensations in the mind, are completely understood, as there’s nothing in them that isn’t perceived. However, if we view them as signs or images linked to objects or ideal forms that exist outside of our minds, we fall into skepticism. We only see appearances, not the true qualities of things. We can't know what the real size, shape, or movement of anything is, or what it is in itself; we can only understand the way they relate to our senses. As things stay the same, our ideas change, and we cannot determine which of our ideas, if any, truly reflects the real qualities of the thing. For all we know, everything we see, hear, and feel could just be a mere illusion and might not correspond at all to the things that really exist in the world. This skepticism arises from assuming a distinction between things and ideas, and that the former exist independently of the mind or are unperceived. It would be easy to elaborate on this topic and demonstrate how the arguments made by skeptics throughout history rely on the assumption of external objects.

88. IF THERE BE EXTERNAL MATTER, NEITHER THE NATURE NOR EXISTENCE OF THINGS CAN BE KNOWN.--So long as we attribute a real existence to unthinking things, distinct from their being perceived, it is not only impossible for us to know with evidence the nature of any real unthinking being, but even that it exists. Hence it is that we see philosophers distrust their senses, and doubt of the existence of heaven and earth, of everything they see or feel, even of their own bodies. And, after all their labour and struggle of thought, they are forced to own we cannot attain to any self-evident or demonstrative knowledge of the existence of sensible things. But, all this doubtfulness, which so bewilders and confounds the mind and makes philosophy ridiculous in the eyes of the world, vanishes if we annex a meaning to our words, and not amuse ourselves with the terms "absolute," "external," "exist," and such-like, signifying we know not what. I can as well doubt of my own being as of the being of those things which I actually perceive by sense; it being a manifest contradiction that any sensible object should be immediately perceived by sight or touch, and at the same time have no existence in nature, since the very existence of an unthinking being consists in being perceived.

88. IF THERE IS EXTERNAL MATTER, NEITHER THE NATURE NOR EXISTENCE OF THINGS CAN BE KNOWN.--As long as we believe that unthinking things have a real existence separate from being perceived, it's impossible for us to clearly understand the nature of any real unthinking being or even confirm that it exists. That's why we see philosophers question their senses and doubt the existence of heaven and earth, of everything they see or feel, even their own bodies. After all their effort and mental struggle, they have to admit that we can't achieve any self-evident or demonstrative knowledge about the existence of sensible things. But all of this uncertainty, which confuses and baffles the mind and makes philosophy seem ridiculous to the world, goes away if we attach clear meanings to our words, instead of getting caught up in terms like "absolute," "external," "exist," and similar ones that we don't fully understand. I can doubt my own existence just as easily as I can doubt the existence of the things I actually perceive through my senses; it contradicts reason that any object should be directly perceived by sight or touch, yet have no existence in reality, since an unthinking being's existence relies on being perceived.

89. OF THING OR BEING.--Nothing seems of more importance towards erecting a firm system of sound and real knowledge, which may be proof against the assaults of Scepticism, than to lay the beginning in a distinct explication of what is meant by thing, reality, existence; for in vain shall we dispute concerning the real existence of things, or pretend to any knowledge thereof, so long as we have not fixed the meaning of those words. Thing or Being is the most general name of all; it comprehends under it two kinds entirely distinct and heterogeneous, and which have nothing common but the name. viz. spirits and ideas. The former are active, indivisible substances: the latter are inert, fleeting, dependent beings, which subsist not by themselves, but are supported by, or exist in minds or spiritual substances. We comprehend our own existence by inward feeling or reflexion, and that of other spirits by reason. We may be said to have some knowledge or notion of our own minds, of spirits and active beings, whereof in a strict sense we have not ideas. In like manner, we know and have a notion of relations between things or ideas--which relations are distinct from the ideas or things related, inasmuch as the latter may be perceived by us without our perceiving the former. To me it seems that ideas, spirits, and relations are all in their respective kinds the object of human knowledge and subject of discourse; and that the term idea would be improperly extended to signify everything we know or have any notion of.

89. OF THING OR BEING.--Nothing seems more important for establishing a solid system of sound and genuine knowledge that can withstand the challenges of Scepticism than starting with a clear explanation of what is meant by thing, reality, or existence. It’s pointless to argue about the real existence of things or claim to have any knowledge of it as long as we haven't clearly defined those terms. Thing or Being is the broadest term of all; it includes two completely distinct and different kinds, which share nothing in common except the name: spirits and ideas. The former are active, indivisible substances, while the latter are inert, fleeting, dependent beings that do not exist on their own but are supported by or exist in minds or spiritual substances. We understand our own existence through inner feeling or reflection, and the existence of other spirits through reason. We can be said to have some knowledge or notion of our own minds, as well as spirits and active beings, even though in a strict sense we do not have ideas about them. Similarly, we know and have a notion of the relationships between things or ideas—these relationships are distinct from the ideas or things they connect, as we can perceive the latter without necessarily perceiving the former. It seems to me that ideas, spirits, and relationships are all, in their own ways, objects of human knowledge and subjects for discussion; and it would be incorrect to use the term idea to mean everything we know or have any notion of.

90. EXTERNAL THINGS EITHER IMPRINTED BY OR PERCEIVED BY SOME OTHER MIND.--Ideas imprinted on the senses are real things, or do really exist; this we do not deny, but we deny they can subsist without the minds which perceive them, or that they are resemblances of any archetypes existing without the mind; since the very being of a sensation or idea consists in being perceived, and an idea can be like nothing but an idea. Again, the things perceived by sense may be termed external, with regard to their origin--in that they are not generated from within by the mind itself, but imprinted by a Spirit distinct from that which perceives them. Sensible objects may likewise be said to be "without the mind" in another sense, namely when they exist in some other mind; thus, when I shut my eyes, the things I saw may still exist, but it must be in another mind.

90. EXTERNAL THINGS EITHER IMPRINTED BY OR PERCEIVED BY SOME OTHER MIND.--Ideas that are imprinted on our senses are real and do actually exist; we acknowledge this, but we reject the idea that they can exist independently of the minds that perceive them, or that they are copies of any archetypes that exist outside of the mind. The essence of a sensation or idea is in being perceived, and an idea can't be anything other than another idea. Additionally, the things we perceive through our senses can be called external in terms of their origin—because they aren't created from within our own minds, but are imprinted by a Spirit different from the one that perceives them. Sensible objects can also be considered "outside the mind" in another sense, meaning that they exist in some other mind; for example, when I close my eyes, what I saw might still exist, but only in someone else's mind.

91. SENSIBLE QUALITIES REAL.--It were a mistake to think that what is here said derogates in the least from the reality of things. It is acknowledged, on the received principles, that extension, motion, and in a word all sensible qualities have need of a support, as not being able to subsist by themselves. But the objects perceived by sense are allowed to be nothing but combinations of those qualities, and consequently cannot subsist by themselves. Thus far it is agreed on all hand. So that in denying the things perceived by sense an existence independent of a substance of support wherein they may exist, we detract nothing from the received opinion of their reality, and are guilty of no innovation in that respect. All the difference is that, according to us, the unthinking beings perceived by sense have no existence distinct from being perceived, and cannot therefore exist in any other substance than those unextended indivisible substances or spirits which act and think and perceive them; whereas philosophers vulgarly hold that the sensible qualities do exist in an inert, extended, unperceiving substance which they call Matter, to which they attribute a natural subsistence, exterior to all thinking beings, or distinct from being perceived by any mind whatsoever, even the eternal mind of the Creator, wherein they suppose only ideas of the corporeal substances created by him; if indeed they allow them to be at all created.

91. SENSIBLE QUALITIES REAL.--It would be a mistake to think that what is said here in any way undermines the reality of things. It is accepted based on common principles that extension, motion, and, in general, all sensible qualities need some sort of support, as they cannot exist on their own. However, the objects we perceive through our senses are understood to be nothing but combinations of these qualities and thus cannot exist by themselves. So far, everyone agrees. Therefore, by denying perceived entities an existence independent of a supportive substance in which they can exist, we take nothing away from the widely held view of their reality and are not introducing any new ideas in that regard. The only difference is that, in our view, the unthinking entities perceived by our senses do not have an existence separate from being perceived, and so cannot exist in anything other than those unextended, indivisible substances or spirits that act, think, and perceive them. Meanwhile, most philosophers commonly believe that sensible qualities do exist in an inert, extended, unperceiving substance they call Matter, which they attribute a natural existence to, outside of all thinking beings, or separate from being perceived by any mind, including the eternal mind of the Creator. They suggest that the Creator only has ideas of the corporeal substances He has created, if they even accept that these substances were created at all.

92. OBJECTIONS OF ATHEISTS OVERTURNED.--For, as we have shown the doctrine of Matter or corporeal substance to have been the main pillar and support of Scepticism, so likewise upon the same foundation have been raised all the impious schemes of Atheism and Irreligion. Nay, so great a difficulty has it been thought to conceive Matter produced out of nothing, that the most celebrated among the ancient philosophers, even of those who maintained the being of a God, have thought Matter to be uncreated and co-eternal with Him. How great a friend material substance has been to Atheists in all ages were needless to relate. All their monstrous systems have so visible and necessary a dependence on it that, when this corner-stone is once removed, the whole fabric cannot choose but fall to the ground, insomuch that it is no longer worth while to bestow a particular consideration on the absurdities of every wretched sect of Atheists.

92. OBJECTIONS OF ATHEISTS OVERTURNED.--As we have shown that the concept of Matter or physical substance is a key foundation for Scepticism, it is also the basis for all the impious beliefs of Atheism and Irreligion. In fact, it has been so challenging to imagine Matter coming from nothing that even the most well-known ancient philosophers, some of whom believed in God, considered Matter to be uncreated and co-eternal with Him. It’s unnecessary to detail how much Material substance has supported Atheists throughout history. Their bizarre theories depend so heavily on it that when this cornerstone is removed, the whole structure is bound to collapse, making it pointless to address the absurdities of each miserable sect of Atheists individually.

93. AND OF FATALISTS ALSO.--That impious and profane persons should readily fall in with those systems which favour their inclinations, by deriding immaterial substance, and supposing the soul to be divisible and subject to corruption as the body; which exclude all freedom, intelligence, and design from the formation of things, and instead thereof make a self--existent, stupid, unthinking substance the root and origin of all beings; that they should hearken to those who deny a Providence, or inspection of a Superior Mind over the affairs of the world, attributing the whole series of events either to blind chance or fatal necessity arising from the impulse of one body or another--all this is very natural. And, on the other hand, when men of better principles observe the enemies of religion lay so great a stress on unthinking Matter, and all of them use so much industry and artifice to reduce everything to it, methinks they should rejoice to see them deprived of their grand support, and driven from that only fortress, without which your Epicureans, Hobbists, and the like, have not even the shadow of a pretence, but become the most cheap and easy triumph in the world.

93. AND OF FATALISTS ALSO.--It's not surprising that irreverent and disrespectful individuals easily align with ideas that cater to their desires, mocking the concept of immaterial substance and believing the soul can be divided and corrupted like the body; they dismiss all notions of freedom, intelligence, and purpose in the creation of things, instead claiming that a self-existent, mindless substance is the foundation of all existence. They listen to those who deny a guiding Providence or the oversight of a Superior Mind over worldly affairs, attributing everything that happens to random chance or inevitable necessity driven by the motion of one body or another—this is all very natural. Conversely, when individuals with better values see the enemies of religion placing so much importance on mindless Matter and utilizing so much effort to reduce everything to that, I think they should take pleasure in witnessing these opponents stripped of their main support and expelled from that only stronghold; without it, your Epicureans, Hobbists, and similar thinkers have no real argument and become the most effortless victory in the world.

94. OF IDOLATORS.--The existence of Matter, or bodies unperceived, has not only been the main support of Atheists and Fatalists, but on the same principle doth Idolatry likewise in all its various forms depend. Did men but consider that the sun, moon, and stars, and every other object of the senses are only so many sensations in their minds, which have no other existence but barely being perceived, doubtless they would never fall down and worship their own ideas, but rather address their homage to that ETERNAL INVISIBLE MIND which produces and sustains all things.

94. OF IDOLATORS.--The existence of matter, or bodies that we can't perceive, has not only been the main support for atheists and fatalists, but idolatry in all its different forms relies on the same principle. If people realized that the sun, moon, and stars, as well as every other sensory object, are just sensations in their minds that only exist because they are perceived, they would definitely stop worshiping their own ideas and instead pay tribute to that ETERNAL INVISIBLE MIND that creates and sustains everything.

95. AND SOCINIANS.--The same absurd principle, by mingling itself with the articles of our faith, has occasioned no small difficulties to Christians. For example, about the Resurrection, how many scruples and objections have been raised by Socinians and others? But do not the most plausible of them depend on the supposition that a body is denominated the same, with regard not to the form or that which is perceived by sense, but the material substance, which remains the same under several forms? Take away this material substance, about the identity whereof all the dispute is, and mean by body what every plain ordinary person means by that word, to wit, that which is immediately seen and felt, which is only a combination of sensible qualities or ideas, and then their most unanswerable objections come to nothing.

95. AND SOCINIANS.--The same ridiculous idea, by mixing in with the beliefs we hold, has caused many challenges for Christians. For instance, regarding the Resurrection, how many doubts and criticisms have been raised by Socinians and others? But don't the most convincing of their arguments rely on the assumption that a body is considered the same, not based on its form or sensory perception, but on the material substance that remains unchanged despite different shapes? Remove this material substance, which is at the heart of all the debates, and interpret body as any ordinary person would—referring to what we can see and touch, which is just a collection of observable qualities or ideas—and then their strongest objections fall apart.

96. SUMMARY OF THE CONSEQUENCES OF EXPELLING MATTER.--Matter being once expelled out of nature drags with it so many sceptical and impious notions, such an incredible number of disputes and puzzling questions, which have been thorns in the sides of divines as well as philosophers, and made so much fruitless work for mankind, that if the arguments we have produced against it are not found equal to demonstration (as to me they evidently seem), yet I am sure all friends to knowledge, peace, and religion have reason to wish they were.

96. SUMMARY OF THE CONSEQUENCES OF EXPELLING MATTER.--Once matter is removed from nature, it brings along many skeptical and disrespectful ideas, along with countless disputes and confusing questions. These have caused frustration for both theologians and philosophers and have resulted in much wasted effort for humanity. Even if the arguments we’ve presented against this are not seen as definitive (though they seem clear to me), I believe that all who value knowledge, peace, and religion have good reason to hope they are.

97. Beside the external existence of the objects of perception, another great source of errors and difficulties with regard to ideal knowledge is the doctrine of abstract ideas, such as it has been set forth in the Introduction. The plainest things in the world, those we are most intimately acquainted with and perfectly know, when they are considered in an abstract way, appear strangely difficult and incomprehensible. Time, place, and motion, taken in particular or concrete, are what everybody knows, but, having passed through the hands of a metaphysician, they become too abstract and fine to be apprehended by men of ordinary sense. Bid your servant meet you at such a time in such a place, and he shall never stay to deliberate on the meaning of those words; in conceiving that particular time and place, or the motion by which he is to get thither, he finds not the least difficulty. But if time be taken exclusive of all those particular actions and ideas that diversify the day, merely for the continuation of existence or duration in abstract, then it will perhaps gravel even a philosopher to comprehend it.

97. In addition to the external existence of the things we perceive, another major source of errors and challenges regarding ideal knowledge is the idea of abstract concepts, as discussed in the Introduction. The simplest things in the world, the ones we know best and understand perfectly, can seem surprisingly complicated and confusing when looked at abstractly. Time, place, and motion, when considered in specific or concrete terms, are things everyone understands, but when they are analyzed by a metaphysician, they become overly abstract and refined for the average person to grasp. If you ask your servant to meet you at a certain time and place, they won’t hesitate to figure out what that means; in imagining that specific time and place, or the movement needed to get there, there's no difficulty at all. However, if time is considered without all the particular actions and ideas that fill the day, just as a measure of continued existence or duration in the abstract, it may even confuse a philosopher trying to understand it.

98. DILEMMA.--For my own part, whenever I attempt to frame a simple idea of time, abstracted from the succession of ideas in my mind, which flows uniformly and is participated by all beings, I am lost and embrangled in inextricable difficulties. I have no notion of it at all, only I hear others say it is infinitely divisible, and speak of it in such a manner as leads me to entertain odd thoughts of my existence; since that doctrine lays one under an absolute necessity of thinking, either that he passes away innumerable ages without a thought, or else that he is annihilated every moment of his life, both which seem equally absurd. Time therefore being nothing, abstracted from the sucession of ideas in our minds, it follows that the duration of any finite spirit must be estimated by the number of ideas or actions succeeding each other in that same spirit or mind. Hence, it is a plain consequence that the soul always thinks; and in truth whoever shall go about to divide in his thoughts, or abstract the existence of a spirit from its cogitation, will, I believe, find it no easy task.

98. DILEMMA.--For me, whenever I try to come up with a clear idea of time, separate from the sequence of thoughts in my mind, which flows consistently and is shared by all beings, I get completely lost and tangled in impossible problems. I have no real idea of it; I only hear others say it's infinitely divisible and talk about it in ways that make me think strange things about my existence. This concept forces one to consider either that they pass countless ages without thinking or that they are being annihilated every moment of their life—both of which seem equally ridiculous. Therefore, time is nothing when separated from the flow of ideas in our minds, which means the duration of any finite spirit must be measured by the number of ideas or actions that follow each other in that same spirit or mind. Thus, it’s clear that the soul is always thinking; and honestly, anyone who tries to separate the existence of a spirit from its thinking will find it quite a challenge.

99. So likewise when we attempt to abstract extension and motion from all other qualities, and consider them by themselves, we presently lose sight of them, and run into great extravagances. All which depend on a twofold abstraction; first, it is supposed that extension, for example, may be abstracted from all other sensible qualities; and secondly, that the entity of extension may be abstracted from its being perceived. But, whoever shall reflect, and take care to understand what he says, will, if I mistake not, acknowledge that all sensible qualities are alike sensations and alike real; that where the extension is, there is the colour, too, i.e., in his mind, and that their archetypes can exist only in some other mind; and that the objects of sense are nothing but those sensations combined, blended, or (if one may so speak) concreted together; none of all which can be supposed to exist unperceived.

99. Similarly, when we try to separate extension and motion from all other qualities and look at them individually, we quickly lose track of them and end up with some wild ideas. This all relies on two kinds of abstraction; first, it’s assumed that extension, for instance, can be separated from all other sensory qualities, and second, that the idea of extension can exist independently of being perceived. But anyone who thinks carefully about this and understands what they’re saying will recognize, if I’m not mistaken, that all sensory qualities are equally sensations and equally real; that where there is extension, there is also color, meaning in the observer's mind, and that their true forms can only exist in another mind. The objects of our senses are really just those sensations combined, blended, or, if you will, merged together; none of which can be thought to exist without being perceived.

100. What it is for a man to be happy, or an object good, every one may think he knows. But to frame an abstract idea of happiness, prescinded from all particular pleasure, or of goodness from everything that is good, this is what few can pretend to. So likewise a man may be just and virtuous without having precise ideas of justice and virtue. The opinion that those and the like words stand for general notions, abstracted from all particular persons and actions, seems to have rendered morality very difficult, and the study thereof of small use to mankind. And in effect the doctrine of abstraction has not a little contributed towards spoiling the most useful parts of knowledge.

100. Everyone thinks they know what it means for a person to be happy or what makes something good. But creating an abstract idea of happiness, separate from specific pleasures, or of goodness, apart from everything that is good, is something few can manage. Similarly, a person can be just and virtuous without having clear definitions of justice and virtue. The belief that these words represent general ideas, disconnected from specific individuals and actions, seems to have made morality very challenging and its study of little benefit to people. In fact, the concept of abstraction has significantly harmed some of the most valuable areas of knowledge.

101. OF NATURAL PHILOSOPHY AND MATHEMATICS.--The two great provinces of speculative science conversant about ideas received from sense, are Natural Philosophy and Mathematics; with regard to each of these I shall make some observations. And first I shall say somewhat of Natural Philosophy. On this subject it is that the sceptics triumph. All that stock of arguments they produce to depreciate our faculties and make mankind appear ignorant and low, are drawn principally from this head, namely, that we are under an invincible blindness as to the true and real nature of things. This they exaggerate, and love to enlarge on. We are miserably bantered, say they, by our senses, and amused only with the outside and show of things. The real essence, the internal qualities and constitution of every the meanest object, is hid from our view; something there is in every drop of water, every grain of sand, which it is beyond the power of human understanding to fathom or comprehend. But, it is evident from what has been shown that all this complaint is groundless, and that we are influenced by false principles to that degree as to mistrust our senses, and think we know nothing of those things which we perfectly comprehend.

101. OF NATURAL PHILOSOPHY AND MATHEMATICS.--The two main areas of speculative science that deal with ideas we get from our senses are Natural Philosophy and Mathematics. I’ll share some thoughts on each of these. First, I’ll talk about Natural Philosophy. This is where skeptics tend to excel. The arguments they use to undermine our abilities and make humanity seem uninformed and trivial mainly come from this area, arguing that we are completely blind to the true and real nature of things. They exaggerate this idea and love to emphasize it. They claim that we are sadly misled by our senses, focused only on the surface and appearance of things. The true essence, internal qualities, and structure of even the simplest object are hidden from us; there’s something in every drop of water and every grain of sand that human understanding cannot grasp or fully comprehend. However, it’s clear from what has been discussed that these complaints are unfounded, and we are swayed by false beliefs to the point where we doubt our senses and assume we know nothing about things we actually understand perfectly.

102. One great inducement to our pronouncing ourselves ignorant of the nature of things is the current opinion that everything includes within itself the cause of its properties; or that there is in each object an inward essence which is the source whence its discernible qualities flow, and whereon they depend. Some have pretended to account for appearances by occult qualities, but of late they are mostly resolved into mechanical causes, to wit, the figure, motion, weight, and suchlike qualities, of insensible particles; whereas, in truth, there is no other agent or efficient cause than spirit, it being evident that motion, as well as all other ideas, is perfectly inert. See sect. 25. Hence, to endeavour to explain the production of colours or sounds, by figure, motion, magnitude, and the like, must needs be labour in vain. And accordingly we see the attempts of that kind are not at all satisfactory. Which may be said in general of those instances wherein one idea or quality is assigned for the cause of another. I need not say how many hypotheses and speculations are left out, and how much the study of nature is abridged by this doctrine.

102. One major reason we claim to be ignorant about the nature of things is the common belief that everything contains within itself the cause of its properties; or that each object has an internal essence that is the source of its observable qualities and on which they depend. Some have tried to explain appearances through hidden qualities, but recently, they are mostly explained through mechanical causes, like the shape, motion, weight, and similar qualities of tiny particles; however, in reality, the only active cause is spirit, since it’s clear that motion, like all other ideas, is completely inactive. See sect. 25. Therefore, trying to explain colors or sounds through shape, motion, size, and the like is bound to be pointless. As a result, we find that these kinds of attempts are not at all satisfactory. This can generally be said about instances where one idea or quality is proposed as the cause of another. I don’t need to mention how many hypotheses and speculations are ignored and how much the study of nature is limited by this view.

103. ATTRACTION SIGNIFIES THE EFFECT, NOT THE MANNER OR CAUSE.--The great mechanical principle now in vogue is attraction. That a stone falls to the earth, or the sea swells towards the moon, may to some appear sufficiently explained thereby. But how are we enlightened by being told this is done by attraction? Is it that that word signifies the manner of the tendency, and that it is by the mutual drawing of bodies instead of their being impelled or protruded towards each other? But, nothing is determined of the manner or action, and it may as truly (for aught we know) be termed "impulse," or "protrusion," as "attraction." Again, the parts of steel we see cohere firmly together, and this also is accounted for by attraction; but, in this as in the other instances, I do not perceive that anything is signified besides the effect itself; for as to the manner of the action whereby it is produced, or the cause which produces it, these are not so much as aimed at.

103. ATTRACTION MEANS THE EFFECT, NOT THE WAY OR REASON.--The big mechanical idea nowadays is attraction. Some might think that a stone falling to the ground or the ocean rising towards the moon is explained by this. But how does saying this happens because of attraction really help us understand? Does that word describe how things are drawn together, as opposed to being pushed towards each other? However, it doesn't clarify the way the action occurs, and it could just as easily be called "impulse" or "pushing" as "attraction." Similarly, we observe that pieces of steel stick together tightly, which is also explained by attraction; yet in this case, just like the others, it seems there's nothing more being conveyed than the effect itself. Regarding how the action happens or the cause behind it, those aspects aren't addressed at all.

104. Indeed, if we take a view of the several phenomena, and compare them together, we may observe some likeness and conformity between them. For example, in the falling of a stone to the ground, in the rising of the sea towards the moon, in cohesion, crystallization, etc, there is something alike, namely, an union or mutual approach of bodies. So that any one of these or the like phenomena may not seem strange or surprising to a man who has nicely observed and compared the effects of nature. For that only is thought so which is uncommon, or a thing by itself, and out of the ordinary course of our observation. That bodies should tend towards the centre of the earth is not thought strange, because it is what we perceive every moment of our lives. But, that they should have a like gravitation towards the centre of the moon may seem odd and unaccountable to most men, because it is discerned only in the tides. But a philosopher, whose thoughts take in a larger compass of nature, having observed a certain similitude of appearances, as well in the heavens as the earth, that argue innumerable bodies to have a mutual tendency towards each other, which he denotes by the general name "attraction," whatever can be reduced to that he thinks justly accounted for. Thus he explains the tides by the attraction of the terraqueous globe towards the moon, which to him does not appear odd or anomalous, but only a particular example of a general rule or law of nature.

104. Indeed, if we look at the various phenomena and compare them, we may notice some similarities and patterns among them. For instance, in the way a stone falls to the ground, the way the sea rises towards the moon, and in cohesion and crystallization, there's something in common: a connection or mutual approach of bodies. So, any of these phenomena or similar ones shouldn't seem strange or surprising to someone who has carefully observed and compared natural effects. Only things that are uncommon or stand alone, outside the ordinary course of our observations, are considered strange. The fact that objects fall towards the center of the earth isn't seen as unusual because it's something we experience every moment of our lives. However, the idea that they might also gravitate towards the center of the moon may seem odd and hard to explain to many people since it's only noticeable in the tides. But a philosopher, whose understanding encompasses a broader scope of nature, having noticed a certain similarity in appearances both in the heavens and on earth, reasons that countless bodies have a mutual attraction to each other, which he refers to as "attraction." Anything that can be explained within this concept he believes is rightly accounted for. In this way, he explains the tides as being caused by the attraction of the earth towards the moon, which doesn't seem strange or exceptional to him, but rather just a specific instance of a general rule or law of nature.

105. If therefore we consider the difference there is betwixt natural philosophers and other men, with regard to their knowledge of the phenomena, we shall find it consists not in an exacter knowledge of the efficient cause that produces them--for that can be no other than the will of a spirit--but only in a greater largeness of comprehension, whereby analogies, harmonies, and agreements are discovered in the works of nature, and the particular effects explained, that is, reduced to general rules, see sect. 62, which rules, grounded on the analogy and uniformness observed in the production of natural effects, are most agreeable and sought after by the mind; for that they extend our prospect beyond what is present and near to us, and enable us to make very probable conjectures touching things that may have happened at very great distances of time and place, as well as to predict things to come; which sort of endeavour towards omniscience is much affected by the mind.

105. If we look at the difference between natural philosophers and other people in terms of their understanding of phenomena, we will see that it doesn’t come from having a more precise knowledge of the efficient cause that brings them about—since that can only be the will of a spirit. Instead, it lies in a broader understanding that uncovers analogies, harmonies, and connections in the workings of nature, explaining specific effects by relating them to general rules, see sect. 62. These rules, based on the analogies and consistency seen in the generation of natural effects, are most appealing and sought after by the mind because they broaden our perspective beyond what is immediate and close to us. They allow us to make very reasonable guesses about events that may have occurred a long time ago in distant places, as well as to predict future events. This pursuit of knowledge is something the mind is particularly drawn to.

106. CAUTION AS TO THE USE OF ANALOGIES.--But we should proceed warily in such things, for we are apt to lay too great stress on analogies, and, to the prejudice of truth, humour that eagerness of the mind whereby it is carried to extend its knowledge into general theorems. For example, in the business of gravitation or mutual attraction, because it appears in many instances, some are straightway for pronouncing it universal; and that to attract and be attracted by every other body is an essential quality inherent in all bodies whatsoever. Whereas it is evident the fixed stars have no such tendency towards each other; and, so far is that gravitation from being essential to bodies that in some instances a quite contrary principle seems to show itself; as in the perpendicular growth of plants, and the elasticity of the air. There is nothing necessary or essential in the case, but it depends entirely on the will of the Governing Spirit, who causes certain bodies to cleave together or tend towards each other according to various laws, whilst He keeps others at a fixed distance; and to some He gives a quite contrary tendency to fly asunder just as He sees convenient.

106. CAUTION ABOUT USING ANALOGIES.--However, we should be careful with this, as we tend to place too much emphasis on analogies, and, to the detriment of truth, indulge our urge to expand our knowledge into broad theories. For instance, when it comes to gravity or mutual attraction, just because it seems to occur in many cases, some people quickly declare it as universal; they argue that the ability to attract and be attracted by every other object is an essential quality inherent to all bodies. However, it is clear that the fixed stars don't have this tendency toward each other; and far from being essential to bodies, gravity sometimes seems to be contradicted, as seen in the vertical growth of plants and the elasticity of air. There is nothing necessary or inherent in this situation, as it relies entirely on the will of the Governing Spirit, who causes certain bodies to stick together or move toward each other according to different laws, while keeping others at a constant distance; and to some, He gives a completely opposing tendency to move apart whenever He deems it appropriate.

107. After what has been premised, I think we may lay down the following conclusions. First, it is plain philosophers amuse themselves in vain, when they inquire for any natural efficient cause, distinct from a mind or spirit. Secondly, considering the whole creation is the workmanship of a wise and good Agent, it should seem to become philosophers to employ their thoughts (contrary to what some hold) about the final causes of things; and I confess I see no reason why pointing out the various ends to which natural things are adapted, and for which they were originally with unspeakable wisdom contrived, should not be thought one good way of accounting for them, and altogether worthy a philosopher. Thirdly, from what has been premised no reason can be drawn why the history of nature should not still be studied, and observations and experiments made, which, that they are of use to mankind, and enable us to draw any general conclusions, is not the result of any immutable habitudes or relations between things themselves, but only of God's goodness and kindness to men in the administration of the world. See sect. 30 and 31 Fourthly, by a diligent observation of the phenomena within our view, we may discover the general laws of nature, and from them deduce the other phenomena; I do not say demonstrate, for all deductions of that kind depend on a supposition that the Author of nature always operates uniformly, and in a constant observance of those rules we take for principles: which we cannot evidently know.

107. Based on what has been discussed, I think we can draw the following conclusions. First, it's clear that philosophers waste their time when they look for any natural cause that exists separately from a mind or spirit. Second, since the entire creation is the work of a wise and good Creator, it seems fitting for philosophers to focus their thoughts (against what some believe) on the final purposes of things. I honestly see no reason why identifying the various purposes for which natural things are suited, and for which they were originally designed with amazing wisdom, shouldn't be considered a valid way to explain them and completely worthy of a philosopher. Third, from what we've established, there's no reason to think that the study of nature shouldn't continue, along with making observations and experiments, which are useful to humanity and help us draw general conclusions not because of any unchanging habits or relationships between things, but solely due to God's goodness and kindness in managing the world. See sect. 30 and 31. Fourth, through careful observation of the phenomena we can see, we can discover the general laws of nature and use them to infer other phenomena; I don't mean to say we can demonstrate them, because all such inferences depend on the assumption that the Author of nature always acts consistently and follows the rules we accept as principles, which we cannot know for sure.

108. THREE ANALOGIES.--Those men who frame general rules from the phenomena and afterwards derive the phenomena from those rules, seem to consider signs rather than causes. A man may well understand natural signs without knowing their analogy, or being able to say by what rule a thing is so or so. And, as it is very possible to write improperly, through too strict an observance of general grammar rules; so, in arguing from general laws of nature, it is not impossible we may extend the analogy too far, and by that means run into mistakes.

108. THREE ANALOGIES.--Those people who create general rules based on observations and then explain those observations using those rules seem to focus more on signs than on causes. A person can understand natural signs without knowing their underlying analogy or being able to explain why something is the way it is. Just as it's possible to write incorrectly by following general grammar rules too rigidly, when we reason from general laws of nature, it's also possible to extend the analogy too far and make mistakes.

109. As in reading other books a wise man will choose to fix his thoughts on the sense and apply it to use, rather than lay them out in grammatical remarks on the language; so, in perusing the volume of nature, it seems beneath the dignity of the mind to affect an exactness in reducing each particular phenomenon to general rules, or showing how it follows from them. We should propose to ourselves nobler views, namely, to recreate and exalt the mind with a prospect of the beauty, order. extent, and variety of natural things: hence, by proper inferences, to enlarge our notions of the grandeur, wisdom, and beneficence of the Creator; and lastly, to make the several parts of the creation, so far as in us lies, subservient to the ends they were designed for, God's glory, and the sustentation and comfort of ourselves and fellow-creatures.

109. Just like a wise person reading other books focuses on the meaning and how to apply it rather than getting caught up in grammar, when exploring the natural world, it seems unworthy of our minds to obsess over precisely fitting every phenomenon into strict rules or demonstrating how they all connect. Instead, we should aim for grander objectives: to uplift and inspire our minds by appreciating the beauty, order, scope, and diversity of nature. From this, we can draw important conclusions that expand our understanding of the greatness, wisdom, and kindness of the Creator. Finally, we should strive to make the various parts of creation, as much as we can, serve the purposes they were meant for: honoring God and supporting and comforting ourselves and others.

110. The best key for the aforesaid analogy or natural Science will be easily acknowledged to be a certain celebrated Treatise of Mechanics. In the entrance of which justly admired treatise, Time, Space, and Motion are distinguished into absolute and relative, true and apparent, mathematical and vulgar; which distinction, as it is at large explained by the author, does suppose these quantities to have an existence without the mind; and that they are ordinarily conceived with relation to sensible things, to which nevertheless in their own nature they bear no relation at all.

110. The best reference for the mentioned analogy or natural science is clearly a well-known treatise on mechanics. At the beginning of this highly regarded treatise, Time, Space, and Motion are categorized into absolute and relative, true and apparent, mathematical and everyday; this distinction, which the author explains in detail, suggests that these quantities exist independently of the mind and that they're usually understood in relation to tangible things, even though in their essence they have no real connection to them.

111. As for Time, as it is there taken in an absolute or abstracted sense, for the duration or perseverance of the existence of things, I have nothing more to add concerning it after what has been already said on that subject. Sect. 97 and 98. For the rest, this celebrated author holds there is an absolute Space, which, being unperceivable to sense, remains in itself similar and immovable; and relative space to be the measure thereof, which, being movable and defined by its situation in respect of sensible bodies, is vulgarly taken for immovable space. Place he defines to be that part of space which is occupied by any body; and according as the space is absolute or relative so also is the place. Absolute Motion is said to be the translation of a body from absolute place to absolute place, as relative motion is from one relative place to another. And, because the parts of absolute space do not fall under our senses, instead of them we are obliged to use their sensible measures, and so define both place and motion with respect to bodies which we regard as immovable. But, it is said in philosophical matters we must abstract from our senses, since it may be that none of those bodies which seem to be quiescent are truly so, and the same thing which is moved relatively may be really at rest; as likewise one and the same body may be in relative rest and motion, or even moved with contrary relative motions at the same time, according as its place is variously defined. All which ambiguity is to be found in the apparent motions, but not at all in the true or absolute, which should therefore be alone regarded in philosophy. And the true as we are told are distinguished from apparent or relative motions by the following properties.--First, in true or absolute motion all parts which preserve the same position with respect of the whole, partake of the motions of the whole. Secondly, the place being moved, that which is placed therein is also moved; so that a body moving in a place which is in motion doth participate the motion of its place. Thirdly, true motion is never generated or changed otherwise than by force impressed on the body itself. Fourthly, true motion is always changed by force impressed on the body moved. Fifthly, in circular motion barely relative there is no centrifugal force, which, nevertheless, in that which is true or absolute, is proportional to the quantity of motion.

111. When it comes to Time, as it's understood in an absolute or abstract sense, referring to the duration or persistence of things' existence, I don't have anything more to add beyond what I’ve already discussed on the topic. Sect. 97 and 98. Additionally, this well-known author believes there is an absolute Space that, being imperceptible to our senses, remains constant and unchanging; and relative space acts as its measurement, which, being movable and defined based on its position relative to physical objects, is commonly mistaken for unchanging space. Place is defined as the part of space occupied by any object; and depending on whether space is absolute or relative, so is the place. Absolute Motion is described as the movement of an object from one absolute location to another, while relative motion occurs from one relative location to another. Since the parts of absolute space aren't detectable by our senses, we have to rely on practical measures for it, defining both place and motion in relation to objects we consider to be stationary. However, it’s suggested in philosophical discussions that we should set aside our sensory perceptions, because what seems to be stationary may not actually be, and what appears to be moving relative to something else could actually be at rest; likewise, one object can be both in relative motion and rest, or even moving in opposite relative directions at the same time, depending on how its position is defined. All these uncertainties arise from apparent movements, but not from true or absolute movement, which should be the focus in philosophy. True motions are differentiated from apparent or relative motions by the following characteristics. First, in true or absolute motion, all parts that maintain the same position relative to the whole share in the motions of the entire entity. Second, if the place is moving, anything located in it also moves; so an object moving in a place that is in motion shares the motion of that place. Third, true motion is never created or altered except through a force applied directly to the body itself. Fourth, true motion is always modified by a force applied to the moving body. Fifth, in purely relative circular motion, there is no centrifugal force; however, in true or absolute movement, this force is proportional to the amount of motion involved.

112. MOTION, WHETHER REAL OR APPARENT, RELATIVE.--But, notwithstanding what has been said, I must confess it does not appear to me that there can be any motion other than relative; so that to conceive motion there must be at least conceived two bodies, whereof the distance or position in regard to each other is varied. Hence, if there was one only body in being it could not possibly be moved. This seems evident, in that the idea I have of motion doth necessarily include relation.

112. MOTION, WHETHER REAL OR APPARENT, RELATIVE.--However, despite what has been said, I have to admit that it seems to me there can't be any motion that isn't relative. To understand motion, you need to think of at least two bodies whose distance or position in relation to each other changes. Therefore, if there were only one body in existence, it couldn't possibly be moved. This seems clear, as the idea I have of motion necessarily involves a relationship.

113. APPARENT MOTION DENIED.--But, though in every motion it be necessary to conceive more bodies than one, yet it may be that one only is moved, namely, that on which the force causing the change in the distance or situation of the bodies, is impressed. For, however some may define relative motion, so as to term that body moved which changes its distance from some other body, whether the force or action causing that change were impressed on it or no, yet as relative motion is that which is perceived by sense, and regarded in the ordinary affairs of life, it should seem that every man of common sense knows what it is as well as the best philosopher. Now, I ask any one whether, in his sense of motion as he walks along the streets, the stones he passes over may be said to move, because they change distance with his feet? To me it appears that though motion includes a relation of one thing to another, yet it is not necessary that each term of the relation be denominated from it. As a man may think of somewhat which does not think, so a body may be moved to or from another body which is not therefore itself in motion.

113. APPARENT MOTION DENIED.--While it's true that when we think about motion, we need to consider more than one body, only one body may actually be in motion—the one that's experiencing a force causing a change in distance or position. Some might define relative motion as that which involves a body changing its distance from another body, regardless of whether the force causing that change is acting on it or not. However, since relative motion is something we perceive through our senses and encounter in our daily lives, it seems that everyone with common sense understands it just as well as the most knowledgeable philosopher. Now, I ask anyone: when you feel motion while walking down the street, can you say that the stones beneath you are moving because they change distance from your feet? To me, it seems that motion involves a relationship between things, but it doesn't mean that each element of that relationship should be identified by the same terminology. Just as a person can think about something that doesn't think, a body can be moved toward or away from another body without being in motion itself.

114. As the place happens to be variously defined, the motion which is related to it varies. A man in a ship may be said to be quiescent with relation to the sides of the vessel, and yet move with relation to the land. Or he may move eastward in respect of the one, and westward in respect of the other. In the common affairs of life men never go beyond the earth to define the place of any body; and what is quiescent in respect of that is accounted absolutely to be so. But philosophers, who have a greater extent of thought, and juster notions of the system of things, discover even the earth itself to be moved. In order therefore to fix their notions they seem to conceive the corporeal world as finite, and the utmost unmoved walls or shell thereof to be the place whereby they estimate true motions. If we sound our own conceptions, I believe we may find all the absolute motion we can frame an idea of to be at bottom no other than relative motion thus defined. For, as has been already observed, absolute motion, exclusive of all external relation, is incomprehensible; and to this kind of relative motion all the above-mentioned properties, causes, and effects ascribed to absolute motion will, if I mistake not, be found to agree. As to what is said of the centrifugal force, that it does not at all belong to circular relative motion, I do not see how this follows from the experiment which is brought to prove it. See Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica, in Schol. Def. VIII. For the water in the vessel at that time wherein it is said to have the greatest relative circular motion, has, I think, no motion at all; as is plain from the foregoing section.

114. Since the concept of place is defined in different ways, the motion related to it also changes. A person on a ship might be considered still in relation to the sides of the vessel but be moving in relation to the land. They could be moving eastward with respect to one and westward with respect to the other. In everyday life, people typically define the location of anything based on the earth, and anything that is still in that context is considered absolutely still. However, philosophers, who think more broadly and have a clearer understanding of the system of things, recognize that even the earth itself is in motion. To clarify their ideas, they often imagine the physical world as finite, with the ultimate immovable boundaries or shell being the reference point for true motion. If we examine our own ideas, we might find that all the absolute motion we can conceive is fundamentally just this type of relative motion. As has been pointed out before, absolute motion, when considered apart from all external references, is beyond comprehension; and the properties, causes, and effects attributed to absolute motion will likely align with this kind of relative motion. Regarding the statement about centrifugal force not being relevant to circular relative motion, I don’t see how that conclusion follows from the experiment intended to prove it. See Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica, in Schol. Def. VIII. The water in the container at the moment it is said to have the greatest relative circular motion, I believe, has no motion at all, as is clear from the previous section.

115. For, to denominate a body moved it is requisite, first, that it change its distance or situation with regard to some other body; and secondly, that the force occasioning that change be applied to it. If either of these be wanting, I do not think that, agreeably to the sense of mankind, or the propriety of language, a body can be said to be in motion. I grant indeed that it is possible for us to think a body which we see change its distance from some other to be moved, though it have no force applied to it (in which sense there may be apparent motion), but then it is because the force causing the change of distance is imagined by us to be applied or impressed on that body thought to move; which indeed shows we are capable of mistaking a thing to be in motion which is not, and that is all.

115. To consider an object as moving, two things are necessary: first, it has to change its distance or position relative to another object; and second, a force must act on it to cause that change. If either of these is missing, I don't think we can truly say, in the common understanding of people or in proper language, that an object is in motion. I do acknowledge that we might perceive an object we see changing its distance from another as being in motion, even if no force is applied to it (this could be what we call apparent motion). However, that's only because we imagine that a force is acting on the object we think is moving; this illustrates that we can mistake something for being in motion when it actually isn't, and that's all there is to it.

116. ANY IDEA OF PURE SPACE RELATIVE.--From what has been said it follows that the philosophic consideration of motion does not imply the being of an absolute Space, distinct from that which is perceived by sense and related bodies; which that it cannot exist without the mind is clear upon the same principles that demonstrate the like of all other objects of sense. And perhaps, if we inquire narrowly, we shall find we cannot even frame an idea of pure Space exclusive of all body. This I must confess seems impossible, as being a most abstract idea. When I excite a motion in some part of my body, if it be free or without resistance, I say there is Space; but if I find a resistance, then I say there is Body; and in proportion as the resistance to motion is lesser or greater, I say the space is more or less pure. So that when I speak of pure or empty space, it is not to be supposed that the word "space" stands for an idea distinct from or conceivable without body and motion--though indeed we are apt to think every noun substantive stands for a distinct idea that may be separated from all others; which has occasioned infinite mistakes. When, therefore, supposing all the world to be annihilated besides my own body, I say there still remains pure Space, thereby nothing else is meant but only that I conceive it possible for the limbs of my body to be moved on all sides without the least resistance, but if that, too, were annihilated then there could be no motion, and consequently no Space. Some, perhaps, may think the sense of seeing doth furnish them with the idea of pure space; but it is plain from what we have elsewhere shown, that the ideas of space and distance are not obtained by that sense. See the Essay concerning Vision.

116. ANY IDEA OF PURE SPACE RELATIVE.--From what has been discussed, it follows that the philosophical examination of motion does not require the existence of absolute Space, separate from what we perceive through our senses and the bodies around us. It's clear that absolute Space cannot exist without the mind, based on the same principles that prove the non-existence of all other sensory objects. And if we look closely, we might find that we can't even imagine pure Space without any body. I must admit this seems impossible, as it is an extremely abstract concept. When I cause motion in any part of my body, if it's free or without resistance, I call it Space; but if I encounter resistance, then I refer to it as Body. The more or less resistance there is to the motion, the more or less pure I consider the space to be. So when I talk about pure or empty space, it shouldn't be assumed that the term "space" represents an idea distinct from or understandable without body and motion—though we usually believe that every noun stands for a distinct idea that can be separated from others, which has led to countless misunderstandings. Therefore, if I imagine the entire world is destroyed except for my own body, when I say there still exists pure Space, I only mean that I can conceive of my limbs moving freely in every direction without any resistance; but if that, too, were gone, then there would be no motion, and therefore no Space. Some might believe that sight provides them with the idea of pure space, but as we've demonstrated elsewhere, the ideas of space and distance are not derived from that sense. See the Essay concerning Vision.

117. What is here laid down seems to put an end to all those disputes and difficulties that have sprung up amongst the learned concerning the nature of pure Space. But the chief advantage arising from it is that we are freed from that dangerous dilemma, to which several who have employed their thoughts on that subject imagine themselves reduced, to wit, of thinking either that Real Space is God, or else that there is something beside God which is eternal, uncreated, infinite, indivisible, immutable. Both which may justly be thought pernicious and absurd notions. It is certain that not a few divines, as well as philosophers of great note, have, from the difficulty they found in conceiving either limits or annihilation of space, concluded it must be divine. And some of late have set themselves particularly to show the incommunicable attributes of God agree to it. Which doctrine, how unworthy soever it may seem of the Divine Nature, yet I do not see how we can get clear of it, so long as we adhere to the received opinions.

117. What’s outlined here seems to settle all the debates and challenges that have emerged among scholars regarding the nature of pure Space. The main benefit of this is that we are released from that tricky dilemma where some thinkers on this topic feel trapped, either believing that Real Space is God, or that there is something other than God that is eternal, uncreated, infinite, indivisible, and unchangeable. Both ideas can rightly be seen as harmful and absurd. It's true that quite a few theologians and notable philosophers, due to the difficulty they experience in imagining either the limits or the total lack of space, have concluded that it must be divine. Recently, some have specifically aimed to demonstrate that the unique attributes of God align with it. Regardless of how unworthy this doctrine might seem of the Divine Nature, I don’t see how we can escape it as long as we stick to the accepted beliefs.

118. THE ERRORS ARISING FROM THE DOCTRINES OF ABSTRACTION AND EXTERNAL MATERIAL EXISTENCES, INFLUENCE MATHEMATICAL REASONINGS.--Hitherto of Natural Philosophy: we come now to make some inquiry concerning that other great branch of speculative knowledge, to wit, Mathematics. These, how celebrated soever they may be for their clearness and certainty of demonstration, which is hardly anywhere else to be found, cannot nevertheless be supposed altogether free from mistakes, if in their principles there lurks some secret error which is common to the professors of those sciences with the rest of mankind. Mathematicians, though they deduce their theorems from a great height of evidence, yet their first principles are limited by the consideration of quantity: and they do not ascend into any inquiry concerning those transcendental maxims which influence all the particular sciences, each part whereof, Mathematics not excepted, does consequently participate of the errors involved in them. That the principles laid down by mathematicians are true, and their way of deduction from those principles clear and incontestible, we do not deny; but, we hold there may be certain erroneous maxims of greater extent than the object of Mathematics, and for that reason not expressly mentioned, though tacitly supposed throughout the whole progress of that science; and that the ill effects of those secret unexamined errors are diffused through all the branches thereof. To be plain, we suspect the mathematicians are as well as other men concerned in the errors arising from the doctrine of abstract general ideas, and the existence of objects without the mind.

118. THE ERRORS ARISING FROM THE DOCTRINES OF ABSTRACTION AND EXTERNAL MATERIAL EXISTENCES INFLUENCE MATHEMATICAL REASONINGS.--Up until now, we've discussed Natural Philosophy; now we turn to explore another major area of speculative knowledge: Mathematics. Despite their reputation for clarity and certainty in demonstration—which is rare to find elsewhere—they cannot be seen as completely free from errors if their principles contain some hidden mistake that's common among both mathematicians and the rest of humanity. Mathematicians, although they derive their theorems from a strong foundation of evidence, are limited to considering only quantities. They don't engage in inquiries about those deeper principles that affect all branches of knowledge, including Mathematics, which thereby share in the errors tied to these principles. We acknowledge that the principles set forth by mathematicians are true, and their methods of deriving conclusions from these principles are clear and indisputable, but we believe there might be certain erroneous maxims that extend beyond the scope of Mathematics itself, which aren't explicitly stated but are implicitly assumed throughout the discipline; the negative consequences of these unexamined errors spread across all its branches. To be straightforward, we suspect that mathematicians are as much affected by the mistakes stemming from the ideas of abstract generalities and the reality of objects outside the mind as anyone else.

119. Arithmetic has been thought to have for its object abstract ideas of Number; of which to understand the properties and mutual habitudes, is supposed no mean part of speculative knowledge. The opinion of the pure and intellectual nature of numbers in abstract has made them in esteem with those philosophers who seem to have affected an uncommon fineness and elevation of thought. It has set a price on the most trifling numerical speculations which in practice are of no use, but serve only for amusement; and has therefore so far infected the minds of some, that they have dreamed of mighty mysteries involved in numbers, and attempted the explication of natural things by them. But, if we inquire into our own thoughts, and consider what has been premised, we may perhaps entertain a low opinion of those high flights and abstractions, and look on all inquiries, about numbers only as so many difficiles nugae, so far as they are not subservient to practice, and promote the benefit of life.

119. Arithmetic is believed to focus on abstract ideas of Number, and understanding their properties and relationships is considered an important aspect of theoretical knowledge. The belief in the pure and intellectual nature of numbers has led some philosophers to value them for their supposed sophistication and depth. This has caused even the most trivial numerical speculations, which are practically useless and merely entertaining, to be held in high regard. Consequently, some have become so captivated that they imagine profound mysteries within numbers and try to explain natural phenomena through them. However, if we reflect on our own thoughts and consider what has been stated, we might find ourselves skeptical of those grand theories and abstractions, viewing all inquiries about numbers as mere intricate trifles, unless they serve practical purposes and enhance life.

120. Unity in abstract we have before considered in sect. 13, from which and what has been said in the Introduction, it plainly follows there is not any such idea. But, number being defined a "collection of units," we may conclude that, if there be no such thing as unity or unit in abstract, there are no ideas of number in abstract denoted by the numeral names and figures. The theories therefore in Arithmetic, if they are abstracted from the names and figures, as likewise from all use and practice, as well as from the particular things numbered, can be supposed to have nothing at all for their object; hence we may see how entirely the science of numbers is subordinate to practice, and how jejune and trifling it becomes when considered as a matter of mere speculation.

120. We've previously discussed unity in abstract in section 13, and based on what was mentioned in the Introduction, it’s clear that there isn't such an idea. However, since we define a number as a "collection of units," we can conclude that if there's no concept of unity or a unit in abstract terms, then there are no abstract ideas of number represented by numeral names and figures. Therefore, the theories in Arithmetic, if removed from the names and figures, as well as from all practical use and the specific things being counted, would have nothing to focus on. This shows just how dependent the science of numbers is on practice, and how dull and trivial it becomes when viewed purely as a theoretical concept.

121. However, since there may be some who, deluded by the specious show of discovering abstracted verities, waste their time in arithmetical theorems and problems which have not any use, it will not be amiss if we more fully consider and expose the vanity of that pretence; and this will plainly appear by taking a view of Arithmetic in its infancy, and observing what it was that originally put men on the study of that science, and to what scope they directed it. It is natural to think that at first, men, for ease of memory and help of computation, made use of counters, or in writing of single strokes, points, or the like, each whereof was made to signify an unit, i.e., some one thing of whatever kind they had occasion to reckon. Afterwards they found out the more compendious ways of making one character stand in place of several strokes or points. And, lastly, the notation of the Arabians or Indians came into use, wherein, by the repetition of a few characters or figures, and varying the signification of each figure according to the place it obtains, all numbers may be most aptly expressed; which seems to have been done in imitation of language, so that an exact analogy is observed betwixt the notation by figures and names, the nine simple figures answering the nine first numeral names and places in the former, corresponding to denominations in the latter. And agreeably to those conditions of the simple and local value of figures, were contrived methods of finding, from the given figures or marks of the parts, what figures and how placed are proper to denote the whole, or vice versa. And having found the sought figures, the same rule or analogy being observed throughout, it is easy to read them into words; and so the number becomes perfectly known. For then the number of any particular things is said to be known, when we know the name of figures (with their due arrangement) that according to the standing analogy belong to them. For, these signs being known, we can by the operations of arithmetic know the signs of any part of the particular sums signified by them; and, thus computing in signs (because of the connexion established betwixt them and the distinct multitudes of things whereof one is taken for an unit), we may be able rightly to sum up, divide, and proportion the things themselves that we intend to number.

121. However, since some people might be misled by the misleading appearance of uncovering abstract truths and waste their time on math theorems and problems that lack any practical use, it would be worthwhile to more thoroughly examine and highlight the futility of that notion. This will become clear by looking at Arithmetic in its early stages and noticing what initially drove people to study this field and what goals they aimed for. It's reasonable to think that at first, people used counters or wrote single lines, dots, or similar marks to help with memory and calculations, where each mark represented one unit—essentially, one specific thing they needed to count. Later on, they discovered more efficient ways to make one symbol stand in for multiple lines or dots. Ultimately, the notation used by the Arabs or Indians became popular, where a few characters or figures, repeated and with different meanings based on their position, can express all numbers effectively. This seems to have been modeled after language, showing a clear parallel between figure notation and names, with the nine simple figures matching the nine basic numeral names, and their positions corresponding to the denominations in language. Following those principles of simple and positional value, methods were developed to determine, from the given figures or marks, what figures and their placements are suitable to represent the whole, or vice versa. Once the required figures are found, following the same rules or analogy throughout makes it easy to translate them into words, thus making the number completely clear. A specific number is considered known when we understand the names of the figures (along with their proper arrangement) that correspond to it based on a consistent analogy. With these signs understood, we can use arithmetic operations to determine the signs of any part of the specific sums they represent. By calculating in signs—thanks to the connection established between them and the distinct quantities, where one is counted as a unit—we can properly add, divide, and proportion the actual items we wish to count.

122. In Arithmetic, therefore, we regard not the things, but the signs, which nevertheless are not regarded for their own sake, but because they direct us how to act with relation to things, and dispose rightly of them. Now, agreeably to what we have before observed of words in general (sect. 19, Introd.) it happens here likewise that abstract ideas are thought to be signified by numeral names or characters, while they do not suggest ideas of particular things to our minds. I shall not at present enter into a more particular dissertation on this subject, but only observe that it is evident from what has been said, those things which pass for abstract truths and theorems concerning numbers, are in reality conversant about no object distinct from particular numeral things, except only names and characters, which originally came to be considered on no other account but their being signs, or capable to represent aptly whatever particular things men had need to compute. Whence it follows that to study them for their own sake would be just as wise, and to as good purpose as if a man, neglecting the true use or original intention and subserviency of language, should spend his time in impertinent criticisms upon words, or reasonings and controversies purely verbal.

122. In arithmetic, we focus not on the actual objects, but on the symbols, which are not valued for their own sake, but because they guide us in how to interact with those objects and manage them correctly. As we noted earlier about words in general (sect. 19, Introd.), it turns out that abstract concepts are believed to be represented by number names or symbols, even though they don’t evoke specific objects in our minds. I won’t get into a detailed discussion on this topic right now, but it’s clear from what has been said that what we consider abstract truths and theorems about numbers ultimately deal with nothing other than specific numerical objects, aside from the names and symbols themselves, which were originally regarded solely because they signify or can effectively represent whatever specific things we need to calculate. Therefore, studying them for their own sake would be just as sensible and productive as someone ignoring the true purpose or original intention of language and wasting their time on pointless critiques of words or on discussions that focus only on the wording.

123. From numbers we proceed to speak of Extension, which, considered as relative, is the object of Geometry. The infinite divisibility of finite extension, though it is not expressly laid down either as an axiom or theorem in the elements of that science, yet is throughout the same everywhere supposed and thought to have so inseparable and essential a connexion with the principles and demonstrations in Geometry, that mathematicians never admit it into doubt, or make the least question of it. And, as this notion is the source from whence do spring all those amusing geometrical paradoxes which have such a direct repugnancy to the plain common sense of mankind, and are admitted with so much reluctance into a mind not yet debauched by learning; so it is the principal occasion of all that nice and extreme subtilty which renders the study of Mathematics so difficult and tedious. Hence, if we can make it appear that no finite extension contains innumerable parts, or is infinitely divisible, it follows that we shall at once clear the science of Geometry from a great number of difficulties and contradictions which have ever been esteemed a reproach to human reason, and withal make the attainment thereof a business of much less time and pains than it hitherto has been.

123. Now let's talk about Extension, which is the focus of Geometry when considered in relation. The idea that finite extension can be infinitely divided isn't explicitly stated as an axiom or theorem in the foundations of that science, but it's always assumed and thought to be so closely linked to the principles and proofs in Geometry that mathematicians never doubt it or question it. This concept is the basis for all those interesting geometric paradoxes that directly clash with common sense and are reluctantly accepted by those not already influenced by academic learning. It also leads to the extreme complexity that makes studying Mathematics so challenging and tedious. Therefore, if we can demonstrate that no finite extension contains endless parts or is infinitely divisible, we will immediately eliminate a significant number of challenges and contradictions that have long been seen as a flaw of human reasoning, making the pursuit of Geometry much quicker and easier than it has been until now.

124. Every particular finite extension which may possibly be the object of our thought is an idea existing only in the mind, and consequently each part thereof must be perceived. If, therefore, I cannot perceive innumerable parts in any finite extension that I consider, it is certain they are not contained in it; but, it is evident that I cannot distinguish innumerable parts in any particular line, surface, or solid, which I either perceive by sense, or figure to myself in my mind: wherefore I conclude they are not contained in it. Nothing can be plainer to me than that the extensions I have in view are no other than my own ideas; and it is no less plain that I cannot resolve any one of my ideas into an infinite number of other ideas, that is, that they are not infinitely divisible. If by finite extension be meant something distinct from a finite idea, I declare I do not know what that is, and so cannot affirm or deny anything of it. But if the terms "extension," "parts," &c., are taken in any sense conceivable, that is, for ideas, then to say a finite quantity or extension consists of parts infinite in number is so manifest a contradiction, that every one at first sight acknowledges it to be so; and it is impossible it should ever gain the assent of any reasonable creature who is not brought to it by gentle and slow degrees, as a converted Gentile to the belief of transubstantiation. Ancient and rooted prejudices do often pass into principles; and those propositions which once obtain the force and credit of a principle, are not only themselves, but likewise whatever is deducible from them, thought privileged from all examination. And there is no absurdity so gross, which, by this means, the mind of man may not be prepared to swallow.

124. Every specific finite extension that we might think about is just an idea that exists in our minds, so each part of it has to be perceived. If I can’t perceive countless parts in any finite extension I consider, it’s clear that those parts aren’t included in it; however, it’s obvious that I can’t identify countless parts in any specific line, surface, or solid that I either sense or imagine in my mind. Therefore, I conclude that they aren’t included in it. Nothing is clearer to me than that the extensions I’m thinking of are just my own ideas, and it’s equally clear that I can’t break down any of my ideas into an infinite number of other ideas, meaning they aren’t infinitely divisible. If “finite extension” refers to something different from a finite idea, I honestly don’t know what that is, so I can’t affirm or deny anything about it. But if the terms “extension,” “parts,” etc., are taken in any understandable sense, meaning as ideas, then saying that a finite amount or extension is made up of infinite parts is such an obvious contradiction that everyone recognizes it immediately; and it’s impossible for any reasonable person to accept it unless they are gradually led to that belief, much like a converted Gentile coming to believe in transubstantiation. Deep-rooted biases can often become principles, and those propositions that gain the power and credibility of a principle are not only accepted themselves but also any conclusions drawn from them, considered immune to scrutiny. There is no absurdity so blatant that the human mind can't be conditioned to accept it through this process.

125. He whose understanding is possessed with the doctrine of abstract general ideas may be persuaded that (whatever be thought of the ideas of sense) extension in abstract is infinitely divisible. And one who thinks the objects of sense exist without the mind will perhaps in virtue thereof be brought to admit that a line but an inch long may contain innumerable parts--really existing, though too small to be discerned. These errors are grafted as well in the minds of geometricians as of other men, and have a like influence on their reasonings; and it were no difficult thing to show how the arguments from Geometry made use of to support the infinite divisibility of extension are bottomed on them. At present we shall only observe in general whence it is the mathematicians are all so fond and tenacious of that doctrine.

125. Someone who fully understands the idea of abstract general concepts might believe that, regardless of what is thought about sensory ideas, abstract extension can be divided infinitely. A person who thinks that sensory objects exist independently of the mind may be led to accept that a line just an inch long can have countless parts—real parts, even if too small to see. These misconceptions are found in the minds of both mathematicians and others, influencing their reasoning in similar ways; it wouldn’t be hard to demonstrate how the arguments from geometry used to support the infinite divisibility of extension are based on these misconceptions. For now, we will simply note that this is why mathematicians are so attached to that doctrine.

126. It has been observed in another place that the theorems and demonstrations in Geometry are conversant about universal ideas (sect. 15, Introd.); where it is explained in what sense this ought to be understood, to wit, the particular lines and figures included in the diagram are supposed to stand for innumerable others of different sizes; or, in other words, the geometer considers them abstracting from their magnitude--which does not imply that he forms an abstract idea, but only that he cares not what the particular magnitude is, whether great or small, but looks on that as a thing different to the demonstration. Hence it follows that a line in the scheme but an inch long must be spoken of as though it contained ten thousand parts, since it is regarded not in itself, but as it is universal; and it is universal only in its signification, whereby it represents innumerable lines greater than itself, in which may be distinguished ten thousand parts or more, though there may not be above an inch in it. After this manner, the properties of the lines signified are (by a very usual figure) transferred to the sign, and thence, through mistake, though to appertain to it considered in its own nature.

126. It has been noted elsewhere that the theorems and proofs in Geometry deal with universal concepts (sect. 15, Introd.); it explains how this should be understood, meaning that the specific lines and shapes shown in the diagram are meant to represent countless others of different sizes. In other words, the geometer views them while ignoring their size—which doesn't mean he creates an abstract idea, but simply that he is unconcerned about the actual size, whether large or small, and considers that as separate from the demonstration. Therefore, a line in the diagram that is just an inch long is discussed as if it had ten thousand segments, since it is seen not for itself but as universal; and it is universal only in what it signifies, by representing countless lines larger than itself, which could have ten thousand segments or more, even though it may only measure an inch. In this way, the properties of the represented lines are (by a common figure of speech) attributed to the symbol, and as a result, mistakenly thought to apply to it when looked at in its own nature.

127. Because there is no number of parts so great but it is possible there may be a line containing more, the inch-line is said to contain parts more than any assignable number; which is true, not of the inch taken absolutely, but only for the things signified by it. But men, not retaining that distinction in their thoughts, slide into a belief that the small particular line described on paper contains in itself parts innumerable. There is no such thing as the ten--thousandth part of an inch; but there is of a mile or diameter of the earth, which may be signified by that inch. When therefore I delineate a triangle on paper, and take one side not above an inch, for example, in length to be the radius, this I consider as divided into 10,000 or 100,000 parts or more; for, though the ten-thousandth part of that line considered in itself is nothing at all, and consequently may be neglected without an error or inconveniency, yet these described lines, being only marks standing for greater quantities, whereof it may be the ten--thousandth part is very considerable, it follows that, to prevent notable errors in practice, the radius must be taken of 10,000 parts or more.

127. There is no limit to how many parts can fit into a line, so the inch-line is said to contain more parts than any number we can assign. This is true, not for the inch itself, but only for what it represents. However, people often forget this distinction and come to believe that the small line drawn on paper contains countless parts. There is no such thing as a ten-thousandth of an inch; however, it exists in a mile or the diameter of the Earth, which can be represented by that inch. So, when I draw a triangle on paper and take one side, not more than an inch long, as the radius, I consider it divided into 10,000 or 100,000 parts or more. While the ten-thousandth part of that line considered on its own is essentially nothing and can be ignored without issue, these drawn lines are only symbols for larger quantities, where the ten-thousandth part can be quite significant. Therefore, to avoid significant errors in practice, the radius should be considered as being made up of 10,000 parts or more.

128. LINES WHICH ARE INFINITELY DIVISIBLE.--From what has been said the reason is plain why, to the end any theorem become universal in its use, it is necessary we speak of the lines described on paper as though they contained parts which really they do not. In doing of which, if we examine the matter thoroughly, we shall perhaps discover that we cannot conceive an inch itself as consisting of, or being divisible into, a thousand parts, but only some other line which is far greater than an inch, and represented by it; and that when we say a line is infinitely divisible, we must mean a line which is infinitely great. What we have here observed seems to be the chief cause why, to suppose the infinite divisibility of finite extension has been thought necessary in geometry.

128. LINES THAT ARE INFINITELY DIVISIBLE.--From what has been discussed, it's clear why, in order for any theorem to be universally applicable, we need to describe the lines drawn on paper as if they contain parts that they actually don't. Upon close examination, we may find that we can't truly think of an inch itself as being divided into a thousand parts; rather, we can only conceive of another line that is much longer than an inch and represented by it. When we say a line is infinitely divisible, we should understand it as a line that is infinitely long. This observation seems to be the main reason why the assumption of the infinite divisibility of finite extension has been considered necessary in geometry.

129. The several absurdities and contradictions which flowed from this false principle might, one would think, have been esteemed so many demonstrations against it. But, by I know not what logic, it is held that proofs a posteriori are not to be admitted against propositions relating to infinity, as though it were not impossible even for an infinite mind to reconcile contradictions; or as if anything absurd and repugnant could have a necessary connexion with truth or flow from it. But, whoever considers the weakness of this pretence will think it was contrived on purpose to humour the laziness of the mind which had rather acquiesce in an indolent scepticism than be at the pains to go through with a severe examination of those principles it has ever embraced for true.

129. The many absurdities and contradictions that came from this false principle might, one would think, have been seen as clear evidence against it. But, for reasons I can't understand, it’s believed that a posteriori proofs shouldn’t be accepted against ideas about infinity, as if it were impossible for even an infinite mind to reconcile contradictions; or as if anything absurd and contradictory could have any necessary connection with truth or come from it. However, anyone who thinks about the weakness of this argument will realize it was likely designed to indulge the laziness of the mind, which would rather settle for a comfortable skepticism than put in the effort to critically examine the principles it has always accepted as true.

130. Of late the speculations about Infinities have run so high, and grown to such strange notions, as have occasioned no small scruples and disputes among the geometers of the present age. Some there are of great note who, not content with holding that finite lines may be divided into an infinite number of parts, do yet farther maintain that each of those infinitesimals is itself subdivisible into an infinity of other parts or infinitesimals of a second order, and so on ad infinitum. These, I say, assert there are infinitesimals of infinitesimals of infinitesimals, &c., without ever coming to an end; so that according to them an inch does not barely contain an infinite number of parts, but an infinity of an infinity of an infinity ad infinitum of parts. Others there be who hold all orders of infinitesimals below the first to be nothing at all; thinking it with good reason absurd to imagine there is any positive quantity or part of extension which, though multiplied infinitely, can never equal the smallest given extension. And yet on the other hand it seems no less absurd to think the square, cube or other power of a positive real root, should itself be nothing at all; which they who hold infinitesimals of the first order, denying all of the subsequent orders, are obliged to maintain.

130. Recently, discussions about infinities have become intense and have led to some really strange ideas that are causing considerable disagreements among today's mathematicians. Some well-known figures believe that not only can finite lines be divided into an infinite number of parts, but they also argue that each of those infinitesimals can be divided into an infinite number of other parts or second-order infinitesimals, and this can go on indefinitely. These individuals claim that there are infinitesimals of infinitesimals of infinitesimals, and so on, without end; thus, according to them, an inch contains not just an infinite number of parts, but an infinity of infinity of infinity of parts ad infinitum. On the other hand, there are those who argue that all infinitesimals lower than the first order don't exist at all; they find it quite logical to think it absurd that there could be any actual quantity or part of extension that, when multiplied infinitely, can never equal the smallest given extension. Yet, conversely, it seems equally absurd to believe that the square, cube, or any other power of a positive real root could be nothing; this is a stance that those who accept first-order infinitesimals and reject all higher orders are forced to take.

131. OBJECTION OF MATHEMATICIANS.--ANSWER.--Have we not therefore reason to conclude they are both in the wrong, and that there is in effect no such thing as parts infinitely small, or an infinite number of parts contained in any finite quantity? But you will say that if this doctrine obtains it will follow the very foundations of Geometry are destroyed, and those great men who have raised that science to so astonishing a height, have been all the while building a castle in the air. To this it may be replied that whatever is useful in geometry, and promotes the benefit of human life, does still remain firm and unshaken on our principles; that science considered as practical will rather receive advantage than any prejudice from what has been said. But to set this in a due light may be the proper business of another place. For the rest, though it should follow that some of the more intricate and subtle parts of Speculative Mathematics may be pared off without any prejudice to truth, yet I do not see what damage will be thence derived to mankind. On the contrary, I think it were highly to be wished that men of great abilities and obstinate application would draw off their thoughts from those amusements, and employ them in the study of such things as lie nearer the concerns of life, or have a more direct influence on the manners.

131. OBJECTION OF MATHEMATICIANS.--ANSWER.--Do we not have reason to conclude that they are both mistaken, and that in reality there are no infinitely small parts or an infinite number of parts within any finite quantity? But you might argue that if this belief holds, it would destroy the very foundations of Geometry, and the great minds who elevated that science to such incredible heights have been constructing a castle in the air all along. In response, it can be said that whatever is useful in geometry and enhances human life remains solid and unshaken by our principles; in fact, practical science will benefit rather than suffer from what has been mentioned. However, explaining this fully may be more suitable for another discussion. Moreover, even if it turns out that some of the more complex and subtle aspects of Theoretical Mathematics can be eliminated without harming the truth, I don't see how this would be detrimental to humanity. On the contrary, I believe it would be highly beneficial if talented and dedicated individuals redirected their focus from these distractions and engaged in studies that are more directly relevant to life or have a greater impact on behavior.

132. SECOND OBJECTION OF MATHEMATICIANS.--ANSWER.--If it be said that several theorems undoubtedly true are discovered by methods in which infinitesimals are made use of, which could never have been if their existence included a contradiction in it; I answer that upon a thorough examination it will not be found that in any instance it is necessary to make use of or conceive infinitesimal parts of finite lines, or even quantities less than the minimum sensible; nay, it will be evident this is never done, it being impossible.

132. SECOND OBJECTION OF MATHEMATICIANS.--ANSWER.--If someone claims that there are many theorems that are undoubtedly true and are discovered using methods involving infinitesimals, which could never have been discovered if their existence contradicted anything, I respond that upon closer examination, it will be clear that in every case, it is not necessary to use or even imagine infinitesimal parts of finite lines, or even quantities smaller than the smallest detectable amount; in fact, it will become obvious that this is never done, as it is impossible.

133. IF THE DOCTRINE WERE ONLY AN HYPOTHESIS IT SHOULD BE RESPECTED FOR ITS CONSEQUENCES.--By what we have premised, it is plain that very numerous and important errors have taken their rise from those false Principles which were impugned in the foregoing parts of this treatise; and the opposites of those erroneous tenets at the same time appear to be most fruitful Principles, from whence do flow innumerable consequences highly advantageous to true philosophy, as well as to religion. Particularly Matter, or the absolute existence of corporeal objects, has been shown to be that wherein the most avowed and pernicious enemies of all knowledge, whether human or divine, have ever placed their chief strength and confidence. And surely, if by distinguishing the real existence of unthinking things from their being perceived, and allowing them a subsistance of their own out of the minds of spirits, no one thing is explained in nature, but on the contrary a great many inexplicable difficulties arise; if the supposition of Matter is barely precarious, as not being grounded on so much as one single reason; if its consequences cannot endure the light of examination and free inquiry, but screen themselves under the dark and general pretence of "infinites being incomprehensible"; if withal the removal of this Matter be not attended with the least evil consequence; if it be not even missed in the world, but everything as well, nay much easier conceived without it; if, lastly, both Sceptics and Atheists are for ever silenced upon supposing only spirits and ideas, and this scheme of things is perfectly agreeable both to Reason and Religion: methinks we may expect it should be admitted and firmly embraced, though it were proposed only as an hypothesis, and the existence of Matter had been allowed possible, which yet I think we have evidently demonstrated that it is not.

133. IF THE DOCTRINE WERE ONLY A HYPOTHESIS IT SHOULD BE RESPECTED FOR ITS CONSEQUENCES.--From what we've established, it's clear that many significant errors have emerged from the false principles criticized earlier in this treatise. The opposing ideas to these erroneous beliefs also appear to be very fruitful principles, leading to countless benefits for true philosophy as well as religion. Particularly, matter, or the absolute existence of physical objects, has been shown to be where the most notorious and harmful enemies of all knowledge, whether human or divine, have always placed their primary strength and confidence. Surely, if we distinguish the real existence of unthinking things from their perception and allow them to exist independently of the minds of spirits, then nothing in nature is explained; instead, many inexplicable difficulties arise. If the idea of matter is merely uncertain, lacking any solid reasoning; if its consequences cannot stand up to scrutiny and free inquiry, hiding instead behind the vague notion that "infinities are incomprehensible"; if removing this matter does not lead to any negative consequences; if it is not even missed in the world but everything is just as easily, if not more so, understood without it; and finally, if both skeptics and atheists can be silenced by only assuming spirits and ideas, and this worldview aligns perfectly with both reason and religion: it seems to me that we should expect it to be accepted and firmly embraced, even if it were proposed only as a hypothesis, and that the existence of matter were considered possible, which I believe we have clearly shown is not the case.

134. True it is that, in consequence of the foregoing principles, several disputes and speculations which are esteemed no mean parts of learning, are rejected as useless. But, how great a prejudice soever against our notions this may give to those who have already been deeply engaged, and make large advances in studies of that nature, yet by others we hope it will not be thought any just ground of dislike to the principles and tenets herein laid down, that they abridge the labour of study, and make human sciences far more clear, compendious and attainable than they were before.

134. It's true that because of the principles mentioned earlier, several debates and theories considered significant parts of learning are dismissed as irrelevant. However, no matter how much bias this may create against our ideas for those who have invested a lot of time and effort in such studies, we hope that others won't see this as a valid reason to dislike the principles and beliefs presented here. They actually simplify the study process and make the human sciences much clearer, more concise, and easier to grasp than they were before.

135. Having despatched what we intended to say concerning the knowledge of IDEAS, the method we proposed leads us in the next place to treat of SPIRITS--with regard to which, perhaps, human knowledge is not so deficient as is vulgarly imagined. The great reason that is assigned for our being thought ignorant of the nature of spirits is our not having an idea of it. But, surely it ought not to be looked on as a defect in a human understanding that it does not perceive the idea of spirit, if it is manifestly impossible there should be any such idea. And this if I mistake not has been demonstrated in section 27; to which I shall here add that a spirit has been shown to be the only substance or support wherein unthinking beings or ideas can exist; but that this substance which supports or perceives ideas should itself be an idea or like an idea is evidently absurd.

135. After discussing what we needed to say about the knowledge of IDEAS, the method we proposed now leads us to talk about SPIRITS—about which, perhaps, human knowledge is not as lacking as is commonly thought. The main reason given for the belief that we are unaware of the nature of spirits is that we don't have an idea of it. However, it shouldn't be seen as a shortcoming of human understanding that it doesn't grasp the idea of spirit if it is clearly impossible for there to be such an idea. I believe this was demonstrated in section 27; to that, I want to add that a spirit has been shown to be the only substance or support in which unthinking beings or ideas can exist; but it is obviously absurd that this substance, which supports or perceives ideas, should itself be an idea or similar to an idea.

136. OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--It will perhaps be said that we want a sense (as some have imagined) proper to know substances withal, which, if we had, we might know our own soul as we do a triangle. To this I answer, that, in case we had a new sense bestowed upon us, we could only receive thereby some new sensations or ideas of sense. But I believe nobody will say that what he means by the terms soul and substance is only some particular sort of idea or sensation. We may therefore infer that, all things duly considered, it is not more reasonable to think our faculties defective, in that they do not furnish us with an idea of spirit or active thinking substance, than it would be if we should blame them for not being able to comprehend a round square.

136. OBJECTION.--ANSWER.--Some might say that we need a special sense (as some have thought) to truly understand substances, and if we had that, we could know our own soul just like we know a triangle. To this, I would respond that even if we were given a new sense, it would only allow us to experience new sensations or ideas. However, I doubt anyone would claim that what they mean by "soul" and "substance" is just a specific type of idea or sensation. Therefore, we can conclude that, after considering everything, it’s not any more reasonable to think our faculties are lacking because they don’t give us an idea of spirit or active thinking substance than it would be to blame them for not grasping the concept of a round square.

137. From the opinion that spirits are to be known after the manner of an idea or sensation have risen many absurd and heterodox tenets, and much scepticism about the nature of the soul. It is even probable that this opinion may have produced a doubt in some whether they had any soul at all distinct from their body since upon inquiry they could not find they had an idea of it. That an idea which is inactive, and the existence whereof consists in being perceived, should be the image or likeness of an agent subsisting by itself, seems to need no other refutation than barely attending to what is meant by those words. But, perhaps you will say that though an idea cannot resemble a spirit in its thinking, acting, or subsisting by itself, yet it may in some other respects; and it is not necessary that an idea or image be in all respects like the original.

137. The belief that spirits can be understood like ideas or sensations has led to many absurd and unconventional beliefs, as well as a lot of skepticism about the nature of the soul. It's even likely that this belief has caused some people to doubt whether they have any soul distinct from their body, since upon reflection they couldn’t find any idea of it. The idea that something inactive, which only exists when perceived, could be the image or likeness of a self-sustaining agent seems to be easily refuted just by considering what those words mean. However, you might argue that even if an idea can’t resemble a spirit in its thinking, acting, or independent existence, it could still do so in other ways; and it’s not necessary for an idea or image to be exactly like the original in every way.

138. I answer, if it does not in those mentioned, it is impossible it should represent it in any other thing. Do but leave out the power of willing, thinking, and perceiving ideas, and there remains nothing else wherein the idea can be like a spirit. For, by the word spirit we mean only that which thinks, wills, and perceives; this, and this alone, constitutes the signification of the term. If therefore it is impossible that any degree of those powers should be represented in an idea, it is evident there can be no idea of a spirit.

138. I respond that if it doesn't exist in those mentioned, then it's impossible for it to be represented in anything else. Just remove the ability to will, think, and perceive ideas, and nothing remains where the idea can resemble a spirit. When we say "spirit," we’re referring only to that which thinks, wills, and perceives; this is the sole meaning of the term. So, if it's impossible for any level of those abilities to be represented in an idea, it's clear there can be no idea of a spirit.

139. But it will be objected that, if there is no idea signified by the terms soul, spirit, and substance, they are wholly insignificant, or have no meaning in them. I answer, those words do mean or signify a real thing, which is neither an idea nor like an idea, but that which perceives ideas, and wills, and reasons about them. What I am myself, that which I denote by the term I, is the same with what is meant by soul or spiritual substance. If it be said that this is only quarreling at a word, and that, since the immediately significations of other names are by common consent called ideas, no reason can be assigned why that which is signified by the name spirit or soul may not partake in the same appellation. I answer, all the unthinking objects of the mind agree in that they are entirely passive, and their existence consists only in being perceived; whereas a soul or spirit is an active being, whose existence consists, not in being perceived, but in perceiving ideas and thinking. It is therefore necessary, in order to prevent equivocation and confounding natures perfectly disagreeing and unlike, that we distinguish between spirit and idea. See sect. 27.

139. Some might argue that if the terms soul, spirit, and substance don’t signify any idea, then they are completely meaningless or have no significance at all. I respond that these words do represent a real thing, which isn’t an idea or like an idea, but rather something that perceives ideas, makes decisions, and reasons about them. What I refer to as myself, using the term I, is the same as what is meant by soul or spiritual substance. If someone claims that this is just nitpicking over a word, and since the direct meanings of other names are commonly referred to as ideas, there's no reason why what is signified by the name spirit or soul couldn’t be categorized the same way. I respond that all unthinking objects of the mind are entirely passive, and their existence is solely dependent on being perceived; whereas a soul or spirit is an active entity whose existence consists, not in being perceived, but in perceiving ideas and thinking. Therefore, it’s essential to differentiate between spirit and idea to avoid confusion and to clarify the distinct and differing natures. See sect. 27.

140. OUR IDEA OF SPIRIT.--In a large sense, indeed, we may be said to have an idea or rather a notion of spirit; that is, we understand the meaning of the word, otherwise we could not affirm or deny anything of it. Moreover, as we conceive the ideas that are in the minds of other spirits by means of our own, which we suppose to be resemblances of them; so we know other spirits by means of our own soul--which in that sense is the image or idea of them; it having a like respect to other spirits that blueness or heat by me perceived has to those ideas perceived by another.

140. OUR IDEA OF SPIRIT.--In a broad sense, we can say we have a concept—or rather a notion—of spirit; that is, we understand what the word means, otherwise we couldn't affirm or deny anything about it. Furthermore, we grasp the ideas present in the minds of other spirits through our own, which we believe to be similar to theirs; thus, we recognize other spirits through our own soul—which, in this context, serves as an image or idea of them. Our soul relates to other spirits in a way similar to how the perception of blueness or heat relates to the ideas perceived by someone else.

141. THE NATURAL IMMORTALITY OF THE SOUL IS A NECESSARY CONSEQUENCE OF THE FOREGOING DOCTRINE.--It must not be supposed that they who assert the natural immortality of the soul are of opinion that it is absolutely incapable of annihilation even by the infinite power of the Creator who first gave it being, but only that it is not liable to be broken or dissolved by the ordinary laws of nature or motion. They indeed who hold the soul of man to be only a thin vital flame, or system of animal spirits, make it perishing and corruptible as the body; since there is nothing more easily dissipated than such a being, which it is naturally impossible should survive the ruin of the tabernacle wherein it is enclosed. And this notion has been greedily embraced and cherished by the worst part of mankind, as the most effectual antidote against all impressions of virtue and religion. But it has been made evident that bodies, of what frame or texture soever, are barely passive ideas in the mind, which is more distant and heterogeneous from them than light is from darkness. We have shown that the soul is indivisible, incorporeal, unextended, and it is consequently incorruptible. Nothing can be plainer than that the motions, changes, decays, and dissolutions which we hourly see befall natural bodies (and which is what we mean by the course of nature) cannot possibly affect an active, simple, uncompounded substance; such a being therefore is indissoluble by the force of nature; that is to say, "the soul of man is naturally immortal."

141. THE NATURAL IMMORTALITY OF THE SOUL IS A NECESSARY CONSEQUENCE OF THE FOREGOING DOCTRINE.--It shouldn’t be assumed that those who claim the natural immortality of the soul believe it is completely incapable of being destroyed, even by the infinite power of the Creator who gave it existence. They only believe that it isn’t subject to being broken down or dissolved by the regular laws of nature or motion. In fact, those who view the human soul as merely a fleeting vital flame or a system of animal spirits consider it to be perishable and corruptible, just like the body; since nothing is easier to dissipate than such a being, which naturally cannot survive the destruction of the physical body it resides in. This idea has been eagerly accepted and nurtured by the worst aspects of humanity, as the most effective deterrent against any feelings of virtue and religion. However, it has been made clear that bodies, regardless of their structure or makeup, are simply passive ideas in the mind, which is more separate and different from them than light is from darkness. We have demonstrated that the soul is indivisible, immaterial, and not extended in space, and therefore it is incorruptible. It is clear that the motions, changes, decays, and dissolutions we witness in natural bodies every day (which we refer to as the course of nature) cannot possibly affect an active, simple, uncompounded substance; thus, this kind of being is indestructible by the forces of nature. In other words, "the soul of man is naturally immortal."

142. After what has been said, it is, I suppose, plain that our souls are not to be known in the same manner as senseless, inactive objects, or by way of idea. Spirits and ideas are things so wholly different, that when we say "they exist," "they are known," or the like, these words must not be thought to signify anything common to both natures. There is nothing alike or common in them: and to expect that by any multiplication or enlargement of our faculties we may be enabled to know a spirit as we do a triangle, seems as absurd as if we should hope to see a sound. This is inculcated because I imagine it may be of moment towards clearing several important questions, and preventing some very dangerous errors concerning the nature of the soul. We may not, I think, strictly be said to have an idea of an active being, or of an action, although we may be said to have a notion of them. I have some knowledge or notion of my mind, and its acts about ideas, inasmuch as I know or understand what is meant by these words. What I know, that I have some notion of. I will not say that the terms idea and notion may not be used convertibly, if the world will have it so; but yet it conduceth to clearness and propriety that we distinguish things very different by different names. It is also to be remarked that, all relations including an act of the mind, we cannot so properly be said to have an idea, but rather a notion of the relations and habitudes between things. But if, in the modern way, the word idea is extended to spirits, and relations, and acts, this is, after all, an affair of verbal concern.

142. After what has been said, I think it’s clear that we can’t understand our souls in the same way we understand lifeless, inactive objects or through ideas. Spirits and ideas are completely different, so when we say “they exist” or “they are known,” these phrases shouldn’t be seen as meaning the same thing for both. There’s nothing alike in them; expecting to know a spirit just like we know a triangle is as ridiculous as hoping to see a sound. I mention this because I believe it’s important for clarifying several significant questions and avoiding serious misconceptions about the nature of the soul. We can’t strictly say we have an idea of an active being or an action, even though we can say we have a notion of them. I have some understanding or notion of my mind and its activities regarding ideas, as long as I know what those words mean. What I know, I have some notion of. I won’t argue that the terms idea and notion can’t be used interchangeably if that’s what people want, but it helps clarity and accuracy if we use different names for very different things. It’s also worth noting that with all relations involving an act of the mind, we can’t properly say we have an idea, but rather a notion of the relationships and connections between things. However, if, in modern usage, the word idea is expanded to include spirits, relations, and acts, that is ultimately just a matter of terminology.

143. It will not be amiss to add, that the doctrine of abstract ideas has had no small share in rendering those sciences intricate and obscure which are particularly conversant about spiritual things. Men have imagined they could frame abstract notions of the powers and acts of the mind, and consider them prescinded as well from the mind or spirit itself, as from their respective objects and effects. Hence a great number of dark and ambiguous terms, presumed to stand for abstract notions, have been introduced into metaphysics and morality, and from these have grown infinite distractions and disputes amongst the learned.

143. It's worth mentioning that the idea of abstract concepts has played a significant role in making certain sciences complicated and unclear, especially those focused on spiritual matters. People have believed they could create abstract ideas about the powers and actions of the mind, viewing them separately from both the mind or spirit itself and their specific objects and effects. As a result, a lot of vague and confusing terms, thought to represent abstract ideas, have been introduced into metaphysics and morality, leading to countless distractions and debates among scholars.

144. But, nothing seems more to have contributed towards engaging men in controversies and mistakes with regard to the nature and operations of the mind, than the being used to speak of those things in terms borrowed from sensible ideas. For example, the will is termed the motion of the soul; this infuses a belief that the mind of man is as a ball in motion, impelled and determined by the objects of sense, as necessarily as that is by the stroke of a racket. Hence arise endless scruples and errors of dangerous consequence in morality. All which, I doubt not, may be cleared, and truth appear plain, uniform, and consistent, could but philosophers be prevailed on to retire into themselves, and attentively consider their own meaning.

144. However, nothing seems to have caused more confusion and debate among people regarding the nature and functions of the mind than talking about these things using terms borrowed from physical experiences. For instance, the will is described as the movement of the soul; this creates a belief that the human mind is like a ball in motion, driven and determined by sensory experiences, just as a ball is by a racket's hit. This leads to endless doubts and errors with potentially serious consequences in morality. I have no doubt that all of this could be clarified, and the truth could be seen as clear, uniform, and consistent, if only philosophers could be encouraged to reflect deeply on their own meanings.

145. KNOWLEDGE OF SPIRITS NOT IMMEDIATE.--From what has been said, it is plain that we cannot know the existence of other spirits otherwise than by their operations, or the ideas by them excited in us. I perceive several motions, changes, and combinations of ideas, that inform me there are certain particular agents, like myself, which accompany them and concur in their production. Hence, the knowledge I have of other spirits is not immediate, as is the knowledge of my ideas; but depending on the intervention of ideas, by me referred to agents or spirits distinct from myself, as effects or concomitant signs.

145. KNOWLEDGE OF SPIRITS IS NOT IMMEDIATE.--From what has been stated, it's clear that we can't know about the existence of other spirits except through their actions or the ideas they trigger in us. I notice several movements, changes, and combinations of ideas that tell me there are specific agents, like myself, that accompany them and contribute to their creation. Therefore, my understanding of other spirits isn't immediate, like my understanding of my ideas; it's based on the ideas that I associate with agents or spirits that are separate from myself, functioning as effects or accompanying signs.

146. But, though there be some things which convince us human agents are concerned in producing them; yet it is evident to every one that those things which are called the Works of Nature, that is, the far greater part of the ideas or sensations perceived by us, are not produced by, or dependent on, the wills of men. There is therefore some other Spirit that causes them; since it is repugnant that they should subsist by themselves. See sect. 29. But, if we attentively consider the constant regularity, order, and concatenation of natural things, the surprising magnificence, beauty, and perfection of the larger, and the exquisite contrivance of the smaller parts of creation, together with the exact harmony and correspondence of the whole, but above all the never-enough-admired laws of pain and pleasure, and the instincts or natural inclinations, appetites, and passions of animals; I say if we consider all these things, and at the same time attend to the meaning and import of the attributes One, Eternal, Infinitely Wise, Good, and Perfect, we shall clearly perceive that they belong to the aforesaid Spirit, "who works all in all," and "by whom all things consist."

146. However, while there are some things that clearly show human involvement in their creation, it's obvious to everyone that what we call the Works of Nature—the vast majority of the ideas or sensations we experience—aren't created by or dependent on human will. There must be another Spirit behind them, because it’s unreasonable to think they could exist on their own. See sect. 29. But if we carefully consider the consistent regularity, order, and connection of natural things, the astonishing grandeur, beauty, and perfection of the larger aspects, and the intricate design of the smaller parts of creation, along with the precise harmony and correspondence of the whole, especially the highly regarded laws of pain and pleasure, as well as the instincts, natural inclinations, appetites, and passions of animals; I mean, if we think about all these factors and also reflect on the meanings of the attributes One, Eternal, Infinitely Wise, Good, and Perfect, we will clearly recognize that these attributes belong to the aforementioned Spirit, "who works all in all," and "by whom all things consist."

147. THE EXISTENCE OF GOD MORE EVIDENT THAN THAT OF MAN.--Hence, it is evident that God is known as certainly and immediately as any other mind or spirit whatsoever distinct from ourselves. We may even assert that the existence of God is far more evidently perceived than the existence of men; because the effects of nature are infinitely more numerous and considerable than those ascribed to human agents. There is not any one mark that denotes a man, or effect produced by him, which does not more strongly evince the being of that Spirit who is the Author of Nature. For, it is evident that in affecting other persons the will of man has no other object than barely the motion of the limbs of his body; but that such a motion should be attended by, or excite any idea in the mind of another, depends wholly on the will of the Creator. He alone it is who, "upholding all things by the word of His power," maintains that intercourse between spirits whereby they are able to perceive the existence of each other. And yet this pure and clear light which enlightens every one is itself invisible.

147. THE EXISTENCE OF GOD IS MORE EVIDENT THAN THAT OF MAN.--Therefore, it's clear that God is known as certainly and immediately as any other mind or spirit that is different from us. We can even say that God's existence is much more obvious than the existence of humans because the effects of nature are infinitely more numerous and significant than those attributed to human actions. There isn't a single characteristic that identifies a man or an effect produced by him that doesn't point more strongly to the existence of that Spirit who is the Creator of Nature. It's clear that when influencing others, a person's will only aims at moving their own body; however, whether that motion evokes any idea in another person's mind entirely depends on the Creator's will. He alone, “upholding all things by the word of His power,” maintains the connection between spirits that allows them to perceive each other's existence. Yet, this pure and clear light that illuminates everyone is itself invisible.

148. It seems to be a general pretence of the unthinking herd that they cannot see God. Could we but see Him, say they, as we see a man, we should believe that He is, and believing obey His commands. But alas, we need only open our eyes to see the Sovereign Lord of all things, with a more full and clear view than we do any one of our fellow--creatures. Not that I imagine we see God (as some will have it) by a direct and immediate view; or see corporeal things, not by themselves, but by seeing that which represents them in the essence of God, which doctrine is, I must confess, to me incomprehensible. But I shall explain my meaning;--A human spirit or person is not perceived by sense, as not being an idea; when therefore we see the colour, size, figure, and motions of a man, we perceive only certain sensations or ideas excited in our own minds; and these being exhibited to our view in sundry distinct collections, serve to mark out unto us the existence of finite and created spirits like ourselves. Hence it is plain we do not see a man--if by man is meant that which lives, moves, perceives, and thinks as we do--but only such a certain collection of ideas as directs us to think there is a distinct principle of thought and motion, like to ourselves, accompanying and represented by it. And after the same manner we see God; all the difference is that, whereas some one finite and narrow assemblage of ideas denotes a particular human mind, whithersoever we direct our view, we do at all times and in all places perceive manifest tokens of the Divinity: everything we see, hear, feel, or anywise perceive by sense, being a sign or effect of the power of God; as is our perception of those very motions which are produced by men.

148. It seems to be a common misconception among the thoughtless crowd that they can’t see God. They say if we could see Him like we see a person, we would believe He exists and, in believing, we would follow His commands. But sadly, we just need to open our eyes to see the Sovereign Lord of all things in a more complete and clear way than we see any of our fellow beings. Not that I think we see God (as some suggest) through a direct and immediate vision, or that we see physical things not by themselves, but by recognizing what represents them in God's essence, a concept I must admit I find hard to grasp. But let me clarify my point: a human spirit or person isn't perceived through our senses, as it isn't an idea; when we see the color, size, shape, and movement of a person, we are only perceiving certain sensations or ideas triggered in our minds. These sensations, presented to us in various distinct collections, help us understand the existence of finite and created beings like ourselves. So, we don't see a person—if by "person" we mean what lives, moves, perceives, and thinks like we do—but only a specific collection of ideas that leads us to believe there is a separate principle of thought and movement, similar to us, accompanying and represented by it. In the same way, we perceive God; the only difference is that while a limited and specific group of ideas indicates a particular human mind, wherever we look, we always perceive clear signs of the Divine: everything we see, hear, feel, or otherwise perceive through our senses is a sign or effect of God's power, just like our perception of the actions produced by people.

149. It is therefore plain that nothing can be more evident to any one that is capable of the least reflexion than the existence of God, or a Spirit who is intimately present to our minds, producing in them all that variety of ideas or sensations which continually affect us, on whom we have an absolute and entire dependence, in short "in whom we live, and move, and have our being." That the discovery of this great truth, which lies so near and obvious to the mind, should be attained to by the reason of so very few, is a sad instance of the stupidity and inattention of men, who, though they are surrounded with such clear manifestations of the Deity, are yet so little affected by them that they seem, as it were, blinded with excess of light.

149. It’s clear that nothing is more obvious to anyone capable of even a little reflection than the existence of God, or a Spirit who is closely present to our minds, creating all the different ideas or sensations that constantly influence us, on whom we completely and entirely depend, in short, "in whom we live, and move, and have our being." The fact that so few people come to realize this important truth, which is so close and obvious to the mind, is a sad example of the ignorance and inattention of people, who, even though they are surrounded by such clear signs of the Divine, are so little affected by them that they seem, in a way, blinded by too much light.

150. OBJECTION ON BEHALF OF NATURE.--ANSWER.--But you will say, has Nature no share in the production of natural things, and must they be all ascribed to the immediate and sole operation of God? I answer, if by Nature is meant only the visible series of effects or sensations imprinted on our minds, according to certain fixed and general laws, then it is plain that Nature, taken in this sense, cannot produce anything at all. But, if by Nature is meant some being distinct from God, as well as from the laws of nature, and things perceived by sense, I must confess that word is to me an empty sound without any intelligible meaning annexed to it. Nature, in this acceptation, is a vain chimera, introduced by those heathens who had not just notions of the omnipresence and infinite perfection of God. But, it is more unaccountable that it should be received among Christians, professing belief in the Holy Scriptures, which constantly ascribe those effects to the immediate hand of God that heathen philosophers are wont to impute to Nature. "The Lord He causeth the vapours to ascend; He maketh lightnings with rain; He bringeth forth the wind out of his treasures." Jerem. 10. 13. "He turneth the shadow of death into the morning, and maketh the day dark with night." Amos, 5. 8. "He visiteth the earth, and maketh it soft with showers: He blesseth the springing thereof, and crowneth the year with His goodness; so that the pastures are clothed with flocks, and the valleys are covered over with corn." See Psalm 65. But, notwithstanding that this is the constant language of Scripture, yet we have I know not what aversion from believing that God concerns Himself so nearly in our affairs. Fain would we suppose Him at a great distance off, and substitute some blind unthinking deputy in His stead, though (if we may believe Saint Paul) "He be not far from every one of us."

150. OBJECTION ON BEHALF OF NATURE.--ANSWER.--But you might ask, does Nature have no role in creating natural things, and should everything be attributed solely to God's direct action? My response is this: if we define Nature as just the visible sequence of effects or sensations that are impressed on our minds according to specific and general laws, then it's clear that Nature, understood this way, cannot create anything at all. However, if we consider Nature to be something separate from God, as well as from the laws of nature, and the things we perceive, I have to say that this term doesn't hold any real meaning for me. In this sense, Nature is just an empty concept, introduced by those ancient thinkers who didn't grasp the omnipresence and infinite perfection of God. It's even more surprising that this idea has been accepted among Christians, who claim to believe in the Holy Scriptures that consistently attribute these effects to God's direct hand, which heathen philosophers tend to ascribe to Nature. "The Lord causes the vapors to rise; He makes lightning with rain; He brings forth the wind from His storehouses." Jerem. 10. 13. "He turns the shadow of death into morning, and brings darkness over the day." Amos, 5. 8. "He visits the earth and makes it soft with showers; He blesses its growth and crowns the year with His goodness, so that the pastures are filled with flocks, and the valleys are covered with grain." See Psalm 65. Yet, despite the fact that this is the consistent message of Scripture, we seem to have some sort of reluctance to believe that God is so involved in our lives. We would rather imagine Him as being far away and replace Him with some blind, unthinking agent, even though (if we can trust Saint Paul) "He is not far from each one of us."

151. OBJECTION TO THE HAND OF GOD BEING THE IMMEDIATE CAUSE, THREEFOLD.--ANSWER.--It will, I doubt not, be objected that the slow and gradual methods observed in the production of natural things do not seem to have for their cause the immediate hand of an Almighty Agent. Besides, monsters, untimely births, fruits blasted in the blossom, rains falling in desert places, miseries incident to human life, and the like, are so many arguments that the whole frame of nature is not immediately actuated and superintended by a Spirit of infinite wisdom and goodness. But the answer to this objection is in a good measure plain from sect. 62; it being visible that the aforesaid methods of nature are absolutely necessary, in order to working by the most simple and general rules, and after a steady and consistent manner; which argues both the wisdom and goodness of God. Such is the artificial contrivance of this mighty machine of nature that, whilst its motions and various phenomena strike on our senses, the hand which actuates the whole is itself unperceivable to men of flesh and blood. "Verily" (saith the prophet) "thou art a God that hidest thyself." Isaiah, 45. 15. But, though the Lord conceal Himself from the eyes of the sensual and lazy, who will not be at the least expense of thought, yet to an unbiased and attentive mind nothing can be more plainly legible than the intimate presence of an All-wise Spirit, who fashions, regulates and sustains the whole system of beings. It is clear, from what we have elsewhere observed, that the operating according to general and stated laws is so necessary for our guidance in the affairs of life, and letting us into the secret of nature, that without it all reach and compass of thought, all human sagacity and design, could serve to no manner of purpose; it were even impossible there should be any such faculties or powers in the mind. See sect. 31. Which one consideration abundantly outbalances whatever particular inconveniences may thence arise.

151. OBJECTION TO THE HAND OF GOD BEING THE IMMEDIATE CAUSE, THREEFOLD.--ANSWER.--I have no doubt that it will be argued that the slow and gradual processes seen in nature don’t really suggest the direct intervention of an Almighty Being. Additionally, things like monsters, premature births, fruit that doesn't develop properly, rain falling in barren places, and the various sufferings of human life are numerous examples that imply the entire structure of nature is not directly managed by an infinitely wise and good Spirit. However, the response to this objection is partly clear from section 62; it's evident that these natural processes are absolutely necessary to operate under simple and general rules and in a consistent manner, which actually reflects both the wisdom and goodness of God. The intricate design of this vast machine of nature means that while its movements and various phenomena impact our senses, the hand that drives it all remains invisible to ordinary humans. "Truly" (the prophet says) "you are a God who hides yourself." Isaiah 45:15. Yet, even though the Lord may keep Himself hidden from those who are sensual and lazy, unwilling to expend even a little thought, for an unbiased and attentive mind, nothing is clearer than the intimate presence of an All-wise Spirit who shapes, governs, and supports the entire system of existence. From what we have noted elsewhere, it is clear that following general and established laws is crucial for guiding us in our lives and revealing the secrets of nature; without this structure, all our mental abilities and plans would serve no real purpose, and it would be impossible for such faculties or powers to exist in the mind. See section 31. This consideration significantly outweighs any particular issues that may arise from it.

152. We should further consider that the very blemishes and defects of nature are not without their use, in that they make an agreeable sort of variety, and augment the beauty of the rest of the creation, as shades in a picture serve to set off the brighter and more enlightened parts. We would likewise do well to examine whether our taxing the waste of seeds and embryos, and accidental destruction of plants and animals, before they come to full maturity, as an imprudence in the Author of nature, be not the effect of prejudice contracted by our familiarity with impotent and saving mortals. In man indeed a thrifty management of those things which he cannot procure without much pains and industry may be esteemed wisdom. But, we must not imagine that the inexplicably fine machine of an animal or vegetable costs the great Creator any more pains or trouble in its production than a pebble does; nothing being more evident than that an Omnipotent Spirit can indifferently produce everything by a mere fiat or act of His will. Hence, it is plain that the splendid profusion of natural things should not be interpreted weakness or prodigality in the agent who produces them, but rather be looked on as an argument of the riches of His power.

152. We should also think about how the flaws and imperfections in nature aren't without their value; they create a nice variety and enhance the beauty of the rest of creation, just like shadows in a painting highlight the brighter and more vivid areas. We should also consider whether criticizing the waste of seeds and embryos, along with the accidental destruction of plants and animals before they reach full maturity, reflects a bias we've developed from being familiar with weak and conservative humans. In humans, being careful with things that require significant effort and hard work can be viewed as wisdom. However, we shouldn't assume that the incredibly complex structure of an animal or plant takes the Creator any more effort or trouble to make than a pebble does; it's clear that an all-powerful Spirit can easily create anything with just a command or an act of His will. Thus, it’s evident that the lavish abundance of natural things shouldn't be seen as weakness or extravagance in the one who creates them, but rather as a demonstration of His immense power.

153. As for the mixture of pain or uneasiness which is in the world, pursuant to the general laws of nature, and the actions of finite, imperfect spirits, this, in the state we are in at present, is indispensably necessary to our well-being. But our prospects are too narrow. We take, for instance, the idea of some one particular pain into our thoughts, and account it evil; whereas, if we enlarge our view, so as to comprehend the various ends, connexions, and dependencies of things, on what occasions and in what proportions we are affected with pain and pleasure, the nature of human freedom, and the design with which we are put into the world; we shall be forced to acknowledge that those particular things which, considered in themselves, appear to be evil, have the nature of good, when considered as linked with the whole system of beings.

153. When it comes to the mix of pain or discomfort present in the world, following the general laws of nature and the actions of limited, imperfect beings, this is absolutely necessary for our well-being in our current state. However, our perspective is often too limited. For example, we focus on a specific pain and see it as bad; yet, if we broaden our perspective to understand the various purposes, connections, and dependencies of things — how we experience pain and pleasure, the nature of human freedom, and the purpose of our existence — we must recognize that what seems to be purely evil in isolation can actually be part of a larger good when linked to the entire system of existence.

154. ATHEISM AND MANICHEISM WOULD HAVE FEW SUPPORTERS IF MANKIND WERE IN GENERAL ATTENTIVE.--From what has been said, it will be manifest to any considering person, that it is merely for want of attention and comprehensiveness of mind that there are any favourers of Atheism or the Manichean Heresy to be found. Little and unreflecting souls may indeed burlesque the works of Providence, the beauty and order whereof they have not capacity, or will not be at the pains, to comprehend; but those who are masters of any justness and extent of thought, and are withal used to reflect, can never sufficiently admire the divine traces of Wisdom and Goodness that shine throughout the Economy of Nature. But what truth is there which shineth so strongly on the mind that by an aversion of thought, a wilful shutting of the eyes, we may not escape seeing it? Is it therefore to be wondered at, if the generality of men, who are ever intent on business or pleasure, and little used to fix or open the eye of their mind, should not have all that conviction and evidence of the Being of God which might be expected in reasonable creatures?

154. ATHEISM AND MANICHEISM WOULD HAVE FEW SUPPORTERS IF PEOPLE WERE GENERALLY ATTENTIVE.--From what has been said, it becomes clear to anyone who thinks about it that the only reason there are supporters of Atheism or the Manichean Heresy is the lack of attention and depth of understanding. Simple and unreflective individuals may mock the works of Providence, the beauty and order of which they lack the capacity or willingness to grasp; however, those who possess a fair degree of insight and reflection can never help but admire the divine evidence of Wisdom and Goodness that permeates the Economy of Nature. But is there any truth that shines so clearly in our minds that we can simply ignore it, choosing to close our eyes? So, is it any wonder that most people, who are constantly focused on work or pleasure and seldom take the time to truly open their minds, do not have the kind of conviction and evidence of God's existence that would be expected from rational beings?

155. We should rather wonder that men can be found so stupid as to neglect, than that neglecting they should be unconvinced of such an evident and momentous truth. And yet it is to be feared that too many of parts and leisure, who live in Christian countries, are, merely through a supine and dreadful negligence, sunk into Atheism. Since it is downright impossible that a soul pierced and enlightened with a thorough sense of the omnipresence, holiness, and justice of that Almighty Spirit should persist in a remorseless violation of His laws. We ought, therefore, earnestly to meditate and dwell on those important points; that so we may attain conviction without all scruple "that the eyes of the Lord are in every place beholding the evil and the good; that He is with us and keepeth us in all places whither we go, and giveth us bread to eat and raiment to put on"; that He is present and conscious to our innermost thoughts; and that we have a most absolute and immediate dependence on Him. A clear view of which great truths cannot choose but fill our hearts with an awful circumspection and holy fear, which is the strongest incentive to Virtue, and the best guard against Vice.

155. We should be more surprised that people can be so foolish as to ignore this truth, rather than that those who do neglect it are unconvinced by such an obvious and important fact. Yet, it’s worrying that too many educated people living in Christian countries have, through sheer laziness and negligence, fallen into Atheism. It's impossible for a soul that truly understands and feels the presence, holiness, and justice of the Almighty to continue to ignore His laws without remorse. Therefore, we should seriously reflect on these crucial points; so we can come to be fully convinced "that the eyes of the Lord are in every place observing the evil and the good; that He is with us and keeps us in all the places we go, providing us with food and clothing"; that He is aware of our deepest thoughts; and that we are completely and directly dependent on Him. A clear understanding of these profound truths will inevitably fill our hearts with a deep sense of awareness and reverence, which is the strongest motivation for Virtue and the best protection against Vice.

156. For, after all, what deserves the first place in our studies is the consideration of GOD and our DUTY; which to promote, as it was the main drift and design of my labours, so shall I esteem them altogether useless and ineffectual if, by what I have said, I cannot inspire my readers with a pious sense of the Presence of God; and, having shown the falseness or vanity of those barren speculations which make the chief employment of learned men, the better dispose them to reverence and embrace the salutary truths of the Gospel, which to know and to practice is the highest perfection of human nature.

156. Ultimately, what should come first in our studies is the understanding of God and our responsibilities. My main goal has always been to promote this, and I would consider my efforts completely useless if I can't inspire my readers with a genuine awareness of God's presence. Having pointed out the emptiness of those pointless theories that occupy many scholars, I hope to encourage a greater respect for and acceptance of the essential truths of the Gospel, which is the ultimate fulfillment of human nature.






Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!