This is a modern-English version of Karl Marx, originally written by Loria, Achille. It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.

Transcriber's Note:

A Table of Contents has been added.

Transcriber's Note:

A Table of Contents has been included.



KARL MARX

KARL MARX

A SKETCH

A Drawing

BY

BY

ACHILLE LORIA

Achille Loria


title page

KARL MARX

BY
ACHILLE LORIA

BY
ACHILLE LORIA

AUTHORISED TRANSLATION FROM THE ITALIAN
WITH A FOREWORD

AUTHORISED TRANSLATION FROM THE ITALIAN
WITH A FOREWORD

BY
EDEN & CEDAR PAUL

BY
EDEN & CEDAR PAUL

logo

New York
THOMAS SELTZER
1920

New York
Thomas Seltzer
1920


Copyright, 1920,
By Thomas Seltzer, Inc.

————
All Rights Reserved

Copyright, 1920,
By Thomas Seltzer, Inc.

————
All Rights Reserved

Printed in the United States of America

Printed in the United States of America


The socialism that inspires hopes and fears to-day is of the school of Marx. No one is seriously apprehensive of any other so-called socialistic movement, and no one is seriously concerned to criticise or refute the doctrines set forth by any other school of "socialists."

The socialism that generates both hope and fear today comes from the Marxist school of thought. No one is genuinely worried about any other so-called socialistic movements, and no one seems particularly interested in criticizing or disputing the ideas put forward by any other group of "socialists."


CONTENTS

    Page
FOREWARD 7
CHAPTER I 57
CHAPTER II 73
CHAPTER III 87
CHAPTER IV 112
CHAPTER V 145

FOREWORD

FOREWORD

BY

BY

EDEN AND CEDAR PAUL

EDEN & CEDAR PAUL


FOREWORD

It has been said that the professional and professorial exponents of economic science confine themselves to variants of a single theme. Usually belonging to the master class by birth and education, and at any rate attached to that class by the ties of economic interest, they are ever guided by the conscious or subconscious aim of providing a theoretical justification for the capitalist system, and their lives are devoted to inculcating the art of extracting honey from the hive without alarming the bees. Achille Loria is an exception to this generalisation. Professor of political economy at Turin, and one of the most learned economists of the day, he is anything but an apologist for the bourgeois economy. With[Pg 10] the exception of the first volume of Marx's Capital, no more telling indictment of capitalism has ever been penned than Loria's Analysis of Capitalist Property (1889).

It has been said that the professionals and professors of economic science stick to variations of a single theme. Usually born and educated in the upper class, and definitely connected to that class through economic interests, they are always driven by the conscious or subconscious goal of providing a theoretical justification for the capitalist system. Their lives are dedicated to teaching the art of extracting rewards from the system without disturbing the status quo. Achille Loria is an exception to this generalization. A professor of political economy at Turin and one of the most knowledgeable economists of his time, he is far from being an apologist for the bourgeois economy. With[Pg 10] the exception of the first volume of Marx's Capital, no more powerful critique of capitalism has ever been written than Loria's Analysis of Capitalist Property (1889).

This gigantic work has not been translated, but a number of Loria's books are available to English readers: The Economic Foundations of Society, 1902; Contemporary Social Problems, 1911; The Economic Synthesis, 1914. A biographical and critical study of Malthus, in the Italian, was rendered into English in 1917 and published in the United States as the opening chapter of a symposium on Population and Birth Control edited by the writers of this foreword. The Economic Foundations of Society has run through five editions in Swan Sonnenschein's (now Allen & Unwin's) "Social Science Series." But on the whole Loria's works are less widely known in England and America than on the continent, far less widely known than they deserve to be.

This massive work hasn't been translated, but several of Loria's books are available to English readers: The Economic Foundations of Society, 1902; Contemporary Social Problems, 1911; The Economic Synthesis, 1914. A biographical and critical study of Malthus, originally in Italian, was translated into English in 1917 and published in the United States as the opening chapter of a symposium on Population and Birth Control edited by the authors of this foreword. The Economic Foundations of Society has gone through five editions in Swan Sonnenschein's (now Allen & Unwin's) "Social Science Series." However, overall, Loria's works are less recognized in England and America than they are on the continent, and they are far less known than they deserve to be.

An exposition of his outlook and a study of his relationship to Marx will not only be of interest in themselves, but will help readers to surmount certain terminological difficulties in the Karl Marx. All original thinkers write perforce in a language of their own minting. Those of us to whom "surplus value," the "class struggle," the "materialist conception," "economic determinism," have been familiar concepts from childhood upwards, are apt to forget that Marx's contemporaries were repelled by what they regarded as superfluous jargon. The first students of Kant, the first students of Darwin, the first students of all great innovators in philosophy, science, and the arts, have had to master a new vocabulary before they could understand what these writers were driving at; for new ideas must be conveyed in a new speech or by the use of old words refashioned. We cannot understand Loria, we cannot appreciate Loria's criticism of Marx, we cannot grasp the nature of Loria's[Pg 12] own affiliation to Marx, unless we realise precisely what the Italian economist means by the speciously familiar terms "income," "subsistence," "unproductive labourers," "recipients of income," and the like. The familiarity of the words makes them all the more misleading to those who do not hold the Lorian clue to guide them through the economic labyrinth. Does this sound alarming? Yet Loria's doctrines, like those of Marx, like those of Darwin, like those of—but we must not say "like those of Kant"—are simplicity itself to anyone who is able to survive the first shock of the encounter, to surmount the first agony of a new idea.

An explanation of his viewpoint and an examination of his connection to Marx will not only be interesting on their own but will also help readers overcome certain language challenges in the Karl Marx. All original thinkers naturally create a language of their own. Those of us who have been familiar with concepts like "surplus value," "class struggle," "materialist conception," and "economic determinism" since childhood might forget that Marx's contemporaries were put off by what they saw as unnecessary jargon. The first students of Kant, the first students of Darwin, and the first students of all major innovators in philosophy, science, and the arts had to learn a new vocabulary to understand what these writers were addressing; new ideas must be expressed in new language or by reinterpreting old words. We can’t fully understand Loria, appreciate his criticism of Marx, or grasp the nature of Loria's[Pg 12] connection to Marx unless we recognize exactly what the Italian economist means by the seemingly familiar terms "income," "subsistence," "unproductive laborers," "recipients of income," and so on. The familiarity of these words makes them even more misleading for those who do not have the Lorian insights to navigate the economic maze. Does this sound daunting? Yet Loria's ideas, like those of Marx, like those of Darwin, like those of—but we shouldn't say "like those of Kant"—are quite simple for anyone who can get past the initial shock of the encounter and move beyond the initial discomfort of a new idea.

In our own view the difficulty of economics in large part depends upon the fact that it is either a system of apologetics or else a system of attack. There are, in fact, two conflicting sciences: the economic science of the master class, and the economic science of the [Pg 13]proletariat. Both are necessarily tendentious, and the conflicting tendencies will remain irreconcilable as long as the class struggle continues. Not until that struggle has been fought to a successful issue, not until the co-operative commonwealth has come into existence, can there be a comparatively dispassionate political economy. As dispassionate as conic sections it can never be, for it is biological, sociological, is by its very nature tinged with human interest, and can therefore never be wholly impartial. But many of the contradictions and perplexities of economics are by no means inherent; they are, we contend, no more than confusing reflexes of the class struggle.

In our opinion, the complexity of economics largely stems from the fact that it operates either as a system of defense or a system of offense. There are actually two opposing branches of economics: the economic perspective of the ruling class and the economic perspective of the proletariat. Both are inherently biased, and the conflicting views will remain irreconcilable as long as the class struggle exists. Only when this struggle has reached a successful conclusion, and the cooperative commonwealth is established, can we have a more objective political economy. However, it will never be as neutral as conic sections because it is biological and sociological; it is inherently influenced by human interests and can never be completely impartial. Many of the contradictions and challenges in economics are not inherent; we argue that they are merely confusing reflections of the class struggle.

Loria seems to hold a somewhat similar opinion. In Contemporary Social Problems (pp. 99, 100) he writes: "I am inclined to consider political economy and socialism as two intellectual weapons which, for a long time separate and mutually antagonistic owing to the apologetic theories of the one and the [Pg 14]subversive utopianism of the other, are drawing closer and closer together as they become more human and the old animosities disappear. Perhaps the day is not far distant when the two forces will unite under one standard." To a casual reader this might suggest that Loria thinks that the class struggle, that the conflict between orthodox economics and socialism, can be overcome within the framework of the bourgeois economy—that the capitalist Old-Man-of-the-Sea can at one and the same time remain seated upon the back of the proletarian Sindbad the Sailor, and walk beside him amicably arm in arm as the two climb the mount of human endeavour. But an attentive student of Loria's Karl Marx will realise that when the Italian speaks of "a day not far distant," he means the morrow of the social revolution, when Marx's promethean work shall have been completed, and when, led by Marx "the emperor in the realm of mind," the human race shall have reached "the brilliant[Pg 15] goal which awaits it in a future not perhaps immeasurably remote" (infra p. 162).

Loria seems to share a similar view. In Contemporary Social Problems (pp. 99, 100), he writes: "I tend to think of political economy and socialism as two intellectual tools that, for a long time, were kept separate and opposed due to the defensive theories of one and the [Pg 14]radical utopianism of the other. However, they are gradually coming together as they evolve to be more humane and the old hostilities fade away. Perhaps the day is not too far off when these two forces will unite under a single banner." To a casual reader, this might imply that Loria believes the class struggle, the conflict between traditional economics and socialism, can be resolved within the context of the bourgeois economy—that the capitalist Old-Man-of-the-Sea can simultaneously stay on the back of the proletarian Sindbad the Sailor while walking alongside him in harmony as they both ascend the mountain of human effort. But a careful reader of Loria's Karl Marx will understand that when the Italian refers to "a day not too far off," he is talking about the day after the social revolution, when Marx's groundbreaking work will be complete, and when, guided by Marx "the emperor in the realm of thought," humanity will have reached "the brilliant[Pg 15] goal that awaits it in a future that isn't maybe too distant" (infra p. 162).

For Loria, one of the greatest living champions of the doctrine of economic determinism, sees no difficulty in reconciling that doctrine with a firm belief in the magistral efficacy, at the stage which evolution has now reached, of the deliberate human will. "The economic natural force," writes Eduard Bernstein (Evolutionary Socialism, p. 14), "like the physical, changes from the ruler of mankind to its servant, according as its nature is recognised." Herein is embodied the application in the special economic field of the profound general truth that by scientific study man, the child of nature, learns to control nature, and thereby to mould his own being and social environment in accordance with the dictates of his own enlightened will. Similarly Loria is far from the rigid economic determinism which would refuse to admit the existence of "ideal" causation, or the [Pg 16]possibility in the sphere of sociology of intelligently adapting means to ends. "Idealism" is a word which has been soiled by such ignoble use that one really hesitates to employ it; but we must distinguish between idealism and sentimentalism, and between idealism and window dressing. The right sort of idealism is realist idealism, and Loria is a realist idealist. He distinguishes clearly between fatalism and quietism, on the one hand, and economic determinism tempered by rationalist guidance, on the other.

For Loria, one of the leading advocates of economic determinism, sees no issue in reconciling that belief with a strong faith in the powerful impact of the deliberate human will at the current stage of evolution. "The economic natural force," writes Eduard Bernstein (Evolutionary Socialism, p. 14), "like the physical, shifts from being the ruler of humanity to becoming its servant, depending on whether its nature is acknowledged." This reflects the application in the specific economic area of the deeper general truth that through scientific study, humanity—being a part of nature—learns to control nature, thus shaping its own existence and social environment according to its enlightened choices. Likewise, Loria is far from the strict economic determinism that would deny the existence of "ideal" causation or the [Pg 16]possibility in sociology of intelligently aligning means with ends. "Idealism" is a term that has been tarnished by misuse to the point that one hesitates to use it; however, we must differentiate between idealism and sentimentalism, and between idealism and superficiality. The right kind of idealism is realist idealism, and Loria embodies a realist idealist perspective. He makes a clear distinction between fatalism and passivity on one side, and economic determinism guided by rational thought on the other.

In The Economic Foundations of Society (pp. 376 et seq.) he writes: "Can we say that a doctrine leads to fatalism which concedes a fertile field to human activity, and which only seeks to mark out the limits within which such efforts may be applied? Can we give the name of quietism to a theory whose aims lie in the direction of substituting enlightened action, aware of its ends, for blind and ignorant innovation which is powerless to realise its [Pg 17]purposes?... Turning to consider the great social transformations which alter the structure of property, our theory does, it is true, deny that such movements can be effected before the necessary change in economic conditions has rendered them inevitable; but far from this conclusion leading to the degradation of human nature, it seems to us to inspire the highest sentiments. If we examine the great spontaneous movements that have sought to modify economic conditions before their time, we shall find that they all lacked definite purpose. There was no clear idea of the new order of things to be substituted for the old; on this account these movements were wanting in discipline; they were anarchic, and hence their lack of effect. Our theory, on the contrary, declares that it is first of all necessary to learn the nature of the future social system, and, after this knowledge has been acquired, to substitute a co-ordination of effort towards this rigorously determined end for the blind[Pg 18] and disorganised attempts that have thus far been made in this direction.... Far from leading towards fatalism our theory tends to encourage rational human activity, which alone can prevent, or at least mitigate, the confusion otherwise attendant upon the social metamorphosis.... A wide field is thus opened to human activity, and it is certainly a noble mission for mankind to withdraw social development from the operation of the blind and brutal forces of physical evolution and to submit the process to the kindlier and more civilised action of human reason."

In The Economic Foundations of Society (pp. 376 et seq.), he writes: "Can we say that a belief leads to fatalism if it recognizes a productive space for human effort and just aims to define the boundaries within which that effort can occur? Can we label a theory as quietism if its goal is to replace mindless and ignorant change, which cannot achieve its aims, with informed action that knows its objectives?... If we look at the significant social changes that shift the structure of property, our theory does indeed argue that such changes cannot happen until the necessary shifts in economic conditions make them unavoidable; but rather than this view diminishing human nature, it seems to inspire the highest ideals. When we analyze the major spontaneous movements that tried to change economic conditions prematurely, we see that they all lacked a clear purpose. There was no solid vision of what the new system should replace the old, which is why these movements lacked discipline; they were chaotic, resulting in their ineffectiveness. Our theory, on the other hand, asserts that it is essential first to understand the nature of the future social system, and only after acquiring this knowledge should we coordinate our efforts toward this clearly defined goal instead of the blind[Pg 18] and disorganized attempts made so far in this direction.... Rather than leading to fatalism, our theory encourages rational human action, which alone can prevent, or at least lessen, the chaos that usually accompanies social transformation.... This opens up a vast area for human effort, and it is indeed a noble task for humanity to steer social development away from the random and harsh forces of natural evolution and to guide the process with the more compassionate and civilized influence of human reason."

The definitive exposition of Loria's views is to be found in The Economic Synthesis; but since in his theory of social evolution the effects of increasing population play so notable a part, reference must first be made to his examination of Malthus' theory of population. At the outset, however, let us recall Marx's attitude to the Malthusian doctrine.

The best explanation of Loria's views can be found in The Economic Synthesis; however, because his theory of social evolution places significant importance on the effects of growing population, we must first refer to his analysis of Malthus' population theory. To start, let's remember Marx's stance on the Malthusian doctrine.

Marx rejected the idea that, for human beings, population tends to grow in such a manner as necessarily to press on the means of subsistence. Though he accepted Darwinism and had a profound admiration for Darwin, as far as the human species is concerned he rejected Malthusianism (on which Darwinism is based), and wrote of Malthus in terms of bitter personal hostility. The animus we may ignore, but the arguments are worth recapitulating. Pressure of population, he says, is the outcome of capitalism. On p. 645 of Capital Marx writes: "The labouring population ... produces, along with the accumulation of capital produced by it, the means by which it is itself made relatively superfluous, is turned into a relatively surplus population, and it does this always to an increasing extent. This is a law of population peculiar to the capitalist mode of production, and in fact every special historic mode of production has its own special laws of population, historically[Pg 20] valid within its limits alone. An abstract law of population exists for plants and animals only, and only in so far as man has not interfered with them." Later in the same chapter he says (in effect) that undue fertility is characteristic of poverty-stricken circumstances, and that with improved conditions the population difficulty tends to settle itself.

Marx dismissed the idea that human populations naturally grow in a way that puts pressure on the means of subsistence. While he accepted Darwinism and greatly admired Darwin, he rejected Malthusian ideas regarding the human species, expressing strong personal animosity toward Malthus. We can overlook the hostility, but the arguments are worth summarizing. He argues that population pressure is a result of capitalism. On page 645 of Capital, Marx writes: "The laboring population ... produces, alongside the accumulation of capital created by it, the means by which it becomes relatively unnecessary, turning it into a relatively surplus population, and this happens increasingly over time. This is a population law unique to the capitalist mode of production, and in fact, each specific historical mode of production has its own distinct population laws, valid only within its own limits. An abstract law of population exists only for plants and animals, and only to the extent that humans have not intervened with them." Later in the same chapter, he observes that excessive fertility is typical of impoverished conditions and that as conditions improve, population issues tend to resolve themselves.

We shall see that Loria says much the same thing, and shall consider the assertion presently.

We will see that Loria says something very similar, and we will look at that claim shortly.

At a later date (1875) Marx writes somewhat more guardedly. In his Criticism of the Gotha Programme the reference to the Malthusian doctrine of population runs as follows: "But if I accept this law [the iron law of wages] as formulated by Lassalle, I must likewise accept its foundation. What is this foundation? As F. A. Lange showed shortly after Lassalle's death, the iron law of wages is founded upon Malthus' theory of population, a theory which Lange himself espoused.[Pg 21] Now if the iron law of wages be correct, it is impossible to abrogate it, even if we should do away with wage labour a hundred times over, for not the wage system alone, but every social system, must be governed by the law. Upon this foundation, for fifty years and more, economists have continued to demonstrate that socialism could never suppress poverty, which they regard as resulting from the nature of things. Socialism, they declare, can only generalise poverty, can only diffuse it simultaneously over the whole surface of society!"

At a later date (1875), Marx writes with a bit more caution. In his Criticism of the Gotha Programme, he references the Malthusian theory of population as follows: “But if I accept this law [the iron law of wages] as stated by Lassalle, I must also accept its basis. What is this basis? As F. A. Lange pointed out shortly after Lassalle's death, the iron law of wages is based on Malthus' population theory, a theory that Lange himself supported.[Pg 21] Now, if the iron law of wages is correct, it cannot be abolished, even if we eliminated wage labor a hundred times over, because not just the wage system, but every social system must adhere to this law. On this basis, for over fifty years, economists have continued to argue that socialism could never eliminate poverty, which they view as a natural consequence of things. They claim socialism can only spread poverty, distributing it evenly across all of society!”

Does it not almost seem as if Marx, by 1875, had, for a moment at least, glimpsed the real difficulty? For if we grant for the sake of argument that the excess of population under capitalism be only a relative excess, if we grant that each historic mode of production has its own special law of population, the question we have to ask ourselves as socialists is, "What will be the law of population under socialism?" May not socialism tend to promote an[Pg 22] absolute excess of population? Will not natural increase, stimulated by easy circumstances, threaten the stability of the system unless the growth of population be deliberately checked? Will not the inhabitants of each area have to specify some limit beyond which it is undesirable that the population of that area should increase? Ways and means, social and individual, lie beyond our present scope. But in our opinion Paul Lafargue, Henry George, and many others who have written on this question, and who have endeavoured to meet the Malthusian difficulty by a simple denial of the facts upon which "Parson Malthus" grounded his theory, have displayed more zeal than knowledge. As Karl Pearson wrote thirty years ago: "Marx by abusing Malthus has not solved the population difficulty"; and we agree with the same writer that "the acceptance of the law discovered by Malthus is an essential of any socialistic theory which pretends to be scientific"; but happily it is no[Pg 23] longer true that "Kautsky seems to stand alone among socialists in accepting the Malthusian law and its consequences" (The Ethic of Free-thought, 1888, pp. 438-9).

Does it not almost seem like Marx, by 1875, had, for a moment at least, caught a glimpse of the real difficulty? For if we assume, just for the sake of argument, that the surplus population under capitalism is only relative, and if we accept that each historical mode of production has its own specific law of population, the question we need to ask ourselves as socialists is, "What will the law of population be under socialism?" Could socialism end up promoting an [Pg 22] absolute surplus population? Will natural growth, encouraged by favorable conditions, threaten the system's stability unless population growth is intentionally controlled? Will the residents of each area need to set some limit beyond which it’s undesirable for the population to grow? The methods and means, both social and individual, go beyond our current discussion. But in our view, Paul Lafargue, Henry George, and many others who have addressed this question and tried to tackle the Malthusian issue by simply denying the facts that "Parson Malthus" based his theory on, have shown more enthusiasm than understanding. As Karl Pearson wrote thirty years ago: "Marx has not solved the population issue by criticizing Malthus"; and we agree with the same author that "accepting the law discovered by Malthus is essential for any socialistic theory that claims to be scientific"; but fortunately, it is no[Pg 23] longer true that "Kautsky seems to stand alone among socialists in accepting the Malthusian law and its consequences" (The Ethic of Free-thought, 1888, pp. 438-9).

Loria's treatment of the subject is closely akin to that of Marx, though Loria differs from Marx in that he speaks with admiration, nay almost with veneration, of the author of The Principles of Population. As regards the main issue, Loria contends that while Malthus elucidated a profoundly important truth, he erred in respect of many of its applications. In present conditions, i.e., under capitalism, says Loria, there is no excess of population over food supply, but merely (in certain countries) an excess of people in relation to the privately owned capital which is able to secure profitable investment. Hence, as a result not of over-population but simply of capitalist conditions, we have in addition to the mass of the workers who obtain subsistence, on the one hand an owning class with a[Pg 24] superfluity, and on the other a parasitic class of dependents, paupers, semi-criminals, and criminals.

Loria's approach to the topic is quite similar to Marx's, but he differs in that he speaks with admiration, even reverence, for the author of The Principles of Population. Regarding the main issue, Loria argues that while Malthus highlighted a deeply significant truth, he made mistakes in many of its applications. In today’s context, that is, under capitalism, Loria states that there is no surplus of population compared to food supply, but rather (in certain countries) there are more people than there is privately owned capital available for profitable investments. Therefore, not due to overpopulation but simply because of capitalist conditions, we see alongside the mass of workers who can meet their basic needs, on one hand, a owning class with a[Pg 24] surplus, and on the other hand, a parasitic class of dependents, poor individuals, semi-criminals, and criminals.

He contends, further, that Malthus' theory is invalidated by the ascertained fact that, as far as human beings are concerned, an excess of food over population does not necessarily lead to an increase in the birth rate—that a rising standard of life is nowadays apt to be characterised by diminished procreation. Speaking of certain postmalthusian applications of Malthus' theory, he writes (Contemporary Social Problems, p. 79): "Some also suggest various physiological expedients—the obscene abominations of the so-called neomalthusians—to limit population. Do they not see that there is no excess of mouths to be fed, and that procreation will of itself diminish with the amelioration of the condition of the working classes, without recourse to loathsome and unnatural practices?"

He argues that Malthus' theory is proven wrong by the fact that, for humans, having more food than people doesn't necessarily lead to a higher birth rate—that a better standard of living today often means fewer children being born. Discussing some recent interpretations of Malthus' theory, he writes (Contemporary Social Problems, p. 79): "Some also propose various physiological methods—the disgusting practices of the so-called neomalthusians—to control population. Don't they realize there's no surplus of mouths to feed, and that reproduction will naturally decline as the conditions for the working class improve, without needing to resort to gross and unnatural methods?"

In this passage, as repeatedly in his Malthus,[Pg 25] Loria fails oddly (for so acute a mind) in his analysis of operating causes. As the result of a rising standard of life—consequent upon improved economic conditions among the proletariat—the workers, we are told (Malthus, p. 80), "become less prolific." Thus the growth of population is "automatically" regulated by economic means, and there is no need to have recourse to "physiological expedients" to limit population. Yet he nowhere endeavours to elucidate the working of this economic factor in the biologic field, or to show how it can possibly operate unless precisely in virtue of what he is so strangely and so inconsistently moved to condemn, viz., the deliberate application of increasing physiological knowledge by individual couples in order to regulate the number of their offspring. In a word, by birth control.

In this passage, as he does repeatedly in his Malthus,[Pg 25] Loria surprisingly (for someone so sharp) misses the mark in his analysis of contributing factors. As a result of a rising standard of living—due to improved economic conditions among the working class—the workers, we're told (Malthus, p. 80), "become less prolific." Thus, the growth of the population is "automatically" regulated by economic means, and there's no need to resort to "physiological expedients" to control population. However, he never attempts to explain how this economic factor functions in the biological realm or how it could possibly work unless it involves what he strangely and inconsistently criticizes, namely, the intentional use of increasing physiological knowledge by individual couples to manage the size of their families. In short, by birth control.

As far as past stages of economic evolution are concerned, the transition from primitive tribal communism to slavery, from slavery to[Pg 26] serfdom and the guild system, and from these to capitalism, Loria himself insists that the prime motive force has been the pressure of increasing population on the means of subsistence. Thus in Contemporary Social Problems (pp. 128 et seq.) he writes: "We easily understand how evolution takes place in the sphere of economic phenomena provided we steadfastly hold in mind the simple premise that ceaseless increase in population makes necessary the occupation and cultivation of lands ever less fertile, hence requiring more efficacious means of production to combat the increasing resistance of matter. Given, therefore, a certain density of population and a certain degree of fertility of cultivated land, there is rendered not only possible, but also necessary, a determinate economic system permitting human labour to attain a commensurate productivity; but population increasing, and the necessity of cultivating less fertile lands becoming urgent, the economic system hitherto[Pg 27] existing proves inadequate, since the degree of productivity which it permits to labour is insufficient to combat matter now become more rebellious. As the economic and productive system which corresponded with the preceding degree of the productivity of the soil has grown incompatible with the new and more exacting conditions, it must be supplanted by a better system. Then follows an epoch of social disintegration which destroys the superannuated form, from whose ashes a new structure arises; on the ruins of the shattered economic system is erected a new one which allows human nature to become more productive, and is therefore adapted, for a time, to combat the increasing resistance of matter. However, with each additional increment to population, a moment comes when it is necessary to bring under cultivation lands which are still more resistant, and for the development of which the prevailing economic system is found to be inadequate; consequently this[Pg 28] system suffers the fate of those which have preceded it, and it is in turn destroyed to give place to a new and superior form."

As for the earlier stages of economic development, the shift from primitive tribal communism to slavery, then from slavery to serfdom and the guild system, and finally to capitalism, Loria asserts that the primary driving force has been the increasing pressure of population on the means of subsistence. In Contemporary Social Problems (pp. 128 et seq.), he writes: "It's easy to understand how evolution occurs in the realm of economic phenomena if we keep in mind the basic idea that the constant growth of population necessitates the use and cultivation of lands that are progressively less fertile, requiring more effective means of production to overcome the rising challenges posed by the material world. Therefore, given a certain population density and a specific level of land fertility, it becomes not only possible but also necessary to establish a distinct economic system that allows human labor to achieve proportional productivity; however, as the population grows and the need to cultivate less fertile lands becomes urgent, the existing economic system proves inadequate, as its allowed productivity is no longer sufficient to tackle the now more resistant materials. When the economic and production system aligning with the previous level of soil productivity becomes unsuitable for the new, more demanding conditions, it must be replaced by a better system. This leads to a period of social disintegration that dismantles the outdated form, allowing a new structure to emerge; atop the ruins of the broken economic system, a new one is constructed that enables human nature to be more productive, thus better suited, for a time, to address the increasing challenges of matter. However, with every population increase, there eventually comes a time when it becomes necessary to cultivate even more resistant lands, and the current economic system is found lacking for this development; consequently, this economic system faces the same fate as its predecessors, and it too is destroyed to pave the way for a newer and superior form."

The detailed application of these ideas is one of the main themes of Loria's Analysis of Capitalist Property. We learn, he says, from history and statistics that capitalistic property (the term is here used by Loria in the widest sense to include all the forms of property which render possible the exploitation of one human being by another) is everywhere and at all times due to one and the same cause, the suppression of free land. As long as there is any free land, as long as any man who so desires can take possession of a piece of land and develop it by his labour, capitalistic property is impossible, because no man will willingly work for another when he can establish himself for his own account on a piece of land without paying for it. Where there is free land, labour owns the means of production, so[Pg 29] that agriculture is carried on by free peasants on small holdings, whilst manufacturing industry (in so far as this exists at such a stage) is in the hands of independent artisans. In these conditions labour is isolated, and isolated labour rarely produces anything more than the labourer's subsistence. The regular supplementary production of "income" is the characteristic feature of associated labour.

The detailed application of these ideas is one of the main themes of Loria's Analysis of Capitalist Property. He tells us that history and statistics show that capitalist property (a term Loria uses broadly to include all types of property that enable one person to exploit another) exists everywhere and at all times for the same reason: the suppression of free land. As long as there is free land and any person can choose to take possession of a piece of land and develop it through their labor, capitalist property cannot exist, because no one will willingly work for another when they can establish themselves on a piece of land without having to pay for it. In areas with free land, labor owns the means of production, so[Pg 29] agriculture is carried out by free peasants on small plots, while manufacturing (as far as it exists at that stage) is managed by independent artisans. Under these conditions, labor is isolated, and isolated labor rarely produces anything beyond what the laborer needs to survive. The regular additional production of "income" is a defining feature of associated labor.

This brings us to The Economic Synthesis, a work which bears as sub-title "A Study of the Laws of Income." It is, Loria tells us, "the complement and the theoretic crown" of all his earlier writings. The meaning he attaches to the word income is, in truth, simple enough; but that meaning is the very core of Lorianism, just as surplus value is (for many) the very core of Marxism. Isolated labour, labour of the kind described in the last paragraph, produces, says Loria, first of all subsistence—the bare necessities of life. In exceptionally favourable conditions even isolated[Pg 30] labour may produce something more than this, and that something more is income. But as a rule, and more and more as population increases and land of diminishing fertility has to be brought under cultivation, isolated labour fails to produce anything beyond subsistence, fails to produce even that, so that it becomes necessary to have recourse to the superior productivity of associated labour. Now for this, since the natural man is averse from associated labour, some form of coercion, direct or indirect, is essential; and the history of all the developed economic systems that have hitherto prevailed is the history, in one form or another, of the coercion to associated labour.

This brings us to The Economic Synthesis, a work subtitled "A Study of the Laws of Income." According to Loria, it is "the complement and the theoretical crown" of all his previous writings. The meaning he assigns to the term income is actually quite straightforward; however, that meaning is the very essence of Lorianism, much like surplus value is (for many) the essence of Marxism. Isolated labor, the kind discussed in the last paragraph, produces, Loria claims, primarily subsistence—the basic necessities of life. Under exceptionally favorable conditions, isolated[Pg 30] labor may produce something beyond this, and that something extra is income. But typically, especially as population grows and less productive land must be cultivated, isolated labor fails to generate anything beyond subsistence, and may even fail to produce that, making it essential to resort to the greater productivity of associated labor. To achieve this, since natural humans resist associated labor, some form of coercion, whether direct or indirect, is necessary; and the history of all the advanced economic systems that have existed is, in one way or another, the history of the coercion to associated labor.

Income, in the Lorian sense of the term, is "the specific product of associated labour"; i.e., it is the surplus produced by labour because it is associated, over and above what the labourers could have produced in isolation. Working in isolation they produce, or theoretically might have produced, subsistence for[Pg 31] themselves; associated they produce something more, which is income, and this accrues to those who control and direct the associating force.

Income, in the Lorian sense, is "the specific product of associated labor"; that is, it's the extra value created by working together compared to what individuals could produce on their own. When working alone, they might produce just enough to meet their basic needs for[Pg 31] themselves; when they collaborate, they create something more, which is income, and this goes to those in charge of directing the collaborative effort.

In primitive tribal communism that force emanates from the collectivity of economic equals, and the "undifferentiated income" is communally owned and consumed. But subsequently "differentiated income," received by non-labourers, makes its appearance. In slave-owning communities, differentiated income goes to the slave owners; in feudal serfdom, it accrues to the baronage; under modern capitalist conditions the dispossessed proletarian masses produce of course their own subsistence, and produce in addition income for the legal owners of land and capital. Slave owners, barons, capitalists, are in successive stages the "recipients of [differentiated] income."

In early tribal communism, power comes from the collective group of economic equals, and the "undifferentiated income" is shared and used by everyone. However, over time, "differentiated income," which is earned by those not working, starts to emerge. In societies that rely on slavery, this differentiated income goes to the slave owners; in feudal systems, it benefits the nobility; and under modern capitalist conditions, the dispossessed working class produces their own means of survival while also generating income for the legal owners of land and capital. Slave owners, nobles, and capitalists are, at different stages, the "recipients of [differentiated] income."

Throughout the history of these economic phases there has been a conflict between the [Pg 32]interests of the labourers and those of the recipients of income, taking the form, in times of exceptional stress, of slave insurrections and slave wars, of jacqueries and ruthless reprisals by the baronage, of strikes and lock-outs. Here we have one aspect of what Loria terms "the struggle between subsistence and income," and this aspect coincides obviously enough with one aspect of the Marxist class struggle.

Throughout the history of these economic phases, there has been a conflict between the [Pg 32] interests of workers and those of income recipients. This conflict has taken the form, during times of extreme stress, of slave revolts and slave wars, of peasant uprisings and brutal reprisals by the nobility, as well as strikes and lockouts. This represents one side of what Loria calls "the struggle between survival and income," and this aspect clearly overlaps with one facet of the Marxist class struggle.

The association of labour is the prime cause of labour's enhanced productivity. But while the association increases productivity, the coercion that is requisite to secure association exercises a restrictive influence upon productivity, the restriction being more marked in proportion to the severity of the coercion. Thus the crude and harsh coercion of the slave-owning system makes slave labour (in part for psychological reasons dependent upon the mentality of the labourer) less productive than serf labour under the feudal system,[Pg 33] wherein coercion was somewhat milder. In modern capitalism coercion, though still very real, is veiled, and for this reason (quite apart from the peculiar advantages of machinofacture) associated labour is more productive under capitalism.

The way workers come together is the main reason why productivity has increased. However, while this collaboration boosts productivity, the force needed to maintain this collaboration actually limits productivity. The more severe the force, the greater the limitation. For example, the brutal and harsh conditions of slavery make slave labor—partly due to the mindset of the laborer—less productive than the work done by serfs in the feudal system, where the coercion was somewhat less intense. In modern capitalism, while coercion is still present, it’s more subtle. Because of this, along with the unique benefits of factory production, teamwork is more productive in capitalism.[Pg 33]

It is the superior productivity of each successive system which has rendered it victorious over its predecessor. With the dry light of economic science Loria displays for us the working of the type of production dominant to-day, the most effective system of production the world has yet known.

It’s the improved productivity of each new system that has made it better than the ones before it. With clear reasoning from economic science, Loria shows us how the current dominant production model works, which is the most efficient system of production the world has ever seen.

Such is Loria's outline picture of the succession of economic phases.

Such is Loria's overview of the series of economic phases.

It is impossible here to trace the Italian economist's detailed analysis of the causes which lead to the break up of one economic system and its replacement by another. Suffice it to say that in his view an important part is played by the action of those whom he calls "unproductive labourers," members of the[Pg 34] educated caste living also on differentiated income, on portions of income reallotted by the primary recipients of income, whose interests, in the prosperous phase of any system of income, the educated caste is thus paid to serve. A typical service is that of the priestly order, which is maintained "to pervert the egoism" of the labourers, to delude them into the belief that they are pursuing their own better interests by peacefully and diligently producing income for the master class.

It’s not possible here to outline the Italian economist's thorough analysis of the reasons that lead to the breakdown of one economic system and the emergence of another. It’s enough to say that, in his opinion, an important role is played by those he refers to as "unproductive laborers," members of the[Pg 34] educated class who also rely on different sources of income, on portions of income redistributed by the primary earners, whose interests, during the prosperous phase of any income system, the educated class is therefore incentivized to support. A typical role is that of the priestly order, which exists "to distort the selfishness" of the laborers, misleading them into believing that they are pursuing their own best interests by peacefully and diligently generating income for the elite.

But in the declining phase of any economic system (and Loria considers that the wage system of capitalism has now, despite its imposing appearance, actually entered its declining phase), the diminution of income curtails the amount available for reallotment to the unproductive labourers. Hence from supporters of the existing system they are speedily transformed into its active opponents. These "intellectuals" now make common cause with the labourers, the disinherited of the earth;[Pg 35] and the old property system totters to its fall.

But in the declining phase of any economic system (and Loria believes that the wage system of capitalism has now, despite its formidable facade, actually entered its decline), the reduction in income limits what can be redistributed to the unproductive workers. As a result, supporters of the existing system quickly become its active opponents. These "intellectuals" now ally themselves with the workers, the dispossessed of the earth;[Pg 35] and the old property system is on the brink of collapse.

He writes (The Economic Foundations of Society, p. 347): "All revolutions undertaken by the non-proprietary classes alone, without the support of the unproductive labourers, are ... foredoomed to failure. The rebels, divided and disorganised, not at all sure of themselves and uncertain of the ends they would attain, soon fall back under the dominion of the proprietary class.... The ancient economy was not destroyed by the revolt of the slaves, nor was the ruin of the medieval economy effected by the armed uprising of the serfs. These two economic systems did not succumb until the clients of the Roman economy and the ecclesiastics of the medieval economy were induced by a falling-off of their share in the constantly decreasing revenues [income] to break their long-standing alliance with the revenue holders [recipients of income] and to lend their support to the final revolt of the labouring classes."

He writes (The Economic Foundations of Society, p. 347): "All revolutions led by the non-proprietary classes alone, without the backing of the unproductive laborers, are ... doomed to fail. The rebels, fragmented and disorganized, unsure of themselves and unclear about their goals, quickly fall back under the control of the proprietary class.... The ancient economy wasn't destroyed by the rebellion of the slaves, nor was the downfall of the medieval economy brought about by the armed uprising of the serfs. These two economic systems didn't collapse until the clients of the Roman economy and the clergy of the medieval economy were pushed by a decline in their share of the increasingly shrinking revenues [income] to break their long-standing alliance with the income holders [recipients of income] and support the final revolt of the laboring classes."

To the Lorian theory of revolution we shall return in conclusion, after we have discussed the relationships of Loria to Marx. The theory involves tactical questions of the utmost interest and importance. Apart from these, the crux of the problem of transition to the co-operative commonwealth centres, as most thoughtful socialists are coming to see, around the question of the coercion to associated labour. A fundamental part of the socialist outlook is the belief that the existence of a special class of recipients of income, whether these be slave owners, feudal barons, or legal monopolists of land and capital, is not needful to modern civilisation. We affirm that the disappearance of such a class (though that class may have played a necessary part in social evolution) can now be witnessed by the enlightened without a single regret. But what is to ensure the continuance of that high social productivity which will be necessary to the maintenance of general wellbeing? Now[Pg 37] that our race is at length becoming truly self-conscious, will it be possible "to transform the economic natural force from the ruler of mankind to its servant?"

To the Lorian theory of revolution, we will return at the end, after discussing how Loria relates to Marx. This theory raises tactical issues that are extremely interesting and important. Besides these, the core of the transition to the cooperative commonwealth, as many thoughtful socialists are beginning to understand, revolves around the issue of coercion to collective labor. A key part of the socialist perspective is the belief that having a specific class of income recipients—whether they are slave owners, feudal lords, or legal monopolists of land and capital—is not necessary for modern civilization. We assert that the elimination of such a class (even though it may have played a crucial role in social development) can now be seen by the enlightened without any regret. But what will guarantee the ongoing high social productivity essential for maintaining overall wellbeing? Now[Pg 37] that our society is finally becoming truly self-aware, is it possible "to transform the economic natural force from the ruler of mankind to its servant?"

The closing sentences of The Economic Synthesis show in outline how Loria envisages that possibility: "The essential social contradiction can be eliminated, economic equilibrium can be established, only by means of a profound transformation, affecting not merely the process of distribution but also the process of production, relieving this latter process from the coercion which has hitherto environed it and restricted its efficiency; in other words by the destruction of the coercive association of labour and its replacement by the free association of labour. Herein is to be found the supreme objective towards which must converge all the forces of social renovation." And in a terminal footnote he adds: "This is now understood by all the most enlightened economists, not excepting the socialists, who point out that[Pg 38] a reform which effects no more than the distribution of income among the proletarians, while leaving unaffected the method by which that income is actually produced, would have no more than an extremely restricted and fugitive effect; and that a decisive and durable social renovation must be initiated by a radical metamorphosis in the process of production."

The closing sentences of The Economic Synthesis outline how Loria sees this possibility: "The main social contradiction can be eliminated and economic stability established only through a deep transformation that impacts not just the distribution process but also the production process. This means freeing the production process from the constraints that have limited its effectiveness so far; in other words, by replacing the coercive structure of labor with a free association of labor. This is the ultimate goal that all forces of social change should aim for." In a final footnote, he adds: "This is now recognized by all the most knowledgeable economists, including socialists, who highlight that [Pg 38] a reform that only changes how income is distributed among the working class, while leaving the production methods untouched, will have a very limited and temporary impact. A significant and lasting social change must start with a fundamental transformation in the production process."

We have now to ask, what does Loria consider the most important elements of Marxist teaching? In his account of the Communist Manifesto (infra p. 68) he tells us that "this writing contains the whole Marxist system in miniature, and ... supplies a critique of all doctrinaire, idealist, and utopian forms of socialism. Thus the Manifesto voices the two fundamentals of Marxism: the dependence of economic evolution upon the evolution of the instrument of production, in other words the technicist determination of economics; and the derivation of the political, moral, and ideal[Pg 39] order from the economic order, in other words the economic determination of sociology—or, as we should express it to-day, historical materialism."

We now need to ask, what does Loria think are the most important aspects of Marxist teaching? In his discussion of the Communist Manifesto (infra p. 68), he states that "this writing contains the entire Marxist system in miniature, and ... offers a critique of all doctrinaire, idealist, and utopian forms of socialism. Thus, the Manifesto presents the two core principles of Marxism: the dependence of economic evolution on the evolution of the means of production, in other words, the technicist determination of economics; and the derivation of the political, moral, and ideal[Pg 39] order from the economic order, in other words, the economic determination of sociology—or, as we would say today, historical materialism."

On pp. 145 and 146 he tells us that we must "recognise in Marx the supreme merit of having been the first to introduce the evolutionary concept into the domain of sociology, the first to introduce it in the only form appropriate to social phenomena and social institutions; not as" an "unceasing and gradual upward movement," but as a "succession of age-long cycles rhythmically interrupted by revolutionary explosions." Speaking of Marx's "masterly investigation into the successive forms of the technical instrument, of productive machinery," he says that Marx may be termed "the Darwin of technology.... This physiology of industry, which is now the least studied and least appreciated of Marx's scientific labours, nevertheless constitutes his most considerable and most enduring contribution to science."

On pp. 145 and 146, he tells us that we need to "acknowledge in Marx the ultimate credit for being the first to bring the idea of evolution into sociology, the first to present it in the only way suitable for social phenomena and institutions; not as" an "endless and gradual upward trend," but as a "series of long-lasting cycles punctuated by revolutionary upheavals." Discussing Marx's "expert analysis of the different forms of technical tools and production machinery," he states that Marx can be seen as "the Darwin of technology.... This study of industry, which is currently the least examined and appreciated of Marx's scientific work, still represents his most significant and lasting contribution to science."

Loria wrote his Karl Marx nearly two years before the publication of William Paul's The State, of which pp. 2 to 7, the section on "Man and Tools" is devoted to a restatement of this aspect of Marxism; and the Italian economist is not acquainted with the thought-trend of Walton Newbold. As far as the young but rapidly growing and vigorous school of British Marxists is concerned, it is certainly no longer true that Marx's work as "the Darwin of technology" is the least studied and least appreciated of Marx's scientific labours.

Loria wrote his Karl Marx nearly two years before William Paul published The State, which dedicates pages 2 to 7 to restating this aspect of Marxism in the section titled "Man and Tools." The Italian economist is also unaware of Walton Newbold's line of thought. Regarding the young, rapidly growing, and energetic group of British Marxists, it is no longer accurate to say that Marx's work as "the Darwin of technology" is the least studied and least appreciated among his scientific contributions.

To the class struggle Loria does not refer at any length in this essay on Karl Marx. We have already seen that he recognises the enormous part the class struggle has played in history; but he has throughout life remained the man of science, the man of the study; he has never entered the arena as what the French term a "militant." In 1904, when the Italian Socialist Party wished him to be socialist parliamentary candidate for Turin, Loria refused[Pg 41] on the ground that parliamentary life would interfere with his theoretical studies; and it may be that for these and other reasons he is less keenly impressed than are most left-wing socialists of the profound importance of diffusing among the workers awareness of the class struggle.

Loria doesn’t really talk about the class struggle in this essay on Karl Marx. We've already seen that he acknowledges how significant the class struggle has been in history, but throughout his life, he's always been a scientist, focused on research; he has never engaged in activism, what the French call a "militant." In 1904, when the Italian Socialist Party wanted him to run as their parliamentary candidate for Turin, Loria declined[Pg 41] because he felt that being in parliament would disrupt his theoretical studies. It might be that for these reasons and others, he doesn’t see as clearly as most left-wing socialists the vital importance of raising awareness about the class struggle among workers.

Economic determinism has been sufficiently considered in what has gone before. If in the present study Loria says less about it than about some of the other elements of Marxism, this is not because he considers it of minor importance, nor because he accepts it uncritically, but because he has devoted an entire volume to the exposition of this aspect of reality.

Economic determinism has been adequately addressed in what’s been discussed earlier. If in this study Loria talks less about it compared to other aspects of Marxism, it’s not because he thinks it’s less important or accepts it without question, but because he has dedicated an entire volume to explaining this aspect of reality.

It remains, then, to discuss Loria's outlook on the Marxist theory of value. It is here that Lorianism will be most strenuously challenged by those more enthusiastic disciples of Marx who, even if they do not accept the dogma of Marx's infallibility, none the less regard the[Pg 42] doctrine of value, based on the labour theory of value, as the very heart of Marxist socialism.

It is now necessary to discuss Loria's perspective on the Marxist theory of value. This is where Lorianism will face the strongest opposition from more passionate followers of Marx who, even if they don't fully buy into the idea that Marx is infallible, still view the[Pg 42] doctrine of value, rooted in the labor theory of value, as the core of Marxist socialism.

We must remember that it is natural for persons who do not gain their subsistence by applying their labour power to the production of commodities, and whose claim to the title of "workers" will nevertheless hardly be disputed, to question the labour theory of value. Bernard Shaw, for example, in his pamphlet The Impossibilities of Anarchism, protests that it is "natural for the [manual] labourer to insist that labour ought to be the measure of price, and that the just wage of labour is its average product; but the first lesson he has to learn in economics is that labour is not and never can be the measure of price under a competitive system. Not until the progress of socialism replaces competitive production and distribution with individual greed for its incentive, by collectivist production and distribution with fair play all round for its[Pg 43] incentive, will the prices either of labour or of commodities represent their just value."

We need to keep in mind that it's common for people who don't earn a living by directly using their labor to produce goods, yet still have a valid claim to being "workers," to question the labor theory of value. Bernard Shaw, for example, in his pamphlet The Impossibilities of Anarchism, argues that it’s "natural for the [manual] laborer to believe that labor should be the measure of price, and that the fair wage for labor is its average product; but the first lesson he has to learn in economics is that labor isn't and never can be the measure of price in a competitive system. Only when socialism evolves to replace competitive production and distribution, driven by personal greed, with collectivist production and distribution, emphasizing fairness for everyone as its[Pg 43] motivation, will the prices of labor or goods reflect their true value."

Leaving Shaw to the tender mercies of the orthodox Marxists who will not be slow to declare that if he means "value" he should not say "price," and that if he thinks that "price" and "value" are interchangeable terms he is not worth powder and shot, and without ourselves venturing to rush into the fray, we may suggest that our propagandists would be less inclined to make the Marxist theory of value an article of faith, "which faith except everyone do keep whole and undefiled without doubt he shall perish everlastingly"—if they could realise that the theory is perhaps no more than a difficult point of abstract economic doctrine which is not essential to the use of the conception of surplus value as a means of making the worker aware of the basic character of capitalist exploitation. Bernstein explains the matter very well in the book previously quoted (p. 35): "Practical [Pg 44]experience shows that in the production and distribution of commodities a part only of the community takes an active share, whilst another part consists of persons who either enjoy an income for services which have no direct relation to the process of production, or have an income without working at all. An essentially greater number of men thus live on the labour of all those engaged in production than are actively engaged in it, and income statistics show that the classes not actively engaged in production appropriate, moreover, a much greater share of the total produced than the ratio of their number to that of the actively producing class. The surplus labour of the latter is an empiric fact, demonstrable by experience, which needs no deductive proof. Whether the Marxist theory of value be correct or not, is quite immaterial to the proof of surplus labour. It is in this respect no demonstration, but only a means of analysis and illustration."

Leaving Shaw to the kind-hearted judgment of the orthodox Marxists who won’t hesitate to assert that if he means “value,” he shouldn’t say “price,” and that if he thinks “price” and “value” are interchangeable, he’s not worth even a moment’s consideration. Without rushing into the debate ourselves, we might suggest that our advocates would be less likely to treat the Marxist theory of value as an unchangeable belief, “which faith except everyone do keep whole and undefiled without doubt he shall perish everlastingly”—if they could realize that the theory is probably just a complicated aspect of abstract economic doctrine that isn’t essential for understanding surplus value as a way to help workers recognize the fundamental nature of capitalist exploitation. Bernstein explains this quite well in the book mentioned earlier (p. 35): “Practical [Pg 44] experience shows that in the production and distribution of goods, only part of the community actively participates, while another part consists of individuals who either earn income for services unrelated to the production process or receive income without working at all. A significantly larger number of people live off the labor of those involved in production than are actively engaged in it, and income statistics indicate that those not actively involved in production take a much larger share of the total output than their numbers would suggest. The surplus labor of the latter is an observable fact, demonstrated by experience, that doesn’t require deductive proof. Whether or not the Marxist theory of value is correct is irrelevant to the proof of surplus labor. In this context, it serves not as a demonstration but merely as a means of analysis and illustration.”

The professional economist, however, cannot rest content with these loose formulations. Loria feels that there is a void in the Marxist system, and it seems to us (though Loria nowhere tells us so in set terms) that the Lorian doctrine of differentiated income, the most essential part of the Italian economist's teaching, is really an attempt to restate the theory of surplus value in a form absolutely proof against enemy attack. Be this as it may, the conception, however interesting, is far less easy to convey to the uninstructed mind, and it is unlikely, for propaganda purposes, to replace the simple formula of surplus value. But is it not essential that those who undertake to teach socialist economics should themselves fully understand the objections to the Marxist theory of value, and that they should have a clear grasp of Loria's alternative doctrine of the nature of capitalist exploitation?

The professional economist, however, cannot be satisfied with these vague ideas. Loria believes there is a gap in the Marxist system, and it seems to us (though Loria never directly says so) that his concept of differentiated income, which is the most important part of his teachings, is essentially an effort to reframe the theory of surplus value in a way that is completely resistant to criticism. Regardless, this idea, while intriguing, is much harder to explain to someone who isn't familiar with the concepts, and it's unlikely to effectively replace the straightforward notion of surplus value for propaganda purposes. But isn't it crucial that those who aim to teach socialist economics fully understand the criticisms of the Marxist theory of value and have a clear understanding of Loria's alternative views on capitalist exploitation?

Let us return, in conclusion, to the Lorian[Pg 46] theory of revolution. If we may summarise that theory in colloquial phraseology, it is that, while economic evolution must pave the way for revolution, the final stages of revolution have been effected in the past, and can only be effected in the future, through the co-operation of "disgruntled intellectuals." These are the "unproductive labourers" of Loria's scheme, who have served as hirelings of the master class during the prosperous phase of an economic system: but in the declining phase of that system, when the diminution of income curtails the amount available for these secondary recipients of income, they turn against the primary recipients, their employers, make common cause with the subject class, and give the death-blow to the old order.

Let’s wrap up by revisiting the Lorian[Pg 46] theory of revolution. To put it simply, this theory states that while economic development has to set the stage for revolution, the final stages of revolution have happened in the past and can only happen in the future through the collaboration of "disgruntled intellectuals." These individuals are the "unproductive laborers" in Loria's framework, who have acted as the workforce for the elite during the boom times of an economic system. But in the downturn of that system, when decreasing income limits what these secondary earners can get, they turn against the primary earners, their employers, join forces with the working class, and deliver the final blow to the old system.

This may possibly have been true of the fall of the slave economy, and it may possibly have been true of the fall of the medieval economy; but we do not think it is true that a revolution of the non-proprietary classes under capitalism[Pg 47] is "foredoomed to failure" unless these classes secure the support of the unproductive labourers. Their support for a genuinely proletarian revolution can hardly be expected, on Loria's own theory. The intellectuals who aided in the overthrow of the slave economy, and the intellectuals who helped to subvert the feudal order and to promote the bourgeois and industrial revolution, did so, says Loria, in order to maintain their position as "recipients of income," to maintain their position as members of a privileged class. What have such as they to gain from a proletarian revolution, which will abolish class, will put an end to exploitation, will do away for ever with the private appropriation of income and surplus value?

This might have been true for the decline of the slave economy and possibly for the fall of the medieval economy; however, we don’t believe it’s accurate to say that a revolution by the non-proprietary classes under capitalism[Pg 47] is "doomed to failure" unless these classes gain the backing of the unproductive workers. According to Loria’s own theory, their support for a genuinely proletarian revolution is hardly something we can expect. The intellectuals who contributed to the downfall of the slave economy and those who helped dismantle the feudal system to promote the bourgeois and industrial revolution did so, as Loria states, to safeguard their status as "recipients of income" and to maintain their role as part of a privileged class. What incentive do people like them have to support a proletarian revolution that would abolish class, end exploitation, and permanently eliminate the private ownership of income and surplus value?

We need only turn our eyes eastward to see how such "intellectuals" will hail the revolution of the propertiless. Despite the onslaughts of the capitalist powers, the Russian Socialist Federative Soviet Republic has lived[Pg 48] long enough to show the sort of help socialists may expect from the Kerenskys. Men of this calibre, "people whose interests lie in the opposite direction," even if they "are carried away by the new ideas and enter the lists for the new order of things" (Boudin, The Theoretical System of Karl Marx, 1918), are aghast when the real revolution comes, and endeavour to lay the red spectre they have helped to conjure up.

We only need to look east to see how these "intellectuals" celebrate the revolution of those without property. Despite the attacks from capitalist powers, the Russian Socialist Federative Soviet Republic has survived[Pg 48] long enough to reveal the kind of support socialists can expect from people like the Kerenskys. Individuals of this sort, "people whose interests lie in the opposite direction," even if they "are caught up in the new ideas and join in the fight for the new order" (Boudin, The Theoretical System of Karl Marx, 1918), are shocked when the real revolution happens, and try to suppress the red specter they've helped create.

In truth, a revolution foredoomed to failure would be that of proletarians who should depend in large measure upon the support of disgruntled intellectuals. A serf's life was on the average better than that of a chattel slave; a wage labourer's life is on the average better than was that of slave or serf. But neither the replacement of slavery by feudalism, nor the replacement of feudalism by capitalism, secured the emancipation of labour in any adequate sense of that term. All that a proletarian revolution carried through with the help of[Pg 49] middle-class intellectuals is likely to bring about is some form of Fabian collectivism or state capitalism—in a word, the servile state. As far as the productive labourers are concerned the revolution would be a sham. The form of the state might be revolutionised, but the authoritative state would endure, and production would be effected, not by the free, but by the coercive association of labour.

In reality, a revolution that is destined to fail would be one led by workers who heavily rely on the backing of unhappy intellectuals. On average, a serf's life was better than that of a chattel slave; similarly, a wage laborer's life is generally better than that of a slave or serf. However, neither the shift from slavery to feudalism nor the transition from feudalism to capitalism truly freed labor in any meaningful way. All that a workers' revolution achieved with the help of [Pg 49] middle-class intellectuals is likely to end up creating a version of Fabian collectivism or state capitalism—in other words, a servile state. For the productive workers, the revolution would be a facade. While the structure of the state may change, the authoritative state would persist, and production would be managed not by voluntary cooperation but by coercive labor associations.

What Loria has failed to recognise is that the conditions of the problem are now radically changed. As he says, in the old revolutions the rebels were divided and disorganised, were not sure of themselves, and were uncertain of the ends they would attain. As far as the workers were concerned, revolt only was possible, not revolution. It is otherwise to-day; and still more will it be otherwise the day after to-morrow. Thanks to the new forms of organisation now being worked out: thanks to industrial unionism and the growth of the workers committees and shop stewards[Pg 50] movements; and thanks above all to independent working class education, which is forging the new weapons and simultaneously teaching the workers how to use them, which is fashioning the limbs of the co-operative commonwealth within the womb of the capitalist order—thanks to all these things, the workers of the day after to-morrow need not put their trust in the frail reed of the support of intellectuals. Once more we raise the Marxist slogan and cry: "The emancipation of the workers must be the work of the workers themselves."

What Loria hasn’t realized is that the conditions of the problem have completely changed. As he points out, in the past revolutions, the rebels were divided and disorganized, unsure of themselves, and unclear about the goals they wanted to achieve. For the workers, revolt was possible, but not revolution. That’s not the case today, and it will be even more true the day after tomorrow. Thanks to new forms of organization currently being developed: thanks to industrial unionism and the growth of workers' committees and shop stewards[Pg 50] movements; and especially due to independent working-class education, which is creating new tools and teaching workers how to use them, shaping the structure of a cooperative commonwealth within the capitalist system—thanks to all these factors, the workers of the future need not rely on the fragile support of intellectuals. Once again, we raise the Marxist slogan and shout: "The emancipation of the workers must be the work of the workers themselves."

And if we modify another Marxist watchword, quoted on p. 154 below, that force is the midwife of every old society pregnant with a new one, it is only to say that, while we do not repudiate force (which the skilled accoucheur ever has in reserve), new times bring new methods. The self-educated workers of the future may have no occasion to use force, and certainly need not await the aid of Loria's[Pg 51] unproductive labourers. For the day draws nigh, and on that day the workers will achieve their own salvation. They will achieve the salvation of all the workers, and indeed of all the world of man; but it will not be all the workers that will actively participate. No more will be possible than that there should be a considerable minority of educated workers. A minority they must inevitably remain until after the social revolution; but a little leaven can leaven a large lump. The midwife of revolution is not force but—independent working class education.

And if we update another Marxist saying, mentioned on p. 154 below, that force is the midwife of every old society giving birth to a new one, we merely mean to say that, while we don’t reject force (which a skilled midwife always has in reserve), new times bring new methods. The self-taught workers of the future might not need to use force at all, and certainly won’t have to wait for the help of Loria's[Pg 51]

In a word, the "dynamogenic function" of which Loria speaks (infra pp. 159 and 160), attaches not to poverty but to slavery. The poor have seldom failed to realise their poverty, and poverty when extreme has at times led to revolt; but it is the new realisation of the slavery of wagedom that is organising the workers for the social revolution. By means of Marxist education "the proletarian is [Pg 52]breaking his chains and entering upon an era of conscious and glorious freedom."

In simple terms, the "dynamogenic function" that Loria mentions (infra pp. 159 and 160), relates not to poverty but to slavery. The poor have usually been aware of their poverty, and extreme poverty has sometimes sparked revolts; however, it’s the new awareness of the slavery of wage labor that is rallying workers for the social revolution. Through Marxist education, "the proletarian is [Pg 52]breaking his chains and stepping into an era of conscious and glorious freedom."

Do we seem to imply that there is no place in our movement for middle-class intellectuals? Such is not our meaning. They have played in the past a rôle of supreme importance, and may still have a notable part to play in the future. But the intellectuals for whom there is a place are not the kind of intellectuals described in Loria's theory of revolution, and the rôle of the intellectual is no longer the one which he assigns. It is not those intellectuals who are dissatisfied with their reallotment of income, not those who are discontented with their ration of loaves and fishes, not those who sigh for the vanishing cakes and ale, who will help the coming of the definitive social revolution. Rarely indeed, too, is the function of the socialist intellectual the function of leadership. To an increasing extent, under the new conditions, he tends to be no more than the fifth wheel of the revolutionary coach.

Do we suggest that there's no room in our movement for middle-class intellectuals? That's not what we mean. They've played a crucial role in the past and can still have an important role in the future. But the kind of intellectuals who have a place here aren't the ones described in Loria's theory of revolution, and the role of the intellectual isn't what he assigns. It's not the intellectuals who are unhappy with their share of income, not those who are dissatisfied with their share of resources, and not those who long for the disappearing comforts who will bring about the upcoming social revolution. In fact, the role of the socialist intellectual is rarely one of leadership. More and more, under new circumstances, they tend to be just an extra part of the revolutionary movement.

The right sort of intellectual had a function in the past; it was to help the workers to overcome their division and disorganisation, to help them to be sure of themselves, to help them to clear views of the ends they must attain. That work is afoot. The ferment has been created: created by such men as Marx, whose abilities would have secured him ease, comfort, wealth, had he made his peace with bourgeoisdom, but who was a revolutionist by deliberate choice; by such men as Engels, a well-to-do manufacturer; by such men as Loria himself, a university professor; by such men as the American, Scott Nearing, who recently forfeited his academic position because he would not keep the class struggle out of his lectures on economics. Can it be said that men like Herzen, Bakunin, and Kropotkin, have been, or that men like Trotzky and Lenin are, the disgruntled intellectuals of Loria's theory of revolution? Quite apart from leadership under such peculiar conditions as obtain in[Pg 54] Russia, there is work for socialist intellectuals, the work of promoting independent working-class education, the work of assisting in the spread of the ferment generated by the writings of earlier revolutionary thinkers.

The right kind of intellectual had a purpose in the past; it was to help workers overcome their divisions and disorganization, to help them feel confident, and to help them develop clear ideas about the goals they need to achieve. That effort is underway. A movement has been sparked: created by people like Marx, whose talents could have brought him comfort and wealth had he chosen to align with the bourgeoisie, but who chose to be a revolutionary; by people like Engels, a successful manufacturer; by people like Loria himself, a university professor; by people like the American Scott Nearing, who recently lost his academic position because he insisted on including the class struggle in his economics lectures. Can we say that figures like Herzen, Bakunin, and Kropotkin were, or that people like Trotsky and Lenin are, the disillusioned intellectuals proposed by Loria's theory of revolution? Aside from leadership under the unique circumstances in [Pg 54] Russia, there is still work for socialist intellectuals, work that involves promoting independent education for the working class and assisting in spreading the movement inspired by the writings of earlier revolutionary thinkers.

Our conviction that we ourselves, declassed bourgeois, have a modest function, that though not part of the team, not even spokes of a fifth wheel, we may at least help to complete the outfit as little dogs under the waggon, is witnessed by our translation of Achille Loria's monograph on Karl Marx.

Our belief that we, the declassed bourgeois, have a small role to play, and that even though we’re not part of the team or even a fifth wheel, we can at least help complete the picture like little dogs under the wagon, is reflected in our translation of Achille Loria's monograph on Karl Marx.

Eden and Cedar Paul.

Eden and Cedar Paul.

London,
   The Centenary of Karl Marx.

London,
The 100th Anniversary of Karl Marx.


KARL MARX

KARL MARX


KARL MARX

Karl Marx

CHAPTER I

It is unquestionably one of the strangest of anomalies exhibited by the polychrome flora of human thought that revolutionary blossoms should so frequently spring from aristocratic seeds, and that the most incendiary and rebellious spirits should emerge from a domestic and social environment compounded of conservatism and reaction. Yet when we look closely into the matter, we find it less strange than it may have appeared at first sight. It is, in fact, not difficult to understand that those only who live in a certain milieu can fully apprehend its vices and its constitutional defects, which are hidden as by a cloud from those who live elsewhere.

It’s undeniably one of the weirdest contradictions in the colorful world of human thought that revolutionary ideas often come from privileged backgrounds, and that the most fiery and rebellious individuals arise from conservative and traditional environments. However, when we examine this closely, it seems less odd than it initially appears. In reality, it’s easy to see that only those who exist within a certain environment can fully recognize its flaws and inherent issues, which remain obscured to those living in different circumstances.

It is true enough that many dwellers in the[Pg 58] perverted environment lack the intelligence which would enable them to understand its defects. Others, again, are induced by considerations of personal advantage to close their eyes to the evils they discern, or cynically to ignore them. But if a man who grows to maturity in such an environment be at once intelligent and free from base elements, the sight of the evil medium from which he himself has sprung will arouse in his mind a righteous wrath and a spirit of indomitable rebellion, will transform the easy-going and cheerful patrician into the prophet and the revolutionary.

It’s certainly true that many people living in the[Pg 58] toxic environment lack the understanding needed to recognize its flaws. Others, meanwhile, choose to ignore the problems they see for personal gain or turn a blind eye out of cynicism. However, if a person grows up in such an environment but is both intelligent and principled, seeing the corruption of the world he comes from will ignite a deep anger and an unyielding sense of rebellion in him, transforming the carefree and optimistic elite into both a prophet and a revolutionary.

Such has been the lot of the great rebels of the world, of men like Dante, Voltaire, Byron, Kropotkin, and Tolstoi, who all sprang from the gentle class, and whose birthright placed them among the owners of property. Similar was the lot of Karl Marx.

Such has been the fate of the great rebels of the world, like Dante, Voltaire, Byron, Kropotkin, and Tolstoy, who all came from the privileged class and whose background positioned them among property owners. Karl Marx faced a similar fate.

It would, indeed, be difficult to imagine a more typically refined and aristocratic [Pg 59]entourage than the one wherein the future high priest of the revolution was born and passed his early years. He was born at Treves on May 5, 1818. His ancestors on both sides had been distinguished rabbis, famed for their commentaries on the scriptures. The father's family was originally known as Mordechai, whilst the mother's family, Pressburg by name, had come from Hungary to settle in Holland. His father, an employee in the state service, became a Christian, and the whole family was baptised when Karl was five years of age. As he grew up, the young man was an intimate in the best houses of the district, and one of his closest friends was Edgar von Westphalen, who subsequently became a member of the reactionary Manteuffel ministry. In 1843 Marx married Westphalen's sister, the beautiful and brilliant Jenny. The match proved well assorted, and was blessed by a love so intense and so unfailing as to lead a certain German pastor to say that it had been ratified in heaven.

It would definitely be hard to picture a more refined and aristocratic [Pg 59] entourage than the one where the future high priest of the revolution was born and spent his early years. He was born in Treves on May 5, 1818. His ancestors on both sides had been prominent rabbis, renowned for their commentaries on the scriptures. His father's family was originally called Mordechai, while his mother's family, named Pressburg, had moved from Hungary to Holland. His father, who worked in the state service, converted to Christianity, and the entire family was baptized when Karl was five years old. As he grew up, the young man became close friends with the best families in the area, with one of his closest friends being Edgar von Westphalen, who later became part of the conservative Manteuffel ministry. In 1843, Marx married Westphalen's sister, the beautiful and intelligent Jenny. The marriage proved to be a great match and was blessed with a love so strong and enduring that a certain German pastor remarked that it had been sanctioned in heaven.

Thus by origin Marx belonged to an extremely ancient stock devoted to the accumulation of wealth, whilst his marriage united him to the race of German feudatories, fierce paladins of the throne and of the altar. Is it not then truly remarkable that from such an environment, eminently calculated to foster ideas of obscurantism and reaction, there should emerge the most brilliant, most consistent, and most invincible example of a thinker and revolutionary agitator?

Thus by heritage, Marx came from a very old lineage focused on accumulating wealth, while his marriage connected him to the German feudal class, staunch defenders of the monarchy and the church. Isn't it truly noteworthy that from such an environment, which was highly likely to encourage ideas of ignorance and conservatism, there arose the most brilliant, consistent, and powerful example of a thinker and revolutionary activist?

Unquestionably, Marx's thought, essentially slow-moving, laborious, and ever subjected to a rigorous process of self-criticism, does not seem at first sight characteristically negational and rebellious. In youth, indeed, he was still no more than the earnest student. Engels tells us that he closed his university career at Bonn in 1841 by writing a brilliant thesis upon the philosophy of Epicurus, while in leisure moments Marx penned verses of no mean order. These latter compositions display numerous[Pg 61] defects of style; they are heavy and turgid; the movement is sluggish; their sonorous gravity reminds the reader of a company of medieval warriors in heavy armour mounting the grand staircase: but they are none the less distinguished by remarkable profundity of thought, and they may be looked upon as versified philosophy rather than as poetry in the proper sense of the term.

Unquestionably, Marx's ideas, which are fundamentally slow-moving, laborious, and always subject to a strict process of self-criticism, don't initially come across as particularly negative or rebellious. In his youth, he was just a diligent student. Engels tells us that he finished his university studies at Bonn in 1841 by writing an impressive thesis on Epicurus' philosophy, and during his free time, Marx wrote verses of notable quality. These compositions have several[Pg 61] flaws in style; they are heavy and wordy; the flow is sluggish; their weighty tone evokes the image of medieval warriors in heavy armor climbing a grand staircase. However, they are still marked by profound thought and can be viewed more as versified philosophy than as poetry in the traditional sense.

In the following year we find Marx at Cologne as editor of the "Rhenish Gazette." His editorials, it is true, were at first devoted to harmless topics of general interest; but he soon began to turn his attention to social questions, such as forest thefts, the subdivision of landed property, the condition of the peasantry in the Moselle district, and French socialism. To this last doctrine, the editor declared himself adverse, while professing a great personal admiration for Proudhon. But the discussion upon socialism revealed to him his own ignorance and incompetence, and induced him[Pg 62] to withdraw from the journalistic arena that he might devote himself to study. An excuse for resigning his editorship was furnished in 1843, when the "Rhenish Gazette" found it necessary to assume an extremely cautious tone in order to avoid the attentions of the police.

In the following year, we find Marx in Cologne as the editor of the "Rhenish Gazette." At first, his editorials were focused on harmless topics of general interest, but he soon shifted his attention to social issues like forest thefts, the subdivision of land, the situation of the peasantry in the Moselle region, and French socialism. Regarding this last ideology, the editor stated that he opposed it, although he expressed great personal admiration for Proudhon. However, the discussions about socialism highlighted his own ignorance and inadequacy, leading him[Pg 62] to step back from journalism to concentrate on study. An opportunity to resign from his editorial position arose in 1843 when the "Rhenish Gazette" had to adopt a very cautious tone to avoid drawing the attention of the police.

But, like all the more brilliant and free-spirited among his contemporaries, he soon found himself incommoded by the obscurantism of Prussia, and, accompanied by his young wife, he hastened to Paris, the city of light, where there shortly assembled a circle of intellectual rebels from all lands—France, Germany, England, Italy, and Russia. The Russians predominated, and indeed we learn from Marx himself that the most fervent of his disciples at this date were drawn from among the scions of the Russian nobility and upper bourgeoisie, who, when they returned to their country, were unhesitatingly to become the sycophants of authority. In this cohort of spiritual rebels he assumed from the first the[Pg 63] position of dictator, and none competed for the crown with the revolutionary Cæsar.

But, like many of the more brilliant and free-spirited people of his time, he soon found himself troubled by the ignorance of Prussia. Accompanied by his young wife, he rushed to Paris, the city of light, where a group of intellectual rebels from all over—France, Germany, England, Italy, and Russia—quickly gathered. The Russians were the majority, and we learn from Marx himself that his most passionate followers at that time came from the children of the Russian nobility and upper middle class, who, once they returned home, would readily become supporters of the authorities. In this group of spiritual rebels, he immediately took on the role of dictator, and no one challenged the revolutionary Cæsar for the crown.

People were already beginning to talk of the Marxists, and the police made a black cross against the name of a Parisian café where the associates of Marx were wont to assemble. He struck up a friendship with Heinrich Heine, and one day, accompanied by his staff, he paid a formal visit to the poet and declared that the latter ought to divide among the exiles the pension granted him by Guizot, to which suggestion Heine cynically replied that he could spend the pension more profitably upon himself. Marx had a yet closer intimacy with Proudhon, with whom he passed long evenings talking about Hegel and discussing the problems of socialism; but this friendship was destined ere long to be replaced by fierce hostility, aroused by fundamental differences of opinion.

People were starting to talk about the Marxists, and the police marked a black cross next to the name of a Parisian café where Marx’s associates used to gather. He became friends with Heinrich Heine, and one day, along with his staff, he paid a formal visit to the poet and suggested that Heine should share the pension granted to him by Guizot with the exiles. Heine cynically replied that he could use the pension more wisely on himself. Marx was even closer to Proudhon, with whom he spent long evenings discussing Hegel and the issues of socialism; however, this friendship was soon to turn into fierce hostility due to fundamental differences in opinion.

In 1844, in conjunction with Arnold Ruge, Marx founded the "Franco-German Year[Pg 64] Book," of which, however, there appeared but one volume, containing writings by Marx himself on the philosophy of law and upon the Jews, in addition to letters from Holland, and articles by Engels, Heine, Freiligrath, and other more or less rebellious spirits.

In 1844, along with Arnold Ruge, Marx started the "Franco-German Year[Pg 64] Book," but only one volume was published. This volume included writings by Marx on the philosophy of law and about the Jews, along with letters from Holland and pieces by Engels, Heine, Freiligrath, and other more or less rebellious figures.

These outward activities represent nothing more than an interlude or partial episode in the series of his essential occupations, science and philosophy. Engels' contribution to the "Year Book," a criticism of political economy, initiated between the two thinkers a friendship which time was to strengthen and to render indissoluble. The first fruit of this friendship was a joint work entitled The Holy Family, a criticism of the philosophy of Bruno Bauer and his followers (1845), stuffed with sallies and orphic sayings of doubtful taste and still more doubtful value. The young men next turned to a weightier task, a criticism of posthegelian philosophy, which filled two huge octavo manuscript volumes, but has never[Pg 65] found a publisher. Nevertheless, Marx tells us, this enormous labour cannot be regarded as utterly wasted, for it enabled the writers to gain an understanding of themselves, and traced the lines by which henceforward they were to be safely guided through the labyrinth of social investigation.

These outward activities are just a brief pause or a minor episode in the ongoing journey of his main pursuits, science and philosophy. Engels' contribution to the "Year Book," which critiqued political economy, sparked a friendship between the two thinkers that would grow stronger over time. The first result of this friendship was a joint project titled The Holy Family, a critique of Bruno Bauer's philosophy and his followers (1845), filled with whimsical remarks and questionable sayings of uncertain worth. The young men then took on a more substantial task, critiquing post-Hegelian philosophy, which filled two large octavo manuscript volumes, but has never[Pg 65] been published. However, Marx tells us that this immense effort wasn't completely in vain, as it helped the writers understand themselves better and laid down the path they would follow through the complex maze of social inquiry.

But revolutionary agitation (which Marx continued even amid his philosophical meditations), and the editorship of the definitely antiprussian journal "Forward," now attracted the hostile attention of the Prussian government, upon whose demand, in January, 1845, Guizot suppressed the periodical and expelled Marx from France. Marx removed to Brussels, where Engels was living, and for the first time devoted himself to prolonged and profound labours. In the year 1847, he published in the Belgian capital his book The Poverty of Philosophy, a Reply to Proudhon's Philosophy of Poverty, a harsh criticism of the "economic contradictions" of his rival. Marx [Pg 66]reproached Proudhon for complete ignorance of that Hegelian philosophy which Proudhon tried to apply to economics, and reproached the French socialist yet more for arbitrary and fallacious expositions, for the idealisation of a tortuous series of fantastic categories (division of labour, machines, competition, rent, etc.), declaring that Proudhon confined himself in each case to an examination of the good and the bad effects without ever troubling to throw light upon the nature of the phenomena under consideration or upon the course of their formation and development. The criticism is apt, but might well rebound upon Marx himself, enmeshed at this epoch in a series of categories whose progressive evolution he arbitrarily asserted. Further, Marx fiercely criticised Proudhon's theory of "constituted value," according to which the reduction of value to labour cannot be effected in extant society, and must be deferred to the future society, fashioned in the brain of the thinker.[Pg 67] It is well to point out that Marx, though in the first volume of Capital he conceives the reduction of value to the quantity of effective labour to be one of the immanent laws of capitalist economy, nevertheless admits in the third volume that in the capitalist economic phase value neither is nor can be reduced to the quantity of labour, and that value as measured by labour is merely an archetype or suprasensible entity, but not a concrete reality. Substantially this means that Marx's labour measure of value is, after all, not essentially different from the constituted value of Proudhon. But amid these unjust or excessive criticisms, Marx's book gives utterance to the idea, profoundly true, and at that time practically original, that economic relationships are no mere arbitrary products or derivatives of human will, but are the inevitable issue of the existing condition of the forces of production. The deduction drawn from this is that utopian socialism, which exhausts itself in futile declamations or[Pg 68] in yet more futile imaginary reconstructions of the social order, must yield place to scientific socialism, wholly devoted to the analysis of the necessary process of economic evolution and to the possibility of accelerating that evolution.

But revolutionary agitation (which Marx continued even during his philosophical reflections) and the editorship of the clearly anti-Prussian journal "Forward" now drew the negative attention of the Prussian government. In January 1845, at their request, Guizot shut down the publication and expelled Marx from France. Marx moved to Brussels, where Engels was living, and for the first time, he focused on intense and serious work. In 1847, he published his book The Poverty of Philosophy, a Reply to Proudhon's Philosophy of Poverty in the Belgian capital, which sharply criticized the "economic contradictions" of his rival. Marx [Pg 66] accused Proudhon of completely misunderstanding the Hegelian philosophy that Proudhon attempted to apply to economics, and he criticized the French socialist even more for his arbitrary and incorrect explanations, as well as for idealizing a convoluted set of abstract categories (like division of labor, machines, competition, rent, etc.), arguing that Proudhon limited himself to examining only the good and bad effects without ever trying to clarify the nature of the phenomena he discussed or their formation and development. This criticism is valid but could equally apply to Marx himself, who at this time was caught up in a series of categories whose progressive development he claimed without justification. Additionally, Marx vehemently criticized Proudhon's theory of "constituted value," which claimed that reducing value to labor cannot happen in current society and must be postponed to a future society imagined by the thinker.[Pg 67] It is worth noting that even though in the first volume of Capital Marx views the reduction of value to the amount of effective labor as one of the inherent laws of capitalist economy, he later acknowledges in the third volume that during the capitalist phase, value is neither reduced to labor quantity nor can it be, and that value measured by labor is merely an ideal or abstract concept, not a concrete reality. Essentially, this means that Marx's labor measure of value is not fundamentally different from Proudhon's constituted value. Yet amidst these unjust or excessive critiques, Marx's book expresses a profoundly true and, at the time, quite original idea that economic relationships are not simply arbitrary products or derivatives of human will, but are the inevitable result of the current state of productive forces. The implication of this is that utopian socialism, which gets caught up in pointless rhetoric or[Pg 68] in even more pointless imaginary redesigns of the social order, must give way to scientific socialism, which is entirely focused on analyzing the necessary process of economic evolution and on the potential for speeding up that evolution.

The same idea can be read between the lines of the Lecture on Free Exchange delivered by Marx at Brussels on January 9, 1849. Herein he asserted that socialism ought to declare in favour of freedom of trade, for this, hastening the dissolution of the old nationalities and accentuating the contrast between the bourgeoisie and the proletariat, would precipitate the dissolution of the capitalist economy. But the idea is affirmed far more categorically in the Manifesto of the Communist Party, the joint composition of Engels and Marx, published in the year 1848, embodying the first and most decisive formulation of the latter's teaching. Even though some of his special theories, subsequently to secure fuller development in[Pg 69] Capital, are but cursorily sketched in the Manifesto, even though some of these theories (for example, the theory of wages, stated to be the price of "wage labour" instead of being the price of "labour power") are still in an undeveloped and imperfect state, it is nevertheless true that this writing contains the whole Marxist system in miniature, and that it supplies a critique of all doctrinaire, idealist, and utopian forms of socialism.

The same idea can be read between the lines of the Lecture on Free Exchange delivered by Marx in Brussels on January 9, 1849. In this lecture, he argued that socialism should support free trade because it would speed up the breakdown of old nations and highlight the divide between the bourgeoisie and the proletariat, ultimately leading to the collapse of the capitalist economy. However, this idea is expressed much more clearly in the Manifesto of the Communist Party, co-authored by Engels and Marx, published in 1848. This manifesto presents the first and most definitive statement of Marx's teachings. Although some of his specific theories, which were further developed in [Pg 69] Capital, are only briefly mentioned in the Manifesto, and some of these theories (like the theory of wages, which is described as the price of "wage labor" instead of the price of "labor power") are still underdeveloped and flawed, it is still true that this text contains the entire Marxist system in a condensed form and critiques all doctrinaire, idealistic, and utopian varieties of socialism.

Thus the Manifesto voices the two fundamentals of Marxism: the dependence of economic evolution upon the evolution of the instrument of production, in other words the technicist determination of economics; and the derivation of the political, moral and ideal order from the economic order, in other words the economic determination of sociology—or, as we should express it to-day, historical materialism. This dependence of the political order upon the economic order, leading as it does to the concentration of political power[Pg 70] in the hands of those who hold economic power, or in the hands of their representatives and agents, renders absurd the idea of effecting by peaceful political means any amelioration in the condition of the proletarian classes, and indicates to the dispossessed that revolution is their only hope of salvation. To revolution, then, or to the compact federation which can alone pave the way for revolution, the Manifesto incites the sufferers of the world with the historic phrase: "Workers of the world, unite." The epoch-making significance of the Manifesto is not to-day disputed by the most resolute adversaries of that document. It is, in fact, the Declaration of Rights of the Fourth Estate, the Magna Charta of the revolutionary proletariat, the oriflamme of fire and blood, the standard round which the insurrectionary phalanxes have ever since mustered.

Thus the Manifesto expresses the two key principles of Marxism: the dependence of economic development on the evolution of production methods, or the technical determination of economics; and the way political, moral, and ideal structures stem from the economic order, or the economic determination of sociology—what we would call historical materialism today. This dependence of the political order on the economic order, which leads to the concentration of political power[Pg 70] in the hands of those who possess economic power, or in the hands of their representatives and agents, makes the idea of achieving any improvement in the conditions of the working class through peaceful political means absurd, indicating to the dispossessed that revolution is their only hope for salvation. Therefore, the Manifesto urges the oppressed of the world towards revolution or to the united federation that can lead to revolution, with the historic call: "Workers of the world, unite." The groundbreaking significance of the Manifesto is not challenged today, even by its staunchest opponents. It is, in fact, the Declaration of Rights of the Fourth Estate, the Magna Carta of the revolutionary working class, the banner of fire and blood, the standard around which the forces of insurrection have gathered ever since.

Hardly had the message been launched upon the world when the young leader hoped to translate it into action, for the movements[Pg 71] of 1848 and 1849 led the rebel masses to entertain new and bolder aspirations. Expelled from Belgium, Marx first went to Paris, and hastened thence to his German homeland, now in a ferment, assuming there editorial charge of the "New Rhenish Gazette." But although the skill of the able editor was for a brief period successful in saving the barque of the imperilled gazette from the waves of police persecution, a day soon arrived when the situation became untenable. An appeal to the German people published in the columns of the journal advocating a refusal to pay taxes led to its suppression and to two criminal charges against the editor. Triumphantly acquitted by the Cologne jury, but none the less exiled by the Prussian government, he immediately returned to Paris, where it seemed to his restless imagination that events were taking a more favourable turn. But France proved a no securer refuge than Germany, and the Parisian government propounded to our[Pg 72] agitator a peremptory dilemma, interment in the remote department of Morbihan or exile from France. He was not likely to hesitate in his choice, and indeed at this juncture was glad to accept an invitation from the executive committee of the Communist Party, then centred in London, to remove with his devoted wife to that great metropolis (1849).

Hardly had the message been released into the world when the young leader aimed to put it into action, as the movements[Pg 71] of 1848 and 1849 inspired the rebel masses to adopt new and bolder ambitions. After being expelled from Belgium, Marx first went to Paris and then quickly returned to his German homeland, which was in turmoil, taking on the editorial role at the "New Rhenish Gazette." Although the skilled editor successfully kept the endangered gazette afloat for a brief time against police persecution, a day soon came when the situation became unsustainable. An appeal to the German people published in the journal, encouraging them to refuse to pay taxes, led to its suppression and two criminal charges against the editor. Although he was triumphantly acquitted by the Cologne jury, he was still exiled by the Prussian government and immediately returned to Paris, where it seemed to his restless mind that things were looking up. However, France turned out to be no safer than Germany, and the Parisian government presented our[Pg 72] agitator with a tough choice: confinement in the remote department of Morbihan or exile from France. He was not likely to hesitate in making his decision and was actually glad to accept an invitation from the executive committee of the Communist Party, which was then based in London, to move with his devoted wife to that great city (1849).


CHAPTER II

In London the saddest trials awaited him, for poverty, gloomy companion, sat ever at his board from the day of his entry into the British capital down to the hour of his last breath. One after another of his children died in the unwholesome dwellings of his exile, and he was forced to beg from friends and comrades the scanty coins needed to pay for their burial; he and his family had to make the best of a diet of bread and potatoes; he was forced to pawn his watch and his clothing, to sell his books, to tramp the streets in search of any help that might offer; the day came when, under the lash of hunger, he was compelled to contemplate seeking work as railway clerk, of placing his daughters out to service, of [Pg 74]making them governesses or actresses, whilst himself retiring with his unhappy wife to dwell in the proletarian quarter of Whitechapel.

In London, the saddest challenges faced him, as poverty, a constant companion, sat at his table from the moment he arrived in the British capital until his last breath. One by one, his children died in the unhealthy living conditions of his exile, and he had to beg friends and comrades for the little money needed to pay for their burials; he and his family had to survive on a diet of bread and potatoes; he was forced to pawn his watch and clothes, sell his books, and walk the streets looking for any help he could find; the day came when, driven by hunger, he had to consider getting a job as a railway clerk, sending his daughters out to work, or making them governesses or actresses, while he and his unhappy wife retreated to live in the working-class neighborhood of Whitechapel.

The severity of these sufferings did much to add a tinge of gall to a character naturally acerb, a character which amid the upheavals and horrors of exile frequently showed itself far from amiable. Mingled sentiments of grief and anger fill our minds when, in Marx's private letters to Engels, we trace the manifestations of this harshness, which left him unmoved by the misfortunes of his dearest friends, which led him to make any use he could of these friends and then to overwhelm them with reproaches and accusations, which showed itself (and this is the worst of all) in a jealous hatred of comrades less unfortunate than himself. Deplorable from every point of view was his conduct towards Freiligrath and Lassalle, in especial towards Lassalle, who had shown him the utmost friendliness,[Pg 75] had given him ample financial assistance, had entertained him in Berlin, had helped him to find a publisher; for Marx subsequently censured Lassalle's works with much acrimony, beheld his triumphs askance, and commented upon the incidents of Lassalle's death in a tone of tepid apology. But you well-fed folk who amid easy circumstances are studying the life of our agitator, be not too ready to blame him, and before stoning him bethink yourselves of all the miseries the exile must suffer, of all the tortures amid which he must bear his cross.

The intensity of these sufferings added a bitter edge to a character that was already naturally harsh, which, during the chaos and horrors of exile, often came across as far from friendly. Mixed feelings of sadness and anger fill our minds when we read Marx’s private letters to Engels and see this harshness emerge, leaving him indifferent to the struggles of his closest friends. This led him to exploit these friends for his own benefit and then bombard them with blame and accusations. The worst part was his jealous resentment towards comrades who were less unfortunate than he was. His treatment of Freiligrath and especially Lassalle was deplorable from every angle. Lassalle had shown him great kindness, provided him with significant financial help, hosted him in Berlin, and assisted him in finding a publisher. Yet, Marx later criticized Lassalle’s work harshly, viewed his successes with suspicion, and commented on the circumstances surrounding Lassalle’s death in a half-heartedly apologetic manner. But you well-fed folks, who study the life of our activist under comfortable circumstances, should refrain from being too quick to judge him. Before throwing stones, consider all the miseries that exiles endure and the pain they must carry along with their burdens.

Vainly did he endeavour by hard work to free himself from the sad restraints of poverty. It is true he was able to place articles with the "New York Tribune," writing for this paper essays on political, economic, and financial questions, which secured much appreciation. But the pay was only one pound per article, and he could write but one article a week. Collaboration in the production of[Pg 76] an American encyclopædia, to be paid at the rate of two dollars a page, seemed to promise more ample funds, and with feverish anxiety he devoted himself to the production of articles on the most varied topics, well stored with facts. But this source of income, limited at best, was suddenly interrupted by the outbreak of the American civil war. The loss was not adequately compensated by the possibility of occasionally inserting some poorly paid contribution in a German newspaper like the "New Oder Gazette" or in one of the Viennese periodicals.

He tried hard to escape the tough limitations of poverty through diligent work. It's true that he managed to get articles published in the "New York Tribune," writing essays on political, economic, and financial issues that received a lot of appreciation. However, he only earned one pound per article and could write just one article a week. Collaborating on producing[Pg 76] an American encyclopedia, which paid two dollars per page, seemed to offer better financial prospects, so he eagerly dedicated himself to writing articles on a wide range of topics, filled with factual information. But this income source, already limited, was abruptly cut off by the start of the American Civil War. The loss wasn't sufficiently made up for by occasionally contributing some poorly paid pieces to a German newspaper like the "New Oder Gazette" or to one of the Viennese magazines.

He was lucky in that certain turns of fortune favoured him from those sources of property and inheritance which he condemned and attacked with such persistence and vehemence. He had a legacy from his mother-in-law; a legacy from his mother; a trifling legacy from an aunt; and Wilhelm Wolff, a companion in exile, bequeathed him £800. An uncle in Holland, whom he had begged for some[Pg 77] trifling help, gave him £160; from Lassalle and Freiligrath came generous gifts; and Droncke, another companion in exile, gave £250 to enable him to complete the scientific work on which he was engaged.

He was fortunate that certain twists of fate worked in his favor from the very sources of wealth and inheritance he criticized and attacked so passionately. He received an inheritance from his mother-in-law, another from his mother, a small bequest from an aunt, and Wilhelm Wolff, a friend in exile, left him £800. An uncle in Holland, from whom he had requested a little support, gave him £160; he also received generous gifts from Lassalle and Freiligrath; and Droncke, another friend in exile, contributed £250 to help him finish the scientific work he was involved in.

But none of these casual resources, however extensive, would have saved him from ruin had it not been for the providential assistance of his friend Friedrich Engels, who applied himself to the care of Marx with inexhaustible generosity, and with the tenderness of a woman. Engels, indeed, will secure a splendid place in the history of socialist thought, were it only because of the way in which he devoted himself to Marx. It was through Engels that Marx was enabled to continue his studies and to complete the work which is his title to eternal fame. Engels, a well-to-do cotton spinner at Manchester, gladly responded to his friend's unremitting requests for aid, succouring him in every emergency. Engels was an expert upon military topics, and penned[Pg 78] articles which Marx passed on to the "Tribune" and to the encyclopædia, articles for which Marx was paid; Engels sent Marx weekly subsidies, and frequently despatched gifts of port wine; he made presents of £100 or £150 at a time; and at length, when his business prospered, he gave his friend a regular allowance of £350 a year.

But none of these casual resources, no matter how extensive, would have saved him from ruin if it weren't for the timely help of his friend Friedrich Engels, who took care of Marx with endless generosity and the tenderness of a woman. Engels will undoubtedly earn a significant place in the history of socialist thought, especially because of how he dedicated himself to Marx. It was through Engels that Marx was able to continue his studies and finish the work that would make him eternally famous. Engels, a successful cotton spinner in Manchester, happily responded to his friend's constant requests for help, supporting him in every crisis. Engels was knowledgeable about military topics and wrote[Pg 78] articles that Marx submitted to the "Tribune" and the encyclopedia, for which Marx received payment; Engels sent Marx weekly financial support and often sent gifts of port wine; he would give £100 or £150 at a time; and eventually, as his business thrived, he provided his friend with a regular allowance of £350 a year.

Not even these strokes of good luck sufficed, it is true, to restore a satisfactory balance to Marx's finances, for he was a bad manager, and the disorder was probably incurable. However, they enabled our thinker to furnish aid to companions yet more unfortunate, to Pieper, Eccarius, and Dupont; they enabled him to escape from the worst extremities of poverty and to establish himself in life under conditions more worthy of an honest and respectable bourgeois. He was able to move from the decayed neighbourhood of Soho Square and to settle in Maitland Park Road on Haverstock Hill; it became possible for[Pg 79] him to secure a good education for his daughters, to have them taught French and Italian, drawing and music; he could weigh the financial status of aspirants to their hands, and could choose Lafargue and Longuet, who were comparatively well off. He often went to the theatre, and with one of his daughters he attended at the Society of Arts a soirée graced by the presence of royalty; from time to time he took his family to the seaside; he liked his wife to sign herself "Jenny, née Baronne de Westphalen"; he was well received in affluent circles, and was frequently consulted by the "Times" upon financial affairs; finally he accepted the office of constable of the vestry of St. Pancras, taking the customary oath, and donning the regulation uniform on gala occasions.

Not even these strokes of good luck were enough to fix Marx's finances, as he was a poor manager and the chaos was likely beyond repair. Still, they allowed him to help friends who were even less fortunate, like Pieper, Eccarius, and Dupont; they helped him escape the worst of poverty and set up a life that was more fitting for an honest and respectable middle-class person. He was able to move from the rundown area of Soho Square to a place on Maitland Park Road in Haverstock Hill; it became possible for[Pg 79] him to ensure a good education for his daughters, including lessons in French and Italian, drawing, and music; he could assess the financial status of potential suitors for their hands and choose Lafargue and Longuet, who were relatively well-off. He often went to the theater, and with one of his daughters, he attended a soirée at the Society of Arts that was attended by royalty; now and then, he took his family to the seaside; he enjoyed having his wife sign herself as "Jenny, née Baronne de Westphalen"; he was welcomed in affluent circles and was frequently consulted by the "Times" on financial matters; ultimately, he took the position of constable of the vestry of St. Pancras, swearing the usual oath and wearing the standard uniform on special occasions.

Nevertheless, neither this final settlement in a foreign land nor the persecution he suffered from the government of his own country could destroy or even lessen his devotion[Pg 80] to Germany. To the day of his death he remained a faithful child of the fatherland, for which he hoped the greatest of futures. He sang the praises of German music and literature; he delighted in German victories and German expansion; he dreaded a weakening of German protectionism which might strengthen the commercial hegemony of Britain; and in 1870 he refused to sign an appeal in favour of peace unless it were definitely stated that Germany was waging a purely defensive war. The French and Russian exiles in London were indignant, and circulated whispers that Marx was a Prussian emissary, and had received a bribe of £10,000. An idle tale! It is true that among German conservatives and among the beneficiaries of Germany there could not be found a supporter more sincere and more fervent than was this proscribed rebel. But he was no paladin on behalf of Prussian imperialism, as we can learn beyond dispute from a letter he sent to[Pg 81] the "Daily News" in 1878 denouncing Bismarckian ambitions and the Bismarckian expansionist policy as a growing peril.

Nevertheless, neither this final settlement in a foreign land nor the persecution he faced from his own country's government could destroy or even lessen his devotion[Pg 80] to Germany. Until the day he died, he remained a loyal child of the fatherland, hoping for the brightest future for it. He praised German music and literature; he celebrated German victories and expansion; he feared a weakening of German protectionism that might boost Britain's commercial dominance; and in 1870, he refused to sign a peace appeal unless it clearly stated that Germany was fighting a purely defensive war. The French and Russian exiles in London were outraged and spread rumors that Marx was a Prussian agent who had received a £10,000 bribe. What a ridiculous claim! It is true that among German conservatives and those benefiting from Germany, there was no more sincere and passionate supporter than this exiled rebel. But he was not a champion for Prussian imperialism, as we can clearly see from a letter he sent to[Pg 81] the "Daily News" in 1878, denouncing Bismarckian ambitions and their expansionist policy as a growing threat.

Yet the supreme aim of his activity and his life enormously transcended the circumscribed range of country and of nation, for he aspired to a loftier goal, to the organisation of the mental and manual workers of all countries so that they might constitute a united revolutionary force. Within a brief time of his arrival in the British metropolis he again became the chief, nay the dictator, of a circle to which none could be admitted without passing a severe examination as to knowledge of science in general and of political economy in particular, an examination so rigorous that even Wilhelm Liebknecht was unable at first to satisfy its requirements, an examination that was physical as well as mental, for the aspirants were subjected (rejoice, shade of Lombroso!) to precise craniometrical tests.

Yet the ultimate goal of his work and life went far beyond the limited scope of country and nation, as he aimed for a higher purpose: to organize the mental and manual workers from all countries into a united revolutionary force. Shortly after arriving in London, he quickly became the leader, even the dictator, of a group that only allowed members who passed a tough examination on general science and political economy. This exam was so strict that even Wilhelm Liebknecht initially couldn't meet its standards; it was both a physical and mental test, as candidates were subjected (rejoice, shade of Lombroso!) to precise craniometrical evaluations.

Thus our thinker, crowned as if by divine right with a kind of imperial halo, exercised undisputed sway over the troop of exiles, Pieper, Bauer, Blind, Biskamp, Eccarius, Liebknecht, Freiligrath, Cesare Orsini (brother of the regicide), and even over the revolutionary agitators in Germany. Soon, however, his mind was invaded and dominated by a yet more ambitious design, for he planned the formation of a society which should unite the proletarians of all the world into one formidable International, to resist the aggressions of capital and to work for the destruction of the capitalist system. It was at first an association of modest proportions, consisting merely of a few revolutionaries assembled in London. Marx absolutely refused the chairmanship, contenting himself with the post, ostensibly less important, of delegate for the German section.

Thus our thinker, as if by divine right and wearing an imperial halo, held undisputed power over the group of exiles: Pieper, Bauer, Blind, Biskamp, Eccarius, Liebknecht, Freiligrath, Cesare Orsini (brother of the regicide), and even over the revolutionary activists in Germany. Soon, however, his mind was overtaken by an even more ambitious project, as he planned to create a society that would unite the workers of the world into one powerful International, to resist the encroachments of capital and to work towards the destruction of the capitalist system. Initially, it was a small association, consisting of just a few revolutionaries gathered in London. Marx outright declined the chairmanship, being satisfied with the supposedly less significant role of delegate for the German section.

From the first formation of the new federation Marx did his utmost to counteract the[Pg 83] influence of Mazzini, for Mazzini, through the instrumentality of two of his followers, Fontana and the elder Wolff, wished to inspire the International with his idealist conceptions and to initiate it into the secrets of conspiracy. Marx, on the other hand, was unwearying in his efforts to advocate his own view that material interests preponderate, and that these interests must be publicly asserted and defended in the arena of history. Soon the federation established branches in France, Germany, the United States, and even the Latin countries; and this involved for Marx, who was really the chief, a mass of work in the way of organisation, and of struggle against those who held conflicting views. Everywhere, in fact, he had to encounter trends differing from his own, and differing no less extensively one from another owing to the varying characters of the countries concerned.

From the very beginning of the new federation, Marx worked hard to counter Mazzini's influence, as Mazzini, through two of his followers, Fontana and the elder Wolff, wanted to fill the International with his idealistic ideas and introduce it to the secrets of conspiracy. In contrast, Marx tirelessly promoted his belief that material interests are more important and that these interests should be publicly acknowledged and defended in history. Before long, the federation set up branches in France, Germany, the United States, and even Latin countries; this meant a lot of work for Marx, who was really the leader, in terms of organization and fighting against those with differing views. Everywhere, he faced trends that differed from his own and varied widely from one another because of the unique characteristics of each country involved.

In Germany he had to fight the opportunism of Lassalle, a man inclined to compromises[Pg 84] and to elastic unions with constituted authority. In France anti-intellectual tendencies were already manifest, so that there was an inclination to restrict the socialist outlook to an aspiration for immediately practical labour legislation of minor importance. In Italy and in Spain, Marx's troubles arose from the anarchist tendencies characteristic of those countries, tendencies fostered by the propaganda of Bakunin.

In Germany, he had to contend with the opportunism of Lassalle, a guy who was prone to compromises[Pg 84] and flexible alliances with established authorities. In France, anti-intellectual attitudes were already showing, leading to a tendency to limit the socialist vision to a quest for practical labor laws of lesser significance. In Italy and Spain, Marx faced issues due to the anarchist tendencies typical of those countries, which were promoted by Bakunin's propaganda.

As against these divergent aims, Marx, with inflexible tenacity, maintained his own programme with the utmost rigour, insisting that it was essential to federate the proletarian forces of the world into an invincible organisation which in all possible ways, by strikes, by parliamentary and legal methods, but also by force should need arise, should deliver onslaughts upon the bourgeoisie and upon constituted authority, should exact concessions of increasing importance, and should ultimately secure a complete triumph. The proletarians[Pg 85] of the two hemispheres were not slow to accept the programme; and this man who was himself suffering from actual hunger, now secured a great position as a thinker, so that the operatives of Paris, New York, and Düsseldorf did honour to his name.

Against these different goals, Marx stubbornly held onto his program with the strictest discipline, insisting that it was crucial to unite the working-class forces around the world into an unstoppable organization. This organization would use every possible method—strikes, parliamentary and legal actions, and, if necessary, force—to attack the bourgeoisie and established authority, demand increasingly significant concessions, and ultimately achieve total victory. The workers[Pg 85] from both hemispheres quickly embraced the program; and this man, who was personally experiencing hunger, gained a massive reputation as a thinker, earning respect from laborers in Paris, New York, and Düsseldorf.

These activities, however, did not completely interrupt his intellectual labours, for during the period at which we have now arrived he published in the "New York Tribune" a series of articles upon Revolution and Counter-revolution in Germany and upon Political Struggles in France. In 1852, in "The Revolution," published in the German tongue in New York, there had appeared the article The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte. Substantially these writings are an application of the materialist conception of history to the more conspicuous events of the recent political history of Germany and of France. In addition, Marx published in the "Tribune" a series of articles of a more [Pg 86]distinctively political character, dealing with The Eastern Question, displaying marvellous erudition and a wonderful power of forecasting events.

These activities, however, didn’t completely interrupt his intellectual work, because during the time we are now discussing, he published a series of articles in the "New York Tribune" about Revolution and Counter-revolution in Germany and Political Struggles in France. In 1852, the article The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte appeared in "The Revolution," published in German in New York. Essentially, these writings apply the materialist conception of history to the significant events of the recent political history of Germany and France. Additionally, Marx published a series of articles in the "Tribune" that had a more [Pg 86]distinctly political focus, discussing The Eastern Question, showcasing remarkable knowledge and an impressive ability to predict events.


CHAPTER III

Nevertheless, the organisation of the proletariat, and his journalistic labours, however intense and however weighty, did not represent in the life of Marx anything more than a vexatious parenthesis or a regrettable delay in the fulfilment of the supreme task he had set before himself from the very outset of his life in Britain. Hardly, in fact, had Marx settled down in the wonderful town of London, to the economist so inexhaustible a field for study and experience, than he proposed to rebuild from the foundations the entire edifice of his economic and statistical knowledge, which was at that time comparatively small when contrasted with the vast extent of his preliminary readings in philosophy. In the British Museum library, therefore, he plunged[Pg 88] into the study of the classical economists of the island realm, showing inexhaustible patience in tracing the earliest and most trifling ramifications of economic science.

Nevertheless, the organization of the working class and his journalistic efforts, no matter how intense or significant, only represented for Marx a frustrating interruption or a regrettable delay in achieving the ultimate goal he had set for himself from the very beginning of his life in Britain. Hardly had Marx settled into the amazing city of London, a place offering such an endless opportunity for study and experience, when he aimed to completely rebuild the foundations of his economic and statistical knowledge, which was relatively limited at that time compared to his extensive preliminary readings in philosophy. At the British Museum library, he then immersed himself[Pg 88] in the study of the classical economists of the UK, demonstrating endless patience in tracing even the smallest and earliest branches of economic science.

Beginning with the study of the theory of rent, he went on to the study of money, of the relationship between the quantity of metal in circulation and the rate of exchange, of the influence of bank reserves upon prices, and so forth. He then devoted himself to the theories of value, profit, interest, and population. Simultaneously he studied without remission statistics, blue books, ministerial and parliamentary concerns.

Beginning with the study of rent theory, he moved on to the study of money, examining the relationship between the amount of metal in circulation and exchange rates, as well as how bank reserves affect prices, and more. He then focused on theories of value, profit, interest, and population. At the same time, he consistently studied statistics, government reports, and parliamentary issues.

From all this gigantic toil he derived the materials for the writing of the work which was henceforward to be at once the sorrow and the joy of his life. His first intention was to limit himself to a critical history of political economy, or a detailed analysis of the theories which he had so often enunciated, as well as of the lacunae which had become [Pg 89]apparent in them. But an unexpected result issued from the mental contact with this huge mass of science and analysis, for he believed that he had made a splendid and startling discovery whereby the sacred theory of profit could be utterly exploded.

From all this massive effort, he gathered the material to write a work that would become both the source of his sorrow and his joy. Initially, he intended to focus on a critical history of political economy or a detailed breakdown of the theories he had frequently discussed, along with the gaps that had become [Pg 89] evident in them. However, an unexpected outcome came from engaging with this vast amount of knowledge and analysis, as he believed he had made a remarkable and shocking discovery that could completely discredit the sacred theory of profit.

Now, therefore, he outlined the design of his great work, which was to consist of two parts; a first, historico-critical, intended to elucidate the different forms of the theory of profit as expounded by the various British economists; and a second, theoretical and constructive, which was to announce to the world the author's own doctrine. This method of exposition is substantially identical with that followed by Böhm-Bawerk in his Capital and Interest, and it corresponds moreover to the immediate requirements of the investigation, which ought to begin with the study of prevailing opinions and doctrines, and then only proceed to innovation. But a more attentive examination of the question soon [Pg 90]convinced Marx that this would not be the most efficacious method of furnishing a theoretical reproduction of actualities, since, to this end, we must let the phenomena tell their own tale before we proceed to call to account those who have already analysed them, and before we draw attention to the ways in which their conception of the facts diverges from that which reality, when directly questioned, reveals. The method has ever been preferred by the most gifted theorists, and has been applied by Bergson with admirable dexterity in his Creative Evolution. Marx, therefore, never weary of destroying and refashioning, inverted his original design, and promptly began the study and analysis of concrete phenomena, to proceed then only to a criticism of the theories of his precursors. It was in accordance with such criteria that he wrote his Criticism of Political Economy, of which the first instalment was published at Berlin in 1859.

Now, he outlined the plan for his major work, which would consist of two parts: the first part being historical and critical, aimed at explaining the different forms of the profit theory as discussed by various British economists; and the second part being theoretical and constructive, to present the author's own ideas. This approach is very similar to the one used by Böhm-Bawerk in his Capital and Interest, and it aligns with the immediate needs of the inquiry, which should start with an exploration of existing opinions and ideas before moving on to new propositions. However, a closer look at the issue soon [Pg 90] led Marx to realize that this wouldn’t be the most effective way to provide a theoretical representation of reality. To do this, we need to allow the phenomena to express their own story before questioning those who have analyzed them and highlighting how their understanding of the facts differs from the reality revealed when examined directly. This method has always been favored by the most insightful theorists and was skillfully utilized by Bergson in his Creative Evolution. Therefore, Marx, never one to tire of deconstructing and reshaping ideas, reversed his original plan and began with the study and analysis of concrete phenomena, only afterward critiquing the theories of those who came before him. It was based on this approach that he composed his Criticism of Political Economy, the first installment of which was published in Berlin in 1859.

The most notable portion of this work is[Pg 91] the preface, which contains the first statement of the theory of historical materialism. The relationships of men in social life, says Marx, are determined by the conditions of production, are necessary relationships independent of the individual will; these determined relationships constitute the real foundation upon which is erected the legislative, political, moral, and religious superstructure of every age. The relationships of production, or the economic relationships prevailing at a given period, are a natural and necessary outcome of the method of production, or rather of the historic phase of the instrument of production. But sooner or later the further development of the productive forces generates a new configuration in technical method, a configuration incompatible with the prevailing relationships of production, those correlative to the productive order hitherto dominant. There then occurs an explosion, a social revolution, which disintegrates economic relationships,[Pg 92] and, by ricochet, disintegrates existing social relationships, replacing them by better economic relationships, adequate to the new and more highly evolved phase of the productive instrument.

The most notable part of this work is[Pg 91] the preface, which presents the first statement of the theory of historical materialism. Marx argues that the relationships among people in society are determined by the conditions of production and are essential relationships that exist independently of individual choices; these relationships form the real foundation upon which the legislative, political, moral, and religious systems of any era are built. The relationships of production, or the economic relationships that exist during a specific period, are a natural and necessary result of the method of production, or more specifically, the historical stage of the production tools. Eventually, the further development of productive forces leads to a new technical method that clashes with the existing relationships of production related to the previous dominant productive order. This results in an explosion, a social revolution, that breaks down economic relationships,[Pg 92] and subsequently disrupts current social relationships, replacing them with improved economic relationships that align with the new and more advanced stage of production tools.

In broad outline it may be said that economic evolution has exhibited four progressive phases; the Asiatic economy, the classical economy, the feudalist economy, and the modern bourgeois or capitalist economy. The evolution of the productive instrument, never arrested in its secular march, will in due course renew the eternally recurrent opposition between the method of production and the relationships of production, rendering these incompatible. Once more will come an explosion, the last of the great social convulsions, whereby the bourgeois economic order will be overthrown and will be replaced by the co-operative commonwealth. This new development will close the primary epoch of the history of human society.

In broad terms, it can be said that economic evolution has gone through four main phases: the Asiatic economy, the classical economy, the feudal economy, and the modern capitalist economy. The evolution of productive tools, which has never stopped in its long progression, will eventually revive the ongoing conflict between the method of production and the relationships of production, making them incompatible. There will be another explosion, the final of the significant social upheavals, through which the capitalist economic order will be toppled and replaced with a cooperative society. This new development will mark the end of the primary phase in the history of human society.

But the work we are discussing is further noteworthy inasmuch as it reflects a special phase of our author's thought, a thought which never ceased to exhibit a struggle between opposing trends and was ever oppressed by their contrast. The book, in fact, shows Marx continually involved in antiquated Hegelian machinery, or proceeding through a chain of categories evolving one from another—capital, landed property, the wage system, the state, foreign commerce, the world market. From each of these categories we may infer how the process of their successive development is accomplished. We are led to infer that the wage system is the outcome of landed proprietorship, for the expropriation of the peasant proprietors produces the proletarianised masses offering labour power for sale; and we are led to infer that the constitution of the world market is the crown and the epilogue of modern capitalist economy. In fact, according to Marx, the historic mission of [Pg 94]capitalism based upon wage labour, whose origins go back to the sixteenth century, is the creation of the world market. The world market is now devoted to the colonisation of California and Australia and to the opening of trading ports in China and Japan; its creation marks the climax of capitalism's historic mission, and indicates the approaching end of the economic form which was destined to fulfill it.

But the work we're talking about is especially noteworthy because it reflects a unique phase of our author's thoughts, which always showed a struggle between opposing ideas and was constantly weighed down by their contrast. This book really shows Marx constantly caught up in outdated Hegelian ideas or moving through a series of categories that build on each other—capital, land ownership, the wage system, the state, foreign trade, the global market. From each of these categories, we can see how their successive development happens. We can conclude that the wage system arises from land ownership, as the displacement of peasant landowners leads to a working class that offers their labor for sale; and we can also conclude that the creation of the global market is the pinnacle and conclusion of modern capitalist economy. According to Marx, the historical mission of [Pg 94] capitalism, based on wage labor and originating in the sixteenth century, is to create the global market. This global market is now focused on colonizing California and Australia and opening up trade ports in China and Japan; its creation represents the peak of capitalism's historic mission, signaling the imminent end of the economic structure meant to accomplish it.

Now these ideas, in themselves arbitrary and fantastic, show how Marx's thought at that epoch was still in an undecided or amphibious phase, in which the torrid sun of British economic science had not as yet succeeded in totally dispelling the fogs of German philosophy. But another incompatibility lessens the value of the book or diminishes its doctrinal efficacy; for Marx, at this stage of his studies, invariably gave to the history of doctrine too preponderant a place, introducing it insistently into the course of his own [Pg 95]exposition, which was thus deprived of continuity and weakened in force.

Now these ideas, which are pretty arbitrary and out there, show that Marx's thinking at that time was still in a confused or mixed state, where the strong influence of British economic science hadn’t completely cleared away the confusion from German philosophy. But another issue reduces the quality of the book or weakens its theoretical impact; at this stage of his studies, Marx often gave too much importance to the history of ideas, constantly weaving it into his own [Pg 95] presentation, which ended up making it less coherent and weaker in impact.

Further, the book we are considering did not directly bear upon any of the social questions which strongly arouse public interest, but was restricted to the study of two theories whose importance at first sight seems purely academic, the theory of value and the theory of money.

Further, the book we're looking at didn't directly address any of the social issues that grab public attention, but focused on the analysis of two theories that, at first glance, seem purely academic: the theory of value and the theory of money.

Marx contended that the value of commodities is exclusively determined by the quantity of labour incorporated into them; he traced the affiliations of this thesis with the work of its first enunciators in Italy and in England; but he did not offer any reasoned demonstration of its truth. On the contrary, he frankly recognised that this contention is full of contradictions alike theoretical and practical, contradictions that appear insoluble; but he promised to vanquish them in the subsequent course of his exposition.

Marx argued that the value of goods is solely based on the amount of labor put into them; he connected this idea to the work of its early proponents in Italy and England; however, he did not provide a solid proof of its accuracy. Instead, he openly acknowledged that this claim is riddled with both theoretical and practical contradictions that seem impossible to resolve; but he promised to overcome them in the following parts of his explanation.

Far more noteworthy is the chapter on[Pg 96] money, for it contains a masterly criticism of the quantitative theory of Ricardo, and an effective refutation of the "labour notes" idea of Bray, Gray, Proudhon, and others. According to this plan, every producer performing a certain quantum of labour would receive from the state a voucher entitling him to obtain from other producers the result of an equal quantum of labour; but the suggestion implies complete ignorance of the intrinsic conditions of the individualistic economy, wherein each producer creates an object without any certainty that there will be a market for it, or that it represents a real utility and will fetch a definite price. It obviously follows that the producer cannot be sure that he will be able to sell the article which he has produced, or that he will be able to transform it into anything with universal purchasing power; the product has to be baptised or sanctioned by the market, which alone has power to stamp it as useful by purchasing it.

Far more significant is the chapter on[Pg 96] money, as it offers a brilliant critique of Ricardo's quantitative theory and effectively counters the "labor notes" concept proposed by Bray, Gray, Proudhon, and others. This idea suggests that each producer, after completing a certain amount of labor, would receive from the government a voucher allowing them to obtain goods from other producers equivalent to the value of their labor. However, this suggestion shows a complete misunderstanding of the fundamental realities of a market economy, where each producer creates a product without any guarantee of a market demand for it or that it has real value, or that it will sell for a specific price. It is clear that the producer can't be certain they'll be able to sell the item they've made, or that they can exchange it for something universally acceptable; the product needs to be recognized or validated by the market, which is the only authority that can deem it useful by purchasing it.

Now the "labour note" system claims that it can forcibly dispense with the market by supplying to the producer of an article whose utility and saleable value has not been recognised by the market, a universally available purchasing power. The practical outcome of this forcible method is that the producer of a useless article can by means of his "labour note" secure for himself a useful article, whereas the producer of this latter will not in turn be able to exchange his own "labour note" for any object possessing utility; that is to say, the article made by the first producer will find no purchaser, and the "labour note" of the second producer will effect no purchase. This is inevitable, for the proposed reform is inconsistent, eclectic, and incomplete, since it pretends to socialise exchange while maintaining production and distribution upon their old individualistic basis, and overlooks the incongruity of any such supposition.

Now the "labor note" system claims it can eliminate the market by giving producers of goods, whose usefulness and market value haven’t been recognized, a universal purchasing power. The practical result of this forced approach is that a producer of a worthless item can use his "labor note" to obtain a useful item, whereas the producer of that useful item won’t be able to exchange his own "labor note" for anything valuable; in other words, the item made by the first producer will find no buyer, and the "labor note" of the second producer won’t make any purchases. This is unavoidable, as the proposed reform is inconsistent, mixed, and incomplete, since it aims to socialize exchange while keeping production and distribution on their old individualistic foundation, and ignores the contradiction of such an idea.

The "labour note" system cannot rationally[Pg 98] be instituted until production has been socialised, or until the state shall impose upon each individual the production of a specified quantity and quality of commodities, correlatively imposing upon the consumer the obligation to acquire these. In such conditions, however, we could no longer speak of commodities or of exchange, for these phenomena belong exclusively to an individualistic economy and would have no place in a socialised economy. This means that the reform of exchange by the suppression of profit can only be effected by the suppression of exchange itself, by the institution of the co-operative commonwealth. Indeed, Robert Owen, who proposed the "labour note" system in 1832, and was the most brilliant of its advocates, clearly recognised this difficulty, and understood that the socialisation of production would be an indispensable preliminary to the adoption of the plan. It was the impatience of his disciples which forced him to [Pg 99]inaugurate the system within the framework of the capitalist economy by founding the National Equitable Labour Exchange. The logic of facts gave a patent demonstration of the irrationality of the attempt; and Owen, saddened and humiliated, was compelled to witness the failure of the new institution.

The "labor note" system can't realistically[Pg 98] be put in place until production is socialized, or until the state requires each individual to produce a certain quantity and quality of goods, while also placing an obligation on consumers to buy these goods. However, under such conditions, we wouldn't be able to talk about commodities or exchange anymore, because these concepts are solely part of an individualistic economy and wouldn't fit in a socialized economy. This means that changing the way we exchange by getting rid of profit can only be achieved by eliminating exchange itself and establishing a cooperative commonwealth. In fact, Robert Owen, who proposed the "labor note" system in 1832 and was its most prominent supporter, recognized this challenge and knew that socializing production was a necessary step before adopting the plan. The impatience of his followers pushed him to [Pg 99]launch the system within the framework of a capitalist economy by setting up the National Equitable Labor Exchange. The reality of the situation clearly demonstrated the irrationality of that attempt; and Owen, feeling disheartened and embarrassed, had to watch the failure of the new institution.

It will readily be understood that these abstruse and abstract investigations, devoid as they are of any tangible connection with the burning problems of property, were not likely to arouse interest among the members of the party. Nothing could be more natural than the tone of hopeless discouragement with which the volume was greeted even by the author's most devoted friends. Liebknecht, for example, declared that he had never before experienced so great a disappointment. Biskamp enquired what on earth it was all about; Burgers deplored that Marx should have published a work so dull and fragmentary. It is true that the book had a [Pg 100]moderate sale; Rau quoted it in his treatise; certain Russian and American economists made it the subject of profound studies. Nevertheless, the publisher refused to proceed with the issue.

It will be easily understood that these complex and theoretical investigations, lacking any real connection to the pressing issues of property, were not likely to spark interest among the party members. It’s completely natural that the volume was met with a tone of hopeless discouragement, even by the author’s most loyal friends. Liebknecht, for instance, said that he had never felt such a huge disappointment before. Biskamp wondered what the whole thing was actually about; Burgers lamented that Marx had published a work that was so dull and disjointed. It's true that the book had a [Pg 100]moderate sales; Rau cited it in his treatise; and certain Russian and American economists made it the focus of in-depth studies. Nevertheless, the publisher refused to move forward with the release.

Hardly had this literary bickering come to an end when Marx became involved in a violent quarrel with the distinguished naturalist Karl Vogt, who publicly charged him with setting snares for the German exiles and with having sordid relationships with the police. Marx replied with a savage booklet entitled Herr Vogt (London, 1860). The style of this polemic writing is intolerably vulgar; but in other respects the book is noteworthy, for it contains interesting revelations anent the Italian campaign and the relationships between Turin and the Tuileries. We must remember, moreover, that the accusation here launched against Vogt, that he was in the pay of the Second Empire, was subsequently confirmed beyond dispute, for in 1871 among the[Pg 101] ruins of the Tuileries there was found a receipt for frs. 40,000 which had been paid over to Vogt.

Hardly had this literary argument wrapped up when Marx got into a heated dispute with the prominent naturalist Karl Vogt, who publicly accused him of setting traps for German exiles and of having shady dealings with the police. Marx responded with a fierce pamphlet titled Herr Vogt (London, 1860). The tone of this polemic is extremely vulgar; however, the book is significant in other ways, as it includes interesting insights about the Italian campaign and the connections between Turin and the Tuileries. It's also important to remember that the accusation against Vogt—that he was on the payroll of the Second Empire—was later proven beyond question, as in 1871 a receipt for frs. 40,000 was discovered among the[Pg 101] ruins of the Tuileries, which had been paid to Vogt.

But scientific failures, personal contests, persistent and distressing domestic discomforts, seemed to inspire our athlete with renewed strength for the continuance of the work he had begun. Nevertheless, profiting by experience, he decided upon a yet further modification in the plan of his book, resolving to defer to its final section all historico-critical disquisitions, and to concentrate his energies upon the positive analysis of concrete reality. Further, being prevented by frequent illness from tackling the more difficult themes of pure economics, he devoted these long intervals of comparative leisure to statistical investigations and to the perusal of factory inspectors' reports, of white books and of blue books, and he plunged into the study of the economic history of Great Britain, so that it became possible for him to interleave the pages of[Pg 102] abstract theory, necessarily difficult to understand, with pages that are really living, pages that vibrate with the reflex of reality. At length, abandoning the method he had previously followed of publishing fragmentary essays, he decided to rewrite the work throughout before sending it to press.

But scientific failures, personal challenges, and constant, frustrating domestic issues seemed to motivate our athlete with renewed energy to continue his work. Nevertheless, learning from experience, he decided to make further changes to his book's plan, choosing to push all historical and critical discussions to the final section and focusing his efforts on the straightforward analysis of concrete reality. Additionally, due to frequent illness preventing him from tackling more complex topics in pure economics, he spent these long breaks engaging in statistical research and reading factory inspectors' reports, white papers, and blue books. He also immersed himself in the economic history of Great Britain, allowing him to blend the pages of[Pg 102] abstract theory, which can be tough to grasp, with pages that are truly vibrant and resonate with the reality of the situation. Ultimately, he decided to abandon his earlier approach of publishing fragmented essays and instead rewrite the entire work before sending it to print.

After several years of incredible labour, the days being devoted to reading in the British Museum library, and the nights (for he often went on writing until four in the morning) to literary composition; falling again and again beneath the burden of his cross, but ever rising to his feet once more, thanks to the demon within urging him on and thanks also to the sustaining hand of his incomparable friend; he at length completed his task, and in the spring of 1867 sailed for Hamburg with the manuscript of the first volume of Capital, which he entrusted to Meissner for publication. In Hamburg he passed pleasant days with Dr. Kugelmann, a friend and fervent[Pg 103] admirer, and with various officials, generals, and bankers; he was visited by a lawyer named Warnebold, an emissary from Bismarck, who, acting on the minister's instructions, exhorted him "to employ his brilliant talents for the advantage of the German people." Before long, however, he returned to London, where he earnestly devoted himself to giving the last touches to his book, which was finally issued from the press in the autumn of the same year.

After several years of hard work, spending days reading in the British Museum library and nights (he often wrote until four in the morning) focusing on his literary projects; repeatedly struggling under the weight of his challenges but always getting back up, driven by the inner fire and supported by his amazing friend; he finally finished his work, and in the spring of 1867, he sailed to Hamburg with the manuscript of the first volume of Capital, which he entrusted to Meissner for publication. In Hamburg, he enjoyed his time with Dr. Kugelmann, a friend and passionate admirer, as well as with various officials, generals, and bankers; he was visited by a lawyer named Warnebold, an envoy from Bismarck, who, following the minister's orders, urged him "to use his brilliant talents for the benefit of the German people." Soon after, though, he returned to London, where he dedicated himself to putting the finishing touches on his book, which was finally published in the autumn of the same year.

Thus was at length given to the world the monumental work destined to revolutionise sociological thought, and to give a new and higher trend, not to socialism alone, but to political economy itself. To sum up its drift very briefly, we may say that the argument follows three chief lines, value, machinery, and primitive accumulation. He set out from the fundamental principle (a principle which the philosopher Krause had declared to be as important to political economy as the fall of heavy bodies is important to physics) that the[Pg 104] value of products is measured by the mass of labour incorporated into them, and drew the conclusion that the profit of capital is nothing other than the materialisation of a quantity of labour expended by the worker, and is in other words unpaid labour, stolen and usurped income. The worker, that is to say, transmits into the product a value equal to the quantity of labour incorporated therein, but receives from the capitalist a value less than this, a value equal to the quantity of labour embodied in the commodities necessary to reproduce the energy expended by the worker.

Thus, the world was finally introduced to a groundbreaking work that would transform sociological thought and elevate not just socialism, but political economy as a whole. To summarize its essence briefly, we can say that the argument follows three main themes: value, machinery, and primitive accumulation. It starts from the fundamental principle (a principle that philosopher Krause claimed was as crucial to political economy as the fall of heavy bodies is to physics) that the[Pg 104] value of products is determined by the amount of labor incorporated into them. The conclusion drawn is that the profit of capital is essentially the manifestation of a quantity of labor expended by the worker, which can be described as unpaid labor, taken and usurped income. In other words, the worker contributes a value to the product equal to the amount of labor involved, but receives from the capitalist a value that is less than this—specifically, a value equivalent to the quantity of labor embodied in the goods necessary to regenerate the energy that the worker exerted.

Now the difference between the value of the product (that is to say the quantity of labour transmitted by the worker into the product) and the value of the labour power (that is to say the quantity of labour employed in producing the commodities consumed by the worker) constitute the surplus value which is gratuitously pocketed by the owner of the means of production in virtue of the fact that[Pg 105] he is owner. In this way Marx attains to the qualitative notion of the income of capital, or explains whereof that income effectively consists. It remains to determine the quantity of income, which cannot be specified unless there have previously been precisely determined the measure and the figure of wages.

Now the difference between the value of the product (which means the amount of labor the worker puts into the product) and the value of the labor power (which means the amount of labor used to create the goods consumed by the worker) makes up the surplus value that the owner of the means of production takes for free simply because[Pg 105] he is the owner. This way, Marx gets to a qualitative understanding of capital income, or explains what that income really consists of. It remains to determine the amount of income, which can't be specified unless the measure and the amount of wages have been clearly established first.

Now though it be true that the growth of accumulation virtually tends to bring about an increase in the amount paid in wages, it is nevertheless within the power of the capitalist to obviate this undesirable event by investing the growing accumulation in the form of technical capital, which by its very nature is without influence upon wages. But the capitalist can do more than this. He can transform into technical capital a part of the capital which has hitherto been utilised in paying wages, thus throwing some of the workers out of employment, or creating an industrial reserve army. This reserve army, on the one hand stifles all resistance on the part of the workers[Pg 106] in active employment, keeping their wages at a level which will purchase the barest necessaries, and on the other hand permits to capitalist industry the sudden expansions in times of prosperity which to the capitalist are so desirable and so profitable.

Now, while it's true that the growth of accumulation tends to lead to an increase in wage payments, the capitalist can still prevent this undesirable outcome by investing the growing accumulation in technical capital, which naturally does not affect wages. However, the capitalist can do even more than that. They can convert part of the capital that has been used for paying wages into technical capital, thereby putting some workers out of jobs or creating an industrial reserve army. This reserve army, on one hand, suppresses any resistance from the workers currently employed, keeping their wages at a level that covers only the bare necessities, and on the other hand, allows capitalist industry to rapidly expand during prosperous times, which is extremely desirable and profitable for the capitalist.[Pg 106]

Thus Marx's qualitative investigation is succeeded by a quantitative investigation, so that we learn, not only what surplus value is, but that it is equal to all the excess over and above the more or less limited subsistence of the worker, and that the worker is not merely defrauded of part of the value resulting from his labour, but is reduced to a wretched pittance, happy if he can secure this, and if he be not condemned by the hopeless entanglements of capitalist relationships to submergence in the backwater of the most terrible poverty. The result is that to the favoured recipients of surplus value there is subject a brutalised crowd reduced to a narrow wage, while at a yet lower level there struggles in the morass the [Pg 107]amorphous mass of those who are condemned to labour without end.

Thus Marx's qualitative investigation is followed by a quantitative analysis, so that we learn not only what surplus value is, but that it equals all the excess beyond the worker's limited means of survival. The worker is not only cheated out of part of the value created by their labor, but is also left with a miserable income, fortunate if they can obtain this, and if they are not trapped by the hopeless entanglements of capitalist relationships, sinking into the depths of severe poverty. As a result, a brutalized crowd is subjected to a low wage for the benefit of those who profit from surplus value, while at an even lower level, the shapeless mass of those condemned to endless labor struggles in the mire.

We thus realise, adds Marx, how profit is born of capital and is in its turn transformed into capital. But none of the considerations hitherto adduced suffice to make it clear what was the origin of primitive capital, that which first of all gave birth to profit, and consequently cannot be the product of profit. The celebrated section on the secret of primitive accumulation was intended to solve this problem. Classical political economy, said Marx, regarded the formation of primitive capital as an episode which occurred during the first days of creation. In times long gone by, there were two sorts of people; one, the diligent, intelligent, and above all frugal élite; the other, lazy rascals, spending their substance, and more, in riotous living. Thus it came to pass before long that the former became impoverished whilst the latter grew wealthy, and the wealthy earned the gratitude of the poor by[Pg 108] hiring these to work for them in return for a paltry wage. The theological legend of original sin tells us how man came to be condemned to eat his bread in the sweat of his brow; but the economic history of original sin reveals to us that there are people to whom this is by no means essential. We learn that one section of humanity has succeeded in eluding the divine judgment and in procuring for itself bread and cakes by the sweat of others.

We therefore understand, Marx adds, how profit is generated from capital and, in turn, transforms back into capital. However, none of the points made so far clearly explains the origin of primitive capital, which initially created profit and, therefore, cannot be the result of profit. The famous section on the secret of primitive accumulation aimed to address this issue. Classical political economy, Marx stated, viewed the formation of primitive capital as an event that happened in the early days of creation. A long time ago, there were two kinds of people; one group, the hardworking, smart, and especially frugal elite, and the other, lazy individuals, wasting their resources on extravagant living. Soon enough, the former found themselves impoverished while the latter became wealthy, and the wealthy earned the gratitude of the poor by[Pg 108] hiring them to work for meager wages. The theological story of original sin tells us how humans were condemned to earn their bread through hard work; however, the economic history of original sin reveals that some people find that this is not necessary. We learn that one part of humanity has managed to escape divine judgment and obtain bread and cakes through the efforts of others.

Unfortunately, continues Marx, a conscientious questioning of history discloses that primitive capital originated in very various ways, of a character anything but idyllic. Until the close of the fifteenth century there existed in England a race of peasant proprietors, nominally subject to the jurisdiction of the great lords of the soil. But the increasing demand for wool which resulted from the expansion of the Flemish wool industry, and the increasing demand for flesh meat consequent upon the growth of population, induced the great [Pg 109]landowners to destroy an agrarian system by which their returns from rent were rendered practically nil. The free cultivators were brutally evicted from the fields which their ancestors had arduously tilled for centuries past, to be replaced by shepherds and flocks, the crowds of the expropriated hastening to the towns to offer the strength of their arms for hire.

Unfortunately, Marx continues, a thorough examination of history shows that primitive capital came about in various ways, and the situation was anything but idyllic. Until the end of the fifteenth century, there was a group of peasant landowners in England, who were nominally under the authority of the powerful landowners. However, the growing demand for wool due to the expansion of the Flemish wool industry, along with the rising need for meat brought on by population growth, led the large landowners to dismantle an agricultural system that had made their rental returns nearly worthless. The free farmers were violently forced off the fields that their ancestors had worked on for generations, replaced by shepherds and their sheep, while the displaced masses rushed to the towns to offer their labor for hire.

Here they happened upon a rout of usurers, traders, house-owners, enriched craftsmen, and lucky speculators; and here too were those who had expropriated them, the landowners who had heaped up savings by fair means or foul, but had hitherto been unable to turn their savings to account owing to the restrictions imposed by the corporative economy (guild system). These accepted as a gift from heaven the influx of the proletarian multitude, and were not slow in setting the newcomers to work on behalf of the growing manufactures. Modern capitalist industry thus originated in a terrible expropriation of the working [Pg 110]population which transformed the independent peasants into an impoverished and hunger-stricken mob. But historic nemesis awaits this society conceived in theft, and Marx predicts its disastrous end in the ominous words: "The knell of capitalist property will sound; the expropriators will be expropriated."

Here they came across a group of moneylenders, merchants, property owners, wealthy artisans, and fortunate investors; and here too were those who had taken their wealth, the landowners who had accumulated savings through both honest and dishonest means, but had so far been unable to make use of their savings because of the restrictions imposed by the guild system. They welcomed the arrival of the working-class masses like a gift from above and quickly set the newcomers to work for the expanding industries. Modern capitalist industry thus arose from a brutal displacement of the working population that turned independent farmers into a destitute and starving crowd. But historical justice awaits this society born of theft, and Marx predicts its disastrous end in the chilling words: "The knell of capitalist property will sound; the expropriators will be expropriated."

The fulfilment of the process will be effected by the forces inherent in the mechanism of the capitalist economy. The more extensive the development of that economy, the fiercer becomes the internecine struggle between the individual aggregations of capital, the more extensive become the accumulations of wealth in the hands of capitalists of the upper stratum, and the smaller becomes the number of these; correlatively there takes place an increase in the size of the working and poverty-stricken crowd, the more hopeless and more pitiful becomes its degradation, whilst simultaneously its cohesion grows more compact, for the workers are disciplined and organised by the very[Pg 111] process which associates labour in the factory and upon the land. At a given moment, when the number of mammoth capitalists has conspicuously diminished, and when the pullulating mass of proletarians has increased to an immeasurable degree and has been forced down into the most abject poverty, it will at length be easy to the dispossessed to expropriate the small group of usurpers.

The completion of the process will happen through the forces built into the capitalist economy’s workings. The more developed that economy becomes, the more intense the competition is between different groups of capitalists, leading to greater wealth accumulation among the upper-class capitalists, while their numbers decrease; at the same time, there’s a significant increase in the size of the working class and those living in poverty, deepening their suffering. Meanwhile, their unity strengthens because the workers are trained and organized by the same[Pg 111] process that brings together labor in factories and on farms. Eventually, when the number of large capitalists has dramatically decreased, and when the overwhelming majority of proletarians has grown to an unimaginable level and has been pushed into severe poverty, it will become easier for the dispossessed to take back what the small group of usurpers has.

Thus the expropriation of the masses by the few, which greeted the dawn of the contemporary economic order, will be counterposed by the expropriation of the restricted number of masters at the hands of the proletarian masses, and this will triumphantly herald a calmer and more resplendent sunrise.

Thus the takeover of the majority by a select few, which marked the beginning of the modern economic system, will be opposed by the taking back of power from the small number of elites by the working masses, and this will proudly signal a more peaceful and brighter dawn.


CHAPTER IV

A broad outline has now been given of the marvellous work which, whatever judgment we may feel it necessary to pass upon the value of the doctrines it enunciates, will remain for all time one of the loftiest summits ever climbed by human thought, one of the imperishable monuments of the creative powers of the human mind. Above all we are impressed and charmed by the magnificent quality of the exposition, in which but one defect can be pointed out, and this was probably imposed by the abnormal conditions under which the author wrote.

A broad outline has now been provided of the amazing work which, regardless of our personal judgments about the value of the ideas it presents, will always stand as one of the highest peaks ever reached by human thought, one of the lasting monuments to the creative abilities of the human mind. Most importantly, we are struck and captivated by the exceptional quality of the presentation, in which only one flaw can be noted, likely caused by the unusual circumstances under which the author wrote.

We allude to the last chapter, the one that crowns the story of the historic expropriation of the workers with the eloquent example of[Pg 113] the colonies. Logically this chapter should precede the penultimate chapter, wherein Marx, from his account of these terrible happenings, casts the horoscope of revolution. It is probable that the inversion was deliberate, for the prophetic call to the proletarian revolution would have been more likely to attract the attention of the censorship had it been placed at the end of the volume.

We refer to the final chapter, the one that concludes the story of the historic expropriation of the workers with the powerful example of[Pg 113] the colonies. Logically, this chapter should come before the second-to-last chapter, where Marx, drawing from his account of these horrific events, predicts the revolution. It’s likely that the reversal was intentional, as the call for a proletarian revolution would have more likely drawn the attention of censors if it had been placed at the end of the book.

Apart from this trifling matter, we cannot but admire the shapely pyramidal construction, the harmonious and flowing movement of the book, which, passing from the most subtle disquisitions upon the algebra of value, deals with the complexities of factory life and machine production, plunges into the inferno of workshops and mines and into the infamous stews of unspeakable poverty, to conclude with a description of the tragic expropriation of a suffering population. The work is a masterpiece wherein all is great, all alike incomparable and wonderful—the acuteness of the[Pg 114] analysis, the statuesque majesty of the whole, the style vibrant with sorrow or with indignation according as the author is sympathising with the woes of the poor or scourging the villainies of the mighty, the vast learning, and the torrential impetus of passion. There is a stupendous harmony of irreconcilables, so that, as in the mysterious creations of nature, we find an almost inconceivable association of real symmetry with apparent disorder; an association of minute attention to detail with monumental synthesis, an association of mathematics with history, an association of repose with movement; so that in all its fibres the book seems to be the offspring of an unfathomable and transcendental union between superhuman labour and superhuman pain.

Aside from this minor detail, we can't help but admire the elegant triangular structure and the smooth flow of the book, which moves from deep discussions on the value of algebra to the complexities of factory life and machine production, diving into the harsh realities of workshops and mines and the dreadful conditions of extreme poverty, ultimately concluding with a portrayal of the heart-wrenching dispossession of a suffering community. This work is a masterpiece where everything is remarkable, all equally unmatched and extraordinary—the sharpness of the[Pg 114] analysis, the grand majesty of the whole, the style filled with sorrow or indignation depending on whether the author is empathizing with the struggles of the poor or condemning the wrongs of the powerful, the vast knowledge, and the overwhelming drive of passion. There is an incredible harmony of opposites, so that, like the mysterious creations of nature, we see a nearly unbelievable blend of true symmetry with apparent chaos; a combination of meticulous attention to detail with grand synthesis, a mix of mathematics with history, a balance of tranquility with movement; so that in every fiber, the book seems to be the product of an unfathomable and transcendent connection between extraordinary labor and extraordinary suffering.

Nothing, therefore, is more natural or more readily explicable than the phenomenal success of Capital, a success which has rarely been paralleled in the history of intellectual productions. Translated into almost every [Pg 115]language (recently even into Chinese); eagerly read by men of learning no less than by statesmen, by reactionaries as well as by rebels; quoted in parliaments and in meetings of the plebs, from the pulpit and from the platform, in huts and in palaces—it speedily secured a world-wide reputation for its author, making him the idol of the most irreconcilable classes and of the most contrasted stocks. Whereas, in fact, the prophetic announcement of the glorious advent of collective property led to the assembling round Marx of all the common people of the west, who hailed him as avenger, as leader, and as seer of the onward march of the proletariat; in such countries as Russia, where capitalist development was as yet in its infancy, the bourgeois classes sang the praises of the book which announced the historic mission of capitalism, and thus it was that the idol of the western pétroleurs became in the far east of Europe the fetich of bankers and manufacturers.

Nothing is more natural or easier to explain than the incredible success of Capital, a success that has rarely been matched in the history of intellectual works. It has been translated into almost every [Pg 115]language (most recently even into Chinese); enthusiastically read by scholars as well as politicians, by conservatives and by revolutionaries; quoted in parliaments and at public gatherings, from the pulpit and from the platform, in huts and in palaces—it quickly earned its author worldwide fame, making him the figurehead for the most opposing classes and diverse backgrounds. While the prophetic announcement of the glorious arrival of collective ownership attracted all the common people of the West around Marx, who saw him as their avenger, leader, and visionary of the proletariat's progress; in countries like Russia, where capitalist development was still just beginning, the bourgeois classes praised the book that proclaimed capitalism's historic mission. Thus, the idol of Western capitalists became in Eastern Europe the icon for bankers and manufacturers.

After the first shock of surprise, however, readers turned to the dispassionate analysis of the individual doctrines advocated in the work, and were not slow to bring to light certain gaps and sophisms. To say truth, no sovereign importance can be attributed to any of these criticisms, nor is it necessary to make much of the numerous attacks upon the statistical demonstrations of Capital.

After the initial shock of surprise, readers began to analyze the individual arguments presented in the work, quickly pointing out some flaws and fallacies. Honestly, none of these criticisms hold much significance, and it isn't essential to dwell on the many criticisms directed at the statistical evidence in Capital.

It is undeniable that Marx's thesis of the progressive concentration of wealth into the hands of an ever-diminishing number of owners, and of the correlatively progressive impoverishment of the common people, has not been confirmed. It has indeed been confuted by the most authoritative statistics collected since the publication of the book, for these show that the greater recipients of income increase more than proportionally to the medium and lesser recipients, whereas the number of taxpayers in the lowest grades diminishes, with a proportionate increase in the number[Pg 117] of those at a slightly higher level. Further, as far as this last fact is concerned, there can be no doubt that wages have increased of late, so that they not merely rise above the miserable level of bare subsistence specified by Lassalle, but also rise above the level (which is still miserable, though a trifle higher) expressed in the calculations of Marx.

It’s clear that Marx's idea about the increasing concentration of wealth among a shrinking group of owners, along with the corresponding worsening situation of the common people, has not been proven. In fact, it has been challenged by the most reliable statistics gathered since the publication of the book, which show that the wealthiest earners are increasing their income more significantly than those with medium or lower incomes. Meanwhile, the number of taxpayers in the lowest income brackets is decreasing, with a proportional rise in those at a slightly higher level. Furthermore, regarding this last point, there’s no doubt that wages have recently gone up, meaning they not only exceed the bare minimum required for survival mentioned by Lassalle but also go beyond the still low level outlined in Marx's calculations.

It is, however, needful to add that the Marxist thesis merely points to a general tendency, and does not imply a denial that more or less considerable fluctuations may occur at particular periods. Moreover, the concentration of wealth does not find expression solely in the diminution of the numerical proportion between the greater and the lesser recipients of income, but in addition in a diminution of the ratio between the taxpayers and the population and in an increase in the contrast between the wealth of the recipients of income in various grades. Further, the most [Pg 118]authoritative statistics demonstrate a growing diminution in the ratio between the owners and the general population. Again, no one can deny that the contrast between high grade and low grade incomes has of late exhibited an enormous increase; that banking concentration and the sway of the banks over industry (a source of increasing disparity in fortunes) has attained in recent years an intensity which even Marx could not have foreseen; and that, subsequently to the publication of Capital and to the death of its author, the social fauna has been enriched by an economic animal of a species previously unknown, the multimillionaire, whose existence undeniably reveals an unprecedented advance in capitalist concentration.

It’s important to note that the Marxist thesis only highlights a general trend and doesn’t exclude the possibility of significant fluctuations at certain times. Additionally, the concentration of wealth is not only shown by the decrease in the number of people earning high vs. low incomes, but also by a drop in the ratio of taxpayers to the overall population and a growing gap between the wealth of different income brackets. Furthermore, the most [Pg 118]reliable statistics show a decline in the ratio of wealth owners to the general population. Additionally, no one can deny that the gap between high and low incomes has significantly widened in recent times; the concentration of banks and their control over industries (which contributes to growing disparities in wealth) has reached levels in recent years that even Marx could not have predicted. Furthermore, since the publication of Capital and the death of its author, we’ve seen the emergence of a new type of economic player—the multimillionaire—whose existence clearly illustrates an unprecedented level of capitalist concentration.

Nay more, after Marx's death, agrarian and industrial concentration attained preposterous proportions, such as he had never ventured to predict. In the American Union, a single landed estate will embrace territories equal to[Pg 119] entire provinces, while industrial capital becomes amassed by milliards in the hands of a few despotic trusts, so that two-thirds of the entire working population are employed by one-twentieth of all the separate enterprises in the country. These statements concern the apex of the social pyramid; but even at the base of that structure the phenomena are far from invalidating the Marxist conception to the extent which many contend. Correlatively with the undeniable rise in wages (which, moreover, has been arrested of late, and has been replaced by a definite movement of retrogression), there has occurred an enormously greater increase in income, and therefore a deterioration in the relative condition of the workers. There has further been manifest an increasing instability of employment, so that unemployment has become more widespread and more frequent, exposing the working classes to impoverishment and incurable degradation.

After Marx's death, both agrarian and industrial concentration reached levels that he never imagined. In the United States, a single estate can cover areas equal to[Pg 119] whole provinces, while industrial capital is accumulating in the hands of a few powerful trusts, meaning that two-thirds of the entire workforce is employed by just one-twentieth of all the businesses in the country. These observations focus on the top of the social hierarchy; however, even at the bottom, the situation doesn't undermine the Marxist view as much as many argue. Along with the undeniable rise in wages (which has recently stalled and turned into a definite decline), there has been a much larger increase in income, resulting in a worse relative situation for workers. Additionally, there has been a noticeable rise in job instability, making unemployment more common and frequent, which exposes the working class to poverty and irreversible degradation.

Marx's other theses, however, are open to more serious objection. Retracing the thread of his demonstrations with special attention to his study of primitive accumulation, no one can deny the absolute authenticity of the facts he narrated. Nor can Marx be blamed for having restricted his historic demonstration to England; though in actual fact the expropriation of the cultivators has been carried out everywhere, openly or tacitly, and everywhere this expropriation has been an initial stage in the foundation of capitalist property. Even Russia, who flattered herself upon her independence of the universal law and upon escaping the fated expropriation of her peasants, Russia, whom Marx himself, as if in a sudden fit of mental aberration, was on the point of excluding from the sphere of his generalisations, has to submit to the invariable rule, and to witness the transformation of her independent peasant proprietors into proletarians.

Marx's other theses, however, face more significant objections. If we trace the thread of his arguments with particular focus on his study of primitive accumulation, no one can deny the complete authenticity of the facts he presented. Marx also can't be criticized for limiting his historical analysis to England; in reality, the expropriation of farmers has happened everywhere, either openly or quietly, and this expropriation has always been a starting point for the establishment of capitalist property. Even Russia, which prided itself on being independent from universal laws and thought it could avoid the inevitable expropriation of its peasants, must ultimately follow this consistent trend and watch as its independent peasant landowners become part of the working class.

The constitutional defect of this portion of Marx's book is of a very different character. Although he tells the story of the expropriation of the cultivators, he fails to explain why such expropriation must always take place, he fails to bring this great historical event beneath the sway of a universal economic theory. Now, putting aside the incongruity that a book essentially founded upon logical demonstration should all at once break off that demonstration to turn to a historical disquisition and a simple record of facts, no one has any right to construct a theoretical generalisation upon the bare narration of hard facts without referring these to the general psychological and logical causes which have produced them. It cannot be denied that in this respect Marx's demonstration presents a defect which it is impossible to make good.

The fundamental flaw in this part of Marx's book is quite different. Even though he recounts the story of the dispossession of farmers, he doesn’t explain why this dispossession always happens; he doesn’t connect this significant historical event to a broader economic theory. Setting aside the inconsistency of a book that is primarily based on logical reasoning suddenly shifting to a historical analysis and a straightforward account of events, no one has the right to form a theoretical generalization based solely on a plain recounting of facts without linking them to the overarching psychological and logical reasons that led to them. It can’t be denied that in this regard, Marx's argument has a flaw that can't be corrected.

Yet more serious criticism may be directed against the theory of the industrial reserve army, the theory wherein Marx attempts to[Pg 122] sum up the law of population of the capitalist era. For the theory is wholly based upon the premise that the conversion of wage capital into technical capital is competent to bring about the permanent unemployment of labour, or definitively to reduce the demand for labour. Now this premise will not hold, for technical capital, by promptly increasing the profit of capital, and by lowering the price of the product in the long run, provides for the capitalist, first of all, and subsequently for the consumer, the possibility of fresh savings, and these in the end create a further demand for labour, so that sooner or later there will be a call upon the active services of the workers who are temporarily unemployed. Vain, therefore, is any attempt to make technical capital responsible for the relative excess of population, which technical capital cannot possibly produce, for this phenomenon must be referred to the presence and to the activity of a very different variety of capital, and one[Pg 123] not considered by Marx, namely unproductive capital.

Yet more serious criticism can be aimed at the theory of the industrial reserve army, which is where Marx tries to[Pg 122] summarize the law of population during the capitalist era. The theory entirely relies on the idea that changing wage capital into technical capital can lead to permanent unemployment or a significant drop in the demand for labor. This assumption is flawed because technical capital, by quickly increasing profits and lowering product prices in the long run, allows capitalists, and eventually consumers, to save more. These savings eventually create a higher demand for labor, meaning that eventually, there will be a need for the workers who are temporarily unemployed. Therefore, it is futile to blame technical capital for the relative surplus of population, which technical capital cannot create. This issue should be attributed to a very different type of capital that Marx did not address, namely unproductive capital.[Pg 123]

But these criticisms, which after all touch no more than points of detail, are mere trifles in comparison with the incurable contradictions in which the author's fundamental theory is involved. In fact, by a vigorous deduction from his premise that the value of commodities is measured by the mass of labour incorporated in them, Marx arrives at the fundamental and logical distinction between constant capital and variable capital. If, however, the value of products be exclusively determined by the mass of labour incorporated in them, it is evident that the capital invested in machinery or in raw material can only transmit to the product a value exactly equal to the quantity of labour contained therein, without adding any surplus, and that it is therefore constant capital; whereas wage capital transmits to the product value equal to all the quantity of labour which it maintains and[Pg 124] sets in motion, a quantity which, as we know, exceeds the quantity of labour contained in the capital itself. In other words, wage capital, besides reproducing its own value, furnishes a supplement or a surplus value, and is therefore variable capital. Consequently surplus value arises exclusively from variable capital, and is therefore precisely proportional to the quantity of this capital.

But these critiques, which really only address specific details, are just minor issues compared to the serious contradictions in the author's main theory. In fact, by logically building on his idea that the value of commodities is based on the amount of labor put into them, Marx establishes the key distinction between constant capital and variable capital. However, if the value of products is only determined by the amount of labor in them, it’s clear that the capital used for machinery or raw materials can only pass on a value equal to the amount of labor present, without adding any extra value, which makes it constant capital. On the other hand, wage capital transfers value to the product equal to all the labor it supports and uses, a quantity that, as we know, is greater than the amount of labor contained in the capital itself. In other words, wage capital not only recoups its own value but also provides an additional or surplus value, making it variable capital. Therefore, surplus value comes solely from variable capital and is directly proportional to the amount of this capital.

It further ensues that of two undertakings employing equal amounts of aggregate capital, the one which employs a larger proportion of constant capital ought to furnish a profit and a rate of profit lower than that furnished by the other. But free competition among the capitalists enforces an equal rate of profit upon the capitals invested in the various undertakings, and leads to the immediate abandonment of undertakings requiring a greater proportion of constant capital, and to the correlative expansion of the others. There consequently results an increase in the value of the products[Pg 125] of the former undertakings, and a diminution in the value of the products of the latter. This process continues until the value of the respective products furnishes an equal rate of profit to the capitals respectively employed in producing them. Value, therefore, though in the first instance it is equivalent to the labour employed in producing the products, necessarily diverges from that standard in the end, and has then an utterly different measure. Thus the theory we are discussing is peremptorily refuted, or is reduced to absurdity.

It follows that between two businesses using the same total capital, the one that uses a larger share of fixed capital should yield a profit and a profit rate lower than the other. However, free competition among capitalists enforces a uniform profit rate on the investments across different businesses, leading to the immediate closure of those that require more fixed capital and the corresponding growth of the others. As a result, the value of the products[Pg 125] from the former businesses increases, while the value of the products from the latter decreases. This cycle continues until the value of the respective products provides an equal profit rate for the capitals invested in their production. Therefore, while value initially corresponds to the labor used to create the products, it inevitably strays from that standard over time and ends up measured in a completely different way. Thus, the theory we’re examining is decisively disproven or reduced to absurdity.

From the outset Marx is distinctly aware of the existence of this striking contradiction, which emerges in so formidable a manner in the first stage of his investigation; he frankly recognises it, but postpones its solution to the later volumes of his treatise. On the very morrow, indeed, of the publication of the first volume, he ardently set to work once more, and sketched to his friend, in monumental pages, the design of the complete book. Just as St.[Pg 126] Augustine was grieved that the duties of his episcopate deprived him of the hours which he would have preferred to devote to the writing of a volume to be the crown of his City of God, so Marx was harassed by the thought of the time which the work of party organisation filched from his scientific labours, and it was solely that he might escape from the absorbing engagements involved in the former task that in the Hague congress of 1872 he proposed the transfer of the International to New York.

From the very beginning, Marx is clearly aware of this striking contradiction that appears so prominently in the first stage of his investigation. He acknowledges it openly but puts off resolving it until later volumes of his work. In fact, the day after the first volume was published, he passionately dove back in and outlined the complete book for his friend in extensive pages. Just as St. Augustine lamented that the responsibilities of his episcopate took away time he would have preferred to spend writing a volume that would be the pinnacle of his City of God, Marx was troubled by how much time the work of party organization stole from his scientific endeavors. It was precisely to escape from the demanding commitments of the former task that he proposed moving the International to New York at the Hague congress in 1872.

But now we unexpectedly reach a "dead point" in the biography of our thinker, for his mental life, otherwise so normal and so brilliant, here suddenly becomes obscured, and is tinged with mystery and enigma. For, on the one hand, Marx clearly affirmed, and showed by his actions, that he definitely wished to devote himself to the completion of his treatise, whereas, on the other hand, it is undeniable that after the publication of the first volume of Capital, he never wrote another line of the[Pg 127] book, and that all the posthumous additions to this volume were composed prior to 1867. I do not mean to imply that during subsequent years he gave himself up to inertia or repose, for it was during this period that he wrote all the economic section in Engels' booklet against Dühring; he learned Russian; he read the agricultural statistics of numerous countries and the reports on poverty in Ireland; he studied the matriarchal system; carried on ingenious discussions with Engels concerning Carey's theory of rent and Bastiat's theory of the cost of reproduction; threw light on the influence of fluctuations in the value of money upon the rate of profit; sketched a mathematical theory of commercial cycles—in a word, his thought-process remained so active that when a certain publisher asked for the right to issue his complete works, he replied, "My works, those which represent my present thought, are not yet written." But the essential work of his life, the work which had been[Pg 128] so much cherished and which he again and again turned over in his thoughts, seems, as far as palpable traces are concerned, to have been entirely dismissed from his mind. We thus look on, marvelling and grieved, at the sight of the enfeebled hero withdrawing from the field, what time his banner, whose staff is not yet firmly implanted in the ground, is left as a target for the easy assaults of his emboldened adversaries.

But now we unexpectedly hit a "dead point" in the biography of our thinker, because his mental life, usually so normal and so brilliant, suddenly becomes obscure and filled with mystery. On one hand, Marx clearly stated and demonstrated through his actions that he wanted to finish his treatise. On the other hand, it’s undeniable that after the first volume of Capital was published, he never wrote another line of the[Pg 127] book, and all the additions made after his death were written before 1867. I don’t mean to suggest that during the years that followed he fell into inactivity or relaxation, because it was during this time that he wrote the entire economic section of Engels' pamphlet against Dühring; he learned Russian; he read agricultural statistics from many countries and reports on poverty in Ireland; he studied the matriarchal system; engaged in thoughtful discussions with Engels about Carey's rent theory and Bastiat's reproduction cost theory; clarified how fluctuations in the value of money affect profit rates; and outlined a mathematical theory of commercial cycles—in short, his thought process remained so active that when a publisher asked for the rights to publish his complete works, he replied, "My works, those that reflect my current thoughts, haven't been written yet." However, the main work of his life, the one that he had so deeply cherished and revisited in his thoughts, seems to have completely slipped his mind, at least in terms of any tangible evidence. We watch in marvel and sadness as the weakened hero withdraws from the field, leaving his banner, which isn’t yet firmly planted in the ground, as a target for the bold attacks of his emboldened opponents.

There certainly contributed to this intellectual shipwreck the illnesses and the misfortunes from which Marx suffered during the later years of his life. His health had been gravely undermined by overwork during the composition of the first volume of Capital and during the task of proletarian organisation; trouble from boils alternated with bronchitis, liver disorder, headache, and lumbago. In vain did he seek health in gentler climes, at Ramsgate, Ventnor, Neuenahr, Carlsbad, Algiers, Monte Carlo, Vevey, and other [Pg 129]fashionable health resorts. All attempts at cure proving inefficacious, he had at length to settle down once more in London.

There definitely contributed to this intellectual disaster the illnesses and misfortunes that Marx experienced in his later years. His health had been seriously damaged by working too much while writing the first volume of Capital and during the efforts to organize the proletariat; he dealt with recurring boils, bronchitis, liver issues, headaches, and back pain. He unsuccessfully sought recovery in milder places like Ramsgate, Ventnor, Neuenahr, Carlsbad, Algiers, Monte Carlo, Vevey, and other [Pg 129] popular health resorts. After all his attempts at healing failed, he ultimately had to settle back in London.

In 1881 occurred the death of his wife; while the death of his beautiful daughter Jenny, Longuet's wife, in January, 1883, was, if possible, a yet more cruel blow. Marx never recovered from this last shock; henceforward he was a broken man, the mere shadow of his former self; he passed his time contemplating the portraits of his two dear ones which Engels was to bury with him, and he no longer took any interest in the world around him or in the social tumult of which he was the inspirer and the originator. He died suddenly at two in the afternoon of March 14, 1883, while seated in his study chair. The titanic brain, which had given a new world to humanity, which had broken once for all the spiritual and material bondage of mankind, had ceased to live and to vibrate.

In 1881, his wife died; then, in January 1883, the death of his beautiful daughter Jenny, Longuet's wife, hit him even harder. Marx never fully recovered from this last shock; from then on, he was a broken man, just a shadow of his former self. He spent his time looking at the portraits of his two beloved ones, which Engels would bury with him, and he lost interest in the world around him and in the social upheaval he had inspired. He died suddenly at 2 p.m. on March 14, 1883, while sitting in his study chair. The brilliant mind that had given humanity a new world and had forever shattered mankind's spiritual and material chains had stopped living and resonating.

Most distressing of all, he had taken with him to the grave the solution of the formidable enigma which everyone, the vulgar and the thinkers alike, had expected his genius to solve, and which no one else could unravel. It is true that shortly before his death he showed his friend the bulky manuscripts dictated in earlier days relating to the Criticism of Political Economy, suggesting that something might be made of this collection. It is also true that Engels, faithful executor of his divinity's wishes, devoted himself with splendid zeal to the publication of the manuscripts. But alas what delusion was in store for the admirers of the master! What a Russian campaign of disaster organised by enthusiastic lieutenants to the hurt of this Napoleon of thought!

Most distressing of all, he took with him to the grave the answer to the daunting riddle that everyone, both the ordinary folks and the intellectuals, had hoped his genius would solve, and which no one else could crack. It's true that shortly before his death, he showed his friend the hefty manuscripts he had dictated back in the day related to the Criticism of Political Economy, hinting that something could come from this collection. It’s also true that Engels, dedicated executor of his mentor's wishes, put in admirable effort to publish the manuscripts. But alas, what a disappointment awaited the admirers of the master! What a catastrophic campaign, like a failed Russian expedition, led by enthusiastic followers that harmed this Napoleon of thought!

In 1885, two years after the death of Marx, there was published under Engels' supervision a so-called second volume of Capital. But the careless and pedestrian editorship, the long[Pg 131] theoretical disquisitions making no appeal to facts for their justification, disquisitions in which the argumentative thread is continually broken, suffice to show that what we have before us is not a book, hardly even a sketch for a book, but a series of casual writings composed for the purposes of study and for personal illumination. Moreover, the work is wholly devoted to uninspiring monetary discussions upon the circulation of capital, to dissertations concerning fixed and circulating capital, the formation of metallic reserves, the circulation of commodity-capital, etc.

In 1885, two years after Marx died, a so-called second volume of Capital was published under Engels' supervision. However, the sloppy and unremarkable editing, along with long theoretical discussions that don’t rely on facts for support and have a broken argumentative thread, show that what we're looking at isn't really a book, or even a good outline for one, but rather a collection of random writings meant for study and personal insight. Additionally, the work focuses entirely on dull monetary discussions about the flow of capital, essays on fixed and circulating capital, the creation of metallic reserves, the circulation of commodity-capital, and so on.

Noteworthy, in any case, are the investigations which aim at throwing light on the process in virtue of which there is effected the formation of metallic reserves which remain out of circulation for a longer or shorter period. If, says Marx, a certain commodity requires for its production six months of labour, and cannot be sold until two months after its production has been completed, the capitalist,[Pg 132] if he is to continue the work of production during the period in which the commodity remains unsold, has need of additional capital which he could dispense with if the sale could be effected immediately after production. But when, at the close of the circulation period, the capitalist resumes possession of the capital first utilised and realises it in money, he has no immediate need of all this capital, but only of the quantity necessary to make good the additional capital which he has invested, that is to say, a quantity of capital equal to the difference between the primary capital and the supplementary capital; consequently the excess remains at liberty, and goes to constitute and to increase monetary reserves. These reserves are formed in addition, and by an analogous process, on account of the wear of machinery; for the portions of value transmitted by the machines to the product and correlative to the wear of these machines are pent up until the day of the complete destruction of the[Pg 133] machines or of their necessary replacement. Thus the difference between the period of production and the period of exchange of the commodities, and the difference between the period of economic redintegration and the period of technical redintegration of the productive machinery, give rise to the formation of monetary or capitalistic reserves, which become in their turn the source of intricate developments and interesting complications.

Notably, there are investigations that seek to clarify how metallic reserves are formed and kept out of circulation for varying lengths of time. Marx explains that if a specific commodity requires six months of labor to produce and cannot be sold until two months after production is finished, the capitalist,[Pg 132] in order to continue production during the time the commodity remains unsold, needs additional capital that would not be necessary if the sale could happen immediately after production. However, when the circulation period ends and the capitalist regains the capital initially used and converts it into money, they do not need all this capital right away, but only the amount necessary to replace the additional capital they have invested. This means they only need a sum equal to the difference between the original capital and the extra capital; as a result, the surplus remains free and contributes to forming and increasing monetary reserves. These reserves are also created through a similar process due to machinery wear; the value transferred from the machines to the product that corresponds to their wear accumulates until the machines are completely destroyed or need to be replaced. Therefore, the gap between the production period and the exchange period of the commodities, along with the difference between the economic reintegration period and the technical reintegration period of the productive machinery, leads to the establishment of monetary or capitalistic reserves, which in turn become the source of complex developments and intriguing complications.

The book likewise contains a masterly, though wordy and disconnected, account of the circulation of capital. But absolutely nowhere does it touch on or even hint at the theoretical enigma left unsolved in the first volume. Solely in Engels' preface do we find an announcement that the definitive solution will be furnished in a subsequent volume, and a suggestion that in the interim economists engage in a sort of academic debate, and bring forward their respective solutions. There actually took part in this strange competition,[Pg 134] with varying success, Conrad Schmidt, Landé, Lexis, Skworzoff, Stiebeling, Julius Wolf, Fireman, Lafargue, Soldi, Coletti, Graziadei, and myself. At length, however, in 1894, appeared the third volume, which was to reveal to an impatient world the desired solution.

The book also features an impressive, though lengthy and disjointed, discussion of how capital circulates. However, it completely fails to address or even hint at the theoretical mystery that was left unresolved in the first volume. The only indication we get of a final answer is in Engels' preface, where he mentions that the complete explanation will be provided in a later volume and suggests that in the meantime, economists should take part in some sort of academic debate and propose their own solutions. In this unusual competition,[Pg 134] various people participated with mixed results, including Conrad Schmidt, Landé, Lexis, Skworzoff, Stiebeling, Julius Wolf, Fireman, Lafargue, Soldi, Coletti, Graziadei, and myself. Finally, in 1894, the third volume was published, aiming to provide the long-awaited answer to the world.

The solution reduces itself to this. It is true, says Marx, that the value commensurate to labour ends by assigning to the capitals respectively employed as constant and as variable, different rates of profit, and that this is radically incompatible with competition. But it is likewise true that products are not actually sold for their value, but for their price of production, which is equal to the capital consumed plus profit at the ordinary rate on the total capital employed. Certainly if we consider the mass of products sold, we find that their total price is precisely equal to their total value. But this integral value is not distributed among the various products in proportion to the quantity of labour incorporated in them,[Pg 135] but in a lesser or greater proportion, according as the products themselves contain a greater or less proportion of the mean between the constant capital and the total capital; that is to say, the products containing a proportion of constant capital superior to the mean are sold at a price above their value in order to eliminate the deficiency of profit due to the preponderance of the capital which does not produce surplus value; whereas the products containing a proportion of constant capital inferior to the mean are sold at a price less than their value so as to eliminate the excess of profit due to the preponderance of the capital that produces surplus value; whilst only the products containing the mean proportion of constant capital and total capital are sold at a price precisely identical with their value.

The solution boils down to this. Marx states that the value associated with labor results in different profit rates for the capital used as constant and variable, which fundamentally conflicts with competition. However, it’s also true that products aren’t sold for their value, but for their production price, which is the capital spent plus the average profit on the total capital used. When we look at the total products sold, we see that their overall price matches their total value. But this overall value isn’t distributed among the different products based on the amount of labor in them,[Pg 135] but rather in a varying proportion, depending on how much they contain of the average between constant capital and total capital. This means that products with a higher proportion of constant capital than the average are sold for a price above their value to compensate for the lower profit caused by the dominance of capital that doesn’t generate surplus value; while products with a lower proportion of constant capital than the average are sold for a price below their value to counteract the excess profit from the capital that does create surplus value; only products with the average proportion of constant and total capital are sold for a price exactly equal to their value.

But it soon becomes apparent that this so-called solution is little more than a play upon words, or, better expressed, little more than a solemn mystification. For when economists[Pg 136] endeavour to throw light upon the laws of value, they naturally consider the value at which the commodities are actually sold, and not a fantastical or transcendental value, not a value which neither possesses nor can possess any concrete relationship to facts. It may well be that value as determined by abstract economic theory will not always correspond precisely with value as a concrete fact, for the complexities and the manifold vicissitudes of real life impose obstacles; it may well be, indeed, that to the rigidity of normal value, constituting the type of the relationship of exchange, we ought to counterpose the comparatively transient fluctuations of current value.

But it quickly becomes clear that this so-called solution is really just a word game, or better put, a serious confusion. When economists[Pg 136] try to explain the laws of value, they obviously look at the prices at which commodities are actually sold, rather than some imaginary or abstract value that has no real connection to facts. It's possible that the value defined by theoretical economics won't always match up perfectly with value as a real fact, since the complexities and various ups and downs of real life create challenges; it might even be that we should contrast the rigidity of normal value, which represents the typical exchange relationship, with the relatively temporary fluctuations of current value.

But it must be understood that no logical fact should stand in the way of the realisation of normal value, for this, conversely, ought to be derived by logical necessity from fundamental economic premises. Of a value, indeed, which not only is not realised, but is not logically capable of realisation, the economist neither[Pg 137] can nor ought to take any account; he should show in what respect, instead of being the expression of what value is, it is the expression of what value is not and cannot be; he should point out the negation of every correct and positive theory of value. Now this value commensurate to labour, value as defined by Marx's theory, not merely has its realisation restricted or modified by the vicissitudes of reality, but further, as Marx himself is constrained to recognise, is not logically capable of realisation, seeing that it would give rise to results incompatible with the most elementary advantage of those who effect the exchange of commodities; consequently, it is not merely an abstraction remote from reality, but is incompatible with reality; not only is it an impossibility in the realm of fact, but further and above all it is a logical impossibility.

But it should be understood that no logical fact should prevent the realization of normal value, which, in turn, should logically arise from fundamental economic principles. An economist cannot and should not consider a value that not only is not realized but also cannot logically be realized; they should demonstrate how it fails to represent what value is and instead reflects what value is not and cannot be. They should highlight the negation of every accurate and positive theory of value. The value tied to labor, as defined by Marx's theory, is not only limited or altered by real-world circumstances but, as Marx himself has to acknowledge, is not logically able to be realized, as it would lead to outcomes that are incompatible with the most basic interests of those exchanging commodities. Therefore, it is not just an abstraction far removed from reality, but it conflicts with reality; it is not only an impossibility in practical terms, but above all, it is a logical impossibility.

Thus, far from effecting the salvation of the threatened doctrine, this alleged solution administers a death-blow, and implies the [Pg 138]categorical negation of what it professes to support. For what meaning can there possibly be in this reduction of value to labour, the doctrine dogmatically affirmed in the first volume, to one who already knows that the author is himself calmly prepared to jettison it? Is there any reason for surprise at Marx's hesitation to publish this so-called defence; need we wonder that his hand trembled, that his spirit quailed, before the inexorable act of destruction?

Thus, instead of saving the threatened doctrine, this supposed solution delivers a fatal blow and suggests the [Pg 138]complete rejection of what it claims to uphold. What value can there possibly be in reducing value to labor, a doctrine firmly asserted in the first volume, when one already knows that the author is willing to discard it? Is it any wonder that Marx hesitated to publish this so-called defense? Should we be surprised that his hand shook and his spirit faltered before the inevitable act of destruction?

Despite all, however, genius will not be denied, and even this volume contains here and there masterly disquisitions, enriching the science of economics with new and fertile truths. It will be enough, in this connection, to refer to two theories. The first of these, the theory of the decline in the rate of profit, though not free from objection, is none the less inspired and profound. The second is the theory of absolute rent, a brilliant and acute deduction from the Marxist theory of value.[Pg 139] This theory, indeed, as we saw just now, leads to the conclusion that value commensurate to labour furnishes an extra profit to the capital which produces commodities requiring for their production an above-average proportion of variable capital. Now, where free competition exists, such extra profit cannot continue, and must necessarily be eliminated by a reduction in the price of the product to a point below its value. But when competition is not fully free, there is no reason why such extra profit should not be permanent. Now agrarian production requires an abnormally high proportion of variable capital, and consequently agricultural produce, when sold for its value, furnishes an extra profit. But since land is a monopolised element, this extra profit can be permanently assigned to the owners of the soil, because there is no effective competition to prevent their continuing to draw it. There thus comes into existence an absolute land rent, in opposition to or in addition to[Pg 140] the differential rent of Ricardo's theory. This absolute rent is not due to the varying cost of production in different areas; it is not the exclusive appanage of lands more favourably situated or of lands of better quality; it arises solely from the excess in the value of agrarian produce over its cost of production, and is a general attribute of land per se, in virtue of its quality as a monopolised element. Marx acutely studies the manifold varieties of this rent according as it is rendered in work, in produce, or in money; and with sound and far-reaching intuition he deduces from his theory explanations of the intricate agrarian relationships among the various peoples of the globe.

Despite everything, genius cannot be overlooked, and even this book includes remarkable insights that add valuable and new ideas to the field of economics. It's enough to mention two theories in this context. The first, the theory of the decline in the rate of profit, while not without its criticisms, is still deeply inspired and insightful. The second is the theory of absolute rent, which is a clever and sharp interpretation derived from the Marxist theory of value.[Pg 139] This theory, as we just discussed, leads to the understanding that labor commensurate value generates an extra profit for the capital that produces goods requiring a higher-than-average amount of variable capital. Where free competition exists, this extra profit can’t last and must be reduced by lowering the product's price below its value. However, when competition isn't fully free, there’s no reason why this extra profit shouldn’t last. Agricultural production needs a particularly high amount of variable capital, and thus agricultural products, when sold for their value, yield an extra profit. Since land is a monopolized resource, this extra profit can be consistently claimed by landowners, as there’s no effective competition preventing them from doing so. This creates an absolute land rent, in contrast to or in addition to[Pg 140] Ricardo’s differential rent theory. This absolute rent doesn’t arise from differing production costs in various regions; it's not solely reserved for better-positioned or higher-quality land; it stems purely from the value of agricultural products exceeding their production costs, and is a fundamental characteristic of land itself due to its monopolized nature. Marx thoughtfully examines the various forms of this rent as it appears in labor, products, or money, and with keen and far-reaching insight, he draws from his theory explanations for the complex agricultural relationships among different peoples around the world.

Nor is this the only gem with which the work is adorned. Very remarkable are the pages upon merchants' capital and moneylenders' capital, on their despotic predominance prior to the inauguration of the capitalist régime, and upon their inevitable [Pg 141]dissolution after the advent of that régime. The closing pages, however, seem to breathe a vague weariness, and we find hardly any trace of masterly theoretical discussion of the class struggle, of its origin, of the instruments through which it operates, although this discussion, according to the author's original plan, was to be the monumental crown of the titanic work.

Nor is this the only highlight of the work. The sections on merchants' capital and moneylenders' capital are especially noteworthy, detailing their oppressive dominance before the rise of capitalism and their inevitable decline after that system emerged. However, the final pages feel somewhat weary, and there's barely any substantial theoretical analysis of the class struggle, its origins, or the tools it uses, even though this analysis was meant to be the crowning achievement of the author's grand vision.

Thus, however fragmentarily, and thanks to the help of lieutenants and of disciples who were not always adequately instructed, the theoretical treatise, at once the pride and the torment of our prophet, at length arrived at completion. But the reader will not forget that to the positive treatment of his subject, Marx always counterposed a historico-critical investigation of the theories of his precursors, and in the more mature design of his work such an exposition was to follow upon the exposition of his own doctrines and to form their apt complement. It remained, therefore, to[Pg 142] bring to light this last part of his researches, a duty which was faithfully discharged (after the death of Engels) by Karl Kautsky, with the publication of the History of the Theory of Surplus Value, which appeared in four volumes during the years 1905 to 1910. Substantially, though publishers have preferred to treat it as a work apart, this book is nothing other than the concluding section of Capital, announced in the preface to the first volume, where the author tells of a sequel to be devoted to the history of this theory.

Thus, even though it was pieced together and with the help of assistants and followers who weren't always fully trained, the theoretical treatise, which was both the pride and the burden of our prophet, finally reached its completion. However, the reader should remember that Marx always paired his direct treatment of his subject with a historical and critical analysis of the theories of those who came before him. In the more developed plan for his work, such an analysis was meant to follow the explanation of his own ideas and serve as a fitting complement. Therefore, it remained to[Pg 142] uncover this final part of his research, a task that was carried out diligently (after Engels’ death) by Karl Kautsky, who published the History of the Theory of Surplus Value in four volumes between 1905 and 1910. Essentially, although publishers have chosen to present it as a separate work, this book is actually just the concluding section of Capital, which is mentioned in the preface to the first volume, where the author refers to a follow-up that would focus on the history of this theory.

In the posthumous work Marx traces the development of the theory of surplus value through its three essential stages, the prericardian, the Ricardian, and the postricardian. To the first of these phases belong the theories of the physiocratic school, whose essence Marx grasps with marvellous acuteness, maintaining that the theories in question were the doctrinal reflection of the interests of the rising capitalist class, constrained to pretend that its own[Pg 143] economic claims were the logical expression of the advantage of the landed and feudalist classes then politically dominant. Particularly noteworthy are the comments on the teaching of Adam Smith. The second volume contains a searching criticism of the Ricardian system, and above all of Ricardo's theories of value and of profit. In the third section Marx passes judgment on the theories of Ricardo's successors, Malthus, Senior, and John Stuart Mill, for these writers, says Marx, follow the setting sun of bourgeois economic science, follow that science to its now inevitable doom.

In this posthumous work, Marx outlines the development of the theory of surplus value through three key stages: the pre-Ricardian, the Ricardian, and the post-Ricardian. The first phase includes the theories of the physiocratic school, which Marx analyzes with remarkable insight. He argues that these theories reflected the interests of the emerging capitalist class, which had to pretend that its own economic claims were actually the logical expression of the benefits for the politically dominant landed and feudal classes. The comments on Adam Smith's teachings are particularly noteworthy. The second volume offers a deep critique of the Ricardian system, especially Ricardo's theories of value and profit. In the third section, Marx evaluates the theories of Ricardo's successors—Malthus, Senior, and John Stuart Mill—stating that these writers are merely following the declining path of bourgeois economic science, leading that science to its inevitable downfall.

It was a fixed idea with Marx that the theoretical analysis of capitalist relationships had secured its fullest and most adequate expression in the pages of Ricardo; he believed that Ricardo had supplied the ultimate synthesis possible on these lines; that any further progress of economic science in its bourgeois trappings had become impossible; that its decline amid contradictions and perversions was [Pg 144]inevitable; and that economics could only be renewed and reborn when the disintegrated vesture of bourgeois economic relationships had been completely thrown aside to give place to a definitive and superior social form. It is scarcely necessary to point to the sophisms and the arbitrary assumptions upon which this concept is based; but it must be admitted that the poverty, deficiency, and incurable vanity of current economic science increasingly tend to give the theory an awkward semblance of truth.

It was a fixed belief for Marx that the theoretical analysis of capitalist relationships was best expressed in the writings of Ricardo. He thought Ricardo had provided the ultimate synthesis on these topics, and that any further development of economic science within its bourgeois framework had become impossible. He believed that its decline amid contradictions and distortions was [Pg 144]inevitable, and that economics could only be refreshed and reborn once the fragmented appearance of bourgeois economic relationships was completely discarded to make way for a definitive and superior social form. It hardly needs to be pointed out how this idea rests on flawed reasoning and arbitrary assumptions; however, it's important to acknowledge that the poverty, inadequacy, and unfixable vanity of modern economic science increasingly give this theory an uncomfortable appearance of truth.


CHAPTER V

To-day, now that the fruits of Marx's meditations, be it only as the result of the work of collaborators, be it only with many gaps and imperfections, have all been given forth to the reading world, it is at length possible to take a general view, and to pass a dispassionate judgment upon the pre-eminent worth of his writings. The most austere criticism must bow reverently before such gigantic mental attainments as have few counterparts in the history of scientific thought, garnering from all branches of knowledge on behalf of the undying cause of mankind. The most inexorable criticism should recognise in Marx the supreme merit of having been the first to introduce the evolutionary concept into the [Pg 146]domain of sociology, the first to introduce it in the only form appropriate to social phenomena and social institutions; not as the unceasing and gradual upward-movement outlined by Spencer, but as the succession of agelong cycles rhythmically interrupted by revolutionary explosions, proceeding in accordance with the manner sketched by Lyell for geological evolution, and in our own time by de Vries for biological evolution.

Today, now that the results of Marx's thoughts, whether thanks to the work of collaborators or with many gaps and imperfections, have all been shared with the reading public, it is finally possible to take a broad view and make an objective judgment on the significant value of his writings. Even the harshest criticism must respect such incredible intellectual achievements, which are rare in the history of scientific thought, gathering insights from all fields of knowledge for the enduring cause of humanity. Even the strictest critics should acknowledge Marx's major contribution as the first to bring the concept of evolution into the [Pg 146] realm of sociology, introducing it in the only manner suitable for social phenomena and institutions; not as a constant and gradual upward movement as outlined by Spencer, but as a series of long cycles rhythmically interrupted by revolutionary bursts, following the pattern described by Lyell for geological evolution, and more recently by de Vries for biological evolution.

With the aid of this concept, strictly positive and scientific, Marx triumphantly overthrew, on the one hand classical economic science, taken prisoner by its own notion of a petrified society, and on the other the philosophy of law and idealist socialism which were convinced that it was possible to mould the world in accordance with the arbitrary conceptions of the thinker. Looked at in this light, the work of Marx presents a new instrument for the use of the philosophy of history and for the use of sociology; and it has contributed no[Pg 147] less powerfully to the advance of technological science, thanks to the writer's masterly investigation into the successive forms of the technical instrument of productive machinery. In this respect more than in any others Marx may be compared with Darwin, and may indeed be spoken of as the Darwin of technology: for no one has ever had a profounder knowledge than Marx of the structural development of the industrial mechanism, no one else has followed step by step the formation and upward elaboration of productive technique; just as Darwin, with invincible mental energy, traced the evolution of animal technique, the development of the functional apparatus of organised beings.

With this concept, which is purely positive and scientific, Marx successfully challenged classical economics, which was trapped by its own outdated ideas about a static society. He also questioned the philosophy of law and idealist socialism, which believed that people could shape the world based on personal beliefs. Viewed this way, Marx's work serves as a new tool for the philosophy of history and sociology. It has also significantly advanced technological science, thanks to his brilliant analysis of the evolving forms of productive machinery. In this regard, Marx can be compared to Darwin and might even be called the Darwin of technology because no one has understood the structural development of the industrial mechanism as deeply as Marx. No one has followed the progression and refinement of productive techniques as closely as he did, much like Darwin meticulously traced the evolution of animals and the development of the functional systems in living organisms.

This physiology of industry, which is now the least studied and least appreciated of Marx's scientific labours, nevertheless constitutes his most considerable and most enduring contribution to science. Noteworthy, in especial, and destined to form a permanent and [Pg 148]integral part of the economic science of the world, are Marx's analyses of money, credit, the circulation of capital, poverty, primitive accumulation, not to speak of the historico-critical investigations into the work of the British classical economists—for here Marx, without prejudice to the merits of those who have fought honourably in this difficult arena, will ever remain the most brilliant and most profound commentator. For these mighty and noble contributions, his name will be inscribed in imperishable letters in the history of creative thought.

This study of industry, which is currently the least explored and least valued of Marx's scientific work, is actually his most significant and lasting contribution to science. Particularly noteworthy and set to become a lasting and [Pg 148]integral part of global economic science are Marx's analyses of money, credit, the flow of capital, poverty, primitive accumulation, not to mention his historical-critical studies of the British classical economists—because in this field, despite the merits of those who have valiantly engaged in this challenging area, Marx will always be seen as the most brilliant and insightful commentator. For these powerful and noble contributions, his name will be etched in everlasting letters in the history of innovative thought.

But if his sociological, historical, and technological investigations, if his studies of money, the banking system, and industrial statistics, be so many intellectual jewels of which no praise can be excessive, it is none the less true that his fundamental economic theory is essentially vitiated and sophistical, and that he is himself responsible for reducing it to hopeless absurdity. We arrive, therefore, at this[Pg 149] remarkable result: that Marx, whose primary aim it was to be a theorist of political economy, and to deal only in subsidiary fashion with the philosophy of history and technology, secured a triumphant success in these subordinate fields; whereas in respect of the fundamental object of his thought, his work was a complete failure.

But while his sociological, historical, and technological investigations, along with his studies of money, the banking system, and industrial statistics, are impressive achievements deserving of high praise, it’s true that his core economic theory is fundamentally flawed and misleading, and he is to blame for making it completely absurd. Hence, we reach this[Pg 149]remarkable conclusion: Marx, whose main goal was to be a theorist of political economy and only address the philosophy of history and technology as a secondary concern, succeeded remarkably in those secondary areas; however, regarding the main focus of his thought, his work was a total failure.

Nor can we deny that the very design of Marx's work, however marvellous in the Michelangelesque grandeur of its ensemble, does not satisfy those who insist upon strictly scientific method, and that in this respect Marx stands far below the great masters of positive science. For, however admirable and however great this man who succeeded in subsuming an entire world within the limits of an extremely simple initial principle, and whose life was but the development of an equation which he had formulated at its outset, how far more straightforward and trustworthy, how far more scientific, was the[Pg 150] method of Darwin, who never formulated any apriorist principles, but, quite free from preconceptions, accepted phenomena in the order of progressive complexity in which life itself presented them. Darwin first studied the natural formation of organised beings, then devoted himself to an examination of the larger types, and was finally led to infer their development by evolutionary growth. This method, which follows nature and reflects it, seems far more worthy of respect, far more honest, far more strictly scientific, than the other method, which manipulates the truth, does violence to the truth, in order to accommodate it to hidden ends.

We can't ignore that the way Marx structured his work, impressive as it is in its grand scope, doesn't meet the standards of those who demand a strictly scientific approach. In this regard, Marx falls short compared to the great leaders of positive science. Even though this man was remarkable and managed to encompass an entire world through a very simple foundational principle, and his life was merely the unfolding of an equation he established early on, Darwin's method was much clearer, more reliable, and more scientific. Darwin didn’t set out with preconceived ideas; instead, he accepted phenomena as they arose in the order of increasing complexity that life itself presented. He began by studying how organized beings naturally formed, then examined the larger categories, and ultimately inferred their development through evolution. This approach, which aligns with nature and accurately reflects it, seems far more deserving of respect, far more honest, and far more scientifically sound than the method that distorts the truth to fit hidden agendas.

There is no reason, therefore, to be surprised that such a flood of criticism should have been directed against this colossus, or that on the morrow of the completion of Marx's work the skies of the two hemispheres should have rung with disorderly clamour proclaiming the crisis, nay the failure, of Marxism. But that[Pg 151] which is less easy to understand, that which discloses the utter immaturity of economic science as well as of contemporary socialism, is that criticism has not been directed against the truly vulnerable point of the system, but has been solely concerned in attacking its better defended and less fragile parts. In fact the scientific and socialist currents partially or wholly opposed to Marxism display a strange reverence for his theory of value, or do not venture to attack it, but concentrate their forces against the statistical and historical theories which are the deductions and complements of the Marxist theory of value.

There’s no reason to be surprised that such a wave of criticism has been aimed at this giant, or that after the completion of Marx's work, the skies of both hemispheres echoed with chaotic voices declaring the crisis, even the failure, of Marxism. However, what's harder to understand, revealing the complete immaturity of economic science as well as contemporary socialism, is that criticism hasn’t targeted the truly vulnerable aspects of the system. Instead, it has focused on attacking its better protected and less fragile components. In fact, the scientific and socialist movements that are partially or entirely opposed to Marxism show a strange respect for his theory of value, or they hesitate to criticize it, choosing instead to focus their attacks on the statistical and historical theories that are extensions and complements of the Marxist theory of value.

In this respect the critics of Marxism form two very distinct groups. The first of these, the reformist or revisionist school, has a high respect for the master's theory of value, and reiterates it as an indisputable truth; whereas reformists criticise the theory of increasing misery, the theory of the concentration of capital, and above all the catastrophic vision of the[Pg 152] proletarian revolution. The writers of this school affirm, and think that in so doing they are setting up an antithesis to Marxism, that to await the millennium of the social revolution is futile utopianism; they contend, that the progressive reduction in the number of the wealthy, paralleled by the ceaseless increase in the number of more and more impoverished proletarians, a development which according to Marx's vision was to provide the apparatus destined to destroy the contemporary economy, is negatived by an actual tendency towards a more democratic distribution of commodities; and they insist, therefore, that socialism should aim at securing the triumph of its cause by means that are less violent but far more efficacious, namely by social legislation or by reforms tending to reduce inequality.

In this regard, critics of Marxism can be divided into two very distinct groups. The first of these, the reformist or revisionist school, holds a high regard for the master's theory of value and repeats it as an undeniable truth; however, reformists criticize the theory of increasing misery, the theory of capital concentration, and especially the bleak outlook on the[Pg 152] proletarian revolution. The writers of this school assert, thinking they are opposing Marxism, that waiting for the social revolution's utopian ideal is pointless; they argue that the ongoing reduction of the wealthy, alongside the continuous rise in the number of increasingly impoverished workers—a trend that according to Marx was supposed to create the conditions needed to dismantle the current economic system—contradicts an actual movement towards a more democratic distribution of goods. They therefore insist that socialism should strive for success through less violent yet more effective means, specifically through social legislation or reforms aimed at reducing inequality.

Now, without troubling to repeat what I have already said, that the Marxist dynamic of the distribution of wealth is far from being as completely negatived by contemporary facts[Pg 153] as these critics are pleased to insist, I merely propose to point out that this paying of high honour to reform and social legislation nowise conflicts with the doctrine or with the work of Marx, who, on the contrary, was the first to throw into high relief the pre-eminent value of social legislation, devoting classical chapters to the elucidation of its most memorable manifestations. In this light, therefore, revisionism or reformism, far from being a negation or correction of Marxism, is a specific application or partial realisation of the doctrine, for it brings into the lime-light one of the numerous sides of that marvellous polyhedron, and deserves credit for having explained and developed this particular aspect of Marxism.

Now, without bothering to repeat what I've already said—that the Marxist understanding of wealth distribution is far from completely disproven by current facts[Pg 153], despite what critics claim—I want to highlight that giving high regard to reform and social legislation does not conflict with Marx's doctrine or work. In fact, Marx was the first to emphasize the crucial importance of social legislation, dedicating significant sections to explaining its most notable examples. Therefore, in this context, revisionism or reformism is not a rejection or correction of Marxism; instead, it's a specific application or partial realization of the doctrine. It highlights one of the many facets of that remarkable polyhedron and deserves recognition for explaining and developing this specific aspect of Marxism.

But revisionism errs gravely in that it wishes to replace the beautiful and complex multiplicity of the Marxist system by forcing us to contemplate this unilateral aspect alone. The reformists err in that they fail to see that [Pg 154]legislative reforms, though desirable and extremely opportune, are invariably circumscribed by the prepotent opposition of the privileged classes, and can never do anything more than mitigate a few of the grosser harshnesses of the present system—whilst, precisely because they effect this mitigation, reforms tend to preserve an increasingly unstable economic order from the imminent disaster of a destructive cataclysm.

But revisionism makes a serious mistake by trying to replace the beautiful and complex variety of the Marxist system with just one narrow perspective. Reformists also make a mistake by not realizing that [Pg 154] legislative reforms, while desirable and timely, are always limited by the overwhelming resistance of the privileged classes. They can only slightly ease some of the harsh conditions of the current system. In fact, because these reforms do provide some relief, they tend to protect an increasingly unstable economic system from facing a catastrophic collapse.

If the reformist school mutilates Marxism thus violently, by reducing the whole of Capital to the paragraphs extolling social legislation, the syndicalists inflict a yet cruder mutilation on the Marxist system by tearing a single page out of Capital, to make of this page the alpha and the omega of their revolutionary creed. It is true that Marx, in the thirty-first chapter of Capital, makes an explicit appeal to force, the midwife of every old society pregnant with a new one; but this appeal is not made until it has been fully [Pg 155]demonstrated that the social revolution can only be effected at the close of a slow and lengthy evolutionary process which shall have caused complete disintegration of the existing economic order and shall have paved the way for its inevitable transformation into a superior order.

If the reformist school distorts Marxism so drastically by reducing the entirety of Capital to the sections praising social legislation, the syndicalists do an even more crude distortion of the Marxist system by ripping out a single page from Capital and using it as the basis of their revolutionary beliefs. It's true that Marx, in the thirty-first chapter of Capital, explicitly calls for force, which is the catalyst for every old society anticipating a new one; however, this call is not made until it has been thoroughly [Pg 155]demonstrated that the social revolution can only take place after a slow and lengthy evolutionary process that causes the complete breakdown of the existing economic order and paves the way for its inevitable transformation into a better system.

Now the syndicalists unhesitatingly sponge all this demonstration from the slate, and affirm that the proletarian masses can undertake action at any moment, can violently overthrow the prevailing economic order whenever it shall please them to do so; and they declare that it is needless for revolutionists to keep their eyes fixed upon the clock of history, in order to see if this is about to sound the knell of the present social order. It would be superfluous to demonstrate the absurdity of such a thesis, for the very school which proclaims it has assumed the task of giving it the lie in clamorous accents. For if, as the new apostles of force contend, the proletarian masses can at any moment[Pg 156] annihilate the prevailing economic order, why do they not rise against the capitalism they detest, and replace it with the co-operative commonwealth for which they long? Why is it that after so much noisy organisation, after so much declamation and delirious excitement, the utmost they are able to do is to tear up a few yards of railway track or to smash a street lamp? Do we not find here an irrefragable demonstration that force is not realisable at any given moment but only in the historic hour when evolution shall have prepared the inevitable fall of the dominant economic system?

Now the syndicalists readily take all this demonstration from the slate and insist that the working masses can take action at any moment, can violently overthrow the current economic order whenever they choose; they claim that it’s unnecessary for revolutionaries to keep their eyes on the clock of history to see if it’s time for the downfall of the present social order. It’s pointless to prove the absurdity of such a claim, since the very school that promotes it has taken on the task of disproving it loudly. For if, as the new advocates of force argue, the working masses can annihilate the existing economic order at any moment[Pg 156], then why don’t they rise up against the capitalism they despise and establish the cooperative commonwealth they desire? Why is it that after so much loud organization, so much rhetoric, and frantic excitement, the most they can achieve is tearing up a few yards of railway track or smashing a street lamp? Doesn’t this clearly show that force cannot be actualized at any moment but only in the historic moment when evolution has paved the way for the inevitable collapse of the dominant economic system?

Thus whatever they can do, it always seems that the infirm will of the disciples who demand an arbitrary renovation of the social system (whether by legal measures or by force) breaks vainly against the fatality of evolution, and that reformism and syndicalism are merely caricatures, counterfeits, or exaggerations of the many-sided and well-balanced[Pg 157] theory of the master, who proposed a threefold line of advance: by social legislation; by the activity of the organised workers; and by revolution. In face of these various forms of neo-marxism, the outcome of mutilations and of one-sided exclusivism, Marx redivivus would have excellent reason for repeating his own adage, so thoughtful and so true, "I am not a Marxist." However striking the temporary success of these new forms among the crowd or among the learned, we may confidently predict that neither reformism nor syndicalism will definitively supplant the Marxist system, which despite all and against all remains and will remain a supreme and invincible force at once of theory and of organisation for the proletarian assault upon the long-enduring fortress of property.

So no matter what they try to do, it always seems like the weak will of the disciples who call for an arbitrary change in the social system (whether through laws or by force) futilely clashes with the inevitability of evolution. Reformism and syndicalism are just distorted, false, or exaggerated versions of the comprehensive and balanced theory of the master, who suggested a threefold path: through social legislation, the efforts of organized workers, and revolution. In light of these various forms of neo-Marxism, outcomes of distortions and one-sided exclusivism, Marx resurrected would have every reason to repeat his well-considered and true saying, "I am not a Marxist." Despite the temporary appeal of these new forms among the masses or the intellectuals, we can confidently predict that neither reformism nor syndicalism will permanently replace the Marxist system, which, despite everything, remains and will continue to be a powerful and unyielding force both in theory and in organizing for the proletariat’s fight against the long-standing stronghold of property.

The value of Marx's work is, in fact, displayed in the most brilliant light by the detailed criticism of the theorists and by the contrast with opposing trends; all the more when[Pg 158] we compare the aspect of economic thought and of proletarian organisation before and after the publication of Capital. For if we study the utterances of thinkers upon these matters during the middle of the nineteenth century, we find that nearly all are dominated by the categorical idea that the social order is of an absolutely immobile character, and that none but a few utopians entertain the thought of changing that order by means of precipitate legislation inspired by their individual preconceptions. In any case, it was an idea common to all, to revolutionists as well as to conservatives, that the poverty of the masses was a negative and distressing residue from the economic system, that it was a purely passive feature of that system which must be accepted with resignation, for it could not exercise any propulsive influence in the general social movement. This is substantially the notion which emerges from Victor Hugo's Les Misérables, for poverty is here regarded as an[Pg 159] overwhelming mass of suffering for which it is impossible to assign the responsibility; it is looked upon as a load pressing with inexorable cruelty upon suffering humanity, which is unable to respond by anything more effective than complaints and tears.

The value of Marx's work is really highlighted by the detailed criticism from theorists and the comparison with opposing trends; especially when[Pg 158] we look at the state of economic thought and the organization of the working class before and after the release of Capital. If we examine the views of thinkers on these issues during the mid-nineteenth century, we find that nearly all are influenced by the strong belief that the social order is completely unchangeable, and that only a few utopians think about changing that order through sudden laws based on their personal ideas. In any case, it was a common belief shared by both revolutionaries and conservatives, that the poverty of the masses was a negative and troubling leftover from the economic system, a purely passive aspect of that system that should be accepted with resignation, as it couldn’t drive any forward movement in society. This is basically the idea presented in Victor Hugo's Les Misérables, where poverty is seen as an[Pg 159] overwhelming burden of suffering for which no one can be blamed; it is viewed as a heavy weight cruelly pressing down on suffering humanity, which can only respond with complaints and tears.

But how utterly different is the notion prevailing in our own days upon this matter. Not only is the conviction now rooted in the mind of every thinker that the economic order is subject to unceasing change, is advancing towards predestined destruction; but it is considered certain that the artificer, the demiurge, the most potent factor of this destruction, will be the active resistance, the unrest, the rebellion, of the proletarians in the grasp of the capitalist machine and eager to destroy it. This conception of the dynamogenic function of poverty is the most characteristic feature of the social thought of our day, the feature wherein that thought contrasts most categorically with the ideas of an earlier age. Just as[Pg 160] the Christian sect, represented by Gibbon as a mere pathological efflorescence growing on the margin of Roman society, is by the better equipped science of our own time looked upon as having been the most potent solvent of the imperial complex and as the ferment generating a new and better life, so the proletarian masses, regarded by the science and the art of the past as a crushed and pitiful appendage of the bourgeois economy, now appear to contemporary science as the most vigorous among the forces tending to disintegrate that economy, as tending irresistibly to create a higher and better balanced form of association.

But the idea that prevails in our own time is completely different. Now, every thinker is convinced that the economic order is constantly changing and heading towards inevitable destruction; it's widely accepted that the main driver of this destruction will be the active resistance, unrest, and rebellion of the working class trapped in the capitalist system and eager to tear it down. This understanding of how poverty fuels social change is the most defining characteristic of today's social thought, marking a stark contrast with the ideas of the past. Just as[Pg 160] the Christian sect, which Gibbon depicted as a mere pathological outgrowth on the edges of Roman society, is now seen by contemporary science as having been a significant catalyst for dissolving the imperial structure and sparking new, improved life, so the working class, which was once viewed by the science and art of the past as a oppressed and miserable byproduct of the bourgeois economy, is now recognized by modern science as one of the most powerful forces likely to dismantle that economy and create a more advanced and balanced form of social organization.

Correlatively with this development, whereas the proletarians of other days were content to sulk in their hovels as they contemplated the brilliant gyrations of the capitalist constellation, merely cursing in secret the sorrows of their lot, to-day the workers of the two worlds are advancing in serried ranks to the conquest of a new humanity and a new life. Thus the[Pg 161] immobility of our fathers has given place to rapid movement; their discouragement and resignation, to rebellious demands; and whereas of old a chasm yawned between the scattered visionaries who entertained dreams of social rebirth and the inert mass of the poverty-stricken, we find to-day that the impoverished are themselves becoming the artificers, the heralds, the pioneers, of the irresistible ascent of humanity towards a juster and better social order. Now all this new moral and social world, unknown to our grandparents, the glory and the plague of science, of society, of contemporary life; all this gigantic tumult of ideas, facts, claims, of assaults, wounds, innovating reconstructions; all this marvellous necromancy is the work of one man, a sage and a martyr. All this we owe to Karl Marx. It measures, concretes, and materialises for us his colossal worth and the omnipotent vastness of his achievement. Though science may well and with full right[Pg 162] complain of the gaps in his doctrinal system, though life may furnish the most definite refutations of his theoretical visions, and though future history may display forms of which he never dreamed, nevertheless, no one will ever be able to unseat him from his throne, or to dispute the sovereignty which accrues to him on account of his splendid contributions to civil progress. Whether praised and accepted, or despised and rejected, by practice or by theory, by history or by reason, he will always remain the emperor in the realm of mind, the Prometheus foredestined to lead the human race towards the brilliant goal which awaits it in a future not perhaps immeasurably remote.

Alongside this development, while workers in the past were satisfied to stay silent in their shabby homes, watching the dazzling movements of capitalism and secretly cursing their misfortunes, today’s workers around the world are marching together to achieve a new humanity and a new life. The inaction of our ancestors has been replaced by swift movement; their discouragement and acceptance have transformed into assertive demands. Whereas there used to be a vast gap between the scattered dreamers who envisioned social renewal and the passive mass of the impoverished, now we see that the poor themselves are becoming the builders, the heralds, the pioneers of humanity’s unstoppable progress toward a fairer and better social order. This entire new moral and social world, unknown to our grandparents—the glory and the burden of science, society, and modern life; this enormous whirlwind of ideas, facts, demands, conflicts, injuries, and innovative changes; all this incredible transformation is the result of one man, a wise figure and a martyr. We owe all this to Karl Marx. It highlights, grounds, and gives tangible form to his immense significance and the far-reaching magnitude of his accomplishment. Even though science may justifiably point out the gaps in his theories, life might provide clear contradictions to his theoretical visions, and future history may show developments he never imagined, no one will ever be able to dethrone him or deny the authority he holds due to his remarkable contributions to social progress. Whether celebrated and embraced, or scorned and rejected, by practice or theory, by history or reason, he will forever remain the ruler of thought, the Prometheus destined to guide humanity toward the brilliant future that awaits it, which may not be as far off as it seems.

For the day is coming. And in that day, when remorseless time shall have destroyed the statues of the saints and of the warriors, renascent humanity will raise in honour of the author of this work of destruction, upon the shores of his native stream, a huge mausoleum[Pg 163] representing the proletarian breaking his chains and entering upon an era of conscious and glorious freedom. Thither will come the regenerated peoples bearing garlands of remembrance and of gratitude to lay upon the shrine of the great thinker, who, amid sufferings, humiliations, and numberless privations, fought unceasingly for the ransom of mankind. And the mothers, as they show to their children the suffering and suggestive figure, will say, their voices trembling with emotion and joy: See from what darkness our light has come forth; see how many tears have watered the seeds of our joy; look, and pay reverence to him who struggled, who suffered, who died for the Supreme Redemption.

For the day is coming. And on that day, when relentless time has worn away the statues of the saints and warriors, reborn humanity will build a massive mausoleum in honor of the creator of this destruction, by the banks of his native stream. It will depict the working class breaking their chains and stepping into an era of conscious and glorious freedom. The revitalized peoples will come with wreaths of remembrance and gratitude to place at the shrine of the great thinker, who, through suffering, humiliation, and countless hardships, tirelessly fought for the liberation of humanity. And the mothers, as they point out the suffering and impactful figure to their children, will say, their voices filled with emotion and joy: Look at how our light emerged from darkness; see how many tears have nurtured the seeds of our happiness; look, and pay tribute to him who struggled, who suffered, who died for the Supreme Redemption.[Pg 163]


Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!