This is a modern-English version of Human, All-Too-Human: A Book for Free Spirits, Part 1: Complete Works, Volume Six, originally written by Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm. It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.

HUMAN

ALL-TOO-HUMAN

A BOOK FOR FREE SPIRITS

PART I

By

FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE

TRANSLATED BY

HELEN ZIMMERN

WITH INTRODUCTION BY

J. M. KENNEDY

The Complete Works of Friedrich Nietzsche

The First Complete and Authorised English Translation

Edited by Dr Oscar Levy

Volume Six

T.N. FOULIS
13 & 15 FREDERICK STREET
EDINBURGH: AND LONDON
1909

CONTENTS.

INTRODUCTION

AUTHOR'S PREFACE

FIRST DIVISION: FIRST AND LAST THINGS
SECOND DIVISION: THE HISTORY OF THE MORAL SENTIMENT
THIRD DIVISION: THE RELIGIOUS LIFE
FOURTH DIVISION: CONCERNING THE SOUL OF ARTISTS AND AUTHORS
FIFTH DIVISION: THE SIGNS OF HIGHER AND LOWER CULTURE
SIXTH DIVISION: MAN IN SOCIETY
SEVENTH DIVISION: WIFE AND CHILD
EIGHTH DIVISION: A GLANCE AT THE STATE
AN EPODE—AMONG FRIENDS

CONTENTS.

INTRODUCTION

AUTHOR'S PREFACE

FIRST DIVISION: FIRST AND LAST THINGS
SECOND DIVISION: THE HISTORY OF THE MORAL SENTIMENT
THIRD DIVISION: THE RELIGIOUS LIFE
FOURTH DIVISION: ABOUT THE SOUL OF ARTISTS AND AUTHORS
FIFTH DIVISION: THE SIGNS OF HIGHER AND LOWER CULTURE
SIXTH DIVISION: PEOPLE IN SOCIETY
SEVENTH DIVISION: WIFE AND CHILD
EIGHTH DIVISION: A LOOK AT THE STATE
AN EPODE—AMONG FRIENDS


INTRODUCTION.

Nietzsche's essay, Richard Wagner in Bayreuth, appeared in 1876, and his next publication was his present work, which was issued in 1878. A comparison of the books will show that the two years of meditation intervening had brought about a great change in Nietzsche's views, his style of expressing them, and the form in which they were cast. The Dionysian, overflowing with life, gives way to an Apollonian thinker with a touch of pessimism. The long essay form is abandoned, and instead we have a series of aphorisms, some tinged with melancholy, others with satire, several, especially towards the end, with Nietzschian wit at its best, and a few at the beginning so very abstruse as to require careful study.

Nietzsche's essay, Richard Wagner in Bayreuth, came out in 1876, and his next publication was his current work, which was released in 1878. A comparison of the two books shows that the two years of reflection in between led to significant changes in Nietzsche's ideas, how he expressed them, and the format he chose. The vibrant, life-filled Dionysian perspective gives way to a more Apollonian thinker with a hint of pessimism. The lengthy essay format is replaced with a series of aphorisms, some colored by melancholy, others with satire, several—particularly towards the end—showing Nietzsche's wit at its best, and a few at the beginning so complex that they require careful reading.

Since the Bayreuth festivals of 1876, Nietzsche had gradually come to see Wagner as he really was. The ideal musician that Nietzsche had pictured in his own mind turned out to be nothing more than a rather dilettante philosopher, an opportunistic decadent with a suspicious tendency towards Christianity. The young philosopher thereupon proceeded to shake off the influence which the musician had exercised upon him. He was successful in doing so, but not without a[Pg viii] struggle, just as he had formerly shaken off the influence of Schopenhauer. Hence he writes in his autobiography:[1] "Human, all-too-Human, is the monument of a crisis. It is entitled: 'A book for free spirits,' and almost every line in it represents a victory—in its pages I freed myself from everything foreign to my real nature. Idealism is foreign to me: the title says, 'Where you see ideal things, I see things which are only—human alas! all-too-human!' I know man better—the term 'free spirit' must here be understood in no other sense than this: a freed man, who has once more taken possession of himself."

Since the Bayreuth festivals of 1876, Nietzsche gradually began to see Wagner for who he really was. The ideal musician Nietzsche imagined turned out to be just a somewhat amateur philosopher, an opportunistic decadent with a troubling leaning toward Christianity. The young philosopher then worked to break free from Wagner's influence over him. He managed to do this, but it wasn't easy, just as he had previously distanced himself from Schopenhauer's influence. He writes in his autobiography: Human, all-too-Human is the monument of a crisis. It’s titled: 'A book for free spirits,' and nearly every line in it represents a victory—in its pages, I liberated myself from everything that wasn’t true to my nature. Idealism is foreign to me: the title says, 'Where you see ideal things, I see things that are only—human, alas! all-too-human!' I understand man better—the term 'free spirit' here should be understood as: a freed man, who has once again taken possession of himself.

The form of this book will be better understood when it is remembered that at this period Nietzsche was beginning to suffer from stomach trouble and headaches. As a cure for his complaints, he spent his time in travel when he could get a few weeks' respite from his duties at Basel University; and it was in the course of his solitary walks and hill-climbing tours that the majority of these thoughts occurred to him and were jotted down there and then. A few of them, however, date further back, as he tells us in the preface to the second part of this work. Many of them, he says, occupied his mind even before he published his first book, The Birth of Tragedy and several others, as we learn from his notebooks and posthumous writings, date from the period of the Thoughts out of Season.

The structure of this book will make more sense when you remember that during this time, Nietzsche was starting to experience stomach issues and headaches. To help with his ailments, he traveled whenever he could take a break from his responsibilities at Basel University; and it was during his solitary walks and climbs that most of these ideas came to him and were written down on the spot. However, a few of them are from earlier, as he explains in the preface to the second part of this work. Many of these thoughts were on his mind even before he published his first book, The Birth of Tragedy, and several others, as noted in his notebooks and writings published after his death, date back to the time of Thoughts out of Season.

It must be clearly understood, however, that[Pg ix] Nietzsche's disease must not be looked upon in the same way as that of an ordinary man. People are inclined to regard a sick man as rancorous; but any one who rights with and conquers his disease, and even exploits it, as Nietzsche did, benefits thereby to an extraordinary degree. In the first place, he has passed through several stages of human psychology with which a healthy man is entirely unacquainted; e.g. he has learnt by introspection the spiteful and revengeful spirit of the sick man and his religion. Secondly, in his moments of freedom from pain and gloom his thoughts will be all the more brilliant.

It should be clearly understood, however, that[Pg ix] Nietzsche's illness should not be viewed like that of an ordinary person. People tend to see a sick person as bitter; however, anyone who struggles against and overcomes their illness, and even uses it to their advantage like Nietzsche did, gains remarkable benefits from it. First of all, he has gone through different levels of human psychology that a healthy person knows nothing about; e.g. he has understood through self-reflection the spiteful and vengeful mindset of the sick and their beliefs. Secondly, during his pain-free moments, his thoughts become even more brilliant.

In support of this last statement, one instance may be selected out of hundreds that could be adduced. Heinrich Heine spent the greater part of his life in exile from his native country, tortured by headaches, and finally dying in a foreign land as the result of a spinal disease. His splendid works were composed in his moments of respite from illness, and during the last years of his life, when his health was at its worst, he gave to the world his famous Romancero. We would likewise do well to recollect Goethe's saying:

In support of this last statement, consider one example from the many that could be mentioned. Heinrich Heine spent most of his life in exile from his home country, suffering from severe headaches, and ultimately dying in a foreign land due to a spinal disease. His beautiful works were created during his brief moments of relief from illness, and in the last years of his life, when his health was at its lowest, he shared with the world his famous Romancero. We should also remember Goethe's saying:

Zart Gedicht, wie Regenbogen,
Wird nur auf dunkelm Grund gezogen.[2]

Zart Gedicht, wie Regenbogen,
Wird nur auf dunklem Grund gezogen.[2]

Thus neither the form of this book—so startling at first to those who have been brought up in the traditions of our own school—nor the[Pg x] treat all men as equals, and proclaim the establishment of equal rights:

Thus neither the format of this book—so surprising at first to those who have been raised in the traditions of our own school—nor the[Pg x] treat all people as equals and declare the establishment of equal rights:

so far a socialistic mode of thought which is based on justice is possible; but, as has been said, only within the ranks of the governing classes, which in this case practises justice with sacrifices and abnegations. On the other hand, to demand equality of rights, as do the Socialists of the subject caste, is by no means the outcome of justice, but of covetousness. If you expose bloody pieces of flesh to a beast, and then withdraw them again until it finally begins to roar, do you think that the roaring implies justice?

So far, a socialist mindset based on justice is possible; however, as mentioned, it's only present among the ruling classes, who in this case practice justice through sacrifices and self-denial. On the other hand, demanding equal rights from the oppressed group, as the Socialists do, isn't a result of justice, but rather of greed. If you show bloody pieces of flesh to a beast and then take them away until it finally starts to roar, do you really think that the roaring means justice?

Theologians on the other hand, as may be expected, will find no such ready help in their difficulties from Nietzsche. They must, on the contrary, be on their guard against so alert an adversary—a duty which they are apparently not going to shirk; for theologians are amongst the most ardent students of Nietzsche in this country. Their attention may therefore be drawn to aphorism 630 of this book, dealing with convictions and their origin, which will no doubt be successfully refuted by the defenders of the true faith. In fact, there is not a single paragraph in the book that does not deserve careful study by all serious thinkers.

Theologians, as might be expected, won't find much easy support from Nietzsche when facing their challenges. Instead, they need to be cautious of such a vigilant opponent—a responsibility they clearly intend to uphold; after all, theologians are some of the most passionate readers of Nietzsche in this country. This leads them to aphorism 630 of this book, which discusses convictions and their origins, likely to be effectively countered by those defending the true faith. In reality, there isn't a single paragraph in the book that doesn't warrant close examination by all serious thinkers.

On the whole, however, this is a calm book, and those who are accustomed to Nietzsche the out-spoken Immoralist, may be somewhat astonished at the calm tone of the present volume. The explanation is that Nietzsche was now just beginning to walk on his own philosophical path. His life-long aim, the uplifting of the type man, was still in view, but the way leading towards it was once more uncertain. Hence the peculiarly calm, even[Pg xi] melancholic, and what Nietzsche himself would call Apollonian, tinge of many of these aphorisms, so different from the style of his earlier and later writings. For this very reason, however, the book may appeal all the more to English readers, who are of course more Apollonian than Dionysian. Nietzsche is feeling his way, and these aphorisms represent his first steps. As such—besides having a high intrinsic value of themselves—they are enormous aids to the study of his character and temperament.

Overall, this is a calm book, and those who are used to Nietzsche as the outspoken Immoralist might be surprised by the serene tone of this volume. The reason for this is that Nietzsche was just starting to navigate his own philosophical journey. His lifelong goal of elevating humanity was still present, but the path to achieving it was once again uncertain. This leads to the uniquely calm, even melancholic, and what Nietzsche himself would describe as Apollonian flavor of many of these aphorisms, which is so different from the style of his earlier and later works. For this reason, the book may resonate even more with English readers, who tend to be more Apollonian than Dionysian. Nietzsche is exploring his ideas, and these aphorisms mark his initial steps. As such—while also possessing great intrinsic value—they significantly contribute to understanding his character and temperament.

J. M. KENNEDY.

J.M. Kennedy.


[1] Ecce Homo, p. 75.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Ecce Homo, p. 75.

[2] "Tender poetry, like rainbows, can appear only on a dark and sombre background."—J.M.K.

[2] "Gentle poetry, like rainbows, can only show up against a dark and gloomy backdrop."—J.M.K.


PREFACE

1.

1.

I have been told frequently, and always with great surprise, that there is something common and distinctive in all my writings, from the Birth of Tragedy to the latest published Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future. They all contain, I have been told, snares and nets for unwary birds, and an almost perpetual unconscious demand for the inversion of customary valuations and valued customs. What? Everything only—human-all-too-human? People lay down my writings with this sigh, not without a certain dread and distrust of morality itself, indeed almost tempted and encouraged to become advocates of the worst things: as being perhaps only the best disparaged? My writings have been called a school of suspicion and especially of disdain, more happily, also, a school of courage and even of audacity. Indeed, I myself do not think that any one has ever looked at the world with such a profound suspicion; and not only as occasional Devil's Advocate, but equally also, to speak theologically, as enemy and impeacher of God; and he who realises something of the consequences involved,[Pg 2] in every profound suspicion, something of the chills and anxieties of loneliness to which every uncompromising difference of outlook condemns him who is affected therewith, will also understand how often I sought shelter in some kind of reverence or hostility, or scientificality or levity or stupidity, in order to recover from myself, and, as it were, to obtain temporary self-forgetfulness; also why, when I did not find what I needed, I was obliged to manufacture it, to counterfeit and to imagine it in a suitable manner (and what else have poets ever done? And for what purpose has all the art in the world existed?). What I always required most, however, for my cure and self-recovery, was the belief that I was not isolated in such circumstances, that I did not see in an isolated manner—a magic suspicion of relationship and similarity to others in outlook and desire, a repose in the confidence of friendship, a blindness in both parties without suspicion or note of interrogation, an enjoyment of foregrounds, and surfaces of the near and the nearest, of all that has colour, epidermis, and outside appearance. Perhaps I might be reproached in this respect for much "art" and fine false coinage; for instance, for voluntarily and knowingly shutting my eyes to Schopenhauer's blind will to morality at a time when I had become sufficiently clear-sighted about morality; also for deceiving myself about Richard Wagner's incurable romanticism, as if it were a beginning and not an end; also about the Greeks, also about the Germans and their future—and there would still probably be quite a long list of such alsos? Supposing[Pg 3] however, that this were all true and that I were reproached with good reason, what do you know, what could you know as to how much artifice of self-preservation, how much rationality and higher protection there is in such self-deception,—and how much falseness I still require in order to allow myself again and again the luxury of my sincerity? ... In short, I still live; and life, in spite of ourselves, is not devised by morality; it demands illusion, it lives by illusion ... but——There! I am already beginning again and doing what I have always done, old immoralist and bird-catcher that I am,—I am talking un-morally, ultra-morally, "beyond good and evil"?...

I've often been told, much to my surprise, that there’s something unique and consistent in all my writings, from the *Birth of Tragedy* to the latest *Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future.* People say they’re full of traps for unsuspecting readers and carry a constant, unconscious urge to flip around traditional values and accepted customs. What? *Everything* is merely—human-all-too-human? Readers often put down my works with a sigh, feeling a certain dread and distrust toward morality itself, even being tempted to champion the *worst* things, as if they might just be the *best* that got overlooked? My writings have been labeled a school of suspicion, and, more happily, a school of courage and even audacity. Indeed, I don’t believe anyone has looked at the world with such deep suspicion; not just as the occasional Devil's Advocate, but also, to put it theologically, as an enemy and accuser of God. Anyone who grasps even a part of the consequences tied to deep suspicion, along with the chills and loneliness faced by anyone who holds a starkly different perspective, will understand how often I've sought refuge in reverence, hostility, scientific thought, or even frivolity and ignorance to regain a sense of self and temporary self-forgetfulness. When I couldn't find what I *needed,* I had to create it, to mimic and imagine it in a fitting way (what else have poets ever done? And why has all the art in the world existed?). Yet what I needed most for healing and self-recovery was the belief that I was *not* alone in such circumstances, that I wasn’t *seeing* things in isolation—a magical sense of connection and similarity to others in perspective and desire, a comforting trust in friendship, a mutual blindness without suspicion or interrogation, an appreciation for the immediate, for the colorful, the surface, the external appearance. I might be criticized for my "art" and clever falsehoods; for example, for closing my eyes to Schopenhauer's blind morality at a time when I had become clear-eyed about it, and for deceiving myself about Richard Wagner's unshakeable romanticism, as if it were a beginning rather than an end; the same goes for the Greeks, the Germans, and their future—and there could likely be a long list of such claims. But suppose this were all true and I were justly criticized, what do *you* know, what *could* you know about how much self-preservation, rationality, and higher protection there is in such self-deception—and how much falseness I still *need* to give myself the luxury of *my* sincerity? ... In short, I still live; and life, despite our intentions, isn’t structured by morality; it *demands* illusion, it *thrives* on illusion ... but—There! I’m already at it again, doing what I’ve always done, old immoralist and bird-catcher that I am—I’m speaking immorally, ultra-morally, "beyond good and evil"?...

2.

2.

Thus then, when I found it necessary, I invented once on a time the "free spirits," to whom this discouragingly encouraging book with the title Human, all-too-Human, is dedicated. There are no such "free spirits" nor have there been such, but, as already said, I then required them for company to keep me cheerful in the midst of evils (sickness, loneliness, foreignness,—acedia, inactivity) as brave companions and ghosts with whom I could laugh and gossip when so inclined and send to the devil when they became bores,—as compensation for the lack of friends. That such free spirits will be possible some day, that our Europe will have such bold and cheerful wights amongst her sons of to-morrow and the day after to-morrow,[Pg 4] as the shadows of a hermit's phantasmagoria—I should be the last to doubt thereof. Already I see them coming, slowly, slowly; and perhaps I am doing something to hasten their coming when I describe in advance under what auspices I see them originate, and upon what paths I see them come.

So, when I found it necessary, I invented the "free spirits," to whom this discouragingly encouraging book titled *Human, all-too-Human* is dedicated. There are no such "free spirits," nor have there ever been, but as I mentioned, I needed them for company to keep my spirits up in the face of troubles (sickness, loneliness, unfamiliarity—acedia, inactivity) as brave companions and imaginary friends with whom I could laugh and chat whenever I wanted and send away when they got boring—acting as a substitute for the lack of friends. That such free spirits will be possible one day, that our Europe will have such bold and cheerful souls among her future generations, like the shadows of a hermit's phantasmagoria—I would be the last to doubt that. I already see them coming, slowly, slowly; and perhaps I am doing something to speed up their arrival when I describe in advance the circumstances I see them emerging from and the paths I see them taking.

3.

3.

One may suppose that a spirit in which the type "free spirit" is to become fully mature and sweet, has had its decisive event in a great emancipation, and that it was all the more fettered previously and apparently bound for ever to its corner and pillar. What is it that binds most strongly? What cords are almost unrendable? In men of a lofty and select type it will be their duties; the reverence which is suitable to youth, respect and tenderness for all that is time-honoured and worthy, gratitude to the land which bore them, to the hand which led them, to the sanctuary where they learnt to adore,—their most exalted moments themselves will bind them most effectively, will lay upon them the most enduring obligations. For those who are thus bound the great emancipation comes suddenly, like an earthquake; the young soul is all at once convulsed, unloosened and extricated—it does not itself know what is happening. An impulsion and-compulsion sway and over-master it like a command; a will and a wish awaken, to go forth on their course, anywhere, at any cost; a violent, dangerous curiosity about an undiscovered world flames and flares in every sense. "Better to[Pg 5] die than live here"—says the imperious voice and seduction, and this "here," this "at home" is all that the soul has hitherto loved! A sudden fear and suspicion of that which it loved, a flash of disdain for what was called its "duty," a rebellious, arbitrary, volcanically throbbing longing for travel, foreignness, estrangement, coldness, disenchantment, glaciation, a hatred of love, perhaps a sacrilegious clutch and look backwards, to where it hitherto adored and loved, perhaps a glow of shame at what it was just doing, and at the same time a rejoicing that it was doing it, an intoxicated, internal, exulting thrill which betrays a triumph—a triumph? Over what? Over whom? An enigmatical, questionable, doubtful triumph, but the first triumph nevertheless;—such evil and painful incidents belong to the history of the great emancipation. It is, at the same time, a disease which may destroy the man, this first outbreak of power and will to self-decision, self-valuation, this will to free will; and how much disease is manifested in the wild attempts and eccentricities by which the liberated and emancipated one now seeks to demonstrate his mastery over things! He roves about raging with unsatisfied longing; whatever he captures has to suffer for the dangerous tension of his pride; he tears to pieces whatever attracts him. With a malicious laugh he twirls round whatever he finds veiled or guarded by a sense of shame; he tries how these things look when turned upside down. It is a matter of arbitrariness with him, and pleasure in arbitrariness, if he now perhaps bestow his favour on what[Pg 6] had hitherto a bad repute,—if he inquisitively and temptingly haunt what is specially forbidden. In the background of his activities and wanderings —for he is restless and aimless in his course as in a desert—stands the note of interrogation of an increasingly dangerous curiosity. "Cannot all valuations be reversed? And is good perhaps evil? And God only an invention and artifice of the devil? Is everything, perhaps, radically false? And if we are the deceived, are we not thereby also deceivers? Must we not also be deceivers?"—Such thoughts lead and mislead him more and more, onward and away. Solitude encircles and engirdles him, always more threatening, more throttling, more heart-oppressing, that terrible goddess and mater sæva cupidinum—but who knows nowadays what solitude is?...

One might think that a spirit classified as a "free spirit" reaches its peak maturity and sweetness after a significant event like a great emancipation, especially after being so constrained before, seemingly forever stuck in its corner. What truly binds us the most? What ties are nearly impossible to break? For individuals of a high and distinguished type, it’s their responsibilities; the respect fitting for youth, the care and reverence for all that’s respected and cherished, gratitude towards the land that nurtured them, to the hands that guided them, to the sanctuary where they learned to worship—these exalted moments themselves create the strongest bonds, imposing lasting obligations. For those who feel these ties, emancipation hits suddenly, like an earthquake; the young spirit is suddenly shaken, loosened, and freed—it doesn’t even understand what’s happening. A force and drive take over, almost like a command; a desire to venture out, anywhere, at any price awakens; a fierce, dangerous curiosity about an uncharted world ignites every sense. "Better to[Pg 5] die than live here,” commands an insistent voice and seduction, and this "here," this "at home," is everything the soul has ever loved! Suddenly, there’s fear and distrust of what it once cherished, a flash of disdain for what it deemed its "duty," a rebellious, throbbing urge for travel, foreignness, alienation, chilliness, disillusionment, apathy, a disdain for love, perhaps a sacrilegious glance backwards at what it has always adored and cherished, and maybe even a blush of shame for what it’s doing, while simultaneously feeling a thrill that it’s doing it, an inner intoxication, an exhilarating joy that signals a victory—a victory? Over what? Over whom? An enigmatic, questionable triumph, yet the first triumph nevertheless; —such troubling and painful experiences are part of the journey to true freedom. It’s also a kind of sickness that could ruin the person: this initial outburst of power and intention to make one's own choices, an insistence on free will; and how much illness is shown in the wild efforts and oddities through which the now-liberated one tries to assert control over everything! He wanders around, seething with unfulfilled longing; whatever he seizes suffers from the tension of his pride; he tears apart anything that draws his attention. With a mischievous laugh, he spins around whatever he finds hidden or protected by shame; he experiments with how these things appear when turned inside out. It becomes a matter of randomness that he relishes, whether he chooses to favor things [Pg 6] that have previously been looked down upon—if he curiously and temptingly explores what is especially forbidden. In the backdrop of his actions and wandering—because he is restless and aimless like in a desert—lurks the questioning note of increasingly precarious curiosity. "Can’t all values be flipped? Could good actually be bad? And is God just a clever invention of the devil? Is everything fundamentally deceptive? And if we are the deceived, aren’t we also deceivers? Must we become deceivers ourselves?"—These thoughts will guide and mislead him further and further away. Solitude surrounds him, becoming more menacing, suffocating, and oppressive, that formidable goddess and mater sæva cupidinum—but who truly understands what solitude is nowadays?...

4.

4.

From this morbid solitariness, from the desert of such years of experiment, it is still a long way to the copious, overflowing safety and soundness which does not care to dispense with disease itself as an instrument and angling-hook of knowledge;—to that mature freedom of spirit which is equally self-control and discipline of the heart, and gives access to many and opposed modes of thought;—to that inward comprehensiveness and daintiness of superabundance, which excludes any danger of the spirit's becoming enamoured and lost in its own paths, and[Pg 7] lying intoxicated in some corner or other; to that excess of plastic, healing, formative, and restorative powers, which is exactly the sign of splendid health, that excess which gives the free spirit the dangerous prerogative of being entitled to live by experiments and offer itself to adventure; the free spirit's prerogative of mastership! Long years of convalescence may lie in between, years full of many-coloured, painfully-enchanting magical transformations, curbed and led by a tough will to health, which often dares to dress and disguise itself as actual health. There is a middle condition therein, which a man of such a fate never calls to mind later on without emotion; a pale, delicate light and a sunshine-happiness are peculiar to him, a feeling of bird-like freedom, prospect, and haughtiness, a tertium quid in which curiosity and gentle disdain are combined. A "free spirit"—this cool expression does good in every condition, it almost warms. One no longer lives, in the fetters of love and hatred, without Yea, without Nay, voluntarily near, voluntarily distant, preferring to escape, to turn aside, to flutter forth, to fly up and away; one is fastidious like every one who has once seen an immense variety beneath him,—and one has become the opposite of those who trouble themselves about things which do not concern them. In fact, it is nothing but things which now concern the free spirit,—and how many things!—which no longer trouble him!

From this grim solitude, from the wasteland of those years of experimentation, there is still a long journey to reach the abundant, overflowing safety and well-being that doesn’t shy away from using illness as a tool and lure for knowledge;—to that mature freedom of spirit that embodies both self-control and heart discipline, granting access to diverse and conflicting ways of thinking;—to that inner richness and delicateness of abundance, which prevents any risk of the spirit getting captivated and lost in its own paths, and[Pg 7] lying intoxicated in some hidden corner; to that excess of creative, healing, shaping, and restorative powers, which is the true sign of splendid health, that excess which gives the free spirit the risky privilege to live through experiments and open itself to adventure; the free spirit's privilege of mastery! Long years of recovery may lie ahead, filled with vibrant, painfully enchanting transformations, guided and controlled by a strong will to health, which often dares to appear and disguise itself as real health. There exists a transitional state within this, which a person with such a fate never recalls later on without feeling emotional; a pale, delicate light and a sunshine-happiness are unique to him, a sensation of bird-like freedom, foresight, and pride, a tertium quid where curiosity and gentle disdain intertwine. A "free spirit"—this cool term brings comfort in every situation, it almost provides warmth. One no longer lives shackled by love and hate, without affirmation or negation, choosing voluntarily to be near or far, preferring to escape, to divert, to flit away, to soar up and out; one becomes selective like everyone who has once seen an immense variety beneath them,—and has become the opposite of those who concern themselves with matters that do not involve them. In fact, it is only matters that now concern the free spirit,—and how many things!—which no longer trouble him!

5.

5.

A step further towards recovery, and the free spirit again draws near to life; slowly, it is true, and almost stubbornly, almost distrustfully. Again it grows warmer around him, and, as it were, yellower; feeling and sympathy gain depth,. thawing winds of every kind pass lightly over him. He almost feels as if his eyes were now first opened to what is near. He marvels and is still; where has he been? The near and nearest things, how changed they appear to him! What a bloom and magic they have acquired meanwhile! He looks back gratefully,—grateful to his wandering, his austerity and self-estrangement, his far-sightedness and his bird-like flights in cold heights. What a good thing that he did not always stay "at home," "by himself," like a sensitive, stupid tenderling. He has been beside himself, there is no doubt. He now sees himself for the first time,—and what surprises he feels thereby! What thrills unexperienced hitherto! What joy even in the weariness, in the old illness, in the relapses of the convalescent! How he likes to sit still and suffer, to practise patience, to lie in the sun! Who is as familiar as he with the joy of winter, with the patch of sunshine upon the wall! They are the most grateful animals in the world, and also the most unassuming, these lizards of convalescents with their faces half-turned towards life once more:—there are those amongst them who never let a day pass without hanging a little hymn of praise on its trailing fringe. And, speaking seriously, it[Pg 9] is a radical cure for all pessimism (the well-known disease of old idealists and falsehood-mongers) to become ill after the manner of these free spirits, to remain ill a good while, and then grow well (I mean "better") for a still longer period. It is wisdom, practical wisdom, to prescribe even health for one's self for a long time only in small doses.

A step closer to recovery, and the free spirit comes back to life; slowly, it's true, and almost stubbornly, almost distrustfully. It starts to feel warmer around him, and, in a way, more vibrant; feelings and compassion deepen, as gentle breezes pass over him. He almost feels like his eyes are just now opening to what is near. He wonders and is still; where has he been? The nearby things—how changed they seem to him! They've taken on such beauty and magic in the meantime! He looks back with gratitude—thankful for his wandering, his toughness and self-isolation, his vision and his bird-like flights in cold heights. What a good thing that he didn’t always stay "at home," "by himself," like a sensitive, clueless softie. No doubt, he has been beside himself. He finally sees himself for the first time—what surprises come with that! What new thrills! What joy even in the exhaustion, in the old illness, in the setbacks of recovery! He enjoys sitting still and enduring, practicing patience, lying in the sun! Who knows the joy of winter better than he does, relishing the patch of sunshine on the wall! They are the most grateful creatures in the world, and the most humble too, these lizards of recovery, with their faces half-turned towards life again: there are those among them who never let a day go by without sending a little hymn of praise on its trailing edge. Seriously, it[Pg 9] is a radical cure for all pessimism (the well-known illness of old idealists and liars) to become ill like these free spirits, to stay ill for a while, and then gradually get better (I mean "better") for an even longer time. It’s wise, practical wisdom, to prescribe even health for oneself in small doses for a long time.

6.

6.

About this time it may at last happen, under the sudden illuminations of still disturbed and changing health, that the enigma of that great emancipation begins to reveal itself to the free, and ever freer, spirit,—that enigma which had hitherto lain obscure, questionable, and almost intangible, in his memory. If for a long time he scarcely dared to ask himself, "Why so apart? So alone? denying everything that I revered? denying reverence itself? Why this hatred, this suspicion, this severity towards my own virtues?"—he now dares and asks the questions aloud, and already hears something like an answer to them— "Thou shouldst become master over thyself and master also of thine own virtues. Formerly they were thy masters; but they are only entitled to be thy tools amongst other tools. Thou shouldst obtain power over thy pro and contra, and learn how to put them forth and withdraw them again in accordance with thy higher purpose. Thou shouldst learn how to take the proper perspective of every valuation—the shifting, distortion, and apparent teleology of the horizons and everything[Pg 10] that belongs to perspective; also the amount of stupidity which opposite values involve, and all the intellectual loss with which every pro and every contra has to be paid for. Thou shouldst learn how much necessary injustice there is in every for and against, injustice as inseparable from life, and life itself as conditioned by the perspective and its injustice. Above all thou shouldst see clearly where the injustice is always greatest:—namely, where life has developed most punily, restrictedly, necessitously, and incipiently, and yet cannot help regarding itself as the purpose and standard of things, and for the sake of self-preservation, secretly, basely, and continuously wasting away and calling in question the higher, greater, and richer,—thou shouldst see clearly the problem of gradation of rank, and how power and right and amplitude of perspective grow up together. Thou shouldst——" But enough; the free spirit knows henceforth which "thou shalt" he has obeyed, and also what he can now do, what he only now—may do....

About this time, it might finally happen, under the sudden insights of still unsettled and changing health, that the mystery of that great liberation begins to reveal itself to the free, and ever freer, spirit—this mystery that had previously remained obscure, questionable, and almost intangible in his memory. If for a long time he barely dared to ask himself, "Why so separate? So alone? Denying everything that I valued? Denying respect itself? Why this hatred, this suspicion, this harshness toward my own virtues?"—he now dares to ask those questions aloud, and already hears something like an answer to them—"You should become the master of yourself and also the master of your own virtues. Previously, they were your masters; but they should only be your tools among other tools. You should gain control over your pros and cons and learn how to present and withdraw them in accordance with your higher purpose. You should learn to take the right perspective on every valuation—the shifting, distortion, and apparent purpose of the horizons and everything that belongs to perspective; also the amount of foolishness that opposing values involve, and all the intellectual cost that comes with every pro and every con. You should understand how much necessary injustice exists in every for and against, injustice that is inseparable from life, and life itself as conditioned by perspective and its injustices. Above all, you should clearly see where the injustice is always greatest:—namely, where life has developed most miserably, restrictively, and must inescapably regard itself as the purpose and standard of things, and for the sake of self-preservation, secretly, basely, and continuously wasting away and questioning the higher, greater, and richer—you should clearly see the problem of hierarchy and how power, right, and breadth of perspective grow together. You should——" But enough; the free spirit knows henceforth which "you shall" he has obeyed, and also what he can now do, what he only now—may do....

7.

7.

Thus doth the free spirit answer himself with regard to the riddle of emancipation, and ends therewith, while he generalises his case, in order thus to decide with regard to his experience. "As it has happened to me," he says to himself, "so must it happen to every one in whom a mission seeks to embody itself and to 'come into the world.'" The secret power and necessity of this mission will operate in and upon the destined individuals like[Pg 11] an unconscious pregnancy,—long before they have had the mission itself in view and have known its name. Our destiny rules over us, even when we are not yet aware of it; it is the future that makes laws for our to-day. Granted that it is the problem of the gradations of rank, of which we may say that it is our problem, we free spirits; now only in the midday of our life do we first understand what preparations, detours, tests, experiments, and disguises the problem needed, before it was permitted to rise before us, and how we had first to experience the most manifold and opposing conditions of distress and happiness in soul and body, as adventurers and circumnavigators of the inner world called "man," as surveyors of all the "higher" and the "one-above-another," also called "man"—penetrating everywhere, almost without fear, rejecting nothing, losing nothing, tasting everything, cleansing everything from all that is accidental, and, as it were, sifting it out—until at last we could say, we free spirits, "Here—a new problem! Here a long ladder, the rungs of which we ourselves have sat upon and mounted,—which we ourselves at some time have been! Here a higher place, a lower place, an under-us, an immeasurably long order, a hierarchy which we see; here—our problem!"

Thus the free spirit responds to himself regarding the puzzle of freedom, concluding while he generalizes his situation to clarify his experiences. "What has happened to me," he tells himself, "must also happen to everyone who has a mission that seeks to manifest and 'come into the world.'" The secret force and inevitability of this mission will affect the destined individuals like[Pg 11] an unacknowledged pregnancy—long before they even consider the mission or recognize its name. Our destiny governs us, even when we're not aware of it; the future sets the rules for our present. Assuming it is the problem of the gradations of rank, which we can claim as our problem, we free spirits only in the peak of our lives come to realize what preparations, detours, tests, experiments, and disguises this problem required before it was allowed to present itself to us. We had to first endure the most diverse and conflicting experiences of suffering and joy in mind and body, as explorers and navigators of the inner world known as "man," as observers of all the "higher" and the "one-above-another," also referred to as "man"—penetrating everywhere, nearly without fear, accepting nothing, losing nothing, experiencing everything, cleansing everything of the incidental, and, in a sense, filtering it out—until we could finally state, we free spirits, "Here—a new problem! Here’s a long ladder, the rungs of which we have climbed and ascended ourselves—which we have at some point been! Here is a higher place, a lower place, an under-us, an infinitely long order, a hierarchy that we see; here—our problem!"

8.

8.

No psychologist or augur will be in doubt for a moment as to what stage of the development just described the following book belongs (or is assigned[Pg 12] to). But where are these psychologists nowadays? In France, certainly; perhaps in Russia; assuredly not in Germany. Reasons are not lacking why the present-day Germans could still even count this as an honour to them—bad enough, surely, for one who in this respect is un-German in disposition and constitution! This German book, which has been able to find readers in a wide circle of countries and nations—it has been about ten years going its rounds—and must understand some sort of music and piping art, by means of which even coy foreign ears are seduced into listening,—it is precisely in Germany that this book has been most negligently read, and worst listened to; what is the reason?" It demands too much, "I have been told," it appeals to men free from the pressure of coarse duties, it wants refined and fastidious senses, it needs superfluity—superfluity of time, of clearness of sky and heart, of otium in the boldest sense of the term:—purely good things, which we Germans of to-day do not possess and therefore cannot give." After such a polite answer my philosophy advises me to be silent and not to question further; besides, in certain cases, as the proverb points out, one only remains a philosopher by being—silent.[1]

No psychologist or soothsayer will have any doubt about what stage of development the following book fits into (or is assigned[Pg 12]). But where are those psychologists now? Definitely in France; maybe in Russia; surely not in Germany. There are plenty of reasons why present-day Germans could even consider this an honor for them—certainly not great for someone who is, in this regard, un-German in both mindset and nature! This German book, which has been able to reach readers across many countries and cultures—it’s been circulating for about ten years—and must have some sort of musical quality or charm that even reluctant foreign ears find hard to resist, is ironically the least read and listened to in Germany; what’s the reason?" It requires too much, "I've been told," it appeals to people unburdened by heavy responsibilities, it needs refined and discerning senses, it requires abundance—abundance of time, of clarity of mind and spirit, of otium in the boldest sense of the term:—purely good things that we Germans today do not have and therefore cannot provide." After such a polite response, my philosophy tells me to stay quiet and not ask further questions; besides, in certain situations, as the saying goes, one remains a philosopher only by being—silent.[1]

NICE, Spring 1886.

NICE, Spring 1886.


[1] An allusion to the mediæval Latin distich:

[1] A reference to the medieval Latin couplet:

O si tacuisses,
Philosophus mansisses.—J.M.K.

O si tacuisses,
Philosopher mansisses.—J.M.K.


HUMAN, ALL-TOO-HUMAN.


FIRST DIVISION.

FIRST AND LAST THINGS.

1.

1.

Chemistry of Ideas and Sensations.—Philosophical problems adopt in almost all matters the same form of question as they did two thousand years ago; how can anything spring from its opposite? for instance, reason out of unreason, the sentient out of the dead, logic out of unlogic, disinterested contemplation out of covetous willing, life for others out of egoism, truth out of error? Metaphysical philosophy has helped itself over those difficulties hitherto by denying the origin of one thing in another, and assuming a miraculous origin for more highly valued things, immediately out of the kernel and essence of the "thing in itself." Historical philosophy, on the contrary, which is no longer to be thought of as separate from physical science, the youngest of all philosophical methods, has ascertained in single cases (and presumably this will happen in everything)[Pg 14] that there are no opposites except in the usual exaggeration of the popular or metaphysical point of view, and that an error of reason lies at the bottom of the opposition: according to this explanation, strictly understood, there is neither an unegoistical action nor an entirely disinterested point of view, they are both only sublimations in which the fundamental element appears almost evaporated, and is only to be discovered by the closest observation. All that we require, and which can only be given us by the present advance of the single sciences, is a chemistry of the moral, religious, æsthetic ideas and sentiments, as also of those emotions which we experience in ourselves both in the great and in the small phases of social and intellectual intercourse, and even in solitude; but what if this chemistry should result in the fact that also in this case the most beautiful colours have been obtained from base, even despised materials? Would many be inclined to pursue such examinations? Humanity likes to put all questions as to origin and beginning out of its mind; must one not be almost dehumanised to feel a contrary tendency in one's self?

Chemistry of Ideas and Feelings.—Philosophical problems still ask the same questions they did two thousand years ago: how can something come from its opposite? For example, how does reason come from unreason, feeling from the lifeless, logic from illogic, disinterested reflection from selfish desire, life for others from egoism, or truth from error? Metaphysical philosophy has historically handled these challenges by denying that one thing arises from another and assuming a miraculous origin for the things we value more, coming straight from the core essence of the “thing in itself.” On the other hand, historical philosophy, which can no longer be seen as separate from physical science, the newest of all philosophical methods, has found in specific cases (and likely will in all cases)[Pg 14] that opposites exist only in the typical exaggeration of popular or metaphysical perspectives, and that a fundamental error in reason underlies this opposition: according to this interpretation, when understood strictly, there’s no such thing as a completely selfless action or a fully disinterested viewpoint; they are just distortions where the underlying element seems almost evaporated and can only be revealed through careful observation. What we need, which can only come from the advancements in individual sciences, is a chemistry of moral, religious, and aesthetic ideas and feelings, as well as the emotions we experience both in significant and trivial aspects of social and intellectual interactions, and even in solitude; but what if this chemistry shows that even in this case, the most beautiful outcomes come from lowly, perhaps despised materials? Would many people be willing to engage in such explorations? Humanity tends to avoid questions about origin and existence; must one almost lose their humanity to feel a different urge within oneself?

2.

2.

Inherited Faults of Philosophers.—All philosophers have the common fault that they start from man in his present state and hope to attain their end by an analysis of him. Unconsciously they look upon "man" as an cetema Veritas, as a thing unchangeable in all commotion, as a sure[Pg 15] standard of things. But everything that the philosopher says about man is really nothing more than testimony about the man of a very limited space of time. A lack of the historical sense is the hereditary fault of all philosophers; many, indeed, unconsciously mistake the very latest variety of man, such as has arisen under the influence of certain religions, certain political events, for the permanent form from which one must set out. They will not learn that man has developed, that his faculty of knowledge has developed also; whilst for some of them the entire world is spun out of this faculty of knowledge. Now everything essential in human development happened in pre-historic times, long before those four thousand years which we know something of; man may not have changed much during this time. But the philosopher sees "instincts" in the present man and takes it for granted that this is one of the unalterable facts of mankind, and, consequently, can furnish a key to the understanding of the world; the entire teleology is so constructed that man of the last four thousand years is spoken of as an eternal being, towards which all things in the world have from the beginning a natural direction. But everything has evolved; there are no eternal facts, as there are likewise no absolute truths. Therefore, historical philosophising is henceforth necessary, and with it the virtue of diffidence.

Philosophers' Inherited Flaws.—All philosophers share the flaw of starting with humans as they are now and hoping to reach their goals through analysis of them. Unknowingly, they view "man" as an eternal truth, as something that doesn’t change amid turmoil, as a reliable[Pg 15] standard for everything. Yet, what philosophers say about man is really just a reflection of people from a very limited period. A lack of historical perspective is the common flaw among all philosophers; many, in fact, mistakenly believe that the most recent version of humanity, shaped by certain religions and political events, represents a permanent starting point. They fail to recognize that humans have evolved, and so has their capacity for knowledge; for some, the entire universe revolves around this capacity for knowledge. Most significant developments in human history occurred in prehistoric times, long before the last four thousand years we know something about; humans may not have changed much in that time. However, the philosopher sees "instincts" in modern humans and assumes this is an unchangeable aspect of humanity, thereby providing a key to understanding the world; the entire teleological view is structured so that the man of the last four thousand years is treated as an eternal being, toward which everything in the world has had a natural tendency from the beginning. But everything has changed; there are no eternal facts, just as there are no absolute truths. Therefore, historical philosophy is now essential, along with the virtue of humility.

3.

3.

Appreciation of Unpretentious Truths.—It is a mark of a higher culture to value the[Pg 16] little unpretentious truths, which have been found by means of strict method, more highly than the joy-diffusing and dazzling errors which spring from metaphysical and artistic times and peoples. First of all one has scorn on the lips for the former, as if here nothing could have equal privileges with anything else, so unassuming, simple, bashful, apparently discouraging are they, so beautiful, stately, intoxicating, perhaps even animating, are the others. But the hardly attained, the certain, the lasting, and therefore of great consequence for all wider knowledge, is still the higher; to keep one's self to that is manly and shows bravery, simplicity, and forbearance. Gradually not only single individuals but the whole of mankind will be raised to this manliness, when it has at last accustomed itself to the higher appreciation of durable, lasting knowledge, and has lost all belief in inspiration and the miraculous communication of truths. Respecters of forms, certainly, with their standard of the beautiful and noble, will first of all have good reasons for mockery, as soon as the appreciation of unpretentious truths, and the scientific spirit, begin to obtain the mastery; but only because their eye has either not yet recognised the charm of the simplest form, or because men educated in that spirit are not yet completely and inwardly saturated by it, so that they still thoughtlessly imitate old forms (and badly enough, as one does who no longer cares much about the matter). Formerly the spirit was not occupied with strict thought, its earnestness then lay in the spinning out of symbols and forms. This is[Pg 17] changed; that earnestness in the symbolical has become the mark of a lower culture. As our arts themselves grow evermore intellectual, our senses more spiritual, and as, for instance, people now judge concerning what sounds well to the senses quite differently from how they did a hundred years ago, so the forms of our life grow ever more spiritual, to the eye of older ages perhaps uglier, but only because it is incapable of perceiving how the kingdom of the inward, spiritual beauty constantly grows deeper and wider, and to what extent the inner intellectual look may be of more importance to us all than the most beautiful bodily frame and the noblest architectural structure.

Appreciating Simple Truths.—It's a sign of a more advanced culture to value the[Pg 16] simple, unpretentious truths discovered through rigorous methods more than the captivating and complex errors that arise from philosophical and artistic eras. At first, there's a tendency to look down on these basic truths, as if nothing could be as important as these humble, straightforward, and seemingly discouraging ideas, while the other truths seem so beautiful, grand, and possibly inspiring. However, the hard-won, certain, and lasting truths are far more significant for our broader understanding; sticking to them shows strength, simplicity, and patience. Gradually, not just individuals but all of humanity will grow to appreciate this strength when it finally learns to value enduring knowledge over myths of inspiration and miraculous truths. Those who admire forms, certainly, will still find reasons to mock when the appreciation of unpretentious truths and the scientific mindset take hold; but this is only because their perspective hasn't yet recognized the appeal of the simplest form, or because those educated in that mindset aren't fully immersed in it yet and still thoughtlessly imitate outdated forms (and do so poorly, like someone who no longer cares much). In the past, the spirit was not focused on strict reasoning; its seriousness came from elaborating on symbols and forms. This is[Pg 17] no longer the case; that seriousness in symbolism is now characteristic of a lower culture. As our arts become increasingly intellectual, and our senses more attuned to the spiritual, and just as people now perceive what pleases the senses differently than they did a century ago, the forms of our lives become ever more spiritual, perhaps seen as uglier by those from older times, but only because they can't see how the realm of inner, spiritual beauty continues to grow deeper and broader, and how the inner intellectual perspective may matter to us all more than the most beautiful physical appearance or the grandest architectural design.

4.

4.

Astrology and the Like.—It is probable that the objects of religious, moral, æsthetic and logical sentiment likewise belong only to the surface of things, while man willingly believes that here, at least, he has touched the heart of the world; he deceives himself, because those things enrapture him so profoundly, and make him so profoundly unhappy, and he therefore shows the same pride here as in astrology. For astrology believes that the firmament moves round the destiny of man; the moral man, however, takes it for granted that what he has essentially at heart must also be the essence and heart of things.

Astrology and similar topics.—It’s likely that the objects of religious, moral, aesthetic, and logical feelings also only scratch the surface of reality, while people are quick to believe that this is where they’ve truly connected with the core of the world. They’re fooling themselves because these things captivate them deeply and also make them profoundly unhappy, so they display the same kind of pride here as they do in astrology. Astrology assumes that the heavens revolve around human destiny; however, moral individuals take for granted that what they hold dear must also represent the essence and core of everything.

5.

5.

Misunderstanding of Dreams.—In the ages of a rude and primitive civilisation man believed[Pg 18] that in dreams he became acquainted with a second actual world; herein lies the origin of all metaphysics. Without dreams there could have been found no reason for a division of the world. The distinction, too, between soul and body is connected with the most ancient comprehension of dreams, also the supposition of an imaginary soul-body, therefore the origin of all belief in spirits, and probably also the belief in gods. "The dead continues to live, for he appears to the living in a dream": thus men reasoned of old for thousands and thousands of years.

Misinterpretation of Dreams.—In the early days of a rough and primitive civilization, people believed[Pg 18] that dreams allowed them to connect with a second real world; this belief is at the root of all metaphysics. Without dreams, there would have been no reason to split the world into different aspects. The difference between the soul and the body is also linked to the earliest understanding of dreams, as well as the idea of an imaginary soul-body, which leads to the belief in spirits, and probably also in gods. "The dead continue to live, for they appear to the living in a dream": this is how people reasoned for thousands and thousands of years.

6.

6.

The Scientific Spirit Partially But Not Wholly Powerful.—The smallest subdivisions of science taken separately are dealt with purely in relation to themselves,—the general, great sciences, on the contrary, regarded as a whole, call up the question—certainly a very non-objective one—"Wherefore? To what end?" It is this utilitarian consideration which causes them to be dealt with less impersonally when taken as a whole than when considered in their various parts. In philosophy, above all, as the apex of the entire, pyramid of science, the question as to the utility of knowledge is involuntarily brought forward, and every philosophy has the unconscious intention of ascribing to it the greatest usefulness. For this reason there is so much high-flying metaphysics in all philosophies and such a shyness of the apparently unimportant solutions of physics; for[Pg 19] the importance of knowledge for life must appear as great as possible. Here is the antagonism between the separate provinces of science and philosophy. The latter desires, what art does, to give the greatest possible depth and meaning to life and actions; in the former one seeks knowledge and nothing further, whatever may emerge thereby. So far there has been no philosopher in whose hands philosophy has not grown into an apology for knowledge; on this point, at least, every one is an optimist, that the greatest usefulness must be ascribed to knowledge. They are all tyrannised over by logic, and this is optimism—in its essence.

The Scientific Spirit: Partially but Not Entirely Powerful.—The smallest parts of science are looked at individually, while the big, overarching sciences raise questions—certainly very subjective ones—like, "Why? What’s the purpose?" This practical focus makes them feel less objective when viewed as a whole compared to when they’re examined in their individual components. In philosophy, especially as the peak of the entire science pyramid, the usefulness of knowledge inevitably comes up, and every philosophy seems to unconsciously aim to highlight its greatest value. That’s why there’s so much grand metaphysics in all philosophies and such a reluctance to address the seemingly trivial solutions of physics; because[Pg 19] the significance of knowledge for life must appear as substantial as possible. Here lies the conflict between the distinct fields of science and philosophy. The latter seeks, much like art, to add depth and meaning to life and actions; while in the former, the pursuit is simply knowledge, regardless of other outcomes. So far, there hasn’t been a philosopher who hasn’t turned philosophy into a defense of knowledge; on this issue, at least, everyone is optimistic that knowledge must hold great value. They are all dominated by logic, which is basically a form of optimism.

7.

7.

The Kill-joy in Science.—Philosophy separated from science when it asked the question, "Which is the knowledge of the world and of life which enables man to live most happily?" This happened in the Socratic schools; the veins of scientific investigation were bound up by the point of view of happiness,—and are so still.

The Fun-Sucker in Science.—Philosophy split from science when it posed the question, "What kind of knowledge about the world and life allows people to live the happiest?" This took place in the Socratic schools; the roots of scientific inquiry became restricted by the perspective of happiness,—and still are.

8.

8.

Pneumatic Explanation of Nature.—Metaphysics explains the writing of Nature, so to speak, pneumatically, as the Church and her learned men formerly did with the Bible. A great deal of understanding is required to apply to Nature the same method of strict interpretation as the philologists have now established for all books[Pg 20] with the intention of clearly understanding what the text means, but not suspecting a double sense or even taking it for granted. Just, however, as with regard to books, the bad art of interpretation is by no means overcome, and in the most cultivated society one still constantly comes across the remains of allegorical and mystic interpretation, so it is also with regard to Nature, indeed it is even much worse.

Pneumatic Explanation of Nature.—Metaphysics interprets Nature's writing in a way similar to how the Church and its scholars used to approach the Bible. It takes a lot of insight to apply the same rigorous interpretation methods that philologists have established for all texts[Pg 20], aiming for a clear understanding of the text without assuming a hidden meaning or taking it for granted. Just like with books, poor interpretation skills still persist, and even in the most educated societies, you frequently encounter remnants of allegorical and mystical readings. This is also true for Nature, and in fact, it's often much worse.

9.

9.

The Metaphysical World.—It is true that there might be a metaphysical world; the absolute possibility of it is hardly to be disputed. We look at everything through the human head and cannot cut this head off; while the question remains, What would be left of the world if it had been cut off? This is a purely scientific problem, and one not very likely to trouble mankind; but everything which has hitherto made metaphysical suppositions valuable, terrible, delightful for man, what has produced them, is passion, error, and self-deception; the very worst methods of knowledge, not the best, have taught belief therein. When these methods have been discovered as the foundation of all existing religions and metaphysics, they have been refuted. Then there still always remains that possibility; but there is nothing to be done with it, much less is it possible to let happiness, salvation, and life depend on the spider-thread of such a possibility. For nothing could be said of the metaphysical world but that it would be a different condition, a condition[Pg 21] inaccessible and incomprehensible to us; it would be a thing of negative qualities. Were the existence of such a world ever so well proved, the fact would nevertheless remain that it would be precisely the most irrelevant of all forms of knowledge: more irrelevant than the knowledge of the chemical analysis of water to the sailor in danger in a storm.

The Metaphysical Realm.—It’s possible that there could be a metaphysical world; the idea itself is hard to dispute. We perceive everything through our human perspective and can't remove that perspective; meanwhile, the question is, what would the world look like without it? This is purely a scientific problem and unlikely to concern most people; however, everything that has made metaphysical ideas valuable, terrible, delightful to humanity has come from passion, error, and self-deception. The worst methods of understanding, rather than the best, have led us to believe in these ideas. Once these methods are revealed as the basis of all existing religions and metaphysics, they have been challenged. Yet, that possibility always remains; but it’s not something we can act on, let alone build happiness, salvation, and life upon the fragile thread of such a possibility. All that could be said about the metaphysical world is that it would be a different state, one that is[Pg 21] unreachable and beyond our comprehension; it would consist of negative attributes. Even if the existence of such a world were firmly established, it would still be the most irrelevant form of knowledge possible: more irrelevant than understanding the chemical makeup of water to a sailor caught in a storm.

10.

10.

The Harmlessness of Metaphysics in the Future.—Directly the origins of religion, art, and morals have been so described that one can perfectly explain them without having recourse to metaphysical concepts at the beginning and in the course of the path, the strongest interest in the purely theoretical problem of the "thing-in-itself" and the "phenomenon" ceases. For however it may be here, with religion, art, and morals we do not touch the "essence of the world in itself"; we are in the domain of representation, no "intuition" can carry us further. With the greatest calmness we shall leave the question as to how our own conception of the world can differ so widely from the revealed essence of the world, to physiology and the history of the evolution of organisms and ideas.

The Harmlessness of Metaphysics in the Future.—Once the origins of religion, art, and morals have been described in a way that allows for a complete explanation without relying on metaphysical concepts at the start or during the process, the strong interest in the purely theoretical issue of the "thing-in-itself" and the "phenomenon" fades away. Because when it comes to religion, art, and morals, we are not engaging with the "essence of the world in itself"; we are dealing with representation, and no "intuition" can take us further. We will calmly leave the question of why our understanding of the world can differ so greatly from the revealed essence of the world to physiology and the study of the evolution of organisms and ideas.

11.

11.

Language As a Presumptive Science.—The importance of language for the development of culture lies in the fact that in language man has[Pg 22] placed a world of his own beside the other, a position which he deemed so fixed that he might therefrom lift the rest of the world off its hinges, and make himself master of it. Inasmuch as man has believed in the ideas and names of things as æternæ veritates for a great length of time, he has acquired that pride by which he has raised himself above the animal; he really thought that in language he possessed the knowledge of the world. The maker of language was not modest enough to think that he only gave designations to things, he believed rather that with his words he expressed the widest knowledge of the things; in reality language is the first step in the endeavour after science. Here also it is belief in ascertained truth, from which the mightiest sources of strength have flowed. Much later—only now—it is dawning upon men that they have propagated a tremendous error in their belief in language. Fortunately it is now too late to reverse the development of reason, which is founded upon that belief. Logic, also, is founded upon suppositions to which nothing in the actual world corresponds,—for instance, on the supposition of the equality of things, and the identity of the same thing at different points of time,—but that particular science arose out of the contrary belief (that such things really existed in the actual world). It is the same with mathematics, which would certainly not have arisen if it had been known from the beginning that in Nature there are no exactly straight lines, no real circle, no absolute standard of size.

Language as a Potential Science.—The significance of language for cultural development stems from the fact that humans have created a world of their own alongside the existing one, a belief so strong that it made them feel capable of reshaping the entire world and controlling it. Since humanity has viewed the ideas and names of things as æternæ veritates for a long time, they have developed a pride that elevates them above animals; they genuinely believed that through language, they held the knowledge of the world. The creator of language wasn't humble enough to see their role as merely naming things; instead, they thought their words conveyed the broadest understanding of those things. In truth, language is the initial step in the pursuit of science. Here too, it is a belief in established truths that has led to immense sources of strength. Much later—only now—it’s becoming clear that people have spread a significant misconception regarding language. Luckily, it's now too late to undo the development of reason that is built upon that belief. Logic, too, is based on assumptions that have no actual counterparts in the real world—for example, the assumption of the equality of things and the sameness of an object at different times—but that particular branch of study emerged from the opposing belief (that such things genuinely existed in reality). The same goes for mathematics, which certainly wouldn't have come about if it had been understood from the start that there are no perfectly straight lines, no true circles, and no absolute standards of measurement in Nature.

12.

12.

Dream and Culture.—The function of the brain which is most influenced by sleep is the memory; not that it entirely ceases; but it is brought back to a condition of imperfection, such as everyone may have experienced in pre-historic times, whether asleep or awake. Arbitrary and confused as it is, it constantly confounds things on the ground of the most fleeting resemblances; but with the same arbitrariness and confusion the ancients invented their mythologies, and even at the present day travellers are accustomed to remark how prone the savage is to forgetfulness, how, after a short tension of memory, his mind begins to sway here and there from sheer weariness and gives forth lies and nonsense. But in dreams we all resemble the savage; bad recognition and erroneous comparisons are the reasons of the bad conclusions, of which we are guilty in dreams: so that, when we clearly recollect what we have dreamt, we are alarmed at ourselves at harbouring so much foolishness within us. The perfect distinctness of all dream-representations, which pre-suppose absolute faith in their reality, recall the conditions that appertain, to primitive man, in whom hallucination was extraordinarily frequent, and sometimes simultaneously seized entire communities, entire nations. Therefore, in sleep and in dreams we once more carry out the task of early humanity.

Dreams and Culture.—The part of the brain most affected by sleep is memory; it doesn’t stop completely, but it returns to a flawed state, something we’ve all likely experienced throughout history, whether asleep or awake. As arbitrary and confused as it is, it constantly mixes things up based on the most fleeting similarities; yet, with the same randomness and confusion, ancient people created their mythologies. Even today, travelers often observe how prone some indigenous people are to forgetfulness, how, after a brief mental effort, their minds begin to drift due to sheer fatigue, producing lies and nonsense. In dreams, we all resemble these individuals; poor recognition and faulty comparisons lead to the ridiculous conclusions we reach in our dreams: so that when we clearly recall what we have dreamt, we are often shocked to find such foolishness within us. The clear vividness of all dream images, which implies a complete belief in their reality, recalls the conditions relevant to early humans, for whom hallucinations occurred often, sometimes affecting whole communities or nations simultaneously. Thus, in sleep and dreams, we once again engage in the tasks of early humanity.

13.

13.

The Logic of Dreams.—In sleep our nervous system is perpetually excited by numerous inner occurrences; nearly all the organs are disjointed and in a state of activity, the blood runs its turbulent course, the position of the sleeper causes pressure on certain limbs, his coverings influence his sensations in various ways, the stomach digests and by its movements it disturbs other organs, the intestines writhe, the position of the head occasions unaccustomed play of muscles, the feet, unshod, not pressing upon the floor with the soles, occasion the feeling of the unaccustomed just as does the different clothing of the whole body: all this, according to its daily change and extent, excites by its extraordinariness the entire system to the very functions of the brain, and thus there are a hundred occasions for the spirit to be surprised and to seek for the reasons of this excitation;—the dream, however, is the seeking and representing of the causes of those excited sensations,—that is, of the supposed causes. A person who, for instance, binds his feet with two straps will perhaps dream that two serpents are coiling round his feet; this is first hypothesis, then a belief, with an accompanying mental picture and interpretation—" These serpents must be the causa of those sensations which I, the sleeper, experience,"—so decides the mind of the sleeper. The immediate past, so disclosed, becomes to him the present through his excited imagination. Thus every one knows from experience how quickly the[Pg 25] dreamer weaves into his dream a loud sound that he hears, such as the ringing of bells or the firing of cannon, that is to say, explains it from afterwards so that he first thinks he experiences the producing circumstances and then that sound. But how does it happen that the mind of the dreamer is always so mistaken, while the same mind when awake is accustomed to be so temperate, careful, and sceptical with regard to its hypotheses? so that the first random hypothesis for the explanation of a feeling suffices for him to believe immediately in its truth? (For in dreaming we believe in the dream as if it were a reality, i.e. we think our hypothesis completely proved.) I hold, that as man now still reasons in dreams, so men reasoned also when awake through thousands of years; the first causa which occurred to the mind to explain anything that required an explanation, was sufficient and stood for truth. (Thus, according to travellers' tales, savages still do to this very day.) This ancient element in human nature still manifests itself in our dreams, for it is the foundation upon which the higher reason has developed and still develops in every individual; the dream carries us back into remote conditions of human culture, and provides a ready means of understanding them better. Dream-thinking is now so easy to us because during immense periods of human development we have been so well drilled in this form of fantastic and cheap explanation, by means of the first agreeable notions. In so far, dreaming is a recreation for the brain, which by day has to[Pg 26] satisfy the stern demands of thought, as they are laid down by the higher culture. We can at once discern an allied process even in our awakened state, as the door and ante-room of the dream. If we shut our eyes, the brain produces a number of impressions of light and colour, probably as a kind of after-play and echo of all those effects of light which crowd in upon it by day. Now, however, the understanding, together with the imagination, instantly works up this play of colour, shapeless in itself, into definite figures, forms, landscapes, and animated groups. The actual accompanying process thereby is again a kind of conclusion from the effect to the cause: since the mind asks, "Whence come these impressions of light and colour?" it supposes those figures and forms as causes; it takes them for the origin of those colours and lights, because in the daytime, with open eyes, it is accustomed to find a producing cause for every colour, every effect of light. Here, therefore, the imagination constantly places pictures before the mind, since it supports itself on the visual impressions of the day in their production, and the dream-imagination does just the same thing,—that is, the supposed cause is deduced from the effect and represented after the effect; all this happens with extraordinary rapidity, so that here, as with the conjuror, a confusion of judgment may arise and a sequence may look like something simultaneous, or even like a reversed sequence. From these circumstances we may gather how lately the more acute logical thinking, the strict discrimination of cause and effect has[Pg 27] been developed, when our reasoning and understanding faculties still involuntarily hark back to those primitive forms of deduction, and when we pass about half our life in this condition. The poet, too, and the artist assign causes for their moods and conditions which are by no means the true ones; in this they recall an older humanity and can assist us to the understanding of it.

The Logic of Dreams.—When we sleep, our nervous system is constantly stimulated by many internal events; almost all our organs are disjointed and active, blood flows chaotically, the sleeper's position puts pressure on certain limbs, their coverings affect their sensations in different ways, the stomach digests and moves, disturbing other organs, the intestines twist, and the position of the head causes unusual muscle movements. Bare feet, not pressing against the floor, create unfamiliar feelings, just like different clothing can do: all these daily shifts and variations excite the entire system, even affecting brain function, leading the mind to be surprised and search for the reasons behind this stimulation. The dream, then, is the search for and representation of the causes of those stimulated sensations — that is, of the assumed causes. For example, someone who tightly binds their feet with straps might dream of two snakes coiling around them; this begins as a hypothesis, then becomes a belief, accompanied by a mental image and interpretation — "These snakes must be the causa of the sensations I, the sleeper, am feeling," which the sleeper's mind concludes. The recent past, thus revealed, becomes the present through their active imagination. Everyone knows how quickly a[Pg 25] dreamer can weave into their dream a loud sound they hear, like the ringing of bells or the firing of cannons, essentially explaining it afterwards so they first believe they are experiencing the causing circumstances and then the sound. But why does the dreamer's mind always get it wrong while the same mind, when awake, tends to be so careful, cautious, and skeptical about its hypotheses? Why does the first random assumption about a feeling suffice for them to immediately accept it as truth? (In dreams, we accept the dream as if it were real, i.e. we consider our hypothesis fully proven.) I believe that just as people still reason in dreams, they also reasoned when awake for thousands of years; the first causa that came to mind to explain something needing an explanation was enough and was accepted as truth. (According to travelers' tales, this is still done by savages today.) This ancient aspect of human nature shows itself in our dreams, as it is the basis on which higher reasoning has developed and continues to develop in each individual; dreams take us back to earlier stages of human culture and help us understand them better. Dream-thinking is now so effortless for us because, over vast stretches of human development, we've been well trained in this form of imaginative and simple explanation, using initial pleasant ideas. In this way, dreaming serves as a break for the brain, which during the day has to[Pg 26] meet the strict demands of thought set by higher culture. We can easily identify a similar process even while awake, as the doorway and ante-room of the dream. When we close our eyes, the brain generates various impressions of light and color, likely as a kind of afterplay and echo of all the light effects it encounters during the day. Now, however, understanding, along with imagination, quickly transforms this shapeless play of color into clear images, shapes, landscapes, and animated scenes. The accompanying process is again a sort of conclusion from effect to cause: since the mind asks, "Where do these impressions of light and color come from?" it assumes those figures and shapes as causes; it takes them to be the source of those colors and lights because, during the day with open eyes, it expects to find a producing cause for every color, every light effect. Here, then, the imagination continually presents images to the mind, as it relies on the visual impressions from the day, and the dream-imagination does precisely the same — that is, the supposed cause is inferred from the effect and represented post-effect; all of this occurs at lightning speed, creating a potential for confusion similar to that of a magician, making a sequence appear simultaneous or even reversed. From this, we can see how recently sharper logical thinking and strict discrimination of cause and effect have emerged, when our reasoning and understanding faculties still involuntarily revert to those primitive forms of deduction, and when we spend about half our lives in this state. Poets and artists also assign causes to their emotions and states that are not at all accurate; in this, they recall an earlier humanity and can aid us in understanding it.

14.

14.

Co-echoing.—All stronger moods bring with them a co-echoing of kindred sensations and moods, they grub up the memory, so to speak. Along with them something within us remembers and becomes conscious of similar conditions and their origin. Thus there are formed quick habitual connections of feelings and thoughts, which eventually, when they follow each other with lightning speed, are no longer felt as complexes but as unities. In this sense one speaks of the moral feeling, of the religious feeling, as if they were absolute unities: in reality they are streams with a hundred sources and tributaries. Here also, as so often happens, the unity of the word is no security for the unity of the thing.

Co-reflecting.—All stronger emotions bring with them a resonance of related feelings and moods; they dredge up memories, so to speak. Along with these emotions, something within us recalls and becomes aware of similar experiences and their origins. This creates quick, habitual connections between feelings and thoughts, which, when they occur in rapid succession, are no longer perceived as separate complexes but as unities. In this sense, we talk about moral feelings or religious feelings as if they were absolute unities; in reality, they are streams with many sources and tributaries. Here, as often occurs, the unity of a word does not guarantee the unity of the concept.

15.

15.

No Internal and External in the World.—As Democritus transferred the concepts "above" and "below" to endless space where they have no sense, so philosophers in[Pg 28] general have transferred the concepts "Internal" and "External" to the essence and appearance of the world; they think that with deep feelings one can penetrate deeply into the internal and approach the heart of Nature. But these feelings are only deep in so far as along with them, barely noticeable, certain complicated groups of thoughts, which we call deep, are regularly excited; a feeling is deep because we think that the accompanying thought is deep. But the "deep" thought can nevertheless be very far from the truth, as, for instance, every metaphysical one; if one take away from the deep feeling the commingled elements of thought, then the strong feeling remains, and this guarantees nothing for knowledge but itself, just as strong faith proves only its strength and not the truth of what is believed in.

No Internal or External in the World.—As Democritus took the ideas of "above" and "below" and applied them to infinite space where they don't really apply, philosophers in [Pg 28] have similarly applied the concepts of "Internal" and "External" to the nature and appearance of the world; they believe that by having deep feelings, one can truly understand the internal and get to the core of Nature. However, these feelings are only deep in that they often come with subtle, complex thoughts, which we label as deep; a feeling is considered deep because we think the associated thought is profound. But that "deep" thought can be very far from the truth, as is the case with many metaphysical ideas; if you strip the deep feeling of its intertwined thought elements, only the strong feeling remains, which doesn't guarantee any knowledge beyond itself, just as strong faith only demonstrates its own strength and not the validity of what is believed.

16.

16.

Phenomenon and Thing-in-itself.—Philosophers are in the habit of setting themselves before life and experience—before that which they call the world of appearance—as before a picture that is once for all unrolled and exhibits unchangeably fixed the same process,—this process, they think, must be rightly interpreted in order to come to a conclusion about the being that produced the picture: about the thing-in-itself, therefore, which is always accustomed to be regarded as sufficient ground for the world of phenomenon. On the other hand, since one always makes the idea of the metaphysical stand definitely as that of th[Pg 29]e unconditioned, consequently also unconditioning, one must directly disown all connection between the unconditioned (the metaphysical world) and the world which is known to us; so that the thing-in-itself should most certainly not appear in the phenomenon, and every conclusion from the former as regards the latter is to be rejected. Both sides overlook the fact that that picture—that which we now call human life and experience—has gradually evolved,—nay, is still in the full process of evolving,—and therefore should not be regarded as a fixed magnitude from which a conclusion about its originator might be deduced (the sufficing cause) or even merely neglected. It is because for thousands of years we have looked into the world with moral, æsthetic, and religious pretensions, with blind inclination, passion, or fear, and have surfeited ourselves in the vices of illogical thought, that this world has gradually become so marvellously motley, terrible, full of meaning and of soul, it has acquired colour—but we were the colourists; the human intellect, on the basis of human needs, of human emotions, has caused this "phenomenon" to appear and has carried its erroneous fundamental conceptions into things. Late, very late, it takes to thinking, and now the world of experience and the thing-in-itself seem to it so extraordinarily different and separated, that it gives up drawing conclusions from the former to the latter—or in a terribly mysterious manner demands the renunciation of our intellect, of our personal will, in order thereby to reach the essential, that one may become essential. Again,[Pg 30] others have collected all the characteristic features of our world of phenomenon,—that is, the idea of the world spun out of intellectual errors and inherited by us,—and instead of accusing the intellect as the offenders, they have laid the blame on the nature of things as being the cause of the hard fact of this very sinister character of the world, and have preached the deliverance from Being. With all these conceptions the constant and laborious process of science (which at last celebrates its greatest triumph in a history of the origin of thought) becomes completed in various ways, the result of which might perhaps run as follows:—"That which we now call the world is the result of a mass of errors and fantasies which arose gradually in the general development of organic being, which are inter-grown with each other, and are now inherited by us as the accumulated treasure of all the past,—as a treasure, for the value of our humanity depends upon it. From this world of representation strict science is really only able to liberate us to a very slight extent—as it is also not at all desirable—inasmuch as it cannot essentially break the power of primitive habits of feeling; but it can gradually elucidate the history of the rise of that world as representation,—and lift us, at least for moments, above and beyond the whole process. Perhaps we shall then recognise that the thing in itself is worth a Homeric laugh; that it seemed so much, indeed everything, and is really empty, namely, empty of meaning."

Phenomenon and the Thing-in-Itself.—Philosophers often position themselves in front of life and experience—what they refer to as the world of appearances—like they would before a picture that has been permanently unfurled and shows a fixed process. They believe this process must be accurately interpreted to draw conclusions about the being that created the picture: about the thing-in-itself, which is typically seen as the foundation for the world of phenomena. However, since the concept of the metaphysical is ideally seen as unconditioned and therefore unconditioning, one must completely reject any connection between the unconditioned (the metaphysical world) and the world we know; hence, the thing-in-itself should definitely not appear in the phenomenon, and any conclusions drawn from the former regarding the latter should be dismissed. Both sides overlook the fact that that picture—what we now call human life and experience—has gradually evolved—and is still evolving—and should not be treated as a fixed entity from which one could infer its originator (the sufficient cause) or be simply disregarded. For thousands of years, we have viewed the world through moral, aesthetic, and religious lenses, driven by blind inclinations, passions, or fears, and have indulged ourselves in the vices of illogical thinking, which has caused the world to become so wonderfully diverse, frightening, meaningful, and soulful. It has acquired color—but we were the ones who added the color; human intellect, based on human needs and emotions, has brought this "phenomenon" to life and has imposed its flawed foundational concepts onto things. Only lately has it started to think, and now the world of experience and the thing-in-itself seem so remarkably different and disconnected that it has stopped trying to draw conclusions from the former to the latter—or, in a perplexingly mysterious way, demands that we renounce our intellect and personal will to thereby reach what is essential, so that one may become essential. Again,[Pg 30] others have gathered all the defining characteristics of our world of phenomena—that is, the idea of the world shaped by intellectual errors and passed down to us—and instead of blaming the intellect as the culprits, they have attributed the sinister aspects of the world to the nature of things and have preached liberation from Being. With all these ideas, the ongoing and painstaking effort of science (which ultimately celebrates its greatest triumph in a history of the origin of thought) reaches completion in various ways, leading to a possible conclusion: "What we now refer to as the world is the result of numerous errors and fantasies that developed gradually in the overall evolution of organic beings, intertwined with one another, and are now inherited by us as the accumulated treasure of the past—treasure, because the value of our humanity depends on it. From this world of representation, strict science can only free us to a very limited extent—and it’s not particularly desirable—since it cannot fundamentally break the hold of primitive emotional habits; but it can gradually clarify the history of the emergence of that world as representation—and help us, at least for moments, rise above and beyond the entire process. Perhaps we will then understand that the thing-in-itself is worth a Homeric laugh; that it seemed like so much, indeed everything, and is actually empty, specifically, empty of meaning."

17.

17.

Metaphysical Explanations.—The young man values metaphysical explanations, because they show him something highly significant in things which he found unpleasant or despicable, and if he is dissatisfied with himself, the feeling becomes lighter when he recognises the innermost world-puzzle or world-misery in that which he so strongly disapproves of in himself. To feel himself less responsible and at the same time to find things more interesting—that seems to him a double benefit for which he has to thank metaphysics. Later on, certainly, he gets distrustful of the whole metaphysical method of explanation; then perhaps it grows clear to him that those results can be obtained equally well and more scientifically in another way: that physical and historical explanations produce the feeling of personal relief to at least the same extent, and that the interest in life and its problems is perhaps still more aroused thereby.

Philosophical Explanations.—The young man appreciates metaphysical explanations because they reveal something deeply meaningful in aspects of life he found unpleasant or contemptible. When he's unhappy with himself, his burdens lighten as he recognizes the complex issues or suffering in the very things he critically judges within himself. This gives him a sense of reduced responsibility while simultaneously making things seem more intriguing—a dual benefit he believes he owes to metaphysics. However, he eventually begins to doubt the entire metaphysical approach to explanation. He may come to understand that similar insights can be achieved just as effectively, and even more scientifically, through other means; that physical and historical explanations can offer just as much personal relief, if not more, and perhaps spark an even greater interest in life and its challenges.

18.

18.

Fundamental Questions of Metaphysics.—When the history of the rise of thought comes to be written, a new light will be thrown on the following statement of a distinguished logician:—"The primordial general law of the cognisant subject consists in the inner necessity of recognising every object in itself in its own nature, as a thing identical with itself, consequently self-existing[Pg 32] and at bottom remaining ever the same and unchangeable: in short, in recognising everything as a substance." Even this law, which is here called "primordial," has evolved: it will some day be shown how gradually this tendency arises in the lower organisms, how the feeble mole-eyes of their organisations at first see only the same thing,—;how then, when the various awakenings of pleasure and displeasure become noticeable, various substances are gradually distinguished, but each with one attribute, i.e. one single relation to such an organism. The first step in logic is the judgment,—the nature of which, according to the decision of the best logicians, consists in belief. At the bottom of all belief lies the sensation of the pleasant or the painful in relation to the sentient subject. A new third sensation as the result of two previous single sensations is the judgment in its simplest form. We organic beings have originally no interest in anything but its relation to us in connection with pleasure and pain. Between the moments (the states of feeling) when we become conscious of this connection, lie moments of rest, of non-feeling; the world and everything is then without interest for us, we notice no change in it (as even now a deeply interested person does not notice when any one passes him). To the plant, things are as a rule tranquil and eternal, everything like itself. From the period of the lower organisms man has inherited the belief that similar things exist (this theory is only contradicted by the matured experience of the most advanced science). The primordial belief of[Pg 33] everything organic from the beginning is perhaps even this, that all the rest of the world is one and immovable. The point furthest removed from those early beginnings of logic is the idea of Causality,—indeed we still really think that all sensations and activities are acts of the free will; when the sentient individual contemplates himself, he regards every sensation, every alteration as something isolated, that is to say, unconditioned and disconnected,—it rises up in us without connection with anything foregoing or following. We are hungry, but do not originally think that the organism must be nourished; the feeling seems to make itself felt without cause and purpose, it isolates itself and regards itself as arbitrary. Therefore, belief in the freedom of the will is an original error of everything organic, as old as the existence of the awakenings of logic in it; the belief in unconditioned substances and similar things is equally a primordial as well as an old error of everything organic. But inasmuch as all metaphysics has concerned itself chiefly with substance and the freedom of will, it may be designated as the science which treats of the fundamental errors of mankind, but treats of them as if they were fundamental truths.

Key Questions of Metaphysics.—When the history of the development of thought is written, it will shed new light on this statement from a prominent logician:—"The basic general law of the aware subject is the inner necessity to recognize every object in itself for what it is, as something that is identical to itself, hence self-existing[Pg 32] and fundamentally unchanging: in short, recognizing everything as a substance." Even this law, referred to as "basic," has evolved: it will eventually be demonstrated how this tendency gradually emerges in simpler organisms, how the rudimentary eyes of their structures initially perceive only the same thing,—; how then, as different feelings of pleasure and pain become evident, various substances are slowly differentiated, but each with one attribute, i.e. one single relation to that organism. The first step in logic is the judgment,—the nature of which, according to leading logicians, is based in belief. At the core of all belief lies the sensation of pleasure or pain in relation to the sentient subject. A new sensation that results from two previous single sensations is judgment in its simplest form. We living beings are originally only concerned with anything in terms of its relationship to us regarding pleasure and pain. Between the moments (the states of feeling) when we become aware of this connection, there are moments of stillness, of not feeling; during those times, the world and everything in it hold no interest for us, and we fail to notice any change (as even now a very preoccupied person fails to notice when someone walks by). For plants, things are generally calm and eternal, everything resembles itself. From the time of lower organisms, humans have inherited the belief that similar things exist (this idea is only challenged by the accumulated experience of the most advanced science). The foundational belief of[Pg 33] all organic life from the start is perhaps that the rest of the world is one and unchanging. The furthest point from those early beginnings of logic is the idea of Causality,—in fact, we still genuinely think that all sensations and actions are acts of free will; when the aware individual reflects on themselves, they view every sensation, every change as something isolated, meaning unconditioned and unrelated,—it appears in us without any connection to what came before or what follows. We feel hunger, but initially do not consider that the organism needs nourishment; the feeling seems to arise without cause or purpose, it sets itself apart and views itself as arbitrary. Therefore, the belief in free will is an original misconception of everything organic, as old as the emergence of logical awareness within it; the belief in unconditioned substances and similar things is also a foundational as well as an ancient error in everything organic. However, since all metaphysics has primarily focused on substance and the freedom of will, it can be regarded as the science that addresses the fundamental misconceptions of humanity, while treating them as if they were fundamental truths.

19.

19.

Number.—The discovery of the laws of numbers is made upon the ground of the original, already prevailing error, that there are many similar things (but in reality there is nothing similar), at least,[Pg 34] that there are things (but there is no "thing"). The supposition of plurality always presumes that there is something which appears frequently,—but here already error reigns, already we imagine beings, unities, which do not exist. Our sensations of space and time are false, for they lead—examined in sequence—to logical contradictions. In all scientific determinations we always reckon inevitably with certain false quantities, but as these quantities are at least constant, as, for instance, our sensation of time and space, the conclusions of science have still perfect accuracy and certainty in their connection with one another; one may continue to build upon them—until that final limit where the erroneous original suppositions, those constant faults, come into conflict with the conclusions, for instance in the doctrine of atoms. There still we always feel ourselves compelled to the acceptance of a "thing" or material "sub-stratum" that is moved, whilst the whole scientific procedure has pursued the very task of resolving everything substantial (material) into motion; here, too, we still separate with our sensation the mover and the moved and cannot get out of this circle, because the belief in things has from immemorial times been bound up with our being. When Kant says, "The understanding does not derive its laws from Nature, but dictates them to her," it is perfectly true with regard to the idea of Nature which we are compelled to associate with her (Nature = World as representation, that is to say as error), but which is the summing up of a number of errors of the understanding. The laws[Pg 35] of numbers are entirely inapplicable to a world which is not our representation—these laws obtain only in the human world.

Number.—The discovery of number laws is based on the original, widespread mistake that there are many similar things (when in fact, nothing is truly similar), at least, [Pg 34] that there are things (but there's no actual "thing"). The assumption of plurality always assumes there's something that shows up often—but even here, error takes hold, and we envision beings and unities that don't exist. Our perceptions of space and time are misleading, as they lead—when analyzed sequentially—to logical contradictions. In all scientific assessments, we inevitably consider certain false quantities; however, since these quantities are at least consistent, like our perception of time and space, scientific conclusions retain perfect accuracy and certainty in their interrelation; we can build upon them—up to the point where the flawed original assumptions, those constant errors, clash with the conclusions, such as in atomic theory. There, we're still compelled to accept a "thing" or material "substance" that moves, while the entire scientific endeavor has aimed to explain everything substantial (material) in terms of motion; here, too, we continue to distinguish between the mover and the moved and can't escape this cycle because the belief in things has been intertwined with our existence since ancient times. When Kant asserts, "The understanding does not derive its laws from Nature, but dictates them to her," it's absolutely true concerning the idea of Nature that we feel compelled to associate with her (Nature = World as representation, meaning as error), which summarizes a number of misunderstandings of the mind. The laws [Pg 35] of numbers don't apply to a reality that isn't our representation—these laws exist only in the human realm.

20.

20.

A Few Steps Back.—A degree of culture, and assuredly a very high one, is attained when man rises above superstitious and religious notions and fears, and, for instance, no longer believes in guardian angels or in original sin, and has also ceased to talk of the salvation of his soul,—if he has attained to this degree of freedom, he has still also to overcome metaphysics with the greatest exertion of his intelligence. Then, however, a retrogressive movement is necessary; he must understand the historical justification as well as the psychological in such representations, he must recognise how the greatest advancement of humanity has come therefrom, and how, without such a retrocursive movement, we should have been robbed of the best products of hitherto existing mankind. With regard to philosophical metaphysics, I always see increasing numbers who have attained to the negative goal (that all positive metaphysics is error), but as yet few who climb a few rungs backwards; one ought to look out, perhaps, over the last steps of the ladder, but not try to stand upon them. The most enlightened only succeed so far as to free themselves from metaphysics and look back upon it with superiority, while it is necessary here, too, as in the hippodrome, to turn round the end of the course.

A Few Steps Back.—A level of culture, and definitely a very high one, is reached when a person rises above superstitions and religious fears, and for example, no longer believes in guardian angels or original sin, and has stopped talking about the salvation of their soul. If someone has reached this level of freedom, they must also overcome metaphysics using their intelligence to the fullest. However, a retrogressive movement is necessary; they must understand both the historical and psychological justifications for such beliefs, recognize how the greatest advancements in humanity have come from them, and see that without this backward step, we would have lost the best contributions from humanity. Regarding philosophical metaphysics, I see more and more people who have reached the negative conclusion (that all positive metaphysics is mistaken), but still few who take a few steps back. It's wise to observe the last steps of the ladder but not try to stand on them. The most enlightened individuals only manage to free themselves from metaphysics and look back on it with a sense of superiority, while it's also necessary, just like in a racetrack, to turn around at the end of the course.

21.

21.

Conjectural Victory of Scepticism.—For once let the sceptical starting-point be accepted,—granted that there were no other metaphysical world, and all explanations drawn from metaphysics about the only world we know were useless to us, in what light should we then look upon men and things? We can think this out for ourselves, it is useful, even though the question whether anything metaphysical has been scientifically proved by Kant and Schopenhauer were altogether set aside. For it is quite possible, according to historical probability, that some time or other man, as a general rule, may grow sceptical; the question will then be this: What form will human society take under the influence of such a mode of thought? Perhaps the scientific proof of some metaphysical world or other is already so difficult that mankind will never get rid of a certain distrust of it. And when there is distrust of metaphysics, there are on the whole the same results as if it had been directly refuted and could no longer be believed in. The historical question with regard to an unmetaphysical frame of mind in mankind remains the same in both cases.

Hypothetical Win of Skepticism.—Let's accept the sceptical perspective for a moment—assuming there isn't any other metaphysical world, and that all the explanations drawn from metaphysics about the only world we know are pointless for us, how should we view people and things? We can think this through on our own; it's useful, even if we completely set aside the question of whether Kant and Schopenhauer have scientifically proven anything metaphysical. Historically, it's quite possible that at some point, humanity as a whole might become sceptical; the question will then be: What shape will human society take under the influence of this way of thinking? Perhaps the scientific proof of some metaphysical realm is already so difficult that humanity will always retain a certain distrust of it. And when there's a distrust of metaphysics, the overall results are pretty much the same as if it had been directly disproven and could no longer be believed. The historical question regarding a non-metaphysical mindset in humanity remains unchanged in both scenarios.

22.

22.

Unbelief in the "monumentum Ære Perennius".—An actual drawback which accompanies the cessation of metaphysical views lies in the fact that the individual looks upon his short span[Pg 37] of life too exclusively and receives no stronger incentives to build durable institutions intended to last for centuries,—he himself wishes to pluck the fruit from the tree which he plants, and therefore he no longer plants those trees which require regular care for centuries, and which are destined to afford shade to a long series of generations. For metaphysical views furnish the belief that in them the last conclusive foundation has been given, upon which henceforth all the future of mankind is compelled to settle down and establish itself; the individual furthers his salvation, when, for instance, he founds a church or convent, he thinks it will be reckoned to him and recompensed to him in the eternal life of the soul, it is work for the soul's eternal salvation. Can science also arouse such faith in its results? As a matter of fact, it needs doubt and distrust as its most faithful auxiliaries; nevertheless in the course of time, the sum of inviolable truths—those, namely, which have weathered all the storms of scepticism, and all destructive analysis—may have become so great (in the regimen of health, for instance), that one may determine to found thereupon "eternal" works. For the present the contrast between our excited ephemeral existence and the long-winded repose of metaphysical ages still operates too strongly, because the two ages still stand too closely together; the individual man himself now goes through too many inward and outward developments for him to venture to arrange his own lifetime permanently, and once and for all. An entirely modern man, for instance, who is going[Pg 38] to build himself a house, has a feeling as if he were going to immure himself alive in a mausoleum.

Doubt in the "monumentum Ære Perennius".—A real drawback that comes with moving away from metaphysical perspectives is that individuals tend to view their short lifespan[Pg 37] too narrowly and lack the motivation to create lasting institutions meant to endure for centuries. They want to see immediate results from the seeds they plant, so they avoid planting trees that need decades of care and are meant to provide shade for future generations. Metaphysical beliefs offer the idea that they provide a solid foundation on which the future of humanity must build, and individuals contribute to their spiritual salvation by founding churches or convents, believing this will be acknowledged and rewarded in the eternal afterlife. Can science inspire such faith in its outcomes? In reality, it thrives on skepticism and uncertainty as essential partners; however, over time, the total sum of indisputable truths—those that have withstood all scrutiny and destructive analysis—might become significant enough (for instance, in health practices) that one could commit to establishing "eternal" works based on them. For now, the contrast between our chaotic, fleeting lives and the prolonged calm of metaphysical eras is still too pronounced, as these two periods are too closely intertwined; the individual experiences so many internal and external changes that he cannot confidently shape his own existence permanently and once and for all. A truly modern person, for instance, who plans[Pg 38] to build a house feels as though they are about to entomb themselves alive in a mausoleum.

23.

23.

The Age of Comparison.—The less men are fettered by tradition, the greater becomes the inward activity of their motives; the greater, again, in proportion thereto, the outward restlessness, the confused flux of mankind, the polyphony of strivings. For whom is there still an absolute compulsion to bind himself and his descendants to one place? For whom is there still anything strictly compulsory? As all styles of arts are imitated simultaneously, so also are all grades and kinds of morality, of customs, of cultures. Such an age obtains its importance because in it the various views of the world, customs, and cultures can be compared and experienced simultaneously,—which was formerly not possible with the always localised sway of every culture, corresponding to the rooting of all artistic styles in place and time. An increased æsthetic feeling will now at last decide amongst so many forms presenting themselves for comparison; it will allow the greater number, that is to say all those rejected by it, to die out. In the same way a selection amongst the forms and customs of the higher moralities is taking place, of which the aim can be nothing else than the downfall of the lower moralities. It is the age of comparison! That is its pride, but more justly also its grief. Let us not be afraid of this grief! Rather will we comprehend[Pg 39] as adequately as possible the task our age sets us: posterity will bless us for doing so,—a posterity which knows itself to be as much above the terminated original national cultures as above the culture of comparison, but which looks back with gratitude on both kinds of culture as upon antiquities worthy of veneration.

The Comparison Era.—The less people are tied down by tradition, the more their motivations become active; and as this increases, so does their restlessness, the chaotic flux of humanity, and the multitude of aspirations. Who still feels an absolute need to commit themselves and their descendants to one place? Who is still bound by anything strictly mandatory? Just as all forms of art are currently being imitated at once, so too are all types and levels of morality, customs, and cultures. This age gains its significance because people can now compare and experience diverse worldviews, customs, and cultures all at once—something that wasn’t possible when every culture was limited by its specific location, reflected in the artistic styles rooted in their own time and place. An enhanced sense of aesthetics will now ultimately choose among the numerous forms available for comparison; it will cause the majority, meaning all those deemed inferior, to fade away. Similarly, a selection among the forms and customs of higher moralities is underway, with the goal being the decline of the lower moralities. It is the age of comparison! This is both its pride and, justly, its sorrow. Let us not shy away from this sorrow! Rather, let us thoroughly understand[Pg 39] the task our age presents us with: future generations will be grateful for this—generations that recognize themselves as being above the now-finished original national cultures, as well as above the culture of comparison, yet look back with appreciation on both as ancient cultures worthy of respect.

24.

24.

The Possibility of Progress.—When a scholar of the ancient culture forswears the company of men who believe in progress, he does quite right. For the greatness and goodness of ancient culture lie behind it, and historical education compels one to admit that they can never be fresh again; an unbearable stupidity or an equally insufferable fanaticism would be necessary to deny this. But men can consciously resolve to develop themselves towards a new culture; whilst formerly they only developed unconsciously and by chance, they can now create better conditions for the rise of human beings, for their nourishment, education and instruction; they can administer the earth economically as a whole, and can generally weigh and restrain the powers of man. This new, conscious culture kills the old, which, regarded as a whole, has led an unconscious animal and plant life; it also kills distrust in progress,—progress is possible. I must say that it is over-hasty and almost nonsensical to believe that progress must necessarily follow; but how could one deny that it is possible? On the[Pg 40] other hand, progress in the sense and on the path of the old culture is not even thinkable. Even if romantic fantasy has also constantly used the word "progress" to denote its aims (for instance, circumscribed primitive national cultures), it borrows the picture of it in any case from the past; its thoughts and ideas on this subject are entirely without originality.

The Potential for Progress.—When a scholar of ancient culture chooses to avoid the company of those who believe in progress, they are absolutely justified. The greatness and value of ancient culture are behind us, and a historical understanding forces one to accept that they can never be renewed; it would take an unbearable ignorance or an equally unmanageable fanaticism to deny this. However, people can consciously choose to advance towards a new culture; while they once developed unconsciously and by chance, they can now create better conditions for human development, nourishment, education, and guidance; they can manage the earth as a whole in an economical manner and can generally evaluate and regulate human powers. This new, conscious culture replaces the old, which, when viewed as a whole, has led an unconscious life akin to that of animals and plants; it also eliminates distrust in progress—progress is possible. I must admit that it is overly hasty and nearly nonsensical to believe that progress must necessarily follow; but how could one deny that it is possible? On the[Pg 40] other hand, progress in the context and direction of the old culture is simply unimaginable. Even if romantic ideals have often used the word "progress" to represent their goals (for example, limited primitive national cultures), they nonetheless borrow the concept from the past; their thoughts and ideas on this subject lack originality.

25.

25.

Private and Œcumenical Morality.—Since the belief has ceased that a God directs in general the fate of the world and, in spite of all apparent crookedness in the path of humanity, leads it on gloriously, men themselves must set themselves œcumenical aims embracing the whole earth. The older morality, especially that of Kant, required from the individual actions which were desired from all men,—that was a delightfully naïve thing, as if each one knew off-hand what course of action was beneficial to the whole of humanity, and consequently which actions in general were desirable; it is a theory like that of free trade, taking for granted that the general harmony must result of itself according to innate laws of amelioration. Perhaps a future contemplation of the needs of humanity will show that it is by no means desirable that all men should act alike; in the interest of œcumenical aims it might rather be that for whole sections of mankind, special, and perhaps under certain circumstances even evil, tasks would have to be set. In[Pg 41] any case, if mankind is not to destroy itself by such a conscious universal rule, there must previously be found, as a scientific standard for œcumenical aims, a knowledge of the conditions of culture superior to what has hitherto been attained. Herein lies the enormous task of the great minds of the next century.

Personal and Universal Ethics.—Since people no longer believe that a God generally directs the fate of the world and leads humanity on to glory despite its many challenges, individuals must set ecumenical goals that include the entire planet. The earlier morality, especially that of Kant, expected individuals to act in ways that were assumed to be beneficial for all, which was a refreshingly naive idea, as if everyone inherently knew what actions were best for humanity and, therefore, what actions were desirable. This theory resembles the notion of free trade, which assumes that overall harmony will naturally emerge according to inherent laws of improvement. Perhaps future reflection on humanity's needs will reveal that it’s not necessarily desirable for everyone to act in the same way; for the sake of ecumenical objectives, it might actually require that certain groups of people are assigned specific, and possibly even harmful, tasks in certain situations. In[Pg 41] any case, if humanity is to avoid self-destruction through such a universal rule, there must first be a superior scientific understanding of the cultural conditions than what has been achieved so far. This is the immense challenge that awaits the great minds of the next century.

26.

26.

Reaction As Progress.—Now and again there appear rugged, powerful, impetuous, but nevertheless backward-lagging minds which conjure up once more a past phase of mankind; they serve to prove that the new tendencies against which they are working are not yet sufficiently strong, that they still lack something, otherwise they would show better opposition to those exorcisers. Thus, for example, Luther's Reformation bears witness to the fact that in his century all the movements of the freedom of the spirit were still uncertain, tender, and youthful; science could not yet lift up its head. Indeed the whole Renaissance seems like an early spring which is almost snowed under again. But in this century also, Schopenhauer's Metaphysics showed that even now the scientific spirit is not yet strong enough; thus the whole mediæval Christian view of the world and human feeling could celebrate its resurrection in Schopenhauer's doctrine, in spite of the long achieved destruction of all Christian dogmas. There is much science in his doctrine, but it does not dominate it: it is rather the old well-known "metaphysical requirement" that[Pg 42] does so. It is certainly one of the greatest and quite invaluable advantages which we gain from Schopenhauer, that he occasionally forces our sensations back into older, mightier modes of contemplating the world and man, to which no other path would so easily lead us. The gain to history and justice is very great,—I do not think that any one would so easily succeed now in doing justice to Christianity and its Asiatic relations without Schopenhauer's assistance, which is specially impossible from the basis of still existing Christianity. Only after this great success of justice, only after we have corrected so essential a point as the historical mode of contemplation which the age of enlightenment brought with it, may we again bear onward the banner of enlightenment, the banner with the three names, Petrarch, Erasmus, Voltaire. We have turned reaction into progress.

Response as Progress.—From time to time, strong, passionate, and yet outdated thinkers emerge who bring back a previous stage of humanity; they demonstrate that the new movements they oppose aren't robust enough yet, that they still lack something, or else they would put up a stronger fight against those trying to drive them away. For instance, Luther's Reformation shows that in his time, all the movements for spiritual freedom were still unsure, fragile, and young; science wasn't ready to take the lead. In fact, the whole Renaissance feels like an early spring that's almost buried under snow again. Even in this century, Schopenhauer's Metaphysics indicated that the scientific spirit still wasn't strong enough; thus, the entire medieval Christian worldview and human emotion could experience a revival in Schopenhauer's teachings, despite the long-standing dismantling of all Christian doctrines. His work contains a lot of scientific ideas, but they don't dominate; rather, the old familiar "metaphysical demand" does. One of the great and invaluable advantages we gain from Schopenhauer is that he occasionally pushes our perceptions back into older, more powerful ways of understanding the world and humanity, which we wouldn't easily access through other means. The benefit to history and justice is significant—it's hard to see how anyone could justly appreciate Christianity and its Asian connections without Schopenhauer's help, especially from the perspective of existing Christianity. Only after this monumental success of justice, after we've addressed such a crucial aspect as the historical way of seeing that the Enlightenment introduced, can we carry on the banner of enlightenment, the banner marked with the three names: Petrarch, Erasmus, Voltaire. We have transformed reaction into progress.

27.

27.

A Substitute For Religion.—It is believed that something good is said of philosophy when it is put forward as a substitute for religion for the people. As a matter of fact, in the spiritual economy there is need, at times, of an intermediary order of thought: the transition from religion to scientific contemplation is a violent, dangerous leap, which is not to be recommended. To this extent the recommendation is justifiable. But one should eventually learn that the needs which have been satisfied by religion and are now to be satisfied by philosophy are not unchangeable;[Pg 43] these themselves can be weakened and eradicated. Think, for instance, of the Christian's distress of soul, his sighing over inward corruption, his anxiety for salvation,—all notions which originate only in errors of reason and deserve not satisfaction but destruction. A philosophy can serve either to satisfy those needs or to set them aside; for they are acquired, temporally limited needs, which are based upon suppositions contradictory to those of science. Here, in order to make a transition, art is far rather to be employed to relieve the mind overburdened with emotions; for those notions receive much less support from it than from a metaphysical philosophy. It is easier, then, to pass over from art to a really liberating philosophical science.

A Replacement for Religion.—People often think it's a good thing when philosophy is proposed as an alternative to religion. In reality, sometimes we need a middle ground of thought: jumping directly from religion to scientific understanding is a jarring and risky move, which isn’t advisable. To that extent, this suggestion makes sense. However, we should eventually realize that the needs fulfilled by religion, which philosophy now aims to address, are not set in stone; they can indeed be weakened and eradicated. Consider, for example, the Christian's struggles with their soul, their lamenting over inner corruption, their fear of damnation—all concepts that arise from flawed reasoning and deserve not fulfillment but to be dismantled. A philosophy can either satisfy those needs or dismiss them; they are temporary wants shaped by ideas that contradict scientific principles. In making this shift, art is much better suited to ease the mind weighed down by emotions; those ideas find little support in it compared to a metaphysical philosophy. Therefore, it's easier to transition from art to genuinely liberating philosophical thought.

28.

28.

Ill-famed Words.—Away with those wearisomely hackneyed terms Optimism and Pessimism! For the occasion for using them becomes less and less from day to day; only the chatterboxes still find them so absolutely necessary. For why in all the world should any one wish to be an optimist unless he had a God to defend who must have created the best of worlds if he himself be goodness and perfection,—what thinker, however, still needs the hypothesis of a God? But every occasion for a pessimistic confession of faith is also lacking when one has no interest in being annoyed at the advocates of God (the theologians, or the theologising philosophers), and in energetically defending the opposite view, that evil reigns, that pain is greater[Pg 44] than pleasure, that the world is a bungled piece of work, the manifestation of an ill-will to life. But who still bothers about the theologians now—except the theologians? Apart from all theology and its contentions, it is quite clear that the world is not good and not bad (to say nothing of its being the best or the worst), and that the terms "good" and "bad" have only significance with respect to man, and indeed, perhaps, they are not justified even here in the way they are usually employed; in any case we must get rid of both the calumniating and the glorifying conception of the world.

Notorious Words.—Let’s get rid of those overused terms Optimism and Pessimism! The reasons for using them keep decreasing every day; only the loudmouths still think they are essential. Why would anyone want to be an optimist unless they had a God to defend who *must* have created the best of worlds if he represents goodness and perfection—what thinker really needs the idea of God anymore? Likewise, there’s no need for a pessimistic confession of faith when you're not bothered by those who advocate for God (the theologians or the philosopher-theologians) and don’t feel the urge to strongly argue against the notion that evil dominates, that pain is greater than pleasure, or that the world is a failed creation that expresses a hatred of life. But who actually cares about theologians these days—other than the theologians themselves? Setting aside all theology and its disputes, it's clear that the world is neither good nor bad (not to mention it is not the best or the worst), and the terms "good" and "bad" only have meaning in relation to humans. In fact, they might not even be justified in the way they're typically used; in any case, we need to move beyond both the condemning and glorifying views of the world.

29.

29.

Intoxicated by the Scent of the Blossoms.—It is supposed that the ship of humanity has always a deeper draught, the heavier it is laden; it is believed that the deeper a man thinks, the more delicately he feels, the higher he values himself, the greater his distance from the other animals,—the more he appears as a genius amongst the animals,—all the nearer will he approach the real essence of the world and its knowledge; this he actually does too, through science, but he means to do so still more through his religions and arts. These certainly are blossoms of the world, but by no means any nearer to the root of the world than the stalk; it is not possible to understand the nature of things better through them, although almost every one believes he can. Error has made man so deep, sensitive, and inventive that he has put forth such[Pg 45] blossoms as religions and arts. Pure knowledge could not have been capable of it. Whoever were to unveil for us the essence of the world would give us all the most disagreeable disillusionment. Not the world as thing-in-itself, but the world as representation (as error) is so full of meaning, so deep, so wonderful, bearing happiness and unhappiness in its bosom. This result leads to a philosophy of the logical denial of the world, which, however, can be combined with a practical world-affirming just as well as with its opposite.

Drunk on the Fragrance of the Flowers.—It's believed that the more weight the ship of humanity carries, the deeper it sinks; the deeper a person thinks, the more sensitively they feel, the higher they think of themselves, and the greater the distance they put between themselves and other animals. The more a person stands out as a genius among animals, the closer they get to the true essence of the world and its knowledge. They actually do get closer through science, but they aim to reach it even more through their religions and arts. These are certainly the blossoms of the world, but they’re not any closer to the root of the world than the stalk; it’s not possible to understand the nature of things better through them, even though almost everyone believes they can. Error has made humanity so deep, sensitive, and inventive that it has produced such[Pg 45] blossoms as religions and arts. Pure knowledge couldn't have achieved that. If someone were to reveal the essence of the world to us, it would lead to all sorts of unpleasant disillusionment. It’s not the world as it truly is, but the world as a representation (as error) that is so full of meaning, so profound, so wonderful, containing both happiness and unhappiness. This outcome leads to a philosophy that logically denies the world, which can, however, coexist with a practical acceptance of the world just as easily as it can with its opposite.

30.

30.

Bad Habits in Reasoning.—The usual false conclusions of mankind are these: a thing exists, therefore it has a right to exist. Here there is inference from the ability to live to its suitability; from its suitability to its rightfulness. Then: an opinion brings happiness; therefore it is the true opinion. Its effect is good; therefore it is itself good and true. To the effect is here assigned the predicate beneficent, good, in the sense of the useful, and the cause is then furnished with the same predicate good, but here in the sense of the logically valid. The inversion of the sentences would read thus: an affair cannot be carried through, or maintained, therefore it is wrong; an opinion causes pain or excites, therefore it is false. The free spirit who learns only too often the faultiness of this mode of reasoning, and has to suffer from its consequences, frequently gives way to the temptation to draw the very opposite[Pg 46] conclusions, which, in general, are naturally just as false: an affair cannot be carried through, therefore it is good; an opinion is distressing and disturbing, therefore it is true.

Flawed Thinking Patterns.—The common misguided conclusions people make are these: something exists, so it has a right to exist. Here, there's a jump from the ability to survive to its appropriateness; from its appropriateness to its rightness. Then: an opinion brings happiness; therefore, it must be the correct opinion. If it has a positive effect, that means it is good and true. The effect is labeled as beneficial and good, in the sense of being useful, and the cause is given the same label of good, but in terms of being logically valid. Reversing the statements would go like this: if something can't be accomplished or maintained, then it is wrong; if an opinion causes pain or distress, then it is false. The free thinker who often realizes how flawed this way of reasoning is and has to deal with its consequences frequently succumbs to the temptation to draw the opposite [Pg 46] conclusions, which are generally just as incorrect: if something can't be accomplished, then it must be good; if an opinion is distressing and unsettling, then it must be true.

31.

31.

The Illogical Necessary.—One of those things that may drive a thinker into despair is the recognition of the fact that the illogical is necessary for man, and that out of the illogical comes much that is good. It is so firmly rooted in the passions, in language, in art, in religion, and generally in everything that gives value to life, that it cannot be withdrawn without thereby hopelessly injuring these beautiful things. It is only the all-too-naïve people who can believe that the nature of man can be changed into a purely logical one; but if there were degrees of proximity to this goal, how many things would not have to be lost on this course! Even the most rational man has need of nature again from time to time, i.e. his illogical fundamental attitude towards all things.

The Necessary Illogical.—One of those things that can drive a thinker to despair is realizing that the illogical is essential for humanity, and that from the illogical arises much that is good. It's so deeply embedded in our passions, language, art, religion, and generally everything that gives life value, that it cannot be removed without causing serious harm to these beautiful aspects. Only the overly naïve can believe that human nature can be transformed into a purely logical one; but if there were steps toward that goal, so many things would have to be sacrificed along the way! Even the most rational person occasionally needs nature back, i.e. their illogical fundamental attitude toward all things.

32.

32.

Injustice Necessary.—All judgments on the value of life are illogically developed, and therefore unjust. The inexactitude of the judgment lies, firstly, in the manner in which the material is presented, namely very imperfectly; secondly, in the manner in which the conclusion is formed out of it; and thirdly, in the fact that every separate[Pg 47] element of the material is again the result of vitiated recognition, and this, too, of necessity. For instance, no experience of an individual, however near he may stand to us, can be perfect, so that we could have a logical right to make a complete estimate of him; all estimates are rash, and must be so. Finally, the standard by which we measure, our nature, is not of unalterable dimensions,—we have moods and vacillations, and yet we should have to recognise ourselves as a fixed standard in order to estimate correctly the relation of any thing whatever to ourselves. From this it will, perhaps, follow that we should make no judgments at all; if one could only live without making estimations, without having likes and dislikes! For all dislike is connected with an estimation, as well as all inclination. An impulse towards or away from anything without a feeling that something advantageous is desired, something injurious avoided, an impulse without any kind of conscious valuation of the worth of the aim does not exist in man. We are from the beginning illogical, and therefore unjust beings, and can recognise this; it is one of the greatest and most inexplicable discords of existence.

Necessary Injustice.—All judgments about the value of life are made illogically and are therefore unjust. The inaccuracy of our judgments comes from three main factors: first, the way the material is presented is very flawed; second, how we draw conclusions from that material; and third, each individual element of that material results from a distorted understanding, which is unavoidable. For example, no one’s experience, no matter how close they are to us, can be perfect enough for us to make a complete assessment of them; all assessments are hasty and must be so. Finally, the standard we use to judge—our own nature—is not fixed; we have moods and changes, yet we must see ourselves as a stable standard in order to accurately assess anything in relation to ourselves. This might suggest that we should not make any judgments at all; if only we could live without making evaluations, without having likes and dislikes! Every dislike is tied to a judgment, just like every preference. An impulse to move towards or away from something without the feeling that we're seeking something beneficial or avoiding something harmful, an impulse without any conscious evaluation of the goal's worth, doesn’t exist in humans. We are fundamentally illogical and therefore unjust beings, and we can recognize this; it is one of the greatest and most puzzling contradictions of existence.

33.

33.

Error About Life Necessary For Life.—Every belief in the value and worthiness of life is based on vitiated thought; it is only possible through the fact that sympathy for the general life and suffering of mankind is very weakly developed[Pg 48] in the individual. Even the rarer people who think outside themselves do not contemplate this general life, but only a limited part of it. If one understands how to direct one's attention chiefly to the exceptions,—I mean to the highly gifted and the rich souls,—if one regards the production of these as the aim of the whole world-development and rejoices in its operation, then one may believe in the value of life, because one thereby overlooks the other men—one consequently thinks fallaciously. So too, when one directs one's attention to all mankind, but only considers one species of impulses in them, the less egoistical ones, and excuses them with regard to the other instincts, one may then again entertain hopes of mankind in general and believe so far in the value of life, consequently in this case also through fallaciousness of thought. Let one, however, behave in this or that manner: with such behaviour one is an exception amongst men. Now, most people bear life without any considerable grumbling, and consequently believe in the value of existence, but precisely because each one is solely self-seeking and self-affirming, and does not step out of himself like those exceptions; everything extra-personal is imperceptible to them, or at most seems only a faint shadow. Therefore on this alone is based the value of life for the ordinary everyday man, that he regards himself as more important than the world. The great lack of imagination from which he suffers is the reason why he cannot enter into the feelings of other beings, and therefore sympathises as little as possible with[Pg 49] their fate and suffering. He, on the other hand, who really could sympathise therewith, would have to despair of the value of life; were he to succeed in comprehending and feeling in himself the general consciousness of mankind, he would collapse with a curse on existence; for mankind as a whole has no goals, consequently man, in considering his whole course, cannot find in it his comfort and support, but his despair. If, in all that he does, he considers the final aimlessness of man, his own activity assumes in his eyes the character of wastefulness. But to feel one's self just as much wasted as humanity (and not only as an individual) as we see the single blossom of nature wasted, is a feeling above all other feelings. But who is capable of it? Assuredly only a poet, and poets always know how to console themselves.

Mistake About Life Essential For Life.—Every belief in the value and worthiness of life comes from flawed thinking; it’s only possible because an individual’s empathy for the collective life and suffering of humanity is very poorly developed[Pg 48]. Even the rare individuals who think beyond themselves do not consider this broader existence, but only a narrow slice of it. If someone focuses mainly on exceptions—by that, I mean the exceptionally talented and wealthy people—and views their existence as the goal of all development in the world, celebrating this phenomenon, then they might believe in the value of life because they are effectively overlooking everyone else—they are thus mistaken in their thinking. Similarly, if one looks at all of humanity but only recognizes one type of impulse within them, such as the less selfish ones, while excusing them for their other instincts, one might again foster optimism about humanity as a whole and believe in the value of life, again due to flawed thinking. But regardless of how one behaves, such behavior makes one an exception among people. Most individuals endure life without significant complaints and thus believe in the value of existence, but this is only because each person is focused on their own self-interest and self-affirmation, not stepping outside of themselves like those exceptions; everything beyond the personal is invisible to them, or at best appears as a faint shadow. Therefore, the ordinary individual values life mainly because they see themselves as more important than the world. Their significant lack of imagination is why they cannot fully empathize with the feelings of others, and as a result, they sympathize very little with[Pg 49] their fates and sufferings. However, someone who genuinely could sympathize would have to despair about the value of life; if they were to grasp and feel within themselves the shared consciousness of humanity, they would be driven to curse existence; for humanity as a whole has no goals, thus when one reflects on their entire journey, they cannot find comfort or support, only despair. If, in everything they do, they consider human aimlessness, their own efforts appear to them as futile. Yet to feel as though they are just as wasted as humanity itself (and not merely as an individual), similar to observing a single blossom of nature wasted, is a feeling above all others. But who is capable of that? Certainly, only a poet, and poets always find ways to console themselves.

34.

34.

For Tranquillity.—But does not our philosophy thus become a tragedy? Does not truth become hostile to life, to improvement? A question seems to weigh upon our tongue and yet hesitate to make itself heard: whether one can consciously remain in untruthfulness? or, supposing one were obliged to do this, would not death be preferable? For there is no longer any "must"; morality, in so far as it had any "must" or "shalt", has been destroyed by our mode of contemplation, just as religion has been destroyed. Knowledge can only allow pleasure and pain, benefit and injury to subsist as motives; but how will these[Pg 50] motives agree with the sense of truth? They also contain errors (for, as already said, inclination and aversion, and their very incorrect determinations, practically regulate our pleasure and pain). The whole of human life is deeply immersed in untruthfulness; the individual cannot draw it up out of this well, without thereby taking a deep dislike to his whole past, without finding his present motives—those of honour, for instance—inconsistent, and without opposing scorn and disdain to the passions which conduce to happiness in the future. Is it true that there remains but one sole way of thinking which brings after it despair as a personal experience, as a theoretical result, a philosophy of dissolution, disintegration, and self-destruction? I believe that the decision with regard to the after-effects of the knowledge will be given through the temperament of a man; I could imagine another after-effect, just as well as that one described, which is possible in certain natures, by means of which a life would arise much simpler, freer from emotions than is the present one, so that though at first, indeed, the old motives of passionate desire might still have strength from old hereditary habit, they would gradually become weaker under the influence—of purifying knowledge. One would live at last amongst men, and with one's self as with Nature, without praise, reproach, or agitation, feasting one's eyes, as if it were a play, upon much of which one was formerly afraid. One would be free from the emphasis, and would no longer feel the goading, of the thought that one is not only nature or more than nature. Certainly, as already remarked, a[Pg 51] good temperament would be necessary for this, an even, mild, and naturally joyous soul, a disposition which would not always need to be on its guard against spite and sudden outbreaks, and would not convey in its utterances anything of a grumbling or sudden nature,—those well-known vexatious qualities of old dogs and men who have been long chained up. On the contrary, a man from whom the ordinary fetters of life have so far fallen that he continues to live only for the sake of ever better knowledge must be able to renounce without envy and regret: much, indeed almost everything that is precious to other men, he must regard as the all-sufficing and the most desirable condition; the free, fearless soaring over men, customs, laws, and the traditional valuations of things. The joy of this condition he imparts willingly, and he has perhaps nothing else to impart,—wherein, to be sure, there is more privation and renunciation. If, nevertheless, more is demanded from him, he will point with a friendly shake of his head to his brother, the free man of action, and will perhaps not conceal a little derision, for as regards this "freedom" it is a very peculiar case.

For Peace.—But doesn't our philosophy turn into a tragedy? Doesn't truth become an enemy to life and progress? There's a question that lingers on our lips but hesitates to come out: can someone consciously live in falsehood? Or, if one had to do this, wouldn’t death be a better option? There’s no longer a "must"; morality, to the extent it ever had a "must" or "shalt," has been dismantled by our way of thinking, just like religion has been. Knowledge can only let pleasure and pain, benefit and harm exist as motives; but how will these[Pg 50] motives align with the sense of truth? They also contain mistakes (because, as mentioned before, our likes and dislikes, along with their often incorrect judgments, essentially govern our pleasure and pain). Human life is deeply entrenched in falsehood; it's impossible for an individual to pull themselves out of this pit without developing a strong dislike for their entire past, without finding their current motives—like honor—contradictory, and without feeling contempt and disdain for the passions that lead to future happiness. Is it true that there's only one way of thinking that results in despair as a personal experience, as a theoretical conclusion, a philosophy of dissolution, disintegration, and self-destruction? I believe the impact of knowledge on a person will depend on their temperament; I can envision an alternative outcome, just as valid as the one described, possible in certain personalities, through which a life would emerge that is much simpler, more free from emotions than our current one. Although at first, the old motives of passionate desire might still have strength due to habit, they would gradually diminish under the influence of purifying knowledge. One would finally live among people, and with oneself as with Nature, without praise, blame, or agitation, enjoying as if it were a play much of what once caused fear. One would be free from pressure and would no longer feel the urgency of the thought that one is not just nature or more than nature. Certainly, as already noted, a[Pg 51] good temperament is essential for this: a calm, kind, and naturally joyful soul, a disposition that doesn’t always need to be on guard against malice and sudden outbursts, and would not express anything grumpy or abrupt—those familiar annoying traits of old dogs and people who have been cooped up for too long. In contrast, a person from whom the usual shackles of life have fallen away to the point they live solely for better knowledge must be able to let go without envy or regret: they must see much, even almost everything precious to others, as the all-sufficient and most desirable state; the freedom to rise above people, customs, laws, and traditional values. The joy of this state is freely shared, and they have perhaps nothing else to share—though this certainly involves more deprivation and sacrifice. If more is demanded from them, they will kindly shake their head towards their brother, the free man of action, perhaps not hiding a little mockery, because this "freedom" is quite a peculiar case.


SECOND DIVISION.

THE HISTORY OF THE MORAL SENTIMENTS.

35.

35.

Advantages of Psychological Observation.—That reflection on the human, all-too-human—or, according to the learned expression, psychological observation—is one of the means by which one may lighten the burden of life, that exercise in this art produces presence of mind in difficult circumstances, in the midst of tiresome surroundings, even that from the most thorny and unpleasant periods of one's own life one may gather maxims and thereby feel a little better: all this was believed, was known in former centuries. Why was it forgotten by our century, when in Germany at least, even in all Europe, the poverty of psychological observation betrays itself by many signs? Not exactly in novels, tales, and philosophical treatises,—they are the work of exceptional individuals,—rather in the judgments on public events and personalities; but above all there is a lack of the art of psychological analysis and summing-up in every rank of society, in which a great deal is talked about men, but nothing about man. Why do we allow the richest and most harmless[Pg 54] subject of conversation to escape us? Why are not the great masters of psychological maxims more read? For, without any exaggeration, the educated man in Europe who has read La Rochefoucauld and his kindred in mind and art, is rarely found, and still more rare is he who knows them and does not blame them. It is probable, however, that even this exceptional reader will find much less pleasure in them than the form of this artist should afford him; for even the clearest head is not capable of rightly estimating the art of shaping and polishing maxims unless he has really been brought up to it and has competed in it. Without this practical teaching one deems this shaping and polishing to be easier than it is; one has not a sufficient perception of fitness and charm. For this reason the present readers of maxims find in them a comparatively small pleasure, hardly a mouthful of pleasantness, so that they resemble the people who generally look at cameos, who praise because they cannot love, and are very ready to admire, but still more ready to run away.

Benefits of Psychological Observation.—Reflecting on human nature—what we call psychological observation—is a way to lighten life's burdens. Practicing this skill fosters presence of mind in tough situations and tedious environments. One can even draw wisdom from the most difficult and unpleasant times in their life, which can help improve their feelings. This knowledge was recognized in past centuries, so why has it been forgotten in ours? In Germany, and throughout Europe, there are clear signs of a decline in psychological observation. It’s not so much in novels, stories, or philosophical writings—those come from exceptional individuals—but in how we judge public events and personalities. More importantly, there’s a lack of psychological analysis and summarization across all levels of society, where we talk a lot about people but very little about humanity. Why do we let the richest and safest topic of discussion slip away? Why aren’t the great masters of psychological insights read more widely? Without exaggeration, it’s rare to find an educated European who has read La Rochefoucauld and other similar thinkers, and even rarer is someone who knows them and doesn’t criticize them. However, even this exceptional reader may not enjoy these works as much as the artist intended; even the clearest thinkers struggle to properly appreciate the art of creating and refining maxims unless they have been trained in it and have actively participated in it. Without practical experience, it’s easy to underestimate how difficult it is to craft and refine ideas, leading to a lack of appreciation for their nuances and appeal. Because of this, today’s readers of maxims derive relatively little enjoyment from them, akin to people who casually admire cameos—offering praise without genuine love for them, eager to express admiration but even quicker to walk away.

36.

36.

Objection.—Or should there be a counter-reckoning to that theory that places psychological observation amongst the means of charming, curing, and relieving existence? Should one have sufficiently convinced one's self of the unpleasant consequences of this art to divert from it designedly the attention of him who is educating himself in it? As a matter of fact, a certain blind belief in the[Pg 55] goodness of human nature, an innate aversion to the analysis of human actions, a kind of shame-facedness with respect to the nakedness of the soul may really be more desirable for the general well-being of a man than that quality, useful in isolated cases, of psychological sharp-sightedness; and perhaps the belief in goodness, in virtuous men and deeds, in an abundance of impersonal goodwill in the world, has made men better inasmuch as it has made them less distrustful. When one imitates Plutarch's heroes with enthusiasm, and turns with disgust from a suspicious examination of the motives for their actions, it is not truth which benefits thereby, but the welfare of human society; the psychological mistake and, generally speaking, the insensibility on this matter helps humanity forwards, while the recognition of truth gains more through the stimulating power of hypothesis than La Rochefoucauld has said in his preface to the first edition of his "Sentences et maximes morales." ... "Ce que le monde nomme vertu n'est d'ordinaire qu'un fantôme formé par nos passions, à qui on donne un nom honnête pour faire impunément ce qu'on veut." La Rochefoucauld and those other French masters of soul-examination who have lately been joined by a German, the author of Psychological Observations[1] resemble good marksmen who again and again hit the bull's-eye; but it is the bull's-eye of human nature. Their art arouses astonishment; but in the end a spectator who is not led by the spirit of science,[Pg 56] but by humane intentions, will probably execrate an art which appears to implant in the soul the sense of the disparagement and suspicion of mankind.

No objections.—Should we counter the idea that sees psychological observation as a way of charming, healing, and improving life? Should we intentionally distract someone learning this skill from the unpleasant outcomes it can bring? In reality, a certain blind faith in the goodness of human nature, a natural reluctance to analyze human actions, and a kind of embarrassment about the rawness of the soul might actually be better for a person’s overall well-being than the ability to see human psychology clearly, which is only helpful in specific situations. Believing in goodness, virtuous people and actions, and a lot of general goodwill in the world may have made people better by making them less suspicious. When we enthusiastically emulate Plutarch's heroes and turn away in disgust from scrutinizing their motives, it's not the truth that benefits but the well-being of society. This psychological oversight and, generally speaking, the insensitivity toward this issue helps humanity progress, while the recognition of truth gains more from the energizing power of hypothesis than La Rochefoucauld suggested in his preface to the first edition of his "Sentences et maximes morales." ... "What the world calls virtue is usually just a shadow formed by our passions, which we give an honorable name to in order to do what we want without consequences." La Rochefoucauld and other French thinkers who analyzed the soul, now joined by a German author of Psychological Observations[1] are like skilled marksmen who consistently hit their target; but they target human nature. Their expertise astonishes, yet in the end, a spectator motivated not by scientific spirit but by humane intentions might curse an art that seems to sow distrust and contempt for humanity in the soul.

37.

37.

Nevertheless.—However it may be with reckoning and counter-reckoning, in the present condition of philosophy the awakening of moral observation is necessary. Humanity can no longer be spared the cruel sight of the psychological dissecting-table with its knives and forceps. For here rules that science which inquires into the origin and history of the so-called moral sentiments, and which, in its progress, has to draw up and solve complicated sociological problems:—the older philosophy knows the latter one not at all, and has always avoided the examination of the origin and history of moral sentiments on any feeble pretext. With what consequences it is now very easy to see, after it has been shown by many examples how the mistakes of the greatest philosophers generally have their starting-point in a wrong explanation of certain human actions and sensations, just as on the ground of an erroneous analysis—for instance, that of the so-called unselfish actions a false ethic is built up; then, to harmonise with this again, religion and mythological confusion are brought in to assist, and finally the shades of these dismal spirits fall also over physics and the general mode of regarding the world. If it is certain, however, that superficiality in psychological[Pg 57] observation has laid, and still lays, the most dangerous snares for human judgments and conclusions, then there is need now of that endurance of work which does not grow weary of piling stone upon stone, pebble on pebble; there is need of courage not to be ashamed of such humble work and to turn a deaf ear to scorn. And this is also true,—numberless single observations on the human and all-too-human have first been discovered, and given utterance to, in circles of society which were accustomed to offer sacrifice therewith to a clever desire to please, and not to scientific knowledge,—and the odour of that old home of the moral maxim, a very seductive odour, has attached itself almost inseparably to the whole species, so that on its account the scientific man involuntarily betrays a certain distrust of this species and its earnestness. But it is sufficient to point to the consequences, for already it begins to be seen what results of a serious kind spring from the ground of psychological observation. What, after all, is the principal axiom to which the boldest and coldest thinker, the author of the book On the Origin of Moral Sensations[2] has attained by means of his incisive and decisive analyses of human actions? "The moral man," he says, "is no nearer to the intelligible (metaphysical) world than is the physical man." This theory, hardened and sharpened under the hammer-blow of historical knowledge, may some time or other, perhaps in[Pg 58] some future period, serve as the axe which is applied to the root of the "metaphysical need" of man,—whether more as a blessing than a curse to the general welfare it is not easy to say, but in any case as a theory with the most important consequences, at once fruitful and terrible, and looking into the world with that Janus-face which all great knowledge possesses.

Nonetheless.—Regardless of how we weigh different arguments, right now in philosophy, there's a pressing need to awaken moral observation. Humanity can no longer endure the harsh view of psychological dissection with its sharp tools. This is the domain of science that investigates the origins and evolution of so-called moral feelings, and as it advances, it has to tackle complex sociological issues—something the older philosophy completely overlooked, always finding flimsy excuses to avoid examining the roots and developments of moral sentiments. The consequences of this are clear now, as countless examples illustrate how the mistakes of the greatest philosophers often stem from misunderstandings of certain human actions and feelings. For instance, a flawed analysis of so-called selfless acts can lead to a false moral framework; to reconcile with this, religion and mythological confusion step in to help, ultimately casting a shadow of despair over physics and the overall view of the world. It’s clear that shallow psychological observation has created, and continues to create, the most dangerous pitfalls for human judgments and conclusions. Therefore, we need the endurance to keep building knowledge, stone by stone, pebble by pebble; we must have the courage to embrace this seemingly humble work and ignore any ridicule. Moreover, it's true that countless individual observations regarding humans have first been identified and articulated in social circles driven by a clever desire to impress rather than by genuine scientific inquiry. The enticing scent of that old moral maxim remains tightly woven into the fabric of this field, leading scientists to unwittingly harbor some skepticism about its seriousness. However, pointing out the outcomes is enough, as we are already beginning to see the profound results emerging from serious psychological observation. What, after all, is the key principle that the boldest and most rational thinker, the author of the book On the Origin of Moral Sensations[2] has reached through sharp and incisive analyses of human actions? He states, "The moral man is no closer to the intelligible (metaphysical) world than the physical man." This theory, refined through the lessons of history, may someday become the tool that cuts to the root of humanity's "metaphysical need"—whether this will be more of a blessing or a curse for the common good is hard to say, but it will certainly be a theory with important, far-reaching, and potentially frightening consequences, always looking at the world with the dual perspective that all significant knowledge possesses.

38.

38.

How Far Useful.—It must remain for ever undecided whether psychological observation is advantageous or disadvantageous to man; but it is certain that it is necessary, because science cannot do without it. Science, however, has no consideration for ultimate purposes, any more than Nature has, but just as the latter occasionally achieves things of the greatest suitableness without intending to do so, so also true science, as the imitator of nature in ideas, will occasionally and in many ways further the usefulness and welfare of man,—but also without intending to do so.

How Useful Is It?.—It will always be up for debate whether psychological observation is beneficial or harmful to humanity; however, it's clear that it's essential because science relies on it. Science, like Nature, doesn't concern itself with ultimate goals. Just as Nature sometimes accomplishes highly suitable outcomes without intending to, true science, as the imitator of nature in ideas, may also unintentionally enhance the usefulness and well-being of humanity—but again, without any purpose in mind.

But whoever feels too chilled by the breath of such a reflection has perhaps too little fire in himself; let him look around him meanwhile and he will become aware of illnesses which have need of ice-poultices, and of men who are so "kneaded together" of heat and spirit that they can hardly find an atmosphere that is cold and biting enough. Moreover, as individuals and nations that are too serious have need of frivolities, as others too[Pg 59] mobile and excitable have need occasionally of heavily oppressing burdens for the sake of their health, should not we, the more intellectual people of this age, that grows visibly more and more inflamed, seize all quenching and cooling means that exist, in order that we may at least remain as constant, harmless, and moderate as we still are, and thus, perhaps, serve some time or other as mirror and self-contemplation for this age?

But whoever feels too overwhelmed by such a reflection might just not have enough passion in themselves; if they look around, they'll notice illnesses that need ice packs, and people who are so "filled with" heat and energy that they can barely find an atmosphere that's cold and harsh enough. Additionally, just as individuals and nations that take life too seriously need some lightheartedness, while others who are too restless and high-strung occasionally need burdens to slow them down for their well-being, shouldn't we, the more intellectual people of this increasingly fiery age, grab hold of all cooling and calming means available? That way, we can at least stay as steady, harmless, and moderate as we currently are, and perhaps, at some point, act as a mirror and reflection for this era?

39.

39.

The Fable of Intelligible Freedom.—The history of the sentiments by means of which we make a person responsible consists of the following principal phases. First, all single actions are called good or bad without any regard to their motives, but only on account of the useful or injurious consequences which result for the community. But soon the origin of these distinctions is forgotten, and it is deemed that the qualities "good" or "bad" are contained in the action itself without regard to its consequences, by the same error according to which language describes the stone as hard, the tree as green,—with which, in short, the result is regarded as the cause. Then the goodness or badness is implanted in the motive, and the action in itself is looked upon as morally ambiguous. Mankind even goes further, and applies the predicate good or bad no longer to single motives, but to the whole nature of an individual, out of whom the motive grows as the plant grows out of the earth. Thus, in turn, man[Pg 60] is made responsible for his operations, then for his actions, then for his motives, and finally for his nature. Eventually it is discovered that even this nature cannot be responsible, inasmuch as it is an absolutely necessary consequence concreted out of the elements and influences of past and present things,—that man, therefore, cannot be made responsible for anything, neither for his nature, nor his motives, nor his actions, nor his effects. It has therewith come to be recognised that the history of moral valuations is at the same time the history of an error, the error of responsibility, which is based upon the error of the freedom of will. Schopenhauer thus decided against it: because certain actions bring ill humour ("consciousness of guilt") in their train, there must be a responsibility; for there would be no reason for this ill humour if not only all human actions were not done of necessity,—which is actually the case and also the belief of this philosopher,—but man himself from the same necessity is precisely the being that he is—which Schopenhauer denies. From the fact of that ill humour Schopenhauer thinks he can prove a liberty which man must somehow have had, not with regard to actions, but with regard to nature; liberty, therefore, to be thus or otherwise, not to act thus or otherwise. From the esse, the sphere of freedom and responsibility, there results, in his opinion, the operari, the sphere of strict causality, necessity, and irresponsibility. This ill humour is apparently directed to the operari,—in so far it is erroneous,—but in reality it is directed to the esse, which is the deed of a free will, the[Pg 61] fundamental cause of the existence of an individual, man becomes that which he wishes to be, his will is anterior to his existence. Here the mistaken conclusion is drawn that from the fact of the ill humour, the justification, the reasonable admissableness of this ill humour is presupposed; and starting from this mistaken conclusion, Schopenhauer arrives at his fantastic sequence of the so-called intelligible freedom. But the ill humour after the deed is not necessarily reasonable, indeed it is assuredly not reasonable, for it is based upon the erroneous presumption that the action need not have inevitably followed. Therefore, it is only because man believes himself to be free, not because he is free, that he experiences remorse and pricks of conscience. Moreover, this ill humour is a habit that can be broken off; in many people it is entirely absent in connection with actions where others experience it. It is a very changeable thing, and one which is connected with the development of customs and culture, and probably only existing during a comparatively short period of the world's history. Nobody is responsible for his actions, nobody for his nature; to judge is identical with being unjust. This also applies when an individual judges himself. The theory is as clear as sunlight, and yet every one prefers to go back into the shadow and the untruth, for fear of the consequences.

The Story of Understandable Freedom.—The history of how we hold someone accountable can be broken down into a few key phases. Initially, each action is labeled as good or bad based solely on the beneficial or harmful outcomes for society, disregarding the underlying motives. However, over time, the reason for these distinctions is forgotten, and people start to believe that the qualities "good" or "bad" are inherent to the action itself, similar to how we describe a stone as hard or a tree as green—meaning the result is mistaken for the cause. Next, people start to link goodness or badness to the motive behind an action, viewing the action itself as morally neutral. Society goes further by attributing good or bad labels not only to individual motives but to a person's entire character, from which the motives arise, much like a plant grows from the ground. Hence, individuals are held accountable for their behaviors, then for their actions, then for their motives, and ultimately for their nature. In the end, it’s realized that even this nature can't be held accountable because it's simply a necessary outcome shaped by past and present influences—thus, people can’t be made responsible for anything, including their nature, motives, actions, or outcomes. It’s acknowledged that the history of moral judgments also represents a history of a mistake—the mistake of responsibility, rooted in the error of free will. Schopenhauer argued against this perspective: he suggested that because certain actions lead to feelings of guilt, there must be a sense of responsibility; otherwise, there would be no reason for that guilt if all human actions were performed out of necessity, which he believed to be true; additionally, he claimed that a person cannot exist because of the same necessity. From the existence of guilt, Schopenhauer believed he could demonstrate a freedom that humans must somehow possess—not regarding actions, but concerning existence; a liberty to be this way or that, not to act this way or that. In his view, from the esse, the realm of freedom and responsibility, follows the operari, the realm of strict causality, necessity, and irresponsibility. The guilt seems to be directed at the operari—thus it's misguided—but in truth, it relates to the esse, which comes from a free will, the [Pg 60] fundamental cause of a person's existence; a person becomes what they wish to be, with their will preceding their existence. A faulty conclusion is drawn that the presence of guilt implies a justification for it, and based on this mistaken assumption, Schopenhauer arrives at his elaborate idea of so-called intelligible freedom. However, the guilt after an action isn’t necessarily justified—in fact, it's likely not justified at all, as it rests on the incorrect assumption that the action didn’t have to happen. Consequently, it’s only because people believe they are free, not because they actually are free, that they feel guilt and conscience pangs. Moreover, this guilt can be a habit that can be broken; many people feel no guilt related to actions that others do. It’s quite variable and linked to the evolution of customs and culture and likely only exists for a relatively brief period in history. No one is accountable for their actions, nor for their nature; to pass judgment is to be unjust. This holds true even when a person judges themselves. The theory is as clear as day, yet everyone tends to retreat into the shadows of untruth, fearing the consequences.

40.

40.

The Super-animal.—The beast in us wishes to be deceived; morality is a lie of necessity in[Pg 62] order that we may not be torn in pieces by it. Without the errors which lie in the assumption of morality, man would have remained an animal. Thus, however, he has considered himself as something higher and has laid strict laws upon himself. Therefore he hates the grades which have remained nearer to animalness, whereby the former scorn of the slave, as a not-yet-man, is to be explained as a fact.

The Super Animal.—The beast within us wants to be fooled; morality is a necessary illusion in[Pg 62] order to avoid being torn apart by it. Without the misconceptions that come with the idea of morality, humanity would have stayed animalistic. Because of this, people see themselves as something greater and impose strict rules on themselves. As a result, they despise those who are closer to their animal instincts, which explains the former contempt for the slave, viewed as not yet fully human.

41.

41.

The Unchangeable Character.—That the character is unchangeable is not true in a strict sense; this favourite theory means, rather, that during the short lifetime of an individual the new influencing motives cannot penetrate deeply enough to destroy the ingrained marks of many thousands of years. But if one were to imagine a man of eighty thousand years, one would have in him an absolutely changeable character, so that a number of different individuals would gradually develop out of him. The shortness of human life misleads us into forming many erroneous ideas about the qualities of man.

The Unchangeable Nature.—It's not strictly true that character is unchangeable; this popular belief suggests that, during a person's short life, new influences can't penetrate deeply enough to erase the deeply ingrained traits developed over thousands of years. However, if one were to envision a person who lived for eighty thousand years, that person would have a completely changeable character, allowing multiple different identities to gradually emerge from him. The brevity of human life leads us to form many misconceptions about human qualities.

42.

42.

The Order of Possessions and Morality.—The once-accepted hierarchy of possessions, according as this or the other is coveted by a lower, higher, or highest egoism, now decides what is moral or immoral. To prefer a lesser good (for instance, the gratification of the senses)[Pg 63] to a more highly valued good (for instance, health) is accounted immoral, and also to prefer luxury to liberty. The hierarchy of possessions, however, is not fixed and equal at all times; if any one prefers vengeance to justice he is moral according to the standard of an earlier civilisation, but immoral according to the present one. To be "immoral," therefore, denotes that an individual has not felt, or not felt sufficiently strongly, the higher, finer, spiritual motives which have come in with a new culture; it marks one who has remained behind, but only according to the difference of degrees. The order of possessions itself is not raised and lowered according to a moral point of view; but each time that it is fixed it supplies the decision as to whether an action is moral or immoral.

The Order of Possessions and Morality.—The once-accepted ranking of possessions, based on what is desired by a lower, higher, or highest form of egoism, now determines what is considered moral or immoral. Choosing a lesser good (like satisfying the senses)[Pg 63] over a higher valued good (such as health) is seen as immoral, as is preferring luxury over freedom. However, the hierarchy of possessions isn’t fixed or equal at all times; for example, if someone prefers revenge to justice, they may be considered moral by the standards of an earlier civilization, but immoral by today's standards. To be "immoral," then, means that a person hasn’t recognized, or hasn’t recognized strongly enough, the higher, more refined, spiritual motivations that have emerged with a new culture; it identifies someone who has lagged behind, but only in terms of degrees. The order of possessions itself is not adjusted up or down from a moral perspective; instead, each time it is established, it determines whether an action is moral or immoral.

43.

43.

Cruel People As Those Who Have Remained Behind.—People who are cruel nowadays must be accounted for by us as the grades of earlier civilisations which have survived; here are exposed those deeper formations in the mountain of humanity which usually remain concealed. They are backward people whose brains, through all manner of accidents in the course of inheritance, have not been developed in so delicate and manifold a way. They show us what we all were and horrify us, but they themselves are as little responsible as is a block of granite for being granite. There must, too, be grooves and twists in our brains which answer to[Pg 64] that condition of mind, as in the form of certain human organs there are supposed to be traces of a fish-state. But these grooves and twists are no longer the bed through which the stream of our sensation flows.

Cruel People as Those Who Have Stayed Behind.—Cruel people today can be seen as remnants of earlier civilizations that have survived; they reveal the deeper layers of humanity that are usually hidden. These are backward individuals whose brains, due to various factors throughout their ancestry, haven't developed as delicately or diversely. They reflect what we all were and disturb us, but they are just as little to blame as a block of granite for being granite. There must also be patterns in our brains that relate to[Pg 64] that state of mind, similar to how certain human organs are thought to show traces of a fish-like existence. However, these patterns are no longer the channel through which our sensations flow.

44.

44.

Gratitude and Revenge.—The reason why the powerful man is grateful is this: his benefactor, through the benefit he confers, has mistaken and intruded into the sphere of the powerful man,—now the latter, in return, penetrates into the sphere of the benefactor by the act of gratitude. It is a milder form of revenge. Without the satisfaction of gratitude, the powerful man would have shown himself powerless, and would have been reckoned as such ever after. Therefore every society of the good, which originally meant the powerful, places gratitude amongst the first duties.—Swift propounded the maxim that men were grateful in the same proportion as they were revengeful.

Gratitude and Revenge.—The reason why the powerful person feels grateful is this: their benefactor, by offering a benefit, has crossed into the powerful person's domain—now the powerful person, in response, enters the benefactor's space through the act of gratitude. It's a softer form of revenge. Without the fulfillment of gratitude, the powerful person would appear powerless and would be seen that way forever after. Therefore, every society of the good, which originally meant the powerful, places gratitude among the highest responsibilities.—Swift suggested that people are grateful in proportion to how revengeful they are.

45.

45.

The Twofold Early History of Good and Evil.—The conception of good and evil has a twofold early history, namely, once in the soul of the ruling tribes and castes. Whoever has the power of returning good for good, evil for evil, and really practises requital, and who is, therefore, grateful and revengeful, is called good; whoever is powerless, and unable to requite, is reckoned as bad. As a good man one is reckoned among the[Pg 65] "good," a community which has common feelings because the single individuals are bound to one another by the sense of requital. As a bad man one belongs to the "bad," to a party of subordinate, powerless people who have no common feeling. The good are a caste, the bad are a mass like dust. Good and bad have for a long time meant the same thing as noble and base, master and slave. On the other hand, the enemy is not looked upon as evil, he can requite. In Homer the Trojan and the Greek are both good. It is not the one who injures us, but the one who is despicable, who is called bad. Good is inherited in the community of the good; it is impossible that a bad man could spring from such good soil. If, nevertheless, one of the good ones does something which is unworthy of the good, refuge is sought in excuses; the guilt is thrown upon a god, for instance; it is said that he has struck the good man with blindness and madness.—

The Dual Early History of Good and Evil.—The idea of good and evil has an early history that can be understood in two ways: first, within the souls of the ruling tribes and castes. Those who are capable of returning kindness for kindness, harm for harm, and genuinely practice reciprocity—who are, therefore, both grateful and vengeful—are considered good. Those who are powerless and unable to respond in kind are seen as bad. As a good person, one is counted among the[Pg 65] "good," a community tied together by shared feelings because its members are connected through a sense of reciprocity. Conversely, a bad person belongs to the "bad," a group of subordinate, powerless individuals who lack any shared sentiment. The good form a distinct caste, while the bad are seen as a mass, like dust. For a long time, good and bad have also meant noble and base, master and slave. However, an enemy isn't seen as evil because they can retaliate. In Homer, both the Trojans and the Greeks are regarded as good. It’s not the one who harms us but the one who is contemptible who is labeled bad. Goodness is inherited within the community of the good; it's believed that a bad person could not arise from such virtuous origins. If, however, someone deemed good does something unworthy, excuses are made; the blame is often placed on a god, claiming that they struck the good person with blindness or madness.

Then in the soul of the oppressed and powerless. Here every other man is looked upon as hostile, inconsiderate, rapacious, cruel, cunning, be he noble or base; evil is the distinguishing word for man, even for every conceivable living creature, e.g. for a god; human, divine, is the same thing as devilish, evil. The signs of goodness, helpfulness, pity, are looked upon with fear as spite, the prelude to a terrible result, stupefaction and out-witting,—in short, as refined malice. With such a disposition in the individual a community could hardly exist, or at most it could exist only in its crudest form, so that in all places where this[Pg 66] conception of good and evil obtains, the downfall of the single individuals, of their tribes and races, is at hand.—Our present civilisation has grown up on the soil of the ruling tribes and castes.

Then in the hearts of the oppressed and powerless. Here every other person is seen as hostile, thoughtless, greedy, cruel, sly, whether they are noble or lowly; evil is the defining term for humanity, even for every imaginable living thing, e.g. for a god; human and divine equate to devilish and evil. Signs of goodness, helpfulness, and compassion are viewed with fear as spite, a precursor to a terrible outcome, confusion and deception,—in short, as refined malice. With such a mindset in individuals, a community could barely survive, or at best, it could exist only in its most primitive form, so that in all places where this[Pg 66] understanding of good and evil exists, the downfall of individuals, their tribes, and races is imminent.—Our current civilization has developed on the soil of the ruling tribes and castes.

46.

46.

Sympathy Stronger Than Suffering.—There are cases when sympathy is stronger than actual suffering. For instance, we are more pained when one of our friends is guilty of something shameful than when we do it ourselves. For one thing, we have more faith in the purity of his character than he has himself; then our love for him, probably on account of this very faith, is stronger than his love for himself. And even if his egoism suffers more thereby than our egoism, inasmuch as it has to bear more of the bad consequences of his fault, the un-egoistic in us—this word is not to be taken too seriously, but only as a modification of the expression—is more deeply wounded by his guilt than is the un-egoistic in him.

Sympathy Stronger Than Pain.—There are times when our sympathy is stronger than the pain of actual suffering. For example, we feel more hurt when a friend does something shameful than when we do it ourselves. One reason is that we often have more faith in the goodness of their character than they do. Also, our love for them, likely because of this belief, is usually stronger than their love for themselves. Even if their self-importance feels the impact of their mistakes more than ours does, since they face the greater consequences of their actions, the selfless part of us—this term should be understood more loosely as a variation of the idea—feels more deeply wounded by their wrongdoing than the selfless part within them does.

47.

47.

Hypochondria.—There are people who become hypochondriacal through their sympathy and concern for another person; the kind of sympathy which results therefrom is nothing but a disease. Thus there is also a Christian hypochondria, which afflicts those solitary, religiously-minded people who keep constantly before their eyes the sufferings and death of Christ.

Health anxiety.—Some people become hypochondriacal because they empathize with and worry about someone else; this kind of empathy can turn into a sickness. There is also a type of Christian hypochondria that affects those solitary, religious individuals who constantly focus on the suffering and death of Christ.

48.

48.

Economy of Goodness.—Goodness and love, as the most healing herbs and powers in human intercourse, are such costly discoveries that one would wish as much economy as possible to be exercised in the employment of these balsamic means; but this is impossible. The economy of goodness is the dream of the most daring Utopians.

Goodness Economy.—Goodness and love, being the most healing qualities in human relationships, are valuable discoveries that we wish could be used as efficiently as possible; however, this is not feasible. The economy of goodness is an ideal envisioned by the boldest Utopians.

49.

49.

Goodwill.—Amongst the small, but countlessly frequent and therefore very effective, things to which science should pay more attention than to the great, rare things, is to be reckoned goodwill; I mean that exhibition of a friendly disposition in intercourse, that smiling eye, that clasp of the hand, that cheerfulness with which almost all human actions are usually accompanied. Every teacher, every official, adds this to whatever is his duty; it is the perpetual occupation of humanity, and at the same time the waves of its light, in which everything grows; in the narrowest circle, namely, within the family, life blooms and flourishes only through that goodwill. Kindliness, friendliness, the courtesy of the heart, are ever-flowing streams of un-egoistic impulses, and have given far more powerful assistance to culture than even those much more famous demonstrations which are called pity, mercy, and self-sacrifice. But they are thought little of, and, as a matter of fact, there is not much that is un-egoistic[Pg 68] in them. The sum of these small doses is nevertheless mighty, their united force is amongst the strongest forces. Thus one finds much more happiness in the world than sad eyes see, if one only reckons rightly, and does not forget all those moments of comfort in which every day is rich, even in the most harried of human lives.

Kindness.—Among the small but incredibly frequent and therefore very effective things that science should focus on more than the big, rare occurrences, is goodwill; I mean that display of a friendly attitude in interactions, that bright smile, that handshake, that warmth that almost all human actions usually carry. Every teacher, every official adds this to their responsibilities; it’s the constant endeavor of humanity, and at the same time the light in which everything thrives; within the smallest circle, namely, within the family, life only blossoms through that goodwill. Kindness, friendliness, and heartfelt courtesy are ever-flowing streams of altruistic impulses, and they have contributed far more significantly to culture than those much more renowned acts known as pity, mercy, and self-sacrifice. Yet, they are often overlooked, and, in reality, there isn’t much that is truly selfless in them. The sum of these small acts is nonetheless powerful, their combined influence is among the strongest forces. Thus, one finds much more happiness in the world than sad eyes perceive, if one simply looks closely and remembers all those moments of comfort that each day offers, even in the most challenging human lives.

50.

50.

The Wish to Arouse Pity.—In the most remarkable passage of his auto—portrait (first printed in 1658), La Rochefoucauld assuredly hits the nail on the head when he warns all sensible people against pity, when he advises them to leave that to those orders of the people who have need of passion (because it is not ruled by reason), and to reach the point of helping the suffering and acting energetically in an accident; while pity, according to his (and Plato's) judgment, weakens the soul. Certainly we should exhibit pity, but take good care not to feel it, for the unfortunate are so stupid that to them the exhibition of pity is the greatest good in the world. One can, perhaps, give a more forcible warning against this feeling of pity if one looks upon that need of the unfortunate not exactly as stupidity and lack of intellect, a kind of mental derangement which misfortune brings with it (and as such, indeed, La Rochefoucauld appears to regard it), but as something quite different and more serious. Observe children, who cry and scream in order to be pitied, and therefore wait[Pg 69] for the moment when they will be noticed; live in intercourse with the sick and mentally oppressed, and ask yourself whether that ready complaining and whimpering, that making a show of misfortune, does not, at bottom, aim at making the spectators miserable; the pity which the spectators then exhibit is in so far a consolation for the weak and suffering in that the latter recognise therein that they possess still one power, in spite of their weakness, the power of giving pain. The unfortunate derives a sort of pleasure from this feeling of superiority, of which the exhibition of pity makes him conscious; his imagination is exalted, he is still powerful enough to give the world pain. Thus the thirst for pity is the thirst for self-gratification, and that, moreover, at the expense of his fellow-men; it shows man in the whole inconsiderateness of his own dear self, but not exactly in his "stupidity," as La Rochefoucauld thinks. In society-talk three-fourths of all questions asked and of all answers given are intended to cause the interlocutor a little pain; for this reason so many people pine for company; it enables them to feel their power. There is a powerful charm of life in such countless but very small doses in which malice makes itself felt, just as goodwill, spread in the same way throughout the world, is the ever-ready means of healing. But are there many honest people who will admit that it is pleasing to give pain? that one not infrequently amuses one's self—and amuses one's self very well—in causing mortifications to others, at least in thought, and firing off at them the[Pg 70] grape-shot of petty malice? Most people are too dishonest, and a few are too good, to know anything of this pudendum these will always deny that Prosper Mérimée is right when he says, "Sachez aussi qu'il n'y a rien de plus commun que de faire le mal pour le plaisir de le faire."

The Need to Inspire Sympathy.—In the most striking part of his autobiography (first printed in 1658), La Rochefoucauld definitely hits the nail on the head when he warns all sensible people against pity. He advises them to leave that to those types of people who need passion (since it isn’t guided by reason) and to focus on helping the suffering and acting decisively in emergencies; while pity, according to his (and Plato's) view, weakens the soul. Certainly, we should show pity, but we should be careful not to feel it, because the unfortunate are so naive that to them, the display of pity is the greatest good in the world. One can perhaps give a stronger warning against this feeling of pity if we view the need of the unfortunate not just as naivety or a lack of intellect—like a sort of mental disorder brought on by misfortune (which, indeed, La Rochefoucauld seems to see it as)—but as something much more serious. Observe children, who cry and scream to be pitied, and therefore wait[Pg 69] for the moment they will be noticed; engage with the sick and mentally distressed, and ask yourself whether their constant complaining and whimpering, their showing off their misfortune, doesn’t ultimately aim at making the observers feel miserable; the pity the observers then show serves as a consolation for the weak and suffering, as it lets them realize they still have one power, despite their weakness, the power to inflict pain. The unfortunate get a sort of pleasure from this feeling of superiority, from which the display of pity makes them aware; their imagination is lifted, they are still powerful enough to cause pain in the world. Thus, the desire for pity is the desire for self-gratification, often at the expense of others; it reveals the inconsiderateness of human nature, but not exactly in its “naivety,” as La Rochefoucauld believes. In social conversations, three-quarters of all questions asked and answers given are meant to cause the other person a little pain; that’s why so many people crave company; it allows them to feel their power. There is a strong allure in the countless small doses of malice experienced in life, just as goodwill, spread similarly throughout the world, is a readily available means of healing. But are there many honest people who will admit that it feels good to inflict pain? That one often finds pleasure—and quite a bit of enjoyment—in causing embarrassment to others, even just in thought, and launching the[Pg 70] grape-shot of minor malice? Most people are too dishonest, and a few are too good, to recognize this shameful truth; they will always deny that Prosper Mérimée is right when he says, "Know that there is nothing more common than doing harm for the pleasure of doing it."

51.

51.

How Appearance Becomes Actuality.—The actor finally reaches such a point that even in the deepest sorrow he cannot cease from thinking about the impression made by his own person and the general scenic effect; for instance, even at the funeral of his child, he will weep over his own sorrow and its expression like one of his own audience. The hypocrite, who always plays one and the same part, ceases at last to be a hypocrite; for instance, priests, who as young men are generally conscious or unconscious hypocrites, become at last natural, and are then really without any affectation, just priests; or if the father does not succeed so far, perhaps the son does, who makes use of his father's progress and inherits his habits. If any one long and obstinately desires to appear something, he finds it difficult at last to be anything else. The profession of almost every individual, even of the artist, begins with hypocrisy, with an imitating from without, with a copying of the effective. He who always wears the mask of a friendly expression must eventually obtain a power over well-meaning dispositions without which the expression of friendliness is not to be[Pg 71] compelled,—and finally, these, again, obtain a power over him, he is well-meaning.

How Appearance Becomes Reality.—The actor eventually reaches a point where, even in his deepest sorrow, he can't stop thinking about the impression he makes and the overall effect of the performance. For example, even at his child's funeral, he will mourn not just for his loss but also for how that sorrow looks to others, like one of his audience members. The hypocrite, who continuously plays the same role, ultimately stops being a hypocrite; for instance, priests, who often start out as either conscious or unconscious hypocrites, eventually become genuine, and then they are just priests without any pretense. If the father doesn’t achieve this, perhaps the son does, leveraging his father's progress and inheriting his ways. If someone desperately wants to appear a certain way for a long time, they find it hard to be anything else. Most people’s professions, including that of artists, start with a form of hypocrisy, mimicking from the outside, copying what works. Someone who always wears a friendly expression will eventually gain influence over well-intentioned behaviors that cannot be summoned without that friendly mask—and ultimately, these behaviors will gain influence over him, and he is genuinely well-meaning.

52.

52.

The Point of Honour in Deception.—In all great deceivers one thing is noteworthy, to which they owe their power. In the actual act of deception, with all their preparations, the dreadful voice, expression, and mien, in the midst of their effective scenery they are overcome by their belief in themselves it is this, then, which speaks so wonderfully and persuasively to the spectators. The founders of religions are distinguished from those great deceivers in that they never awake from their condition of self-deception; or at times, but very rarely, they have an enlightened moment when doubt overpowers them; they generally console themselves, however, by ascribing these enlightened moments to the influence of the Evil One. There must be self-deception in order that this and that may produce great effects. For men believe in the truth of everything that is visibly, strongly believed in.

The Importance of Honor in Deception.—In all great deceivers, one thing stands out that they owe their power to. During the act of deception, despite all their preparations and the intense voice, expression, and demeanor they display amid their convincing settings, they are driven by their belief in themselves; this is what resonates so powerfully and persuasively with the audience. The founders of religions differ from those great deceivers in that they rarely emerge from their state of self-deception; or on rare occasions, they experience a moment of clarity when doubt takes over. However, they usually comfort themselves by attributing these enlightened moments to the influence of the Evil One. There must be self-deception for this or that to produce great effects. People believe in the truth of everything that is visibly and strongly believed in.

53.

53.

The Nominal Degrees of Truth.—One of the commonest mistakes is this: because some one is truthful and honest towards us, he must speak the truth. Thus the child believes in its parents' judgment, the Christian in the assertions of the Founder of the Church. In the same way men refuse to admit that all those things which men defended in former ages with the sacrifice of[Pg 72] life and happiness were nothing but errors; it is even said, perhaps, that they were degrees of the truth. But what is really meant is that when a man has honestly believed in something, and has fought and died for his faith, it would really be too unjust if he had only been inspired by an error. Such a thing seems a contradiction of eternal justice; therefore the heart of sensitive man ever enunciates against his head the axiom: between moral action and intellectual insight there must absolutely be a necessary connection. It is unfortunately otherwise; for there is no eternal justice.

The Basic Truth Levels.—One of the most common mistakes is this: just because someone is truthful and honest with us, it doesn't mean they always speak the truth. For example, a child trusts their parents' judgment, and a Christian believes in the teachings of the Church's Founder. Similarly, people often refuse to accept that all the things that were defended in the past with the sacrifice of[Pg 72] life and happiness were just mistakes; some even say they represented degrees of truth. But what’s really meant is that when a person has sincerely believed in something, and has fought and died for their beliefs, it feels incredibly unjust if they were motivated only by an error. Such a situation seems to contradict the idea of eternal justice; thus the sensitive heart of a person tends to assert against their intellect the belief that there must be a necessary connection between moral actions and intellectual understanding. Unfortunately, that's not the case; there is no eternal justice.

54.

54.

Falsehood.—Why do people mostly speak the truth in daily life?—Assuredly not because a god has forbidden falsehood. But, firstly, because it is more convenient, as falsehood requires invention, deceit, and memory. (As Swift says, he who tells a lie is not sensible how great a task he undertakes; for in order to uphold one lie he must invent twenty others.) Therefore, because it is advantageous in upright circumstances to say straight out, "I want this, I have done that," and so on; because, in other words, the path of compulsion and authority is surer than that of cunning. But if a child has been brought up in complicated domestic circumstances, he employs falsehood, naturally and unconsciously says whatever best suits his interests; a sense of truth and a hatred of falsehood are quite foreign and unknown to him, and so he lies in all innocence.

Lies.—Why do people mostly speak the truth in everyday life?—Definitely not because a god has forbidden lying. Instead, it's because it's easier; lying requires creativity, deceit, and keeping track of what you've said. (As Swift points out, anyone who tells a lie doesn't realize how big of a task they're taking on; to support one lie, they must come up with twenty others.) So, in honest situations, it's more beneficial to just say, "I want this, I did that," and so on; in other words, the route of straightforwardness and clarity is more reliable than trickery. However, if a child grows up in complicated home situations, they might use lies, naturally and unconsciously saying whatever serves their interests best; concepts of truth and a dislike for lying are completely foreign to them, so they lie without any guile.

55.

55.

Throwing Suspicion on Morality For Faith's Sake.—No power can be maintained when it is only represented by hypocrites; no matter how many "worldly" elements the Catholic Church possesses, its strength lies in those still numerous priestly natures who render life hard and full of meaning for themselves, and whose glance and worn bodies speak of nocturnal vigils, hunger, burning prayers, and perhaps even of scourging; these move men and inspire them with fear. What if it were necessary to live thus? This is the terrible question which their aspect brings to the lips. Whilst they spread this doubt they always uprear another pillar of their power; even the free-thinker does not dare to withstand such unselfishness with hard words of truth, and to say, "Thyself deceived, deceive not others!" Only the difference of views divides them from him, certainly no difference of goodness or badness; but men generally treat unjustly that which they do not like. Thus we speak of the cunning and the infamous art of the Jesuits, but overlook the self-control which every individual Jesuit practises, and the fact that the lightened manner of life preached by Jesuit books is by no means for their benefit, but for that of the laity. We may even ask whether, with precisely similar tactics and organisation, we enlightened ones would make equally good tools, equally admirable through self-conquest, indefatigableness, and renunciation.

Casting Doubt on Morality for the Sake of Faith.—No power can be sustained when it’s only represented by hypocrites; no matter how many "worldly" elements the Catholic Church has, its strength comes from those still numerous priestly figures who make life challenging and meaningful for themselves, and whose gaze and tired bodies tell stories of late-night vigils, hunger, fervent prayers, and maybe even self-punishment; these individuals move people and instill fear in them. What if it were necessary to live like this? This is the daunting question that their presence raises. While they spread this doubt, they always reinforce another pillar of their authority; even free-thinkers hesitate to confront such selflessness with harsh truths and say, "You’re deceived, don’t deceive others!" Only differing viewpoints separate them from him, certainly not differences in goodness or badness; but people usually treat unfairly what they don't like. Thus, we speak of the cunning and the infamous tactics of the Jesuits, but overlook the self-discipline that each Jesuit practices, and the fact that the easier way of life promoted by Jesuit writings is not for their benefit, but for the laypeople's. One might even wonder whether, using exactly the same strategies and organization, we enlightened individuals would become equally effective instruments, equally admirable through self-discipline, tirelessness, and sacrifice.

56.

56.

Victory of Knowledge Over Radical Evil.—It is of great advantage to him who desires to be wise to have witnessed for a time the spectacle of a thoroughly evil and degenerate man; it is false, like the contrary spectacle, but for whole long periods it held the mastery, and its roots have even extended and ramified themselves to us and our world. In order to understand ourselves we must understand it but then, in order to mount higher we must rise above it. We recognise, then, that there exist no sins in the metaphysical sense; but, in the same sense, also no virtues; we recognise that the entire domain of ethical ideas is perpetually tottering, that there are higher and deeper conceptions of good and evil, of moral and immoral. He who does not desire much more from things than a knowledge of them easily makes peace with his soul, and will make a mistake (or commit a sin, as the world calls it) at the most from ignorance, but hardly from covetousness. He will no longer wish to excommunicate and exterminate desires; but his only, his wholly dominating ambition, to know as well as possible at all times, will make him cool and will soften all the savageness in his disposition. Moreover, he has been freed from a number of tormenting conceptions, he has no more feeling at the mention of the words "punishments of hell," "sinfulness," "incapacity for good," he recognises in them only the vanishing shadow-pictures of false views of the world and of life.

Victory of Knowledge Over Radical Evil.—It’s really beneficial for anyone who wants to be wise to have observed a truly evil and depraved person for a while; it’s an illusion, just like the opposite view, but for a long time, it dominated, and its influence has spread to us and our world. To understand ourselves, we need to understand it, but then, to rise above it, we have to go beyond that understanding. We recognize that there are no sins in the metaphysical sense; similarly, there are no virtues either; we see that the whole realm of ethical concepts is constantly unstable, and there are deeper and higher ideas of good and evil, of moral and immoral. Someone who doesn’t seek much more from things than just knowledge of them can easily find peace within themselves, and any mistakes they make (or sins, as society calls them) will most likely stem from ignorance rather than greed. They will no longer desire to reject or eliminate their desires; instead, their main ambition to know as much as possible at all times will calm them down and soften any harshness in their nature. Furthermore, they will be free from a lot of distressing ideas; the terms "punishments of hell," "sinfulness," and "incapacity for good" won't affect them anymore, as they now see these only as fading shadows of mistaken interpretations of the world and life.

57.

57.

Morality As the Self-disintegration of Man.—A good author, who really has his heart in his work, wishes that some one could come and annihilate him by representing the same thing in a clearer way and answering without more ado the problems therein proposed. The loving girl wishes she could prove the self-sacrificing faithfulness of her love by the unfaithfulness of her beloved. The soldier hopes to die on the field of battle for his victorious fatherland; for his loftiest desires triumph in the victory of his country. The mother gives to the child that of which she deprives herself—sleep, the best food, sometimes her health and fortune. But are all these un-egoistic conditions? Are these deeds of morality miracles, because, to use Schopenhauer's expression, they are "impossible and yet performed"? Is it not clear that in all four cases the individual loves something of himself, a thought, a desire, a production, better than anything else of himself; that he therefore divides his nature and to one part sacrifices all the rest? Is it something entirely different when an obstinate man says, "I would rather be shot than move a step out of my way for this man"? The desire for something (wish, inclination, longing) is present in all the instances mentioned; to give way to it, with all its consequences, is certainly not "un-egoistic."—In ethics man does not consider himself as Individuum but as dividuum.

Morality as the Breakdown of the Individual.—A passionate author, who genuinely cares about his work, wishes someone could come along and completely replace him by expressing the same ideas more clearly and addressing the questions posed without hesitation. The devoted girl longs to demonstrate the selfless loyalty of her love through the unfaithfulness of her partner. The soldier desires to die in battle for his victorious homeland, as his highest aspirations lie in the triumph of his country. The mother sacrifices her own sleep, the best meals, and sometimes even her health and well-being for her child. But are these actions really selfless? Are these moral deeds miracles, since, to quote Schopenhauer, they are "impossible and yet done"? Isn’t it obvious that in all four situations, the individual loves something about themselves, a thought, a wish, a creation, more than anything else about themselves; thus, they divide their being and sacrifice everything else to one part? Isn’t it entirely different when a stubborn person says, "I would rather be shot than take a step out of my way for this man"? The desire for something (wish, inclination, longing) exists in all the examples given; giving in to it, along with its consequences, is certainly not "selfless."—In ethics, a person does not see themselves as Individuum but as dividuum.

58.

58.

What One May Promise.—One may promise actions, but no sentiments, for these are involuntary. Whoever promises to love or hate a person, or be faithful to him for ever, promises something which is not within his power; he can certainly promise such actions as are usually the results of love, hate, or fidelity, but which may also spring from other motives; for many ways and motives lead to one and the same action. The promise to love some one for ever is, therefore, really: So long as I love you I will act towards you in a loving way; if I cease to love you, you will still receive the same treatment from me, although inspired by other motives, so that our fellow-men will still be deluded into the belief that our love is unchanged and ever the same. One promises, therefore, the continuation of the semblance of love, when, without self-deception, one speaks vows of eternal love.

What Someone Might Promise.—One can promise actions, but not feelings, because those are involuntary. Anyone who promises to love or hate someone, or to be faithful to them forever, is promising something beyond their control; they can certainly promise actions that usually result from love, hate, or fidelity, but which can also come from other motivations. Many paths and reasons can lead to the same action. Therefore, the promise to love someone forever really means: As long as I love you, I will treat you in a loving way; if I stop loving you, you will still be treated the same way by me, but for different reasons, so other people will continue to believe that our love is unchanged and constant. Hence, one is promising to maintain the appearance of love when, without self-deception, one makes vows of eternal love.

59.

59.

Intellect and Morality.—One must have a good memory to be able to keep a given promise. One must have a strong power of imagination to be able to feel pity. So closely is morality bound to the goodness of the intellect.

Intelligence and Ethics.—You need a good memory to keep a promise. You need a strong imagination to feel compassion. Morality is closely tied to the goodness of the intellect.

60.

60.

TO WISH FOR REVENGE AND TO TAKE REVENGE.—To have a revengeful thought and to[Pg 77] carry it into effect is to have a violent attack of fever, which passes off, however,—but to have a revengeful thought without the strength and courage to carry it out is a chronic disease, a poisoning of body and soul which we have to bear about with us. Morality, which only takes intentions into account, considers the two cases as equal; usually the former case is regarded as the worse (because of the evil consequences which may perhaps result from the deed of revenge). Both estimates are short-sighted.

To desire revenge and to enact revenge.—Having a vengeful thought and actually acting on it is like having a fever that eventually goes away; however, having a vengeful thought without the strength or courage to act on it is a long-term illness—a toxic burden on both body and soul that we carry with us. Morality, which only considers intentions, treats both situations as the same; typically, the first case is seen as worse (because of the potential negative outcomes of the revenge act). Both perspectives are shortsighted.

61.

61.

The Power of Waiting.—Waiting is so difficult that even great poets have not disdained to take incapability of waiting as the motive for their works. Thus Shakespeare in Othello or Sophocles in Ajax, to whom suicide, had he been able to let his feelings cool down for one day, would no longer have seemed necessary, as the oracle intimated; he would probably have snapped his fingers at the terrible whisperings of wounded vanity, and said to himself, "Who has not already, in my circumstances, mistaken a fool for a hero? Is it something so very extraordinary?" On the contrary, it is something very commonly human; Ajax might allow himself that consolation. Passion will not wait; the tragedy in the lives of great men frequently lies not in their conflict with the times and the baseness of their fellow-men, but in their incapacity of postponing their work for a year or two; they cannot wait. In all duels advising[Pg 78] friends have one thing to decide, namely whether the parties concerned can still wait awhile; if this is not the case, then a duel is advisable, inasmuch as each of the two says, "Either I continue to live and that other man must die immediately, or vice versa." In such case waiting would mean a prolonged suffering of the terrible martyrdom of wounded honour in the face of the insulter, and this may entail more suffering than life is worth.

The Strength of Patience.—Waiting is so tough that even great poets have made their inability to wait the focus of their works. For instance, in Othello, Shakespeare and in Ajax, Sophocles, who might have avoided suicide if they had been able to cool down for just one day, as the oracle suggested; they probably would have dismissed the awful thoughts of hurt pride and told themselves, "Who hasn’t, in my position, confused a fool with a hero? Is it really that unusual?" On the contrary, it’s something very human; Ajax could take comfort in that. Passion doesn’t wait; the tragedy in the lives of great men often lies not in their struggle against the times or the meanness of others, but in their inability to put off their work for a year or two; they just can’t wait. In every duel, the advising friends have one key question to decide: whether the parties involved can still wait a little longer; if they can’t, then a duel makes sense, because each one thinks, "Either I keep living and that other person has to die right now, or vice versa." In that situation, waiting would mean enduring the awful torment of wounded honor in the face of the person who insulted them, and that might involve more pain than life is worth.

62.

62.

Revelling in Vengeance.—Coarser individuals who feel themselves insulted, make out the insult to be as great as possible, and relate the affair in greatly exaggerated language, in order to be able to revel thoroughly in the rarely awakened feelings of hatred and revenge.

Reveling in Revenge.—Rougher people who feel insulted tend to blow the insult out of proportion and tell the story in an exaggerated way so they can fully indulge in the seldom stirred emotions of hatred and revenge.

63.

63.

The Value of Disparagement.—In order to maintain their self-respect in their own eyes and a certain thoroughness of action, not a few men, perhaps even the majority, find it absolutely necessary to run down and disparage all their acquaintances. But as mean natures are numerous, and since it is very important whether they possess that thoroughness or lose it, hence——

The Importance of Disparagement.—To keep their self-respect and a certain level of decisiveness, many men, maybe even most, feel it's essential to put down and criticize everyone they know. But since there are many petty individuals, and it’s crucial whether they maintain that decisiveness or lose it, therefore——

64.

64.

The Man in a Passion.—We must beware of one who is in a passion against us as of one who[Pg 79] has once sought our life; for the fact that we still live is due to the absence of power to kill,—if looks would suffice, we should have been dead long ago. It is a piece of rough civilisation to force some one into silence by the exhibition of physical savageness and the inspiring of fear. That cold glance which exalted persons employ towards their servants is also a relic of that caste division between man and man, a piece of rough antiquity; women, the preservers of ancient things, have also faithfully retained this survival of an ancient habit.

The Man in Love.—We need to be cautious of someone who is angry with us, just like we would be wary of someone who has previously tried to harm us; the only reason we’re still alive is that they lack the ability to actually kill us. If a deadly gaze could do the trick, we would have been gone a long time ago. It’s a sign of a harsh society to force someone into silence through displays of physical aggression and instilling fear. That cold look that powerful people give their servants is also a remnant of the social divide between individuals, a piece of outdated tradition; women, the keepers of old customs, have also held on to this survival of a bygone practice.

65.

65.

Whither Honesty Can Lead.—Somebody had the bad habit of occasionally talking quite frankly about the motives of his actions, which were as good and as bad as the motives of most men. He first gave offence, then aroused suspicion, was then gradually excluded from society and declared a social outlaw, until at last justice remembered such an abandoned creature, on occasions when it would otherwise have had no eyes, or would have closed them. The lack of power to hold his tongue concerning the common secret, and the irresponsible tendency to see what no one wishes to see—himself—brought him to a prison and an early death.

Where Honesty Can Take You.—Someone had the bad habit of occasionally speaking very openly about the reasons behind his actions, which were as good and as bad as most people's motives. He first offended others, then raised suspicion, and was gradually pushed out of society, eventually being declared a social outcast, until justice finally took notice of such a forsaken individual, at times when it would otherwise have been blind or chose to ignore him. His inability to keep quiet about the shared secret, along with his reckless tendency to confront what no one wants to see—himself—landed him in prison and led to an early death.

66.

66.

Punishable, But Never Punished.—Our crime against criminals lies in the fact that we treat them like rascals.

Punishable, but never held accountable.—Our wrongdoing towards criminals is that we treat them like mischief-makers.

67.

67.

Sancta Simplicitas OF VIRTUE.—Every virtue has its privileges; for example, that of contributing its own little faggot to the scaffold of every condemned man.

Holy Simplicity OF VIRTUE.—Every virtue has its privileges; for instance, it can add its own small bundle of sticks to the pyre of every condemned person.

68.

68.

Morality and Consequences.—It is not only the spectators of a deed who frequently judge of its morality or immorality according to its consequences, but the doer of the deed himself does so. For the motives and intentions are seldom sufficiently clear and simple, and sometimes memory itself seems clouded by the consequences of the deed, so that one ascribes the deed to false motives or looks upon unessential motives as essential. Success often gives an action the whole honest glamour of a good conscience; failure casts the shadow of remorse over the most estimable deed. Hence arises the well-known practice of the politician, who thinks, "Only grant me success, with that I bring all honest souls over to my side and make myself honest in my own eyes." In the same way success must replace a better argument. Many educated people still believe that the triumph of Christianity over Greek philosophy is a proof of the greater truthfulness of the former,—although in this case it is only the coarser and more powerful that has triumphed over the more spiritual and delicate. Which[Pg 81] possesses the greater truth may be seen from the fact that the awakening sciences have agreed with Epicurus' philosophy on point after point, but on point after point have rejected Christianity.

Ethics and Outcomes.—It’s not just the observers of an action who often evaluate its morality or immorality based on its outcomes; the person who commits the act does this too. The motives and intentions are rarely clear-cut, and sometimes a person’s memory is clouded by the consequences of the action, leading them to attribute the act to incorrect motives or to view unimportant motives as crucial. Success often lends an action the positive glow of a clear conscience; failure, conversely, casts a shadow of regret over even the most honorable actions. This is why many politicians think, "Just give me success, and I’ll persuade all honest people to support me and feel honest in my own eyes." In the same way, success often substitutes for a stronger argument. Many educated individuals still believe that Christianity’s victory over Greek philosophy proves the greater truth of the former—when in reality, it’s simply the cruder and more forceful that has prevailed over the more refined and sensitive. Which[Pg 81] holds the greater truth can be seen in the fact that emerging sciences have aligned with Epicurus' philosophy on numerous points while rejecting Christianity on many others.

69.

69.

Love and Justice.—Why do we over-estimate love to the disadvantage of justice, and say the most beautiful things about it, as if it were something very much higher than the latter? Is it not visibly more stupid than justice? Certainly, but precisely for that reason all the pleasanter for every one. It is blind, and possesses an abundant cornucopia, out of which it distributes its gifts to all, even if they do not deserve them, even if they express no thanks for them. It is as impartial as the rain, which, according to the Bible and experience, makes not only the unjust, but also occasionally the just wet through to the skin.

Love and Justice.—Why do we exaggerate love at the expense of justice, and say the most wonderful things about it as if it were far superior to justice? Isn't it obviously more foolish than justice? Definitely, but that's exactly why it seems so much nicer to everyone. It’s blind and has an endless supply, giving out its gifts to all, even if they don’t deserve them, even if they don’t express any gratitude. It’s as impartial as the rain, which, according to the Bible and real life, soaks both the unjust and, at times, the just right to the bone.

70.

70.

Execution.—How is it that every execution offends us more than does a murder? It is the coldness of the judges, the painful preparations, the conviction that a human being is here being used as a warning to scare others. For the guilt is not punished, even if it existed—it lies with educators, parents, surroundings, in ourselves, not in the murderer—I mean the determining circumstances.

Execution.—Why does each execution bother us more than a murder does? It’s the indifference of the judges, the painful preparations, and the unsettling idea that a person is being used as a warning to frighten others. The real guilt isn’t just with the accused, even if they are guilty—it lies with educators, parents, our environment, and ourselves, not just the murderer—I mean the circumstances that led to it.

71.

71.

Hope.—Pandora brought the box of ills and opened it. It was the gift of the gods to men, outwardly a beautiful and seductive gift, and called the Casket of Happiness. Out of it flew all the evils, living winged creatures, thence they now circulate and do men injury day and night. One single evil had not yet escaped from the box, and by the will of Zeus Pandora closed the lid and it remained within. Now for ever man has the casket of happiness in his house and thinks he holds a great treasure; it is at his disposal, he stretches out his hand for it whenever he desires; for he does not know the box which Pandora brought was the casket of evil, and he believes the ill which remains within to be the greatest blessing,—it is hope. Zeus did not wish man, however much he might be tormented by the other evils, to fling away his life, but to go on letting himself be tormented again and again. Therefore he gives man hope,—in reality it is the worst of all evils, because it prolongs the torments of man.

Hope.—Pandora opened the box filled with troubles. It was a beautiful and tempting gift from the gods to humanity, called the Casket of Happiness. From it emerged all the evils, living creatures with wings, which now roam around, causing harm to people day and night. One evil, however, had not yet escaped from the box, and at Zeus's command, Pandora closed the lid, trapping it inside. Now, humanity possesses the casket of happiness in their homes, believing it to be a great treasure; they can reach for it whenever they want. Unbeknownst to them, the box that Pandora brought was actually the casket of evil, and they think that the one ill that remains inside is the greatest blessing—it is hope. Zeus did not want humanity, no matter how much they suffered from the other evils, to give up on life, but instead to keep enduring the torment over and over. Thus, he grants humanity hope—ironically the worst of all evils, because it extends human suffering.

72.

72.

The Degree of Moral Inflammability Unknown.—According to whether we have or have not had certain disturbing views and impressions—for instance, an unjustly executed, killed, or martered father; a faithless wife; a cruel hostile attack—it depends whether our passions reach fever heat and influence our whole[Pg 83] life or not. No one knows to what he may be driven by circumstances, pity, or indignation; he does not know the degree of his own inflammability. Miserable little circumstances make us miserable; it is generally not the quantity of experiences, but their quality, on which lower and higher man depends, in good and evil.

The Level of Moral Sensitivity Unknown.—Whether we have experienced certain troubling thoughts and feelings—like an unjustly executed, killed, or martyred father; a cheating spouse; or a brutal attack—affects whether our passions become overwhelming and shape our entire[Pg 83] life. No one knows what they might be driven to do by circumstances, sympathy, or anger; they don't know how easily they can be ignited. Minor situations can make us feel miserable; it's usually not about how many experiences we have, but the significance of those experiences, that influences both the good and the bad in different kinds of people.

73.

73.

The Martyr in Spite of Himself.—There was a man belonging to a party who was too nervous and cowardly ever to contradict his comrades; they made use of him for everything, they demanded everything from him, because he was more afraid of the bad opinion of his companions than of death itself; his was a miserable, feeble soul. They recognised this, and on the ground of these qualities they made a hero of him, and finally even a martyr. Although the coward inwardly always said No, with his lips he always said Yes, even on the scaffold, when he was about to die for the opinions of his party; for beside him stood one of his old companions, who so tyrannised over him by word and look that he really suffered death in the most respectable manner, and has ever since been celebrated as a martyr and a great character.

The Martyr Despite Himself.—There was a guy in a group who was too anxious and timid to ever stand up to his friends; they used him for everything and demanded everything from him, because he was more terrified of what his friends would think than of death itself; he had a pathetic, weak spirit. They noticed this, and because of these traits, they turned him into a hero, and eventually even a martyr. Even though the coward inwardly always said No, he always said Yes out loud, even when he was on the scaffold, about to die for his group's beliefs; because next to him stood one of his old friends, who dominated him with words and looks so much that he really faced death in the most respectable way, and has since been celebrated as a martyr and a great figure.

74.

74.

I the Every-day Standard.—One will seldom go wrong if one attributes extreme actions to vanity, average ones to habit, and petty ones to fear.

I the Daily Standard.—You can rarely go wrong if you think of extreme actions as stemming from vanity, average actions as coming from habit, and petty actions as driven by fear.

75.

75.

Misunderstanding Concerning Virtue.—Whoever has known immorality in connection with pleasure, as is the case with a man who has a pleasure-seeking youth behind him, imagines that virtue must be connected with absence of pleasure.—Whoever, on the contrary, has been much plagued by his passions and vices, longs to find in virtue peace and the soul's happiness. Hence it is possible for two virtuous persons not to understand each other at all.

Misunderstanding About Virtue.—Anyone who has experienced immorality linked to pleasure, like someone with a pleasure-seeking youth, believes that virtue must mean giving up pleasure. On the other hand, those who have struggled greatly with their passions and vices yearn to find peace and happiness for their soul in virtue. As a result, it's possible for two virtuous individuals not to understand each other at all.

76.

76.

The Ascetic.—The ascetic makes a necessity of virtue.

The Minimalist.—The ascetic turns virtue into a necessity.

77.

77.

Transferring Honour from the Person to the Thing.—Deeds of love and sacrifice for the benefit of one's neighbour are generally honoured, wherever they are manifested. Thereby we multiply the valuation of things which are thus loved, or for which we sacrifice ourselves, although perhaps they are not worth much in themselves. A brave army is convinced of the cause for which it fights.

Shifting Honor from the Individual to the Object.—Acts of love and sacrifice for the benefit of others are usually recognized and valued, no matter where they occur. In doing so, we increase the worth of the things that we cherish or for which we give our all, even if those things may not have much value on their own. A courageous army believes in the cause for which it is fighting.

78.

78.

Ambition a Substitute For the Moral Sense.—The moral sense must not be lacking in those natures which have no ambition. The[Pg 85] ambitious manage without it, with almost the same results. For this reason the sons of unpretentious, unambitious families, when once they lose the moral sense, generally degenerate very quickly into complete scamps.

Ambition as a Replacement for Moral Values.—People who lack ambition shouldn’t also lack a moral sense. Those who are ambitious can get by without it, often achieving similar outcomes. This is why the children of modest, unambitious families, once they lose their moral sense, typically end up becoming total delinquents very quickly.

79.

79.

Vanity Enriches.—How poor would be the human mind without vanity! Thus, however, it resembles a well-stocked and constantly replenished bazaar which attracts buyers of every kind. There they can find almost everything, obtain almost everything, provided that they bring the right sort of coin, namely admiration.

Self-importance Enriches.—How empty would the human mind be without vanity! It’s like a vibrant and ever-filled marketplace that draws in all kinds of shoppers. In this place, they can discover nearly everything and acquire almost anything, as long as they have the right currency—admiration.

80.

80.

Old Age and Death.—Apart from the commands of religion, the question may well be asked, Why is it more worthy for an old man who feels his powers decline, to await his slow exhaustion and extinction than with full consciousness to set a limit to his life? Suicide in this case is a perfectly natural, obvious action, which should justly arouse respect as a triumph of reason, and did arouse it in those times when the heads of Greek philosophy and the sturdiest patriots used to seek death through suicide. The seeking, on the contrary, to prolong existence from day to day, with anxious consultation of doctors and painful mode of living, without the power of drawing nearer to the actual aim of life, is far less worthy. Religion is rich in excuses to reply to the demand for[Pg 86] suicide, and thus it ingratiates itself with those who wish to cling to life.

Aging and Death.—Beyond the teachings of religion, one might wonder, why is it more admirable for an older person who feels their strength fading to passively wait for their slow decline and end rather than actively choose to end their life? In this situation, suicide seems like a completely natural and reasonable action, deserving of respect as a victory of reason, much like how the leaders of Greek philosophy and the strongest patriots once sought death through suicide. In contrast, the effort to extend life day by day—through constant consultations with doctors and a painful way of living, all without making any real progress toward life's ultimate goal—is far less honorable. Religion offers many justifications to address the desire for[Pg 86] suicide, thereby endearing itself to those who want to hold on to life.

81.

81.

Errors of the Sufferer and the Doer.—When a rich man deprives a poor man of a possession (for instance, a prince taking the sweetheart of a plebeian), an error arises in the mind of the poor man; he thinks that the rich man must be utterly infamous to take away from him the little that he has. But the rich man does not estimate so highly the value of a single possession, because he is accustomed to have many; hence he cannot imagine himself in the poor man's place, and does not commit nearly so great a wrong as the latter supposes. They each have a mistaken idea of the other. The injustice of the powerful, which, more than anything else, rouses indignation in history, is by no means so great as it appears. Alone the mere inherited consciousness of being a higher creation, with higher claims, produces a cold temperament, and leaves the conscience quiet; we all of us feel no injustice when the difference is very great between ourselves and another creature, and kill a fly, for instance, without any pricks of conscience. Therefore it was no sign of badness in Xerxes (whom even all Greeks describe as superlatively noble) when he took a son away from his father and had him cut in pieces, because he had expressed a nervous, ominous distrust of the whole campaign; in this case the individual is put out of the way like an unpleasant insect; he[Pg 87] is too lowly to be allowed any longer to cause annoyance to a ruler of the world. Yes, every cruel man is not so cruel as the ill-treated one imagines the idea of pain is not the same as its endurance. It is the same thing in the case of unjust judges, of the journalist who leads public opinion astray by small dishonesties. In all these cases cause and effect are surrounded by entirely different groups of feelings and thoughts; yet one unconsciously takes it for granted that doer and sufferer think and feel alike, and according to this supposition we measure the guilt of the one by the pain of the other.

Mistakes of the Sufferer and the Doer.—When a rich man takes something from a poor man (like a prince claiming the love of a commoner), the poor man thinks the rich man must be completely despicable for taking away the little he has. But the rich man doesn't value a single possession as highly because he's used to having many; therefore, he can't imagine being in the poor man's situation and doesn't commit as terrible an act as the poor man believes. They both have a skewed perception of each other. The injustice from those in power, which tends to provoke the most outrage in history, is often not as severe as it seems. The mere inherited sense of being superior, with more claims to privilege, creates a detached mindset and keeps the conscience at ease; we often feel no injustice when there is a significant gap between ourselves and another being, and for example, we swat a fly without feeling guilty. So, it wasn't a sign of wickedness in Xerxes (whom even all Greeks describe as exceptionally noble) when he had a son taken from his father and executed for showing nervous, foreboding distrust of the entire campaign; in this case, the individual is disposed of like an annoying insect; he[Pg 87] is too insignificant to be allowed to disrupt a ruler of the world. Indeed, every cruel person isn't as brutal as the wronged individual imagines; the concept of pain isn't the same as experiencing it. The same applies to unjust judges or journalists who distort public opinion through small dishonesties. In all these situations, the cause and effect are surrounded by completely different feelings and thoughts; yet one instinctively assumes that the doer and the sufferer think and feel the same way, and based on this assumption, we gauge the guilt of one by the suffering of the other.

82.

82.

The Skin of the Soul.—As the bones, flesh, entrails, and blood-vessels are enclosed within a skin, which makes the aspect of man endurable, so the emotions and passions of the soul are enwrapped with vanity,—it is the skin of the soul.

The Soul's Skin.—Just as bones, flesh, organs, and blood vessels are contained within a skin that makes a person's appearance acceptable, the emotions and passions of the soul are wrapped in vanity—it’s the skin of the soul.

83.

83.

The Sleep of Virtue.—When virtue has slept, it will arise again all the fresher.

The Sleep of Virtue.—When virtue has rested, it will wake up even stronger.

84.

84.

The Refinement of Shame.—People are not ashamed to think something foul, but they are ashamed when they think these foul thoughts are attributed to them.

The Evolution of Shame.—People don’t feel ashamed for having guilty thoughts, but they do feel ashamed when they believe others think those guilty thoughts belong to them.

85.

85.

Malice Is Rare.—Most people are far too much occupied with themselves to be malicious.

Malice is uncommon.—Most people are too focused on their own lives to be malicious.

86.

86.

The Tongue in the Balance.—We praise or blame according as the one or the other affords more opportunity for exhibiting our power of judgment.

The Tongue on the Scale.—We give praise or criticism based on which one allows us more chances to show our judgment.

87.

87.

St. Luke Xviii. 14, Improved.—He that humbleth himself wishes to be exalted.

St. Luke 18:14, Modernized.—The person who humbles themselves wants to be lifted up.

88.

88.

The Prevention of Suicide.—There is a certain right by which we may deprive a man of life, but none by which we may deprive him of death; this is mere cruelty.

Suicide Prevention.—There is a certain right to take a person's life, but none that allows us to take away their death; that is simply cruel.

89.

89.

Vanity.—We care for the good opinion of men, firstly because they are useful to us, and then because we wish to please them (children their parents, pupils their teachers, and well-meaning people generally their fellow-men). Only where the good opinion of men is of importance to some one, apart from the advantage thereof or his wish to please, can we speak of vanity. In[Pg 89] this case the man wishes to please himself, but at the expense of his fellow-men, either by misleading them into holding a false opinion about him, or by aiming at a degree of "good opinion" which must be painful to every one else (by arousing envy). The individual usually wishes to corroborate the opinion he holds of himself by the opinion of others, and to strengthen it in his own eyes; but the strong habit of authority—a habit as old as man himself —induces many to support by authority their belief in themselves: that is to say, they accept it first from others; they trust the judgment of others more than their own. The interest in himself, the wish to please himself, attains to such a height in a vain man that he misleads others into having a false, all too elevated estimation of him, and yet nevertheless sets store by their authority,—thus causing an error and yet believing in it. It must be confessed, therefore, that vain people do not wish to please others so much as themselves, and that they go so far therein as to neglect their advantage, for they often endeavour to prejudice their fellow-men unfavourably, inimicably, enviously, consequently injuriously against themselves, merely in order to have pleasure in themselves, personal pleasure.

Ego.—We care about what others think of us, mainly because they are useful to us and because we want to make them happy (like children wanting to please their parents, students wanting to impress their teachers, and generally decent people wanting to be liked by others). We can only talk about vanity when someone values the opinion of others for reasons beyond personal gain or the desire to please. In[Pg 89] this situation, a person wants to satisfy themselves, even at the cost of others, either by tricking them into thinking highly of them falsely or by aiming for a level of "good opinion" that causes discomfort to everyone else (like stirring up jealousy). People usually want to validate their self-image with how others see them and reinforce it in their own minds; however, the deep-rooted tendency to rely on authority—a trait as old as humanity—leads many to base their self-belief on others' opinions: they value others' judgments more than their own. A vain person cares so much about their self-image that they mislead others into having an inflated view of them, while still placing importance on others' authority—creating a false perception but still believing in it. Thus, it's clear that vain people primarily want to satisfy themselves rather than others, often to the point where they disregard their own well-being, as they sometimes work to make others view them negatively or with hostility, simply to take pleasure in their own self-image.

90.

90.

The Limits of Human Love.—A man who has declared that another is an idiot and a bad companion, is angry when the latter eventually proves himself to be otherwise.

The Boundaries of Human Love.—A man who has called someone an idiot and a bad friend gets upset when that person shows they are not.

91.

91.

Moralité Larmoyante.—What a great deal of pleasure morality gives! Only think what a sea of pleasant tears has been shed over descriptions of noble and unselfish deeds! This charm of life would vanish if the belief in absolute irresponsibility were to obtain supremacy.

Sentimental Morality.—How much joy morality brings! Just think about all the heartfelt tears that have been shed over stories of noble and selfless actions! This beauty of life would disappear if the belief in total irresponsibility were to take over.

92.

92.

The Origin of Justice.—Justice (equity) has, its origin amongst powers which are fairly equal, as Thucydides (in the terrible dialogue between the Athenian and Melian ambassadors) rightly comprehended: that is to say, where there is no clearly recognisable supremacy, and where a conflict would be useless and would injure both sides, there arises the thought of coming to an understanding and settling the opposing claims; the character of exchange is the primary character of justice. Each party satisfies the other, as each obtains what he values more than the other. Each one receives that which he desires, as his own henceforth, and whatever is desired is received in return. Justice, therefore, is recompense and exchange based on the hypothesis of a fairly equal degree of power,—thus, originally, revenge belongs to the province of justice, it is an exchange. Also gratitude.—Justice naturally is based on the point of view of a judicious self-preservation, on the egoism, therefore, of that reflection, "Why should I injure myself uselessly and perhaps not attain[Pg 91] my aim after all?" So much about the origin of justice. Because man, according to his intellectual custom, has forgotten the original purpose of so-called just and reasonable actions, and particularly because for hundreds of years children have been taught to admire and imitate such actions, the idea has gradually arisen that such an action is un-egoistic; upon this idea, however, is based the high estimation in which it is held: which, moreover, like all valuations, is constantly growing, for something that is valued highly is striven after, imitated, multiplied, and increases, because the value of the output of toil and enthusiasm of each individual is added to the value of the thing itself. How little moral would the world look without this forgetfulness! A poet might say that God had placed forgetfulness as door-keeper in the temple of human dignity.

The Origin of Justice.—Justice (fairness) originates among powers that are relatively equal, as Thucydides (in the intense dialogue between the Athenian and Melian ambassadors) rightly understood: that is, where there is no clear dominance, and where conflict would be pointless and harmful to both sides, the idea of reaching an agreement and settling conflicting claims emerges; the essence of exchange is the fundamental essence of justice. Each party satisfies the other, as each gets what they value more than the other. Each person receives what they desire as their own from that point onward, and whatever is desired is received in return. Therefore, justice is about compensation and exchange based on the assumption of a relatively equal level of power—thus, initially, revenge falls under the realm of justice; it is also an exchange. So does gratitude.—Justice is fundamentally rooted in the perspective of sensible self-preservation, in the self-interest that reflects, "Why should I harm myself unnecessarily and maybe not achieve[Pg 91] my goal anyway?" That’s the essence of the origin of justice. Because humans, due to their intellectual habits, have forgotten the original purpose of so-called just and reasonable actions, and especially because, for hundreds of years, children have been taught to admire and imitate such actions, the idea has gradually developed that such action is altruistic; however, this belief underpins the high regard in which it is held: which, like all values, is constantly increasing because something that is highly valued is pursued, imitated, multiplied, and grows because the value of each person's effort and passion adds to the value of the thing itself. How morally empty would the world appear without this forgetfulness! A poet might say that God placed forgetfulness as a gatekeeper at the temple of human dignity.

93.

93.

The Right of the Weaker.—When any one submits under certain conditions to a greater power, as a besieged town for instance, the counter-condition is that one can destroy one's self, burn the town, and so cause the mighty one a great loss. Therefore there is a kind of equalisation here, on the basis of which rights may be determined. The enemy has his advantage in maintaining it. In so far there are also rights between slaves and masters, that is, precisely so far as the possession of the slave is useful and important to his master. The right originally[Pg 92] extends so far as one appears to be valuable to the other, essentially unlosable, unconquerable, and so forth. In so far the weaker one also has rights, but lesser ones. Hence the famous unusquisque tantum juris habet, quantum potentia valet (or more exactly, quantum potentia valere creditur).

The Rights of the Vulnerable.—When someone submits to a greater power under certain conditions, like a besieged town, there’s a counter-condition where they can destroy themselves, set the town on fire, and cause significant loss to the stronger party. Thus, there’s a sort of equalization here that helps define rights. The enemy benefits from maintaining this condition. There are also rights between slaves and masters, specifically as far as the slave's presence is useful and important to the master. The right originally[Pg 92] extends as long as one is perceived to be valuable to the other, essentially unlosable, unconquerable, and so on. In this sense, the weaker party also has rights, but they are lesser rights. Hence the famous unusquisque tantum juris habet, quantum potentia valet (or more precisely, quantum potentia valere creditur).

94.

94.

The Three Phases of Hitherto Existing Morality.—It is the first sign that the animal has become man when its actions no longer have regard only to momentary welfare, but to what is enduring, when it grows useful and practical; there the free rule of reason first breaks out. A still higher step is reached when he acts according to the principle of honour by this means he brings himself into order, submits to common feelings, and that exalts him still higher over the phase in which he was led only by the idea of usefulness from a personal point of view; he respects and wishes to be respected, i.e. he understands usefulness as dependent upon what he thinks of others and what others think of him. Eventually he acts, on the highest step of the hitherto existing—morality, according to his standard of things and men; he himself decides for himself and others what is honourable, what is useful; he has become the law-giver of opinions, in accordance with the ever more highly developed idea of what is useful and honourable. Knowledge enables him to place that which is most useful, that is to say the general, enduring usefulness, above the personal,[Pg 93] the honourable recognition of general, enduring validity above the momentary; he lives and acts as a collective individual.

The Three Phases of Previously Existing Morality.—The first sign that an animal has become human is when its actions no longer focus solely on immediate needs but on what lasts; it becomes useful and practical; this marks the first emergence of the free rule of reason. A further development occurs when a person acts based on the principle of honor, which helps them gain order in their life, align with common feelings, and elevate themselves above the stage where they were driven only by personal usefulness; they respect others and want to be respected, meaning they see usefulness as connected to how they perceive others and how others view them. Ultimately, they reach the highest level of the hitherto existing morality, acting according to their own standards for people and things; they decide for themselves and others what is honorable and useful, becoming the creator of opinions, in line with an ever-evolving understanding of what is useful and honorable. Knowledge allows them to prioritize what is most useful, which is the collective, enduring benefit, over personal interests, and the honorable acknowledgment of general, lasting validity above the immediate; they live and act as part of a collective individual.

95.

95.

The Morality of the Mature Individual.—The impersonal has hitherto been looked upon as the actual distinguishing mark of moral action; and it has been pointed out that in the beginning it was in consideration of the common good that all impersonal actions were praised and distinguished. Is not an important change in these views impending, now when it is more and more recognised that it is precisely in the most personal possible considerations that the common good is the greatest, so that a strictly personal action now best illustrates the present idea of morality, as utility for the mass? To make a whole personality out of ourselves, and in all that we do to keep that personality's highest good in view, carries us further than those sympathetic emotions and actions for the benefit of others. We all still suffer, certainly, from the too small consideration of the personal in us; it is badly developed,—let us admit it; rather has our mind been forcibly drawn away from it and offered as a sacrifice to the State, to science, or to those who stand in need of help, as if it were the bad part which must be sacrificed. We are still willing to work for our fellow-men, but only so far as we find our own greatest advantage in this work, no more and no less. It is only a question of what we[Pg 94] understand as our advantage; the unripe, undeveloped, crude individual will understand it in the crudest way.

The Ethics of a Mature Person.—Until now, moral action has often been defined by its impersonal nature. It has been noted that originally, impersonal actions were praised for their contribution to the common good. However, isn’t it time for a significant shift in this perspective? We are increasingly recognizing that it is through the most personal considerations that the common good is best served, meaning that a strictly personal action now exemplifies the current definition of morality as benefiting the majority. By creating a whole personality out of ourselves and consistently prioritizing that personality's highest good in our actions, we go beyond mere sympathetic emotions and actions aimed at helping others. We still struggle with the narrow focus on our personal selves; it remains underdeveloped—let's be honest. Our minds have often been redirected away from it and sacrificed to the State, to science, or to those in need, as if our personal interests were the undesirable aspect that must be given up. While we're still willing to work for others, we do so only to the extent that we see our own greatest benefit in that work, no more, no less. It all comes down to what we[Pg 94] define as our advantage; the immature, undeveloped individual will interpret this in the most simplistic way.

96.

96.

Custom and Morality.—To be moral, correct, and virtuous is to be obedient to an old-established law and custom. Whether we submit with difficulty or willingly is immaterial, enough that we do so. He is called "good" who, as if naturally, after long precedent, easily and willingly, therefore, does what is right, according to whatever this may be (as, for instance, taking revenge, if to take revenge be considered as right, as amongst the ancient Greeks). He is called good because he is good "for something"; but as goodwill, pity, consideration, moderation, and such like, have come, with the change in manners, to be looked upon as "good for something," as useful, the good-natured and helpful have, later on, come to be distinguished specially as "good." (In the beginning other and more important kinds of usefulness stood in the foreground.) To be evil is to be "not moral" (immoral), to be immoral is to be in opposition to tradition, however sensible or stupid it may be; injury to the community (the "neighbour" being understood thereby) has, however, been looked upon by the social laws of all different ages as being eminently the actual "immorality," so that now at the word "evil" we immediately think of voluntary injury to one's neighbour. The fundamental antithesis which has taught man the distinction between moral and immoral, between[Pg 95] good and evil, is not the "egoistic" and "un-egoistic," but the being bound to the tradition, law, and solution thereof. How the tradition has arisen is immaterial, at all events without regard to good and evil or any immanent categorical imperative, but above all for the purpose of preserving a community, a generation, an association, a people; every superstitious custom that has arisen on account of some falsely explained accident, creates a tradition, which it is moral to follow; to separate one's self from it is dangerous, but more dangerous for the community than for the individual (because the Godhead punishes the community for every outrage and every violation of its rights, and the individual only in proportion). Now every tradition grows continually more venerable, the farther off lies its origin, the more this is lost sight of; the veneration paid it accumulates from generation to generation, the tradition at last becomes holy and excites awe; and thus in any case the morality of piety is a much older morality than that which requires un-egoistic actions.

Tradition and Ethics.—To be moral, correct, and virtuous means to follow long-standing laws and customs. Whether we comply with reluctance or willingly doesn't matter; what matters is that we do comply. A person is labeled "good" who, seemingly naturally, after a long history, easily and willingly does what is considered right, according to whatever that may be (for example, seeking revenge, if revenge is seen as right, as it was among the ancient Greeks). They are called good because they are good "for something"; however, goodwill, compassion, consideration, moderation, and similar traits have come to be seen, with changes in social norms, as "good for something," as useful. Consequently, those who are kind and helpful have later been recognized specifically as "good." (Initially, other and more significant forms of usefulness were in the spotlight.) To be evil is to be "not moral" (immoral), and to be immoral is to go against tradition, no matter how sensible or foolish it may be; harming the community (with "neighbor" meaning the same) has been viewed by the social laws throughout different times as the actual "immorality," so that when we hear "evil," we immediately think of deliberately harming one's neighbor. The core contrast that has taught humanity the difference between moral and immoral, between [Pg 95] good and evil, is not "selfish" versus "selfless," but being bound to tradition, law, and their interpretation. How the tradition has actually arisen doesn’t matter; it exists irrespective of good and evil or any inherent moral imperative, but primarily to preserve a community, a generation, an association, or a people; every superstitious custom that emerges from a misinterpreted event creates a tradition that is considered moral to follow; distancing oneself from it is risky, but it's more perilous for the community than for the individual (because the community faces punishment from the divine for every offense and violation of its rights, while the individual is punished only proportionately). As a tradition ages, it becomes increasingly venerable as its origins fade from view; the respect accorded to it accumulates through generations, and ultimately, the tradition becomes sacred and inspires awe; thus, in any case, the morality of reverence is a much older morality than that which calls for selfless actions.

97.

97.

Pleasure in Traditional Custom.—An important species of pleasure, and therewith the source of morality, arises out of habit. Man does what is habitual to him more easily, better, and therefore more willingly; he feels a pleasure therein, and knows from experience that the habitual has been tested, and is therefore useful; a custom that we can live with is proved to be wholesome and advantageous in contrast[Pg 96] to all new and not yet tested experiments. According to this, morality is the union of the pleasant and the useful; moreover, it requires no reflection. As soon as man can use compulsion, he uses it to introduce and enforce his customs; for in his eyes they are proved as the wisdom of life. In the same way a company of individuals compels each single one to adopt the same customs. Here the inference is wrong; because we feel at ease with a morality, or at least because we are able to carry on existence with it, therefore this morality is necessary, for it seems to be the only possibility of feeling at ease; the ease of life seems to grow out of it alone. This comprehension of the habitual as a necessity of existence is pursued even to the smallest details of custom,—as insight into genuine causality is very small with lower peoples and civilisations, they take precautions with superstitious fear that everything should go in its same groove; even where custom is difficult, hard, and burdensome, it is preserved on account of its apparent highest usefulness. It is not known that the same degree of well-being can also exist with other customs, and that even higher degrees may be attained. We become aware, however, that all customs, even the hardest, grow pleasanter and milder with time, and that the severest way of life may become a habit and therefore a pleasure.

Joy in Traditional Custom.—A significant kind of pleasure, which is also the basis of morality, comes from habit. People do what they're used to more easily, better, and more willingly; they find pleasure in it and know from experience that what is habitual has been tested and is therefore valuable. A custom that we can accept has proven to be healthy and beneficial compared to all new and untested experiences. Based on this, morality is a combination of what is pleasant and useful; it doesn’t require much thought. As soon as people can use force, they use it to establish and enforce their customs; for them, these customs are seen as the wisdom of life. Similarly, a group of people compels each individual to adopt the same customs. This reasoning is flawed; just because we feel comfortable with a morality, or at least can continue to live with it, doesn’t mean it’s necessary, as it seems to be the only way to feel comfortable; the ease of life appears to come solely from it. This understanding of habit as essential to existence extends even to the smallest details of custom—since the understanding of true causality is very limited among less developed societies and civilizations, they take precautions driven by superstitious fear to ensure everything follows the same pattern; even when a custom is difficult, harsh, and burdensome, it is maintained because of its perceived highest usefulness. It’s not recognized that the same level of well-being can also exist with other customs, and that even better outcomes can be achieved. However, we become aware that all customs, even the toughest, become more pleasant and manageable over time, and that even the most severe lifestyles can become habitual and thus pleasurable.

98.

98.

Pleasure and Social Instinct.—Out of his relations with other men, man obtains a new[Pg 97] species of pleasure in addition to those pleasurable sensations which he derives from himself; whereby he greatly increases the scope of enjoyment. Perhaps he has already taken too many of the pleasures of this sphere from animals, which visibly feel pleasure when they play with each other, especially the mother with her young. Then consider the sexual relations, which make almost every female interesting to a male with regard to pleasure, and vice versa. The feeling of pleasure on the basis of human relations generally makes man better; joy in common, pleasure enjoyed together is increased, it gives the individual security, makes him good-tempered, and dispels mistrust and envy, for we feel ourselves at ease and see others at ease. Similar manifestations of pleasure awaken the idea of the same sensations, the feeling of being like something; a like effect is produced by common sufferings, the same bad weather, dangers, enemies. Upon this foundation is based the oldest alliance, the object of which is the mutual obviating and averting of a threatening danger for the benefit of each individual. And thus the social instinct grows out of pleasure.

Joy and Social Drive.—Through his interactions with others, a person experiences a new[Pg 97] type of pleasure beyond the enjoyable feelings he gets from himself, greatly expanding his scope of enjoyment. He might have already taken too many of these pleasures from animals, which clearly show pleasure when they interact, especially mothers with their young. Then there are sexual relationships, which make almost every female appealing to a male regarding pleasure, and vice versa. The pleasure derived from human relationships generally makes people better; shared joy and pleasure enhance the experience, providing individuals with security, improving their mood, and reducing mistrust and jealousy, as we feel comfortable and see others feel comfortable too. Similar manifestations of pleasure evoke the idea of sharing the same sensations, the feeling of being alike; a similar effect comes from shared hardships, like bad weather, threats, or enemies. This foundation supports the oldest alliances, aimed at mutual protection and averting threats for the benefit of each individual. Thus, the social instinct emerges from pleasure.

99.

99.

The Innocent Side of So-called Evil Actions.—All "evil" actions are prompted by the instinct of preservation, or, more exactly, by the desire for pleasure and the avoidance of pain on the part of the individual; thus prompted, but not evil. "To cause pain per se" does not exist,[Pg 98] except in the brains of philosophers, neither does "to give pleasure per se" (pity in Schopenhauer's meaning). In the social condition before the State we kill the creature, be it ape or man, who tries to take from us the fruit of a tree when we are hungry and approach the tree, as we should still do with animals in inhospitable countries. The evil actions which now most rouse our indignation, are based upon the error that he who causes them has a free will, that he had the option, therefore, of not doing us this injury. This belief in option arouses hatred, desire for revenge, spite, and the deterioration of the whole imagination, while we are much less angry with an animal because we consider it irresponsible. To do injury, not from the instinct of preservation, but as requital, is the consequence of a false judgment and therefore equally innocent. The individual can in the condition which lies before the State, act sternly and cruelly towards other creatures for the purpose of terrifying, to establish his existence firmly by such terrifying proofs of his power. Thus act the violent, the mighty, the original founders of States, who subdue the weaker to themselves. They have the right to do so, such as the State still takes for itself; or rather, there is no right that can hinder this. The ground for all-morality can only be made ready when a stronger individual or a collective individual, for instance society or the State, subdues the single individuals,.draws them out of their singleness, and forms them into an association.. Compulsion precedes morality, indeed morality itself is compulsion for a time, to[Pg 99] which one submits for the avoidance of pain. Later on it becomes custom,—later still, free obedience, and finally almost instinct,—then, like everything long accustomed and natural, it is connected with pleasure—and is henceforth called virtue.

The Innocent Angle of So-called Evil Actions.—All "evil" actions are driven by the instinct for survival, or more accurately, by the desire for pleasure and the avoidance of pain by the individual; thus motivated, but not evil. "To cause pain per se" doesn’t exist,[Pg 98] except in the minds of philosophers, nor does "to give pleasure per se" (as pity in Schopenhauer's sense). In the social condition before the State, we kill the being, whether ape or human, who tries to take from us the fruit of a tree when we are hungry and approaching it, just as we would still do with animals in harsh regions. The evil actions that currently provoke our outrage are based on the mistaken belief that the person committing them has free will and could have chosen not to harm us. This belief in choice stirs up hatred, desires for revenge, spite, and a decline in our overall imagination, while we feel less anger towards an animal because we see it as irresponsible. To harm others, not out of the instinct for survival, but as requital, is a result of a false judgment and is thus equally innocent. An individual in the state of nature can act harshly and cruelly towards other beings to terrify, establishing their existence firmly through such displays of power. This is how the violent, the powerful, and the original founders of States operate, subjugating the weaker. They believe they have the right to do so, much like the State does; or rather, there’s no right that can prevent this. The basis for all morality can only be laid down when a stronger individual or collective entity, like society or the State, subdues individual persons, draws them from their isolation, and unites them into an association. Compulsion comes before morality; indeed, morality itself is a form of compulsion for a time, to[Pg 99] which one submits to avoid pain. Later it becomes habit—eventually, free obedience, and finally almost instinct—then, like everything that we become accustomed to and see as natural, it’s linked to pleasure—and is thereafter called virtue.

100.

100.

Shame.—Shame exists everywhere where there is a "mystery"; this, however, is a religious idea, which was widely extended in the older times of human civilisation. Everywhere were found bounded domains to which access was forbidden by divine right, except under certain conditions ; at first locally, as, for example, certain spots that ought not to be trodden by the feet of the uninitiated, in the neighbourhood of which these latter experienced horror and fear. This feeling was a good deal carried over into other relations, for instance, the sex relations, which, as a privilege and ἃδoυτον of riper years, had to be withheld from the knowledge of the young for their advantage, relations for the protection and sanctification of which many gods were invented and were set up as guardians in the nuptial chamber. (In Turkish this room is on this account called harem, "sanctuary," and is distinguished with the same name, therefore, that is used for the entrance courts of the mosques.) Thus the kingdom is as a centre from which radiate power and glory, to the subjects a mystery full of secrecy and shame, of which many after-effects may still be felt among nations which[Pg 100] otherwise do not by any means belong to the bashful type. Similarly, the whole world of inner conditions, the so-called "soul," is still a mystery for all who are not philosophers, after it has been looked upon for endless ages as of divine origin and as worthy of divine intercourse; according to this it is an ἃδoυτον and arouses shame.

Embarrassment.—Shame is everywhere there's a "mystery"; this is a religious concept that was widely accepted in the earlier days of human civilization. There were always restricted areas that were off-limits by divine right, except under specific conditions; initially, these were local, like certain places that shouldn’t be entered by the uninitiated, who felt terror and dread in their presence. This feeling transferred to other aspects of life, such as sexual relationships, which, as a privilege and ἃδoυτον of maturity, had to be kept from the young for their own benefit. Many gods were created to protect and sanctify these relationships, serving as guardians in the wedding chamber. (In Turkish, this room is called harem, meaning "sanctuary," and is identified with the same term used for the entrance courts of mosques.) Thus, the kingdom serves as a center from which power and glory radiate, while to the subjects it remains a mystery filled with secrecy and shame, leaving lingering effects among nations that[Pg 100] might not be known for their modesty. Likewise, the entire realm of inner experiences, the so-called "soul," is still a mystery for those who aren’t philosophers, having been regarded for countless ages as divine in nature and worthy of divine connections; thus, it is an ἃδoυτον that evokes shame.

101.

101.

Judge Not.—In considering earlier periods, care must be taken not to fall into unjust abuse. The injustice in slavery, the cruelty in the suppression of persons and nations, is not to be measured by our standard. For the instinct of justice was not then so far developed. Who dares to reproach the Genevese Calvin with the burning of the physician Servet? It was an action following and resulting from his convictions, and in the same way the Inquisition had a good right; only the ruling views were false, and produced a result which seems hard to us because those views have now grown strange to us. Besides, what is the burning of a single individual compared with eternal pains of hell for almost all! And yet this idea was universal at that time, without essentially injuring by its dreadfulness the conception of a God. With us, too, political sectarians are hardly and cruelly treated, but because one is accustomed to believe in the necessity of the State, the cruelty is not so deeply felt here as it is where we repudiate the views. Cruelty to animals in children and Italians is[Pg 101] due to ignorance, i.e. the animal, through the interests of Church teaching, has been placed too far behind man. Much that is dreadful and inhuman in history, much that one hardly likes to believe, is mitigated by the reflection that the one who commands and the one who carries out are different persons,—the former does not behold the right and therefore does not experience the strong impression on the imagination; the latter obeys a superior and therefore feels no responsibility. Most princes and military heads, through lack of imagination, easily appear hard and cruel without really being so. Egoism is not evil, because the idea of the "neighbour"—the word is of Christian origin and does not represent the truth—is very weak in us; and we feel ourselves almost as free and irresponsible towards him as towards plants and stones. We have yet to learn that others suffer, and this can never be completely learnt.

Don't judge.—When looking back at earlier times, we need to be careful not to fall into unjust criticism. The wrongs of slavery and the cruelty in suppressing individuals and nations shouldn't be judged by our current standards. The sense of justice back then wasn't as advanced. Who is truly in a position to criticize the Genevan Calvin for the burning of the physician Servet? That act stemmed from his beliefs, just as the Inquisition had its justification; the only issue was that their prevailing views were misguided, resulting in outcomes that seem harsh to us now because those beliefs feel foreign. Additionally, what is the death of one person compared to the eternal suffering of many? Yet, that perspective was widely accepted at the time without significantly harming the image of God. In our own society, political dissidents face harsh treatment, but because we tend to believe in the necessity of the State, the cruelty feels less intense compared to regions where those ideas are rejected. The cruelty towards animals exhibited by children and Italians is[Pg 101] rooted in ignorance; that is, due to the interests of religious teachings, animals have often been placed far below humans. Much of the horrific and inhumane actions recorded in history, which are hard to accept, can be softened by the realization that the one giving orders and the one executing them are different— the one in charge may not see the moral implications and thus doesn’t feel the weight of them, while the one obeying a superior feels no sense of accountability. Many rulers and military leaders, lacking imagination, often appear harsh and cruel without truly being that way. Egoism is not evil, because the concept of "neighbor"—a term with Christian roots that doesn’t truly reflect reality—holds very little weight for us; we tend to view ourselves as almost free and unaccountable to others, just as we are with plants and rocks. We still need to learn that others endure suffering, and that understanding can never be fully grasped.

102.

102.

"Man Always Acts Rightly."—We do not complain of nature as immoral because it sends a thunderstorm and makes us wet,—why do we call those who injure us immoral? Because in the latter case we take for granted a free will functioning voluntarily; in the former we see necessity. But this distinction is an error. Thus we do not call even intentional injury immoral in all circumstances; for instance, we kill a fly unhesitatingly and intentionally, only because its[Pg 102] buzzing annoys us; we punish a criminal intentionally and hurt him in order to protect ourselves and society. In the first case it is the individual who, in order to preserve himself, or even to protect himself from worry, does intentional injury; in the second case it is the State. All morals allow intentional injury in the case of necessity, that is, when it is a matter of self-preservation! But these two points of view suffice to explain all evil actions committed by men against men, we are desirous of obtaining pleasure or avoiding pain; in any case it is always a question of self-preservation. Socrates and Plato are right: whatever man does he always does well, that is, he does that which seems to him good (useful) according to the degree of his intellect, the particular standard of his reasonableness.

"Man Always Acts Correctly."—We don’t criticize nature as immoral because it sends a thunderstorm and soaks us; why do we label those who harm us as immoral? It's because in the latter situation we assume there's a free will acting on its own, while in the former we see it as necessity. But this distinction is a mistake. We don’t label every intentional harm as immoral; for example, we kill a fly intentionally and without hesitation, simply because its[Pg 102] buzzing annoys us; we intentionally punish a criminal and hurt him to protect ourselves and society. In the first case, it’s the individual acting to preserve themselves or to avoid worry; in the second case, it’s the State. All moral frameworks permit intentional harm in cases of necessity, especially when it comes to self-preservation! These two perspectives are enough to explain all harmful actions committed by people against one another; we seek pleasure or try to avoid pain; ultimately, it always comes down to self-preservation. Socrates and Plato are correct: whatever a person does, they believe they are doing what is right, that is, they act in a way that seems good (useful) based on their level of understanding and their specific standard of rationality.

103.

103.

The Harmlessness of Malice.—The aim of malice is not the suffering of others in itself, but our own enjoyment; for instance, as the feeling of revenge, or stronger nervous excitement. All teasing, even, shows the pleasure it gives to exercise our power on others and bring it to an enjoyable feeling of preponderance. Is it immoral to taste pleasure at the expense of another's pain? Is malicious joy[3] devilish, as Schopenhauer says? We give ourselves pleasure in[Pg 103] nature by breaking off twigs, loosening stones, fighting with wild animals, and do this in order to become thereby conscious of our strength. Is the knowledge, therefore, that another suffers through us, the same thing concerning which we otherwise feel irresponsible, supposed to make us immoral? But if we did not know this we would not thereby have the enjoyment of our own superiority, which can only manifest itself by the suffering of others, for instance in teasing. All pleasure per se is neither good nor evil; whence should come the decision that in order to have pleasure ourselves we may not cause displeasure to others? From the point of view of usefulness alone, that is, out of consideration for the consequences, for possible displeasure, when the injured one or the replacing State gives the expectation of resentment and revenge: this only can have been the original reason for denying ourselves such actions. Pity aims just as little at the pleasure of others as malice at the pain of others per se. For it contains at least two (perhaps many more) elements of a personal pleasure, and is so far self-gratification; in the first place as the pleasure of emotion, which is the kind of pity that exists in tragedy, and then, when it impels to action, as the pleasure of satisfaction in the exercise of power. If, besides this, a suffering person is very dear to us, we lift a sorrow from ourselves by the exercise of sympathetic actions. Except by a few philosophers, pity has always been placed very low in the scale of moral feelings, and rightly so.

The Innocence of Malice.—The goal of malice isn’t just to make others suffer; it’s about our own enjoyment, like the thrill of revenge or a jolt of nervous excitement. Even teasing shows how much pleasure we get from exercising power over others and feeling superior. Is it immoral to enjoy ourselves while someone else is in pain? Is malicious joy[3] really as evil as Schopenhauer claims? We find pleasure in nature by breaking twigs, moving stones, and battling wild animals, which helps us feel our own strength. So, does knowing that someone else suffers because of us make us immoral? But without that knowledge, we wouldn't experience the pleasure of feeling superior, which often comes from another's suffering, like when we tease. All pleasure per se isn’t good or bad; where do we get the idea that having fun ourselves means we can't cause others to feel bad? From a practical standpoint, we might avoid causing discomfort to others because of the potential consequences, especially if the hurt person might seek revenge. Pity doesn’t aim for others' pleasure any more than malice aims at their pain per se. It involves at least two (maybe more) aspects of personal pleasure: the emotional satisfaction that comes from feeling pity in a tragedy, and the satisfaction we get from taking action. If a suffering person is especially dear to us, we relieve our own sorrow through empathetic actions. Historically, except by a few philosophers, pity has been viewed as a lesser moral feeling, and rightly so.

104.

104.

Self-defence.—If self-defence is allowed to pass as moral, then almost all manifestations of the so-called immoral egoism must also stand; men injure, rob, or kill in order to preserve or defend themselves, to prevent personal injury; they lie where cunning and dissimulation are the right means of self-preservation. Intentional injury, when our existence or safety (preservation of our comfort) is concerned, is conceded to be moral; the State itself injures, according to this point of view, when it punishes. In unintentional injury, of course, there can be nothing immoral, that is ruled by chance. Is there, then, a kind of intentional injury where our existence or the preservation of our comfort is not concerned? Is there an injuring out of pure malice, for instance in cruelty? If one does not know how much an action hurts, it is no deed of malice; thus the child is not malicious towards the animal, not evil; he examines and destroys it like a toy. But do we ever know entirely how an action hurts another? As far as our nervous system extends we protect ourselves from pain; if it extended farther, to our fellow-men, namely, we should do no one an injury (except in such cases as we injure ourselves, where we cut ourselves for the sake of cure, tire and exert ourselves for the sake of health). We conclude by analogy that something hurts somebody, and through memory and the strength of imagination we may suffer from it[Pg 105] ourselves. But still what a difference there is between toothache and the pain (pity) that the sight of toothache calls forth! Therefore, in injury out of so-called malice the degree of pain produced is always unknown to us; but inasmuch as there is pleasure in the action (the feeling of one's own power, one's own strong excitement), the action is committed, in order to preserve the comfort of the individual, and is regarded, therefore, from a similar point of view as defence and falsehood in necessity. No life without pleasure; the struggle for pleasure is the struggle for life. Whether the individual so fights this fight that men call him good, or so that they call him evil, is determined by the measure and the constitution of his intellect.

Self-defense.—If self-defense is seen as moral, then almost all forms of so-called immoral self-interest must also be accepted; people harm, steal, or even kill to protect or defend themselves, to avoid personal harm; they lie when cunning and deceit are the best ways to survive. Intentional harm, especially when our existence or safety (our comfort) is involved, is accepted as moral; the State itself inflicts harm, according to this view, when it punishes. In cases of unintentional harm, there’s clearly nothing immoral, as those are ruled by chance. So, is there a type of intentional harm where our existence or comfort isn’t at stake? Is there harm done purely out of malice, like in cruelty? If someone doesn’t realize how much an action hurts, it’s not malicious; for instance, a child who examines and breaks a toy isn’t being evil. But do we ever fully understand how our actions affect others? As far as our nervous system reaches, we protect ourselves from pain; if it extended further, to include others, we wouldn’t harm anyone (except in rare cases where we injure ourselves for healing, or tire ourselves for health). We infer by analogy that something causes pain to someone else, and through memory and imagination, we might feel that pain [Pg 105] ourselves. Still, there’s a big difference between a toothache and the sympathy (pity) that seeing someone with a toothache brings! Thus, in harm done out of so-called malice, the level of pain inflicted is always unknown to us; however, because the action brings pleasure (the feeling of power, excitement), it’s carried out to maintain individual comfort and is viewed similarly to self-defense and lies out of necessity. No life without pleasure; the pursuit of pleasure is the pursuit of life. Whether someone fights for this pleasure in a way that makes them seem good or in a way that makes them seem evil depends on the measure and constitution of their intellect.

105.

105.

Recompensing Justice.—Whoever has completely comprehended the doctrine of absolute irresponsibility can no longer include the so-called punishing and recompensing justice in the idea of justice, should this consist of giving to each man his due. For he who is punished does not deserve the punishment, he is only used as a means of henceforth warning away from certain actions; equally so, he who is rewarded does not merit this reward, he could not act otherwise than he did. Therefore the reward is meant only as an encouragement to him and others, to provide a motive for subsequent actions; words of praise are flung to the runners on the course, not to the[Pg 106] one who has reached the goal. Neither punishment nor reward is anything that comes to one as one's own; they are given from motives of usefulness, without one having a right to claim them. Hence we must say, "The wise man gives no reward because the deed has been well done," just as we have said, "The wise man does not punish because evil has been committed, but in order that evil shall not be committed." If punishment and reward no longer existed, then the strongest motives which deter men from certain actions and impel them to certain other actions, would also no longer exist; the needs of mankind require their continuance; and inasmuch as punishment and reward, blame and praise, work most sensibly on vanity, the same need requires the continuance of vanity.

Restorative Justice.—Anyone who fully understands the concept of absolute irresponsibility can no longer see the idea of punishing and recompensing justice as part of justice, if that idea means giving everyone what they deserve. The person who is punished doesn’t actually deserve the punishment; they are merely being used as a way to warn others against certain actions. Similarly, the person who is rewarded doesn’t truly earn that reward; they couldn’t have acted differently than they did. Instead, the reward is just a way to encourage them and others, to motivate future actions; words of praise are directed at the runners on the track, not just at the one who crosses the finish line. Neither punishment nor reward is something that belongs to someone as theirs; they are given for practical purposes, without anyone having the right to demand them. Therefore, we must say, "The wise person doesn’t give rewards because the act was done well," just as we’ve said, "The wise person doesn’t punish because wrongdoing has occurred, but to prevent wrongdoing in the future." If punishment and reward no longer existed, then the strongest motivations that keep people from certain actions and drive them toward others would also disappear; humanity’s needs require their existence; and since punishment and reward, blame and praise, strongly affect vanity, we also have a need for the continued existence of vanity.

106.

106.

At the Waterfall.—In looking at a water-fall we imagine that there is freedom of will and fancy in the countless turnings, twistings, and breakings of the waves; but everything is compulsory, every movement can be mathematically calculated. So it is also with human actions; one would have to be able to calculate every single action beforehand if one were all-knowing; equally so all progress of knowledge, every error, all malice. The one who acts certainly labours under the illusion of voluntariness; if the world's wheel were to stand still for a moment and an all-knowing, calculating reason were there to make use of this[Pg 107] pause, it could foretell the future of every creature to the remotest times, and mark out every track upon which that wheel would continue to roll. The delusion of the acting agent about himself, the supposition of a free will, belongs to this mechanism which still remains to be calculated.

By the Waterfall.—When we look at a waterfall, we think there's freedom in the way the water twists, turns, and breaks; but everything is predetermined, and every movement can be mathematically figured out. The same goes for human actions; to truly understand everything, you'd need to be able to predict every single action if you had all knowledge, along with every step of learning, every mistake, and every act of malice. Those who act are under the illusion that they’re making choices; if the world's wheel were to stop for just a moment and an all-knowing, calculating mind were there to take advantage of this[Pg 107] pause, it could predict the future of every being for all time and trace every path that wheel would keep rolling along. The misguided belief of the acting person about themselves, the idea of free will, is part of this mechanism that still needs to be understood.

107.

107.

Irresponsibility and Innocence.—The complete irresponsibility of man for his actions and his nature is the bitterest drop which he who understands must swallow if he was accustomed to see the patent of nobility of his humanity in responsibility and duty. All his valuations, distinctions, disinclinations, are thereby deprived of value and become false,—his deepest feeling for the sufferer and the hero was based on an error; he may no longer either praise or blame, for it is absurd to praise and blame nature and necessity. In the same way as he loves a fine work of art, but does not praise it, because it can do nothing for itself; in the same way as he regards plants, so must he regard his own actions and those of mankind. He can admire strength, beauty, abundance, in themselves; but must find no merit therein,—the chemical progress and the strife of the elements, the torments of the sick person who thirsts after recovery, are all equally as little merits as those struggles of the soul and states of distress in which we are torn hither and thither by different impulses until we finally decide[Pg 108] for the strongest—as we say (but in reality it is the strongest motive which decides for us). All these motives, however, whatever fine names we may give them, have all grown out of the same root, in which we believe the evil poisons to be situated; between good and evil actions there is no difference of species, but at most of degree. Good actions are sublimated evil ones; evil actions are vulgarised and stupefied good ones. The single longing of the individual for self-gratification (together with the fear of losing it) satisfies itself in all circumstances: man may act as he can, that is as he must, be it in deeds of vanity, revenge, pleasure, usefulness, malice, cunning; be it in deeds of sacrifice, of pity, of knowledge. The degrees of the power of judgment determine whither any one lets himself be drawn through this longing; to every society, to every individual, a scale of possessions is continually present, according to which he determines his actions and judges those of others. But this standard changes constantly; many actions are called evil and are only stupid, because the degree of intelligence which decided for them was very low. In a certain sense, even, all actions are still stupid; for the highest degree of human intelligence which can now be attained will assuredly be yet surpassed, and then, in a retrospect, all our actions and judgments will appear as limited and hasty as the actions and judgments of primitive wild peoples now appear limited and hasty to us. To recognise all this may be deeply painful, but consolation comes after; such pains are the pangs of birth. The[Pg 109] butterfly wants to break through its chrysalis: it rends and tears it, and is then blinded and confused by the unaccustomed light, the kingdom of liberty. In such people as are capable of such sadness—and how few are!—the first experiment made is to see whether mankind can change itself from a moral into a wise mankind. The sun of a new gospel throws its rays upon the highest point in the soul of each single individual, then the mists gather thicker than ever, and the brightest light and the dreariest shadow lie side by side. Everything is necessity—so says the new knowledge, and this knowledge itself is necessity. Everything is innocence, and knowledge is the road to insight into this innocence. Are pleasure, egoism, vanity necessary for the production of the moral phenomena and their highest result, the sense for truth and justice in knowledge; were error and the confusion of the imagination the only means through which mankind could raise itself gradually to this degree of self-enlightenment and self-liberation—who would dare to undervalue these means? Who would dare to be sad if he perceived the goal to which those roads led? Everything in the domain of morality has evolved, is changeable, unstable, everything is dissolved, it is true; but everything is also streaming towards one goal. Even if the inherited habit of erroneous valuation, love and hatred, continue to reign in us, yet under the influence of growing knowledge it will become weaker; a new habit, that of comprehension, of not loving, not hating, of overlooking, is gradually implanting itself in us upon[Pg 110] the same ground, and in thousands of years will perhaps be powerful enough to give humanity the strength to produce wise, innocent (consciously innocent) men, as it now produces unwise, guilt-conscious men,—that is the necessary preliminary step, not its opposite.

Carelessness and Naivety.—The complete lack of responsibility of man for his actions and nature is the hardest truth that anyone who understands must confront, especially if they've always seen the nobility of humanity in responsibility and duty. All of his values, distinctions, and aversions lose their meaning and become false—his deepest feelings for those who suffer and for heroes were based on a misunderstanding; he can no longer praise or blame, because it makes no sense to praise or blame nature and necessity. Just like he loves a beautiful piece of art but doesn’t praise it because it can’t do anything for itself; just as he regards plants, he must regard his own actions and those of humanity. He can admire strength, beauty, and abundance for their own sake but must find no merit in them—chemical progress and the struggles of the elements, as well as the suffering of a sick person yearning for recovery, hold no merit just like the struggles of the soul and the states of distress where we’re pulled in different directions until we finally choose[Pg 108] the strongest one—as we say (but in reality, it’s the strongest motive that decides for us). However, all these motives, no matter how noble the names we give them, stem from the same source, where we think the evil poisons lie; there’s no real difference between good and evil actions, only a difference in degree. Good actions are elevated versions of evil ones; evil actions are degraded versions of good ones. The individual’s desire for self-satisfaction (along with the fear of losing it) plays out in every situation: man acts as he can and must, whether in acts of vanity, revenge, pleasure, usefulness, malice, or cunning; or in acts of sacrifice, compassion, or knowledge. The level of judgment determines how one allows oneself to be swayed by this longing; every society and individual continuously has a scale of values based on which they determine their actions and judge others. But this standard is constantly shifting; many actions are labeled evil but are merely foolish, because the intelligence that led to them was very limited. In a certain sense, even all actions can still be seen as foolish; because the highest level of human intelligence we can currently reach will surely be surpassed, making all our actions and judgments seem as limited and hasty as those of primitive tribes seem to us today. Recognizing this can be deeply painful, but there’s comfort that follows; such pains are the labor pains of birth. The[Pg 109] butterfly wants to break free from its chrysalis: it rips and tears it, then finds itself blinded and disoriented by the strange light, the realm of freedom. Among those who can feel such sadness—and how few are there!—the first test is to see whether humanity can transform from a moral to a wise state. The sun of a new gospel shines its rays on the highest part of each individual’s soul, but then the fog thickens more than ever, with the brightest light and the darkest shadow lying side by side. Everything is necessity—so says the new understanding, and this understanding itself is necessity. Everything is innocence, and knowledge is the path to realizing this innocence. Are pleasure, egoism, and vanity necessary for the emergence of moral phenomena and their highest outcome, the sense of truth and justice in knowledge? If error and confusion of the imagination are the only means through which humanity gradually raises itself to this level of self-awareness and liberation—who would dare to undervalue these means? Who would dare to feel sad upon seeing the destination these paths lead to? Everything in the realm of morality has evolved, is changeable, and unstable; it is true that everything is dissolving; but everything is also moving toward one goal. Even if the inherited habits of misguided values, love, and hatred continue to dominate us, under the influence of increasing knowledge, they will weaken; a new habit of understanding, of not loving or hating, of overlooking, is slowly taking root in us upon[Pg 110] the same foundation, and in thousands of years may be strong enough to allow humanity to create wise, innocent (consciously innocent) individuals, just as it now produces unwise, guilt-ridden ones—this is the necessary first step, not its opposite.


[1] Dr. Paul Rée.—J.M.K.

Dr. Paul Rée.—J.M.K.

[2] Dr. Paul Rée.—J.M.K.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Dr. Paul Rée.—J.M.K.

[3] This is the untranslatable word Schadenfreude, which means joy at the misfortune of others.—J.M.K.

[3] This is the untranslatable word Schadenfreude, which means taking pleasure in someone else's misfortune.—J.M.K.


THIRD DIVISION.

THE RELIGIOUS LIFE.

108.

108.

The Double Fight Against Evil.—When misfortune overtakes us we can either pass over I it so lightly that its cause is removed, or so that the result which it has on our temperament is altered, through a changing, therefore, of the evil into a good, the utility of which is perhaps not visible until later on. Religion and art (also metaphysical philosophy) work upon the changing of the temperament, partly through the changing of our judgment on events (for instance, with the help of the phrase "whom the Lord loveth He chasteneth"), partly through the awakening of a pleasure in pain, in emotion generally (whence the tragic art takes its starting-point). The more a man is inclined to twist and arrange meanings the less he will grasp the causes of evil and disperse them; the momentary mitigation and influence of a narcotic, as for example in toothache, suffices him even in more serious sufferings. The more the dominion of creeds and all arts dispense with narcotics, the more strictly men attend to the actual removing of the evil, which is certainly[Pg 112] bad for writers of tragedy; for the material for tragedy is growing scarcer because the domain of pitiless, inexorable fate is growing ever narrower,—but worse still for the priests, for they have hitherto lived on the narcotisation of human woes.

The Dual Battle Against Evil.—When misfortune strikes us, we can either brush it off so that its cause is eliminated, or we can change how it affects our temperament, turning the evil into something good, even if its benefits only become clear later. Religion and art (along with metaphysical philosophy) help shift our temperament, partly by changing our perspective on events (for instance, with the saying "whom the Lord loves, He chastens"), and partly by awakening a sense of pleasure in suffering and emotion in general (which is where tragic art draws its inspiration). The more someone tries to reinterpret meanings, the less they'll understand the causes of evil and eliminate them; the momentary relief provided by a narcotic, like in the case of tooth pain, is often enough for them, even in more serious suffering. The more religious beliefs and all forms of art move away from narcotics, the more people focus on actually getting rid of evil, which is certainly[Pg 112] bad for writers of tragedy; the resources for tragedy are dwindling because the realm of harsh, unyielding fate is becoming narrower— but it's worse for the priests, who have relied on dulling human suffering.

109.

109.

Sorrow Is Knowledge.—How greatly we should like to exchange the false assertions of the priests, that there is a god who desires good from us, a guardian and witness of every action, every moment, every thought, who loves us and seeks our welfare in all misfortune,—how greatly we would like to exchange these ideas for truths which would be just as healing, pacifying and beneficial as those errors! But there are no such truths; at most philosophy can oppose to them metaphysical appearances (at bottom also untruths). The tragedy consists in the fact that we cannot believe those dogmas of religion and metaphysics, if we have strict methods of truth in heart and brain: on the other hand, mankind has, through development, become so delicate, irritable and suffering, that it has need of the highest means of healing and consolation; whence also the danger arises that man would bleed to death from recognised truth, or, more correctly, from discovered error. Byron has expressed this in the immortal lines:—

Sorrow Equals Knowledge.—How much we would love to trade the misleading claims of the priests, that there is a god who wants good from us, a guardian and witness of every action, every moment, every thought, who loves us and cares about our well-being in all misfortune,—how much we would like to replace these ideas with truths that would be just as healing, calming, and beneficial as those falsehoods! But such truths don’t exist; at best, philosophy can offer us metaphysical illusions (which are ultimately also untruths). The tragedy lies in the fact that we cannot believe those religious and metaphysical doctrines if we have a commitment to truth in our hearts and minds: on the other hand, humanity has become so sensitive, irritable, and suffering through its development that it desperately needs the highest means of healing and comfort; thus, the danger arises that a person might be overwhelmed by recognized truth, or, more accurately, by discovered falsehood. Byron captured this in his timeless lines:—

Sorrow is knowledge: they who know the most
Must mourn the deepest o'er the fatal truth,
The Tree of Knowledge is not that of Life.

Sorrow is knowledge: those who know the most
Must grieve the hardest over the harsh truth,
The Tree of Knowledge is not the Tree of Life.

For such troubles there is no better help than to recall the stately levity of Horace, at least for the worst hours and eclipses of the soul, and to say with him:

For such struggles, there's no better remedy than to remember the dignified lightness of Horace, especially during the darkest moments and challenges of the soul, and to say with him:

... quid æternis minorem
consiliis animum fatigas?
cur non sub alta vel platano vel hac
pinu jacentes.[1]

... why exhaust yourself with constant planning?
Why not lie down under a tall plane tree or this
pine?[1]

But assuredly frivolity or melancholy of every degree is better than a romantic retrospection and desertion of the flag, an approach to Christianity in any form; for according to the present condition of knowledge it is absolutely impossible to approach it without hopelessly soiling our intellectual conscience and giving ourselves away to ourselves and others. Those pains may be unpleasant enough, but we cannot become leaders and educators of mankind without pain; and woe to him who would wish to attempt this and no longer have that clear conscience!

But definitely, being silly or feeling sad is better than getting lost in romantic thoughts and abandoning our beliefs, or trying to approach Christianity in any way; because with the current level of understanding, it's completely impossible to engage with it without seriously compromising our intellectual conscience and betraying ourselves and others. Those struggles might not be pleasant, but we can't be leaders and teachers of humanity without going through pain; and shame on anyone who tries to do this without maintaining a clear conscience!

110.

110.

The Truth in Religion.—In the period of rationalism justice was not done to the importance of religion, of that there is no doubt, but equally there is no doubt that in the reaction that followed this rationalism justice was far overstepped; for religions were treated lovingly,[Pg 114] even amorously, and, for instance, a deeper, even the very deepest, understanding of the world was ascribed to them; which science has only to strip of its dogmatic garment in order to possess the "truth" in unmythical form. Religions should, therefore,—this was the opinion of all opposers of rationalism,—sensu allegorico, with all consideration for the understanding of the masses, give utterance to that ancient wisdom which is wisdom itself, inasmuch as all true science of later times has always led up to it instead of away from it, so that between the oldest wisdom of mankind and all later harmonies similarity of discernment and a progress of knowledge—in case one should wish to speak of such a thing—rests not upon the nature but upon the way of communicating it. This whole conception of religion and science is thoroughly erroneous, and none would still dare to profess it if Schopenhauer's eloquence had not taken it under its protection; this resonant eloquence which, however, only reached its hearers a generation later. As surely as from Schopenhauer's religious-moral interpretations of men and the world much may be gained for the understanding of the Christian and other religions, so surely also is he mistaken about the value of religion for knowledge. Therein he himself was only a too docile pupil of the scientific teachers of his time, who all worshipped romanticism and had forsworn the spirit of enlightenment; had he been born in our present age he could not possibly have talked about the sensus allegoricus of religion; he would much rather have given[Pg 115] honour to truth, as he used to do, with the words, "no religion, direct or indirect, either as dogma or as allegory, has ever contained a truth." For each has been born of fear and necessity, through the byways of reason did it slip into existence; once, perhaps, when imperilled by science, some philosophic doctrine has lied itself into its system in order that it may be found there later, but this is a theological trick of the time when a religion already doubts itself. These tricks of theology (which certainly were practised in the early days of Christianity, as the religion of a scholarly period steeped in philosophy) have led to that superstition of the sensus allegoricus, but yet more the habits of the philosophers (especially the half-natures, the poetical philosophers and the philosophising artists), to treat all the sensations which they discovered in themselves as the fundamental nature of man in general, and hence to allow their own religious feelings an important influence in the building up of their systems. As philosophers frequently philosophised under the custom of religious habits, or at least under the anciently inherited power of that "metaphysical need," they developed doctrinal opinions which really bore a great resemblance to the Jewish or Christian or Indian religious views,—a resemblance, namely, such as children usually bear to their mothers, only that in this case the fathers were not clear about that motherhood, as happens sometimes,—but in their innocence romanced about a family likeness between all religion and science. In reality, between religions and real science there[Pg 116] exists neither relationship nor friendship, nor even enmity; they live on different planets. Every philosophy which shows a religious comet's tail shining in the darkness of its last prospects makes all the science it contains suspicious; all this is presumably also religion, even though in the guise of science. Moreover, if all nations were to agree about certain religious matters, for instance the existence of a God (which, it may be remarked, is not the case with regard to this point), this would only be an argument against those affirmed matters, for instance the existence of a God; the consensus gentium and hominum in general can only take place in case of a huge folly. On the other hand, there is no consensus omnium sapientium, with regard to any single thing, with that exception mentioned in Goethe's lines:

The Truth in Religion.—During the time of rationalism, the significance of religion was definitely overlooked, but it’s also clear that in the backlash against rationalism, religion was treated with excessive reverence; for instance, people claimed it offered a deeper, even the deepest, understanding of the world, which science could grasp only by shedding its dogmatic framework to reveal the "truth" in a straightforward manner. Therefore, according to those who opposed rationalism, religions should, sensu allegorico, express that ancient wisdom—which is true wisdom—keeping in mind that all genuine science developed later has always led toward this wisdom rather than away from it. Thus, there’s a similarity in understanding and a progression of knowledge between the earliest human wisdom and later insights—not based on their essence but on how they're communicated. This entire view of religion and science is fundamentally flawed, and no one would dare to assert it if it hadn't been defended by Schopenhauer's powerful eloquence; however, that eloquence only resonated with audiences a generation later. Just as there is much to be gained from Schopenhauer's religious-moral insights about humanity and the world to aid in understanding Christianity and other religions, he is also mistaken regarding the value of religion for knowledge. In this respect, he was simply too obedient a student of the scientific thinkers of his time, who all revered romanticism and had rejected the spirit of enlightenment; had he been born today, he wouldn’t have talked about the sensus allegoricus of religion; he would instead have honored truth, as he once did, with the assertion, "No religion, direct or indirect, whether as dogma or as allegory, has ever contained a truth." Because each one arose from fear and necessity, finding its way into existence through convoluted reasoning; once, possibly under threat from science, some philosophical doctrine managed to worm its way into the system only to be later discovered there, a theological sleight of hand emerging when a religion begins to doubt itself. These theological tricks (which certainly occurred in the early days of Christianity, during a time steeped in scholarly philosophy) have contributed to the superstition of the sensus allegoricus, but even more so the tendencies of philosophers (especially those of a poetic inclination and artistic thinkers) to treat all the sensations they uncovered within themselves as the fundamental essence of humanity as a whole, thus allowing their own religious feelings to significantly influence the formulation of their philosophies. As philosophers often philosophized within the framework of religious customs or at least the traditionally inherited power of that "metaphysical need," they developed doctrines resembling Jewish, Christian, or Indian religious beliefs—similarities akin to those between children and their mothers, except in this case the fathers weren’t clear about that motherhood, as sometimes happens—but in their naivety, they fantasized about a familial resemblance between all religion and science. In truth, there is no actual relationship, friendship, or even enmity between religions and genuine science; they exist on entirely different planes. Every philosophy that shows a religious comet’s tail gleaming in the darkness of its final prospects makes all the science contained within it suspect; this is presumably also religion masquerading as science. Furthermore, even if all nations were to agree on some religious aspects, such as the existence of a God (which, notably, they do not), this would only serve as an argument against those claims—like the existence of a God; the consensus gentium and hominum can arise only from enormous folly. Conversely, there is no consensus omnium sapientium on any single issue, except for the exception mentioned in Goethe's lines:

"Alle die Weisesten aller der Zeiten
Lächeln und winken und stimmen mit ein:
Thöricht, auf Bess'rung der Thoren zu harren!
Kinder der Klugheit, o habet die Narren
Eben zum Narren auch, wie sich's gehört!"[2]

"All the wisest of all times
Smile and wave and join in:
Foolish to wait for the improvement of fools!
Children of wisdom, oh, consider the fools
Just as fools too, as is fitting!"[2]

Spoken without verse and rhyme and applied to our case, the consensus sapientium consists in this: that the consensus gentium counts as a folly.

Spoken without any rhythm or rhyme and applied to our situation, the consensus sapientium means this: that the consensus gentium is considered foolishness.

111.

111.

The Origin of the Religious Cult.—If we go back to the times in which the religious life flourished to the greatest extent, we find a fundamental conviction, which we now no longer share, and whereby the doors leading to a religious life are closed to us once for all,—it concerns Nature and intercourse with her. In those times people knew nothing of natural laws; neither for earth nor for heaven is there a "must"; a season, the sunshine, the rain may come or may not come. In short, every idea of natural causality is lacking. When one rows, it is not the rowing that moves the boat, but rowing is only a magical ceremony by which one compels a dæmon to move the boat. All maladies, even death itself, are the result of magical influences. Illness and death never happen naturally; the whole conception of "natural sequence" is lacking,—it dawned first amongst the older Greeks, that is, in a very late phase of humanity, in the conception of Moira, enthroned above the gods. When a man shoots with a bow, there is still always present an irrational hand and strength; if the wells suddenly dry up, men think first of subterranean dæmons and their tricks; it must be the arrow of a god beneath whose invisible blow a man suddenly sinks down. In India (says Lubbock) a carpenter is accustomed to offer sacrifice to his hammer, his hatchet, and the rest of his tools; in the same way a Brahmin treats the pen with which he writes, a soldier the weapons he requires in the field of[Pg 118] battle, a mason his trowel, a labourer his plough. In the imagination of religious people all nature is a summary of the actions of conscious and voluntary creatures, an enormous complex of arbitrariness. No conclusion may be drawn with regard to everything that is outside of us, that anything will be so and so, must be so and so; the approximately sure, reliable are we,—man is the rule, nature is irregularity,—this theory contains the fundamental conviction which obtains in rude, religiously productive primitive civilisations. We latter-day men feel just the contrary,—the richer man now feels himself inwardly, the more polyphonous is the music and the noise of his soul the more powerfully the symmetry of nature works upon him; we all recognise with Goethe the great means in nature for the appeasing of the modern soul; we listen to the pendulum swing of this greatest of clocks with a longing for rest, for home and tranquillity, as if we could absorb this symmetry into ourselves and could only thereby arrive at the enjoyment of ourselves. Formerly it was otherwise; if we consider the rude, early condition of nations, or contemplate present-day savages' at close quarters, we find them most strongly influenced by law and by tradition: the individual is almost automatically bound to them, and moves with the uniformity of a pendulum. To him Nature—uncomprehended, terrible, mysterious Nature—must appear as the sphere of liberty, of voluntariness, of the higher power, even as a superhuman degree of existence, as God. In those times and conditions, however,[Pg 119] every individual felt that his existence, his happiness, and that of the family and the State, and the success of all undertakings, depended on those spontaneities of nature; certain natural events must appear at the right time, others be absent at the right time. How can one have any influence on these terrible unknown things, how can one bind the sphere of liberty? Thus he asks himself, thus he inquires anxiously;—is there, then, no means of making those powers as regular through tradition and law as you are yourself? The aim of those who believe in magic and miracles is to impose a law on nature,—and, briefly, the religious cult is a result of this aim. The problem which those people have set themselves is closely related to this: how can the weaker race dictate laws to the stronger, rule it, and guide its actions (in relation to the weaker)? One would first remember the most harmless sort of compulsion, that compulsion which one exercises when one has gained any one's affection. By imploring and praying, by submission, by the obligation of regular taxes and gifts, by flattering glorifications, it is also possible to exercise an influence upon the powers of nature, inasmuch as one gains the affections; love binds and becomes bound. Then one can make compacts by which one is mutually bound to a certain behaviour, where one gives pledges and exchanges vows. But far more important is a species of more forcible compulsion, by magic and witchcraft. As with the sorcerer's help man is able to injure a more powerful enemy and keep him in fear, as the love-charm works at[Pg 120] a distance, so the weaker man believes he can influence the mightier spirits of nature. The principal thing in all witchcraft is that we must get into our possession something that belongs to some one, hair, nails, food from their table, even their portrait, their name. With such apparatus we can then practise sorcery; for the fundamental rule is, to everything spiritual there belongs something corporeal; with the help of this we are able to bind the spirit, to injure it, and destroy it; the corporeal furnishes the handles with which we can grasp the spiritual. As man controls man, so he controls some natural spirit or other; for this has also its corporeal part by which it may be grasped. The tree and, compared with it, the seed from which it sprang,—this enigmatical contrast seems to prove that the same spirit embodied itself in both forms, now small, now large. A stone that begins to roll suddenly is the body in which a spirit operates; if there is an enormous rock lying on a lonely heath it seems impossible to conceive human strength sufficient to have brought it there, consequently the stone must have moved there by itself, that is, it must be possessed by a spirit. Everything that has a body is susceptible to witchcraft, therefore also the natural spirits. If a god is bound to his image we can use the most direct compulsion against him (through refusal of sacrificial food, scourging, binding in fetters, and so on). In order to obtain by force the missing favour of their god the lower classes in China wind cords round the image of the one who has left them in the lurch,[Pg 121] pull it down and drag it through the streets in the dust and the dirt: "You dog of a spirit," they say, "we gave you a magnificent temple to live in, we gilded you prettily, we fed you well, we offered you sacrifice, and yet you are so ungrateful." Similar forcible measures against pictures of the Saints and Virgin when they refused to do their duty in pestilence or drought, have been witnessed even during the present century in Catholic countries. Through all these magic relations to nature, countless ceremonies have been called into life; and at last, when the confusion has grown too great, an endeavour has been made to order and systematise them, in order that the favourable course of the whole progress of nature, i.e. of the great succession of the seasons, may seem to be guaranteed by a corresponding course of a system of procedure. The essence of the religious cult is to determine and confine nature to human advantage, to impress it with a legality, therefore, which it did not originally possess; while at the present time we wish to recognise the legality of nature in order to adapt ourselves to it. In short, then, the religious cult is based upon the representations of sorcery between man and man,—and the sorcerer is older than the priest. But it is likewise based upon other and nobler representations; it premises the sympathetic relation of man to man, the presence of goodwill, gratitude, the hearing of pleaders, of treaties between enemies, the granting of pledges, and the claim to the protection of property. In very low stages of[Pg 122] civilisation man does not stand in the relation of a helpless slave to nature, he is not necessarily its involuntary, bondsman. In the Greek grade of religion, particularly in relation to the Olympian gods, there may even be imagined a common life between two castes, a nobler and more powerful one, and one less noble; but in their origin both belong to each other somehow, and are of one kind; they need not be ashamed of each other. That is the nobility of the Greek religion.

The Origin of the Religious Cult.—If we look back at the time when religious life was at its peak, we find a core belief that we no longer share, and this belief has permanently closed the doors to a religious life for us—it relates to Nature and our interaction with it. Back then, people were unaware of natural laws; there was no "must" for the earth or the heavens; seasons, sunshine, and rain could come or go as they pleased. Essentially, there was no understanding of natural causality. When someone rows a boat, it’s not the rowing that propels it; rowing is just a magical act that compels a dæmon to move the boat. All illnesses, even death, were attributed to magical forces. Illness and death didn’t happen naturally; the idea of "natural sequence" didn’t exist—it first emerged among the older Greeks, during a much later stage of humanity, in the idea of Moira, who was seen as ruling over the gods. When a person shoots an arrow, there's always an irrational hand and strength involved; if wells suddenly dry up, people first think of underground dæmons and their tricks; it must be the arrow of a god that causes someone to suddenly collapse. In India (as Lubbock states), a carpenter typically makes sacrifices to his tools like his hammer and hatchet; similarly, a Brahmin honors the pen with which he writes, a soldier pays respect to his weapons, a mason to his trowel, and a laborer to his plough. In the eyes of religious people, all of nature is a collection of actions from conscious and voluntary beings, an immense web of arbitrariness. No conclusions can be drawn about anything outside of us, as in if something will be or must be a certain way; we, as humans, are the rule, while nature represents irregularity. This perspective is a foundational belief in primitive, religiously oriented cultures. In contrast, we modern folks feel the opposite—the richer a person feels inside, the more vibrant and harmonious the music and noise of their soul, the more strongly nature's symmetry affects them; we all recognize, alongside Goethe, nature’s powerful role in soothing the modern soul. We listen to the ticking of this grand clock, longing for rest, home, and peace, as if we could absorb this symmetry into ourselves to truly enjoy our own existence. It used to be different; when we consider the primitive state of nations or observe present-day societies closely, we see that they are heavily influenced by law and tradition: individuals are almost automatically bound to them and move with the consistency of a pendulum. To them, Nature—unfathomable, frightening, and mysterious—appears as the sphere of liberty, of volition, and of a higher power, almost like a god. In those times and conditions, every individual felt that their existence, happiness, that of their family and the State, and the success of all undertakings relied on nature’s erratic behaviors; specific natural events needed to occur at the right moment while others had to be absent. How could one influence these terrifying unknowns? How could one impose order on the realm of freedom? Such were the anxious inquiries of the people—was there no way to regularize those forces through tradition and law just as one regulates oneself? The goal of those who believe in magic and miracles is to impose a law on nature,—and, in short, the religious cult results from this ambition. The dilemma they face is closely related: how can the weaker group dictate laws to the stronger, control it, and direct its actions in relation to the weaker? Initially, one might consider the least invasive form of compulsion, which arises when one gains someone’s affection. Through pleading and prayer, submission, the obligation of regular taxes and gifts, and flattering praise, one can influence nature’s powers by earning their favor; love ties and binds. Then, one can establish agreements that mutually bind behaviors, involving pledges and vows. But far more critical is a more forceful type of compulsion, through magic and witchcraft. Just as the sorcerer can harm a stronger enemy and instill fear, as love spells work at [Pg 120] a distance, so too does the weaker individual believe they can influence the more powerful spirits of nature. The heart of all witchcraft lies in acquiring something that belongs to someone—hair, nails, a meal they have eaten, even their portrait or name. With such items, one can then practice sorcery; for the fundamental rule is that anything spiritual has a corresponding physical element; with these, one can bind, harm, or destroy the spirit; the physical provides the means with which one can grasp the spiritual. Just as one human can control another, so can one control a natural spirit, as these too have physical forms that can be grasped. The tree and its seed—this mysterious contrast suggests that the same spirit exists in both forms, now small, now large. A stone that suddenly begins to roll is the physical manifestation of a spirit at work; if there’s a huge boulder on a deserted heath, it seems unfathomable for human strength to have placed it there, thus the stone must have moved there by itself, meaning it must be driven by a spirit. Everything that possesses a body is vulnerable to witchcraft; therefore, so are the natural spirits. If a god is linked to their image, we can exercise the most direct compulsion against them (by withholding sacrifices, punishing, binding them, and so on). To regain their god's favor by force, the lower classes in China wrap cords around the image of the deity that has disappointed them, [Pg 121] drag it through the streets in the dirt, and berate it: "You ungrateful spirit," they say, "we built you a magnificent temple, we adorned you, we provided for you, and yet you are so ungrateful." Similar forced actions against images of Saints and the Virgin when they do not come through during plagues or droughts have even been observed in Catholic countries in recent times. Through all these magical relations with nature, countless ceremonies have emerged, and eventually, when the disorder has grown too overwhelming, efforts have been made to organize and systematize them so that the favorable trend of nature's progression—the grand cycle of seasons—appears to be ensured by a corresponding set of practices. The essence of religious cults is to define and confine nature for human benefit, to impose a structure on it that it didn’t originally possess; whereas in our current time, we aim to understand nature’s underlying principles to adapt ourselves to it. In summary, the religious cult is rooted in the representations of sorcery between individuals—and the sorcerer predates the priest. Yet, it’s also based on other, more noble representations; it presumes a sympathetic relationship among people, the presence of goodwill, gratitude, the listening to pleas, treaties among adversaries, the making of pledges, and the right to safeguard one’s property. In very primitive stages of [Pg 122] civilization, a person does not stand as a helpless slave to nature; they are not necessarily its involuntary bondsman. In the Greek form of religion, especially concerning the Olympian gods, one can even envision a shared existence between two classes, a nobler, more powerful one, and a less noble one; yet, both are somehow intertwined in their origins and of the same kind; they have no need to feel ashamed of each other. That is the nobility of Greek religion.

112.

112.

At the Sight of Certain Antique Sacrificial Implements.—The fact of how many feelings are lost to us may be seen, for instance, in the mingling of the droll, even of the obscene, with the religious feeling. The sensation of the possibility of this mixture vanishes, we only comprehend historically that it existed in the feasts of Demeter and Dionysus, in the Christian Easter-plays and Mysteries. But we also know that which is noble in alliance with burlesque and such like, the touching mingled with the laughable, which perhaps a later age will not be able to understand.

At the Sight of Some Old Sacrificial Tools.—The number of feelings we've lost is evident, for example, in how the funny, even the offensive, blends with religious sentiment. The idea of this mixture fades away; we only understand historically that it once existed during the feasts of Demeter and Dionysus, as well as in Christian Easter plays and Mysteries. Yet, we also recognize the noble combined with the absurd and similar elements, the poignant mixed with the comedic, which perhaps a future generation won't be able to grasp.

113.

113.

Christianity As Antiquity.—When on a Sunday morning we hear the old bells ring out, we ask ourselves, "Is it possible! This is done on account of a Jew crucified two thousand years ago who said he was the Son of God. The proof of such an assertion is wanting." Certainly in our[Pg 123] times the Christian religion is an antiquity that dates from very early ages, and the fact that its assertions are still believed, when otherwise all claims are subjected to such strict examination, is perhaps the oldest part of this heritage. A God who creates a son from a mortal woman; a sage who requires that man should no longer work, no longer judge, but should pay attention to the signs of the approaching end of the world; a justice that accepts an innocent being as a substitute in sacrifice; one who commands his disciples to drink his blood; prayers for miraculous intervention; sins committed against a God and atoned for through a God; the fear of a future to which death is the portal; the form of the cross in an age which no longer knows the signification and the shame of the cross,[3] how terrible all this appears to us, as if risen from the grave of the ancient past! Is it credible that such things are still believed?

Christianity in Ancient Times.—When we hear the old bells ringing on a Sunday morning, we find ourselves pondering, "Is this really happening? This is because of a Jew who was crucified two thousand years ago, claiming to be the Son of God. There's no proof for such a claim." Definitely, in our[Pg 123] times, Christianity feels like a relic from a long time ago, and the fact that its teachings are still accepted, even when everything else is scrutinized so closely, is perhaps the most ancient part of this tradition. A God who creates a son from a mortal woman; a wise figure saying that people should stop working and judging, and instead pay attention to signs of the world's end; a justice system that permits an innocent person to be a sacrificial substitute; someone who tells his followers to drink his blood; prayers asking for miraculous help; sins committed against a God and forgiven through another God; the anxiety about a future where death is the gateway; the symbol of the cross in a time that no longer understands its meaning or shame, [3] how frightening all this seems, as if it arose from the depths of an ancient grave! Can it really be that such beliefs are still held?

114.

114.

What Is Un-greek in Christianity.—The Greeks did not regard the Homeric gods as raised above them like masters, nor themselves as being under them like servants, as the Jews did. They only saw, as in a mirror, the most perfect examples of their own caste; an ideal, therefore, and not an opposite of their own nature. There is a feeling[Pg 124] of relationship, a mutual interest arises, a kind of symmachy. Man thinks highly of himself when he gives himself such gods, and places himself in a relation like that of the lower nobility towards the higher; while the Italian nations hold a genuine peasant-faith, with perpetual fear of evil and mischievous powers and tormenting spirits. Wherever the Olympian gods retreated into the background, Greek life was more sombre and more anxious. Christianity, on the contrary, oppressed man and crushed him utterly, sinking him as if in deep mire; then into the feeling of absolute depravity it suddenly threw the light of divine mercy, so that the surprised man, dazzled by forgiveness, gave a cry of joy and for a moment believed that he bore all heaven within himself. All psychological feelings of Christianity work upon this unhealthy excess of sentiment, and upon the deep corruption of head and heart it necessitates; it desires to destroy, break, stupefy, confuse,—only one thing it does not desire, namely moderation, and therefore it is in the deepest sense barbaric, Asiatic, ignoble and un-Greek.

What Is Un-Greek in Christianity.—The Greeks didn’t see the Homeric gods as superior beings like masters, nor did they view themselves as subservient like the Jews did. Instead, they perceived these gods as reflections of their own ideals, perfect examples of their own kind, rather than as something completely different. There was a sense of connection, a shared interest—a kind of partnership. People held themselves in high regard when they created these gods, positioning themselves like the lesser nobility towards the higher ranks; meanwhile, the Italian nations maintained a genuine peasant-like faith, filled with constant fear of evil, mischief, and malevolent spirits. When the Olympian gods faded from view, Greek life became more somber and anxious. In contrast, Christianity weighed heavily on humanity, dragging individuals down as if into deep mud; then, in the midst of utter depravity, it suddenly illuminated the path with divine mercy, causing the astonished individual to feel overwhelmed by forgiveness, momentarily believing he held all of heaven within himself. All the psychological aspects of Christianity operate on this excessive sentiment and the profound corruption of both mind and heart it requires; it seeks to destroy, break, confuse, and stupefy—yet there is one thing it does not aspire to: moderation. Therefore, it is in the deepest sense barbaric, Asiatic, ignoble, and un-Greek.

115.

115.

To Be Religious With Advantage.—There are sober and industrious people on whom religion is embroidered like a hem of higher humanity; these do well to remain religious, it beautifies them. All people who do not understand some kind of trade in weapons—tongue and pen included as weapons—become servile; for such the Christian[Pg 125] religion is very useful, for then servility assumes the appearance of Christian virtues and is surprisingly beautified. People to whom their daily life appears too empty and monotonous easily grow religious; this is comprehensible and excusable, only they have no right to demand religious sentiments from those whose daily life is not empty and monotonous.[4]

Be Religious for Benefit.—There are serious and hardworking people for whom religion is like a beautiful trim that enhances their humanity; these individuals should stay religious, as it adds to their character. Anyone who doesn’t have a skill or trade—whether it's verbal or written communication—ends up becoming submissive; for these people, Christianity is quite beneficial, as it allows submission to take on the facade of Christian virtues, appearing surprisingly uplifting. Those whose daily lives seem too dull or repetitive are likely to turn to religion; this is understandable and forgivable, but they shouldn’t expect others with fulfilling lives to feel the same religious inclination.[4]

116.

116.

The Commonplace Christian.—If Christianity were right, with its theories of an avenging God, of general sinfulness, of redemption, and the danger of eternal damnation, it would be a sign of weak intellect and lack of character not to become a priest, apostle or hermit, and to work only with fear and trembling for one's own salvation; it would be senseless thus to neglect eternal benefits for temporary comfort. Taking it for granted that there is belief, the commonplace Christian is a miserable figure, a man that really cannot add two and two together, and who, moreover, just because of his mental incapacity for responsibility, did not deserve to be so severely punished as Christianity has decreed.

The Everyday Christian.—If Christianity is correct, with its ideas of a vengeful God, universal sin, redemption, and the risk of eternal damnation, then it would show a lack of intelligence and character not to become a priest, apostle, or hermit, and to instead focus solely on one's own salvation with fear and trembling; it would be foolish to ignore eternal rewards for short-term comfort. Assuming there is belief, the typical Christian is a pitiful figure, someone who truly struggles to put two and two together, and who, because of his inability to take responsibility, doesn't deserve the harsh punishment that Christianity dictates.

117.

117.

Of the Wisdom of Christianity.—It is a clever stroke on the part of Christianity to teach[Pg 126] the utter unworthiness, sinfulness, and despicableness of mankind so loudly that the disdain of their fellow-men is no longer possible. "He may sin as much as he likes, he is not essentially different from me,—it is I who am unworthy and despicable in every way," says the Christian to himself. But even this feeling has lost its sharpest sting, because the Christian no longer believes in his individual despicableness; he is bad as men are generally, and comforts himself a little with the axiom, "We are all of one kind."

Of the Wisdom of Christianity.—Christianity cleverly teaches[Pg 126] about the complete worthlessness, sinfulness, and contemptibility of humanity so loudly that it's no longer possible to look down on others. "He can sin as much as he wants; he isn't essentially different from me—I’m the one who is unworthy and despicable in every way," thinks the Christian. But even this feeling has lost its sharpest edge because the Christian no longer believes in his individual contemptibility; he’s just as flawed as everyone else, and finds some comfort in the saying, "We are all of one kind."

118.

118.

Change of Front.—As soon as a religion triumphs it has for its enemies all those who would have been its first disciples.

Front Change.—Once a religion succeeds, it gains as its opponents all the people who could have been its initial followers.

119.

119.

The Fate of Christianity.—Christianity arose for the purpose of lightening the heart; but now it must first make the heart heavy in order afterwards to lighten it. Consequently it will perish.

The Future of Christianity.—Christianity started out to bring joy to people's hearts; but now it first burdens the heart before it can bring relief. As a result, it is destined to fade away.

120.

120.

The Proof of Pleasure.—The agreeable opinion is accepted as true,—this is the proof of the pleasure (or, as the Church says, the proof of the strength), of which all religions are so proud when they ought to be ashamed of it. If Faith did not make blessed it would not be believed in; of how little value must it be, then!

The Proof of Pleasure.—The positive opinion is taken as true—this is the proof of pleasure (or, as the Church puts it, the proof of strength), which all religions boast about when they should really feel embarrassed by it. If Faith didn’t bring blessings, it wouldn’t be believed in; so how valuable can it really be?

121.

121.

A Dangerous Game.—Whoever now allows scope to his religious feelings must also let them increase, he cannot do otherwise. His nature then gradually changes; it favours whatever is connected with and near to the religious element, the whole extent of judgment and feeling becomes clouded, overcast with religious shadows. Sensation cannot stand still; one must therefore take care.

A Risky Game.—Whoever allows their religious feelings to grow will find that they inevitably expand; there's no way around it. This causes a gradual change in their nature, leading to an increased affinity for anything related to religion. Their entire capacity for judgment and emotion becomes obscured, overshadowed by religious influences. Sensation can't remain static; so, one must be cautious.

122.

122.

The Blind Disciples.—So long as one knows well the strength and weakness of one's doctrine, one's art, one's religion, its power is still small. The disciple and apostle who has no eyes for the weaknesses of the doctrine, the religion, and so forth, dazzled by the aspect of the master and by his reverence for him, has on that account usually more power than the master himself. Without blind disciples the influence of a man and his work has never yet become great. To help a doctrine to victory often means only so to mix it with stupidity that the weight of the latter carries off also the victory for the former.

The Unseen Followers.—As long as someone understands the strengths and weaknesses of their beliefs, their art, or their religion, its impact is still limited. A disciple or follower who overlooks the flaws in these teachings, captivated by the master's persona and their own admiration, often possesses more influence than the master. Without these blind followers, a person's impact and their work have never truly reached greatness. Helping a belief system succeed often just means blending it with ignorance so that the latter drags the former along to a hollow victory.

123.

123.

Church Disestablishment.—There is not enough religion in the world even to destroy religions.

Church Separation.—There isn't enough faith in the world to even wipe out religions.

124.

124.

The Sinlessness of Man.—If it is understood how "sin came into the world," namely through errors of reason by which men held each other, even the single individual held himself, to be much blacker and much worse than was actually the case, the whole sensation will be much lightened, and man and the world will appear in a blaze of innocence which it will do one good to contemplate. In the midst of nature man is always the child per se. This child sometimes has a heavy and terrifying dream, but when it opens its eyes it always finds itself back again in Paradise.

The Innocence of Humanity.—If we understand how "sin entered the world," specifically through the mistakes in reasoning where people judged one another, and even judged themselves, to be far worse than they actually are, the entire experience becomes much lighter, and humanity and the world will look radiant with innocence, which is uplifting to reflect upon. In the midst of nature, man is always a child per se. This child may sometimes have a heavy and frightening dream, but when it opens its eyes, it always finds itself back in Paradise.

125.

125.

The Irreligiousness of Artists.—Homer is so much at home amongst his gods, and is so familiar with them as a poet, that he must have been deeply irreligious; that which the popular faith gave him—a meagre, rude, partly terrible superstition—he treated as freely as the sculptor does his clay, with the same unconcern, therefore, which Æschylus and Aristophanes possessed, and by which in later times the great artists of the Renaissance distinguished themselves, as also did Shakespeare and Goethe.

The Non-religiousness of Artists.—Homer is so comfortable with his gods and so familiar with them as a poet that he must have been quite irreverent. The popular beliefs of his time—a sparse, rough, partly frightening superstition—he approached as freely as a sculptor works with clay, with the same indifference that Æschylus and Aristophanes had, and which later marked the great artists of the Renaissance, as well as Shakespeare and Goethe.

126.

126.

The Art and Power of False Interpretations.—All the visions, terrors, torpors,[Pg 129] and ecstasies of saints are well-known forms of disease, which are only, by reason of deep-rooted religious and psychological errors, differently explained by him, namely not as diseases. Thus, perhaps, the Daimonion of Socrates was only an affection of the ear, which he, in accordance with his ruling moral mode of thought, expounded differently from what would be the case now. It is the same thing with the madness and ravings of the prophets and soothsayers; it is always the degree of knowledge, fantasy, effort, morality in the head and heart of the interpreters which has made so much of it. For the greatest achievements of the people who are called geniuses and saints it is necessary that they should secure interpreters by force, who misunderstand them for the good of mankind.

The Skill and Influence of Misinterpretation.—All the visions, fears, numbness, [Pg 129], and ecstasies of saints are well-known types of illness, which are only, due to deeply ingrained religious and psychological misconceptions, interpreted differently by him, namely not as illnesses. Thus, perhaps, the Daimonion of Socrates was just an ear condition, which he, in line with his dominant moral way of thinking, explained in a way that's different from how it would be understood today. The same goes for the madness and ranting of prophets and soothsayers; it’s always the level of knowledge, imagination, effort, and morality in the minds and hearts of the interpreters that has shaped so much of it. For the most significant accomplishments of those labeled geniuses and saints, it's essential that they have interpreters who misinterpret them for the benefit of humanity.

127.

127.

The Veneration of Insanity.—Because it was remarked that excitement frequently made the mind clearer and produced happy inspirations it was believed that the happiest inspirations and suggestions were called forth by the greatest excitement; and so the insane were revered as wise and oracular. This is based on a false conclusion.

The Celebration of Madness.—It was noted that excitement often cleared the mind and led to positive insights, so people thought that the best ideas and suggestions came from intense excitement; as a result, those who were insane were honored as wise and prophetic. This belief is founded on a mistaken conclusion.

128.

128.

The Promises of Science.—The aim of modern science is: as little pain as possible, as long a life as possible,—a kind of eternal blessedness,[Pg 130] therefore; but certainly a very modest one as compared with the promises of religions.

The Promises of Science.—The goal of modern science is: to cause as little pain as possible and to extend life for as long as possible—a sort of eternal happiness,[Pg 130] which is definitely modest when compared to what religions promise.

129.

129.

Forbidden Generosity.—There is not sufficient love and goodness in the world to permit us to give some of it away to imaginary beings.

Taboo Kindness.—There isn't enough love and goodness in the world for us to share it with fictional beings.

130.

130.

The Continuance of the Religious Cult in the Feelings.—The Roman Catholic Church, and before that all antique cults, dominated the entire range of means by which man was put into unaccustomed moods and rendered incapable of the cold calculation of judgment or the clear thinking of reason. A church quivering with deep tones; the dull, regular, arresting appeals of a priestly throng, unconsciously communicates its tension to the congregation and makes it listen almost fearfully, as if a miracle were in preparation; the influence of the architecture, which, as the dwelling of a Godhead, extends into the uncertain and makes its apparition to be feared in all its sombre spaces,—who would wish to bring such things back to mankind if the necessary suppositions are no longer believed? But the results of all this are not lost, nevertheless; the inner world of noble, emotional, deeply contrite dispositions, full of presentiments, blessed with hope, is inborn in mankind mainly through this cult; what exists of it now in the[Pg 131] soul was then cultivated on a large scale as it germinated, grew up and blossomed.

The Ongoing Influence of Religious Beliefs on Emotions.—The Roman Catholic Church, along with all ancient religious practices, held sway over the ways people experienced unfamiliar emotions and became less capable of cold, rational judgment or clear thinking. A church filled with deep resonant sounds; the steady, repetitive, and captivating calls of a group of priests unconsciously transfer their intense energy to the congregation, making them listen with a sense of apprehension, as if a miracle were about to happen; the impact of the architecture, which serves as the dwelling place of a deity, reaches into the unknown and invokes fear in its dark corners—who would want to revive such things for humanity if the foundational beliefs are no longer held? Yet, the results of all this are not lost; the inner world of noble, emotional, and deeply remorseful feelings, filled with forewarnings and blessed with hope, is primarily ingrained in humanity through this worship; what remains in the [Pg 131] soul was once nurtured extensively as it sprouted, matured, and flourished.

131.

131.

THE PAINFUL CONSEQUENCES OF RELIGION.—However much we may think we have weaned ourselves from religion, it has nevertheless not been done so thoroughly as to deprive us of pleasure in encountering religious sensations and moods in music, for instance; and if a philosophy shows us the justification of metaphysical hopes and the deep peace of soul to be thence acquired, and speaks, for instance, of the "whole, certain gospel in the gaze of Raphael's Madonnas," we receive such statements and expositions particularly warmly; here the philosopher finds it easier to prove; that which he desires to give corresponds to a heart that desires to receive. Hence it may be observed how the less thoughtful free spirits really only take offence at the dogmas, but are well acquainted with the charm of religious sensations; they are sorry to lose hold of the latter for the sake of the former. Scientific philosophy must be very careful not to smuggle in errors on the ground of that need,—a need which has grown up and is consequently temporary,—even logicians speak of "presentiments" of truth in ethics and in art (for instance, of the suspicion that "the nature of things is one"), which should be forbidden to them Between the carefully established truths and such "presaged" things there remains the[Pg 132] unbridgable chasm that those are due to intellect and these to requirement Hunger does not prove that food exists to satisfy it, but that it desires food. To "presage" does not mean the acknowledgment of the existence of a thing in any one degree, but its possibility, in so far as it is desired or feared; "presage" does not advance one step into the land of certainty. We believe involuntarily that the portions of a philosophy which are tinged with religion are better proved than others; but actually it is the contrary, but we have the inward desire that it may be so, that that which makes blessed, therefore, may be also the true. This desire misleads us to accept bad reasons for good ones.

THE PAINFUL CONSEQUENCES OF RELIGION.—No matter how much we think we’ve moved away from religion, we haven’t completely let go of the enjoyment we find in the religious feelings and moods in music, for example. When a philosophy presents the justification for metaphysical hopes and the inner peace that can be gained from them, like when it talks about the "whole, certain gospel in the gaze of Raphael's Madonnas," we tend to embrace those ideas warmly. Here, the philosopher finds it easier to prove their point; what they want to share resonates with a heart that is eager to accept it. Thus, it can be observed that less reflective free thinkers may only have issues with dogmas but are well-acquainted with the allure of religious feelings; they don’t want to lose those sensations just because of the dogmas. Scientific philosophy must be cautious not to let temporary needs—needs that have developed over time—slip in as errors. Even logicians refer to "presentiments" of truth in ethics and art (like the suspicion that "the nature of things is one"), which should really be off-limits for them. There remains an unbridgeable gap between thoroughly established truths and these "presaged" ideas; the former stem from intellect, while the latter arise from need. Hunger doesn’t prove that food exists to satisfy it, but rather it shows that there is a desire for food. To "presage" doesn’t mean acknowledging the existence of something at any level, but rather its possibility, as far as it is wanted or feared; "presage" doesn’t take us one step further into certainty. We involuntarily believe that the parts of a philosophy that have a hint of religion are better supported than others; in reality, it’s the opposite, but we have an internal wish that it might be true, that what brings bliss might also be the truth. This wish leads us to accept poor justifications for good ones.

132.

132.

Of the Christian Need of Redemption.—With careful reflection it must be possible to obtain an explanation free from mythology of that process in the soul of a Christian which is called the need of redemption, consequently a purely psychological explanation. Up to the present, the psychological explanations of religious conditions and processes have certainly been held in some disrepute, inasmuch as a theology which called itself free carried on its unprofitable practice in this domain; for here from the beginning (as the mind of its founder, Schleiermacher, gives us reason to suppose) the preservation of the Christian religion and the continuance of Christian theology was kept in view; a[Pg 133] theology which was to find a new anchorage in the psychological analyses of religious "facts," and above all a new occupation. Unconcerned about such predecessors we hazard the following interpretation of the phenomenon in question. Man is conscious of certain actions which stand far down in the customary rank of actions; he even discovers in himself a tendency towards similar actions, a tendency which appears to him almost as unchangeable as his whole nature. How willingly would he try himself in that other species of actions which in the general valuation are recognised as the loftiest and highest, how gladly would he feel himself to be full of the good consciousness which should follow an unselfish mode of thought! But unfortunately he stops short at this wish, and the discontent at not being able to satisfy it is added to all the other discontents which his lot in life or the consequences of those above-mentioned evil actions have aroused in him; so that a deep ill-humour is the result, with the search for a physician who could remove this and all its causes. This condition would not be felt so bitterly if man would only compare himself frankly with other men,—then he would have no reason for being dissatisfied with himself to a particular extent, he would only bear his share of the common burden of human dissatisfaction and imperfection. But he compares himself with a being who is said to be capable only of those actions which are called un-egoistic, and to live in the perpetual consciousness of an[Pg 134] unselfish mode of thought, i.e. with God; it is because he gazes into this clear mirror that his image appears to him so dark, so unusually warped. Then he is alarmed by the thought of that same creature, in so far as it floats before his imagination as a retributive justice; in all possible small and great events he thinks he recognises its anger and menaces, that he even feels its scourge-strokes as judge and executioner. Who will help him in this danger, which, by the prospect of an immeasurable duration of punishment, exceeds in horror all the other terrors of the idea?

Regarding the Christian Need for Redemption.—With thoughtful consideration, it should be possible to provide a clear explanation, free from mythology, of what is known as the need for redemption in a Christian's soul, hence a strictly psychological explanation. So far, psychological interpretations of religious states and processes have faced skepticism, mainly because a theology that labeled itself as progressive pursued unhelpful practices in this area; from the start (as the mindset of its founder, Schleiermacher, suggests), the aim was to preserve the Christian faith and continue Christian theology. This theology sought to find a new foundation in psychological analyses of religious "facts," and of course, a new focus. Without concern for such predecessors, we offer the following interpretation of the phenomenon at hand. A person is aware of certain actions that rank low in the usual hierarchy of actions; they even discover within themselves a tendency towards similar actions, a tendency that feels almost as fixed as their entire nature. How eager would they be to engage in those other types of actions that are recognized in general as the highest and most noble, how gladly would they embrace the good feeling that should accompany an unselfish mindset! But unfortunately, they come up short in fulfilling this desire, and their disappointment in being unable to do so adds to all the other dissatisfaction stirred up by their circumstances or the effects of those previously mentioned negative actions; as a result, they are left with a deep sense of frustration and a quest for a healer who can alleviate this along with all its causes. This state wouldn't feel so painful if people would honestly compare themselves with others—then they wouldn’t have a particular reason to be dissatisfied with themselves, but would simply share in the common weight of human dissatisfaction and imperfection. However, they compare themselves to a being said to be capable only of actions deemed unselfish, living in the constant awareness of an [Pg 134] unselfish mindset, i.e. God; it is in looking into this clear mirror that their own reflection appears dark and unusually distorted. Then they are filled with dread by the thought of that very being, as it looms in their imagination as a force of retributive justice; in every possible small and large event, they believe they detect its anger and threats and even feel its punishing strokes as judge and executioner. Who will rescue them from this peril, which, with the dread of unending punishment, surpasses all other fears associated with this concept?

133.

133.

Before we examine the further consequences of this mental state, let us acknowledge that it is not through his "guilt" and "sin" that man has got into this condition, but through a series of errors of reason; that it was the fault of the mirror if his image appeared so dark and hateful to him, and that that mirror was his work, the very imperfect work of human imagination and power of judgment. In the first place, a nature that is only capable of purely un-egoistic actions is more fabulous than the phœnix; it cannot even be clearly imagined, just because, when closely examined, the whole idea "un-egoistic action" vanishes into air. No man ever did a thing which was done only for others and without any personal motive; how should he be able to do anything which had no relation[Pg 135] to himself, and therefore without inward obligation (which must always have its foundation in a personal need)? How could the ego act without ego A God who, on the contrary, is all love, as such a one is often represented, would not be capable of a single un-egoistic action, whereby one is reminded of a saying of Lichtenberg's which is certainly taken from a lower sphere: "We cannot possibly feel for others, as the saying is; we feel only for ourselves. This sounds hard, but it is not so really if it be rightly understood. We do not love father or mother or wife or child, but the pleasant sensations they cause us;" or, as Rochefoucauld says: "Si on croit aimer sa maîtresse pour l'amour d'elle, on est bien trompé." To know the reason why actions of love are valued more than others, not on account of their nature, namely, but of their usefulness, we should compare the examinations already mentioned, On the Origin of Moral Sentiments. But should a man desire to be entirely like that God of Love, to do and wish everything for others and nothing for himself, the latter is impossible for the reason that he must do very much for himself to be able to do something for the love of others. Then it is taken for granted that the other is sufficiently egoistic to accept that sacrifice again and again, that living for him,—so that the people of love and sacrifice have an interest in the continuance of those who are loveless and incapable of sacrifice, and, in order to exist, the highest morality would be obliged positively[Pg 136] to compel the existence of un-morality (whereby it would certainly annihilate itself). Further: the conception of a God disturbs and humbles so long as it is believed in; but as to how it arose there can no longer be any doubt in the present state of the science of comparative ethnology; and with a comprehension of this origin all belief falls to the ground. The Christian who compares his nature with God's is like Don Quixote, who under-valued his own bravery because his head was full of the marvellous deeds of the heroes of the chivalric; romances,—the standard of measurement in both cases belongs to the domain of fable. But if the idea of God is removed, so is also the feeling of "sin" as a trespass against divine laws, as a stain in a creature vowed to God. Then, perhaps, there still remains that dejection which is intergrown and connected with the fear of the punishment of worldly justice or of the scorn of men; the dejection of the pricks of conscience, the sharpest thorn in the consciousness of sin, is always removed if we recognise that though by our own deed we have sinned against human descent, human laws and ordinances, still that we have not imperilled the "eternal salvation of the Soul" and its relation to the Godhead. And if man succeeds in gaining philosophic conviction of the absolute necessity of all actions and their entire irresponsibility, and absorbing this into his flesh and blood, even those remains of the pricks of conscience vanish.

Before we look at the further consequences of this mental state, let's acknowledge that it isn't through his "guilt" and "sin" that a person has ended up in this condition, but through a series of reasoning errors; it was the fault of the mirror if his reflection appeared so dark and repulsive to him, and that mirror was his creation, the very imperfect product of human imagination and judgment. First of all, a nature that is only capable of purely altruistic actions is more mythical than the phoenix; it can't even be clearly imagined because, upon closer examination, the whole idea of "altruistic action" disappears. No one ever did something solely for others and without any personal motive; how could anyone be able to do anything that had no relevance[Pg 135] to themselves, and therefore without an internal obligation (which must always have its roots in a personal need)? How could the ego act without ego? A God who, on the other hand, is all love, as such beings are often portrayed, would not be capable of a single altruistic action, reminding one of a saying by Lichtenberg which certainly comes from a less lofty sphere: "We cannot possibly feel for others, as the saying goes; we only feel for ourselves. This sounds harsh, but it’s not really so if understood correctly. We do not love father or mother or spouse or child, but the pleasant feelings they give us;" or, as Rochefoucauld says: "Si on croit aimer sa maîtresse pour l'amour d'elle, on est bien trompé." To understand why acts of love are valued more than others—not because of their nature, but due to their usefulness, we should look at the discussions previously mentioned, On the Origin of Moral Sentiments. But if someone desires to be entirely like that God of Love, to do and wish everything for others and nothing for themselves, the latter is impossible because they must do a lot for themselves to then be able to do something for the love of others. It is assumed that the other person is self-centered enough to accept that sacrifice repeatedly, that living for them—so that those who love and sacrifice have an interest in the survival of those who are loveless and unable to sacrifice, and, in order to exist, the highest morality would be obliged to compel the existence of immorality (which would undoubtedly destroy itself). Furthermore, the idea of God causes disturbance and humility as long as it is believed; but regarding how it came into being, there can no longer be any doubt in the current state of comparative ethnology; and with an understanding of this origin, all belief collapses. The Christian who compares his nature to God's is like Don Quixote, who undervalued his own bravery because his mind was filled with the marvelous deeds of the heroes from chivalric romances—the standard of measurement in both cases belongs to the realm of fable. However, if the idea of God is removed, so too is the feeling of "sin" as a violation of divine laws, as a stain on a creature devoted to God. Then, perhaps, that sorrow which is intertwined with the fear of worldly justice's punishment or people's scorn may remain; the guilt from conscience, the sharpest thorn in the awareness of sin, is always removed if we recognize that although by our own actions we have sinned against human descent, human laws, and regulations, we haven't endangered the "eternal salvation of the Soul" or its relationship to the divine. And if a person manages to gain a philosophical understanding of the absolute necessity of all actions and their complete irresponsibility, and truly internalizes this, even the remnants of guilty conscience will fade away.

134.

134.

Now if the Christian, as we have said, has fallen into the way of self-contempt in consequence of certain errors through a false, unscientific interpretation of his actions and sensations, he must notice with great surprise how that state of contempt, the pricks of conscience and displeasure generally, does not endure, how sometimes there come hours when all this is wafted away from his soul and he feels himself once more free and courageous. In truth, the pleasure in himself, the comfort of his own strength, together with the necessary weakening through time of every deep emotion, has usually been victorious; man loves himself once again, he feels it,—but precisely this new love, this self-esteem, seems to him incredible, he can only see in it the wholly undeserved descent of a stream of mercy from on high. If he formerly believed that in every event he could recognise warnings, menaces, punishments, and every kind of manifestation of divine anger, he now finds divine goodness in all his experiences, —this event appears to him to be full of love, that one a helpful hint, a third, and, indeed, his whole happy mood, a proof that God is merciful. As formerly, in his state of pain, he interpreted his actions falsely, so now he misinterprets his experiences; his mood of comfort he believes to be the working of a power operating outside of himself, the love with which he really loves himself seems to him to be divine love; that which he[Pg 138] calls mercy, and the prologue to redemption, is actually self-forgiveness, self-redemption.

Now, if the Christian, as we've mentioned, has fallen into self-hate due to certain mistakes from a misguided, unscientific interpretation of his actions and feelings, he must be surprised to notice how that feeling of contempt, the nagging conscience, and general dissatisfaction don't last. Sometimes, there are moments when all of it is lifted from his soul, and he feels free and brave again. In fact, the enjoyment of himself, the comfort in his own strength, along with the inevitable fading of intense emotions over time, usually prevails; he loves himself once more, and he can sense it—but this newfound love, this self-respect, seems unbelievable to him; he can only see it as an undeserved flow of mercy coming from above. If he once thought that in every situation he could find warnings, threats, punishments, and various signs of divine anger, he now discovers divine goodness in all his experiences—one event feels filled with love, another is a helpful pointer, and the overall happiness he feels proves that God is merciful. Just as he previously misinterpreted his actions during times of pain, he now misreads his experiences; he believes that his sense of comfort comes from a power outside himself, and the love he genuinely feels for himself seems to him like divine love; what he calls mercy and the beginning of redemption is really self-forgiveness and self-redemption.

135.

135.

Therefore: A certain false psychology, a certain kind of imaginative interpretation of motives and experiences, is the necessary preliminary for one to become a Christian and to feel the need of redemption. When this error of reason and imagination is recognised, one ceases to be a Christian.

Therefore: A certain flawed psychology, a specific type of imaginative interpretation of motives and experiences, is the necessary first step for someone to become a Christian and to feel the need for redemption. Once this misunderstanding of reason and imagination is recognized, a person stops being a Christian.

136.

136.

Of Christian Asceticism and Holiness.—As greatly as isolated thinkers have endeavoured to depict as a miracle the rare manifestations of morality, which are generally called asceticism and holiness, miracles which it would be almost an outrage and sacrilege to explain by the light of common sense, as strong also is the inclination towards this outrage. A mighty impulse of nature has at all times led to a protest against those manifestations; science, in so far as it is an imitation of nature, at least allows itself to rise against the supposed inexplicableness and unapproachableness of these objections. So far it has certainly not succeeded: those appearances are still unexplained, to the great joy of the above-mentioned worshippers of the morally marvellous. For, speaking generally, the unexplained must be absolutely inexplicable, the inexplicable absolutely unnatural, supernatural, wonderful,—thus runs the demand in the souls of[Pg 139] all religious and metaphysical people (also of artists, if they should happen to be thinkers at the same time); whilst the scientist sees in this demand the "evil principle" in itself. The general, first probability upon which one lights in the contemplation of holiness and asceticism is this, that their nature is a complicated one, for almost everywhere, within the physical world as well as in the moral, the apparently marvellous has been successfully traced back to the complicated, the many-conditioned. Let us venture, therefore, to isolate separate impulses from the soul of saints and ascetics, and finally to imagine them as intergrown.

Of Christian Asceticism and Holiness.—While individual thinkers have tried to portray the rare instances of morality known as asceticism and holiness as miraculous events that shouldn’t be explained using common sense, there's also a strong temptation to challenge that notion. Throughout history, a powerful drive in nature has consistently pushed back against these displays; science, as a reflection of nature, at least tries to contest the supposed unexplainability and inaccessibility of these issues. So far, it hasn’t fully succeeded; those phenomena remain mysterious, delighting the followers of the morally extraordinary. Generally speaking, the unexplained must be completely inexplicable, and the inexplicable is seen as wholly unnatural, supernatural, or wonderful—this is the expectation in the hearts of[Pg 139] all religious and metaphysical individuals (including artists, should they also be thinkers). Meanwhile, the scientist views this expectation as the "evil principle" itself. The primary assumption one arrives at when considering holiness and asceticism is that their nature is complicated, because in both the physical and moral worlds, what seems extraordinary has often been traced back to complexity and multiple factors. Therefore, let’s attempt to isolate distinct impulses from the souls of saints and ascetics and ultimately imagine them as interconnected.

137.

137.

There is a defiance of self, to the sublimest manifestation of which belong many forms of asceticism. Certain individuals have such great need of exercising their power and love of ruling that, in default of other objects, or because they have never succeeded otherwise, they finally ex-cogitate the idea of tyrannising over certain parts of their own nature, portions or degrees of themselves. Thus many a thinker confesses to views which evidently do not serve either to increase or improve his reputation; many a one deliberately calls down the scorn of others when by keeping silence he could easily have remained respected; others contradict former opinions and do not hesitate to be called inconsistent—on the contrary, they strive after this, and behave like reckless[Pg 140] riders who like a horse best when it has grown wild, unmanageable, and covered with sweat. Thus man climbs dangerous paths up the highest mountains in order that he may laugh to scorn his own fear and his trembling knees; thus the philosopher owns to views on asceticism, humility, holiness, in the brightness of which his own picture shows to the worst possible disadvantage. This crushing of one's self, this scorn of one's own nature, this spernere se sperm, of which religion has made so much, is really a very high degree of vanity. The whole moral of the Sermon on the Mount belongs here; man takes a genuine delight in doing violence to himself by these exaggerated claims, and afterwards idolising these tyrannical demands of his soul. In every ascetic morality man worships one part of himself as a God, and is obliged, therefore, to diabolise the other parts.

There is a defiance of self, and the most intense expression of this includes many kinds of asceticism. Some people feel such a strong need to exert their power and love of control that, when they can't find other outlets, or because they’ve never succeeded in other ways, they end up focusing on dominating certain aspects of their own nature—parts or levels of themselves. Many thinkers admit to beliefs that clearly do nothing to enhance their reputation; some actively invite the disdain of others when they could easily stay respected by remaining silent; others contradict their previous opinions and don’t mind being labeled inconsistent—in fact, they often seek this out, acting like reckless[Pg 140] riders who prefer a horse when it's wild, unmanageable, and covered in sweat. Similarly, people tackle dangerous trails up the steepest mountains to mock their own fear and trembling legs; philosophers admit to views on asceticism, humility, and holiness that expose their own image in the worst light. This self-suppression, this disdain for one’s own nature, this spernere se sperm, which religion has emphasized so much, is really a high form of vanity. The entire message of the Sermon on the Mount fits here; people genuinely enjoy inflicting pain on themselves with these lofty demands, then idolize these tyrannical requirements of their own souls. In every form of ascetic morality, individuals end up worshiping one part of themselves as a God, which leads them to demonize the other parts.

138.

138.

Man is not equally moral at all hours, this is well known. If his morality is judged to be the capability for great self-sacrificing resolutions and self-denial (which, when continuous and grown habitual, are called holiness), he is most moral in the passions; the higher emotion provides him with entirely new motives, of which he, sober and cold as usual, perhaps does not even believe himself capable. How does this happen? Probably because of the proximity of everything great and highly exciting; if man is once wrought up[Pg 141] to a state of extraordinary suspense, he is as capable of carrying out a terrible revenge as of a terrible crushing of his need for revenge. Under the influence of powerful emotion, he desires in any case the great, the powerful, the immense; and if he happens to notice that the sacrifice of himself satisfies him as well as, or better than, the sacrifice of others, he chooses that. Actually, therefore, he only cares about discharging his emotion; in order to ease his tension he seizes the enemy's spears and buries them in his breast. That there was something great in self-denial and not in revenge had to be taught to mankind by long habit; a Godhead that sacrificed itself was the strongest, most effective symbol of this kind of greatness. As the conquest of the most difficult enemy, the sudden mastering of an affection—thus this denial appears; and so far it passes for the summit of morality. In reality it is a question of the confusion of one idea with another, while the temperament maintains an equal height, an equal level. Temperate men who are resting from their passions no longer understand the morality of those moments; but the general admiration of those who had the same experiences upholds them; pride is their consolation when affection and the understanding of their deed vanish. Therefore, at bottom even those actions of self-denial are not moral, inasmuch as they are not done strictly with regard to others; rather the other only provides the highly-strung temperament with an opportunity of relieving itself through that denial.

It's well known that people aren't moral all the time. If we define morality as the ability to make self-sacrificial choices and practice self-denial (which, when done consistently and becomes a habit, is called holiness), then people are most moral during intense emotional moments; high emotions give them completely new motivations that, when they’re calm and rational, they might doubt they're even capable of. How does this happen? Probably because they're close to everything intense and exciting; once someone is caught up in deep emotion, they're just as capable of enacting a harsh revenge as they are of suppressing their desire for revenge. Under powerful emotions, they seek greatness, power, and enormity; if they notice that sacrificing themselves satisfies them just as much, or even more than sacrificing others, they will choose that. In reality, what they care about is relieving their emotions; to alleviate their tension, they take the enemy's weapons and turn them against themselves. The idea that there is something noble in self-denial, as opposed to revenge, required a long-standing belief to be ingrained in humanity; a God who sacrifices itself serves as the strongest symbol of this kind of nobility. This denial is seen as a triumph over the toughest adversary, a sudden mastery over emotion, and is considered the peak of morality. However, this is really just a mix-up of two ideas, while the person's temperament stays at the same level. Those who are calm and resting from their passions often don’t grasp the morality of those intense moments; however, the admiration from others who have had similar experiences keeps that morality alive; their pride becomes their comfort when emotion and understanding of their actions fade. Thus, at its core, even those self-denying actions aren't moral, as they're not genuinely aimed at benefiting others; rather, the other person merely gives an excuse for the highly charged temperament to find relief through that denial.

139.

139.

In many respects the ascetic seeks to make life easy for himself, usually by complete subordination to a strange will or a comprehensive law and ritual; something like the way a Brahmin leaves nothing whatever to his own decision but refers every moment to holy precepts. This submission is a powerful means of attaining self-mastery: man is occupied and is therefore not bored, and yet has no incitement to self-will or passion; after a completed deed there is no feeling of responsibility and with it no tortures of remorse. We have renounced our own will once and for ever, and this is easier than only renouncing it occasionally; as it is also easier to give up a desire entirely than to keep it within bounds. When we remember the present relation of man to the State, we find that, even here, unconditional obedience is more convenient than conditional. The saint, therefore, makes his life easier by absolute renunciation of his personality, and we are mistaken if in that phenomenon we admire the loftiest heroism of morality. In any case it is more difficult to carry one's personality through without vacillation and unclearness than to liberate one's self from it in the above-mentioned manner; moreover, it requires far more spirit and consideration.

In many ways, an ascetic aims to simplify life for themselves, typically by fully submitting to an external will or a strict set of laws and rituals, similar to how a Brahmin doesn't make personal decisions but instead follows sacred teachings in every moment. This submission serves as a strong way to gain self-control: a person remains engaged and therefore avoids boredom, while also having no urges for self-indulgence or intense emotions; once an action is completed, there's no sense of responsibility and consequently no painful feelings of regret. We have completely given up our own will, which is easier than just doing it sometimes; it's also easier to completely let go of a desire than to try and keep it under control. When we think about the current relationship between individuals and the State, we see that, even here, total obedience is easier than partial obedience. Thus, a saint makes life simpler by fully renouncing their individuality, and we are mistaken if we see this as the highest form of moral heroism. Ultimately, it's more challenging to maintain one's individuality clearly and consistently than to free oneself from it in this way; additionally, it takes much more spirit and thoughtfulness.

140.

140.

After having found in many of the less easily explicable actions manifestations of that pleasure[Pg 143] in emotion per se, I should like to recognise also in self-contempt, which is one of the signs of holiness, and likewise in the deeds of self-torture (through hunger and scourging, mutilation of limbs, feigning of madness) a means by which those natures fight against the general weariness of their life-will (their nerves); they employ the most painful irritants and cruelties in order to emerge for a time, at all events, from that dulness and boredom into which they so frequently sink through their great mental indolence and that submission to a strange will already described.

After seeing many of the less easily explained actions reveal a sense of pleasure[Pg 143] in emotion itself, I also want to acknowledge self-contempt, which is one of the signs of holiness, and the acts of self-torture (like fasting, whipping, mutilating limbs, or pretending to be insane) as ways for those individuals to combat the general weariness of their life-will (their nerves); they use the most painful irritants and hardships to escape, even if just for a while, from the dullness and boredom they often experience due to their significant mental laziness and their submission to an external will, as previously described.

141.

141.

The commonest means which the ascetic and saint employs to render life still endurable and amusing consists in occasional warfare with alternate victory and defeat. For this he requires an opponent, and finds it in the so-called "inward enemy." He principally makes use of his inclination to vanity, love of honour and rule, and of his sensual desires, that he may be permitted to regard his life as a perpetual battle and himself as a battlefield upon which good and evil spirits strive with alternating success. It is well known that sensual imagination is moderated, indeed almost dispelled, by regular sexual intercourse, whereas, on the contrary, it is rendered unfettered and wild by abstinence or irregularity. The imagination of many Christian saints was filthy to an extraordinary degree; by virtue of those theories that these desires were actual demons raging within[Pg 144] them they did not feel themselves to be too responsible; to this feeling we owe the very instructive frankness of their self-confessions. It was to their interest that this strife should always be maintained in one degree or another, because, as we have already said, their empty life was thereby entertained. But in order that the strife might seem sufficiently important and arouse the enduring sympathy and admiration of non-saints, it was necessary that sensuality should be ever more reviled and branded, the danger of eternal damnation was so tightly bound up with these things that it is highly probable that for whole centuries Christians generated children with a bad conscience, wherewith humanity has certainly suffered a great injury. And yet here truth is all topsy-turvy, which is particularly unsuitable for truth. Certainly Christianity had said that every man is conceived and born in sin, and in the insupportable superlative-Christianity of Calderon this thought again appears, tied up and twisted, as the most distorted paradox there is, in the well-known lines—

The most common way that ascetics and saints cope with life, making it bearable and even entertaining, is by engaging in a constant struggle marked by victories and defeats. For this, they need an opponent, which they identify as the "inner enemy." They mainly battle against their tendencies toward vanity, the desire for honor and authority, and their sensual urges, viewing their lives as an ongoing conflict where good and evil forces compete with varying degrees of success. It's well known that regular sexual activity calms, or even nearly eliminates, sensual fantasies, while abstaining or experiencing irregularity makes those fantasies more unrestrained and wild. Many Christian saints had incredibly impure imaginations; according to their beliefs, these desires were regarded as actual demons raging within them, allowing them to feel less accountable for their thoughts. This mindset explains the candidness of their self-assessments. It benefitted them to keep this inner conflict alive to some degree since, as noted earlier, it provided entertainment for their otherwise empty lives. However, to ensure that this struggle appeared significant enough to earn the lasting sympathy and admiration of non-saints, it was crucial to continue denouncing and shaming sensuality. The threat of eternal damnation was so intricately linked to these desires that it's likely that for centuries, Christians have brought children into the world with a sense of guilt, inflicting great harm on humanity. Yet, in this matter, truth is entirely skewed, which is especially inappropriate for truth. Certainly, Christianity teaches that every person is conceived and born in sin, and in Calderon’s extreme version of Christianity, this idea reappears, twisted in the most absurd way, in the well-known lines—

"The greatest sin of man
Is that he was ever born."

"The biggest sin of humanity
Is that we were ever born."

In all pessimistic religions the act of generation was looked upon as evil in itself. This is by no means the verdict of all mankind, not even of all pessimists. For instance, Empedocles saw in all erotic things nothing shameful, diabolical, or, sinful; but rather, in the great plain of disaster he saw only one hopeful and redeeming figure, that[Pg 145] of Aphrodite; she appeared to him as a guarantee that the strife should not endure eternally, but that the sceptre should one day be given over to a gentler dæmon. The actual Christian pessimists had, as has been said, an interest in the dominance of a diverse opinion; for the solitude and spiritual wilderness of their lives they required an ever living enemy, and a generally recognised enemy, through whose fighting and overcoming they could constantly represent themselves to the non-saints as incomprehensible, half—supernatural beings. But when at last this enemy took to flight for ever in consequence of their mode of life and their impaired health, they immediately understood how to populate their interior with new dæmons. The rising and falling of the scales of pride and humility sustained their brooding minds as well as the alternations of desire and peace of soul. At that time psychology served not only to cast suspicion upon everything human, but to oppress, to scourge, to crucify; people wished to find themselves as bad and wicked as possible, they sought anxiety for the salvation of their souls, despair of their own strength. Everything natural with which man has connected the idea of evil and sin (as, for instance, he is still accustomed to do with regard to the erotic) troubles and clouds the imagination, causes a frightened glance, makes man quarrel with himself and uncertain and distrustful of himself. Even his dreams have the flavour of a restless conscience. And yet in the reality of things this suffering from what is natural is entirely without foundation, it is only the[Pg 146] consequence of opinions about things. It is easily seen how men grow worse by considering the inevitably-natural as bad, and afterwards always feeling themselves made thus. It is the trump-card of religion and metaphysics, which wish to have man evil and sinful by nature, to cast suspicion on nature and thus really to make him bad, for he learns to feel himself evil since he cannot divest himself of the clothing of nature. After living for long a natural life, he gradually comes to feel himself weighed down by such a burden of sin that supernatural powers are necessary to lift this burden, and therewith arises the so-called need of redemption, which corresponds to no real but only to an imaginary sinfulness. If we survey the separate moral demands of the earliest times of Christianity it will everywhere be found that requirements are exaggerated in order that man cannot satisfy them; the intention is not that he should become more moral, but that he should feel himself as sinful as possible. If man had not found this feeling agreeable—why would he have thought out such an idea and stuck to it so long? As in the antique world an immeasurable power of intellect and inventiveness was expended in multiplying the pleasure of life by festive cults, so also in the age of Christianity an immeasurable amount of intellect has been sacrificed to another endeavour,—man must by all means be made to feel himself sinful and thereby be excited, enlivened, en-souled. To excite, enliven, en-soul at all costs—is not that the watchword of a relaxed, over-ripe, over-cultured age? The range[Pg 147] of all natural sensations had been gone over a hundred times, the soul had grown weary, whereupon the saint and the ascetic invented a new species of stimulants for life. They presented themselves before the public eye, not exactly as an example for the many, but as a terrible and yet ravishing spectacle, which took place on that border-land between world and over-world, wherein at that time all people believed they saw now rays of heavenly light and now unholy tongues of flame glowing in the depths. The saint's eye, fixed upon the terrible meaning of this short earthly life, upon the nearness of the last decision concerning endless new spans of existence, this burning eye in a half-wasted body made men of the old world tremble to their very depths; to gaze, to turn shudderingly away, to feel anew the attraction of the spectacle and to give way to it, to drink deep of it till the soul quivered with fire and ague,—that was the last pleasure that antiquity invented after it had grown blunted even at the sight of beast-baitings and human combats.

In all pessimistic religions, the act of reproduction was seen as inherently evil. However, this is not the perspective of all people, nor even all pessimists. For example, Empedocles viewed all erotic matters as neither shameful, diabolical, nor sinful; instead, in the vast landscape of suffering, he recognized one hopeful and redeeming figure, that of Aphrodite; to him, she symbolized the promise that conflict would not last forever, and that one day, power would be handed over to a gentler spirit. The actual Christian pessimists, as previously mentioned, had an interest in the acceptance of a variety of opinions; for their isolated and spiritually barren lives, they needed a constant, living adversary—an enemy they could identify with to portray themselves to others as incomprehensible, almost supernatural beings. However, when this enemy eventually retreated permanently due to their lifestyle and declining health, they quickly learned to fill their inner world with new spirits. The fluctuating dynamics of pride and humility nourished their brooding minds, as did the shifts between desire and inner peace. During this period, psychology not only cast doubt on all things human but also served to oppress, punish, and crucify; people wanted to perceive themselves as as bad and wicked as possible, seeking anxiety for the sake of their souls and despairing of their own strength. Everything natural that humans associated with the idea of evil and sin—like what they still associate with eroticism—disturbs and clouds the imagination, prompting fear, leading them to argue with themselves, and becoming insecure and distrustful. Even their dreams reflected a restless conscience. Yet, in reality, this suffering from what is natural has no basis, it is merely the result of opinions about things. It is apparent how people become worse by labeling the inevitably natural as evil and then always feeling that they have become so. This is the trump card of religion and metaphysics, which try to convince man that he is evil and sinful by nature, casting suspicion on nature and consequently making him feel bad, as he cannot strip away the essence of his nature. After living a natural life for a long time, he increasingly feels burdened by sin to such an extent that he believes he needs supernatural powers to relieve this weight, leading to the so-called need for redemption that corresponds to an imagined sinfulness rather than a real one. If we consider the separate moral demands from the earliest times of Christianity, we see that the expectations are exaggerated so that man cannot meet them; the goal is not to make him more moral, but instead to make him feel as sinful as possible. If man did not find this feeling agreeable, why would he have devised such an idea and adhered to it for so long? Just as in the ancient world, where immense intellectual effort was expended to enhance life's pleasure through festive rituals, in the Christian era, a remarkable amount of intellect has been dedicated to another goal—man must be made to feel sinful and thus be stirred, invigorated, and enlivened. To excite, invigorate, and enliven at all costs—isn’t that the motto of an exhausted, overripe, overly cultured age? The spectrum of all natural sensations had been explored a hundred times, the soul had grown weary, prompting the saint and the ascetic to create new forms of life stimulants. They presented themselves not exactly as models for the masses, but as a terrifying yet captivating spectacle, occurring in the borderland between the mundane and the divine, where at that time, everyone believed they could see rays of heavenly light and unholy flames flickering in the depths. The saint's gaze, focused on the dire significance of this brief earthly existence, on the immediacy of the ultimate judgment concerning endless spans of life, this intense gaze from a partially withered body, made people from the old world tremble to their core; to look, to turn away in horror, to feel the allure of the spectacle and yield to it, to immerse themselves in it until their souls quaked with fire and chills—that was the final pleasure that antiquity conceived after it had become dulled even by the sight of animal baiting and human combat.

142.

142.

Now to sum up. That condition of soul in which the saint or embryo saint rejoiced, was composed of elements which we all know well, only that under the influence of other than religious conceptions they exhibit themselves in other colours and are then accustomed to encounter man's blame as fully as, with that decoration of religion and the ultimate meaning[Pg 148] of existence, they may reckon on receiving admiration and even worship,—might reckon, at least, in former ages. Sometimes the saint practises that defiance of himself which is a near relative of domination at any cost and gives a feeling of power even to the most lonely; sometimes his swollen sensibility leaps from the desire to let his passions have full play into the desire to overthrow them like wild horses under the mighty pressure of a proud spirit; sometimes he desires a complete cessation of all disturbing, tormenting, irritating sensations, a waking sleep, a lasting rest in the lap of a dull, animal, and plant-like indolence; sometimes he seeks strife and arouses it within himself, because boredom has shown him its yawning countenance. He scourges his self-adoration with self-contempt and cruelty, he rejoices in the wild tumult of his desires and the sharp pain of sin, even in the idea of being lost; he understands how to lay a trap for his emotions, for instance even for his keen love of ruling, so that he sinks into the most utter abasement and his tormented soul is thrown out of joint by this contrast; and finally, if he longs for visions, conversations with the dead or with divine beings, it is at bottom a rare kind of delight that he covets, perhaps that delight in which all others are united. Novalis, an authority on questions of holiness through experience and instinct, tells the whole secret with naïve joy: "It is strange enough that the association of lust, religion, and cruelty did not long ago[Pg 149] draw men's attention to their close relationship and common tendency."

Now to sum up. The state of mind in which the saint, or budding saint, takes joy is made up of elements we all recognize. However, influenced by non-religious ideas, these elements show themselves in different ways and are often met with criticism from people. With the embellishment of religion and the ultimate meaning of existence, they used to receive admiration and even worship—at least in earlier times. Sometimes the saint challenges himself in a way that is closely related to seeking power at any cost, which can give a sense of control even to the most isolated person. Other times, his heightened sensitivity shifts from wanting to fully express his passions to wanting to break free from them, like wild horses under the weight of a proud spirit. Sometimes he craves complete escape from all distressing and irritating feelings—a kind of waking sleep, a long-lasting rest in a dull, plant-like laziness. At other times, he seeks conflict and stirs it within himself because boredom has shown him its yawning face. He punishes his self-love with contempt and cruelty, revels in the chaotic clash of his desires, and feels the sharp pain of sin, even in the thought of being lost. He knows how to lure his emotions into traps, such as his strong desire to dominate, leading him into utter humiliation, while his tormented soul is thrown into turmoil by this contrast. Finally, when he yearns for visions or conversations with the dead or divine beings, it’s really an unusual kind of pleasure he seeks, perhaps one that encompasses all other pleasures. Novalis, knowledgeable on matters of holiness through experience and instinct, expresses this whole truth with innocent joy: "It is strange enough that the association of lust, religion, and cruelty did not long ago draw men's attention to their close relationship and common tendency."

143.

143.

That which gives the saint his historical value is not the thing he is, but the thing he represents in the eyes of the unsaintly. It was through the fact that errors were made about him, that the state of his soul was falsely interpreted, that men separated themselves from him as much as possible, as from something incomparable and strangely superhuman, that he acquired the extraordinary power which he exercised over the imagination of whole nations and whole ages. He did not know himself; he himself interpreted the writing of his moods, inclinations, and actions according to an art of interpretation which was as exaggerated and artificial as the spiritual interpretation of the Bible. The distorted and diseased in his nature, with its combination of intellectual poverty, evil knowledge, ruined health, and over-excited nerves, remained hidden from his own sight as well as from that of his spectators. He was not a particularly good man, and still less was he a particularly wise one; but he represented something that exceeded the human standard in goodness and wisdom. The belief in him supported the belief in the divine and miraculous, in a religious meaning of all existence, in an impending day of judgment. In the evening glory of the world's sunset, which glowed over[Pg 150] the Christian nations, the shadowy form of the saint grew to vast dimensions, it grew to such a height that even in our own age, which no longer believes in God, there are still thinkers who believe in the saint.

What gives a saint their historical significance isn't who they are, but what they represent to those who aren't saintly. Because people misunderstood him, misjudged the state of his soul, and distanced themselves from him as if he were something extraordinary and almost superhuman, he gained a remarkable influence over the imaginations of entire nations and eras. He didn't truly know himself; he interpreted his moods, desires, and actions through a lens that was as exaggerated and artificial as the spiritual interpretation of the Bible. The flawed and unhealthy aspects of his character—including his lack of intellectual depth, harmful knowledge, poor health, and overly stimulated nerves—remained hidden from both himself and those around him. He wasn't a particularly good person, nor was he especially wise; yet he represented ideals that surpassed human standards of goodness and wisdom. Faith in him bolstered belief in the divine and miraculous, in the spiritual significance of life, and in an upcoming day of reckoning. Amid the evening glow of sunset over[Pg 150] the Christian nations, the saint's shadowy figure loomed larger, reaching such heights that even in our current age, which no longer believes in God, there are still thinkers who hold onto belief in the saint.

144.

144.

It need not be said that to this description of the saint which has been made from an average of the whole species, there may be opposed many a description which could give a more agreeable impression. Certain exceptions stand out from among this species, it may be through great mildness and philanthropy, it may be through the magic of unusual energy; others are attractive in the highest degree, because certain wild ravings have poured streams of light on their whole being, as is the case, for instance, with the famous founder of Christianity, who thought he was the Son of God and therefore felt himself sinless—so that through this idea—which we must not judge too hardly because the whole antique world swarms with sons of God—he reached that same goal, that feeling of complete sinlessness, complete irresponsibility, which every one can now acquire by means of science. Neither have I mentioned the Indian saints, who stand midway between the Christian saint and the Greek philosopher, and in so far represent no pure type. Knowledge, science—such as existed then—the uplifting above other men through logical[Pg 151] discipline and training of thought, were as much fostered by the Buddhists as distinguishing signs of holiness as the same qualities in the Christian world are repressed and branded as signs of unholiness.

It goes without saying that the description of the saint based on an average of the whole group may be challenged by many other descriptions that leave a more positive impression. Certain exceptions stand out from this group, whether through remarkable kindness and compassion or through the extraordinary energy they exude; others are highly appealing because wild outbursts of inspiration have illuminated their entire existence. This is evident, for example, with the famous founder of Christianity, who believed he was the Son of God and thus felt sinless—achieving a sense of total innocence and complete freedom from guilt that anyone today can attain through science. I haven't mentioned the Indian saints, who sit between the Christian saint and the Greek philosopher and therefore don't represent a pure type. Knowledge and science—as they existed then—along with the elevation above others through logical discipline and intellectual training, were as much encouraged by Buddhists as the same traits in the Christian world were suppressed and labeled as signs of unholiness.


[1] Why harass with eternal designs a mind too weak to compass them? Why do we not, as we lie beneath a lofty plane-tree or this pine [drink while we may]? HOR., Odes III. ii. 11-14.—J.M.K.

[1] Why torment a mind that can't grasp endless plans? Why not enjoy ourselves as we relax under a tall plane tree or this pine [while we still can]? HOR., Odes III. ii. 11-14.—J.M.K.

[2] "All greatest sages of all latest ages
Will chuckle and slily agree,
'Tis folly to wait till a fool's empty pate
Has learnt to be knowing and free:
So children of wisdom, make use of the fools
And use them whenever you can as your tools."—J.M.K.

[2] "All the greatest thinkers of the most recent times
Will laugh and nod in agreement,
It's foolish to wait until a fool's empty head
Has learned how to be wise and free:
So wise people, make use of the fools
And use them whenever you can as your tools."—J.M.K.

[3] It may be remembered that the cross was the gallows of the ancient world.—J.M.K.

[3] It's worth noting that the cross was the execution method of the ancient world.—J.M.K.

[4] This may give us one of the reasons for the religiosity still happily prevailing in England and the United States.—J.M.K.

[4] This might explain one of the reasons for the ongoing religiosity that remains strong in England and the United States.—J.M.K.


FOURTH DIVISION.

CONCERNING THE SOUL OF ARTISTS AND AUTHORS.

145.

145.

The Perfect Should Not Have Grown.—With regard to everything that is perfect we are accustomed to omit the question as to how perfection has been acquired, and we only rejoice in the present as if it had sprung out of the ground by magic. Probably with regard to this matter we are still under the effects of an ancient mythological feeling. It still almost seems to us (in such a Greek temple, for instance, as that of Pæstum) as if one morning a god in sport had built his dwelling of such enormous masses, at other times it seems as if his spirit had suddenly entered into a stone and now desired to speak through it. The artist knows that his work is only fully effective if it arouses the belief in an improvisation, in a marvellous instantaneousness of origin; and thus he assists this illusion and introduces into art those elements of inspired unrest, of blindly groping disorder, of listening dreaming at the beginning of creation, as a means of deception, in order so to influence the soul of the spectator or hearer that it may[Pg 154] believe in the sudden appearance of the perfect. It is the business of the science of art to contradict this illusion most decidedly, and to show up the mistakes and pampering of the intellect, by means of which it falls into the artist's trap.

The Perfect Shouldn't Have Grown.—When it comes to anything perfect, we tend to skip over the question of how that perfection came to be, and we simply celebrate the present as if it appeared out of nowhere, like magic. We might still be influenced by an ancient mythological mindset. It almost feels to us (like in a Greek temple, for example, such as that of Pæstum) as if one morning a god playfully constructed his home from massive stones, and at other times it seems like his spirit just suddenly inhabited a stone and now wants to communicate through it. The artist knows that their work is most impactful when it evokes the belief in improvisation, in a miraculous immediacy of origin; and so they nurture this illusion, incorporating elements of inspired chaos, blind searching, and attentive dreaming at the dawn of creation as a trick to influence the viewer's or listener's soul into believing in the sudden emergence of the perfect. It is the job of the science of art to strongly refute this illusion and expose the errors and indulgences of the intellect that lead it into the artist's trap.

146.

146.

The Artist's Sense of Truth.—With regard to recognition of truths, the artist has a weaker morality than the thinker; he will on no account let himself be deprived of brilliant and profound interpretations of life, and defends himself against temperate and simple methods and results. He is apparently fighting for the higher worthiness and meaning of mankind; in reality he will not renounce the most effective suppositions for his art, the fantastical, mythical, uncertain, extreme, the sense of the symbolical, the over-valuation of personality, the belief that genius is something miraculous,—he considers, therefore, the continuance of his art of creation as more important than the scientific devotion to truth in every shape, however simple this may appear.

The Artist's Perspective on Truth.—When it comes to recognizing truths, the artist has a weaker sense of morality than the thinker; he won’t let go of brilliant and deep interpretations of life, and he defends himself against straightforward and simple methods and outcomes. He seems to be fighting for the greater value and meaning of humanity; in reality, he won’t give up the most effective ideas for his art — the imaginative, mythical, uncertain, extreme, the symbolic, the overvaluation of personality, and the belief that genius is something extraordinary. He therefore sees the continuation of his artistic creation as more important than a scientific commitment to truth in any form, no matter how straightforward it may seem.

147.

147.

Art As Raiser of the Dead.—Art also fulfils the task of preservation and even of brightening up extinguished and faded memories; when it accomplishes this task it weaves a rope round the ages and causes their spirits to return. It is, certainly, only a phantom-life that results[Pg 155] therefrom, as out of graves, or like the return in dreams of our beloved dead, but for some moments, at least, the old sensation lives again and the heart beats to an almost forgotten time. Hence, for the sake of the general usefulness of art, the artist himself must be excused if he does not stand in the front rank of the enlightenment and progressive civilisation of humanity; all his life long he has remained a child or a youth, and has stood still at the point where he was overcome by his artistic impulse; the feelings of the first years of life, however, are acknowledged to be nearer to those of earlier times than to those of the present century. Unconsciously it becomes his mission to make mankind more childlike; this is his glory and his limitation.

Art as a Means to Revive the Dead.—Art also serves the purpose of preserving and even reviving extinguished and faded memories; when it does this, it weaves a connection across the ages and brings back their spirits. It is, of course, only a phantom-life that results[Pg 155] from this, like emerging from graves or the return of our beloved dead in dreams, but for a few moments, at least, the old sensations come back and the heart beats to a time almost forgotten. Thus, for the sake of the general value of art, we can forgive the artist if he doesn’t lead the way in enlightenment and the advancement of human civilization; throughout his life, he remains a child or youth, stuck at the point where his artistic impulse overcame him. The feelings from the early years of life are recognized as being closer to those of times long past than to those of the present century. Unconsciously, it becomes his mission to make humanity more childlike; this is both his honor and his limitation.

148.

148.

Poets As the Lighteners of Life.—Poets, inasmuch as they desire to lighten the life of man, either divert his gaze from the wearisome present, or assist the present to acquire new colours by means of a life which they cause to shine out of the past. To be able to do this, they must in many respects themselves be beings who are turned towards the past, so that they can be used as bridges to far distant times and ideas, to dying or dead religions and cultures. Actually they are always and of necessity epigoni. There are, however, certain drawbacks to their means of lightening life,—they appease and heal only temporarily,[Pg 156] only for the moment; they even prevent men from labouring towards a genuine improvement in their conditions, inasmuch as they remove and apply palliatives to precisely that passion of discontent that induces to action.

Poets as the Brighteners of Life.—Poets, because they want to make life easier for people, either shift attention away from the dull here and now, or help the present to take on new shades through a life they illuminate from the past. To achieve this, they often have to be individuals who look backwards, serving as bridges to distant times and ideas, to dying or extinct religions and cultures. In reality, they are always and inevitably epigoni. However, there are downsides to their method of lightening life—they only soothe and heal temporarily,[Pg 156] just for the moment; they even stop people from working towards real improvement in their situations, as they soothe and cover up exactly that feeling of discontent that drives one to take action.

149.

149.

The Slow Arrow of Beauty.—The noblest kind of beauty is that which does not transport us suddenly, which does not make stormy and intoxicating impressions (such a kind easily arouses disgust), but that which slowly filter into our minds, which we take away with us almost unnoticed, and which we encounter again in our dreams; but which, however, after having long lain modestly on our hearts, takes entire possession of us, fills our eyes with tears and our hearts with longing. What is it that we long for at the sight of beauty? We long to be beautiful, we fancy it must bring much happiness with it. But that is a mistake.

The Slow Arrow of Beauty.—The highest form of beauty is the one that doesn’t overwhelm us all at once, that doesn’t create intense and dizzying impressions (that type can easily lead to disgust). Instead, it’s the beauty that gradually seeps into our minds, which we carry with us almost without noticing, and which we encounter again in our dreams. This beauty, after quietly resting in our hearts for a long time, ultimately takes complete control of us, filling our eyes with tears and our hearts with longing. What do we yearn for when we see beauty? We desire to be beautiful, believing it must bring us a lot of happiness. But that’s a misconception.

150.

150.

The Animation of Art.—Art raises its head where creeds relax. It takes over many feelings and moods engendered by religion, lays them to its heart, and itself becomes deeper, more full of soul, so that it is capable of transmitting exultation and enthusiasm, which it previously was not able to do. The abundance of religious feelings which have grown into a stream are[Pg 157] always breaking forth again and desire to conquer new kingdoms, but the growing enlightenment has shaken the dogmas of religion and inspired a deep mistrust,—thus the feeling, thrust by enlightenment out of the religious sphere, throws itself upon art, in a few cases into political life, even straight into science. Everywhere where human endeavour wears a loftier, gloomier aspect, it may be assumed that the fear of spirits, incense, and church-shadows have remained attached to it.

Art Animation.—Art emerges where beliefs weaken. It absorbs many emotions and moods influenced by religion, embraces them, and becomes deeper and more soulful, enabling it to convey joy and passion that it couldn't express before. The wealth of religious emotions has transformed into a continuous force that constantly seeks to expand its reach, but the rise of understanding has shaken religious doctrines and sparked deep skepticism—so the feelings pushed out of the religious realm by enlightenment turn toward art, and in some cases, into political life and even directly into science. Wherever human efforts take on a more elevated, serious tone, it's likely that the fear of spirits, incense, and church shadows has lingered.

151.

151.

How Rhythm Beautifies.—Rhythm casts a veil over reality; it causes various artificialities of speech and obscurities of thought; by the shadow it throws upon thought it sometimes conceals it, and sometimes brings it into prominence. As shadow is necessary to beauty, so the "dull" is necessary to lucidity. Art makes the aspect of life endurable by throwing lover it the veil of obscure thought.

How Rhythm Enhances Beauty.—Rhythm creates a filter for reality; it introduces certain artificial elements in speech and obscurities in thought; by casting a shadow over thought, it can either hide it or highlight it. Just as shadow enhances beauty, the "dull" aspect is essential for clarity. Art makes life more bearable by covering it with the veil of complex thought.

152.

152.

The Art of the Ugly Soul.—Art is confined within too narrow limits if it be required that only the orderly, respectable, well-behaved soul should be allowed to express itself therein. As in the plastic arts, so also in music and poetry: there is an art of the ugly soul side by side with the art of the beautiful soul; and the mightiest effects of art, the crushing of souls,[Pg 158] moving of stones and humanising of beasts, have perhaps been best achieved precisely by that art.

The Art of the Ugly Soul.—Art becomes too limited if we only allow orderly, respectable, and well-behaved expressions. Just like in visual arts, there’s an art of the ugly soul alongside the art of the beautiful soul. In fact, some of the most powerful effects of art—the breaking of souls,[Pg 158] the moving of stones, and the humanizing of beasts—might have been achieved best through that very art.

153.

153.

Art Makes Heavy the Heart of the Thinker.—How strong metaphysical need is and how difficult nature renders our departure from it may be seen from the fact that even in the free spirit, when he has cast off everything metaphysical, the loftiest effects of art can easily produce a resounding of the long silent, even broken, metaphysical string,—it may be, for instance, that at a passage in Beethoven's Ninth Symphony he feels himself floating above the earth in a starry dome with the dream of immortality in his heart; all the stars seem to shine round him, and the earth to sink farther and farther away.—If he becomes conscious of this state, he feels a deep pain at his heart, and sighs for the man who will lead back to him his lost darling, be it called religion or metaphysics. In such moments his intellectual character is put to the test.

Art Weighs Down the Heart of the Thinker.—The strong need for metaphysics and how hard it is to escape it can be seen in the fact that even a free spirit, who has let go of all metaphysical ideas, can still be deeply moved by the greatest works of art. For example, when listening to a part of Beethoven's Ninth Symphony, he might feel as if he's floating in a starry sky with the hope of immortality in his heart; the stars seem to shine around him while the earth fades further away. If he becomes aware of this feeling, he experiences a deep ache in his heart and longs for someone to bring back his lost love, whether that’s called religion or metaphysics. In these moments, his intellectual character is challenged.

154.

154.

Playing With Life.—The lightness and frivolity of the Homeric imagination was necessary to calm and occasionally to raise the immoderately passionate temperament and acute intellect of the Greeks. If their intellect speaks, how harsh and cruel does life then appear! They do not deceive themselves, but they intentionally weave lies round[Pg 159] life. Simonides advised his countrymen to look upon life as a game; earnestness was too well-known to them as pain (the gods so gladly hear the misery of mankind made the theme of song), and they knew that through art alone misery might be turned into pleasure. As a punishment for this insight, however, they were so plagued with the love of romancing that it was difficult for them in everyday life to keep themselves free from falsehood and deceit; for all poetic nations have such a love of falsehood, and yet are innocent withal. Probably this occasionally drove the neighbouring nations to desperation.

Living Life to the Fullest.—The carefree and whimsical nature of the Homeric imagination was essential to soothe and sometimes elevate the intense passions and sharp intellect of the Greeks. When their intellect speaks, how harsh and cruel does life seem! They are not deceiving themselves; instead, they deliberately weave lies around[Pg 159] life. Simonides advised his fellow countrymen to view life as a game; seriousness was too familiar to them as pain (the gods gladly listen to the suffering of humanity as the subject of songs), and they realized that only through art could misery be transformed into joy. However, as a consequence of this understanding, they became so consumed with the love of storytelling that it was hard for them to remain truthful and free from deceit in their everyday lives; for all poetic cultures have this fondness for falsehood, yet they remain innocent. This probably drove neighboring nations to despair at times.

155.

155.

The Belief in Inspiration.—It is to the interest of the artist that there should be a belief in sudden suggestions, so-called inspirations; as if the idea of a work of art, of poetry, the fundamental thought of a philosophy shone down from heaven like a ray of grace. In reality the imagination of the good artist or thinker constantly produces good, mediocre, and bad, but his judgment, most clear and practised, rejects and chooses and joins together, just as we now learn from Beethoven's notebooks that he gradually composed the most beautiful melodies, and in a manner selected them, from many different attempts. He who makes less severe distinctions, and willingly abandons himself to imitative memories, may under certain circumstances become a great improvisatore; but artistic improvisation[Pg 160] ranks low in comparison with serious and laboriously chosen artistic thoughts. All great men were great workers, unwearied not only in invention but also in rejection, reviewing, transforming, and arranging.

The Belief in Inspiration.—Artists benefit from the belief in sudden flashes of inspiration, as if the concept for a piece of art, poetry, or deep philosophical thought comes down from above like a blessing. In reality, the imagination of a skilled artist or thinker consistently generates good, mediocre, and poor ideas, but their judgment, which is sharp and well-practiced, filters out and selects the best ideas. For example, we see from Beethoven's notebooks that he gradually crafted his most beautiful melodies, choosing them from many different tries. Those who blur these distinctions and allow themselves to be guided by imitative memories can, under certain conditions, become impressive improvisers; however, artistic improvisation[Pg 160] pales in comparison to serious, carefully chosen artistic ideas. All great individuals were hard workers, tirelessly engaged not just in creating but also in eliminating, reviewing, transforming, and organizing their thoughts.

156.

156.

Inspiration Again.—If the productive power has been suspended for a length of time, and has been hindered in its outflow by some obstacle, there comes at last such a sudden out-pouring, as if an immediate inspiration were taking place without previous inward working, consequently a miracle. This constitutes the familiar deception, in the continuance of which, as we have said, the interest of all artists is rather too much concerned. The capital has only accumulated, it has not suddenly fallen down from heaven. Moreover, such apparent inspirations are seen elsewhere, for instance in the realm of goodness, of virtue and of vice.

Inspiration Again.—If someone's creative ability has been on hold for a while and has been blocked by some obstacle, there eventually comes a sudden surge, as if a spontaneous inspiration is happening without any prior inner effort, resulting in what seems like a miracle. This creates the common illusion that we’ve mentioned, in which the interest of all artists is perhaps overly invested. The talent has only built up, it hasn’t suddenly dropped down from the skies. Additionally, these kinds of apparent inspirations can also be seen in other areas, such as in goodness, virtue, and vice.

157.

157.

The Suffering of Genius and Its Value.—The artistic genius desires to give pleasure, but if his mind is on a very high plane he does not easily find any one to share his pleasure; he offers entertainment but nobody accepts it. This gives him, in certain circumstances, a comically touching pathos; for he has really no right to force pleasure on men. He pipes, but none will dance: can that be tragic? Perhaps.—As compensation for this deprivation, however, he finds more pleasure in[Pg 161] creating than the rest of mankind experiences in all other species of activity. His sufferings are considered as exaggerated, because the sound of his complaints is louder and his tongue more eloquent; and yet sometimes his sufferings are really very great; but only because his ambition and his envy are so great. The learned genius, like Kepler and Spinoza, is usually not so covetous and does not make such an exhibition of his really greater sufferings and deprivations. He can reckon with greater certainty on future fame and can afford to do without the present, whilst an artist who does this always plays a desperate game that makes his heart ache. In very rare cases, when in one and the same individual are combined the genius of power and of knowledge and the moral genius, there is added to the above-mentioned pains that species of pain which must be regarded as the most curious exception in the world; those extra- and super-personal sensations which are experienced on behalf of a nation, of humanity, of all civilisation, all suffering existence, which acquire their value through the connection with particularly difficult and remote perceptions (pity in itself is worth but little). But what standard, what proof is there for its genuineness? Is it not almost imperative to be mistrustful of all who talk of feeling sensations of this kind?

The Pain of Genius and Its Worth.—An artistic genius wants to bring joy, but if his thoughts soar to a high level, he often struggles to find anyone who can appreciate that joy; he puts on a show, but nobody shows up. This creates a bittersweet comedy for him because he has no right to impose his joy on others. He plays a tune, but no one dances: can that be tragic? Maybe.—As a trade-off for this loneliness, he finds more joy in[Pg 161] creating than most people do in any other activities. His pain is often seen as exaggerated because his complaints are louder and more eloquent; however, sometimes his suffering is genuinely intense, but usually only because his ambitions and envy run deep. The intellectual genius, like Kepler and Spinoza, is generally less greedy and tends not to showcase the even greater struggles and losses he faces. He can be more certain of future recognition and can manage without immediate rewards, while an artist who does the same gambles desperately, which causes heartache. In very rare cases, when an individual possesses the genius of power, knowledge, and moral insight, the previously mentioned pains are accompanied by a unique type of suffering; those extra and super-personal sensations felt on behalf of a nation, humanity, or all of civilization, which gain significance through connections with especially challenging and distant perceptions (after all, pity in itself doesn’t hold much value). But what benchmark, what proof is there for its authenticity? Isn’t it almost necessary to be wary of anyone who claims to feel sensations like this?

158.

158.

The Destiny of Greatness.—Every great phenomenon is followed by degeneration, especially[Pg 162] in the world of art. The example of the great tempts vainer natures to superficial imitation or exaggeration; all great gifts have the fatality of crushing many weaker forces and germs, and of laying waste all nature around them. The happiest arrangement in the development of an art is for several geniuses mutually to hold one another within bounds; in this strife it generally happens that light and air are also granted to the weaker and more delicate natures.

The Path to Greatness.—Every major phenomenon is eventually followed by a decline, especially[Pg 162] in the art world. The presence of greatness often tempts less capable individuals to imitate superficially or exaggerate. All significant talents have the tendency to overpower many weaker forces and ideas and can devastate the surrounding environment. The best situation for the evolution of an art form is when several geniuses keep each other in check; through this competition, it's common for the weaker and more sensitive talents to also receive their share of support and opportunity.

159.

159.

Art Dangerous For the Artist.—When art takes strong hold of an individual it draws him back to the contemplation of those times when art flourished best, and it has then a retrograde effect. The artist grows more and more to reverence sudden inspirations; he believes in gods and dæmons, he spiritualises all nature, hates science, is changeable in his moods like the ancients, and longs for an overthrow of all existing conditions which are not favourable to art, and does this with the impetuosity and unreasonableness of a child. Now, in himself, the artist is already a backward nature, because he halts at a game that belongs properly to youth and childhood; to this is added the fact that he is educated back into former times. Thus there gradually arises a fierce antagonism between him and his contemporaries, and a sad ending; according to the accounts of the ancients, Homer and Æschylus spent their last years, and died, in melancholy.

Art is Dangerous for the Artist.—When art really grips someone, it pulls them back to times when art was at its peak, causing them to regress. The artist starts to deeply admire sudden bursts of inspiration; they believe in gods and spirits, see a spiritual essence in everything, despise science, fluctuate in their emotions like the ancients, and yearn for a complete change of all current conditions that aren't supportive of art, approaching this with the impulsiveness and irrationality of a child. In essence, the artist is already outdated, clinging to a pursuit that truly belongs to youth and childhood; on top of that, they are often educated to think of the past. This creates a growing conflict between them and their peers, often leading to a sorrowful conclusion; according to ancient accounts, both Homer and Æschylus spent their final years in despair and died filled with sorrow.

160.

160.

Created Individuals.—When it is said that the dramatist (and the artist above all) creates real characters, it is a fine deception and exaggeration, in the existence and propagation of which art celebrates one of its unconscious but at the same time abundant triumphs. As a matter of fact, we do not understand much about a real, living man, and we generalise very superficially when we ascribe to him this and that character; this very imperfect attitude of ours towards man is represented by the poet, inasmuch as he makes into men (in this sense "creates") outlines as superficial as our knowledge of man is superficial. There is a great deal of delusion about these created characters of artists; they are by no means living productions of nature, but are like painted men, somewhat too thin, they will not bear a close inspection. And when it is said that the character of the ordinary living being contradicts itself frequently, and that the one created by the dramatist is the original model conceived by nature, this is quite wrong. A genuine man is something absolutely necessary (even in those so-called contradictions), but we do not always recognise this necessity. The imaginary man, the phantasm, signifies something necessary, but only to those who understand a real man only in a crude, unnatural simplification, so that a few strong, oft-repeated traits, with a great deal of light and shade and half-light about them, amply satisfy their notions. They are, therefore, ready to treat the phantasm as a genuine, necessary[Pg 164] man, because with real men they are accustomed to regard a phantasm, an outline, an intentional abbreviation as the whole. That the painter and the sculptor express the "idea" of man is a vain imagination and delusion; whoever says this is in subjection to the eye, for this only sees the' surface, the epidermis of the human body,—the inward body, however, is equally a part of the idea. Plastic art wishes to make character visible on the surface; histrionic art employs speech for the same purpose, it reflects character in sounds. Art starts from the natural ignorance of man about his interior condition (in body and character); it is not meant for philosophers or natural scientists.

Created Individuals.—When people say that a playwright (or any artist, really) creates real characters, it’s a clever illusion and an exaggeration, signaling one of art's unconscious yet significant victories. In truth, we don’t really understand a real, living person very well, and we oversimplify when we attribute certain traits to them; this very imperfect view we have of human beings is mirrored by the poet, who turns outlines into characters that are as superficial as our own understanding. There's a lot of misunderstanding surrounding these characters created by artists; they aren't fully alive in the way nature produces them but are more like painted figures—too flat to withstand close scrutiny. And when it's claimed that the character of an ordinary person often contradicts itself while the one crafted by the playwright is the original model envisioned by nature, that's simply incorrect. A true person is something entirely necessary (even with those so-called contradictions), but we don’t always recognize this necessity. The imaginary character, the phantom, signifies something essential, but only for those who interpret a real person through a crude, unnatural lens, satisfied by a few bold, repeated traits, surrounded by light, shadow, and half-light. They tend to accept the phantom as a genuine, necessary[Pg 164] person because they tend to see a phantom, an outline, or a deliberate abbreviation as the complete picture when it comes to real people. The belief that painters and sculptors express the "idea" of a person is a misleading notion; anyone who thinks that is limited by their visual perception, which only captures the surface, the outer layer of the human body—the inner self is just as much a part of the idea. Plastic art aims to make character visible on the surface; theatrical art uses language to achieve the same goal, reflecting character through sound. Art begins with the natural ignorance people have about their inner state (both body and character); it's not intended for philosophers or scientists.

161.

161.

The Over-valuation of Self in the Belief in Artists and Philosophers.—We are all prone to think that the excellence of a work of art or of an artist is proved when it moves and touches us. But there our own excellence in judgment and sensibility must have been proved first, which is not the case. In all plastic art, who had greater power to effect a charm than Bernini, who made a greater effect than the orator that appeared after Demosthenes introduced the Asiatic style and gave it a predominance which lasted throughout two centuries? This predominance during whole centuries is not a proof of the excellence and enduring validity of a style; therefore we must not be too certain in our good opinion of any artist,—this is not only belief[Pg 165] in the truthfulness of our sensations but also in the infallibility of our judgment, whereas judgment or sensation, or even both, may be too coarse or too fine, exaggerated or crude. Neither are the blessings and blissfulness of a philosophy or of a religion proofs of its truth; just as little as the happiness which an insane person derives from his fixed idea is a proof of the reasonableness of this idea.

The Overvaluation of Self in the Belief in Artists and Philosophers.—We tend to believe that the greatness of a piece of art or an artist is confirmed when it moves us. But our own excellence in judgment and feeling must have been established first, which is often not the case. In all forms of visual art, who had a greater ability to create beauty than Bernini? Who made a bigger impact than the speaker who followed Demosthenes, who popularized the Asiatic style and maintained its dominance for two centuries? This long-standing dominance doesn’t prove the quality or lasting importance of a style; therefore, we shouldn’t be too confident in our positive opinion of any artist—this reflects not only our belief[Pg 165] in the accuracy of our feelings but also in the infallibility of our judgment, while our judgment or feelings, or even both, may be overly simplistic or overly refined, exaggerated or blunt. Similarly, the advantages and happiness derived from a philosophy or religion are not proofs of their truth; just as the joy an insane person feels from their delusion isn’t evidence of the rationality of that delusion.

162.

162.

The Cult of Genius For the Sake of Vanity.—Because we think well of ourselves, but nevertheless do not imagine that we are capable of the conception of one of Raphael's pictures or of a scene such as those of one of Shakespeare's dramas, we persuade ourselves that the faculty for doing this is quite extraordinarily wonderful, a very rare case, or, if we are religiously inclined, a grace from above. Thus the cult of genius fosters our vanity, our self-love, for it is only when we think of it as very far removed from us, as a miraculum, that it does not wound us (even Goethe, who was free from envy, called Shakespeare a star of the farthest heavens, whereby we are reminded of the line "die Sterne, die begehrt man nicht".[1]) But, apart from those suggestions of our[Pg 166] vanity, the activity of a genius does not seem so radically different from the activity of a mechanical inventor, of an astronomer or historian or strategist. All these forms of activity are explicable if we realise men whose minds are active in one special direction, who make use of everything as material, who always eagerly study their own inward life and that of others, who find types and incitements everywhere, who never weary in the employment of their means. Genius does nothing but learn how to lay stones, then to build, always to seek for material and always to work upon it. Every human activity is marvellously complicated, and not only that of genius, but it is no "miracle." Now whence comes the belief that genius is found only in artists, orators, and philosophers, that they alone have "intuition" (by which we credit them with a kind of magic glass by means of which they see straight into one's "being")? It is clear that men only speak of genius where the workings of a great intellect are most agreeable to them and they have no desire to feel envious. To call any one "divine" is as much as saying "here we have no occasion for rivalry." Thus it is that everything completed and perfect is stared at, and everything incomplete is undervalued. Now nobody can see how the work of an artist has developed; that is its advantage, for everything of which the development is seen is looked on coldly The perfected art of representation precludes all thought of its development, it tyrannises as present perfection. For this reason artists of representation are especially held to be possess[Pg 167] of genius, but not scientific men. In reality, however, the former valuation and the latter under-valuation are only puerilities of reason.

The Cult of Genius for the Sake of Vanity.—We generally think highly of ourselves, but we don't believe we could ever create something as amazing as a Raphael painting or a scene from one of Shakespeare's plays. So, we convince ourselves that the ability to do so is incredibly special, a rare gift, or, for those who are religious, a blessing from above. This belief in genius boosts our vanity and self-love, because we only see it as something far removed from us, like a miraculum, which makes us feel safe (even Goethe, who was not envious, referred to Shakespeare as a star in the farthest heavens, reminding us of the line "die Sterne, die begehrt man nicht".[1]) But aside from these glimpses of our vanity, the work of a genius doesn’t seem so fundamentally different from that of a mechanical inventor, astronomer, historian, or strategist. All these activities can be understood if we recognize people whose minds are focused in a specific direction, who utilize everything as material, who are constantly eager to examine their own lives and those of others, who spot examples and inspiration everywhere, and who tirelessly employ their resources. Genius simply learns how to place stones, then how to build, always searching for material and continuously working on it. Every human endeavor is incredibly complex, not just the work of a genius, and it’s not a "miracle." So where does the idea come from that genius is only found in artists, speakers, and philosophers, and that only they possess "intuition" (which suggests they have a kind of magical insight to see right into one's "being")? It seems that people speak of genius primarily when a great mind's work appeals to them, and they don't feel threatened by it. To label someone as "divine" implies "there's no competition here." That's why completed and perfected works are admired, while anything unfinished is undervalued. No one can see how an artist's work has developed; that's its advantage, because works whose development is visible are viewed with indifference. The perfected art of representation suggests no thought of its development; it dominates as an existing perfection. For this reason, representational artists are especially regarded as geniuses, while scientists are not. In reality, the former praise and the latter neglect are just childish attitudes of reason.

163.

163.

The Earnestness of Handicraft.—Do not talk of gifts, of inborn talents! We could mention great men of all kinds who were but little gifted. But they obtained greatness, became "geniuses" (as they are called), through qualities of the lack of which nobody who is conscious of them likes to speak. They all had that thorough earnestness for work which learns first how to form the different parts perfectly before it ventures to make a great whole; they gave themselves time for this, because they took more pleasure in doing small, accessory things well than in the effect of a dazzling whole. For instance, the recipe for becoming a good novelist is easily given, but the carrying out of the recipe presupposes qualities which we are in the habit of overlooking when we say, "I have not sufficient talent." Make a hundred or more sketches of novel-plots, none more than two pages long, but of such clearness that every word in them is necessary; write down anecdotes every day until you learn to find the most pregnant, most effective form; never weary of collecting and delineating human types and characters; above all, narrate things as often as possible and listen to narrations with a sharp eye and ear for the effect upon other people present; travel like a landscape painter and a[Pg 168] designer of costumes; take from different sciences everything that is artistically effective, if it be well represented; finally, meditate on the motives for human actions, scorn not even the smallest point of instruction on this subject, and collect similar matters by day and night. Spend some ten years in these various exercises: then the creations of your study may be allowed to see the light of day. But what do most people do, on the contrary? They do not begin with the part, but with the whole. Perhaps they make one good stroke, excite attention, and ever afterwards their work grows worse and worse, for good, natural reasons. But sometimes, when intellect and character are lacking for the formation of such an artistic career, fate and necessity take the place of these qualities and lead the future master step by step through all the phases of his craft.

The Importance of Craftsmanship.—Don’t talk about gifts or natural talents! We could point out many remarkable people who weren’t especially gifted. But they achieved greatness, became “geniuses” (as people call them), through qualities that those who are aware of them often shy away from discussing. They all had a solid dedication to their work, which involves understanding how to master the individual components before attempting to create a larger body of work; they took the time to do this because they found more joy in executing small, supporting tasks well than in the dazzling impact of a finished whole. For example, the formula for becoming a good novelist is simple, but following that formula requires qualities we tend to overlook when we say, “I don’t have enough talent.” Create a hundred or more outlines for stories, none longer than two pages, ensuring that every word is essential; write down anecdotes daily until you can discover the most meaningful and effective expressions; never tire of observing and depicting human types and characters; most importantly, narrate stories as often as you can and pay close attention to the effects on the audience; travel like a landscape artist and a[Pg 168] costume designer; draw from different fields of science anything that is artistically powerful, as long as it's well-presented; finally, reflect on the motivations behind human actions, don’t disregard even the smallest detail of instruction on this topic, and gather similar insights day and night. Spend about ten years practicing these different exercises: then, your creations can finally share the light of day. But what do most people do instead? They start with the whole rather than the parts. Perhaps they produce one exceptional piece that grabs attention, and from then on, their work declines for understandable reasons. However, sometimes, when there’s a lack of intellect and character necessary for forming an artistic career, fate and necessity step in to guide the future master through all the stages of their craft.

164.

164.

The Danger and the Gain in the Cult of Genius.—The belief in great, superior, fertile minds is not necessarily, but still very frequently, connected with that wholly or partly religious superstition that those spirits are of superhuman origin and possess certain marvellous faculties, by means of which they obtained their knowledge in ways quite different from the rest of mankind. They are credited with having an immediate insight into the nature of the world, through a peep-hole in the mantle of the phenomenon as it were, and it is believed that, without the[Pg 169] trouble and severity of science, by virtue of this marvellous prophetic sight, they could impart something final and decisive about mankind and the world. So long as there are still believers in miracles in the world of knowledge it may perhaps be admitted that the believers themselves derive a benefit therefrom, inasmuch as by their absolute subjection to great minds they obtain the best discipline and schooling for their own minds during the period of development. On the other hand, it may at least be questioned whether the superstition of genius, of its privileges and special faculties, is useful for a genius himself when it implants itself in him. In any case it is a dangerous sign when man shudders at his own self, be it that famous Cæsarian shudder or the shudder of genius which applies to this case, when the incense of sacrifice, which by rights is offered to a God alone, penetrates into the brain of the genius, so that he begins to waver and to look upon himself as something superhuman. The slow consequences are: the feeling of irresponsibility, the exceptional rights, the belief that mere intercourse with him confers a favour, and frantic rage at any attempt to compare him with others or even to place him below them and to bring into prominence whatever is unsuccessful in his work. Through the fact that he ceases to criticise himself one pinion after another falls out of his plumage,—that superstition undermines the foundation of his strength and even makes him a hypocrite after his power has failed him.[Pg 170] For great minds it is, therefore, perhaps better when they come to an understanding about their strength and its source, when they comprehend what purely human qualities are mingled in them, what a combination they are of fortunate conditions: thus once it was continual energy, a decided application to individual aims, great personal courage, and then the good fortune of an education, which at an early period provided the best teachers, examples, and methods. Assuredly, if its aim is to make the greatest possible effect, abstruseness has always done much for itself and that gift of partial insanity; for at all times that power has been admired and envied by means of which men were deprived of will and imbued with the fancy that they were preceded by supernatural leaders. Truly, men are exalted and inspired by the belief that some one among them is endowed with supernatural powers, and in this respect insanity, as Plato says, has brought the greatest blessings to mankind. In a few rare cases this form of insanity may also have been the means by which an all-round exuberant nature was kept within bounds; in individual life the imaginings of frenzy frequently exert the virtue of remedies which are poisons in themselves; but in every "genius" that believes in his own divinity the poison shows itself at last in the same proportion as the "genius" grows old; we need but recollect the example of Napoleon, for it was most assuredly through his faith in himself and his star, and through his scorn of mankind, that he[Pg 171] grew to that mighty unity which distinguished him from all modern men, until at last, however, this faith developed into an almost insane fatalism, robbed him of his quickness of comprehension and penetration, and was the cause of his downfall.

The Risks and Rewards of the Cult of Genius.—The belief in great, superior, and highly creative minds is not necessarily, but often linked to a kind of religious superstition that these individuals have superhuman origins and possess extraordinary abilities, allowing them to gain knowledge in ways that regular people cannot. They are thought to have a direct insight into the nature of the world, almost as if they have a special view into the essence of things, and it’s believed that, without the rigorous hard work of scientific inquiry, they can provide definitive truths about humanity and the world. As long as there are still people who believe in miracles in the realm of knowledge, it can be acknowledged that these believers themselves gain something from their devotion to great minds, as they receive top-notch training and education for their own intellectual development. However, it might be questioned whether the superstition surrounding genius, along with its privileges and unique abilities, is beneficial for the genius themselves when it becomes ingrained in them. It’s definitely a worrying sign when a person starts to feel uneasy about their own identity, whether it’s that famous Cæsarian sense of anxiety or the unease associated with genius, when the worship and sacrifice meant only for a deity spills over into the psyche of the genius, causing them to waver and see themselves as something beyond human. The long-term effects can include a sense of irresponsibility, a belief in exceptional rights, the assumption that merely being in their presence is a privilege, and an intense anger at any comparison to others or highlighting of their failures. As they stop critiquing themselves, one by one, their strengths begin to falter—this superstition erodes the base of their power and may lead to hypocrisy once their abilities decline.[Pg 170] For great minds, it’s probably better to understand their strengths and where they come from, recognizing the purely human traits they possess and the combination of favorable circumstances that gave rise to their talents: a continuous drive, focused dedication to personal goals, immense personal bravery, and the fortunate access to a quality education that early on provided the best teachers, role models, and methods. Certainly, if the goal is to make the greatest possible impact, obscurity has often served its purpose, along with that touch of partial madness; throughout history, people have admired and envied the power that comes from becoming so engrossed in their vision that they lose their will and believe they were led by supernatural figures. Indeed, people are uplifted and inspired by the belief that someone among them possesses extraordinary abilities, and in this way, as Plato noted, madness has often been a source of great benefits for humanity. In a few rare instances, this form of madness may also help to keep a vibrant personality in check; in personal lives, the delirium of frenzy can sometimes act as remedies even though they may be toxic; but in every "genius" who believes in their own divinity, the poison ultimately reveals itself as they grow older; we need only think of Napoleon, who certainly grew into a powerful figure due to his faith in himself and his destiny, along with his contempt for humanity, which set him apart from all modern figures, until eventually this faith morphed into a nearly insane fatalism, stripping him of his sharpness of understanding and insight, leading to his downfall.

165.

165.

Genius and Nullity.—It is precisely the original artists, those who create out of their own heads, who in certain circumstances can bring forth complete emptiness and husk, whilst the more dependent natures, the so-called talented ones, are full of memories of all manner of goodness, and even in a state of weakness produce something tolerable. But if the original ones are abandoned by themselves, memory renders them no assistance; they become empty.

Genius and Nothingness.—It’s the original artists, those who come up with ideas entirely on their own, who, in certain situations, can end up producing total emptiness and hollow work. In contrast, the more dependent types, the so-called talented ones, are filled with memories of all kinds of good things and can still create something decent, even when they’re feeling weak. However, if the original artists are left on their own, their memories don’t help them; they become void.

166.

166.

The Public.—The people really demands nothing more from tragedy than to be deeply affected, in order to have a good cry occasionally; the artist, on the contrary, who sees the new tragedy, takes pleasure in the clever technical inventions and tricks, in the management and distribution of the material, in the novel arrangement of old motives and old ideas. His attitude is the æsthetic attitude towards a work of art, that of the creator; the one first described, with regard solely to the material, is that of he people. Of the individual who stands between[Pg 172] the two nothing need be said: he is neither "people" nor artist, and does not know what he wants—therefore his pleasure is also clouded and insignificant.

The Public.—People really want nothing more from tragedy than to feel something deeply, so they can have a good cry every now and then; the artist, on the other hand, who experiences the new tragedy, enjoys the clever technical tricks and methods, the way the material is arranged and presented, and the fresh take on old themes and ideas. His perspective is the aesthetic one towards a piece of art, that of the creator; the first perspective, focused solely on the content, is that of the public. As for the individual who stands between[Pg 172] the two, there's nothing more to say: he is neither "public" nor artist, and doesn’t really know what he wants—so his enjoyment is also muddled and trivial.

167.

167.

The Artistic Education of the Public.—If the same motif is not employed in a hundred ways by different masters, the public never learns to get beyond their interest in the subject; but at last, when it is well acquainted with the motif through countless different treatments, and no longer finds in it any charm of novelty or excitement, it will then begin to grasp and enjoy the various shades and delicate new inventions in its treatment.

The Artistic Education of the Public.—If the same theme isn’t used in a hundred different ways by various artists, the public never moves past their basic interest in the topic; but eventually, when they’ve become very familiar with the theme through countless different interpretations, and no longer find it exciting or fresh, they will start to appreciate the different nuances and subtle innovations in its presentation.

168.

168.

The Artist and His Followers Must Keep in Step.—The progress from one grade of style to another must be so slow that not only the artists but also the auditors and spectators can follow it and know exactly what is going on. Otherwise there will suddenly appear that great chasm between the artist, who creates his work upon a height apart, and the public, who cannot rise up to that height and finally sinks discontentedly deeper. For when the artist no longer raises his public it rapidly sinks downwards, and its fall is the deeper and more dangerous in proportion to the height to which genius has carried it, like the eagle, out of whose talons a tortoise that has been borne up into the clouds falls to its destruction.

The Artist and His Followers Need to Stay in Sync.—The shift from one style to another needs to be gradual enough that both the artists and the audience can keep up and fully understand what's happening. If not, a huge gap will form between the artist, who creates in an elevated place, and the audience, who can't reach that level and ends up feeling increasingly frustrated and left behind. When the artist stops uplifting their audience, that audience quickly falls away, and the higher they were lifted by talent, the harder their fall will be, much like a tortoise dropped from the clouds by an eagle.

169.

169.

The Source of the Comic Element.—If we consider that for many thousands of years man was an animal that was susceptible in the highest degree to fear, and that everything sudden and unexpected had to find him ready for battle, perhaps even ready for death; that even later, in social relations, all security was based on the expected, on custom in thought and action, we need not be surprised that at everything sudden and unexpected in word and deed, if it occurs without danger or injury, man becomes exuberant and passes over into the very opposite of fear—the terrified, trembling, crouching being shoots upward, stretches itself: man laughs. This transition from momentary fear into short-lived exhilaration is called the Comic. On the other hand, in the tragic phenomenon, man passes quickly from great enduring exuberance into great fear; but as amongst mortals great and lasting exuberance is much rarer than the cause for fear, there is far more comedy than tragedy in the world; we laugh much offener than we are agitated.

The Origin of the Comic Element.—If we think about how for many thousands of years humans were creatures highly sensitive to fear, and that anything sudden and unexpected made them ready to fight, or even face death; that even later, in social interactions, all security relied on what was expected, on customs in thought and behavior, we shouldn’t be surprised that when something sudden and unexpected happens, if it poses no real danger or harm, people become joyful and move from being terrified, trembling, and crouching to standing tall and laughing. This shift from brief fear to momentary joy is what we call the Comic. Conversely, in tragic situations, people quickly move from great, lasting joy into deep fear; however, since enduring joy is much rarer among humans than the things that provoke fear, there is a lot more comedy than tragedy in the world; we laugh far more often than we feel anxious.

170.

170.

The Artist's Ambition.—The Greek artists, the tragedians for instance, composed in order to conquer; their whole art cannot be imagined without rivalry,—the good Hesiodian Eris, Ambition, gave wings to their genius. This ambition further demanded that their work[Pg 174] should achieve the greatest excellence in their own eyes, as they understood excellence, without any regard for the reigning taste and the general opinion about excellence in a work of art; and thus it was long before Æschylus and Euripides achieved any success, until at last they educated judges of art, who valued their work according to the standards which they themselves appointed. Hence they strove for victory over rivals according to their own valuation, they really wished to be more excellent; they demanded assent from without to this self-valuation, the confirmation of this verdict. To achieve honour means in this case "to make one's self superior to others, and to desire that this should be recognised publicly." Should the former condition be wanting, and the latter nevertheless desired, it is then called vanity. Should the latter be lacking and not missed, then it is named pride.

The Artist's Dream.—Greek artists, like the tragedians, created to achieve greatness; their entire art form couldn’t exist without competition—the good Hesiodian Eris, Ambition, fueled their creativity. This ambition also required that their work[Pg 174] reach the highest level of excellence in their own view, as they interpreted excellence, regardless of current trends and popular opinions about what constitutes great art; it took a long time for Æschylus and Euripides to find success, until eventually they educated critics who valued their work based on the standards they set themselves. Therefore, they aimed for victory over rivals according to their own assessments, truly wanting to be superior; they sought external validation for this self-assessment, a confirmation of their judgment. In this context, achieving honor means "to elevate oneself above others and wish for that to be recognized publicly." If the first condition is missing, yet the latter is still desired, it is called vanity. If the latter is absent and not missed, it is referred to as pride.

171.

171.

What Is Needful to a Work of Art.—Those who talk so much about the needful factors of a work of art exaggerate; if they are artists they do so in majorem artis gloriam, if they are laymen, from ignorance. The form of a work of art, which gives speech to their thoughts and is, therefore, their mode of talking, is always somewhat uncertain, like all kinds of speech. The sculptor can add or omit many little traits, as can also the exponent, be he an actor or, in music, a performer or conductor. These many little traits and finishing touches afford him[Pg 175] pleasure one day and none the next, they exist more for the sake of the artist than the art; for he also has occasionally need of sweetmeats and playthings to prevent him from becoming morose with the severity and self-restraint which the representation of the dominant idea demands from him.

What Is Necessary for a Work of Art.—People who go on and on about what’s essential for a work of art tend to exaggerate; if they’re artists, they do it in majorem artis gloriam, and if they’re not, it’s usually out of ignorance. The form of a work of art, which expresses their thoughts and serves as their way of communicating, is always a bit uncertain, just like any form of communication. The sculptor can add or leave out many small details, just as an actor, musician, or conductor can. These little touches and finishing details bring them joy one day and none the next; they exist more for the artist than for the art itself, as artists sometimes need little treats and distractions to keep from getting downcast by the seriousness and discipline that conveying the main idea demands of them.

172.

172.

To Cause the Master to Be Forgotten.—The pianoforte player who executes the work of a master will have played best if he has made his audience forget the master, and if it seemed as if he were relating a story from his own life or just passing through some experience. Assuredly, if he is of no importance, every one will abhor the garrulity with which he talks about his own life. Therefore he must know how to influence his hearer's imagination favourably towards himself. Hereby are explained all the weaknesses and follies of "the virtuoso."

To Make the Master Unforgettable.—A pianist who performs a master’s work will have done their best if they manage to make the audience forget the master, as if they’re sharing a personal story or just going through an experience of their own. If the pianist isn’t skilled, everyone will dislike the way they keep talking about their own life. Therefore, they must know how to positively capture their listeners’ imagination. This explains all the flaws and quirks of "the virtuoso."

173.

173.

Corriger La Fortune.—There are unfortunate accidents in the lives of great artists, which compel the painter, for instance, to sketch out his most important picture only as a passing thought, or such as obliged Beethoven to leave behind him only the insufficient pianoforte score of many great sonatas (as in the great B flat). In these cases the artist of a later day must endeavour to fill out the life of the great man,—[Pg 176]of all orchestral effects, would call into life that symphony which has fallen into the piano-trance.

Fixing Fortune.—There are unfortunate events in the lives of great artists that force a painter, for example, to only sketch his most important work as a fleeting idea, or that caused Beethoven to leave behind only the incomplete piano score of many brilliant sonatas (like the grand B flat). In these situations, later artists must try to bring to life the legacy of these great individuals,—[Pg 176]of all orchestral sounds, would revive that symphony which has become trapped in the realm of piano.

174.

174.

Reducing.—Many things, events, or persons, cannot bear treatment on a small scale. The Laocoon group cannot be reduced to a knick-knack; great size is necessary to it. But more seldom still does anything that is naturally small bear enlargement; for which reason biographers succeed far oftener in representing a great man as small than a small one as great.

Cutting down.—Many things, events, or people can’t be treated on a small scale. The Laocoon group can’t be turned into a little trinket; it needs to be large. But even rarer is the case where something naturally small can be made larger; this is why biographers are much more likely to depict a great person as small rather than a small person as great.

175.

175.

Sensuousness in Present-day Art.—Artists nowadays frequently miscalculate when they count on the sensuous effect of their works, for their spectators or hearers have no longer a fully sensuous nature, and, quite contrary to the artist's intention, his work produces in them a "holiness" of feeling which is closely related to boredom. Their sensuousness begins, perhaps, just where that of the artist ceases; they meet, therefore, only at one point at the most.

Sensuality in Modern Art.—Artists today often get it wrong when they rely on the sensuous impact of their work, because their audience no longer has a fully sensuous nature. Instead of experiencing the intended feeling, people often find a sense of "holiness" that is closely tied to boredom. Their sensuous experience might start just where the artist's ends, so they connect at most at one single point.

176.

176.

Shakespeare As a Moralist.—Shakespeare meditated much on the passions, and on account of his temperament had probably a close acquaintance with many of them (dramatists are in general rather wicked men). He could, however[Pg 177] not talk on the subject, like Montaigne, but put his observations thereon into the mouths of impassioned figures, which is contrary to nature, certainly, but makes his dramas so rich in thought that they cause all others to seem poor in comparison and readily arouse a general aversion to them. Schiller's reflections (which are almost always based on erroneous or trivial fancies) are just theatrical Reflections, and as such are very effective; whereas Shakespeare's reflections do honour to his model, Montaigne, and contain quite serious thoughts in polished form, but on that account are too remote and refined for the eyes of the theatrical public, and are consequently ineffective.

Shakespeare as a moralist.—Shakespeare thought a lot about emotions, and because of his nature, he likely understood many of them well (dramatists are generally pretty mischievous). However, he couldn’t discuss them like Montaigne; instead, he expressed his insights through passionate characters, which is certainly contrary to nature but makes his plays so rich in ideas that they make all others seem lacking and easily evoke a general dislike for them. Schiller’s thoughts (which are almost always based on mistaken or trivial ideas) are just theatrical reflections and work very well in that context; whereas Shakespeare’s reflections honor his inspiration, Montaigne, and contain serious thoughts presented elegantly, but because of that, they are too distant and sophisticated for the average theatergoer and therefore aren’t as effective.

177.

177.

Securing a Good Hearing.—It is not sufficient to know how to play well; one must also know how to secure a good hearing. A violin in the hand of the greatest master gives only a little squeak when the place where it is heard is too large; the master may then be mistaken for any bungler.

Getting a Good Hearing.—It's not enough to just play well; you also need to know how to get a good audience. A violin played by the greatest master may only produce a faint sound in a space that's too big; the master could then be confused with any amateur.

178.

178.

The Incomplete As the Effective.—Just as figures in relief make such a strong impression on the imagination because they seem in the act of emerging from the wall and only stopped by some sudden hindrance; so the relief-like, incomplete representation of a thought, or a whole philosophy, is sometimes more effective than its exhaustive[Pg 178] amplification,—more is left for the investigation of the onlooker, he is incited to the further study of that which stands out before him in such strong light and shade; he is prompted to think out the subject, and even to overcome the hindrance which hitherto prevented it from emerging clearly.

The Incomplete as the Effective.—Just like relief sculptures make a strong impact on our imagination because they seem to be breaking free from the wall but are suddenly held back, an incomplete or relief-like representation of a concept, or an entire philosophy, can sometimes be more powerful than a thorough explanation[Pg 178]. It leaves more for the viewer to explore, encouraging them to delve deeper into what stands out in such striking contrasts of light and shadow; it prompts them to think through the topic and even tackle the barriers that have prevented it from being clearly understood.

179.

179.

Against the Eccentric.—When art arrays itself in the most shabby material it is most easily recognised as art.

Against the Unusual.—When art presents itself in the most worn-out material, it is most readily recognized as art.

180.

180.

Collective Intellect.—A good author possesses not only his own intellect, but also that of his friends.

Collective Intelligence.—A good author has not only their own intelligence but also that of their friends.

181.

181.

Different Kinds of Mistakes.—The misfortune of acute and clear authors is that people consider them as shallow and therefore do not devote any effort to them; and the good fortune of obscure writers is that the reader makes an effort to understand them and places the delight in his own zeal to their credit.

Types of Mistakes.—The downside for clear and sharp authors is that people see them as superficial and don’t bother to engage with their work; meanwhile, the upside for obscure writers is that readers put in the effort to understand them and take pride in their own enthusiasm for the writing.

182.

182.

Relation to Science.—None of the people have any real interest in a science, who only begin to be enthusiastic about it when they themselves lave made discoveries in it.

Connection to Science.—None of the people have any real interest in a science, who only begin to be enthusiastic about it when they themselves lave made discoveries in it.

183.

183.

The Key.—The single thought on which an eminent man sets a great value, arousing the derision and laughter of the masses, is for him a key to hidden treasures; for them, however, it is nothing more than a piece of old iron.

The Key.—The single idea that a prominent person values highly, which brings on the scorn and laughter of the crowds, is for them a key to hidden treasures; for the masses, though, it's just a piece of old iron.

184.

184.

Untranslatable.—It is neither the best nor the worst parts of a book which are untranslatable.

Untranslatable.—It’s not just the best or worst parts of a book that can’t be translated.

185.

185.

Authors' Paradoxes.—The so-called paradoxes of an author to which a reader objects are often not in the author's book at all, but in the reader's head.

Authors' Dilemmas.—The so-called paradoxes of an author that a reader complains about often aren’t in the author’s book at all, but in the reader’s mind.

186.

186.

WIT.—The wittiest authors produce a scarcely noticeable smile.

WIT.—The cleverest authors create a barely noticeable smile.

187.

187.

Antithesis.—Antithesis is the narrow gate through which error is fondest of sneaking to the truth.

Contrast.—Antithesis is the narrow gate through which error loves to sneak up on the truth.

188.

188.

Thinkers As Stylists.—Most thinkers write badly, because they communicate not only their thoughts, but also the thinking of them.

Thinkers as Stylists.—Most thinkers write poorly because they convey not just their ideas but also the process of thinking them through.

189.

189.

Thoughts in Poetry.—The poet conveys his thoughts ceremoniously in the vehicle of rhythm, usually because they are not able to go on foot.

Poetry Thoughts.—The poet expresses his ideas formally through rhythm, often because they can't walk on their own.

190.

190.

The Sin Against the Reader's Intellect.—When an author renounces his talent in order merely to put himself on a level with the reader, he commits the only deadly sin which the latter will never forgive, should he notice anything of it. One may say everything that is bad about a person, but in the manner in which it is said one must know how to revive his vanity anew.

The Offense Against the Reader's Intelligence.—When an author gives up their talent just to be on the same level as the reader, they commit the one unforgivable sin, should the reader pick up on it. You can say anything negative about someone, but you have to know how to stroke their ego in the way you say it.

191.

191.

The Limits of Uprightness.—Even the most upright author lets fall a word too much when he wishes to round off a period.

The Limits of Integrity.—Even the most honest writer slips and says a bit too much when trying to finish a thought.

192.

192.

The Best Author.—The best author will be he who is ashamed to become one.

Best Author.—The best author will be the one who is embarrassed to be one.

193.

193.

Draconian Law Against Authors.—One should regard authors as criminals who only obtain acquittal or mercy in the rarest cases,—that would be a remedy for books becoming too rife.

Harsh Law Against Authors.—One should see authors as criminals who only get pardoned or shown mercy in the rarest instances,—that would be a solution

194.

194.

The Fools of Modern Culture.—The fools of mediæval courts correspond to our feuilleton writers; they are the same kind of men, semi-rational, witty, extravagant, foolish, sometimes there only for the purpose of lessening the pathos of the outlook with fancies and chatter, and of drowning with their clamour the far too deep and solemn chimes of great events; they were formerly in the service of princes and nobles, now they are in the service of parties (since a large portion of the old obsequiousness in the intercourse of the people with their prince still survives in party-feeling and party-discipline). Modern literary men, however, are generally very similar to the feuilleton writers, they are the "fools of modern culture," whom one judges more leniently when one does not regard them as fully responsible beings. To look upon writing as a regular profession should justly be regarded as a form of madness.

The Fools of Today's Culture.—The fools of medieval courts are like our feuilleton writers; they’re similar types of people, half-rational, clever, extravagant, foolish, sometimes there just to lighten the serious mood with their quirks and chatter, and to drown out the significant and serious tolls of major events with their noise; they used to serve princes and nobles, and now they serve political parties (since a large part of the old servility in how people interacted with their rulers still exists in party loyalty and discipline). However, modern writers are generally very much like the feuilleton writers; they are the "fools of modern culture," who are judged more softly when we don't see them as fully accountable individuals. Thinking of writing as a regular job should rightfully be seen as a kind of madness.

195.

195.

After the Example of the Greeks.—It is a great hindrance to knowledge at present that, owing to centuries of exaggeration of feeling, all words have become vague and inflated. The higher stage of culture, which is under the sway (though not under the tyranny) of knowledge, requires great sobriety of feeling and thorough concentration of words—on which points the Greeks in the time of Demosthenes set an[Pg 182] example to us. Exaggeration is a distinguishing mark of all modern writings, and even when they are simply written the expressions therein are still felt as too eccentric. Careful reflection, conciseness, coldness, plainness, even carried intentionally to the farthest limits,—in a word, suppression of feeling and taciturnity,—these are the only remedies. For the rest, this cold manner of writing and feeling is now very attractive, as a contrast; and to be sure there is a new danger therein. For intense cold is as good a stimulus as a high degree of warmth.

After the Example of the Greeks.—Right now, a big obstacle to knowledge is that, after centuries of over-the-top emotions, all words have become vague and inflated. The advanced stage of culture, which is influenced by knowledge (but not dominated by it), needs a clear-headed approach to feeling and a precise use of words—something the Greeks during Demosthenes' time showed us well.[Pg 182] Exaggeration marks most modern writing, and even when these works are simply written, the expressions still feel too eccentric. Thoughtful reflection, brevity, emotional restraint, straightforwardness, even pushed to the extreme—essentially, suppressing emotions and being reserved—are the only solutions. On the other hand, this chilly style of writing and feeling is now appealing as a contrast, though it brings a new risk. An intense cold can be just as stimulating as a high level of warmth.

196.

196.

Good Narrators, Bad Explainers.—In good narrators there is often found an admirable psychological sureness and logicalness, as far as these qualities can be observed in the actions of their personages, in positively ludicrous contrast to their inexperienced psychological reasoning, so that their culture appears to be as extraordinarily high one moment as it seems regrettably defective the next. It happens far too frequently that they give an evidently false explanation of their own heroes and their actions,—of this there is no doubt, however improbable the thing may appear. It is quite likely that the greatest pianoforte player has thought but little about the technical conditions and the special virtues, drawbacks, usefulness, and tractability of each finger (dactylic ethics), and makes big mistakes whenever he speaks of such things.

Great Storytellers, Poor Explainers.—Good narrators often display an impressive level of psychological insight and logical reasoning, at least in how they portray their characters. This is often humorously contrasted with their lack of understanding in psychological reasoning, leading to a culture that seems incredibly sophisticated one moment and unfortunately flawed the next. It's all too common for them to provide a clearly inaccurate explanation of their own heroes and their actions—there's no doubt about this, no matter how unlikely it may seem. It’s likely that the best pianist hasn’t thought much about the technical aspects or the specific strengths, weaknesses, practicality, and control of each finger (dactylic ethics) and makes significant mistakes whenever discussing such topics.

197.

197.

The Writings of Acquaintances and Their Readers.—We read the writings of our acquaintances (friends and enemies) in a double sense, inasmuch as our perception constantly whispers, "That is something of himself, a remembrance of his inward being, his experiences, his talents," and at the same time another kind of perception endeavours to estimate the profit of the work in itself, what valuation it merits apart from its author, how far it will enrich knowledge. These two manners of reading and estimating interfere with each other, as may naturally be supposed. And a conversation with a friend will only bear good fruit of knowledge when both think only of the matter under consideration and forget that they are friends.

The Writings of Friends and Their Readers.—We read the writings of people we know (friends and foes) in two ways. One way is that our inner voice constantly reminds us, "This reflects something about him—his inner self, his experiences, his skills." The other way involves trying to judge the work on its own merits, what value it has apart from its author, and how much it contributes to our understanding. These two ways of reading often clash, as you'd expect. A discussion with a friend will only lead to real insights when both parties focus solely on the topic at hand and forget about their friendship.

198.

198.

Rhythmical Sacrifice.—Good writers alter the rhythm of many a period merely because they do not credit the general reader with the ability to comprehend the measure followed by the period in its first version; thus they make it easier for the reader, by giving the preference to the better known rhythms.. This regard for the rhythmical incapacity of the modern reader has already called forth many a sigh, for much has been sacrificed to it. Does not the same thing happen to good musicians?

Rhythmic Sacrifice.—Good writers often change the rhythm of a sentence simply because they don't think the average reader can grasp the original rhythm as it was first written. By doing this, they make it easier for the reader by sticking to more familiar rhythms. This consideration for the rhythmical limitations of today's readers has led to many complaints, as a lot has been sacrificed because of it. Doesn't the same issue occur with talented musicians?

199.

199.

The Incomplete As an Artistic Stimulus.—The incomplete is often more effective than perfection, and this is the case with eulogies. To effect their purpose a stimulating incompleteness is necessary, as an irrational element, which calls up a sea before the hearer's imagination, and, like a mist, conceals the opposite coast, i.e. the limits of the object of praise. If the well-known merits of a person are referred to and described at length and in detail, it always gives rise to the suspicion that these are his only merits. The perfect eulogist takes his stand above the person praised, he appears to overlook him. Therefore complete praise has a weakening effect.

The Incomplete as an Artistic Inspiration.—The incomplete is often more impactful than perfection, and this holds true for eulogies. To achieve their intended effect, a stimulating incompleteness is essential, serving as an irrational element that evokes a vastness in the listener's imagination and, like mist, obscures the opposite shore, i.e. the boundaries of the subject being praised. When the well-known qualities of a person are referenced and described in detail, it often raises the suspicion that these are their only qualities. The ideal eulogist positions themselves above the individual being praised, appearing to overlook them. Thus, complete praise can have a diminishing effect.

200.

200.

Precautions in Writing and Teaching.—Whoever has once written and has been seized with the passion for writing learns from almost all that he does and experiences that which is literally communicable. He thinks no longer of himself, but of the author and his public; he desires insight into things; but not for his own use. He who teaches is mostly incapable of doing anything for his own good: he is always thinking of the good of his scholars, and all knowledge delights him only in so far as he is able to teach it. He comes at last to regard himself as a medium of knowledge, and above all as a means thereto, so that he has lost all serious consideration for himself.

Writing and Teaching Precautions.—Once someone has written and been consumed by the passion for writing, they learn from almost everything they do and experience that can be shared. They no longer think about themselves, but rather about the author and their audience; they seek understanding not for personal gain. A teacher often finds it difficult to focus on their own interests; they are always considering the well-being of their students, and they only find joy in knowledge to the extent that they can share it. In the end, they come to see themselves as a channel for knowledge, primarily as a way to share it, to the point where they no longer take their own needs seriously.

201.

201.

The Necessity For Bad Authors.—There will always be a need of bad authors; for they meet the taste of readers of an undeveloped, immature age—these have their requirements as well as mature readers. If human life were of greater length, the number of mature individuals would be greater than that of the immature, or at least equally great; but, as it is, by far the greater number die too young: i.e. there are always many more undeveloped intellects with bad taste. These demand, with the greater impetuosity of youth, the satisfaction of their needs, and they insist on having bad authors.

The Need for Bad Authors.—There will always be a need for bad authors because they cater to the tastes of readers who are still developing—these readers have their own needs, just like more mature readers do. If human life were longer, there would be more mature individuals compared to those who are still immature, or at least the numbers would be equal; but as it stands, many people die too young: i.e. there are always far more underdeveloped minds with poor taste. These young readers demand, with the greater urgency of youth, to have their cravings satisfied, and they insist on having bad authors.

202.

202.

Too Near and Too Far.—The reader and the author very often do not understand each other, because the author knows his theme too well and finds it almost slow, so that he omits the examples, of which he knows hundreds; the reader, however, is interested in the subject, and is liable to consider it as badly proved if examples are lacking.

Too Close and Too Far.—The reader and the author often misunderstand each other because the author is so familiar with their topic that it seems obvious to them, leading them to skip examples they could easily provide. Meanwhile, the reader is interested in the subject and may feel it's poorly supported if examples are missing.

203.

203.

A Vanished Preparation For Art.—Of everything that was practised in public schools, the thing of greatest value was the exercise in Latin style,—this was an exercise in art, whilst all[Pg 186] other occupations aimed only at the acquirement of knowledge. It is a barbarism to put German composition before it, for there is no typical German style developed by public oratory; but if there is a desire to advance practice in thought by means of German composition, then it is certainly better for the time being to pay no attention to style, to separate the practice in thought, therefore, from the practice in reproduction. The latter should confine itself to the various modes of presenting a given subject, and should not concern itself with the independent finding of a subject. The mere presentment of given subject was the task of the Latin style, for which the old teachers possessed a long vanished delicacy of ear. Formerly, whoever learned to write well in a modern language had to thank this practice for the acquirement (now we are obliged to go to school to the older French writers). But yet more: he obtained an idea of the loftiness and difficulty of form, and was prepared for art in the only right way: by practice.

A Lost Art Preparation.—Among everything taught in public schools, the most valuable was the exercise in Latin style—this was a true art practice, while all[Pg 186] other subjects were focused solely on acquiring knowledge. It's a mistake to prioritize German composition over it, as there’s no distinct German style developed through public speaking; however, if there's a desire to enhance thinking skills through German composition, it’s definitely more effective to temporarily ignore style and separate thought practice from reproduction practice. The latter should focus on various ways to present a given topic and should not involve the independent creation of a topic. The primary task of Latin style was to present a given subject, for which the old teachers had a sense of nuance that has long since disappeared. In the past, anyone who learned to write well in a modern language owed it to this practice (now we must learn from older French writers). Moreover, it provided a sense of the elevation and complexity of form, preparing one for art in the only correct way: through practice.

204.

204.

Darkness and Over-brightness Side by Side.—Authors who, in general, do not understand how to express their thoughts clearly are fond of choosing, in detail, the strongest, most exaggerated distinctions and superlatives,—thereby is produced an effect of light, which is like torchlight in intricate forest paths.

Darkness and Brightness Side by Side.—Writers who typically struggle to convey their ideas clearly tend to focus on the most extreme, exaggerated differences and superlatives. This creates a bright effect, similar to the glare of a torch illuminating complicated trails in a dense forest.

205.

205.

Literary Painting.—An important object will be best described if the colours for the painting are taken out of the object itself, as a chemist does, and then employed like an artist, so that the drawing develops from the outlines and transitions of the colours. Thus the painting acquires something of the entrancing natural element which gives such importance to the object itself.

Literary Art.—An important subject will be best captured if the colors for the painting are drawn from the subject itself, like a chemist does, and then used like an artist, so that the drawing unfolds from the shapes and gradations of the colors. This way, the painting gains some of the captivating natural essence that makes the subject itself so significant.

206.

206.

Books Which Teach How to Dance.—There are authors who, by representing the impossible as possible, and by talking of morality and cleverness as if both were merely moods and humours assumed at will, produce a feeling of exuberant freedom, as if man stood on tiptoe and were compelled to dance from sheer, inward delight.

Books That Teach You How to Dance.—There are writers who, by making the impossible seem possible, and by discussing morality and intelligence as if they were just moods or attitudes we can adopt at will, create a sense of exhilarating freedom, as if a person is standing on tiptoes, driven to dance out of pure, inner joy.

207.

207.

Unfinished Thoughts.—Just as not only manhood, but also youth and childhood have a value per se, and are not to be looked upon merely as passages and bridges, so also unfinished thoughts have their value. For this reason we must not torment a poet with subtle explanations, but must take pleasure in the uncertainty of his horizon, as if the way to further thoughts were still open. We stand on the threshold; we wait as for the digging up of a treasure, it is as if a well of profundity were about to be discovered. The[Pg 188] poet anticipates something of the thinker's pleasure in the discovery of a leading thought, an makes us covetous, so that we give chase to it; but it flutters past our head and exhibits the loveliest butterfly-wings,—and yet it escapes us.

Incomplete Thoughts.—Just as manhood, youth, and childhood each have their own inherent value and shouldn’t be seen just as stages to get through, unfinished thoughts also hold significance. For this reason, we shouldn’t burden a poet with intricate explanations but should find joy in the ambiguity of their perspective, as if there’s still a path to new ideas. We’re on the edge, waiting for what feels like the unearthing of treasure, as if a deep well of insight is about to be found. The[Pg 188] poet hints at the pleasure that comes from discovering a key idea, making us eager to pursue it; yet it flits away just above us, showcasing its beautiful, butterfly-like wings—and still, it slips out of our grasp.

208.

208.

The Book Grown Almost Into a Human Being.—Every author is surprised anew at the way in which his book, as soon as he has sent it out, continues to live a life of its own; it seems to him as if one part of an insect had been cut off and now went on its own way. Perhaps he forgets it almost entirely, perhaps he rises above the view expressed therein, perhaps even he understands it no longer, and has lost that impulse upon which he soared at the time he conceived the book; meanwhile it seeks its readers, inflames life, pleases, horrifies, inspires new works, becomes the soul of designs and actions,—in short, it lives like a creature endowed with mind and soul, and yet is no human being. The happiest fate is that of the author who, as an old man, is able to say that all there was in him of life-inspiring, strengthening, exalting, enlightening thoughts and feelings still lives on in his writings, and that he himself now only represents the gray ashes, whilst the fire has been kept alive and spread out. And if we consider that every human action, not only a book, is in some way or other the cause of other actions, decisions, and thoughts; that everything that happens is inseparably connected with everything[Pg 189] that is going to happen, we recognise the real immortality, that of movement,—that which has once moved is enclosed and immortalised in the general union of all existence, like an insect within a piece of amber.

The Book Has Grown Almost Into a Person.—Every author is continually amazed at how their book, once it’s been released, seems to take on a life of its own; it’s as if a part of an insect has been detached and now goes off independently. They might forget about it entirely, rise above the ideas expressed in it, or even lose touch with the drive that inspired them at the time of writing; meanwhile, the book pursues its readers, sparks excitement, brings joy or horror, inspires new creations, and becomes the essence of plans and actions—in short, it lives like a being with thoughts and feelings, yet it is not a person. The most fortunate authors are those who, in their old age, can say that all their life-affirming, empowering, uplifting, and enlightening thoughts and feelings still exist in their writings, while they themselves have become mere remnants, with the fire of their earlier passion still alive and spreading. And when we consider that every human action, not just a book, ultimately sparks further actions, choices, and thoughts; that everything that happens is deeply interconnected with everything that is yet to happen, we recognize true immortality, that of movement—what has once moved is captured and immortalized in the intricate tapestry of existence, like an insect preserved in amber.

209.

209.

Joy in Old Age.—The thinker, as likewise the artist, who has put his best self into his works, feels an almost malicious joy when he sees how mind and body are being slowly damaged and destroyed by time, as if from a dark corner he were spying a thief at his money-chest, knowing all the time that it was empty and his treasures in safety.

Joy in Later Life.—The thinker, just like the artist, who has poured their best self into their work, experiences a kind of dark joy when they observe how time gradually harms and erodes both mind and body, as if from a hidden spot they’re watching a thief approach their empty treasure chest, fully aware that their true riches are still safe.

210.

210.

Quiet Fruitfulness.—The born aristocrats of the mind are not in too much of a hurry; their creations appear and fall from the tree on some quiet autumn evening, without being rashly desired, instigated, or pushed aside by new matter. The unceasing desire to create is vulgar, and betrays envy, jealousy, and ambition. If a man is something, it is not really necessary for him to do anything—and yet he does a great deal. There is a human species higher even than wie "productive" man.

Quiet Productivity.—The naturally gifted thinkers are not rushed; their ideas come to life and fade away like leaves from a tree on a peaceful autumn evening, without being impulsively wanted, forced, or overshadowed by new concepts. An unending urge to create is crass and reveals envy, jealousy, and ambition. If someone is truly accomplished, it isn't essential for them to constantly produce—and yet they contribute a great deal. There exists a higher kind of person than the so-called "productive" individual.

211.

211.

Achilles and Homer.—It is always like the case of Achilles and Homer,—the one has[Pg 190] the experiences and sensations, the other describes them. A genuine author only puts into words the feelings and adventures of others, he is an artist, and divines much from the little he has experienced. Artists are by no means creatures of great passion; but they frequently represent themselves as such with the unconscious feeling that their depicted passion will be better believed in if their own life gives credence to their experience in these affairs. They need only let themselves go, not control themselves, and give free play to their anger and their desires, and every one will immediately cry out, "How passionate he is!" But the deeply stirring passion that consumes and often destroys the individual is another matter: those who have really experienced it do not describe it in dramas, harmonies or romances. Artists are frequently unbridled individuals, in so far as they are not artists, but that is a different thing.

Achilles and Homer.—It’s always like the situation with Achilles and Homer—the one has[Pg 190] the experiences and feelings, the other describes them. A true author only expresses the emotions and adventures of others; they are an artist and perceive much from the little they have personally experienced. Artists aren’t necessarily people of intense passion, but they often portray themselves as such with the unspoken belief that their shown passion will be more convincing if their own lives support their experiences in these matters. They just need to let themselves be, not hold back, and unleash their anger and desires, and everyone will immediately exclaim, "How passionate he is!" But the intense passion that consumes and often ruins a person is a different story: those who have truly felt it don’t express it in plays, melodies, or stories. Artists are often uninhibited individuals, as far as they are not artists, but that’s a separate issue.

212.

212.

Old Doubts About the Effect of Art.—Should pity and fear really be unburdened through tragedy, as Aristotle would have it, so that the hearers return home colder and quieter? Should ghost-stories really make us less fearful and superstitious? In the case of certain physical processes, in the satisfaction of love, for instance, it is true that with the fulfilment of a need there follows an alleviation and temporary decrease in the impulse. But fear and pity are not in this sense the needs of particular organs[Pg 191] which require to be relieved. And in time every instinct is even strengthened by practice in its satisfaction, in spite of that periodical mitigation. It might be possible that in each single case pity and fear would be soothed and relieved by tragedy; nevertheless, they might, on the whole, be increased by tragic influences, and Plato would be right in saying that tragedy makes us altogether more timid and susceptible. The tragic poet himself would then of necessity acquire a gloomy and fearful view of the world, and a yielding, irritable, tearful soul; it would also agree with Plato's view if the tragic poets, and likewise the entire part of the community that derived particular pleasure from them, degenerated into ever greater licentiousness and intemperance. But what right, indeed, has our age to give an answer to that great question of Plato's as to the moral influence of art? If we even had art,—where have we an influence, any kind of an art-influence?

Lingering Doubts About the Impact of Art.—Should pity and fear really be released through tragedy, as Aristotle suggested, so that the audience leaves feeling colder and calmer? Should ghost stories actually make us less scared and superstitious? In some physical situations, like the satisfaction of love, it’s true that fulfilling a need leads to relief and a temporary reduction in desire. But fear and pity aren’t like needs of specific organs[Pg 191] that require relief. Over time, every instinct is even strengthened by repeated satisfaction, despite those occasional moments of relief. It could be that in each instance, tragedy might soothe and alleviate pity and fear; however, overall, these emotions might be intensified by tragic influences, supporting Plato's claim that tragedy makes us more timid and sensitive. As a result, the tragic poet would inevitably adopt a gloomy and fearful outlook on the world, along with a yielding, irritable, tearful temperament. Plato's view would also align if tragic poets, as well as the segment of society that particularly enjoys them, became increasingly licentious and excessive. But what right does our era have to answer Plato's profound question about the moral impact of art? Even if we had art—where is our influence, any kind of art influence?

213.

213.

Pleasure in Nonsense.—How can we take pleasure in nonsense? But wherever there is laughter in the world this is the case: it may even be said that almost everywhere where there is happiness, there is found pleasure in nonsense. The transformation of experience into its opposite, of the suitable into the unsuitable, the obligatory into the optional (but in such a manner that this process produces no injury and is only[Pg 192] imagined in jest), is a pleasure; for it temporarily liberates us from the yoke of the obligatory, suitable and experienced, in which we usually find our pitiless masters; we play and laugh when the expected (which generally causes fear and expectancy) happens without bringing any injury. It is the pleasure felt by slaves in the Saturnalian feasts.

Joy in Absurdity.—How can we find joy in nonsense? But wherever there's laughter in the world, this holds true: it can even be said that almost everywhere happiness exists, there's also enjoyment in nonsense. The shift of experience into its opposite, from what's appropriate to what's inappropriate, from the required to the optional (but in a way that doesn’t cause harm and is only[Pg 192] imagined in jest), brings pleasure; it temporarily frees us from the burdens of duty, appropriateness, and experience, which usually constrain us like unyielding masters. We laugh and play when the unexpected (which generally brings fear and anticipation) occurs without any harm. It’s the joy felt by slaves during the Saturnalian feasts.

214.

214.

The Ennobling of Reality.—Through the fact that in the aphrodisiac impulse men discerned a godhead and with adoring gratitude felt it working within themselves, this emotion has in the course of time become imbued with higher conceptions, and has thereby been materially ennobled. Thus certain nations, by virtue of this art of idealisation, have created great aids to culture out of diseases,—the Greeks, for instance, who in earlier centuries suffered from great nervous epidemics (like epilepsy and St. Vitus' Dance), and developed out of them the splendid type of the Bacchante. The Greeks, however, enjoyed an astonishingly high degree of health—their secret was, to revere even disease as a god, if it only possessed power.

The Elevation of Reality.—Because men recognized a divine presence in their sexual desires and felt it working within them with sincere gratitude, this feeling has gradually taken on deeper meanings and has thus become genuinely elevated. Certain cultures, through this ability to idealize, have turned afflictions into significant contributions to civilization—like the Greeks, for example, who in earlier times faced serious nervous disorders (such as epilepsy and St. Vitus' Dance) and transformed these into the magnificent figure of the Bacchante. The Greeks, however, maintained an impressively high level of health—their secret was to honor even illness as a divine force, as long as it held power.

215.

215.

Music.—Music by and for itself is not so portentous for our inward nature, so deeply moving, that it ought to be looked upon as the direct language of the feelings; but its ancient union with poetry has infused so much symbolism[Pg 193] into rhythmical movement, into loudness and softness of tone, that we now imagine it speaks directly to and comes from the inward nature. Dramatic music is only possible when the art of harmony has acquired an immense range of symbolical means, through song, opera, and a hundred attempts at description by sound. "Absolute music" is either form per se, in 'the rude condition of music, when playing in time and with various degrees of strength gives pleasure, or the symbolism of form which speaks to the understanding even without poetry, after the two arts were joined finally together after long development and the musical form had been woven about with threads of meaning and feeling. People who are backward in musical development can appreciate a piece of harmony merely as execution, whilst those who are advanced will comprehend it symbolically. No music is deep and full of meaning in itself, it does not speak of "will," of the "thing-in-itself"; that could be imagined by the intellect only in an age which had conquered for musical symbolism the entire range of inner life. It was the intellect itself that first gave this meaning to sound, just as it also gave meaning to the relation between lines and masses in architecture, but which in itself is quite foreign to mechanical laws.

Music.—Music on its own isn’t as powerful for our inner nature or as deeply moving that it should be seen as the direct language of feelings. However, its long-standing connection with poetry has added so much symbolism[Pg 193] to rhythmic movement and variations in loudness and softness that we now imagine it speaks directly to and comes from our inner selves. Dramatic music is only possible when the art of harmony has developed a vast range of symbolic tools through song, opera, and numerous attempts at conveying meaning through sound. "Absolute music" exists as either form per se, in its basic state where playing in time and with varying intensities brings pleasure, or as the symbolism of form that communicates understanding even without poetry, after the two arts finally united following extensive development and the musical form became intertwined with layers of meaning and emotion. People who haven't advanced much in musical understanding may only appreciate a piece of harmony for its performance, while those who are more knowledgeable will see it symbolically. No music is inherently deep or meaningful on its own; it doesn’t express "will" or the "thing-in-itself." Such concepts could only be conceived by the intellect in a time when musical symbolism encompassed the full scope of inner life. It was the intellect that first assigned this meaning to sound, just as it also gave significance to the relationship between lines and shapes in architecture, even though that’s quite separate from mechanical laws.

216.

216.

Gesture and Speech.—Older than speech is the imitation of gestures, which is carried on[Pg 194] unconsciously and which, in the general repression of the language of gesture and trained control of the muscles, is still so great that we cannot look at a face moved by emotion without feeling an agitation of our own face (it may be remarked that feigned yawning excites real yawning in any one who sees it). The imitated gesture leads the one who imitates back to the sensation it expressed in the face or body of the one imitated. Thus men learned to understand one another, thus the child still learns to understand the mother. Generally speaking, painful sensations may also have been expressed by gestures, and the pain which caused them (for instance, tearing the hair, beating the breast, forcible distortion and straining of the muscles of the face). On the other hand, gestures of joy were themselves joyful and lent themselves easily to the communication of the understanding; (laughter, as the expression of the feeling when being tickled, serves also for the expression of other pleasurable sensations). As soon as men understood each other by gestures, there could be established a symbolism of gestures; I mean, an understanding could be arrived at respecting the language of accents, so that first accent and gesture (to which it was symbolically added) were produced, and later on the accent alone. In former times there happened very frequently that which now happens in the development of music, especially of dramatic music,—while music, without explanatory dance and pantomime (language of gesture), is at first only empty sound, but by long familiarity with that[Pg 195] combination of music and movement the ear becomes schooled into instant interpretation of the figures of sound, and finally attains a height of quick understanding, where it has no longer any need of visible movement and understands the sound-poet without it. It is then called absolute music, that is music in which, without further help, everything is symbolically understood.

Body language and communication.—Older than spoken language is the imitation of gestures, which happens[Pg 194] unconsciously. Even with the general suppression of gesture language and trained muscle control, the response is so strong that we can't see a face expressing emotion without feeling a movement in our own face (for example, seeing someone yawn makes us yawn too). Imitating a gesture brings the imitator back to the sensation it conveyed in the imitated person's face or body. This is how people learned to understand each other, and it’s also how children learn to understand their mothers. In general, painful feelings were likely expressed through gestures, and the pain that caused them (like pulling hair, hitting the chest, or forcing facial muscles) contributed to that expression. Conversely, joyful gestures were genuinely joyful and easily communicated understanding; for instance, laughter from being tickled also expresses other pleasurable feelings. Once people began to understand each other through gestures, a symbolism of gestures developed; in other words, they created a shared understanding of the language of accents, which initially combined accent and gesture, and eventually progressed to relying solely on accent. In ancient times, this process resembled the evolution of music today, especially in dramatic music—where music alone, without accompanying dance and pantomime (gesture language), initially feels like empty sound. However, after long exposure to the combination of music and movement, listeners train themselves to instantly interpret the musical patterns and eventually reach a level of understanding where they no longer need visible movement to grasp the meaning; they can connect with the sound-poet directly. This is referred to as absolute music, meaning music that conveys understanding symbolically without further assistance.

217.

217.

The Spiritualising of Higher Art.—By virtue of extraordinary intellectual exercise through the art-development of the new music, our ears have been growing more intellectual. For this reason we can now endure a much greater volume of sound, much more "noise," because we are far better practised in listening for the sense in it than were our ancestors. As a matter of fact, all our senses have been somewhat blunted, because they immediately look for the sense; that is, they ask what "it means" and not what "it is,"—such a blunting betrays itself, for instance, in the absolute dominion of the temperature of sounds; for ears which still make the finer distinctions, between eis and des, for instance, are now amongst the exceptions. In this respect our ear has grown coarser. And then the ugly side of the world, the one originally hostile to the senses, has been conquered for music; its power has been immensely widened, especially in the expression of the noble, the terrible, and the mysterious: our music now[Pg 196] gives utterance to things which had formerly no tongue. In the same way certain painters have rendered the eye more intellectual, and have gone far beyond that which was formerly called pleasure in colour and form. Here, too, that side of the world originally considered as ugly has been conquered by the artistic intellect. What results from all this? The more capable of thought that eye and ear become, the more they approach the limit where they become senseless, the seat of pleasure is moved into the brain, the organs of the senses themselves become dulled and weak, the symbolical takes more and more the place of the actual,—and thus we arrive at barbarism in this way as surely as in any other. In the meantime we may say: the world is uglier than ever, but it represents a more beautiful world than has ever existed. But the more the amber-scent of meaning is dispersed and evaporated, the rarer become those who perceive it, and the remainder halt at what is ugly and endeavour to enjoy it direct, an aim, however, which they never succeed in attaining. Thus, in Germany there is a twofold direction of musical development, here a throng of ten thousand with ever higher, finer demands, ever listening more and more for the "it means," and there the immense countless mass which yearly grows more incapable of understanding what is important even in the form of sensual ugliness, and which therefore turns ever more willingly to what in music is ugly and foul in itself, that is, to the basely sensual.

The Spiritualization of Higher Art.—Thanks to intense intellectual engagement through the evolution of new music, our ears have become more sophisticated. Because of this, we can now tolerate much larger volumes of sound, much more "noise," since we’re much better at listening for the sense in it than our ancestors were. In fact, all our senses have become somewhat dulled because they immediately seek out meaning; they inquire about what "it means" rather than what "it is." This dulling shows itself in how we perceive sounds; those who still distinguish between eis and des are now a rarity. In this way, our sense of hearing has become coarser. Furthermore, the harsh aspects of the world, which were once a threat to the senses, have been tamed by music; its scope has greatly expanded, particularly in conveying the noble, the terrible, and the mysterious: our music now[Pg 196] articulates things that previously had no voice. Similarly, certain painters have made the eye more intellectual, pushing beyond what was once merely pleasurable in color and form. Here too, the ugly aspects of the world, once dismissed, have been mastered by artistic intellect. What do we take from all this? As the eye and ear become more capable of thought, they inch closer to a point where they become meaningless; the center of pleasure shifts to the brain, and the sense organs themselves grow dull and weak; symbolism increasingly replaces reality,—and thus, we can descend into barbarism just as surely as through any other path. Meanwhile, we can observe that the world is uglier than ever, but it represents a more beautiful world than has ever existed. However, as the sweet aroma of meaning dissipates, those who can perceive it become rarer, and the rest settle for the ugly and try to enjoy it directly, a goal they never achieve. In Germany, there is a twofold trend in musical development: on one side, a crowd of ten thousand with increasingly higher, finer demands, ever listening more intently for the "it means," and on the other, the vast numbers growing more and more incapable of understanding what’s important even in the guise of sensual ugliness, thus increasingly turning to what is inherently ugly and vile in music, that is, to the crudely sensual.

218.

218.

A Stone Is More of a Stone Than Formerly.—As a general rule we no longer understand architecture, at least by no means in the same way as we understand music. We have outgrown the symbolism of lines and figures, just as we are no longer accustomed to the sound-effects of rhetoric, and have not absorbed this kind of mother's milk of culture since our first moment of life. Everything in a Greek or Christian building originally had a meaning, and referred to a higher order of things; this feeling of inexhaustible meaning enveloped the edifice like a mystic veil. Beauty was only a secondary consideration in the system, without in any way materially injuring the fundamental sentiment of the mysteriously-exalted, the divinely and magically consecrated; at the most, beauty tempered horror—but this horror was everywhere presupposed. What is the beauty of a building now? The same thing as the beautiful face of a stupid woman, a kind of mask.

A stone is more of a stone than it used to be..—Generally speaking, we no longer grasp architecture in the same way we do music. We've outgrown the symbolism in lines and shapes, just like we’re not used to the dramatic effects of rhetoric anymore, and we haven't truly absorbed this foundational aspect of culture since the very start of our lives. Everything in a Greek or Christian building had a meaning that pointed to a higher reality; this sense of boundless meaning wrapped the structure in a mystic veil. Beauty was just a secondary consideration in this system and didn’t diminish the overall feeling of the mysteriously elevated, the divinely and magically enshrined; at best, beauty softened horror—but that horror was assumed everywhere. What is the beauty of a building now? It's comparable to the pretty face of a foolish woman, merely a mask.

219.

219.

The Religious Source of the Newer Music.—Soulful music arose out of the Catholicism re-established after the Council of Trent, through Palestrina, who endowed the newly-awakened, earnest, and deeply moved spirit with sound; later on, in Bach, it appeared also in[Pg 198] Protestantism, as far as this had been deepened by the Pietists and released from its originally dogmatic character. The supposition and necessary preparation for both origins is the familiarity with music, which existed during and before the Renaissance, namely that learned occupation with music, which was really scientific pleasure in the masterpieces of harmony and voice-training. On the other hand, the opera must have preceded it, wherein the layman made his protest against a music that had grown too learned and cold, and endeavoured to re-endow Polyhymnia with a soul. Without the change to that deeply religious sentiment, without the dying away of the inwardly moved temperament, music would have remained learned or operatic; the spirit of the counter-reformation is the spirit of modern music (for that pietism in Bach's music is also a kind of counter-reformation). So deeply are we indebted to the religious life. Music was the counter-reformation in the field of art; to this belongs also the later painting of the Caracci and Caravaggi, perhaps also the baroque style, in any case more than the architecture of the Renaissance or of antiquity. And we might still ask: if our newer music could move stones, would it build them up into antique architecture? I very much doubt it. For that which predominates in this music, affections, pleasure in exalted, highly-strained sentiments, the desire to be alive at any cost, the quick change of feeling, the strong relief-effects of light and shade, the combination of the ecstatic and the naïve,—all this has already reigned in the plastic arts and[Pg 199] created new laws of style:—but it was neither in the time of antiquity nor of the Renaissance.

The Religious Origin of Contemporary Music.—Soulful music emerged from the Catholicism that was revived after the Council of Trent, thanks to Palestrina, who infused the newly awakened, earnest, and deeply moved spirit with sound; later, in Bach, this spirit also expressed itself in[Pg 198] Protestantism, as it was deepened by the Pietists and freed from its originally dogmatic nature. A prerequisite for both origins is the familiarity with music that existed during and before the Renaissance, meaning an educated engagement with music that really offered a scientific enjoyment of the masterpieces of harmony and vocal training. On the other hand, opera must have preceded it, where the layperson protested against music that had become too complex and cold, seeking to infuse Polyhymnia with a sense of soul. Without the shift to that deeply religious sentiment, without the fading of the inwardly stirred temperament, music would have remained either learned or operatic; the spirit of the counter-reformation is also the spirit of modern music (for the Pietism in Bach's music is itself a kind of counter-reformation). We are profoundly indebted to religious life. Music was the counter-reformation in the world of art; this also includes the later works of Caracci and Caravaggio, and perhaps even the baroque style, certainly more than the architecture of the Renaissance or ancient times. And we might still ask: if our newer music could shape stones, would it build them into ancient architecture? I very much doubt it. Because what predominates in this music—emotions, enjoyment of elevated, highly intense feelings, the desire to live at all costs, the rapid shifts of feeling, the striking contrasts of light and shade, the blend of the ecstatic and the naïve—all of this has already been prevalent in the visual arts and[Pg 199] created new stylistic laws: but it did not exist in the era of antiquity nor in the Renaissance.

220.

220.

The Beyond in Art.—It is not without deep pain that we acknowledge the fact that in their loftiest soarings, artists of all ages have exalted and divinely transfigured precisely those ideas which we now recognise as false; they are the glorifiers of humanity's religious and philosophical errors, and they could not have been this without belief in the absolute truth of these errors. But if the belief in such truth diminishes at all, if the rainbow colours at the farthest ends of human knowledge and imagination fade, then this kind of art can never re-flourish, for, like the Divina Commedia, Raphael's paintings, Michelangelo's frescoes, and Gothic cathedrals, they indicate not only a cosmic but also a metaphysical meaning in the work of art. Out of all this will grow a touching legend that such an art and such an artistic faith once existed.

The Beyond in Art.—It is with great sadness that we recognize the truth that throughout history, artists have celebrated and beautifully transformed ideas that we now see as false. They have glorified humanity's religious and philosophical mistakes, and they couldn't have done this without believing in the absolute truth of those mistakes. However, if the belief in such truths starts to fade, if the vibrant colors at the edges of human knowledge and imagination begin to dull, then this type of art will never thrive again. Like the Divina Commedia, Raphael’s paintings, Michelangelo’s frescoes, and Gothic cathedrals, this art represents not just a cosmic but also a deeper metaphysical significance. From all this, a moving legend will emerge that such art and such artistic faith once existed.

221.

221.

Revolution in Poetry.—The strict limit which the French dramatists marked out with regard to unity of action, time and place, construction of style, verse and sentence, selection of words and ideas, was a school as important as that of counterpoint and fugue in the development of modern music or that of the Gorgianic figures in Greek oratory. Such a restriction may appear[Pg 200] absurd; nevertheless there is no means of getting out of naturalism except by confining ourselves at first to the strongest (perhaps most arbitrary) means. Thus we gradually learn to walk gracefully on the narrow paths that bridge giddy abysses, and acquire great suppleness of movement as a result, as the history of music proves to our living eyes. Here we see how, step by step, the fetters get looser, until at last they may appear to be altogether thrown off; this appearance is the highest achievement of a necessary development in art. In the art of modern poetry there existed no such fortunate, gradual emerging from self-imposed fetters. Lessing held up to scorn in Germany the French form, the only modern form of art, and pointed to Shakespeare; and thus the steadiness of that unfettering was lost and a spring was made into naturalism—that is, back into the beginnings of art. From this Goethe endeavoured to save himself, by always trying to limit himself anew in different ways; but even the most gifted only succeeds by continuously experimenting, if the thread of development has once been broken. It is to the unconsciously revered, if also repudiated, model of French tragedy that Schiller owes his comparative sureness of form, and he remained fairly independent of Lessing (whose dramatic attempts he is well known to have rejected). But after Voltaire the French themselves suddenly lacked the great talents which would have led the development of tragedy out of constraint to that apparent freedom; later on they followed the German example and made a spring[Pg 201] into a sort of Rousseau-like state of nature and experiments. It is only necessary to read Voltaire's "Mahomet" from time to time in order to perceive clearly what European culture has lost through that breaking down of tradition. Once for all, Voltaire was the last of the great dramatists who with Greek proportion controlled his manifold soul, equal even to the greatest storms of tragedy,—he was able to do what no German could, because the French nature is much nearer akin to the Greek than is the German; he was also the last great writer who in the wielding of prose possessed the Greek ear, Greek artistic conscientiousness, and Greek simplicity and grace; he was, also, one of the last men able to combine in himself the greatest freedom of mind and an absolutely unrevolutionary way of thinking without being inconsistent and cowardly. Since that time the modern spirit, with its restlessness and its hatred of moderation and restrictions, has obtained the mastery on all sides, let loose at first by the fever of revolution, and then once more putting a bridle on itself when it became filled with fear and horror at itself,—but it was the bridle of rigid logic, no longer that of artistic moderation. It is true that through that unfettering for a time we are able to enjoy the poetry of all nations, everything that has sprung up in hidden places, original, wild, wonderfully beautiful and gigantically irregular, from folk-songs up to the "great barbarian" Shakespeare; we taste the joys of local colour and costume, hitherto unknown to all artistic nations; we make liberal use of the "barbaric[Pg 202] advantages" of our time, which Goethe accentuated against Schiller in order to place the formlessness of his Faust in the most favourable light. But for how much longer? The encroaching flood of poetry of all styles and all nations must gradually sweep away that magic garden upon which a quiet and hidden growth would still have been possible; all poets must become experimenting imitators, daring copyists, however great their primary strength may be. Eventually, the public, which has lost the habit of seeing the actual artistic fact in the controlling of depicting power, in the organising mastery over all art-means, must come ever more and more to value power for power's sake, colour for colour's sake, idea for idea's sake, inspiration for inspiration's sake; accordingly it will not enjoy the elements and conditions of the work of art, unless isolated, and finally will make the very natural demand that the artist must deliver it to them isolated. True, the "senseless" fetters of Franco-Greek art have been thrown off, but unconsciously we have grown accustomed to consider all fetters, all restrictions as senseless;—and so art moves towards its liberation, but, in so doing, it touches—which is certainly highly edifying—upon all the phases of its beginning, its childhood, its incompleteness, its sometime boldness and excesses,—in perishing it interprets its origin and growth. One of the great ones, whose instinct may be relied on and whose theory lacked nothing but thirty years more of practice, Lord Byron, once said: that with regard to poetry in general, the more he thought about it the more convinced[Pg 203] he was that one and all we are entirely on a wrong track, that we are following an inwardly false revolutionary system, and that either our own generation or the next will yet arrive at this same conviction. It is the same Lord Byron who said that he "looked upon Shakespeare as the very worst model, although the most extraordinary poet." And does not Goethe's mature artistic insight in the second half of his life say practically the same thing?—that insight by means of which he made such a bound in advance of whole generations that, generally speaking, it may be said that Goethe's influence has not yet begun, that his time has still to come. Just because his nature held him fast for a long time in the path of the poetical revolution, just because he drank to the dregs of whatsoever new sources, views and expedients had been indirectly discovered through that breaking down of tradition, of all that had been unearthed from under the ruins of art, his later transformation and conversion carries so much weight; it shows that he felt the deepest longing to win back the traditions of art, and to give in fancy the ancient perfection and completeness to the abandoned ruins and colonnades of the temple, with the imagination of the eye at least, should the strength of the arm be found too weak to build where such tremendous powers were needed even to destroy. Thus he lived in art as in the remembrance of the true art, his poetry had become an aid to remembrance, to the understanding of old and long-departed ages of art. With respect to the strength of the new age, his demands could not be satisfied; but[Pg 204] the pain this occasioned was amply balanced by the joy that they have been satisfied once, and that we ourselves can still participate in this satisfaction. Not individuals, but more or less ideal masks; no reality, but an allegorical generality; topical characters, local colours toned down and rendered mythical almost to the point of invisibility; contemporary feeling and the problems of contemporary society reduced to the simplest forms, stripped of their attractive, interesting pathological qualities, made ineffective in every other but the artistic sense; no new materials and characters, but the old, long-accustomed ones in constant new animation and transformation; that is art, as Goethe understood it later, as the Greeks and even the French practised it.

Poetry Revolution.—The strict boundaries that the French playwrights defined regarding the unity of action, time, and place, along with the structure of style, verse and sentence, word choice, and ideas, constituted a school as significant as the study of counterpoint and fugue in the evolution of modern music, or the Gorgianic figures in Greek rhetoric. Such a limitation might seem[Pg 200] absurd; however, there’s no way to move past naturalism without first confining ourselves to the most compelling (even possibly arbitrary) methods. In doing so, we gradually learn to navigate the narrow paths that connect dizzying depths, gaining a great flexibility of movement in the process, as the history of music demonstrates. Here we see how, step by step, the restraints become looser, until they may finally seem completely removed; this appearance signifies the highest accomplishment of an essential evolution in art. In the realm of modern poetry, there was no such fortunate, gradual breaking free from self-imposed constraints. Lessing publicly criticized the French form, the only modern art style, in Germany, pointing to Shakespeare; thus, the steadiness of that liberation was lost and a leap was taken back into naturalism—that is, back to the origins of art. Goethe tried to escape this by continually imposing new limits in various ways; however, even the most talented could only succeed by constantly experimenting once the thread of development had been severed. Schiller owes his relative certainty of form to the unconsciously admired, albeit rejected, model of French tragedy, and he maintained a degree of independence from Lessing (whose dramatic efforts he is well known to have dismissed). But after Voltaire, the French themselves suddenly lacked the great talents needed to advance tragedy from constraint toward that seeming freedom; later, they followed the German example and made a leap[Pg 201] into a kind of Rousseau-like state of nature and experimentation. It’s only necessary to occasionally read Voltaire's "Mahomet" to clearly see what European culture has lost due to the breakdown of tradition. Once for all, Voltaire was the last of the great dramatists who, with Greek balance, controlled his multifaceted soul, equal even to the greatest tempests of tragedy—he could do what no German could, because the French nature is much closer to the Greek than the German; he was also the last major writer to wield prose with the Greek ear, Greek artistic integrity, and Greek simplicity and elegance; he was, furthermore, one of the last individuals capable of combining vast freedom of thought with an entirely non-revolutionary mindset without being inconsistent or cowardly. Since then, the modern spirit, with its restlessness and its disdain for moderation and constraints, has gained dominance everywhere, initially unleashed by the frenzy of revolution, and then reining itself in again when it became filled with fear and horror at itself—but it was a bridle of rigid logic, not one of artistic moderation. It is true that through that liberation, we were able for a time to enjoy the poetry of all nations, everything that has emerged from hidden places, original, wild, wonderfully beautiful, and immensely irregular, from folk songs to the "great barbarian" Shakespeare; we savored the delights of local color and costume, previously unknown to all artistic cultures; we made liberal use of the "barbaric[Pg 202] advantages" of our time, which Goethe emphasized against Schiller to cast the formlessness of his Faust in the most favorable light. But for how much longer? The encroaching wave of poetry from all styles and all nations must gradually wash away that magical garden where quiet and hidden growth could still have been possible; all poets must become experimental imitators, daring copyists, regardless of how great their initial strength may be. Eventually, the public, which has lost the habit of recognizing the true artistic fact in the control of creative power, in the organizing mastery over all artistic means, must increasingly come to value power for power’s sake, color for color’s sake, idea for idea’s sake, inspiration for inspiration’s sake; thus it will not appreciate the elements and conditions of the artwork unless isolated, and ultimately will demand that the artist must deliver it to them in isolation. True, the "senseless" constraints of Franco-Greek art have been cast off, but unconsciously we have grown accustomed to viewing all constraints, all limits as senseless;—and so art moves toward its liberation, but in doing so, it touches—which is certainly highly enlightening—upon all the stages of its beginning, its childhood, its incompleteness, its occasional boldness, and its excesses;—in its demise, it interprets its origin and growth. One of the great figures, whose instinct can be trusted and whose theory simply lacked thirty more years of practical experience, Lord Byron, once stated that regarding poetry in general, the more he contemplated it, the more convinced[Pg 203] he became that we are entirely on the wrong path, that we are following an inherently flawed revolutionary system, and that either our generation or the next will come to this same realization. It is the same Lord Byron who expressed that he "viewed Shakespeare as the very worst model, though the most extraordinary poet." And doesn’t Goethe’s mature artistic insight in the latter part of his life essentially express the same sentiment?—that insight by which he made such a remarkable advance over entire generations, so much so that it can be said that Goethe's influence has not yet begun, that his time is still to come. Just because his nature kept him firmly on the path of poetic revolution for a long time, just because he fully engaged with whatever new sources, perspectives, and methods had been indirectly discovered through that breakdown of tradition, from everything that had been unearthed from the remnants of art, his later transformation and realization carry great significance; it illustrates his profound desire to reclaim the traditions of art and to restore in imagination the ancient perfection and completeness to the abandoned ruins and columns of the temple, at least in the mind’s eye, should the strength of the hand prove too weak to construct where such tremendous forces were even needed to destroy. Thus, he lived in art as in the memory of true art, with his poetry becoming an aid to remembering, to understanding the ancient and long-lost ages of art. Regarding the strength of the new era, his demands couldn’t be met; but[Pg 204] the pain this brought was more than balanced by the joy that they have been met once, and that we can still partake in this satisfaction. Not individuals, but rather more or less ideal masks; no reality, but an allegorical generality; topical characters, local colors toned down and rendered mythical to the point of being nearly invisible; contemporary feelings and the issues of contemporary society simplified to their basic forms, stripped of their engaging, interesting pathological qualities, rendered ineffective in every sense except the artistic; no new materials and characters, but the old, long-familiar ones in constant new animation and transformation; that is art, as Goethe understood it later, as the Greeks and even the French practiced it.

222.

222.

What Remains of Art.—It is true that art has a much greater value in the case of certain metaphysical hypotheses, for instance when the belief obtains that the character is unchangeable and that the essence of the world manifests itself continually in all character and action; thus the artist's work becomes the symbol of the eternally constant, while according to our views the artist can only endow his picture with temporary value, because man on the whole has developed and is mutable, and even the individual man has nothing fixed and constant. The same thing holds good with another metaphysical hypothesis: assuming that our visible world were only a delusion, as metaphysicians declare, then art would come very[Pg 205] near to the real world, for there would then be far too much similarity between the world of appearance and the dream-world of the artist; and the remaining difference would place the meaning of art higher even than the meaning of nature, because art would represent the same forms, the types and models of nature. But those suppositions are false; and what position does art retain after this acknowledgment? Above all, for centuries it has taught us to look upon life in every shape with interest and pleasure and to carry our feelings so far that at last we exclaim, "Whatever it may be, life is good." This teaching of art, to take pleasure in existence and to regard human life as a piece of nature, without too vigorous movement, as an object of regular development,—this teaching has grown into us; it reappears as an all-powerful need of knowledge. We could renounce art, but we should not therewith forfeit the ability it has taught us,—just as we have given up religion, but not the exalting and intensifying of temperament acquired through religion. As the plastic arts and music are the standards of that wealth of feeling really acquired and obtained through religion, so also, after a disappearance of art, the intensity and multiplicity of the joys of life which it had implanted in us would still demand satisfaction. The scientific man is the further development of the artistic man.

What’s Left of Art.—It’s true that art holds much greater significance in relation to certain metaphysical beliefs, especially when the idea persists that character is unchangeable and that the essence of the world is constantly manifested in all characters and actions; thus, the artist’s work becomes a symbol of the eternally constant, while according to our views, the artist can only give their artwork a temporary value, because humanity as a whole is evolving and mutable, and even each individual person lacks anything fixed and constant. The same applies to another metaphysical belief: if we assume that our visible world is merely an illusion, as metaphysicians claim, then art would come quite[Pg 205] close to the real world, since there would be too much resemblance between the world of appearances and the artist’s dream world; and the remaining difference would elevate the meaning of art above that of nature, because art would represent the same forms, types, and models as nature. However, those assumptions are incorrect; so what role does art have after this acknowledgment? For centuries, it has taught us to view life in every form with interest and joy, prompting us to eventually declare, "No matter what, life is good." This lesson from art—to find joy in existence and to see human life as a part of nature, with a steady rhythm rather than chaotic motion, as a subject of regular development—has been ingrained in us; it reappears as an essential need for understanding. We might be able to give up art, but we wouldn’t lose the appreciation it has taught us—just as we have moved on from religion but still retain the uplifting and enriching qualities gained through it. Just as the visual arts and music embody the emotional wealth truly gained from religion, even after art fades away, the intensity and variety of the joys of life that it has instilled in us would still seek fulfillment. The scientific individual is the further evolution of the artistic individual.

223.

223.

The After-glow of Art.—Just as in old age we remember our youth and celebrate festivals[Pg 206] of memory, so in a short time mankind will stand towards art: its relation will be that of a touching memory of the joys of youth. Never, perhaps, in former ages was art dealt with so seriously and thoughtfully as now when it appears to be surrounded by the magic influence of death. We call to mind that Greek city in southern Italy, which once a year still celebrates its Greek feasts, amidst tears and mourning, that foreign barbarism triumphs ever more and more over the customs its people brought with them into the land; and never has Hellenism been so much appreciated, nowhere has this golden nectar been drunk with so great delight, as amongst these fast disappearing Hellenes. The artist will soon come to be regarded as a splendid relic, and to him, as to a wonderful stranger on whose power and beauty depended the happiness of former ages, there will be paid such honour as is not often enjoyed by one of our race. The best in us is perhaps inherited from the sentiments of former times, to which it is hardly possible for us now to return by direct ways; the sun has already disappeared, but the heavens of our life are still glowing and illumined by it, although we can behold it no longer.

The Afterglow of Art.—Just like in old age we reminisce about our youth and celebrate memories, soon humanity will reflect on art: it will be viewed as a touching memory of youthful joys. Perhaps never before has art been treated so seriously and thoughtfully as now, when it seems enveloped by the haunting presence of death. We think back to that Greek city in southern Italy, which still commemorates its Greek festivals each year, amidst tears and mourning, as foreign barbarism increasingly overpowers the traditions its people brought with them; and never has Hellenism been so valued, nor has this golden nectar been enjoyed so much, as among these swiftly fading Hellenes. The artist will soon be seen as a magnificent relic, receiving the kind of honor that is rarely given to anyone of our time, as if he were a remarkable stranger whose power and beauty once brought happiness to past ages. The best of us may be inherited from the feelings of those earlier times, which we can hardly return to in direct ways; the sun has already set, but the skies of our lives still shimmer and glow from its light, even though we can no longer see it.


[1] The allusion is to Goethe's lines:

[1] The reference is to Goethe's lines:

Die Sterne, die begehrt man nicht,
Man freut sich ihrer Pracht.

You don't desire the stars,
You enjoy their beauty.

We do not want the stars themselves,
Their brilliancy delights our hearts.—J.M.K.

We don’t want the stars themselves,
Their brightness brings us joy.—J.M.K.


FIFTH DIVISION.

THE SIGNS OF HIGHER AND LOWER CULTURE.

224.

224.

Ennoblement Through Degeneration.—History teaches that a race of people is best preserved where the greater number hold one common spirit in consequence of the similarity of their accustomed and indisputable principles: in consequence, therefore, of their common faith. Thus strength is afforded by good and thorough customs, thus is learnt the subjection of the individual, and strenuousness of character becomes a birth gift and afterwards is fostered as a habit. The danger to these communities founded on individuals of strong and similar character is that gradually increasing stupidity through transmission, which follows all stability like its shadow. It is on the more unrestricted, more uncertain and morally weaker individuals that depends the intellectual progress of such communities, it is they who attempt all that is new and manifold. Numbers of these perish on account of their weakness, without having achieved any specially visible effect; but generally, particularly when they have descendants, they flare up and from[Pg 208] time to time inflict a wound on the stable element of the community. Precisely in this sore and weakened place the community is inoculated with something new; but its general strength must be great enough to absorb and assimilate this new thing into its blood. Deviating natures are of the utmost importance wherever there is to be progress. Every wholesale progress must be preceded by a partial weakening. The strongest natures retain the type, the weaker ones help it to develop. Something similar happens in the case of individuals;'a deterioration, a mutilation, even a vice and, above all, a physical or moral loss is seldom without its advantage. For instance, a sickly man in the midst of a warlike and restless race will perhaps have more chance of being alone and thereby growing quieter and wiser, the one-eyed man will possess a stronger eye, the blind man will have a deeper inward sight and will certainly have a keener sense of hearing. In so far it appears to me that the famous Struggle for Existence is not the only point of view from which an explanation can be given of the progress or strengthening of an individual or a race. Rather must two different things converge: firstly, the multiplying of stable strength through mental binding in faith and common feeling; secondly, the possibility of attaining to higher aims, through the fact that there are deviating natures and, in consequence, partial weakening and wounding of the stable strength; it is precisely the weaker nature, as the more delicate and free, that makes all progress[Pg 209] at all possible. A people that is crumbling and weak in any one part, but as a whole still strong and healthy, is able to absorb the infection of what is new and incorporate it to its advantage. The task of education in a single individual is this: to plant him so firmly and surely that, as a whole, he can no longer be diverted from his path. Then, however, the educator must wound him, or else make use of the wounds which fate inflicts, and when pain and need have thus arisen, something new and noble can be inoculated into the wounded places. With regard to the State, Machiavelli says that, "the form of Government is of very small importance, although halfeducated people think otherwise. The great aim of State-craft should be duration, which out-weighs all else, inasmuch as it is more valuable than liberty." It is only with securely founded and guaranteed duration that continual development and ennobling inoculation are at all possible. As a rule, however, authority, the dangerous companion of all duration, will rise in opposition to this.

Elevation Through Decline.—History shows that a group of people is best preserved when most of them share a common spirit due to their similar, accepted, and undeniable beliefs: as a result, their shared faith provides strength through solid customs. This teaches individuals to submit themselves, and a strong character becomes an inherent trait that is nurtured over time. The risk for these communities, built on individuals with strong and similar characters, is the gradual increase in ignorance that follows stability like a shadow. The intellectual progress of such communities relies on the more unrestricted, uncertain, and morally weaker individuals, as they are the ones who try new and diverse things. Many of these individuals fail due to their weakness, without making any significant impact; however, particularly when they have descendants, they can ignite change and, from[Pg 208] time to time, inflict harm on the stable core of the community. In this wounded, vulnerable spot, the community is inoculated with something new; but its overall strength must be sufficient to absorb and integrate this novelty into its essence. Unusual individuals are crucial wherever progress is expected. Any major advancement must first be preceded by some degree of weakening. The strongest natures maintain the type, while the weaker contribute to its development. A similar phenomenon occurs with individuals; deterioration, injury, or even a flaw—especially a physical or moral loss—often brings with it some hidden benefit. For instance, a frail person in a combative and restless society may have a better chance of finding solitude, allowing them to become calmer and wiser; a one-eyed person may develop stronger vision in one eye, and a blind person may enhance their inner insight and certainly have a sharper sense of hearing. Thus, it seems to me that the well-known Struggle for Existence isn't the only perspective to explain the advancement or strengthening of an individual or a race. Instead, two different factors must come together: first, the growth of stable strength through mental unity based on faith and shared feelings; and second, the opportunity for achieving higher goals, due to the presence of divergent individuals, leading to partial weakening and injury to the stable strength; it is precisely the weaker nature, being more delicate and free, that makes any progress[Pg 209] possible. A society that is deteriorating and weak in any aspect, yet remains strong and healthy overall, can absorb the infection of new ideas and incorporate them for its benefit. The goal of educating a single individual is this: to establish them so firmly and confidently that they can no longer be diverted from their path as a whole. However, the educator must inflict some sort of wound or take advantage of those inflicted by fate, and once pain and hardship arise, something new and noble can then be introduced into those wounded areas. Regarding the State, Machiavelli asserts that "the form of Government is of very small importance, although half-educated people think otherwise. The great aim of State-craft should be duration, which outweighs all else, as it is more valuable than liberty." Only with solid, guaranteed duration can continual development and noble integration be possible. However, authority, the dangerous companion of all duration, generally opposes this.

225.

225.

Free-thinker a Relative Term.—We call that man a free-thinker who thinks otherwise than is expected of him in consideration of his origin, surroundings, position, and office, or by reason of the prevailing contemporary views. He is the exception, fettered minds are the rule; these latter reproach him, saying that his free principles either have their origin in a desire[Pg 210] to be remarkable or else cause free actions to inferred,—that is to say, actions which are not compatible with fettered morality. Sometimes it is also said that the cause of such and such free principles may be traced to mental perversity and extravagance; but only malice speaks thus, nor does it believe what it says, but wishes thereby to do an injury, for the free-thinker; usually bears the proof of his greater goodness and keenness of intellect written in his face so plainly that the fettered spirits understand it well enough. But the two other derivations of free-thought are honestly intended; as a matter of fact, many free-thinkers are created in one or other of these ways. For this reason, however, the tenets to which they attain in this manner might be truer and more reliable than those of the fettered spirits. In the knowledge of truth, what really matters is the possession of it, not the impulse under which it was sought, the way in which it was found. If the free-thinkers are right then the fettered spirits are wrong, and it is a matter of indifference whether the former have reached truth through immorality or the latter hitherto retained hold of untruths through morality. Moreover, it is not essential to the free-thinker that he should hold more correct views, but that he should have liberated himself from what was customary, be it successfully or disastrously. As a rule, however, he will have truth, or at least the spirit of truth-investigation, on his side; he demands reasons, the others demand faith.

Free-thinker is a relative term.—A person is called a free-thinker if they think differently than what's expected of them based on their background, environment, status, and role, or due to the popular opinions of their time. They are the exception; most people have constrained minds. These constrained thinkers criticize him, claiming that his free ideas either come from a desire to stand out or lead to actions that conflict with conventional morality. Sometimes it’s also suggested that a free-thinker’s beliefs stem from mental disorder and extremism; but such claims often come from malice, as they don’t truly believe what they say and just want to harm the free-thinker, who typically shows evidence of greater goodness and intelligence that is clear to those with limited thinking. The other two sources of free thought are more genuine; in fact, many free-thinkers arise from one of these paths. However, the beliefs they arrive at this way could be more accurate and trustworthy than those of constrained thinkers. In understanding the truth, what truly matters is the possession of it, not the motivation behind its pursuit or the method of its discovery. If free-thinkers are correct, then constrained thinkers are wrong, and it doesn’t matter whether the former found truth through immorality or the latter held onto falsehoods through morality. Additionally, it’s not crucial for a free-thinker to hold more accurate views, but rather that they have freed themselves from what’s customary, whether successfully or unsuccessfully. Typically, however, they will have truth, or at least a commitment to seeking the truth, on their side; they seek reasons, while others seek faith.

226.

226.

The Origin of Faith.—The fettered spirit does not take up his position from conviction, but from habit; he is a Christian, for instance, not because he had a comprehension of different creeds and could take his choice; he is an Englishman, not because he decided for England, but he found Christianity and England ready-made and accepted them without any reason, just as one who is born in a wine-country becomes a wine-drinker. Later on, perhaps, as he was a Christian and an Englishman, he discovered a few reasons in favour of his habit; these reasons may be upset, but he is not therefore upset in his whole position. For instance, let a fettered spirit be obliged to bring forward his reasons against bigamy and then it will be seen whether his holy zeal in favour of monogamy is based upon reason or upon custom. The adoption of guiding principles without reasons is called faith.

The Source of Faith.—A constrained mind doesn't form opinions based on belief, but rather on tradition; for example, someone identifies as a Christian not because they’ve explored different beliefs and made a choice, but because they found Christianity readily available and accepted it without any justification, much like someone born in a wine-producing region becomes a wine drinker. Later, as they embrace Christianity and identify as English, they might find some justifications for their choices; these justifications can be challenged, but it doesn’t shake their overall stance. For instance, if someone with a constrained mind is asked to justify their opposition to bigamy, it will reveal whether their strong support for monogamy comes from reasoning or simply from tradition. Embracing principles without understanding is what we call faith.

227.

227.

Conclusions Drawn from the Consequences and Traced Back to Reason and Un-reason.—All states and orders of society, professions, matrimony, education, law: all these find strength and duration only in the faith which the fettered spirits repose in them,—that is, in the absence of reasons, or at least in the averting of inquiries as to reasons. The restricted spirits do not willingly acknowledge this, and feel that[Pg 212] it is a pudendum. Christianity, however, which was very simple in its intellectual ideas, remarked nothing of this pudendum, required faith and nothing but faith, and passionately repulsed the demand for reasons; it pointed to the success of faith: "You will soon feel the advantages of faith," it suggested, "and through faith shall ye be saved." As an actual fact, the State pursues the same course, and every father brings up his son in the same way: "Only believe this," he says, "and you will soon feel the good it does." This implies, however, that the truth of an opinion is proved by its personal usefulness; the wholesomeness of a doctrine must be a guarantee for its intellectual surety and solidity. It is exactly as if an accused person in a court of law were to say, "My counsel speaks the whole truth, for only see what is the result of his speech: I shall be acquitted." Because the fettered spirits retain their principles on account of their usefulness, they suppose that the free spirit also seeks his own advantage in his views and only holds that to be true which is profitable to him. But as he appears to find profitable just the contrary of that which his compatriots or equals find profitable, these latter assume that his principles are dangerous to them; they say or feel, "He must not be right, for he is injurious to us."

Conclusions Based on the Outcomes and Linked to Logic and Illogic.—All states and social orders, professions, marriage, education, law: all of these find strength and longevity only in the faith that the constrained minds place in them—that is, in the lack of reasons, or at least in avoiding questions about reasons. The restricted minds do not willingly admit this, and feel that[Pg 212] it is a shameful secret. Christianity, however, which was very straightforward in its intellectual ideas, didn’t notice this shameful secret, demanded faith and nothing but faith, and forcefully rejected the demand for reasons; it pointed to the success of faith: "You will soon experience the benefits of faith," it suggested, "and through faith shall you be saved." In reality, the State follows the same approach, and every father raises his son in the same manner: "Just believe this," he says, "and you will soon see the good it brings." This means, however, that the truth of an opinion is validated by its personal usefulness; the healthiness of a doctrine must be a guarantee for its intellectual reliability and strength. It’s just like if a defendant in a court of law were to say, "My lawyer tells the whole truth, because just look at the outcome of his words: I will be acquitted." Because the constrained minds hold onto their principles because of their usefulness, they assume that the free spirit is also looking for his own benefit in his beliefs and only considers true what is advantageous to him. But since he seems to find advantageous exactly the opposite of what his peers or equals find beneficial, these others believe that his principles are a threat to them; they say or feel, "He must be wrong, because he harms us."

228.

228.

The Strong, Good Character.—The restriction of views, which habit has made instinct,[Pg 213] leads to what is called strength of character. When any one acts from few but always from the same motives, his actions acquire great energy; if these actions accord with the principles of the fettered spirits they are recognised, and they produce, moreover, in those who perform them the sensation of a good conscience. Few motives, energetic action, and a good conscience compose what is called strength of character. The man of strong character lacks a knowledge of the many possibilities and directions of action; his intellect is fettered and restricted, because in a given case it shows him, perhaps, only two possibilities; between these two he must now of necessity choose, in accordance with his whole nature, and he does this easily and quickly because he has not to choose between fifty possibilities. The educating surroundings aim at fettering every individual, by always placing before him the smallest number of possibilities. The individual is always treated by his educators as if he were, indeed, something new, but should become a duplicate. If he makes his first appearance as something unknown, unprecedented, he must be turned into something known and precedented. In a child, the familiar manifestation of restriction is called a good character; in placing itself on the side of the fettered spirits the child first discloses its awakening common feeling; with this foundation of common sentiment, he will eventually become useful to his State or rank.

Strong, Good Character.—The limitation of perspectives that habit has turned into instinct,[Pg 213] results in what we refer to as strength of character. When someone acts based on a few consistent motives, their actions gain significant momentum; if these actions align with the principles of restricted individuals, they are acknowledged, and they also create a feeling of good conscience in those who perform them. A few motives, decisive action, and a clear conscience make up what we call strength of character. The person with strong character lacks an understanding of the many possibilities and choices available; their thinking is confined and limited because, in any situation, it may present only two options. Between these two, they must inevitably choose, based on their overall nature, and they do this easily and quickly because they aren’t faced with fifty options. The educational environment aims to restrict each individual by continually presenting them with the smallest number of choices. The individual is always treated by their educators as though they are something new, but should become a duplicate. If they initially appear as something unknown and unprecedented, they must be transformed into something known and familiar. In a child, this common manifestation of restriction is seen as good character; by aligning themselves with the restricted individuals, the child first reveals their emerging shared feelings; with this foundation of common sentiment, they will eventually become beneficial to their society or position.

229.

229.

The Standards and Values of the Fettered Spirits.—There are four species of things concerning which the restricted spirits say they are in the right. Firstly: all things that last are right; secondly: all things that are not burdens to us are right; thirdly: all things that are advantageous for us are right; fourthly: all things for which we have made sacrifices are right. The last sentence, for instance, explains why a war that was begun in opposition to popular feeling is carried on with enthusiasm directly a sacrifice has been made for it. The free spirits, who bring their case before the forum of the fettered spirits, must prove that free spirits always existed, that free-spiritism is therefore enduring, that it will not become a burden, and, finally, that on the whole they are an advantage to the fettered spirits. It is because they cannot convince the restricted spirits on this last point that they profit nothing by having proved the first and second propositions.

The Standards and Values of the Fettered Spirits.—There are four types of things that the restricted spirits claim are right. First: all things that endure are right; second: all things that don’t weigh us down are right; third: all things that benefit us are right; fourth: all things for which we have made sacrifices are right. The last statement, for example, explains why a war that started against popular opinion gains enthusiasm once a sacrifice has been made for it. The free spirits, who present their case to the forum of the fettered spirits, must demonstrate that free spirits have always existed, that free spirit-ism is therefore lasting, that it won’t become a burden, and finally, that overall, they are beneficial to the fettered spirits. It is because they fail to convince the restricted spirits on this last point that proving the first two points is of no benefit to them.

230.

230.

Esprit Fort.—Compared with him who has tradition on his side and requires no reasons for his actions, the free spirit is always weak, especially in action; for he is acquainted with too many motives and points of view, and has, therefore, an uncertain and unpractised hand. What means exist of making him strong in spite[Pg 215] of this, so that he will, at least, manage to survive, and will not perish ineffectually? What is the source of the strong spirit (esprit fort)! This is especially the question as to the production of genius. Whence comes the energy, the unbending strength, the endurance with which the one, in opposition to accepted ideas, endeavours to obtain an entirely individual knowledge of the world?

Strong Spirit.—Compared to someone who has tradition backing them and doesn’t need to justify their actions, the free spirit is always at a disadvantage, especially when it comes to taking action; they are aware of too many motives and perspectives, which leaves them with an unsure and inexperienced approach. What can be done to make them strong despite[Pg 215] this, so that they can at least find a way to survive and not fade away uselessly? Where does the strong spirit (esprit fort) come from? This raises important questions about the nature of genius. Where does the drive, the relentless strength, and the perseverance come from that enables someone, in defiance of conventional ideas, to strive for a completely personal understanding of the world?

231.

231.

The Rise of Genius.—The ingenuity with which a prisoner seeks the means of freedom, the most cold-blooded and patient employment of every smallest advantage, can teach us of what tools Nature sometimes makes use in order to produce Genius,—a word which I beg will be understood without any mythological and religious flavour; she, Nature, begins it in a dungeon and excites to the utmost its desire to free itself. Or to give another picture: some one who has completely lost his way in a wood, but who with unusual energy strives to reach the open in one direction or another, will sometimes discover a new path which nobody knew previously, thus arise geniuses, who are credited with originality. It has already been said that mutilation, crippling, or the loss of some important organ, is frequently the cause of the unusual development of another organ, because this one has to fulfil its own and also another function. This explains the source of many a brilliant[Pg 216] talent. These general remarks on the origin of genius may be applied to the special case, the origin of the perfect free spirit.

The Rise of Genius.—The cleverness with which a prisoner seeks freedom and the cold and patient use of every small advantage can teach us about the tools Nature sometimes uses to create Genius—a term I hope will be taken without any mythological or religious connotations; Nature often starts this process in a dungeon and stirs up a deep desire to escape. To give another example: someone who has completely lost his way in a forest but who energetically tries to find a way out in one direction or another might discover a new path that no one knew about before, thus creating geniuses who are credited with originality. It has been noted that injuries, disabilities, or the loss of a significant organ often lead to the heightened development of another organ, as it has to perform its own function along with an additional one. This helps explain the source of many brilliant[Pg 216] talents. These general observations about the origin of genius can be applied to the specific case of the emergence of the perfect free spirit.

232.

232.

Conjecture As to the Origin of Free-spiritism.—Just as the glaciers increase when in equatorial regions the sun shines upon the seas with greater force than hitherto, so may a very strong and spreading free-spiritism be a proof that somewhere or other the force of feeling has grown extraordinarily.

Speculation About the Origin of Free-Spiritism.—Just like glaciers expand when the sun shines more intensely on the seas in equatorial regions, a powerful and widespread free-spiritism might indicate that, somewhere, the intensity of emotion has increased significantly.

233.

233.

The Voice of History.—In general, history appears to teach the following about the production of genius: it ill-treats and torments mankind—calls to the passions of envy, hatred, and rivalry—drives them to desperation, people against people, throughout whole centuries! Then, perhaps, like a stray spark from the terrible energy thereby aroused, there flames up suddenly the light of genius; the will, like a horse maddened by the rider's spur, thereupon breaks out and leaps over into another domain. He who could attain to a comprehension of the production of genius, and desires to carry out practically the manner in which Nature usually goes to work, would have to be just as evil and regardless as Nature itself. But perhaps we have not heard rightly.

The Voice of History.—Overall, history seems to show that the process of creating genius is harsh and punishing for humanity—it provokes feelings of envy, hatred, and rivalry—driving people to desperation against one another for entire centuries! Then, maybe, like a random spark from the intense energy generated, the light of genius suddenly ignites; the will, like a horse driven wild by the rider’s spur, then breaks free and leaps into a new realm. Anyone who wants to fully understand how genius is produced and aims to replicate how Nature typically operates would need to be just as cruel and indifferent as Nature itself. But perhaps we have misunderstood.

234.

234.

The Value of the Middle of the Road.—It is possible that the production of genius is reserved to a limited period of mankind's history. For we must not expect from the future everything that very defined conditions were able to produce; for instance, not the astounding effects of religious feeling. This has had its day, and much that is very? good can never grow again, because it could grow out of that alone. There will never again be a horizon of life and culture that is bounded by religion. Perhaps even the type of the saint is only possible with that certain narrowness of intellect, which apparently has completely disappeared. And thus the greatest height of intelligence has perhaps been reserved for a single age; it appeared—and appears, for we are still in that age—when an extraordinary, long-accumulated energy of will concentrates itself, as an exceptional case, upon intellectual aims. That height will no longer exist when this wildness and energy cease to be cultivated. Mankind probably approaches nearer to its actual aim in the middle of its road, in the middle time of its existence than at the end. It may be that powers with which, for instance, art is a condition, die out altogether; the pleasure in lying, in the undefined, the symbolical, in intoxication, in ecstasy might fall into disrepute. For certainly, when life is ordered in the perfect State, the present will provide no more motive for poetry, and it would only be those persons who had remained behind who would ask[Pg 218] for poetical unreality. These, then, would assuredly look longingly backwards to the times of the imperfect State, of half-barbaric society, to our times.

The Importance of Taking the Middle Ground.—It’s possible that the emergence of genius is limited to specific periods in human history. We shouldn't expect the future to produce everything that very specific conditions were capable of producing; for example, we won't see the incredible effects of religious sentiment again. That time has passed, and much that is truly great may never arise again because it could only come from those particular conditions. There will never be a time when life and culture are solely defined by religion. Perhaps even the ideal of the saint was only possible within a certain narrow-mindedness, which seems to have completely vanished. And so, the greatest peak of intelligence may have been confined to a single era; it appeared—and still appears, as we are still in that time—when an extraordinary, long-accumulated drive for willpower focuses, as an exception, on intellectual goals. That peak will no longer exist when this wildness and energy cease to be nurtured. Humanity likely gets closer to its true purpose in the middle of its journey, during the middle phase of its existence, than at the end. It’s possible that the forces that, for example, make art possible might completely fade away; the enjoyment of lying, the vague, the symbolic, intoxication, and ecstasy might fall out of favor. Because, certainly, when life is organized in the perfect State, the present will no longer inspire poetry, and only those who have fallen behind would long for poetic unreality. These individuals would surely look back nostalgically at the times of the imperfect State, of semi-barbaric society, to our era.

235.

235.

Genius and the Ideal State in Conflict.—The Socialists demand a comfortable life for the greatest possible number. If the lasting house of this life of comfort, the perfect State, had really been attained, then this life of comfort would have destroyed the ground out of which grow the great intellect and the mighty individual generally, 11 mean powerful energy. Were this State reached, mankind would have grown too weary to be still capable of producing genius. Must we not hence wish that life should retain its forcible character, and that wild forces and energies should continue, to be called forth afresh? But warm and sympathetic hearts desire precisely the removal of that wild and forcible character, and the warmest hearts we can imagine desire it the most passionately of all, whilst all the time its passion derived its fire, its warmth, its very existence precisely from that wild and forcible character; the warmest heart, therefore, desires the removal of its own foundation, the destruction of itself,—that is, it desires something illogical, it is not intelligent. The highest intelligence and the warmest heart cannot exist together in one person, and the wise man who passes judgment upon life looks beyond goodness and only regards it as something which is not without value in the general summing-up of life. The[Pg 219] wise man must oppose those digressive wishes of unintelligent goodness, because he has an interest in the continuance of his type and in the eventual appearance of the highest intellect; at least, he will not advance the founding of the "perfect State," inasmuch as there is only room in it for wearied individuals. Christ, on the contrary, he whom we may consider to have had the warmest heart, advanced the process of making man stupid, placed himself on the side of the intellectually poor, and retarded the production of the greatest intellect, and this was consistent. His opposite, the man of perfect wisdom,—this may be safely prophesied—will just as necessarily hinder the production of a Christ. The State is a wise arrangement for the protection of one individual against another; if its ennobling is exaggerated the individual will at last be weakened by it, even effaced, —thus the original purpose of the State will be most completely frustrated.

Genius and the Ideal State in Conflict.—The Socialists want a comfortable life for as many people as possible. If the ideal of this comfortable life, the perfect State, were truly achieved, then this comfort would eliminate the conditions needed for great intellect and strong individuals, or powerful energy. If we reached this State, humanity would become too exhausted to create genius. Shouldn’t we wish for life to maintain its vigorous character, with untamed forces and energies continually being awakened? Yet, compassionate and empathetic hearts actually want to eliminate this untamed and vigorous nature, and the most caring hearts desire this the most passionately, while all the while their passion derives its energy, its warmth, and its very existence from that untamed and vigorous nature; hence, the warmest heart seeks to remove its own foundation, leading to its own destruction—essentially, they want something irrational, something not intelligent. The highest intelligence and the warmest heart cannot coexist in one individual, and the wise person who examines life looks beyond goodness, viewing it merely as a factor that holds some value in the overall evaluation of life. The[Pg 219] wise person must oppose those meandering desires of thoughtless goodness because they have a stake in the survival of their kind and the eventual emergence of the highest intellect; at the very least, they will not promote the establishment of the "perfect State," since there is only space for exhausted individuals within it. Christ, on the other hand, who we might view as having the warmest heart, contributed to making humanity less intelligent, aligned himself with the intellectually poor, and hindered the emergence of the greatest intellect, and this was consistent with his beliefs. His opposite, the person of perfect wisdom—this can be confidently predicted—will equally impede the emergence of a Christ. The State serves as a smart arrangement for protecting one individual from another; if its nobility is overstated, it will ultimately weaken the individual, even erase them—thus completely undermining the original purpose of the State.

236.

236.

The Zones of Culture.—It may be figuratively said that the ages of culture correspond to the zones of the various climates, only that they lie one behind another and not beside each other like the geographical zones. In comparison with the temperate zone of culture, which it is our object to enter, the past, speaking generally, gives the impression of a tropical climate. Violent contrasts, sudden changes between day and night, heat and colour-splendour, the reverence of all[Pg 220] that was sudden, mysterious, terrible, the rapidity with which storms broke: everywhere that lavish abundance of the provisions of nature; and opposed to this, in our culture, a clear but by no means bright sky, pure but fairly unchanging air, sharpness, even cold at times; thus the two zones are contrasts to each other. When we see how in that former zone the most raging passions are suppressed and broken down with mysterious force by metaphysical representations, we feel as if wild tigers were being crushed before our very eyes in the coils of mighty serpents; our mental climate lacks such episodes, our imagination is temperate, even in dreams there does not happen to us what former peoples saw waking. But should we not rejoice at this change, even granted that artists are essentially spoiled by the disappearance of the tropical culture and find us non-artists a little too timid? In so far artists are certainly right to deny "progress," for indeed it is doubtful whether the last three thousand years show an advance in the arts. In the same way, a metaphysical philosopher like Schopenhauer would have no cause to acknowledge progress with a regard to metaphysical philosophy and religion if he glanced back over the last four thousand years. For us, however, the existence even of the temperate zones of culture is progress.

The Cultural Zones.—We can say that the ages of culture are like the zones of different climates, except they line up sequentially rather than side by side like geographical zones. Compared to the temperate zone of culture we want to explore, the past generally feels like a tropical climate. There are intense contrasts, rapid shifts between day and night, heat and vibrant colors, and a deep respect for all that is sudden, mysterious, and terrifying, along with the swift arrival of storms. Nature's bounty was everywhere; in contrast, our culture has a clear but not overly bright sky, clean but quite stable air, and a sharpness that can even feel cold at times. Thus, the two zones oppose each other. When we see how, in that earlier zone, the most intense passions are controlled and diminished by metaphysical ideas, it’s like watching wild tigers getting crushed before our very eyes by powerful serpents; our mental climate doesn’t have such dramatic moments, and our imagination is moderate—even in dreams, we don't experience what previous cultures did while awake. But shouldn't we celebrate this shift, even if artists feel a bit deprived by the loss of tropical culture and think we non-artists are a bit too cautious? In that sense, artists are correct to question "progress," since the last three thousand years may not really show any advancement in the arts. Similarly, a metaphysical philosopher like Schopenhauer wouldn’t see much progress in metaphysical philosophy or religion if he looked back over the last four thousand years. For us, though, the very existence of temperate zones of culture is a form of progress.

237.

237.

Renaissance and Reformation.—The Italian Renaissance contained within itself all the positive forces to which we owe modern culture.[Pg 221] Such were the liberation of thought, the disregard of authorities, the triumph of education over the darkness of tradition, enthusiasm for science and the scientific past of mankind, the unfettering of the Individual, an ardour for truthfulness and a dislike of delusion and mere effect (which ardour blazed forth in an entire company of artistic characters, who with the greatest moral purity required from themselves perfection in their works, and nothing but perfection); yes, the Renaissance had positive forces, which have, as yet, never become so mighty again in our modern culture. It was the Golden Age of the last thousand years, in spite of all its blemishes and vices. On the other hand, the German Reformation stands out as an energetic protest of antiquated spirits, who were by no means tired of mediæval views of life, and who received the signs of its dissolution, the extraordinary flatness and alienation of the religious life, with deep dejection instead of with the rejoicing that would have been seemly. With their northern strength and stiff-neckedness they threw mankind back again, brought about the counter-reformation, that is, a Catholic Christianity of self-defence, with all the violences of a state of siege, and delayed for two or three centuries the complete awakening and mastery of the sciences; just as they probably made for ever impossible the complete inter-growth of the antique and the modern spirit. The great task of the Renaissance could not be brought to a termination, this was prevented by the protest of the contemporary backward German spirit (which, for its salvation,[Pg 222] had had sufficient sense in the Middle Ages to cross the Alps again and again). It was the chance of an extraordinary constellation of politics that Luther was preserved, and that his protest; gained strength, for the Emperor protected him in order to employ him as a weapon against the Pope, and in the same way he was secretly favoured by the Pope in order to use the Protestant princes as a counter-weight against the Emperor. Without this curious counter-play of intentions, Luther would have been burnt like Huss,—and the morning sun of enlightenment would probably have risen somewhat earlier, and with a splendour more beauteous than we can now imagine.

Renaissance and Reformation.—The Italian Renaissance encompassed all the positive forces that have shaped modern culture.[Pg 221] These included the freedom of thought, disregard for traditional authorities, the triumph of education over the darkness of custom, enthusiasm for science and humanity’s scientific achievements, the liberation of the individual, a passion for honesty, and a disdain for deception and superficiality (this passion ignited a group of artists who demanded perfection from themselves and their work, striving for nothing less); indeed, the Renaissance harnessed positive forces that have, to this day, never regained such power in our modern culture. It was the Golden Age of the past thousand years, despite its flaws and moral issues. In contrast, the German Reformation emerged as a vigorous protest from outdated minds, who were not ready to let go of medieval perspectives and who met the signs of its decline, like the profound dullness and alienation of spiritual life, with despair rather than the joy they should have embraced. With their northern strength and stubbornness, they held humanity back, led to the counter-reformation—a Catholic Christianity focused on self-defense, complete with the aggression of a besieged state—and postponed the full awakening and mastery of the sciences for two or three centuries; they likely made it impossible to fully blend the ancient and modern spirit. The Renaissance's grand task couldn’t reach completion because of the protest from the contemporary regressive German spirit (which, for its redemption,[Pg 222] had enough sense during the Middle Ages to repeatedly cross the Alps). Luther's survival and the strengthening of his protest were due to an unusual political constellation: the Emperor protected him to use him as a weapon against the Pope, while the Pope secretly supported Luther to leverage the Protestant princes against the Emperor. Without this strange interplay of motives, Luther would have faced a fate like Huss,—and the dawn of enlightenment might have come somewhat earlier, shining with a brilliance more beautiful than we can currently conceive.

238.

238.

Justice Against the Becoming God.— When the entire history of culture unfolds itself to our gaze, as a confusion of evil and noble, of true and false ideas, and we feel almost seasick at the sight of these tumultuous waves, we then under stand what comfort resides in the conception of a becoming God. This Deity is unveiled ever more and more throughout the changes and fortunes of mankind; it is not all blind mechanism, a senseless and aimless confusion of forces. The deification of the process of being is a metaphysical outlook, seen as from a lighthouse overlooking the sea of history, in which a far-too historical generation of scholars found their comfort. This must not arouse anger, however erroneous the view may be. Only those who, like Schopenhauer, deny development[Pg 223] also feel none of the misery of this historical wave, and therefore, because they know nothing of that becoming God and the need of His supposition, they should in justice withhold their scorn.

Justice Against the Coming God.— When the entire history of culture unfolds before us, showing a mix of good and evil, true and false ideas, we often feel overwhelmed by the chaotic waves. In that moment, we realize how comforting the idea of a becoming God can be. This Deity reveals itself more and more through the changes and experiences of humanity; it's not just random chaos, a mindless swirl of forces. The idea of a God in the process of becoming offers a philosophical perspective, like a lighthouse guiding us through the sea of history, providing comfort for a generation of scholars too wrapped up in their historical viewpoints. This shouldn't provoke anger, even if that perspective is flawed. Only those who, like Schopenhauer, reject the idea of progress[Pg 223] are immune to the struggles of history, and since they know nothing of this becoming God and the need for such a belief, they should justly keep their disdain to themselves.

239.

239.

The Fruits According to Their Seasons.—Every better future that is desired for mankind is necessarily in many respects also a worse future, for it is foolishness to suppose that a new, higher grade of humanity will combine in itself all the good points of former grades, and must produce, for instance, the highest form of art. Rather has every season its own advantages and charms, which exclude those of the other seasons. That which has grown out of religion and in its neighbourhood cannot grow again if this has been destroyed; at the most, straggling and belated off-shoots may lead to deception on that point, like the occasional outbreaks of remembrance of the old art, a condition that probably betrays the feeling of loss and deprivation, but which is no proof of the power from which a new art might be born.

The Fruits Based on Their Seasons.—Every desired better future for humanity is also, in many ways, a worse future because it’s naive to think that a new, higher level of humanity will encompass all the positive traits of previous levels and, for example, create the highest form of art. Instead, each season has its own strengths and attractions that exclude those of other seasons. What has emerged from religion and its context cannot regenerate if that foundation has been destroyed; at most, scattered and delayed offshoots may create false impressions about that, similar to the occasional nostalgia for old art, which likely reveals a sense of loss and deprivation, but is not evidence of the vitality from which a new art could emerge.

240.

240.

The Increasing Severity of the World.—The higher culture an individual attains, the less field there is left for mockery and scorn. Voltaire thanked Heaven from his heart for the invention of marriage and the Church, by which[Pg 224] it had so well provided for our cheer. But he and his time, and before him the sixteenth century, had exhausted their ridicule on this theme; everything that is now made fun of on this theme is out of date, and above all too cheap to tempt a purchaser. Causes are now inquired after; ours is an age of seriousness. Who cares now to discern, laughingly, the difference between reality and pretentious sham, between that which man is and that which he wishes to represent; the feeling of this contrast has quite a different effect if we seek reasons. The more thoroughly any one understands life, the less he will mock, though finally, perhaps, he will mock at the "thoroughness of his understanding."

The Growing Severity of the World.—The higher the culture an individual reaches, the less room there is for mockery and scorn. Voltaire sincerely thanked Heaven for marriage and the Church, which[Pg 224] provided us with such joy. However, he and his contemporaries, along with those from the sixteenth century before him, had already exhausted their ridicule on this subject; everything that is currently mocked about it feels outdated and, above all, too trivial to attract attention. Nowadays, we seek deeper reasons; we live in a serious age. Who cares to humorously spot the difference between reality and fake pretentiousness, between what a person is and what they want to portray? The awareness of this contrast has a completely different impact when we look for explanations. The more someone understands life, the less they will mock, although eventually, they might end up mocking the "thoroughness of their understanding."

241.

241.

The Genius of Culture.—If any one wished to imagine a genius of culture, what would it be like? It handles as its tools falsehood, force, and thoughtless selfishness so surely that I could only be called an evil, demoniacal being but its aims, which are occasionally transparent, are great and good. It is a centaur, half-beast, half-man, and, in addition, has angel's wings upon its head.

The Brilliance of Culture.—If someone wanted to picture a genius of culture, what would it look like? It wields falsehood, force, and careless selfishness with such skill that it could only be seen as an evil, demonic entity, yet its goals, which are sometimes clear, are grand and noble. It's a centaur, half-beast, half-man, and also has angel wings on its head.

242.

242.

The Miracle-education.—Interest in Education will acquire great strength only from the moment when belief in a God and His care is renounced, just as the art of healing you[Pg 225] only flourish when the belief in miracle-cures ceased. So far, however, there is universal belief in the miracle-education; out of the greatest disorder and confusion of aims and unfavourableness of conditions, the most fertile and mighty men have been seen to grow; could this happen naturally? Soon these cases will be more closely looked into, more carefully examined; but miracles will never be discovered. In similar circumstances countless persons perish constantly; the few saved have, therefore, usually grown stronger, because they endured these bad conditions by virtue of an inexhaustible inborn strength, and this strength they had also exercised and increased by fighting against these circumstances; thus the miracle is explained. An education that no longer believes in miracles must pay attention to three things: first, how much energy is inherited? secondly, by what means can new energy be aroused? thirdly, how can the individual be adapted to so many and manifold claims of culture without being disquieted and destroying his personality,—in short, how can the individual be initiated into the counterpoint of private and public culture, how can he lead the melody and at the same time Accompany it?

The Miracle Education.—Interest in education will become much stronger once we lose belief in a God and His care, just like the field of healing only flourished when faith in miracle cures faded. However, there is still a widespread belief in miracle-education; out of great disorder and confusion of goals and unfavorable conditions, some of the most capable and powerful individuals have emerged. Could this happen by chance? Soon, these cases will be examined more closely and carefully, but miracles will never be found. In similar situations, countless people continually fail; the few who succeed have usually become stronger because they survived these tough conditions thanks to an endless inner strength, which they also developed and enhanced by battling against these circumstances; thus, the miracle is explained. An education that no longer believes in miracles must focus on three things: first, how much energy is inherited? Second, how can new energy be stimulated? Third, how can individuals be adapted to the diverse demands of culture without feeling overwhelmed and losing their identity—in short, how can one learn to balance personal and public culture, leading the melody while simultaneously accompanying it?

243.

243.

The Future of the Physician.—There is now no profession which would admit of such an enhancement as that of the physician; that is, after the spiritual physicians the so-called[Pg 226] pastors, are no longer allowed to practise their conjuring tricks to public applause, and a cultured person gets out of their way. The highest mental development of a physician has not yet been reached, even if he understands the best and newest methods, is practised in them, and knows how to draw those rapid conclusions from effects to causes for which the diagnostics are celebrated; besides this, he must possess a gift of eloquence that adapts itself to every individual and draws his heart out of his body; a manliness, the sight of which alone drives away all despondency (the canker of all sick people), the tact and suppleness of a diplomatist in negotiations between such as have need of joy for their recovery and such as, for reasons of health, must (and can) give joy; the acuteness of a detective and an attorney to divine the secrets of a soul without betraying them,—in short, a good physician now has need of all the artifices and artistic privileges of every other professional class. Thus equipped, he is then ready to be a benefactor to the whole of society, by increasing good works, mental joys and fertility, by preventing evil thoughts, projects and villainies (the evil source of which is so often the belly), by the restoration of a mental and physical aristocracy (as a maker and hinderer of marriages), by judiciously checking all so-called soul-torments and pricks of conscience. Thus from a "medicine man" he becomes a saviour, and yet need work no miracle, neither is he obliged to let himself be crucified.

The Future of Doctors.—There’s no profession that could benefit from improvement like that of the physician; especially now that spiritual healers and so-called [Pg 226] pastors can no longer perform their tricks to public acclaim, and educated individuals tend to avoid them. The highest level of mental development for a physician hasn’t been reached yet, even if they know the best and latest methods, are skilled in them, and can quickly connect symptoms to causes, for which diagnostics are known. Additionally, they must have a way with words that adapts to each patient and resonates with their emotions; a strength that alone dispels all despair (which plagues all sick people), the finesse and adaptability of a diplomat in negotiations between those in need of hope for recovery and those who, for health reasons, must (and can) provide that hope; the sharpness of a detective and a lawyer to understand a person's innermost secrets without exposing them—essentially, a good physician today needs all the skills and creative abilities of every other professional field. With this toolkit, they are prepared to serve society by promoting good deeds, mental well-being, and productivity, while preventing harmful thoughts, schemes, and wrongdoing (often stemming from basic needs), restoring a sense of mental and physical nobility (as a facilitator and opponent of marriages), and skillfully addressing all forms of spiritual distress and guilt. In this way, a "medicine man" transforms into a savior, yet does not need to perform miracles, nor is he required to suffer.

244.

244.

In the Neighbourhood of Insanity.—The sum of sensations, knowledge and experiences, the whole burden of culture, therefore, has become so great that an overstraining of nerves and powers of thought is a common danger, indeed the cultivated classes of European countries are throughout neurotic, and almost every one of their great families is on the verge of insanity in one of their branches. True, health is now sought in every possible way; but in the main a diminution of that tension of feeling, of that oppressive burden of culture, is needful, which, even though it might be bought at a heavy sacrifice, would at least give us room for the great hope of a new Renaissance. To Christianity, to the philosophers, poets, and musicians we owe an abundance of deeply emotional sensations; in order that these may not get beyond our control we must invoke the spirit of science, which on the whole makes us somewhat colder and more sceptical, and in particular cools the faith in final and absolute truths; it is chiefly through Christianity that it has grown so wild.

In the Area of Madness.—The total of sensations, knowledge, and experiences, the entire weight of culture, has become so immense that straining our nerves and mental capacities is a common risk. In fact, the educated classes in European countries are largely neurotic, and nearly every prominent family has someone on the brink of insanity in one of its branches. It's true that health is now pursued in every way possible; however, we mainly need to reduce that tension of feeling, that heavy burden of culture, which, even if it comes at a steep price, would at least give us space for the great hope of a new Renaissance. We owe an abundance of deeply emotional experiences to Christianity, as well as to philosophers, poets, and musicians. To ensure these don't spiral out of control, we must call upon the spirit of science, which generally makes us somewhat cooler and more skeptical, particularly by diminishing our belief in final and absolute truths; it is mainly due to Christianity that it has become so unruly.

245.

245.

The Bell-founding of Culture.—Culture has been made like a bell, within a covering of coarser, commoner material, falsehood, violence, the boundless extension of every individual "I,"[Pg 228] of every separate people—this was the covering. Is it time to take it off? Has the liquid set, have the good and useful impulses, the habits of the nobler nature become so certain and so general that they no longer require to lean on metaphysics and the errors of religion, no longer have need of hardnesses and violence as powerful bonds between man and man, people and people? No sign from any God can any longer help us to answer this question; our own insight must decide. The earthly rule of man must be taken in hand by man himself, his "omniscience" must watch over the further fate of culture with a sharp eye.

The Culture's Bell Foundry.—Culture is shaped like a bell, wrapped in rough, common materials like falsehood, violence, and the endless expansion of each individual's "I,"[Pg 228] alongside every distinct community—this was the outer layer. Is it time to remove it? Has the liquid solidified, and have the positive and constructive impulses, the habits of a nobler nature become so reliable and widespread that they no longer need to rely on metaphysics and religious fallacies, nor require harshness and violence as strong ties between individuals and communities? No divine sign can help us answer this question; it’s up to our own understanding to determine. The earthly governance of humanity must be taken over by humanity itself, and our "omniscience" must oversee the ongoing fate of culture with keen vigilance.

246.

246.

The Cyclopes of Culture.—Whoever has seen those furrowed basins which once contained glaciers, will hardly deem it possible that a time will come when the same spot will be a valley of woods and meadows and streams. It is the same in the history of mankind; the wildest forces break the way, destructively at first, but their activity was nevertheless necessary in order that later on a milder civilisation might build up its house These terrible energies—that which is called Evil—are the cyclopic architects and road-makers of humanity.

The Cultural Cyclopes.—Anyone who has seen those deep basins that once held glaciers will find it hard to believe that one day the same area could become a valley filled with forests, meadows, and streams. The same is true in human history; the most chaotic forces pave the way, destructively at first, but their impact is essential for a gentler civilization to eventually establish itself. These overwhelming energies—what we call Evil—are the giant builders and path-makers of humanity.

247.

247.

The Circulation of Humanity.—It is possible that all humanity is only a phase of[Pg 229] development of a certain species of animal of limited duration. Man may have grown out of the ape and will return to the ape again,[1] without anybody taking an interest in the ending of this curious comedy. Just as with the decline of Roman civilisation and its most important cause, the spread of Christianity, there was a general uglification of man within the Roman Empire, so, through the eventual decline of general culture, there might result a far greater uglification and finally an animalising of man till he reached the ape. But just because we are able to face this prospect, we shall perhaps be able to avert such an end.

Humanity's Circulation.—It’s possible that all of humanity is just a phase in the development of a specific animal species that won’t last forever. Humans might have evolved from apes and could eventually revert back to being apes,[1] with no one really caring about how this strange story ends. Just like the decline of Roman civilization, largely caused by the rise of Christianity, led to a general degradation of people within the Roman Empire, a similar decline in overall culture could lead to an even greater degradation and ultimately a return to a more animalistic state, bringing humans back to the level of apes. However, simply being aware of this possibility might help us prevent such an outcome.

248.

248.

The Consoling Speech of a Desperate Advance.—Our age gives the impression of an intermediate condition; the old ways of regarding the world, the old cultures still partially exist, the new are not yet sure and customary and hence are without decision and consistency. It appears as if everything would become chaotic, as if the old were being lost, the new worthless and ever becoming weaker. But this is what the soldier feels who is learning to march; for a time he is more uncertain and awkward, because his muscles are moved sometimes according to the old system and sometimes according to the new, and neither gains a' decisive victory. We waver,[Pg 230] but it is necessary not to lose courage and give up what we have newly gained. Moreover, we cannot go back to the old, we have burnt our boats; there remains nothing but to be brave whatever happen.—March ahead, only get forward! Perhaps our behaviour looks like progress; but if not, then the words of Frederick the Great may also be applied to us, and indeed as a consolation: "Ah, mon cher Sulzer, vous ne connaissez pas assez cette race maudite, à laquelle nous appartenons."

The Comforting Talk of a Hopeless Push.—Our time seems to be in a middle ground; the old ways of viewing the world and the old cultures still somewhat exist, but the new ones aren't fully established or consistent yet. It feels like everything might fall into chaos, with the old fading away, the new proving useless, and getting weaker all the time. But this is how a soldier feels when learning to march; for a while, he feels more uncertain and clumsy because his movements vary between the old method and the new, and neither one wins out decisively. We hesitate,[Pg 230] but we must not lose courage or abandon what we've recently gained. Besides, we cannot go back to the old ways; we have burned our bridges; we have no choice but to be brave, no matter what happens.—March forward, just keep moving ahead! Maybe our actions look like progress; but if they don’t, then the words of Frederick the Great might also apply to us, offering some comfort: "Ah, mon cher Sulzer, vous ne connaissez pas assez cette race maudite, à laquelle nous appartenons."

249.

249.

Suffering from Past Culture.—Whoever has solved the problem of culture suffers from a feeling similar to that of one who has inherited unjustly-gotten riches, or of a prince who reigns thanks to the violence of his ancestors. He thinks of their origin with grief and is often ashamed, often irritable. The whole sum of strength, joy, vigour, which he devotes to his possessions, is often balanced by a deep weariness, he cannot forget their origin. He looks despondingly at the future; he knows well that his successors will suffer from the past as he does.

Struggling with past culture.—Anyone who has figured out the complexities of culture feels something like someone who has inherited ill-gotten wealth, or a prince whose rule is based on the violence of his ancestors. They reflect on their origins with sadness and often feel ashamed, sometimes angry. The entire energy, joy, and vitality they put into their possessions is often countered by a profound weariness; they can’t escape their origins. They look at the future with despair, fully aware that their descendants will face the same burdens from the past that they do.

250.

250.

Manners.—Good manners disappear in proportion as the influence of a Court and an exclusive aristocracy lessens; this decrease can be plainly observed from decade to decade by those who have an eye for public behaviour, which grows visibly[Pg 231] more vulgar. No one any longer knows how to court and flatter intelligently; hence arises the ludicrous fact that in cases where we must render actual homage (to a great statesman or artist, for instance), the words of deepest feeling, of simple, peasant-like honesty, have to be borrowed, owing to the embarrassment resulting from the lack of grace and wit. Thus the public ceremonious meeting of men appears ever more clumsy, but more full of feeling and honesty without really being so. But must there always be a decline in manners? It appears to me, rather, that manners take a deep curve and that we are approaching their lowest point. When society has become sure of its intentions and principles, so that they have a moulding effect (the manners we have learnt from former moulding conditions are now inherited and always more weakly learnt), there will then be company manners, gestures and social expressions, which must appear as necessary and simply natural because they are intentions and principles. The better division of time and work, the gymnastic exercise transformed into the accompaniment of all beautiful leisure, increased and severer meditation, which brings wisdom and suppleness even to the body, will bring all this in its train. Here, indeed, we might think with a smile of our scholars, and consider whether, as a matter of fact, they who wish to be regarded as the forerunners of that new culture are distinguished by their better manners? This is hardly the case; although their spirit may be willing enough their flesh is weak. The past of culture is still too[Pg 232] powerful in their muscles, they still stand in a fettered position, and are half worldly priests and half dependent educators of the upper classes, and besides this they have been rendered crippled and lifeless by the pedantry of science and by antiquated, spiritless methods. In any case, therefore, they are physically, and often three-fourths mentally, still the courtiers of an old, even antiquated culture, and as such are themselves antiquated; the new spirit that occasionally inhabits these old dwellings often serves only to make them more uncertain and frightened. In them there dwell the ghosts of the past as well as the ghosts of the future; what wonder if they do not wear the best expression or show the most pleasing behaviour?

Etiquette.—Good manners fade as the influence of the Court and the elite aristocracy diminishes; this decline can be clearly seen over the decades by those who observe public behavior, which becomes more and more crude[Pg 231]. People no longer know how to flatter or charm intelligently; this leads to the absurd situation where, when we must pay genuine tribute (to a prominent politician or artist, for example), we have to borrow words filled with deep emotion and simple honesty because of the awkwardness caused by a lack of grace and wit. As a result, public gatherings of men seem increasingly clumsy, yet more emotionally expressive and honest without truly being so. But does manners always have to decline? It seems to me that manners are taking a significant turn and we may be approaching a low point. Once society is confident in its intentions and principles, allowing them to shape behavior (the manners we learned from past contexts are now inherited and learned less effectively), there will again be social manners, gestures, and expressions that seem essential and natural because they stem from clear intentions and principles. With a better allocation of time and effort, physical activities transformed into a framework for enjoyable leisure, and greater thoughtful meditation that promotes both wisdom and body flexibility, all of this will follow. Here, we might smile at our scholars and wonder whether those who aim to be the pioneers of this new culture are actually marked by better manners. This is rarely the case; although their intentions are good, they often lack the ability. The history of culture is still too[Pg 232] strong in their makeup; they remain tied down, a mix of worldly priests and dependent educators of the elite, and they have been hindered and made dull by the rigidity of scientific study and outdated, uninspired practices. In any case, therefore, they are physically, and often mostly mentally, still the courtiers of an old, even outdated culture, and as such they themselves are outdated; the new spirit that sometimes inhabits these old spaces often only serves to heighten their uncertainty and fear. Within them dwell the remnants of the past as well as echoes of the future; it’s no surprise that they don't always convey the best expressions or exhibit the most appealing behavior.

251.

251.

The Future of Science.—To him who works and seeks in her, Science gives much pleasure,—to him who learns her facts, very little. But as all important truths of science must gradually become commonplace and everyday matters, even this small amount of pleasure ceases, just as we have long ceased to take pleasure in learning the admirable multiplication table. Now if Science goes on giving less pleasure in herself, and always takes more pleasure in throwing suspicion on the consolations of metaphysics, religion and art, that greatest of all sources of pleasure, to which mankind owes almost its whole humanity, becomes impoverished. Therefore a higher culture must give man a double brain, two brain-chambers, so[Pg 233] to speak, one to feel science and the other to feel non-science, which can lie side by side, without confusion, divisible, exclusive; this is a necessity of health. In one part lies the source of strength, in the other lies the regulator; it must be heated with illusions, onesidednesses, passions; and the malicious and dangerous consequences of over-heating must be averted by the help of conscious Science. If this necessity of the higher culture is not satisfied, the further course of human development can almost certainly be foretold: the interest in what is true ceases as it guarantees less pleasure; illusion, error, and imagination reconquer step by step the ancient territory, because they are united to pleasure; the ruin of science: the relapse into barbarism is the next result; mankind must begin to weave its web afresh after having, like Penelope, destroyed it during the night. But who will assure us that it will always find the necessary strength for this?

The Future of Science.—For those who work and seek in her, Science brings a lot of joy; for those who learn her facts, very little. Yet, since all significant truths of science eventually become ordinary and mundane, even this small joy fades, much like how we no longer find joy in learning the multiplication table. If Science continues to bring less joy in itself and increasingly casts doubt on the comforts of metaphysics, religion, and art—our greatest sources of happiness, which are essential to our humanity—then humanity suffers. So, a higher culture should give people a dual way of thinking, two separate areas of thought, to put it simply: one for understanding science and the other for appreciating non-science, which can coexist without confusion, distinct and separate; this is vital for our well-being. One part is where our strength comes from, and the other part regulates it; it needs to be fueled by illusions, biases, and emotions; the harmful consequences of overheating must be managed by conscious Science. If this need for a higher culture isn't met, we can almost certainly predict the future of human development: interest in truth will fade as it promises less enjoyment; illusion, falsehood, and imagination will gradually reclaim territory because they are tied to pleasure; this leads to the downfall of science: the regression into barbarism will be the next outcome; humanity will have to start rebuilding its foundations after having, like Penelope, unraveled them during the night. But who can assure us that we will always have the strength to do this?

252.

252.

The Pleasure in Discernment.—Why is discernment, that essence of the searcher and the philosopher, connected with pleasure? Firstly, and above all, because thereby we become conscious of our strength, for the same reason that gymnastic exercises, even without spectators, are enjoyable. Secondly, because in the course of knowledge we surpass older ideas and their representatives, and become, or believe ourselves to be, conquerors. Thirdly, because even a very[Pg 234] little new knowledge exalts us above every one, and makes us feel we are the only ones who know the subject aright. These are the three most important reasons of the pleasure, but there are many others, according to the nature of the discerner. A not inconsiderable index of such is given, where no one would look for it, in a passage of my parenetic work on Schopenhauer,[2] with the arrangement of which every experienced servant of knowledge may be satisfied, even though he might wish to dispense with the ironical touch that seems to pervade those pages. For if it be true that for the making of a scholar "a number of very human impulses and desires must be thrown together," that the scholar is indeed a very noble but not a pure metal, and "consists of a confused blending of very different impulses and attractions," the same thing may be said equally of the making and nature of the artist, the philosopher and the moral genius—and whatever glorified great names there may be in that list. Everything human deserves ironical consideration with respect to its origin,—therefore irony is so superfluous in the world.

The Joy of Discernment.—Why is discernment, which is essential for seekers and philosophers, linked to pleasure? First and foremost, because it makes us aware of our own strength, similar to how gym workouts are enjoyable even without an audience. Second, as we gain knowledge, we move beyond older ideas and their proponents, feeling, or believing ourselves to be, victorious. Third, even a small amount of new knowledge elevates us above everyone, making us feel like we are the only ones who truly understand the topic. These are the three main reasons for this pleasure, but there are many others, depending on the individual doing the discerning. A significant indicator of this is found where one might least expect it, in a section of my advisory work on Schopenhauer,[2] which every knowledgeable person may appreciate, even if they might prefer to skip the ironic tone that seems to permeate those pages. For if it’s true that creating a scholar involves combining "a number of very human impulses and desires," that the scholar is indeed a noble yet impure metal, and "is made up of a confused mix of various impulses and attractions," the same can be said about the creation and nature of artists, philosophers, and moral geniuses—and whoever else might have earned great names in that realm. Everything human deserves ironic reflection regarding its origin,—hence irony is so unnecessary in the world.

253.

253.

Fidelity As a Proof of Validity.—It is a perfect sign of a sound theory if during forty years its originator does not mistrust it; but I[Pg 235] maintain that there has never yet been a philosopher who has not eventually deprecated the philosophy of his youth. Perhaps, however, he has not spoken publicly of this change of opinion, for reasons of ambition, or, what is more probable in noble natures, out of delicate consideration for his adherents.

Fidelity as Evidence of Authenticity.—It's a strong indicator of a solid theory if its creator doesn't doubt it for forty years; however, I[Pg 235] argue that no philosopher has ever failed to criticize the philosophy of their youth eventually. Perhaps, though, they haven’t openly discussed this change of heart, either due to ambition or, more likely in noble individuals, out of a respectful consideration for their followers.

254.

254.

The Increase of What Is Interesting.—In the course of higher education everything becomes interesting to man, he knows how to find the instructive side of a thing quickly and to put his finger on the place where it can fill up a gap in his ideas, or where it may verify a thought. Through this boredom disappears more and more, and so does excessive excitability of temperament. Finally he moves among men like a botanist among plants, and looks upon himself as a phenomenon, which only greatly excites his discerning instinct.

The Rise of What’s Interesting.—During higher education, everything becomes interesting to a person; they learn to quickly identify the educational aspects of things and pinpoint where they can fill gaps in their understanding or confirm an idea. As a result, boredom decreases, and so does excessive emotional agitation. Ultimately, they navigate social interactions like a botanist among plants, viewing themselves as a phenomenon that greatly stimulates their insightful instincts.

255.

255.

The Superstition of the Simultaneous.—Simultaneous things hold together, it is said. A relative dies far away, and at the same time we dream about him,—Consequently! But countless relatives die and we do not dream about them. It is like shipwrecked people who make vows; afterwards, in the temples, we do not see the votive tablets of those who perished. A man dies, an owl hoots, a clock stops, all at one hour of the night,—must there not be some connection? Such an[Pg 236] intimacy with nature as this supposition implies is flattering to mankind. This species of superstition is found again in a refined form in historians and delineators of culture, who usually have a kind of hydrophobic horror of all that senseless mixture, in which individual and national life is so rich.

The Simultaneous Superstition.—It's said that simultaneous events are connected. A relative passes away far away, and at the same time, we dream about them—therefore! But many relatives die and we don’t dream of them. It’s like shipwreck survivors making vows; later on, in the temples, we don’t see the votive tablets of those who were lost. A man dies, an owl hoots, a clock stops, all at the same hour of the night—surely there must be some link? This kind of closeness to nature, as this idea suggests, flatters humanity. This type of superstition appears again in a more refined form among historians and cultural commentators, who often have a kind of aversion to the chaotic mix that defines individual and national life.

256.

256.

Action and Not Knowledge Exercised by Science.—The value of strictly pursuing science for a time does not lie precisely in its results, for these, in proportion to the ocean of what is worth knowing, are but an infinitesimally small drop. But it gives an additional energy, decisiveness, and toughness of endurance; it teaches how to attain an aim suitably. In so far it is very valuable, with a view to all that is done later on, to have once been a scientific man.

Action and Not Knowledge Applied by Science.—The real value of dedicating time to science isn't exactly in its outcomes, since those, compared to the vast sea of what is worth knowing, are just a tiny drop. However, it provides extra energy, decisiveness, and resilience; it shows how to achieve a goal effectively. In that sense, having been a scientist proves to be very valuable for everything that follows.

257.

257.

The Youthful Charm of Science.—The search for truth still retains the charm of being in strong contrast to gray and now tiresome error; but this charm is gradually disappearing. It is true we still live in the youthful age of science and are accustomed to follow truth as a lovely girl; but how will it be when one day she becomes an elderly, ill-tempered looking woman? In almost all sciences the fundamental knowledge is either found in earliest times or is still being sought; what a different attraction this exerts[Pg 237] compared to that time when everything essential has been found and there only remains for the seeker a scanty gleaning (which sensation may be learnt in several historical disciplines).

The Fun Appeal of Science.—The quest for truth still holds a certain allure, especially when contrasted with the dull and often frustrating nature of error; however, this allure is fading. It's true that we still inhabit the vibrant era of science and are used to pursuing truth like a beautiful young woman; but what will happen when she eventually becomes an elderly, cantankerous woman? In almost all fields of science, the foundational knowledge is either discovered in ancient times or is still being pursued; how different the appeal is[Pg 237] compared to the moment when everything crucial has been uncovered and only a minimal collection remains for the seeker (a dynamic that can be observed in various historical disciplines).

258.

258.

The Statue of Humanity.—The genius of culture fares as did Cellini when his statue of Perseus was being cast; the molten mass threatened to run short, but it had to suffice, so he flung in his plates and dishes, and whatever else his hands fell upon. In the same way genius flings in errors, vices, hopes, ravings, and other things of baser as well as of nobler metal, for the statue of humanity must emerge and be finished; what does it matter if commoner material is used here and there?

The Human Statue.—The brilliance of culture is like Cellini when he was casting his statue of Perseus; the molten metal was running low, but it had to be enough, so he tossed in his plates and dishes, along with anything else he could grab. In the same way, genius incorporates mistakes, flaws, hopes, outbursts, and other elements of both lesser and greater value, because the statue of humanity must take shape and be completed; who cares if some ordinary materials are used here and there?

259.

259.

A Male Culture.—The Greek culture of the classic age is a male culture. As far as women are concerned, Pericles expresses everything in the funeral speech: "They are best when they are as little spoken of as possible amongst men." The erotic relation of men to youths was the necessary and sole preparation, to a degree unattainable to our comprehension, of all manly education (pretty much as for a long time all higher education of women was only attainable through love and marriage). All idealism of the strength of the Greek nature threw itself into that relation, and it is probable that never since have young men been treated so attentively, so lovingly,[Pg 238] so entirely with a view to their welfare (virtus) as in the fifth and sixth centuries B.C.—according to the beautiful saying of Hölderlin: "denn liebend giebt der Sterbliche vom Besten."[3] The higher the light in which this relation was regarded, the lower sank intercourse with woman; nothing else was taken into consideration than the production of children and lust; there was no intellectual intercourse, not even real love-making. If it be further remembered that women were even excluded from contests and spectacles of every description, there only remain the religious cults as their sole higher occupation. For although in the tragedies Electra and Antigone were represented, this was only tolerated in art, but not liked in real life,—just as now we cannot endure anything pathetic in life but like it in art. The women had no other mission than to produce beautiful, strong bodies, in which the father's character lived on as unbrokenly as possible, and therewith to counteract the increasing nerve-tension of such a highly developed culture. This kept the Greek culture young for a relatively long time; for in the Greek mothers the Greek genius always returned to nature.

A Male Culture.—Greek culture during the classic age is primarily a male culture. Regarding women, Pericles sums it up in his funeral speech: "They are best when they are hardly mentioned among men." The romantic relationships between men and young boys were seen as essential for preparing young men for their education—something that’s hard for us to fully grasp today—much like how women's higher education used to depend on love and marriage. All the idealism around the strength of Greek nature focused on this relationship, and it's likely that young men have never been cared for so attentively, so lovingly, so completely with their well-being in mind (virtus) as they were in the fifth and sixth centuries B.C.—according to Hölderlin's beautiful saying: "denn liebend giebt der Sterbliche vom Besten."[3] The more highly this relationship was regarded, the less importance was placed on interactions with women; the focus was solely on procreation and lust, with no intellectual exchange or genuine love-making. Furthermore, women were excluded from competitions and spectacles of all kinds, leaving religious cults as their only significant activity. Although women were depicted in tragedies like Electra and Antigone, this was only tolerated in art and not accepted in real life—similar to how we can appreciate pathos in art but find it difficult to accept in life. Women had no other role than to bear beautiful, strong children, ensuring that the father's traits were passed on as intact as possible, which also helped counter the growing tension of such an advanced culture. This kept Greek culture youthful for quite some time, as the genius of Greece continuously returned to its roots through its mothers.

260.

260.

The Prejudice in Favour of Greatness.—It is clear that men overvalue everything great[Pg 239] and prominent. This arises from the conscious or unconscious idea that they deem it very useful when one person throws all his strength into one thing and makes himself into a monstrous organ. Assuredly, an equal development of all his powers is more useful and happier for man; for every talent is a vampire which sucks blood and strength from other powers, and an exaggerated production can drive the most gifted almost to madness. Within the circle of the arts, too, extreme natures excite far too much attention; but a much lower culture is necessary to be captivated by them. Men submit from habit to everything that seeks power.

The Preference for Greatness.—It’s obvious that people tend to overvalue anything grand[Pg 239] and outstanding. This comes from the belief, whether they're aware of it or not, that it's incredibly beneficial when someone pours all their energy into a single pursuit and becomes an extraordinary force. Certainly, a balanced development of all abilities is more beneficial and leading to greater happiness for individuals; every talent acts like a vampire, draining energy and strength from other abilities, and an overly intense focus can push even the most talented to the brink of madness. In the realm of the arts, extreme personalities garner far too much attention, but a much simpler taste is needed to be enchanted by them. People often accept everything that seeks to dominate out of habit.

261.

261.

The Tyrants of the Mind.—It is only where the ray of myth falls that the life of the Greeks shines; otherwise it is gloomy. The Greek philosophers are now robbing themselves of this myth; is it not as if they wished to quit the sunshine for shadow and gloom? Yet no plant avoids the light; and, as a matter of fact, those philosophers were only seeking a brighter sun; the myth—was not pure enough, not shining enough for them. They found this light in their knowledge, in that which each of them called his "truth." But in those times knowledge shone with a greater glory; it was still young and knew but little of all the difficulties and dangers of its path; it could still hope to reach in one single bound the central point of all being, and from thence to solve the riddle of the world. These philosophers had a firm belief in[Pg 240] themselves and their "truth," and with it they overthrew all their neighbours and predecessors; each one was a warlike, violent tyrant. The happiness in believing themselves the possessors of truth was perhaps never greater in the world, but neither were the hardness, the arrogance, and the tyranny and evil of such a belief. They were tyrants, they were that, therefore, which every Greek wanted to be, and which every one was if he was able. Perhaps Solon alone is an exception; he tells in his poems how he disdained personal tyranny. But he did it for love of his works, of his law-giving; and to be a law-giver is a sublimated form of tyranny. Parmenides also made laws. Pythagoras and Empedocles probably did the same; Anaximander founded a city. Plato was the incarnate wish to become the greatest philosophic law-giver and founder of States; he appears to have suffered terribly over the non-fulfilment of his nature, and towards his end his soul was filled with the bitterest gall. The more the Greek philosophers lost in power the more they suffered inwardly from this bitterness and malice; when the various sects fought for their truths in the street, then first were the souls of these wooers of truth completely clogged through envy and spleen; the tyrannical element then raged like poison within their bodies. These many petty tyrants would have liked to devour each other; there survived not a single spark of love and very little joy in their own knowledge. The saying that tyrants are generally murdered and that their descendants are short-lived, is true also of the tyrants of the mind. Their history is short and[Pg 241] violent, and their after-effects break off suddenly. It may be said of almost all great Hellenes that they appear to have come too late: it was thus with Æschylus, with Pindar, with Demosthenes, with Thucydides: one generation—and then it is passed for ever. That is the stormy and dismal element in Greek history. We now, it is true, admire the gospel of the tortoises. To think historically is almost the same thing now as if in all ages history had been made according to the theory "The smallest possible amount in the longest possible time!" Oh! how quickly Greek history runs on! Since then life has never been so extravagant—so unbounded. I cannot persuade myself that the history of the Greeks followed that natural course for which it is so celebrated. They were much too variously gifted to be gradual the orderly manner of the tortoise when running a race with Achilles, and that is called natural development. The Geeks went rapidly forward, but equally rapidly downwards; the movement of the whole machine is so intensified that a single stone thrown amid its wheels was sufficient to break it. Such a stone, for instance, was Socrates; the hitherto so wonderfully regular, although certainly too rapid, development of the philosophical science was destroyed in one night. It is no idle question whether Plato, had he remained free from the Socratic charm, would not have discovered a still higher type of the philosophic man, which type is for ever lost to us. We look into the ages before him as into a sculptor's workshop of such types. The fifth and sixth centuries B.C. seemed to promise something more[Pg 242] and higher even than they produced; they stopped short at promising and announcing. And yet there is hardly a greater loss than the loss of a type, of a new, hitherto undiscovered highest possibility of the philosophic life:—Even of the older type the greater number are badly transmitted; it seems to me that all philosophers, from Thales to Democritus, are remarkably difficult to recognise, but whoever succeeds in imitating these figures walks amongst specimens of the mightiest and purest type. This ability is certainly rare, it was even absent in those later Greeks, who occupied themselves with the knowledge of the older philosophy; Aristotle, especially, hardly seems to have had eyes in his head when he stands before these great ones. And thus it appears as if these splendid philosophers had lived in vain, or as if they had only been intended to prepare the quarrelsome and talkative followers of the Socratic schools. As I have said, here is a gap, a break in development; some great misfortune must have happened, and the only statue which might have revealed the meaning and purpose of that great artistic training was either broken or unsuccessful; what actually happened has remained for ever a secret of the workshop.

The Tyrants of the Mind.—It's only where the light of myth shines that Greek life glows; otherwise, it’s bleak. The Greek philosophers are now stripping away this myth; isn’t it like they want to leave the sunlight for shadows and darkness? Yet no plant avoids light; in reality, those philosophers were only searching for a brighter sun; the myth wasn’t pure enough, nor bright enough for them. They found this light in their knowledge, in what each claimed to be their "truth." But back then, knowledge shone with greater brilliance; it was still young and unaware of all the challenges and dangers ahead; it could still dream of reaching the core of all existence in one leap and from there unravel the mysteries of the world. These philosophers had a strong belief in[Pg 240] themselves and their "truth," and with that, they overthrew all their neighbors and predecessors; each one was a fierce, aggressive tyrant. The happiness they felt in believing they possessed truth may have never been greater in the world, but neither were the harshness, arrogance, tyranny, and evil stemming from such a belief. They were tyrants, which was precisely what every Greek aspired to be, and which everyone was if he had the means. Perhaps Solon is the only exception; he states in his poems how he looked down upon personal tyranny. Yet he did so out of love for his work, for his law-making; being a lawmaker is a refined form of tyranny. Parmenides also created laws. Pythagoras and Empedocles probably did the same; Anaximander founded a city. Plato embodied the desire to be the greatest philosophical lawmaker and state founder; he seemed to suffer greatly from not fulfilling his nature, and towards the end, his soul was filled with the deepest bitterness. The more the Greek philosophers lost influence, the more they suffered internally from this bitterness and malice; when various sects fought for their truths in the streets, that was when the souls of these truth-seekers became completely weighed down with envy and spite; the tyrannical element raged like poison inside them. These many little tyrants would have liked to consume each other; there was not a single spark of love and very little joy in their own knowledge. The saying that tyrants often get murdered and that their descendants don’t last long is also true for the tyrants of the mind. Their history is short and[Pg 241] violent, and their aftermath ends abruptly. It could be said of almost all great Hellenes that they seemed to arrive too late: this was the case with Æschylus, Pindar, Demosthenes, and Thucydides: one generation—and then it’s gone forever. That’s the tumultuous and grim aspect of Greek history. We now admire the tale of the tortoises. To think historically is almost like assuming that throughout all ages history unfolded according to the theory "The least amount in the longest possible time!" Oh! how swiftly Greek history unfolds! Since then, life has never been so extravagant—so unrestricted. I can’t bring myself to believe that Greek history followed the natural course for which it is so famous. They were far too diverse in their abilities to be gradual in the steady manner of the tortoise racing against Achilles, which is called natural development. The Greeks advanced quickly, but equally quickly fell; the whole system moved so intensely that a single stone thrown among its wheels could break it. Such a stone, for example, was Socrates; the once wonderfully consistent, albeit surely too fast, growth of philosophical science was destroyed overnight. It's no small question whether Plato, had he remained untouched by Socratic charm, would have discovered an even higher type of philosopher, one that is forever lost to us. We peer into the ages before him like looking into a sculptor's workshop full of such types. The fifth and sixth centuries B.C. seemed to promise something even more[Pg 242] elevated than what they produced; they stopped just short of fulfilling that promise. Yet, there’s hardly a greater loss than losing a type, a new, previously undiscovered highest possibility of philosophical life:—Even among the older types, most are poorly transmitted; to me, all philosophers, from Thales to Democritus, are incredibly hard to recognize, but whoever manages to emulate these figures walks among examples of the mightiest and purest type. This ability is certainly rare; it was even absent in those later Greeks who studied the knowledge of the older philosophy; Aristotle, in particular, hardly seems to have had awareness when standing before these great individuals. Thus, it appears as if these remarkable philosophers lived in vain, or as if they were merely meant to prepare the contentious and loquacious followers of the Socratic schools. As I’ve noted, there exists a gap, a break in development; some great misfortune must have occurred, and the only statue that might have revealed the significance and purpose of that great artistic training was either broken or never completed; what actually transpired remains forever a mystery of the workshop.

That which happened amongst the Greeks—namely, that every great thinker who believed himself to be in possession of the absolute truth became a tyrant, so that even the mental history of the Greeks acquired that violent, hasty and dangerous character shown by their political history,—this type of event was not therewith exhausted, much that is similar has happened even in more modern[Pg 243] times, although gradually becoming rarer and now but seldom showing the pure, naïve conscience of the Greek philosophers. For on the whole, opposition doctrines and scepticism now speak too powerfully, too loudly. The period of mental tyranny is past. It is true that in the spheres of higher culture there must always be a supremacy, but henceforth this supremacy lies in the hands of the oligarchs of the mind. In spite of local and political separation they form a cohesive society, whose members recognise and acknowledge each other, whatever public opinion and the verdicts of review and newspaper writers who influence the masses may circulate in favour of or against them. Mental superiority, which formerly divided and embittered, nowadays generally unites; how could the separate individuals assert themselves and swim through life on their own course, against all currents, if they did not see others like them living here and there under similar conditions, and grasped their hands in the struggle as much against the ochlocratic character of the half mind and half culture as against the occasional attempts to establish a tyranny with the help of the masses? Oligarchs are necessary to each other, they are each other's best joy, they understand their signs, but each is nevertheless free, he fights and conquers in his >place and perishes rather than submit.

What happened among the Greeks—specifically, that every great thinker who thought they held the absolute truth became a tyrant—resulted in the mental history of the Greeks taking on a violent, hasty, and dangerous character, much like their political history. This phenomenon hasn’t completely disappeared; similar events have occurred even in more modern times, although they are becoming rarer and rarely show the pure, naïve conscience of the Greek philosophers. Nowadays, opposing ideas and skepticism carry too much weight, too much volume. The age of mental tyranny is over. It's true that in the realms of higher culture there will always be a supremacy, but that supremacy now lies with the *oligarchs of the mind.* Despite local and political divisions, they form a cohesive society, where members *recognize and acknowledge* each other, regardless of what public opinion and the judgments of reviewers and journalists influencing the masses might say about them. Mental superiority, which used to divide and create resentment, generally *unites* today. How could individuals assert themselves and navigate life against all odds if they didn’t see others like them living under similar circumstances, joining hands in the struggle against the chaotic nature of half-hearted minds and cultures, as well as against the occasional efforts to impose tyranny with the help of the masses? Oligarchs need each other; they are each other’s greatest joy, they understand each other's signals, but each one remains free, fighting and succeeding in *his* place and preferring to perish rather than submit.

262.

262.

Homer.—The greatest fact in Greek culture remains this, that Homer became so early Pan-Hellenic.[Pg 244] All mental and human freedom to which the Greeks attained is traceable to this fact. At the same time it has actually been fatal to Greek culture, for Homer levelled, inasmuch as he centralised, and dissolved the more serious instincts of independence. From time to time there arose from the depths of Hellenism an opposition to Homer: but he always remained victorious. All great mental powers have an oppressing effect as well as a liberating one; but it certainly makes a difference whether it is Homer or the Bible or Science that tyrannises over mankind.

Homer.—The biggest fact in Greek culture is that Homer became Pan-Hellenic so early on.[Pg 244] All the mental and human freedom that the Greeks achieved can be traced back to this fact. At the same time, it has actually harmed Greek culture because Homer flattened and centralized the more serious instincts of independence. Over time, there were movements against Homer emerging from the depths of Hellenism, but he always came out on top. All great intellectual forces have both a constraining and a liberating effect; however, it definitely matters whether it's Homer, the Bible, or Science that holds sway over humanity.

263.

263.

Talents.—In such a highly developed humanity as the present, each individual naturally has access to many talents. Each has an inborn talent, but only in a few is that degree of toughness, endurance, and energy born and trained that he really becomes a talent, becomes what he is, that is, that he discharges it in works and actions.

Skills.—In today's advanced society, every person naturally has access to various talents. Everyone has an inborn talent, but only a few possess the toughness, endurance, and energy required to truly realize their potential, become who they are, meaning that they express it through their work and actions.

264.

264.

The Witty Person Either Overvalued Or Undervalued.—Unscientific but talented people value every mark of intelligence, whether it be on a true or a false track; above all, they want the person with whom they have intercourse to entertain them with his wit, to spur them on, to inflame them, to carry them away in seriousness and play, and in any case to be a[Pg 245] powerful amulet to protect them against boredom. Scientific natures, on the other hand, know that the gift of possessing all manner of notions should be strictly controlled by the scientific spirit: it is not that which shines, deludes and excites, but the often insignificant truth that is the fruit which he knows how to shake down from the tree of knowledge. Like Aristotle, he is not permitted to make any distinction between the "bores" and the "wits," his dæmon leads him through the desert as well as through tropical vegetation, in order that he may only take pleasure in the really actual, tangible, true. In insignificant scholars this produces a general disdain and suspicion of cleverness, and, on the other hand, clever people frequently have an aversion to science, as have, for instance, almost all artists.

The Clever Person is Either Overestimated or Underestimated.—Unscientific but talented individuals value every sign of intelligence, whether it's accurate or not; more than anything, they want their conversation partner to entertain them with their wit, to inspire them, to excite them, to engage them seriously and playfully, and in any case to serve as a[Pg 245] strong protection against boredom. Scientific minds, on the other hand, understand that the ability to have all kinds of ideas should be carefully guided by the scientific spirit: it’s not the flashy, misleading, and stimulating ideas that matter, but the often trivial truths that he knows how to extract from the tree of knowledge. Like Aristotle, he cannot distinguish between "bores" and "wits"; his dæmon guides him through deserts as well as through lush jungles, so that he may only enjoy what is real, tangible, and true. In mediocre scholars, this breeds a general disdain and distrust of cleverness, while, conversely, clever folks often hold a bias against science, like almost all artists do, for example.

265.

265.

Sense in School.—School has no task more important than to teach strict thought, cautious judgment, and logical conclusions, hence it must pay no attention to what hinders these operations, such as religion, for instance. It can count on the fact that human vagueness, custom, and need will later on unstring the bow of all-too-severe thought. But so long as its influence lasts it should enforce that which is the essential and distinguishing point in man: "Sense and Science, the very highest power of man"—as Goethe judges. The great natural philosopher, Von Baer, thinks that the superiority of all Europeans, when compared to[Pg 246] Asiatics, lies in the trained capability of giving reasons for that which they believe, of which the latter are utterly incapable. Europe went to the school of logical and critical thought, Asia still fails to know how to distinguish between truth and fiction, and is not Conscious whether its convictions spring from individual observation and systematic thought or from imagination. Sense in the school has made Europe what it is; in the Middle Ages it was on the road to become once more a part and dependent of Asia,—forfeiting, therefore, the scientific mind which it owed to the Greeks.

School Sensibility.—Schools have no task more important than teaching clear thinking, careful judgment, and logical reasoning. Therefore, they shouldn't get distracted by things that hinder these processes, like religion, for example. It's a given that human ambiguity, tradition, and necessity will later soften overly strict thinking. But while this influence lasts, schools should reinforce what is essential and unique to humanity: "Sense and Science, the very highest power of man," as Goethe puts it. The great natural philosopher, Von Baer, believes that the superiority of all Europeans compared to [Pg 246] Asians lies in their ability to reason about what they believe, something that the latter struggle with. Europe has embraced logical and critical thinking, while Asia often cannot tell the difference between fact and fiction and isn’t aware if its beliefs come from personal observation and systematic reasoning or simply from imagination. The sense taught in schools has shaped Europe into what it is today; during the Middle Ages, it was at risk of reverting to being part of and dependent on Asia—thus losing the scientific mindset it inherited from the Greeks.

266.

266.

The Undervalued Effect of Public School Teaching.—The value of a public school is seldom sought in those things which are really learnt there and are carried away never to be lost, but in those things which are learnt and which the pupil only acquires against his will, in order to get rid of them again as soon as possible. Every educated person acknowledges that the reading of the classics, as now practised, is monstrous proceeding carried on before you people are ripe enough for it by teachers who with every word, often by their appearance alone, throw a mildew on a good author. But therein lies the value, generally unrecognised, of these teachers who speak the abstract language of the higher culture, which, though dry and difficult to understand, is yet a sort of higher gymnastics of the brain; and there is value in the constant recurrence[Pg 247] in their language of ideas, artistic expressions, methods and allusions which the young people hardly ever hear in the conversations of their relatives and in the street. Even if the pupils only hear, their intellect is involuntarily trained to a scientific mode of regarding things. It is not possible to emerge from this discipline entirely untouched by its abstract character, and to remain a simple child of nature.

The Underappreciated Impact of Public School Teaching.—The true value of a public school is rarely recognized for what students actually learn there and take with them for life, but rather for the information they acquire reluctantly, just to forget it as quickly as possible. Every educated person acknowledges that the way classics are taught today is a bizarre practice happening before students are truly ready for it, facilitated by teachers who, with every word and often just their presence, tarnish a good author's work. However, the often-overlooked value of these teachers lies in their ability to speak the abstract language of the higher culture, which, while dry and hard to grasp, serves as a sort of advanced exercise for the mind. There is merit in their frequent use[Pg 247] of ideas, artistic expressions, methods, and references that young people seldom encounter in conversations with family or on the streets. Even if students only hear it, their minds are unintentionally trained to think scientifically. It’s impossible to go through this training without being affected by its abstract nature, and to remain just a simple child of nature.

267.

267.

LEARNING MANY LANGUAGES.—The learning of many languages fills the memory with words instead of with facts and thoughts, and this is a vessel which, with every person, can only contain a certain limited amount of contents. Therefore the learning of many languages is injurious, inasmuch as it arouses a belief in possessing dexterity and, as a matter of fact, it lends a kind of delusive importance to social intercourse. It is also indirectly injurious in that it opposes the acquirement of solid knowledge and the intention to win the respect of men in an honest way. Finally, it is the axe which is laid to the root of a delicate sense of language in our mother-tongue, which thereby is incurably injured and destroyed. The two nations which produced the greatest stylists, the Greeks and the French, learned no foreign languages. But as human intercourse must always grow more cosmopolitan, and as, for instance, a good merchant in London must now be able to read and write eight languages, the learning of[Pg 248] many tongues has certainly become a necessary evil; but which, when finally carried to an extreme, will compel mankind to find a remedy, and in some far-off future there will be a new language, used at first as a language of commerce, then as a language of intellectual intercourse generally, then for all, as surely as some time or other there will be aviation. Why else should philology have studied the laws of languages for a whole century, and have estimated the necessary, the valuable, and the successful portion of each separate language?

LEARNING MULTIPLE LANGUAGES.—Learning multiple languages fills the mind with vocabulary instead of facts and ideas, and each person can only hold a limited amount of information. Therefore, studying many languages can be harmful, as it fosters a belief in one’s skill and creates a false sense of significance in social interactions. It also hinders the acquisition of substantial knowledge and the pursuit of genuine respect from others. Ultimately, it damages one's sensitivity to the nuances of our native language, leading to lasting harm. The two cultures that produced the finest writers, the Greeks and the French, didn’t learn foreign languages. However, as global interaction becomes increasingly cosmopolitan—like how a good merchant in London must now know eight languages—learning many tongues has unfortunately become a necessary burden. If taken to an extreme, it will force humanity to seek a solution, and in some distant future, a new language will emerge, first as a means of trade, then as a common language for intellectual communication, and eventually for everyone, just as aviation will eventually exist. Why else has philology spent a century studying the rules of languages, evaluating what is necessary, valuable, and effective in each language?

268.

268.

The War History of the Individual.—In a single human life that passes through many styles of culture we find that struggle condense which would otherwise have been played out between two generations, between father and son; the closeness of the relationship sharpens this struggle, because each party ruthlessly drags in the familiar inward nature of the other party; and thus this struggle in the single individual becomes most embittered \ here every new phase disregards the earlier ones with cruel injustice and misunderstanding of their means and aims.

The Personal History of War.—In one human life that goes through various cultural styles, we see a condensed struggle that would typically unfold between two generations, between a father and son. The closeness of their relationship intensifies this conflict, as each person brutally exposes the familiar inner traits of the other. Consequently, this struggle within the individual becomes most embittered, as every new phase ignores the previous ones with harsh injustice and a lack of understanding of their intentions and goals.

269.

269.

A Quarter of an Hour Earlier.—A mark is found occasionally whose views are beyond his time, but only to such an extent that he anticipates the common views of the next decade. He[Pg 249] possesses public opinion before it is public; that is, he has fallen into the arms of a view that deserves to be trivial a quarter of an hour sooner than other people. But his fame is usually far noisier than the fame of those who are really great and prominent.

Fifteen Minutes Earlier.—Sometimes, a person emerges whose opinions are ahead of their time, but just enough to reflect what will be widely accepted in the next ten years. They[Pg 249] grasp public opinion before it becomes popular; in other words, they embrace an idea that could easily be seen as unimportant just a little earlier than everyone else. However, their recognition tends to be much louder than that of truly great and significant individuals.

270.

270.

The Art of Reading.—Every strong tendency is one-sided; it approaches the aim of the straight line and, like this, is exclusive, that is, it does not touch many other aims, as do weak parties and natures in their wave-like rolling to-and-fro; it must also be forgiven to philologists that they are one-sided. The restoration and keeping pure of texts, besides their explanation, carried on in common for hundreds of years, has finally enabled the right methods to be found; the whole of the Middle Ages was absolutely incapable of a strictly philological explanation, that is, of the simple desire to comprehend what an author says—it was an achievement, finding these methods, let it not be undervalued! Through this all science first acquired continuity and steadiness, so that the art of reading rightly, which is called philology, attained its summit.

Reading 101.—Every strong tendency is one-sided; it moves towards the goal of a straight line and, like that line, is exclusive, meaning it doesn’t engage with many other goals, unlike weaker groups and personalities that oscillate back and forth. We can also forgive philologists for being one-sided. The preservation and clarification of texts, along with their explanation, carried out collectively for hundreds of years, has finally led to the discovery of the right methods; the entire Middle Ages was completely incapable of a strictly philological explanation, which is simply the desire to understand what an author is saying—it was a significant achievement to discover these methods, and it shouldn’t be underestimated! Through all this, science first gained continuity and stability, allowing the art of reading correctly, known as philology, to reach its peak.

271.

271.

The Art of Reasoning.—The greatest advance that men have made lies in their[Pg 250] acquisition of the art to reason rightly. It is not so very natural, as Schopenhauer supposes when he says, "All are capable of reasoning but few of judging," it is learnt late and has not yet attained supremacy. False conclusion are the rule in older ages; and the mythologies of all peoples, their magic and their superstition, their religious cult and their law are the inexhaustible sources of proof of this theory.

The Art of Thinking.—The biggest progress humans have made is in their[Pg 250] ability to reason correctly. It's not as natural as Schopenhauer suggests when he says, "Everyone can reason, but only a few can judge." This skill is learned later in life and hasn't gained full dominance yet. Wrong conclusions were common in earlier times; the mythologies of all cultures, along with their magic, superstitions, religious practices, and laws, serve as endless evidence of this idea.

272.

272.

Phases of Individual Culture.—Th strength and weakness of mental productiveness depend far less on inherited talents than on the accompanying amount of elasticity. Most educated young people of thirty turn round at this solstice of their lives and are afterwards disinclined for new mental turnings. Therefore, for the salvation of a constantly increasing culture, a new generation is immediately necessary, which will not do very much either, for in order to come up with the father's culture the son must exhaust almost all the inherited energy which the father himself possessed at that stage of life when his son was born; with the little addition he gets further on (for as here the road is being traversed for the second time progress is—a little quicker; in order to learn that which the father knew, the son does not consume quite so much strength). Men of great elasticity, like Goethe, for instance, get through[Pg 251] almost more than four generations in succession would be capable of; but then they advance too quickly, so that the rest of mankind only comes up with them in the next century, and even then perhaps not completely, because the exclusiveness of culture and the consecutiveness of development have been weakened by the frequent interruptions. Men catch up more quickly with the ordinary phases of intellectual culture which has been acquired in the course of history. Nowadays they begin to acquire culture as religiously inclined children, and perhaps about their tenth year these sentiments attain to their highest point, and are then changed into weakened forms (pantheism), whilst they draw near to science; they entirely pass by God, immortality, and such-like things, but are overcome by the witchcraft of a metaphysical philosophy. Eventually they find even this unworthy of belief; art, on the contrary, seems to vouchsafe more and more, so that for a time metaphysics is metamorphosed and continues to exist either as a transition to art or as an artistically transfiguring temperament. But the scientific sense grows more imperious and conducts man to natural sciences and history, and particularly to the severest methods of knowledge, whilst art has always a milder and less exacting meaning. All this usually happens within the first thirty years of a man's life. It is the recapitulation of a pensum, for which humanity had laboured perhaps thirty thousand years.

Stages of Personal Culture.—The strength and weakness of mental productivity depend much less on inherited talents and more on the level of elasticity. Most educated young people around the age of thirty look at this turning point in their lives and become less willing to explore new ideas. Therefore, to sustain a continually growing culture, a new generation is needed right away, although they won’t contribute much either. In order to match the culture of their fathers, the sons must use almost all the inherited energy that their fathers had at the same stage of life when they were born. With a bit of additional energy gained later on (since they are retracing the same path, progress is a bit faster; it doesn't take as much effort for the son to learn what the father knew). Highly adaptable individuals, like Goethe, for example, manage to achieve what would require more than four generations, but they advance so quickly that the rest of humanity only manages to keep up with them in the following century, and even then perhaps not entirely, because the exclusivity of culture and the sequence of development have been disrupted by frequent interruptions. People catch up more rapidly with the standard phases of intellectual culture that have developed through history. Nowadays, they start to absorb culture like devout children, often peaking around the age of ten, before transitioning to weaker versions of those beliefs (pantheism) as they approach science; they completely bypass concepts like God and immortality, instead becoming fascinated by the allure of metaphysical philosophy. Eventually, they find even this not worth believing in; however, art seems to offer more and more, so metaphysics is transformed and continues to exist either as a bridge to art or as an artistically inspired mindset. But the drive for scientific understanding intensifies, leading individuals toward natural sciences and history, particularly through rigorous methods of knowledge, while art remains a gentler, less demanding pursuit. All this usually occurs within the first thirty years of a person’s life. It is a recap of a pensum, for which humanity has worked perhaps for thirty thousand years.

273.

273.

Retrograded, Not Left Behind.—Whoever, in the present day, still derives his development from religious sentiments, and perhaps lives for some length of time afterwards in metaphysics and art, has assuredly gone back a considerable distance and begins his race with other modern men under unfavourable conditions; he apparently loses time and space. But because he stays in those domains where ardour and energy are liberated and force flows continuously as a volcanic stream out of an inexhaustible source, he goes forward all the more quickly as soon as he has freed himself at the right moment from those dominators; his feet are winged, his breast has learned quieter, longer, and more enduring breathing. He has only retreated in order to have sufficient room to leap; thus something terrible and threatening may lie in this retrograde movement.

Retrograded, Not Abandoned.—Anyone today who still bases their growth on religious beliefs, and perhaps spends some time afterwards in metaphysics and art, has definitely taken a step backward and starts off with other modern people under less-than-ideal circumstances; it seems like they’re wasting time and space. However, because they remain in those areas where passion and energy are set free and power flows continuously like a volcanic eruption from an endless source, they can move ahead much faster once they manage to break free from those constraints at the right time; their feet become light, and they learn to breathe more calmly, deeply, and steadily. They have only pulled back to create enough space to leap forward; thus, something daunting and threatening may hide in this backward movement.

274.

274.

A Portion of Our Ego As an Artistic Object.—It is a sign of superior culture consciously to retain and present a true picture of certain phases of development which commoner men live through almost thoughtlessly and then efface from the tablets of their souls: this is a higher species of the painter's art which only the few understand. For this it is necessary to isolate those phases artificially. Historical studies form the qualification for this painting, for they[Pg 253] constantly incite us in regard to a portion of history, a people, or a human life, to imagine for ourselves a quite distinct horizon of thoughts, a certain strength of feelings, the prominence of this or the obscurity of that. Herein consists the historic sense, that out of given instances we can quickly reconstruct such systems of thoughts and feelings, just as we can mentally reconstruct a temple out of a few pillars and remains of walls accidentally left standing. The next result is that we understand our fellow-men as belonging to distinct systems and representatives of different cultures—that is, as necessary, but as changeable; and, again, that we can separate portions of our own development and put them down independently.

A Piece of Our Ego as an Art Object.—It shows a higher level of culture to consciously keep and share an accurate representation of certain stages of growth that ordinary people often go through almost without thinking and then forget: this is a more refined kind of art that only a few grasp. To achieve this, it's essential to artificially isolate those stages. Historical studies prepare us for this artistic representation, as they[Pg 253] continually inspire us to explore specific events in history, particular societies, or individual lives, leading us to envision a distinct landscape of thoughts, specific emotions, and the significance or obscurity of various elements. This historic awareness allows us to quickly reconstruct systems of thought and feelings from particular examples, similar to how we can mentally piece together a temple from several standing pillars and remnants of walls. As a result, we come to understand our fellow humans as part of different systems and embodiments of various cultures—that is, as essential, yet adaptable; and we can also identify segments of our own growth and examine them independently.

275.

275.

Cynics and Epicureans.—The cynic recognises the connection between the multiplied and stronger pains of the more highly cultivated man and the abundance of requirements; he comprehends, therefore, that the multitude of opinions about what is beautiful, suitable, seemly and pleasing, must also produce very rich sources of enjoyment, but also of displeasure. In accordance with this view he educates himself backwards, by giving up many of these opinions and withdrawing from certain demands of culture; he thereby gains a feeling of freedom and strength; and gradually, when habit has made his manner of life endurable, his sensations of displeasure[Pg 254] are, as a matter of fact, rarer and weaker than those of cultivated people, and approach those of the domestic animal; moreover, he experiences everything with the charm of contrast, and—he can also scold to his heart's content; so that thereby he again rises high above the sensation-range of the animal. The Epicurean has the same point of view as the cynic; there is usually only a difference of temperament between them. Then the Epicurean makes use of his higher culture to render himself independent of prevailing opinions, he raises himself above them, whilst the cynic only remains negative. He walks, as it were, in wind-protected, well-sheltered, half-dark paths, whilst over him, in the wind, the tops of the trees rustle and show him how violently agitated is the world out there. The cynic, on the contrary, goes, as it were, naked into the rushing of the wind and hardens himself to the point of insensibility.

Cynics and Epicureans.—The cynic sees the link between the intense and multiplied pains of a more highly cultivated person and their numerous needs. He understands that the many opinions about what is beautiful, appropriate, tasteful, and enjoyable also bring rich sources of pleasure but also discomfort. Based on this perspective, he educates himself in a backward manner by letting go of many of these opinions and withdrawing from certain cultural demands; as a result, he gains a sense of freedom and strength. Over time, when he becomes accustomed to his way of life, his feelings of discomfort[Pg 254] are actually less frequent and less intense than those experienced by more cultivated individuals, approaching those of a domesticated animal. Additionally, he experiences everything with the charm of contrast and can vent his frustrations freely, which allows him to rise above the sensations found in the animal realm. The Epicurean shares the same viewpoint as the cynic; often, the only difference between them is their temperament. The Epicurean uses his higher culture to free himself from prevailing opinions, elevating himself above them, while the cynic remains negative. He walks, so to speak, along wind-sheltered, safe, dim paths, while above him, the treetops rustle in the wind, showing how tumultuous the outside world is. In contrast, the cynic faces the rushing wind unprotected and toughens himself to the point of numbness.

276.

276.

Microcosm and Macrocosm of Culture.—The best discoveries about culture man makes within himself when he finds two heterogeneous powers ruling therein. Supposing some one were living as much in love for the plastic arts or for music as he was carried away by the spirit of science, and that he were to regard it as impossible for him to end this contradiction by the destruction of one and complete liberation of the other power, there would therefore remain nothing[Pg 255] for him to do but to erect around himself such a large edifice of culture that those two powers might both dwell within it, although at different ends, whilst between them there dwelt reconciling, intermediary powers, with predominant strength to quell, in case of need, the rising conflict. But such an edifice of culture in the single individual will bear a great resemblance to the culture of entire periods, and will afford consecutive analogical teaching concerning it. For wherever the great architecture of culture manifested itself it was its mission to compel opposing powers to agree, by means of an overwhelming accumulation of other less unbearable powers, without thereby oppressing and fettering them.

Microcosm and Macrocosm of Culture.—The most valuable insights about culture come from within ourselves when we recognize the conflicting forces at play. Imagine someone who is equally passionate about the visual arts and music as he is drawn to science, feeling that he cannot resolve this conflict by destroying one passion to fully embrace the other. In that case, the only option left would be to build a vast structure of culture around himself, allowing both passions to coexist at opposite ends, with mediating influences in between to help manage any emerging tensions. This personal cultural structure will resemble the cultural movements of entire eras and will provide meaningful lessons about them. Wherever the grand design of culture emerges, its purpose has always been to harmonize opposing forces through a significant gathering of other, less intense influences, without oppressing or constraining them.

277.

277.

Happiness and Culture.—We are moved at the sight of our childhood's surroundings,—the arbour, the church with its graves, the pond and the wood,—all this we see again with pain. We are seized with pity for ourselves; for what have we not passed through since then! And everything here is so silent, so eternal, only we are so changed, so moved; we even find a few human beings, on whom Time has sharpened his teeth no more than on an oak tree,—peasants, fishermen, woodmen—they are unchanged. Emotion and self-pity at the sight of lower culture is the sign of higher culture; from which the conclusion may be drawn that happiness has certainly not been increased by it. Whoever[Pg 256] wishes to reap happiness and comfort in life should always avoid higher culture.

Joy and Culture.—We feel a deep emotion when we see the places of our childhood—the cozy nook, the church with its graves, the pond, and the forest—all of this brings us a bittersweet ache. We feel sorry for ourselves; look at everything we’ve been through since those days! And everything here is so quiet, so eternal, yet we have changed so much, and we're filled with feeling; we even find a few people whose appearance hasn’t been touched by time any more than an oak tree—peasants, fishermen, woodworkers—they remain the same. The emotional response and self-pity we experience when seeing simpler cultures is a marker of a more advanced culture; from this, we can conclude that happiness hasn’t really been enhanced by it. Anyone[Pg 256] who wants to find joy and comfort in life should always steer clear of higher culture.

278.

278.

The Simile of the Dance.—It must now be regarded as a decisive sign of great culture if some one possesses sufficient strength and flexibility to be as pure and strict in discernment as, in other moments, to be capable of giving poetry, religion, and metaphysics a hundred paces' start and then feeling their force and beauty. Such a position amid two such different demands is very difficult, for science urges the absolute supremacy of its methods, and if this insistence is not yielded to, there arises the other danger of a weak wavering between different impulses. Meanwhile, to cast a glance, in simile at least, on a solution of this difficulty, it may be remembered that dancing is not the same as a dull reeling to and fro between different impulses. High culture will resemble a bold dance,—wherefore, as has been said, there is need of much strength and suppleness.

The Dance Simile.—It should now be seen as a clear sign of great culture if someone has the strength and flexibility to be as discerning and precise as they are able to appreciate the power and beauty of poetry, religion, and metaphysics when given some distance. Balancing these two very different demands is quite challenging, as science pushes for the absolute dominance of its methods. If this pressure is not accepted, there's a risk of becoming indecisive and wavering between conflicting motivations. Meanwhile, to consider a potential solution to this difficulty, it's worth remembering that dancing is not the same as mindlessly swaying back and forth between different impulses. A high level of culture will resemble an energetic dance—which is why, as mentioned, a lot of strength and flexibility are essential.

279.

279.

Of the Relieving of Life.—A primary way of lightening life is the idealisation of all its occurrences; and with the help of painting we should make it quite clear to ourselves what idealising means. The painter requires that the spectator should not observe too closely or too sharply, he forces him back to a certain distance from whence[Pg 257] to make his observations; he is obliged to take for granted a fixed distance of the spectator from the picture,—he must even suppose an equally certain amount of sharpness of eye in his spectator; in such things he must on no account waver. Every one, therefore, who desires to idealise his life must not look at it too closely, and must always keep his gaze at a certain distance. This was a trick that Goethe, for instance, understood.

Of the Relief of Life.—One main way to lighten life is by idealizing everything that happens. Through painting, we can clearly understand what idealizing means. The painter needs the viewer to not look too closely or carefully; instead, he encourages them to step back to a certain distance from which[Pg 257] to observe. He must assume a fixed distance between the viewer and the artwork—and he must also expect a certain level of sharpness in the viewer's eyesight; in these matters, he cannot be uncertain. Therefore, anyone who wants to idealize their life should avoid examining it too closely and should always maintain a certain distance. This was a technique that Goethe, for example, understood well.

280.

280.

Aggravation As Relief, and vice Versa.—Much that makes life more difficult in certain grades of mankind serves to lighten it in a higher grade, because such people have become familiar with greater aggravations of life. The contrary also happens; for instance, religion has a double face, according to whether a man looks up to it to relieve him of his burden and need, or looks down upon it as-upon fetters laid on him to prevent him from soaring too high into the air.

Aggravation as Relief, and vice versa.—A lot of what makes life harder for some people actually makes it easier for those in a higher social class, as they've learned to deal with bigger challenges. The opposite can also be true; for example, religion can be viewed in two ways: some see it as a way to lighten their burdens and fulfill their needs, while others see it as restrictions that hold them back from reaching their full potential.

281.

281.

The Higher Culture Is Necessarily Misunderstood.—He who has strung his instrument with only two strings, like the scholars who, besides the instinct of knowledge possess only an acquired religious instinct, does not understand people who can play upon more strings. It lies in the nature of the higher, many-stringed culture that it should always be falsely interpreted by the lower; an example of this is when art[Pg 258] appears as a disguised form of the religious. People who are only religious understand even science as a searching after the religious sentiment, just as deaf mutes do not know what music is, unless it be visible movement.

The Higher Culture is Always Misunderstood..—Someone who has tuned their instrument with just two strings, like those scholars who only possess a natural instinct for knowledge along with a learned religious instinct, won't understand people who can play with more strings. It's in the nature of higher, multifaceted culture to be misinterpreted by those at a lower level; an example of this is when art[Pg 258] is seen merely as a different form of religion. People who are solely focused on religion perceive even science as just searching for religious feelings, much like deaf mutes don’t grasp what music is unless they can see it expressed through movement.

282.

282.

Lamentation.—It is, perhaps, the advantages of our epoch that bring with them a backward movement and an occasional undervaluing of the vita contemplativa. But it must be acknowledged that our time is poor in the matter of great moralists, that Pascal, Epictetus, Seneca, and Plutarch are now but little read, that work and industry—formerly in the following of the great goddess Health—sometimes appear to rage like a disease. Because time to think and tranquillity in thought are lacking, we no longer ponder over different views, but content ourselves with hating them. With the enormous acceleration of life, mind and eye grow accustomed to a partial and false sight and judgment, and all people are like travellers whose only acquaintance with countries and nations is derived from the railway. An independent and cautious attitude of knowledge is looked upon almost as a kind of madness; the free spirit is brought into disrepute, chiefly through scholars, who miss their thoroughness and ant-like industry in his art of regarding things and would gladly banish him into one single corner of science, while it has the different and higher mission of commanding the battalion rear-guard of scientific and learned men from an isolated[Pg 259] position, and showing them the ways and aims of culture. A song of lamentation such as that which has just been sung will probably have its own period, and will cease of its own accord on a forcible return of the genius of meditation.

Sorrow.—Perhaps the benefits of our time come with a backward trend and occasional undervaluing of the vita contemplativa. Yet, it must be admitted that our era lacks great moral thinkers; figures like Pascal, Epictetus, Seneca, and Plutarch are seldom read anymore, and work and productivity—previously aligned with the pursuit of Health—sometimes feel like an illness. Without the time to reflect and the calm to think, we no longer explore different perspectives but settle for simply despising them. As life speeds up, our minds and eyes acclimate to a narrow and distorted view, turning all of us into travelers whose only experience of countries and cultures comes from train rides. An independent and cautious approach to knowledge is often seen as a form of insanity; the free thinker is disparaged, especially by scholars, who miss the thoroughness and industriousness of his method of observation and would prefer to confine him to a small corner of academia. Meanwhile, this free spirit has the broader and more significant role of guiding the collective backline of scholars and scientists, helping them understand the paths and goals of culture. A lament like the one we’ve just expressed will likely have its time and will fade away with a strong resurgence of reflective thought.

283.

283.

The Chief Deficiency of Active People.—Active people are usually deficient in the higher activity, I mean individual activity. They are active as officials, merchants, scholars, that is as a species, but not as quite distinct separate and single individuals; in this respect they are idle. It is the misfortune of the active that their activity is almost always a little senseless. For instance, we must not ask the money-making banker the reason of his restless activity, it is foolish. The active roll as the stone rolls, according to the stupidity of mechanics. All mankind is divided, as it was at all times and is still, into slaves and freemen; for whoever has not two-thirds of his day for himself is a slave, be he otherwise whatever he likes, statesman, merchant, official, or scholar.

The Main Weakness of Active People.—Active individuals often lack a higher level of activity, specifically personal activity. They operate actively as officials, merchants, and scholars, meaning they engage as a group, but not as truly distinct and individual persons; in that sense, they are inactive. The downside for these active individuals is that their efforts often feel aimless. For example, asking a money-focused banker about the purpose of his relentless activity is pointless. They move about like a rolling stone, driven by the routine of mechanics. All of humanity has always been, and continues to be, divided into slaves and free people; anyone who doesn’t have two-thirds of their day for themselves is a slave, regardless of their role as a statesman, merchant, official, or scholar.

284.

284.

In Favour of the Idle.—As a sign that the value of a contemplative life has decreased, scholars now vie with active people in a sort of hurried enjoyment, so that they appear to value this mode of enjoying more than that which really pertains to them, and which, as a matter of fact, is a far greater enjoyment. Scholars are[Pg 260] ashamed of otium. But there is one noble thing about idleness and idlers. If idleness is really the beginning of all vice, it finds itself, therefore, at least in near neighbourhood of all the virtues; the idle man is still a better man than the active. You do not suppose that in speaking of idleness and idlers I am alluding to you, you sluggards?

In Support of the Lazy.—As proof that the value of a thoughtful life has declined, scholars now compete with busy people in a kind of frantic enjoyment, making it seem like they value this way of enjoying life more than the one that truly suits them, which, in reality, offers much greater enjoyment. Scholars are[Pg 260] embarrassed about otium. However, there is something admirable about idleness and idlers. If idleness is indeed the beginning of all vice, it is also, therefore, at least in close proximity to all the virtues; the idle person is still a better person than the active one. You don’t think I’m referring to you, do you, you lazy folks?

285.

285.

Modern Unrest.—Modern restlessness increases towards the west, so that Americans look upon the inhabitants of Europe as altogether peace-loving and enjoying beings, whilst in reality they swarm about like wasps and bees. This restlessness is so great that the higher culture cannot mature its fruits, it is as if the seasons followed each other too quickly. For lack of rest our civilisation is turning into a new barbarism. At no period have the active, that is, the restless, been of more importance. One of the necessary corrections, therefore, which must be undertaken in the character of humanity is to strengthen the contemplative element on a large scale. But every individual who is quiet and steady in heart and head already has the right to believe that he possesses not only a good temperament, but also a generally useful virtue, and even fulfils a higher mission by the preservation of this virtue.

Current Unrest.—Modern restlessness is growing stronger in the west, leading Americans to see Europeans as completely peaceful and content, when in reality they buzz around like wasps and bees. This restlessness is so intense that our higher culture struggles to bear fruit; it feels like the seasons are changing too fast. Our civilization, lacking in rest, is devolving into a new form of barbarism. At no time has the active, or restless, been more significant. Therefore, one necessary change that humanity needs to undertake is to broadly enhance the contemplative aspect. However, anyone who is calm and steady in heart and mind already has a valid reason to feel they not only have a good temperament but also possess a valuable virtue, fulfilling a higher purpose by preserving this virtue.

286.

286.

To What Extent the Active Man Is Lazy.—I believe that every one must have his[Pg 261] own opinion about everything concerning which opinions are possible, because he himself is a peculiar, unique thing, which assumes towards all other things a new and never hitherto existing attitude. But idleness, which lies at the bottom of the active man's soul, prevents him from drawing water out of his own well. Freedom of opinion is like health; both are individual, and no good general conception can be set up of either of them. That which is necessary for the health of one individual is the cause of disease in another, and many means and ways to the freedom of the spirit are for more highly developed natures the ways and means to confinement.

To What Degree the Active Person Is Lazy.—I believe everyone has their[Pg 261] own take on everything that invites opinions, because each person is a unique individual, creating a fresh and previously nonexistent perspective towards all things. However, the laziness that exists deep within the active man's soul prevents him from tapping into his own potential. Freedom of opinion is similar to health; both are personal, and it’s impossible to establish a solid general definition for either. What is necessary for one person’s health can lead to illness in another, and many paths that offer spiritual freedom can confine those who are more evolved.

287.

287.

Censor Vitæ—Alternations of love and hatred for a long period distinguish the inward condition of a man who desires to be free in his judgment of life; he does not forget, and bears everything a grudge, for good and evil. At last, when the whole tablet of his soul is written full of experiences, he will not hate and despise existence, neither will he love it, but will regard it sometimes with a joyful, sometimes with a sorrowful eye, and, like nature, will be now in a summer and now in an autumn mood.

Life's Censor—For a long time, a mix of love and hate characterizes the inner state of a person who wants to have the freedom to judge life. They remember everything and hold onto grudges about both the good and the bad. Eventually, when every experience is etched into their soul, they won’t entirely hate or despise life, nor will they fully love it. Instead, they will sometimes look at it with joy and at other times with sadness, shifting like nature between summer and autumn moods.

288.

288.

The Secondary Result.—Whoever earnestly desires to be free will therewith and without any compulsion lose all inclination for faults and vices; he will also be more rarely overcome by anger and[Pg 262] vexation. His will desires nothing more urgently than to discern, and the means to do this,—that is, the permanent condition in which he is best able to discern.

The Secondary Outcome.—Anyone who truly wants to be free will naturally and without pressure let go of all tendencies toward faults and vices; they will also be less frequently overtaken by anger and[Pg 262] annoyance. Their will seeks nothing more than to understand, and the way to achieve this—that is, the ongoing state in which they can best understand.

289.

289.

The Value of Disease.—The man who is bed-ridden often perceives that he is usually ill of his position, business, or society, and through them has lost all self-possession. He gains this piece of knowledge from the idleness to which his illness condemns him.

The Value of Illness.—The person who is stuck in bed often realizes that he is usually troubled by his situation, work, or social life, and as a result, he has lost all sense of control. He comes to this understanding during the inactivity that his illness forces upon him.

290.

290.

Sensitiveness in the Country.—If there are no firm, quiet lines on the horizon of his life, a species of mountain and forest line, man's inmost will itself becomes restless, inattentive, and covetous, as is the nature of a dweller in towns; he has no happiness and confers no happiness.

Sensitivity in the Country.—If there are no solid, peaceful lines on the horizon of his life, like a mountain and forest backdrop, a person's deepest desires become restless, distracted, and greedy, just like someone living in a city; they find no happiness and spread none to others.

291.

291.

Prudence of the Free Spirits.—Free-thinkers, those who live by knowledge alone, will soon attain the supreme aim of their life and their ultimate position towards society and State, and will gladly content themselves, for instance, with a small post or an income that is just sufficient to enable them to live; for they will arrange to live in such a manner that a great change of outward prosperity, even an overthrow of the political order, would not cause an overthrow of their life. To all these things they devote as little energy as[Pg 263] possible in order that with their whole accumulated strength, and with a long breath, they may dive into the element of knowledge. Thus they can hope to dive deep and be able to see the bottom. Such a spirit seizes only the point of an event, he does not care for things in the whole breadth and prolixity of their folds, for he does not wish to entangle himself in them. He, too, knows the weekdays of restraint, of dependence and servitude. But from time to time there must dawn for him a Sunday of liberty, otherwise he could not endure life. It is probable that even his love for humanity will be prudent and somewhat short-winded, for he desires to meddle with the world of inclinations and of blindness only as far as is necessary for the purpose of knowledge. He must trust that the genius of justice will say something for its disciple and protege if accusing voices were to call him poor in love. In his mode of life and thought there is a refined heroism, which scorns to offer itself to the great mob-reverence, as its coarser brother does, and passes quietly through and out of the world. Whatever labyrinths it traverses, beneath whatever rocks its stream has occasionally worked its way—when it reaches the light it goes clearly, easily, and almost noiselessly on its way, and lets the sunshine strike down to its very bottom.

Wisdom of the Free Spirits.—Free-thinkers, those who rely solely on knowledge, will quickly reach the ultimate goal of their lives and their place in society and the state. They will be satisfied, for example, with a small job or just enough income to get by, as they will arrange their lives in such a way that even a significant change in their external circumstances or a complete political upheaval won't disrupt their way of living. They invest as little energy as[Pg 263]possible in these matters so that they can focus their entire strength, with great endurance, on diving into the realm of knowledge. This way, they can hope to dive deep and clearly see what lies below. Such a spirit only grabs onto the essence of an event, avoiding the complexities and endless details because he doesn’t want to get caught up in them. He, too, understands the everyday life of restraint, dependence, and servitude. But now and then, he needs a Sunday of freedom, or else he won't be able to bear life. It’s likely that his love for humanity is cautious and somewhat limited, as he wishes to engage with the world of desires and ignorance only as much as necessary for the sake of knowledge. He must trust that the spirit of justice will speak favorably of him if he is ever accused of lacking love. In his way of living and thinking, there is a refined heroism, which refuses to bow to the masses' reverence, unlike its coarser counterpart, and instead quietly passes through and beyond the world. No matter what paths it navigates or what obstacles it encounters—when it finally emerges into the light, it flows clearly, effortlessly, and almost silently, allowing sunlight to shine down to its very depths.

292.

292.

Forward.—And thus forward upon the path of wisdom, with a firm step and good confidence! However you may be situated, serve yourself as a[Pg 264] source of experience! Throw off the displeasure at your nature, forgive yourself your own individuality, for in any case you have in yourself a ladder with a hundred steps upon which you can mount to knowledge. The age into which with grief you feel yourself thrown thinks you happy because of this good fortune; it calls out to you that you shall still have experiences which men of later ages will perhaps be obliged to forego. Do not despise the fact of having been religious; consider fully how you have had a genuine access to art. Can you not, with the help of these experiences, follow immense stretches of former humanity with a clearer understanding? Is not that ground which sometimes displeases you so greatly, that ground of clouded thought, precisely the one upon which have grown many of the most glorious fruits of older civilisations? You must have loved religion and art as you loved mother and nurse,—otherwise you cannot be wise. But you must be able to see beyond them, to outgrow them; if you, remain under their ban you do not understand them. You must also be familiar with history and that cautious play with the balances: "On the one hand—on the other hand." Go back, treading in the footsteps made by mankind in its great and painful journey through the desert of the past, and you will learn most surely whither it is that all later humanity never can or may go again. And inasmuch as you wish with all your strength to see in advance how the knots of the future are tied, your own life acquires the value of an instrument and means of knowledge. It is within your[Pg 265] power to see that all you have experienced, trials, errors, faults, deceptions, passions, your love and your hope, shall be merged wholly in your aim. This aim is to become a necessary chain of culture-links yourself, and from this necessity to draw a conclusion as to the necessity in the progress of general culture. When your sight has become strong enough to see to the bottom of the dark well of your nature and your knowledge, it is possible that in its mirror you may also behold the far-away visions of future civilisations. Do you think that such a life with such an aim is too wearisome, too empty of all that is agreeable? Then you have still to learn that no honey is sweeter than that of knowledge, and that the overhanging clouds of trouble must be to you as an udder from which you shall draw milk for your refreshment. And only when old age approaches will you rightly perceive how you listened to the voice of nature, that nature which rules the whole world through pleasure; the same life which has its zenith in age has also its zenith in wisdom, in that mild sunshine of a constant mental joyfulness; you meet them both, old age and wisdom, upon one ridge of life,—it was thus intended by Nature. Then it is time, and no cause for anger, that the mists of death approach. Towards the light is your last movement; a joyful cry of knowledge is your last sound.

Next.—So, move forward on the path of wisdom, with confidence and purpose! No matter your situation, use yourself as a[Pg 264] source of experience! Let go of any frustration with your nature, forgive your unique self, because within you lies a ladder with a hundred steps leading to knowledge. The era you find yourself in, which you may dread, considers you fortunate; it tells you that you will have experiences that future generations might miss out on. Don’t underestimate having been spiritual; reflect on how you’ve genuinely engaged with art. Can you not, through these experiences, grasp vast elements of human history with greater clarity? Isn’t the difficult ground of muddled thoughts the very soil from which many remarkable achievements of past civilizations grew? You must have cherished religion and art as you would your mother and caretaker—otherwise, wisdom eludes you. Yet, you need to see beyond them, to rise above them; if you remain trapped by their influence, you do not truly understand them. You must also know history and engage in the careful weighing of perspectives: "On one hand—on the other hand." Retrace the steps taken by humanity in its arduous journey through the past’s desert, and you will surely learn where later generations can never tread again. As you earnestly wish to foresee how the future unfolds, your life becomes an invaluable tool for understanding. It is within your[Pg 265] ability to ensure that all you’ve experienced—challenges, mistakes, flaws, deceptions, passions, love, and hope—are fully integrated into your purpose. This purpose is to become a vital link in the cultural chain, drawing necessary conclusions about the development of culture as a whole. When your insight becomes keen enough to peer deeply into the well of your own nature and knowledge, you might see reflections of future civilizations in that mirror. Do you believe such a life with such a purpose is too tiresome or devoid of pleasure? Then you must still learn that no sweetness compares to that of knowledge, and the looming clouds of challenges should serve as a source from which you draw sustenance. Only when old age approaches will you truly understand how you listened to the voice of nature, the same nature that governs the world through joy; the life that peaks in old age also reaches its height in wisdom, offering the gentle warmth of enduring mental happiness; you will find both old age and wisdom on the same path of life—it was the intention of Nature. At that point, it is time, and no reason for resentment, when the mists of death draw near. Toward the light is your final move; a joyful cry of knowledge is your last sound.


[1] This may remind one of Gobineau's more jocular saying: "Nous ne descendons pas du singe, mais nous y allons."—J.M.K.

[1] This may bring to mind Gobineau's more humorous remark: "We don't descend from monkeys, but we're definitely heading that way."—J.M.K.

[2] This refers to his essay, "Schopenhauer as Educator," in Thoughts Out of Season, vol. ii. of the English edition.—J.M.K.

[2] This refers to his essay, "Schopenhauer as Educator," in Thoughts Out of Season, vol. ii. of the English edition.—J.M.K.

[3] For it is when loving that mortal man gives of his best.—J.M.K.

[3] For it is when he loves that a mortal man gives his best.—J.M.K.


SIXTH DIVISION.

MAN IN SOCIETY.

293.

293.

Well-meant Dissimulation.—In intercourse with men a well-meant dissimulation is often necessary, as if we did not see through the motives of their actions.

Good intentions, hidden motives.—In interactions with others, it’s often necessary to pretend to be unaware of the true motives behind their actions.

294.

294.

Copies.—We not unfrequently meet with copies of prominent persons; and as in the case of pictures, so also here, the copies please more than the originals.

Copies.—We often come across copies of famous people; and just like with pictures, these copies often appeal more than the originals do.

295.

295.

The Public Speaker.—One may speak with the greatest appropriateness, and yet so that everybody cries out to the contrary,—that is to say, when one does not speak to everybody.

The Speaker.—One can speak very appropriately, and still have everyone disagree—that is, when one doesn't address everyone.

296.

296.

Want of Confidence.—Want of confidence among friends is a fault that cannot be censured without becoming incurable.

Low self-esteem.—A lack of confidence among friends is a problem that can't be criticized without becoming permanent.

297.

297.

The Art of Giving.—To have to refuse a gift, merely because it has not been offered in the right way, provokes animosity against the giver.

The Art of Giving.—Having to turn down a gift just because it wasn't given in the right manner creates resentment toward the giver.

298.

298.

The Most Dangerous Partisan.—In every party there is one who, by his far too dogmatic expression of the party-principles, excites defection among the others.

The Most Dangerous Partisan.—In every political party, there's always someone whose overly rigid expression of the party's principles causes others to rebel.

299.

299.

Advisers of the Sick.—Whoever gives advice to a sick person acquires a feeling of superiority over him, whether the advice be accepted or rejected. Hence proud and sensitive sick persons hate advisers more than their sickness.

Advisers for the Sick.—Anyone who gives advice to a sick person gains a sense of superiority over them, regardless of whether the advice is accepted or rejected. As a result, proud and sensitive sick individuals dislike advisers even more than their illness.

300.

300.

Double Nature of Equality.—The rage for equality may so manifest itself that we seek either to draw all others down to ourselves (by belittling, disregarding, and tripping up), or ourselves and all others upwards (by recognition, assistance, and congratulation).

Dual Nature of Equality.—The obsession with equality can show itself in two ways: we might try to bring everyone down to our level (by belittling, ignoring, and sabotaging), or we might strive to lift ourselves and everyone else up (through recognition, support, and praise).

301.

301.

Against Embarrassment.—The best way to relieve and calm very embarrassed people is to give them decided praise.

Defying Embarrassment.—The best way to ease and comfort people who are really embarrassed is to offer them clear praise.

302.

302.

Preference For Certain Virtues.—We set no special value on the possession of a virtue until we perceive that it is entirely lacking in our adversary.

Preference for Specific Virtues.—We don’t really appreciate a virtue until we notice that our opponent completely lacks it.

303.

303.

Why We Contradict.—We often contradict an opinion when it is really only the tone in which it is expressed that is unsympathetic to us.

Why We Disagree.—We often disagree with an opinion when it's actually just the way it's expressed that rubs us the wrong way.

304.

304.

Confidence and Intimacy.—Whoever proposes to command the intimacy of a person is usually uncertain of possessing his confidence. Whoever is sure of a person's confidence attaches little value to intimacy with him.

Confidence and Connection.—Anyone who tries to gain someone's trust usually doubts that they have it. Those who are confident of a person's trust don’t place much importance on being close with them.

305.

305.

The Equilibrium of Friendship.—The right equilibrium of friendship in our relation to other men is sometimes restored when we put a few grains of wrong on our own side of the scales.

The Balance of Friendship.—The proper balance of friendship in our relationships with others is sometimes achieved when we add a few grains of fault on our own side of the scales.

306.

306.

The Most Dangerous Physicians.—The most dangerous physicians are those who, like born actors, imitate the born physician with the perfect art of imposture.

The Most Dangerous Doctors.—The most dangerous doctors are the ones who, like natural actors, perfectly imitate the skills of a true physician with the art of deception.

307.

307.

When Paradoxes Are Permissible.—In order to interest clever persons in a theory, it is sometimes only necessary to put it before them in the form of a prodigious paradox.

When Paradoxes Are Allowed.—To capture the interest of smart people in a theory, it can often be enough to present it as an astonishing paradox.

308.

308.

How Courageous People Are Won Over.—Courageous people are persuaded to a course of action by representing it as more dangerous than it really is.

How Brave People Are Persuaded.—Courageous people are convinced to take action by making it seem more dangerous than it actually is.

309.

309.

Courtesies.—We regard the courtesies show us by unpopular persons as offences.

Politeness.—We consider the kindnesses shown to us by unpopular people as offenses.

310.

310.

Keeping People Waiting.—A sure way of exasperating people and of putting bad thoughts into their heads is to keep them waiting long. That makes them immoral.

Waiting on People.—A guaranteed way to frustrate people and make them think negatively is to make them wait for a long time. That drives them to act unethically.

311.

311.

Against the Confidential.—Persons who give us their full confidence think they hay thereby a right to ours. That is a mistake people acquire no rights through gifts.

Against the Confidential.—People who place their complete trust in us believe they have a claim to our trust in return. That’s a misunderstanding; individuals don’t gain rights through acts of generosity.

312.

312.

A Mode of Settlement.—It often suffices to give a person whom we have injured an opportunity to make a joke about us to give him[Pg 271] personal satisfaction, and even to make him favourably disposed to us.

A Way to Settle.—It often just takes giving someone we've hurt a chance to make a joke at our expense to provide him[Pg 271] personal satisfaction, and even to make him more positively inclined towards us.

313.

313.

The Vanity of the Tongue.—Whether man conceals his bad qualities and vices, or frankly acknowledges them, his vanity in either case seeks its advantage thereby,—only let it be observed how nicely he distinguishes those from whom he conceals such qualities from those with whom he is frank and honest.

The Vanity of Words.—Whether a person hides their flaws and vices or openly admits to them, their vanity, in either situation, aims to benefit from it—just notice how well they distinguish between those from whom they hide such qualities and those with whom they are straightforward and honest.

314.

314.

Considerate.—To have no wish to offend or injure any one may as well be the sign of a just as of a timid nature.

Thoughtful.—Not wanting to offend or hurt anyone can show either a fair-minded or a shy personality.

315.

315.

Requisite For Disputation.—He who cannot put his thoughts on ice should not enter into the heat of dispute.

Requirement for Debate.—A person who can't keep their cool shouldn't engage in a heated argument.

316.

316.

Intercourse and Pretension.—We forget our pretensions when we are always conscious of being amongst meritorious people; being alone implants presumption in us. The young are pretentious, for they associate with their equals, who are all ciphers but would fain have a great significance.

Hookup Culture and Pretense.—We lose our pretensions when we are constantly aware of being around deserving people; being alone makes us arrogant. Young people tend to be pretentious because they hang out with their peers, who are all nobodies but desperately want to feel important.

317.

317.

Motives of an Attack.—One does not attack a person merely to hurt and conquer him, but perhaps merely to become conscious of one's own strength.

Reasons for an Attack.—You don’t attack someone just to hurt or defeat them; sometimes it’s just to become aware of your own strength.

318.

318.

Flattery.—Persons who try by means of flattery to put us off our guard in intercourse with them, employ a dangerous expedient, like a sleeping-draught, which, when it does not send the patient to sleep, keeps him all the wider awake.

Compliments.—People who try to use flattery to lower our defenses in their interactions with us are using a risky tactic, like a sedative that, instead of making the patient sleep, only makes them more alert.

319.

319.

A Good Letter-writer.—A person who does not write books, thinks much, and lives in unsatisfying society, will usually be a good letter-writer.

A great letter writer.—Someone who doesn’t write books, thinks a lot, and is part of an unfulfilling social scene will typically be a good letter-writer.

320.

320.

The Ugliest of All.—It may be doubted whether a person who has travelled much has found anywhere in the world uglier places than those to be met with in the human face.

The Ugliest of All.—One might question if a person who has traveled extensively has discovered anywhere in the world that is uglier than the places found in the human face.

321.

321.

The Sympathetic Ones.—Sympathetic natures, ever ready to help in misfortune, are seldom those that participate in joy; in the happiness of others they have nothing to occupy them, they are superfluous, they do not feel themselves in possession of their superiority, and hence readily show their displeasure.

The Kind Ones.—People with sympathetic natures, who are always prepared to help in tough times, are rarely the ones who share in happiness; when it comes to the joy of others, they have nothing to engage them, they feel unnecessary, they don't recognize their own superiority, and as a result, they quickly express their dissatisfaction.

322.

322.

The Relatives of a Suicide.—The relatives of a suicide take it in ill part that he did not remain alive out of consideration for their reputation.

The Family of a Suicide.—The relatives of a suicide feel upset that he didn't stay alive for the sake of their reputation.

323.

323.

Ingratitude Foreseen.—He who makes a large gift gets no gratitude; for the recipient is already overburdened by the acceptance of the gift.

Ingratitude Expected.—Someone who gives a big gift often receives no thanks; the person receiving it feels weighed down by having to accept such a large gift.

324.

324.

In Dull Society.—Nobody thanks a witty man for politeness when he puts himself on a par with a society in which it would not be polite to show one's wit.

In a Boring Society.—No one appreciates a witty person for being polite when they lower themselves to a society that wouldn’t consider it polite to display their cleverness.

325.

325.

The Presence of Witnesses.—We are doubly willing to jump into the water after some one who has fallen in, if there are people present who have not the courage to do so.

Witnesses Present.—We’re even more eager to jump into the water to save someone who has fallen in if there are people around who lack the courage to do it.

326.

326.

Being Silent.—For both parties in a controversy, the most disagreeable way of retaliating is to be vexed and silent; for the aggressor usually regards the silence as a sign of contempt.

Stay Quiet.—For both sides in a dispute, the worst way to respond is to get upset and stay silent; the person who started the conflict often sees the silence as a sign of disrespect.

327.

327.

Friends' Secrets.—Few people will not expose the private affairs of their friends when at a loss for a subject of conversation.

Friends' Secrets.—Few people can resist revealing their friends' private matters when they're struggling to find something to talk about.

328.

328.

Humanity.—The humanity of intellectual celebrities consists in courteously submitting to[Pg 274] unfairness in intercourse with those who are I not celebrated.

Humankind.—The humanity of intellectual celebrities lies in graciously accepting[Pg 274] unfairness in their interactions with those who are not famous.

329.

329.

The Embarrassed.—People who do not feel sure of themselves in society seize every opportunity of publicly showing their superiority to close friends, for instance by teasing them.

The Awkward.—People who lack confidence in social situations often take any chance to publicly demonstrate their superiority over close friends, such as by teasing them.

330.

330.

Thanks.—A refined nature is vexed by knowing that some one owes it thanks, a coarse nature by knowing that it owes thanks to some one.

You're welcome!.—A refined person feels annoyed knowing that someone is grateful to them, while a coarse person feels troubled knowing they need to show gratitude to someone.

331.

331.

A Sign of Estrangement.—The surest sign of the estrangement of the opinions of two persons is when they both say something ironical to each other and neither of them feels the irony.

A Sign of Disconnection.—The clearest sign that two people have become estranged in their opinions is when they both say something ironic to one another and neither of them realizes the irony.

332.

332.

Presumption in Connection With Merit.—Presumption in connection with merit offends us even more than presumption in persons devoid of merit, for merit in itself offends us.

Assumption About Merit.—Presumption related to merit bothers us even more than presumption about people without merit, because merit itself bothers us.

333.

333.

Danger in the Voice.—In conversation we are sometimes confused by the tone of our own voice, and misled to make assertions that do not at all correspond to our opinions.

Danger in the Voice.—In conversation, we can sometimes get confused by the tone of our own voice and are led to make statements that don't really reflect our true opinions.

334.

334.

In Conversation.—Whether in conversation with others we mostly agree or mostly disagree with them is a matter of habit; there is sense in both cases.

Chatting.—Whether we mostly agree or disagree with others in conversation comes down to habit; there’s logic in both situations.

335.

335.

Fear of Our Neighbour.—We are afraid of the animosity of our neighbour, because we are apprehensive that he may thereby discover our secrets.

Fear of Our Neighbor.—We fear our neighbor's hostility because we're worried he might uncover our secrets.

336.

336.

Distinguishing by Blaming.—Highly respected persons distribute even their blame in such fashion that they try to distinguish us therewith. It is intended to remind us of their serious interest in us. We misunderstand them entirely when we take their blame literally and protest against it; we thereby offend them and estrange ourselves from them.

Blame and Distinguish.—Well-respected people often share their criticism in a way that aims to highlight our differences. It's meant to show their genuine concern for us. We completely misunderstand them when we take their criticism at face value and respond negatively; we end up upsetting them and creating distance between ourselves and them.

337.

337.

Indignation at the Goodwill of Others.—We are mistaken as to the extent to which we think we are hated or feared; because,' though we ourselves know very well the extent of our divergence from a person, tendency, or party, those others know us only superficially, and can, therefore, only hate us superficially. We often meet with goodwill which is inexplicable to us; but when we comprehend it, it shocks us, because it shows that we are not considered with sufficient Seriousness or importance.

Feeling annoyed by the kindness of others.—We often overestimate how much we are hated or feared. Even though we are keenly aware of how different we are from others—people, groups, or parties—those others only know us on a surface level, so they can only dislike us on a surface level too. We frequently encounter kindness that we can't understand, but when we finally grasp it, it surprises us because it reveals that we aren't taken as seriously or as important as we thought.

338.

338.

Thwarting Vanities.—When two persons meet whose vanity is equally great, they have afterwards a bad impression of each other because each has been so occupied with the impression he wished to produce on the other that the other has made no impression upon him; at last it becomes clear to them both that their efforts have been in vain, and each puts the blame on the other.

Avoiding Ego Trips.—When two people meet who are both very vain, they end up with a negative impression of each other because each is so focused on the impression they want to leave that they don’t really impact the other at all; eventually, they both realize their efforts were pointless, and each blames the other.

339.

339.

Improper Behaviour As a Good Sign.—A superior mind takes pleasure in the tactlessness, pretentiousness, and even hostility of ambitious youths; it is the vicious habit of fiery horses which have not yet carried a rider, but, in a short time, will be so proud to carry one.

Misbehavior as a Positive Indicator.—A strong mind finds enjoyment in the awkwardness, showiness, and even aggression of driven young people; it's like the wild nature of spirited horses that haven't been ridden yet, but soon will be eager to carry a rider.

340.

340.

When It Is Advisable to Suffer Wrong.—It is well to put up with accusations without refutation, even when they injure us, when the accuser would see a still greater fault on our part if we contradicted and perhaps even refuted him. In this way, certainly, a person may always be wronged and always have right on his side, and may eventually, with the best conscience in the world, become the most intolerable tyrant and tormentor; and what happens in the individual may also take place in whole classes of society.

When It's Wise to Endure Injustice.—It’s wise to deal with accusations without trying to defend ourselves, even if they hurt us, when the accuser would perceive an even bigger flaw in us if we contradict them or even prove them wrong. In this way, a person can always be mistreated while still being in the right and can eventually, with a clear conscience, become the most unbearable tyrant and tormentor. What happens to an individual can also occur to entire groups in society.

341.

341.

Too Little Honoured.—Very conceited persons, who have received less consideration than they expected, attempt for a long time to deceive themselves and others with regard to it, and become subtle psychologists in order to make out that they have been amply honoured. Should they not attain their aim, should the veil of deception be torn, they give way to all the greater fury.

Underrated.—Superficially confident people, who feel they've received less respect than they anticipated, spend a long time trying to convince themselves and others otherwise, becoming skilled at justifying that they've been well honored. If they don't achieve this goal and their deception is revealed, they fall into an even greater rage.

342.

342.

Primitive Conditions Re—echoing in Speech.—By the manner in which people make assertions in their intercourse we often recognise an echo of the times when they were more conversant with weapons than anything else; sometimes they handle their assertions like sharp-shooters using their arms, sometimes we think we hear the whizz and clash of swords, and with some men an assertion crashes down like a stout cudgel. Women, on the contrary, speak like beings who for thousands of years have sat at the loom, plied the needle, or played the child with children.

Basic Conditions Re—echoing in Speech.—The way people make claims in conversation often reminds us of a time when they were more familiar with weapons than anything else; sometimes they deliver their claims like sharpshooters using their rifles, at times we can almost hear the swoosh and clash of swords, and with some men, a claim hits hard like a heavy club. Women, on the other hand, speak like those who have spent thousands of years at the loom, sewing with a needle, or playing with children.

343.

343.

The Narrator.—He who gives an account of something readily betrays whether it is because the fact interests him, or because he wishes to excite interest by the narration. In the latter case he will exaggerate, employ superlatives, and such like. He then does not usually tell his story[Pg 278] so well, because he does not think so much about his subject as about himself.

The Narrator.—When someone tells a story, it's pretty obvious if they’re genuinely interested in the subject or just trying to grab attention with their storytelling. In the second case, they tend to exaggerate and use over-the-top expressions. As a result, their storytelling isn't usually that effective because they focus more on themselves than on the actual topic.[Pg 278]

344.

344.

The Reciter.—He who recites dramatic works makes discoveries about his own character; he finds his voice more natural in certain moods and scenes than in others, say in the pathetic or in the scurrilous, while in ordinary life, perhaps, he has not had the opportunity to exhibit pathos or scurrility.

The Speaker.—A person who performs dramatic works learns about their own character; they discover that their voice feels more genuine in specific moods and scenes than in others, like when expressing sadness or humor, while in everyday life, they might not have had the chance to show sadness or humor.

345.

345.

A Comedy Scene in Real Life.—Some one conceives an ingenious idea on a theme in order to express it in society. Now in a comedy we should hear and see how he sets all sail for that point, and tries to land the company at the place where he can make his remark, how he continuously pushes the conversation towards the one goal, sometimes losing the way, finding it again, and finally arriving at the moment: he is almost breathless—and then one of the company takes the remark itself out of his mouth! What will he do? Oppose his own opinion?

A Funny Scene in Real Life.—Someone comes up with a clever idea on a topic to share with others. In a comedy, we would watch and listen as he navigates his way to that point and tries to guide everyone to where he can make his point, constantly steering the conversation toward that one outcome, sometimes losing his way, finding it again, and finally reaching the moment: he’s nearly out of breath—and then one of the group steals his punchline! What will he do? Disagree with his own opinion?

346.

346.

Unintentionally Discourteous.—When a person treats another with unintentional discourtesy,—for instance, not greeting him because not recognising him,—he is vexed by it, although he cannot reproach his own sentiments; he is hurt by the bad opinion which he has produced[Pg 279] in the other person, or fears the consequences of his bad humour, or is pained by the thought of having injured him,—vanity, fear, or pity may therefore be aroused; perhaps all three together.

Unintentionally Rude.—When someone treats another with unintended disrespect—like not greeting them because they didn’t recognize them—they feel upset about it, even though they can't blame their own feelings. They're hurt by the poor impression they've created[Pg 279] in the other person, or they're concerned about the outcomes of their bad mood, or they feel pain at the idea of having harmed them. This situation can trigger feelings of vanity, fear, or pity—possibly all three at once.

347.

347.

A Masterpiece of Treachery.—To express a tantalising distrust of a fellow-conspirator, lest he should betray one, and this at the very moment when one is practising treachery one's self, is a masterpiece of wickedness; because it absorbs the other's attention and compels him for a time to act very unsuspiciously and openly, so that the real traitor has thus acquired a free hand.

A Masterpiece of Betrayal.—Expressing a tempting distrust of a fellow conspirator, to prevent him from betraying you, especially while you're plotting treachery yourself, is a true work of wickedness; it distracts the other person and forces him to behave in a very trusting and open manner, giving the real traitor the freedom to act.

348.

348.

To Injure and to Be Injured.—It is far pleasanter to injure and afterwards beg for forgiveness than to be injured and grant forgiveness. He who does the former gives evidence of power and afterwards of kindness of character. The person injured, however, if he does not wish to be considered inhuman, must forgive; his enjoyment of the other's humiliation is insignificant on account of this constraint.

To Hurt and to Be Hurt.—It’s much more enjoyable to hurt someone and then ask for forgiveness than to be the one who gets hurt and has to forgive. The person who hurts others shows strength and later reveals kindness. However, the one who has been hurt, if they don’t want to seem heartless, must forgive; their pleasure in the other person’s humiliation is minimal because of this obligation.

349.

349.

In a Dispute.—When we contradict another's opinion and at the same time develop our own, the constant consideration of the other opinion usually disturbs the natural attitude of our own[Pg 280] which appears more intentional, more distinct, and perhaps somewhat exaggerated.

In a Disagreement.—When we challenge someone else's opinion while expressing our own, constantly thinking about their viewpoint often interferes with our natural stance. Our opinion ends up seeming more calculated, clearer, and maybe a bit over the top. [Pg 280]

350.

350.

An Artifice.—He who wants to get another to do something difficult must on no account treat the matter as a problem, but must set forth his plan plainly as the only one possible; and when the adversary's eye betrays objection and opposition he must understand how to break off quickly, and allow him no time to put in a word.

A Trick.—If you want someone to do something challenging, you should never treat it like a problem. Instead, you should present your plan straightforwardly as the only viable option. And when the other person shows signs of disagreement or resistance, you should know how to cut the conversation short and not give them a chance to respond.

351.

351.

Pricks of Conscience After Social Gatherings.—Why does our conscience prick us after ordinary social gatherings? Because we have treated serious things lightly, because in talking of persons we have not spoken quite justly or have been silent when we should have spoken, because, sometimes, we have not jumped up and run away,—in short, because we have behaved in society as if we belonged to it.

Pricks of Conscience After Social Events.—Why does our conscience nag us after regular social events? It's because we've taken important matters too casually, because when discussing others, we haven't been entirely fair or have stayed quiet when we should have spoken up, and because sometimes, we haven't just gotten up and left—basically, because we've acted in social situations as if we truly belonged there.

352.

352.

We Are Misjudged.—He who always listens to hear how he is judged is always vexed. For we are misjudged even by those who are nearest to us ("who know us best"). Even good friends sometimes vent their ill-humour in a spiteful word; and would they be our friends if they knew us rightly? The judgments of the indifferent[Pg 281] wound us deeply, because they sound so impartial, so objective almost. But when we see that some one hostile to us knows us in a concealed point as well as we know ourselves, how great is then our vexation!

We're Misunderstood.—The person who constantly pays attention to how others judge them is always frustrated. We are often misjudged, even by those closest to us ("who know us best"). Even good friends sometimes express their irritation through a hurtful comment; would they still be our friends if they truly understood us? The opinions of those who are indifferent[Pg 281] hurt us deeply because they seem so fair, so unbiased. But when we realize that someone who dislikes us understands a hidden part of us just as well as we do, our frustration increases significantly!

353.

353.

The Tyranny of the Portrait.—Artists and statesmen, who out of particular features quickly construct the whole picture of a man or an event, are mostly unjust in demanding that the event or person should afterwards be actually as they have painted it; they demand straightway that a man should be just as gifted, cunning, and unjust as he is in their representation of him.

The Tyranny of the Portrait.—Artists and politicians, who often build a complete image of a person or event from just a few specific traits, are usually unfair when they expect that the reality should match their depiction. They immediately insist that a person should be as talented, clever, and unjust as they have portrayed them.

354.

354.

Relatives As the Best Friends.—The Greeks, who knew so well what a friend was, they alone of all peoples have a profound and largely philosophical discussion of friendship; so that it is by them firstly (and as yet lastly) that the problem of the friend has been recognised as worthy of solution,—these same Greeks have designated relatives by an expression which is the superlative of the word "friend." This is inexplicable to me.

Relatives as Best Friends.—The Greeks, who understood friendship deeply, uniquely engaged in a profound and largely philosophical discussion about it. They were the first (and still the only ones) to recognize the complexities of friendship as worthy of exploration. Interestingly, these same Greeks refer to relatives using a term that is the highest form of the word "friend." This makes no sense to me.

355.

355.

Misunderstood Honesty.—When any one quotes himself in conversation ("I then said," "I am accustomed to say"), it gives the impression of presumption; whereas it often proceeds from[Pg 282] quite an opposite source; or at least from honesty, which does not wish to deck and adorn the present moment with wit which belongs to an earlier moment.

Misunderstood Truth.—When someone quotes themselves in a conversation ("I then said," "I usually say"), it can come off as arrogant; however, it often comes from[Pg 282] a completely different place; or at the very least, from honesty, which doesn’t want to embellish the present moment with cleverness that originally belongs to a past moment.

356.

356.

The Parasite.—It denotes entire absence of a noble disposition when a person prefers to live in dependence at the expense of others, usually with a secret bitterness against them, in order only that he may not be obliged to work. Such a disposition is far more frequent in women than in men, also far more pardonable (for historical reasons).

The Parasite.—It shows a total lack of noble character when someone chooses to rely on others for support, often harboring secret resentment towards them, just so they can avoid having to work. This attitude is much more common in women than in men, and it's also more forgivable (due to historical reasons).

357.

357.

On the Altar of Reconciliation.—There are circumstances under which one can only gain a point from a person by wounding him and becoming hostile; the feeling of having a foe torments him so much that he gladly seizes the first indication of a milder disposition to effect a reconciliation, and offers on the altar of this reconciliation what was formerly of such importance to him that he would not give it up at any price.

On the Altar of Forgiveness.—There are times when you can only get through to someone by hurting them and becoming adversarial; the discomfort of having an enemy bothers them so much that they eagerly jump at the first sign of a softer approach to make peace, offering up what was once so important to them that they wouldn't have given it up for anything.

358.

358.

Presumption in Demanding Pity.—There are people who, when they have been in a rage and have insulted others, demand, firstly, that it shall all be taken in good part; and, secondly, that they shall be pitied because they are subject to such violent paroxysms. So far does human presumption extend.

Entitlement in Seeking Sympathy.—There are people who, after losing their temper and insulting others, insist, first, that everyone should take it lightly; and second, that they should be pitied because they suffer from such intense outbursts. This is how far human arrogance goes.

359.

359.

Bait.—"Every man has his price"—that is not true. But perhaps every one can be found a bait of one kind or other at which he will snap. Thus, in order to gain some supporters for a cause, it is only necessary to give it the glamour of being philanthropic, noble, charitable, and self-denying—and to what cause could this glamour not be given! It is the sweetmeat and dainty of their soul; others have different ones.

Bait.—"Every person has a price"—that's not true. But maybe everyone can be tempted by some kind of bait that they'll bite on. So, to attract some supporters for a cause, you just need to make it sound philanthropic, noble, charitable, and selfless—and what cause couldn't wear that appeal? It's like the treat for their soul; others have different ones.

360.

360°

The Attitude in Praising.—When good friends praise a gifted person he often appears to be delighted with them out of politeness and goodwill, but in reality he feels indifferent. His real nature is quite unmoved towards them, and will not budge a step on that account out of the sun or shade in which it lies; but people wish to please by praise, and it would grieve them if one did not rejoice when they praise a person.

The Approach to Praise.—When close friends compliment a talented person, they often seem truly happy and appreciative out of politeness and goodwill, but in reality, they feel indifferent. Their true feelings are unaffected by the praise, and they won't change their position in response to it; however, people want to please through compliments, and it would upset them if someone didn’t seem happy when they praised another person.

361.

361.

The Experience of Socrates.—If one has become a master in one thing, one has generally remained, precisely thereby, a complete dunce in most other things; but one forms the very reverse opinion, as was already experienced by Socrates. This is the annoyance which makes association with masters disagreeable.

Socrates' Experience.—If someone becomes an expert in one area, they often end up being completely clueless in most other areas. However, people tend to think the opposite, as was already shown by Socrates. This is the frustration that makes being around experts unpleasant.

362.

362.

A Means of Defence.—In warring against stupidity, the most just and gentle of men at last become brutal. They are thereby, perhaps, taking the proper course for defence; for the most appropriate argument for a stupid brain is the clenched fist. But because, as has been said, their character is just and gentle, they suffer more by this means of protection than they injure their opponents by it.

A Way to Defend.—In fighting against ignorance, even the kindest and most fair-minded people can become harsh. They might be choosing the right way to defend themselves since the best argument for a foolish mind is a clenched fist. However, because they are inherently just and gentle, they end up hurting themselves more with this method of protection than they harm their adversaries.

363.

363.

Curiosity.—If curiosity did not exist, very little would be done for the good of our neighbour. But curiosity creeps into the houses of the unfortunate and the needy under the name of duty or of pity. Perhaps there is a good deal of curiosity even in the much-vaunted maternal love.

Curiosity.—If curiosity didn't exist, not much would be done to help our neighbors. But curiosity sneaks into the homes of those who are unfortunate and in need, disguised as duty or pity. There might even be a lot of curiosity in the so-called maternal love that people praise.

364.

364.

Disappointment in Society.—One man wishes to be interesting for his opinions, another for his likes and dislikes, a third for his acquaintances, and a fourth for his solitariness—and they all meet with disappointment. For he before whom the play is performed thinks himself the only play that is to be taken into account.

Disappointment with Society.—One person wants to be intriguing because of their opinions, another because of their preferences, a third because of their connections, and a fourth because of their solitude—and they all end up feeling let down. The audience member thinks they are the only act that matters in the performance.

365.

365

The Duel.—It may be said in favour of duels and all affairs of honour that if a man has such[Pg 285] susceptible feelings that he does not care to live when So-and-so says or thinks this or that about him; he has a right to make it a question of the death of the one or the other. With regard to the fact that he is so susceptible, it is not at all to be remonstrated with, in that matter we are the heirs of the past, of its greatness as well as of its exaggerations, without which no greatness ever existed. So when there exists a code of honour which lets blood stand in place of death, so that the mind is relieved after a regular duel it is a great blessing, because otherwise many human lives would be in danger. Such an institution, moreover, teaches men to be cautious in their utterances and makes intercourse with them possible.

The Showdown.—It can be argued in favor of duels and all matters of honor that if a man has such[Pg 285] sensitive feelings that he feels he can't go on living when someone says or thinks something about him, he has the right to make it a question of one person's life or the other’s. As for the fact that he is so sensitive, it’s not really something to be criticized; we are the heirs to the past, with all its greatness and its exaggerations, which are essential for any greatness to exist. So when there’s a code of honor that allows for bloodshed in place of death, and brings relief to the mind after a proper duel, it's a significant benefit, because otherwise many lives would be at risk. This kind of institution also teaches men to be careful with their words and makes it possible to interact with them.

366.

366.

Nobleness and Gratitude.—A noble soul will be pleased to owe gratitude, and will not anxiously avoid opportunities of coming under obligation; it will also be moderate afterwards in the expression of its gratitude: baser souls, on the other hand, are unwilling to be under any obligation, or are afterwards immoderate in their expressions of thanks and altogether too devoted. The latter is, moreover, also the case with persons of mean origin or depressed circumstances; to show them a favour seems to them a miracle of grace.

Nobility and Gratitude.—A noble person enjoys feeling grateful and doesn't shy away from opportunities to be indebted; they will also express their gratitude in a balanced way afterward. In contrast, those with less noble character are hesitant to be in anyone's debt or are overly emotional in their thanks, going to extremes in showing their devotion. This is also true for people from humble beginnings or tough situations; receiving a favor feels to them like a miraculous act of kindness.

367.

367.

Occasions of Eloquence.—In order to talk well one man needs a person who is decidedly and[Pg 286] avowedly his superior to talk to, while another can only find absolute freedom of speech and happy turns of eloquence before one who is his inferior. In both cases the cause is the same; each of them talks well only when he talks sans gêne—the one because in the presence of something higher he does not feel the impulse of rivalry and competition, the other because he also lacks the same impulse in the presence of something lower. Now there is quite another type of men, who talk well only when debating, with the intention of conquering. Which of the two types is the more aspiring: the one that talks well from excited ambition, or the one that talks badly or not at all from precisely the same motive?

Eloquent Moments.—To speak well, one person needs someone who is clearly and[Pg 286] openly superior to them, while another can only express complete freedom of speech and enjoy fluent conversation in front of someone they see as inferior. In both situations, the reason is the same; each of them speaks well only when they talk without restraint—the first because in the presence of someone greater, they don’t feel the urge for rivalry and competition, and the second because they also lack this urge in front of someone lesser. Then there’s a different kind of person who speaks well only when debating, with the goal of winning. Which of these two types is more ambitious: the one who speaks well out of eager ambition, or the one who talks poorly or not at all for the same reason?

368.

368.

The Talent For Friendship.—Two types are distinguished amongst people who have a special faculty for friendship. The one is ever on the ascent, and for every phase of his development he finds a friend exactly suited to him. The series of friends which he thus acquires is seldom a consistent one, and is sometimes at variance and in contradiction, entirely in accordance with the fact that the later phases of his development neutralise or prejudice the earlier phases. Such a man may jestingly be called a ladder. The other type is represented by him who exercises an attractive influence on very different characters and endowments, so that he wins a whole circle of friends; these, however, are thereby brought voluntarily into[Pg 287] friendly relations with one another in spite of all differences. Such a man may be called a circle, for this homogeneousness of such different temperaments and natures must somehow be typified in him. Furthermore, the faculty for having good friends is greater in many people than the faculty for being a good friend.

The Gift of Friendship.—There are two types of people who have a special gift for friendship. One type is always growing, and at every stage of his development, he finds friends who are just right for him. The series of friends he gathers is rarely consistent and can sometimes contradict itself, reflecting the fact that his later stages of growth can overshadow or diminish earlier ones. This kind of person could humorously be called a ladder. The other type is represented by someone who has a magnetic charm that draws in very different personalities and talents, allowing him to create a wide circle of friends; these friends are willingly brought into[Pg 287] friendly relationships with each other despite their differences. This type of person may be called a circle, as he somehow embodies the unity of such diverse temperaments and natures. Additionally, the ability to have good friends is often greater in many people than their ability to be a good friend.

369.

369.

Tactics in Conversation.—After a conversation with a person one is best pleased with him I when one has had an opportunity of exhibiting one's intelligence and amiability in all its glory. Shrewd people who wish to impress a person favourably make use of this circumstance, they provide him with the best opportunities for making a good I joke, and so on in conversation. An amusing conversation might be imagined between two very shrewd persons, each wishing to impress the other favourably, and therefore each throwing to the other the finest chances in conversation, which neither of them accepted, so that the conversation on the whole might turn out spiritless and unattractive because each assigned to the other the opportunity of being witty and charming.

Conversation Tactics.—After talking with someone, you feel best about them when you’ve had a chance to show your intelligence and friendly nature at its best. Clever people who want to make a good impression on others take advantage of this by giving them great moments to crack a good joke and shine in conversation. Imagine a funny exchange between two clever individuals, each trying to impress the other and therefore passing up the best opportunities to be witty and charming. As a result, the conversation might end up dull and unappealing since both are waiting for the other to take the lead.

370.

370.

Discharge of Indignation.—The man who meets with a failure attributes this failure rather to the ill-will of another than to fate.[Pg 288] His irritated feelings are alleviated by thinking that a person and not a thing is the cause of his failure; for he can revenge himself on persons, but is obliged to swallow down the injuries of fate. Therefore when anything has miscarried with a prince, those about him are accustomed to point out some individual as the ostensible cause, who is sacrificed in the interests of all the courtiers; for otherwise the prince's indignation would vent itself on them all, as he can take no revenge on the Goddess of Destiny herself.

Release of Anger.—When a man faces failure, he often blames another person rather than fate.[Pg 288] His anger is eased by believing that someone, not just circumstances, is responsible for his setback; he can seek revenge on people, but he has to just accept the blows dealt by destiny. So, when things go wrong for a prince, those around him usually point to a specific individual as the main scapegoat, who is sacrificed to appease all the courtiers; otherwise, the prince's anger would be directed at them all, since he can’t retaliate against the Goddess of Destiny herself.

371.

371.

Assuming the Colours of the Environment.—Why are likes and dislikes so contagious that we can hardly live near a very sensitive person without being filled, like a hogshead, with his fors and againsts? In the first place, complete forbearance of judgment is very difficult, and sometimes absolutely intolerable to our vanity; it has the same appearance as poverty of thought and sentiment, or as timidity and unmanliness; and so we are, at least, driven on to take a side, perhaps contrary to our environment, if this attitude gives greater pleasure to our pride. As a rule, however,—and this is the second point,—we are not conscious of the transition from indifference to liking or disliking, but we gradually accustom ourselves to the sentiments of our environment, and because sympathetic agreement and acquiescence are so agreeable, we soon wear all the signs and party-colours of our surroundings.

Adapting to the Colors of Our Environment.—Why are our likes and dislikes so contagious that we can hardly be around a very sensitive person without being filled, like a barrel, with their pros and cons? First of all, complete tolerance of judgment is really hard and sometimes completely unbearable for our pride; it seems like a lack of thought and feeling, or like being timid and unmanly. So, we often feel pushed to take a side, maybe one that goes against our surroundings, if it makes us feel better about ourselves. Usually, though—this is the second point—we aren’t even aware of how we shift from being indifferent to having preferences; we slowly get used to the feelings of those around us, and because it feels nice to agree and go along with them, we quickly adopt all the signs and colors of our environment.

372.

372.

Irony.—Irony is only permissible as a pedagogic expedient, on the part of a teacher when dealing with his pupils; its purpose is to humble and to shame, but in the wholesome way that causes good resolutions to spring up and teaches people to show honour and gratitude, as they would to a doctor, to him who has so treated them. The ironical man pretends to be ignorant, and does it so well that the pupils conversing with him are deceived, and in their firm belief in their own superior knowledge they grow bold and expose all their weak points; they lose their cautiousness and reveal themselves as they are,—until all of a sudden the light which they have held up to the teacher's face casts its rays back very humiliatingly upon themselves. Where such a relation, as that between teacher and pupil, does not exist, irony is a rudeness and a vulgar conceit. All ironical writers count on the silly species of human beings, who like to feel themselves superior to all others in common with the author himself, whom they look upon as the mouthpiece of their arrogance. Moreover, the habit of irony, like that of sarcasm, spoils the character; lit gradually fosters the quality of a malicious superiority; one finally grows like a snappy dog, that has learnt to laugh as well as to bite.

Irony.—Irony is only acceptable as a teaching tool when used by a teacher with their students; its aim is to humble and embarrass, but in a constructive way that encourages good resolutions and teaches respect and gratitude, similar to how one would feel towards a doctor. The ironic person pretends to be clueless, doing it so convincingly that the students talking to them are fooled, and in their strong belief in their own greater knowledge, they become bold and reveal their weaknesses; they let down their guard and show who they really are—until suddenly, the light they’ve shone on the teacher reflects back on them in a very humbling way. When a relationship like that between teacher and student doesn’t exist, irony becomes rude and pretentious. All ironic writers rely on a foolish type of person who enjoys feeling superior to others, just like the author, whom they see as the spokesperson for their arrogance. Furthermore, the habit of using irony, like sarcasm, damages one’s character; it gradually nurtures a malicious sense of superiority; ultimately, one becomes like an irritable dog that has learned to both mock and bite.

373.

373.

Arrogance.—There is nothing one should so guard against as the growth of the weed called[Pg 290] arrogance, which spoils all one's good harvest; for there is arrogance in cordiality, in showing honour, in kindly familiarity, in caressing, in friendly counsel, in acknowledgment of faults, in sympathy for others,—and all these fine things arouse aversion when the weed in question grows up among them. The arrogant man—that is to say, he who desires to appear more than he is or passes for—always miscalculates. It is true that he obtains a momentary success, inasmuch as those with whom he is' arrogant generally give him the amount of honour that he demands, owing to fear or for the sake of convenience; but they take a bad revenge for it, inasmuch as they subtract from the value which they hitherto attached to him just as much as he demands above that amount. There is nothing for which men ask to be paid dearer than for humiliation. The arrogant man can make his really great merit so suspicious and small in the eyes of others that they tread on it with dusty feet. If at all, we should only allow ourselves a proud manner where we are quite sure of not being misunderstood and considered as arrogant; as, for instance, with friends and wives. For in social intercourse there is no greater folly than to acquire a reputation for arrogance; it is still worse than not having learnt to deceive politely.

Ego.—There's nothing to guard against more than the weed called [Pg 290] arrogance, which ruins all your good efforts; because arrogance can creep into friendliness, showing respect, being familiar, offering affection, giving advice, acknowledging mistakes, and feeling sympathy for others—when that weed grows among these good traits, it makes them unappealing. The arrogant person—that is, someone who wants to seem more than they truly are or is perceived to be—always miscalculates. True, they might achieve short-term success since those they act arrogantly towards often give them the respect they demand out of fear or convenience; however, they get a negative payback, as people reduce the value they once placed on them by the same amount that the arrogant person over-claims. Nothing makes people more unwilling to pay the price for their humiliation. An arrogant person can make their true worth seem so questionable and small in the eyes of others that people disregard it without thinking. If we must act proud, we should only do so when we’re sure we won’t be misunderstood or come off as arrogant; for instance, with friends and loved ones. In social interactions, nothing is more foolish than earning a reputation for arrogance; it's even worse than not learning to be polite about deception.

374.

374.

Tête-à-tête—Private conversation is the perfect conversation, because everything the one' person says receives its particular colouring, its[Pg 291] tone, and its accompanying gestures out of strict consideration for the other person engaged in the conversation, it therefore corresponds to what takes place in intercourse by letter, viz., that one and the same person exhibits ten kinds of psychical expression, according as he writes now to this individual and now to that one. In duologue there is only a single refraction of thought; the person conversed with produces it, as the mirror in whom we want to behold our thoughts anew in their finest form. But how is it when there are two or three, or even more persons conversing with one? Conversation then necessarily loses something of its individualising subtlety, different considerations thwart and neutralise each other; the style which pleases one does not suit the taste of another. In intercourse with several individuals a person is therefore to withdraw within himself and represent facts as they are; but he has also to remove from the subjects the pulsating ether of humanity which makes conversation one of the pleasantest things in the world. Listen only to the tone in which those who mingle with whole groups of men are in the habit of speaking; it is as if the fundamental base of all speech were, "It is myself; I say this, so make what you will of it!" That is the reason why clever ladies usually leave a singular, painful, and forbidding impression on those who have met them in society; it is the talking to many people, before many people, that robs them of all intellectual amiability and shows only their conscious dependence on themselves, their tactics, and their intention of gaining a[Pg 292] public victory in full light; whilst in a private conversation the same ladies become womanly again, and recover their intellectual grace and charm.

Face-to-face—A private conversation is the best kind of conversation because everything one person says takes on its own unique flavor, tone, and gestures, in genuine consideration for the other person involved. It mirrors what happens in letter writing, where the same person can display a variety of emotional expressions depending on who they are addressing. In a dialogue, there's just one reflection of thought; the person you're talking to brings it out, like a mirror showing your thoughts at their best. But what happens when there are two, three, or more people in the conversation? It starts to lose some of its personal nuance as different viewpoints clash and cancel each other out; what appeals to one might not appeal to another. When talking to a group, a person often retreats into themselves, presenting facts as they are, yet they also have to remove the vibrant human essence that makes conversation one of the most enjoyable experiences. Just listen to how those who interact with large groups tend to speak; it’s as if the core of all their communication is, "It is myself; I’m saying this, so interpret it however you like!" This is why sharp-witted women often leave a confusing, uncomfortable impression on those who meet them in social settings; it’s the talking to and in front of many people that strips away their intellectual warmth, revealing only their self-reliance, strategies, and desire for a big public win. In private conversations, these same women become more feminine and regain their intellectual elegance and charm.

375.

375.

Posthumous Fame.—There is sense in hoping for recognition in a distant future only when we take it for granted that mankind will remain essentially unchanged, and that whatever is great is not for one age only but will be looked upon as great for all time. But this is an error. In all their sentiments and judgments concerning what is good and beautiful mankind have greatly changed; it is mere fantasy to imagine one's self to be a mile ahead, and that the whole of mankind is coming our way. Besides, a scholar who is misjudged may at present reckon with certainty that his discovery will be made by others, and that, at best, it will be allowed to him later on by some historian that he also already knew this or that but was not in a position to secure the recognition of his knowledge. Not to be recognised, is always interpreted by posterity as lack of power. In short, one should not so readily speak in favour of haughty solitude. There are, however, exceptional cases; but it is chiefly our faults, weakness, and follies that hinder the recognition of our great qualities.

Afterlife Fame.—There’s a certain logic in hoping for recognition in the future only if we assume that humanity will stay pretty much the same and that what’s considered great will always be seen as great. But this is a mistake. People’s feelings and opinions about what is good and beautiful have changed a lot over time; it’s just wishful thinking to believe we’re far ahead of everyone else, and that humanity is moving toward us. Moreover, a scholar who is misunderstood can be sure that someone else will make their discovery and, at best, some historian later will acknowledge that they also knew this or that but couldn’t get credit for it. Not being recognized is often interpreted by future generations as a sign of weakness. In short, we shouldn’t be so quick to praise proud solitude. There are, however, exceptional cases; but it’s mainly our flaws, weaknesses, and mistakes that prevent our great qualities from being recognized.

376.

376.

Of Friends.—Just consider with thyself how different are the feelings, how divided are the[Pg 293] opinions of even the nearest acquaintances; how even the same opinions in thy friend's mind have quite a different aspect and strength from what they have in thine own; and how manifold are the occasions which arise for misunderstanding and hostile severance. After all this thou wilt say to thyself, "How insecure is the ground upon which all our alliances and friendships rest, how liable to cold downpours and bad weather, how lonely is every creature!" When a person recognises this fact, and, in addition, that all opinions and the nature and strength of them in his fellow-men are just as necessary and irresponsible as their actions; when his eye learns to see this internal necessity of opinions, owing to the indissoluble interweaving of character, occupation, talent, and environment,—he will perhaps get rid of the bitterness and sharpness of the feeling with which the sage exclaimed, "Friends, there are no friends!" Much rather will he make the confession to himself:—Yes, there are friends, but they were drawn towards thee by error and deception concerning thy character; and they must have learnt to be silent in order to remain thy friends; for such human relationships almost always rest on the fact that some few things are never said, are never, indeed, alluded to; but if these pebbles are set rolling friendship follows afterwards and is broken. Are there any who would not be mortally injured if they were to learn what their most intimate friends really knew about them? By getting a knowledge of ourselves, and by looking upon our nature as a changing sphere of opinions and moods,[Pg 294] and thereby learning to despise ourselves a little, we recover once more our equilibrium with the rest of mankind. It is true that we have good reason to despise each of our acquaintances, even the greatest of them; but just as good reason to turn this feeling against ourselves. And so we will bear with each other, since we bear with ourselves; and perhaps there will come to each a happier hour, when he will exclaim:

Of Friends.—Just think about how different our feelings are, how varied the[Pg 293] opinions of even our closest acquaintances can be; how even the same opinions in your friend's mind look and feel completely different than they do in yours; and how many chances there are for misunderstandings and conflicts. After all this, you might say to yourself, "How shaky is the foundation of all our relationships and friendships, how susceptible to sudden storms and tough times, how lonely is every individual!" When someone realizes this, and, in addition, understands that everyone else's opinions, as well as their nature and strength, are just as necessary and unpredictable as their actions; when they start to see this internal necessity of opinions, caused by the tight interweaving of character, work, talent, and surroundings,—they might let go of the bitterness and sharpness of the sentiment expressed by the wise person who cried out, "Friends, there are no friends!" Instead, they might admit to themselves: Yes, there are friends, but they were drawn to you through misunderstandings and deception regarding your character; and they had to learn to keep quiet to remain your friends; because these human relationships often depend on the fact that certain topics are never discussed or even hinted at; but if these hidden truths come to light, friendship often crumbles. Are there any who wouldn’t be deeply hurt if they found out what their closest friends truly thought about them? By becoming aware of ourselves, and viewing our nature as a shifting landscape of opinions and moods,[Pg 294] and learning to criticize ourselves just a bit, we can restore our balance with the rest of humanity. It's true that we have every reason to look down on each of our acquaintances, even the most esteemed among them; but we also have as much reason to direct this judgment against ourselves. And so we will tolerate each other, since we tolerate ourselves; and perhaps there will come a happier moment for each person when they will exclaim:

"Friends, there are really no friends!" thus cried
th' expiring old sophist;
"Foes, there is really no foe!"—thus shout I,
the incarnate fool.

"Friends, there are really no friends!" shouted
the dying old philosopher;
"Enemies, there are really no enemies!"—this I yell,
the clueless fool.


SEVENTH DIVISION.

WIFE AND CHILD.

377.

377.

The Perfect Woman.—The perfect woman is a higher type of humanity than the perfect man, and also something much rarer. The natural history of animals furnishes grounds in support of this theory.

The Ideal Woman.—The perfect woman is a superior type of humanity compared to the perfect man and is also much rarer. The natural history of animals provides evidence for this theory.

378.

378.

Friendship and Marriage.—The best friend will probably get the best wife, because a good marriage is based on talent for friendship.

Friendship and Marriage.—The best friend will likely end up with the best wife, because a successful marriage relies on the ability to be a good friend.

379.

379.

The Survival of the Parents.—The undissolved dissonances in the relation of the character and sentiments of the parents survive in the nature of the child and make up the history of its inner sufferings.

The Parents' Survival.—The unresolved conflicts in the relationship between the character and feelings of the parents continue to exist in the child's nature and contribute to the story of its inner struggles.

380.

380.

Inherited from the Mother.—Every one bears within him an image of woman, inherited from his mother: it determines his attitude[Pg 296] towards women as a whole, whether to honour, despise, or remain generally indifferent to them.

Inherited from Mom.—Everyone carries an image of woman inside them, inherited from their mother: it shapes their attitude[Pg 296] toward women as a whole, influencing whether they honor, despise, or feel indifferent towards them.

381.

381.

Correcting Nature.—Whoever has not got a good father should procure one.

Fixing Nature.—Anyone who doesn't have a good father should find one.

382.

382.

Fathers and Sons.—Fathers have much to do to make amends for having sons.

Dads and Kids.—Fathers have a lot to make up for when it comes to having sons.

383.

383.

The Error of Gentlewomen.—Gentle-women think that a thing does not really exist when it is not possible to talk of it in society.

The Mistake of Gentlewomen.—Women of status believe that something doesn't truly exist if it's not something that can be discussed in social settings.

384.

384.

A Male Disease.—The surest remedy for the male disease of self-contempt is to be loved by a sensible woman.

A Men's Health Issue.—The best cure for a man's self-hatred is to be loved by a smart woman.

385.

385.

A Species of Jealousy.—Mothers are readily jealous of the friends of sons who are particularly successful. As a rule a mother loves herself in her son more than the son.

A Type of Jealousy.—Mothers can easily feel jealous of their sons' friends who are especially successful. Generally, a mother loves herself in her son more than she loves her son.

386.

386.

RATIONAL IRRATIONALITY.—In the maturity of life and intelligence the feeling comes over a man that his father did wrong in begetting him.

RATIONAL IRRATIONALITY.—As one reaches maturity in life and intelligence, a person may feel that their father made a mistake in bringing them into the world.

387.

387.

Maternal Excellence.—Some mothers need happy and honoured children, some need unhappy ones,—otherwise they cannot exhibit their maternal excellence.

Motherhood Excellence.—Some mothers need their children to be happy and respected, while others need them to be unhappy, otherwise they can’t showcase their maternal excellence.

388.

388.

Different Sighs.—Some husbands have sighed over the elopement of their wives, the greater number, however, have sighed because nobody would elope with theirs.

Different Sighs.—Some husbands have sighed over their wives running away with someone else, but most have sighed because no one would want to run away with theirs.

389.

389.

Love Matches.—Marriages which are contracted for love (so-called love-matches) have error for their father and need (necessity) for their mother.

Love Matches.—Marriages that happen because of love (known as love matches) are born from mistakes and driven by necessity.

390.

390.

Women's Friendships.—Women can enter into friendship with a man perfectly well; but in order to maintain it the aid of a little physical antipathy is perhaps required.

Women's friendships.—Women can form friendships with men just fine; however, to keep that friendship going, a small amount of physical dislike might be needed.

391.

391.

Ennui.—Many people, especially women, never feel ennui because they have never learnt to work properly.

Bored.—Many people, especially women, never feel bored because they have never learned how to work effectively.

392.

392.

An Element of Love.—In all feminine love something of maternal love also comes to light.

A Factor of Love.—In every woman's love, there’s also a hint of maternal love that shines through.

393.

393.

Unity of Place and Drama.—If married couples did not live together, happy marriages would be more frequent.

Place and Drama Unity.—If married couples didn't live together, happy marriages would happen more often.

394.

394.

The Usual Consequences of Marriage.—All intercourse which does not elevate a person, debases him, and vice versa; hence men usually sink a little when they marry, while women are somewhat elevated. Over-intellectual men require marriage in proportion as they are opposed to it as to a repugnant medicine.

The Typical Effects of Marriage.—All interactions that don't uplift a person bring them down, and vice versa; therefore, men often experience a slight decline when they get married, while women tend to gain some elevation. Highly intellectual men tend to need marriage in proportion to how much they resist it, viewing it like an unpleasant medicine.

395.

395.

Learning to Command.—Children of unpretentious families must be taught to command, just as much as other children must be taught to obey.

Learning to Lead.—Kids from humble backgrounds need to learn how to lead, just like other kids need to learn how to follow.

396.

396.

Wanting to Be in Love.—Betrothed couples who have been matched by convenience often exert themselves to fall in love, to avoid the reproach of cold, calculating expediency. In the same manner those who become converts to Christianity for their advantage exert themselves to become genuinely pious; because the religious cast of countenance then becomes easier to them.

Wanting to Be in Love.—Engaged couples who were matched out of convenience often try hard to fall in love, to escape the judgment of being seen as cold and calculating. Similarly, those who convert to Christianity for personal gain put in the effort to become truly devout; because maintaining a religious appearance then becomes easier for them.

397.

397.

No Standing Still in Love.—A musician who loves the slow tempo will play the same pieces[Pg 299] ever more slowly. There is thus no standing still in any love.

No Stagnation in Love.—A musician who loves the slow tempo will keep playing the same pieces[Pg 299] slower and slower. So, there’s no standing still in any love.

398.

398.

Modesty.—Women's modesty usually increases with their beauty.[1]

Modesty.—Women's modesty often grows as their beauty increases.[1]

399.

399.

Marriage on a Good Basis.—A marriage in which each wishes to realise an individual aim by means of the other will stand well; for instance, when the woman wishes to become famous through the man and the man beloved through the woman.

Marriage on a Strong Foundation.—A marriage where both people want to achieve their personal goals with each other's support will thrive; for example, when a woman aims to gain fame through her partner and a man seeks affection through his partner.

400.

400.

Proteus-nature.—Through love women actually become what they appear to be in the imagination of their lovers.

Proteus nature.—Through love, women truly become what they seem to be in the minds of their lovers.

401.

401.

To Love and to Possess.—As a rule women love a distinguished man to the extent that they wish to possess him exclusively. They would gladly keep him under lock and key, if their vanity did not forbid, but vanity demands that he should also appear distinguished before others.

To Love and To Own.—Generally, women love a notable man so much that they want to possess him completely. They would happily keep him locked away if their vanity didn't stop them, but vanity insists that he should also look distinguished in front of others.

402.

402.

The Test of a Good Marriage.—The goodness of a marriage is proved by the fact that it can stand an "exception."

The Test of a Good Marriage.—The strength of a marriage is shown by its ability to handle an "exception."

403.

403.

Bringing Anyone Round to Anything.—One may make any person so weak and weary by disquietude, anxiety, and excess of work or thought that he no longer resists anything that appears complicated, but gives way to it,—diplomatists and women know this.

Convincing Anyone of Anything.—You can wear someone down with worry, stress, and too much work or thinking until they stop resisting things that seem complicated and just give in to them—diplomats and women understand this.

404.

404.

Propriety and Honesty.—Those girls who mean to trust exclusively to their youthful charms for their provision in life, and whose cunning is further prompted by worldly mothers, have just the same aims as courtesans, only they are wiser and less honest.

Respect and Honesty.—The girls who plan to rely solely on their youthful looks for their future and whose cleverness is encouraged by their worldly mothers have the same goals as courtesans; they’re just smarter and less honest.

405.

405.

Masks.—There are women who, wherever one examines them, have no inside, but are mere masks. A man is to be pitied who has connection with such almost spectre-like and necessarily unsatisfactory creatures, but it is precisely such women who know how to excite a man's desire most strongly; he seeks for their soul, and seeks evermore.

Face masks.—Some women are just facades; no matter how you look at them, there's nothing beneath. A man should feel sorry for himself if he gets involved with these almost ghostly and ultimately disappointing beings. Yet, it’s these very women who can stir a man’s desire the most; he searches for their soul, always yearning.

406.

406.

Marriage As a Long Talk.—In entering on a marriage one should ask one's self the question, "Do you think you will pass your time well with this woman till your old age?" All else in marriage is transitory; talk, however, occupies most of the time of the association.

Marriage Is a Long Conversation.—When you enter into a marriage, you should ask yourself, "Do you think you'll enjoy spending your life with this woman until you're old?" Everything else in marriage is temporary; conversation, however, takes up most of the time in the relationship.

407.

407.

Girlish Dreams.—Inexperienced girls flatter themselves with the notion that it is in their power to make a man happy; later on they learn that it is equivalent to underrating a man to suppose that he needs only a girl to make him happy. Women's vanity requires a man to be something more than merely a happy husband.

Girlhood Dreams.—Naive girls often convince themselves they can make a man happy; eventually, they realize that it's an insult to think a man only needs a girl to be truly happy. A woman's pride demands that a man be more than just a content husband.

408.

408.

The Dying-out of Faust and Marguerite.—According to the very intelligent remark of a scholar, the educated men of modern Germany resemble somewhat a mixture of Mephistopheles and Wagner, but are not at all like Faust, whom our grandfathers (in their youth at least) felt agitating within them. To them, therefore,—to continue the remark,—Marguerites are not suited, for two reasons. And because the latter are no longer desired they seem to be dying out.

The Decline of Faust and Marguerite.—As a smart scholar once pointed out, the educated people of modern Germany are kind of a blend of Mephistopheles and Wagner, but they don’t really resemble Faust, who our grandparents (at least in their younger days) felt stirring within them. So, to build on that point—Marguerites just don’t fit for two reasons. And since they’re no longer wanted, they seem to be fading away.

409.

409.

Classical Education For Girls.—For goodness' sake let us not give our classical education to girls! An education which, out of ingenious, inquisitive, ardent youths, so frequently makes—copies of their teacher!

Classical Education for Girls.—For heaven's sake, let's not provide classical education to girls! An education that often turns clever, curious, passionate young people into mere replicas of their teachers!

410.

410.

Without Rivals.—Women readily perceive in a man whether his soul has already been taken[Pg 302] possession of; they wish to be loved without rivals, and find fault with the objects of his ambition, his political tasks, his sciences and arts, if he have a passion for such things. Unless he be distinguished thereby,—then, in the case of a love-relationship between them, women look at the same time for an increase of their own distinction; under such circumstances, they favour the lover.

No Competitors.—Women can easily tell if a man's heart has already been claimed[Pg 302]; they want to be loved without competition and will criticize what he aspires to, whether it's his career, his interests, or his passions in the arts and sciences. If he stands out because of these pursuits, then in a romantic relationship, women also seek to enhance their own status; in those situations, they support their partner.

411.

411.

The Feminine Intellect.—The intellect of women manifests itself as perfect mastery, presence of mind, and utilisation of all advantages. They transmit it as a fundamental quality to their children, and the father adds thereto the darker background of the will. His influence determines as it were the rhythm and harmony with which the new life is to be performed; but its melody is derived from the mother. For those who know how to put a thing properly: women have intelligence, men have character and passion. This does not contradict the fact that men actually achieve so much more with their intelligence: they have deeper and more powerful impulses; and it is these which carry their understanding (in itself something passive) to such an extent. Women are often silently surprised at the great respect men pay to their character. When, therefore, in the choice of a partner men seek specially for a being of deep and strong character, and women for a being of intelligence, brilliancy, and presence of mind, it is plain that at bottom men[Pg 303] seek for the ideal man, and women for the ideal woman,—consequently not for the complement but for the completion of their own excellence.

The Female Mind.—The intellect of women shows itself as perfect mastery, quick thinking, and the ability to use all advantages. They pass this fundamental quality on to their children, while the father contributes the darker background of willpower. His influence shapes the rhythm and harmony with which new life unfolds; however, its melody comes from the mother. For those who know how to frame it: women have intelligence, while men have character and passion. This doesn’t change the fact that men often achieve much more with their intelligence: they possess deeper and more powerful impulses, which propel their understanding (in itself somewhat passive) to a greater extent. Women are often quietly amazed at the respect men have for their character. Thus, when men look for a partner, they especially seek someone with deep and strong character, while women search for someone with intelligence, brilliance, and quick thinking. It’s clear that, in essence, men seek the ideal man, and women seek the ideal woman—thereby looking not for a complement but for the completion of their own excellence.

412.

412.

Hesiod's Opinion Confirmed.—It is a sign of women's wisdom that they have almost always known how to get themselves supported, like drones in a bee-hive. Let us just consider what this meant originally, and why men do not depend upon women for their support. Of a truth it is because masculine vanity and reverence are greater than feminine wisdom; for women have known how to secure for themselves by their subordination the greatest advantage, in fact, the upper hand. Even the care of children may originally have been used by the wisdom of women as an excuse for withdrawing themselves as much as possible from work. And at present they still understand when they are really active (as house-keepers, for instance) how to make a bewildering fuss about it, so that the merit of their activity is usually ten times over-estimated by men.

Hesiod’s View Confirmed.—It's a sign of women's intelligence that they've almost always known how to get support for themselves, like drones in a bee-hive. Let's think about what this originally meant and why men don't rely on women for support. The truth is, it's because masculine pride and respect are stronger than feminine wisdom; women have figured out how to gain the greatest advantage, in fact, the upper hand, through their subordination. Even the responsibility for children may have been used by women's wisdom as a reason to step back from work as much as possible. And even today, when they are truly active (like as housekeepers, for example), they know how to create a big fuss about it, so that the value of their efforts is often exaggerated by men.

413.

413.

Lovers As Short-sighted People.—A pair of powerful spectacles has sometimes sufficed to cure a person in love; and whoever has had sufficient imagination to represent a face or form twenty years older, has probably gone through life not much disturbed.

Lovers as shortsighted people.—A strong pair of glasses has sometimes been enough to cure someone in love; and anyone who has had enough imagination to picture a face or body twenty years older has likely lived their life with little disturbance.

414.

414.

Women in Hatred.—In a state of hatred women are more dangerous than men; for one thing, because they are hampered by no regard for fairness when their hostile feelings have been aroused; but let their hatred develop unchecked to its utmost consequences; then also, because they are expert in finding sore spots (which every man and every party possess), and pouncing upon them: for which purpose their dagger-pointed intelligence is of good service (whilst men, hesitating at the sight of wounds, are often generously and conciliatorily inclined).

Women in Hate.—In a state of hatred, women are more dangerous than men; partly because they’re not held back by any sense of fairness when their anger is stirred. If their hatred is allowed to grow unchecked, they become skilled at identifying vulnerabilities (which every man and every group has) and attacking them: their sharp intelligence serves this purpose well, while men, often hesitant at the sight of wounds, tend to be more generous and conciliatory.

415.

415.

Love.—The love idolatry which women practise is fundamentally and originally an intelligent device, inasmuch as they increase their power by all the idealisings of love and exhibit themselves as so much the more desirable in the eyes of men. But by being accustomed for centuries to this exaggerated appreciation of love, it has come to pass that they have been caught in their own net and have forgotten the origin of the device. They themselves are now still more deceived than the men, and on that account also suffer more from the disillusionment which, almost necessarily, enters into the life of every woman—so far, at any rate, as she has sufficient imagination and intelligence to be able to be deceived and undeceived.

Love.—The way women idolize love is, at its core, a clever strategy since it boosts their power through the ideals of love, making them appear more desirable to men. However, after centuries of this inflated view of love, they’ve become ensnared in their own trap and lost sight of the original intent. Now, they are often more misled than the men, which leads to greater suffering when disillusionment inevitably comes into every woman's life—at least for those who have enough imagination and intelligence to both fall for and see through the illusions.

416.

416.

The Emancipation of Women.—Can women be at all just, when they are so accustomed to love and to be immediately biased for or against? For that reason they are also less interested in things and more in individuals: but when they are interested in things they immediately become their partisans, and thereby spoil their pure, innocent effect. Thus there arises a danger, by no means small, in entrusting politics and certain portions of science to them (history, for instance). For what is rarer than a woman who really knows what science is? Indeed the best of them cherish in their breasts a secret scorn for science, as if they were somehow superior to it. Perhaps all this can be changed in time; but meanwhile it is so.

Women’s Liberation.—Can women really be fair when they're so used to loving and being biased for or against things? Because of this, they tend to care more about individuals than about broader issues; but when they do focus on issues, they quickly become biased supporters, which ruins their pure, innocent perspective. This creates a significant risk in allowing them to handle politics and certain areas of science (like history, for example). What’s rarer than a woman who truly understands what science is? Indeed, many of them secretly look down on science, as if they are somehow above it. Maybe this can change over time; but for now, that's how it is.

417.

417.

The Inspiration in Women's Judgments.—The sudden decisions, for or against, which women are in the habit of making, the flashing illumination of personal relations caused by their spasmodic inclinations and aversions,—in short, the proofs of feminine injustice have been invested with a lustre by men who are in love, as if all women had inspirations of wisdom, even without the Delphic cauldron and the laurel wreaths; and their utterances are interpreted and duly set forth as Sibylline oracles for long afterwards. When one considers, however, that for every person and for every cause something can be said in favour[Pg 306] of it but equally also something against it, that things are not only two-sided, but also three and four-sided, it is almost difficult to be entirely at fault in such sudden decisions; indeed, it might be said that the nature of things has been so arranged that women should always carry their point.[2]

The Inspiration in Women's Decisions.—The quick decisions, whether for or against something, that women often make, the sudden clarity in personal relationships brought on by their unpredictable likes and dislikes—essentially, the evidence of feminine bias has been romanticized by men in love, as if all women possess a spark of wisdom without the need for oracles or laurel crowns; their words are interpreted and remembered as prophetic insights for a long time. However, when you think about the fact that for every person and every issue, there’s something to be said both for and against it, and that matters can be seen in multiple dimensions, it’s almost impossible to be completely wrong in such snap judgments; indeed, one could argue that the situation is set up in such a way that women will always get their way.[2]

418.

418.

Being Loved.—As one of every two persons in love is usually the one who loves, the other the one who is loved, the belief has arisen that in every love-affair there is a constant amount of love; and that the more of it the one person monopolises the less is left for the other. Exceptionally it happens that the vanity of each of the parties persuades him or her that it is he or she who must be loved; so that both of them wish to be loved: from which cause many half funny, half absurd scenes take place, especially in married life.

Being Loved.—In any romantic relationship, typically one person is the lover and the other is the one being loved. This has led to the idea that there is a fixed amount of love in any relationship; the more one person keeps for themselves, the less there is for the other. Sometimes, each person’s ego convinces them that they need to be the one who is loved, causing both to want love for themselves. This often results in many situations that are part amusing and part ridiculous, especially in marriage.

419.

419.

Contradictions in Feminine Minds.—Owing to the fact that women are so much more personal than objective, there are tendencies included in the range of their ideas which are logically in contradiction to one another; they are accustomed in turn to become enthusiastically fond just of the representatives of these tendencies[Pg 307] and accept their systems in the lump; but in such wise that a dead place originates wherever a new personality afterwards gets the ascendancy. It may happen that the whole philosophy in the mind of an old lady consists of nothing but such dead places.

Contradictions in Women's Minds.—Because women tend to be more personal than objective, their ideas can often contradict each other. They become passionately attached to the representatives of these conflicting ideas and tend to accept their systems as a whole; however, this leads to stagnant areas whenever a new personality comes to the forefront. It's possible that the entire philosophy in an older woman's mind is just filled with these stagnant areas.[Pg 307]

420.

420.

Who Suffers the More?—After a personal dissension and quarrel between a woman and a man the latter party suffers chiefly from the idea of having wounded the other, whilst the former suffers chiefly from the idea of not having wounded the other sufficiently; so she subsequently endeavours by tears, sobs, and discomposed mien, to make his heart heavier.

Who suffers more?—After a personal conflict and argument between a woman and a man, the man mainly suffers from the feeling that he has hurt her, while the woman primarily suffers from the belief that she hasn’t hurt him enough. As a result, she tries to make him feel worse by crying, sobbing, and displaying a troubled expression.

421.

421.

An Opportunity For Feminine Magnanimity.—If we could disregard the claims of custom in our thinking we might consider whether nature and reason do not suggest several marriages for men, one after another: perhaps that, at the age of twenty-two, he should first marry an older girl who is mentally and morally his superior, and can be his leader through all the dangers of the twenties (ambition, hatred, self-contempt, and passions of all kinds). This woman's affection would subsequently change entirely into maternal love, and she would not only submit to it but would encourage the man in the most salutary manner, if in his thirties he contracted an alliance with quite a young girl whose education he[Pg 308] himself should take in hand. Marriage is a necessary institution for the twenties; a useful, but not necessary, institution for the thirties; for later life it is often harmful, and promotes the mental deterioration of the man.

An Opportunity for Kindness.—If we could set aside traditional views in our thinking, we might explore whether nature and reason suggest that men could have multiple marriages over time. For instance, perhaps by the age of twenty-two, a man should first marry an older woman who is intellectually and morally superior to him, guiding him through the challenges of his twenties—ambition, hatred, self-doubt, and various passions. Over time, her affection would transform into a maternal love, and she would not only accept this change but also support him in a positive way if, in his thirties, he marries a much younger woman whose education he should manage himself. Marriage is essential in the twenties, useful but not crucial in the thirties, and often detrimental in later life, leading to the man's mental decline.

422.

422.

The Tragedy of Childhood.—Perhaps it not infrequently happens that noble men with lofty aims have to fight their hardest battle in childhood; by having perchance to carry out their principles in opposition to a base-minded father addicted to feigning and falsehood, or living, like Lord Byron, in constant warfare with a childish and passionate mother. He who has had such an experience will never be able to forget all his life who has been his greatest and most dangerous enemy.

The Tragedy of Childhood.—It often happens that honorable people with high aspirations have to face their toughest challenges in childhood, whether it's standing up for their principles against a deceitful father who is all about pretense and lies, or, like Lord Byron, battling against a childish and emotional mother. Anyone who has gone through this experience will always remember who their greatest and most formidable adversary has been.

423.

423.

Parental Folly.—The grossest mistakes in judging a man are made by his parents,—this is a fact, but how is it to be explained? Have the parents too much experience of the child and cannot any longer arrange this experience into a unity? It has been noticed that it is only in the earlier period of their sojourn in foreign countries that travellers rightly grasp the general distinguishing features of a people; the better they come to know it, they are the less able to see what is typical and distinguishing in a people. As soon as they grow short-sighted their eyes cease to be long-sighted. Do parents, therefore,[Pg 309] judge their children falsely because they have never stood far enough away from them? The following is quite another explanation: people are no longer accustomed to reflect on what is close at hand and surrounds them, but just accept it. Perhaps the usual thoughtlessness of parents is the reason why they judge so wrongly when once they are compelled to judge their children.

Parenting Mistakes.—The biggest mistakes in judging a person often come from their parents—this is a fact, but why is that? Could it be that parents have so much experience with their child that they can no longer see the bigger picture? It's been observed that travelers tend to accurately understand the key traits of a culture only during the early stages of their visits; as they get to know it better, they become less able to identify what is typical and distinctive. Once their long-range vision fades, they lose that wider perspective. So, do parents judge their children inaccurately because they’ve never taken a step back? Here’s another possibility: people generally aren’t in the habit of reflecting on what’s right in front of them and just accept it as it is. Maybe the usual thoughtlessness of parents is why they often misjudge their children when they’re forced to evaluate them.

424.

424.

The Future of Marriage.—The noble and liberal-minded women who take as their mission the education and elevation of the female sex, should not overlook one point of view: Marriage regarded in its highest aspect, as, the spiritual friendship of two persons of opposite sexes, and accordingly such as is hoped for in future, contracted for the purpose of producing and educating a new generation,—such marriage, which only makes use of the sensual, so to speak, as a rare and occasional means to a higher purpose, will, it is to be feared, probably need a natural auxiliary, namely, concubinage. For if, on the grounds of his health, the wife is also to serve for the sole satisfaction of the man's sexual needs, a wrong perspective, opposed to the aims indicated, will have most influence in the choice of a wife. The aims referred to: the production of descendants, will be accidental, and their successful education highly improbable. A good wife, who has to be friend, helper, child-bearer, mother, family-head and manager, and has even[Pg 310] perhaps to conduct her own business and affairs separately from those of the husband, cannot at the same time be a concubine; it would, in general, be asking too much of her. In the future, therefore, a state of things might take place the opposite of what existed at Athens in the time of Pericles; the men, whose wives were then little more to them than concubines, turned besides to the Aspasias, because they longed for the charms of a companionship gratifying both to head and heart, such as the grace and intellectual suppleness of women could alone provide. All human institutions, just like marriage, allow only a moderate amount of practical idealising, failing which coarse remedies immediately become necessary.

The Future of Marriage.—The enlightened and forward-thinking women who dedicate themselves to the education and upliftment of women should not overlook an important perspective: Marriage, viewed at its highest level as a spiritual partnership between two people of opposite sexes, aimed at creating and nurturing a new generation—such a marriage, which utilizes physical intimacy only as a rare and occasional means to achieve a greater purpose, may likely require a natural supplement, namely, concubinage. If, for the sake of his health, the wife is to fulfill solely the man's sexual needs, then a misguided perspective will greatly influence the choice of a wife, contradicting the stated aims. The goal of producing offspring will become incidental, and successfully raising them will be highly unlikely. A good wife must serve as a friend, helper, child-bearer, mother, family leader, and manager, and she may even need to handle her own business and affairs separately from her husband's. It is unreasonable to expect her to also be a concubine. Therefore, in the future, we might see a reversal of what existed in Athens during Pericles' time; men, whose wives were then reduced to little more than concubines, sought out Aspasias because they craved the benefits of companionship that fulfilled both the intellect and the heart, which only the grace and mental agility of women could provide. All human institutions, including marriage, allow only a moderate degree of practical idealization, beyond which coarse remedies quickly become necessary.

425.

425.

The "Storm and Stress" Period of Women.—In the three or four civilised countries of Europe, it is possible, by several centuries of education, to make out of women anything we like,—even men, not in a sexual sense, of course, but in every other. Under such influences they will acquire all the masculine virtues and forces, at the same time, of course, they must also have taken all the masculine weaknesses and vices into the bargain: so much, as has been said, we can I command. But how shall we endure the intermediate state thereby induced, which may even last two or three centuries, during which feminine follies and injustices, woman's original birthday endowment, will still maintain the ascendancy[Pg 311] over all that has been otherwise gained and acquired? This will be the time when indignation will be the peculiar masculine passion; indignation, because all arts and sciences have been overflowed and choked by an unprecedented dilettanteism, philosophy talked to death by brain-bewildering chatter, politics more fantastic and partisan than ever, and society in complete disorganisation, because the conservatrices of ancient customs have become ridiculous to themselves, and have endeavoured in every way to place themselves outside the pale of custom. If indeed women had their greatest power in custom, where will they have to look in order to reacquire a similar plenitude of power after having renounced custom?

The "Storm and Stress" Period for Women.—In three or four advanced countries in Europe, after several centuries of education, it’s possible to shape women into anything we want—like men, not in a sexual way, but in every other respect. Under these circumstances, they will develop all the masculine virtues and strengths, but they will also take on all the masculine weaknesses and vices that come with it. However, how do we navigate the intermediate period this creates, which might last two or three centuries? During this time, the naive quirks and injustices that women are originally born with will still hold sway over everything else that has been learned and accomplished[Pg 311]. This will be an era when indignation becomes a uniquely masculine emotion; indignation over the fact that all arts and sciences have been overwhelmed and suffocated by an unprecedented trend of superficial interest, philosophy has been diluted by confusing chatter, politics has become more absurd and partisan than ever, and society is completely disarrayed because the guardians of old customs have become comical to themselves and have tried to distance themselves from traditional norms. If women derived their greatest power from these customs, where will they turn to regain a similar level of influence after abandoning those customs?

426.

426.

Free-spirit and Marriage.—Will free-thinkers live with women? In general, I think that, like the prophesying birds of old, like the truth-thinkers and truth-speakers of the present, they must prefer to fly alone.

Free spirit and marriage.—Do free-thinkers choose to live with women? Generally, I believe that, like the prophetic birds of the past, like the truth-seekers and truth-tellers of today, they likely prefer to fly solo.

427.

427.

The Happiness of Marriage.—Everything to which we are accustomed draws an ever-tightening cobweb-net around us; and presently We notice that the threads have become cords, and that we ourselves sit in the middle like a spider that has here got itself caught and must feed on its own blood. Hence the free spirit hates all rules and customs, all that is[Pg 312] permanent and definitive, hence he painfully tears asunder again and again the net around him, though in consequence thereof he will suffer from numerous wounds, slight and severe; for he must break off every thread from himself, from his body and soul. He must learn to love where he has hitherto hated, and vice versa. Indeed, it must not be a thing impossible for him to sow dragon's teeth in the same field in which he formerly scattered the abundance of his bounty. From this it can be inferred whether he is suited for the happiness of marriage.

The Joy of Marriage.—Everything we’re used to creates a tighter and tighter web around us; and soon we realize that the threads have turned into cords, and we find ourselves stuck in the middle like a spider trapped and forced to feast on its own blood. This is why the free spirit despises all rules and customs, anything that feels [Pg 312] permanent and set in stone. As a result, they struggle to break free from the web, enduring many wounds, both minor and major; for they must detach every thread from themselves, from body and soul. They must learn to love where they once hated, and vice versa. Indeed, it shouldn't be impossible for them to plant dragon's teeth in the same field where they previously scattered their generosity. From this, we can tell if they are ready for the happiness of marriage.

428.

428.

Too Intimate.—When we live on too intimate terms with a person it is as if we were again and again handling a good engraving with our fingers; the time comes when we have soiled and damaged paper in our hands, and nothing more. A man's soul also gets worn out by constant handling; at least, it eventually appears so to us—never again do we see its original design and beauty. We always lose through too familiar association with women and friends; and sometimes we lose the pearl of our life thereby.

Too close.—When we become too close to someone, it’s like constantly touching a beautiful engraving; eventually, we end up with a damaged piece of paper in our hands. A person’s spirit also gets worn out by constant interaction; at least, it eventually seems that way to us—we no longer see its original design and beauty. We always lose something through overly familiar relationships with women and friends; sometimes, we end up losing the most valuable part of our lives because of it.

429.

429.

The Golden Cradle.—The free spirit will always feel relieved when he has finally resolved to shake off the motherly care and guardianship with which women surround him. What harm will a rough wind, from which he has been so[Pg 313] anxiously protected, do him? Of what consequence is a genuine disadvantage, loss, misfortune, sickness, illness, fault, or folly more or less in his life, compared with the bondage of the golden cradle, the peacock's-feather fan, and the oppressive feeling that he must, in addition, be grateful because he is waited on and spoiled like a baby? Hence it is that the milk which is offered him by the motherly disposition of the women about him can so readily turn into gall.

The Golden Cradle.—The free spirit always feels relieved once he decides to break free from the motherly care and protection that women provide. What harm can a strong wind, from which he has been so[Pg 313] carefully shielded, do to him? How significant are the genuine setbacks, losses, misfortunes, illnesses, flaws, or mistakes in his life when compared to the confinement of the golden cradle, the peacock feather fan, and the burdensome expectation that he should be grateful for being pampered like a child? This is why the nurturing milk provided by the women around him can easily turn into bitterness.

430.

430.

A Voluntary Victim.—There is nothing by, which able women can so alleviate the lives of their husbands, should these be great and famous, as by becoming, so to speak, the receptacle for the general disfavour and occasional ill-humour of the rest of mankind. Contemporaries are usually accustomed to overlook many mistakes, follies, and even flagrant injustices in their great men if only they can find some one to maltreat and kill, as a proper victim for the relief of their feelings. A wife not infrequently has the ambition to present herself for this sacrifice, and then the husband may indeed feel satisfied,—he being enough of an egoist to have such a voluntary storm, rain, and lightning-conductor beside him.

A willing victim.—There’s nothing that capable women can do to make the lives of their great and famous husbands easier than by, in a way, becoming the target for the general discontent and occasional bad mood of others. People around them often ignore many mistakes, foolishness, and even blatant injustices in their great men if they can find someone to mistreat and blame, serving as a suitable victim to relieve their emotions. A wife often has the desire to take on this role, and then the husband may indeed feel content—being enough of an egoist to have such a willing lightning rod for his storms, rain, and troubles beside him.

431.

431.

Agreeable Adversaries.—The natural inclination, of women towards quiet, regular, happily[Pg 314] tuned existences and intercourse, the oil-like and calming effect of their influence upon the sea of life, operates unconsciously against the heroic inner impulse of the free spirit. Without knowing it, women act as if they were taking away the stones from the path of the wandering mineralogist in order that he might not strike his foot against them—when he has gone out for the very purpose of striking against them.

Friendly Rivals.—Women naturally tend towards peaceful, regular, and happily settled lives, and their calming influence on the chaos of life works unconsciously against the bold drive of the free spirit. Without realizing it, women seem to remove obstacles from the wandering mineralogist's path, so he doesn't stumble over them—when he is actually out to encounter those very challenges.

432.

432.

The Discord of Two Concords.—Woman wants to serve, and finds her happiness therein; the free spirit does not want to be served, and therein finds his happiness.

The Discord of Two Agreements.—A woman wants to serve and finds her happiness in that; the free spirit does not want to be served and finds his happiness in that.

433.

433.

Xantippe.—Socrates found a wife such as he required,—but he would not have sought her had he known her sufficiently well; even the heroism of his free spirit would not have gone so far. As a matter of fact, Xantippe forced him more and more into his peculiar profession, inasmuch as she made house and home doleful and dismal to him; she taught him to live in the streets and wherever gossiping and idling went on, and thereby made him the greatest Athenian street-dialectician, who had, at last, to compare himself to a gad-fly which a god had set on the neck of the beautiful horse Athens to prevent it from resting.

Xantippe.—Socrates found the wife he needed—but he wouldn't have chosen her if he'd known her well enough; even his heroic independent spirit wouldn't have stretched that far. In reality, Xantippe increasingly pushed him into his unique profession, since she made home life bleak and miserable for him. She taught him to live on the streets and to mingle with gossipers and idlers, turning him into the greatest street philosopher in Athens, who ultimately likened himself to a gadfly that a god had placed on the neck of the beautiful horse Athens to keep it from resting.

434.

434.

Blind to the Future.—Just as mothers have senses and eye only for those pains of their children that are evident to the senses and eye, so the wives of men of high aspirations cannot accustom themselves to see their husbands suffering, starving, or slighted,—although all this is, perhaps, not only the proof that they have rightly chosen their attitude in life, but even the guarantee that their great aims must be achieved some time. Women always intrigue privately against the higher souls of their husbands; they want to cheat them out of their future for the sake of a painless and comfortable present.

Blind to the Future.—Just as mothers tend to focus only on the obvious pains of their children, wives of ambitious men struggle to see their husbands in pain, starving, or overlooked—even though this may actually prove that they’ve made the right choices in life and guarantee that their big goals will eventually be achieved. Women often secretly plot against the higher aspirations of their husbands; they want to rob them of their future for the sake of an easy and comfortable present.

435.

435.

Authority and Freedom.—However highly women may honour their husbands, they honour still more the powers and ideas recognised by society; they have been accustomed for millennia to go along with their hands folded on their breasts, and their heads bent before everything dominant, disapproving of all resistance to public authority. They therefore unintentionally, and as if from instinct, hang themselves as a drag on the wheels of free-spirited, independent endeavour, and in certain circumstances make their husbands highly impatient, especially when the latter persuade themselves that it is really love which prompts the action of their wives. To disapprove of women's methods and generously to honour the motives that prompt them—that is man's nature and often enough his despair.

Power and Liberty.—No matter how much women may respect their husbands, they respect even more the powers and ideas recognized by society; they have been conditioned for thousands of years to stand quietly with their hands on their chests and their heads down before anything powerful, disapproving of any challenge to public authority. Thus, they unintentionally, as if by instinct, become a burden on the wheels of free-spirited, independent efforts, and in certain situations, this can make their husbands very frustrated, especially when the latter convince themselves that it is truly love that drives their wives' actions. To criticize women's approaches while generously praising the intentions behind them—that is a man's nature and often brings him despair.

436.

436.

Ceterum Censeo.—It is laughable when a company of paupers decree the abolition of the right of inheritance, and it is not less laughable when childless persons labour for the practical law-giving of a country: they have not enough ballast in their ship to sail safely over the ocean of the future. But it seems equally senseless if a man who has chosen for his mission the widest knowledge and estimation of universal existence, burdens himself with personal considerations for a family, with the support, protection, and care of wife and child, and in front of his telescope hangs that gloomy veil through which hardly a ray from the distant firmament can penetrate. Thus I, too, agree with the opinion that in matters of the highest philosophy all married men are to be suspected.

Ceterum Censeo.—It's ridiculous when a group of broke people decides to get rid of the right to inherit, and it’s equally absurd when people without children try to shape the laws of a country; they don’t have enough stability to navigate the future’s waters. It also seems pointless if someone dedicated to understanding and appreciating all of existence lets personal matters, like taking care of a family, weigh him down, blocking his view of the universe with a dark veil that hardly lets any light through. So, I, too, agree that when it comes to the deepest philosophical issues, all married men should be viewed with suspicion.

437.

437.

Finally.—There are many kinds of hemlock, and fate generally finds an opportunity to put a cup of this poison to the lips of the free spirit,—in order to "punish" him, as every one then says. What do the women do about him then? They cry and lament, and perhaps disturb the sunset-calm of the thinker, as they did in the prison at Athens. "Oh Crito, bid some one take those women away!" said Socrates at last.

Finally.—There are many types of hemlock, and fate usually finds a way to bring a cup of this poison to the lips of the free spirit—to "punish" him, as everyone likes to say. What do the women do about him then? They cry and mourn, and maybe disrupt the quiet reflection of the thinker, just like they did in the prison in Athens. "Oh Crito, tell someone to take those women away!" Socrates finally said.


[1] The opposite of this aphorism also holds good.—J.M.K.

[1] The reverse of this saying is also true.—J.M.K.

[2] It may be remarked that Nietzsche changed his view on this subject later on, and ascribed more importance to woman's intuition. Cf. also Disraeli's reference to the "High Priestesses of predestination."—J.M.K.

[2] It's worth noting that Nietzsche later changed his perspective on this topic and came to value women's intuition more. See also Disraeli's mention of the "High Priestesses of predestination."—J.M.K.


EIGHTH DIVISION.

A GLANCE AT THE STATE.

438.

438.

Asking to Be Heard.—The demagogic disposition and the intention of working upon the masses is at present common to all political parties; on this account they are all obliged to change their principles into great al fresco follies and thus make a show of them. In this matter there is no further alteration to be made: indeed, it is superfluous even to raise a finger against it; for here Voltaire's saying applies: "Quand la populace se mêle de raisonner, tout est perdu." Since this has happened we have to accommodate ourselves to the new conditions, as we have to accommodate ourselves when an earthquake has displaced the old boundaries and the contour of the land and altered the value of property. Moreover, when it is once for all a question in the politics of all parties to make life endurable to the greatest possible majority, this majority may always decide what they understand by an endurable life; if they believe their intellect capable of finding the right means to this end why should we doubt about it? They want, once for all, to be the architects of their own good or ill fortune; and if[Pg 318] their feeling of free choice and their pride in the five or six ideas that their brain conceals and brings to light, really makes life so agreeable to them that they gladly put up with the fatal consequences of their narrow-mindedness, there is little to object to, provided that their narrow-mindedness does not go so far as to demand that everything shall become politics in this sense, that all shall live and act according to this standard. For, in the first place, it must be more than ever permissible for some people to keep aloof from politics and to stand somewhat aside. To this they are also impelled by the pleasure of free choice, and connected with this there may even be some little pride in keeping silence when too many, and only the many, are speaking. Then this small group must be excused if they do not attach such great importance to the happiness of the majority (nations or strata of population may be understood thereby), and are occasionally guilty of an ironical grimace; for their seriousness lies elsewhere, their conception of happiness is quite different, and their aim cannot be encompassed by every clumsy hand that has just five fingers. Finally, there comes from time to time—what is certainly most difficult to concede to them, but must also be conceded—a moment when they emerge from their silent solitariness and try once more the strength of their lungs; they then call to each other like people lost in a wood, to make themselves known and for mutual encouragement; whereby, to be sure, much becomes audible that sounds evil to ears for which it is not intended.[Pg 319] Soon, however, silence again prevails in the wood, such silence that the buzzing, humming, and fluttering of the countless insects that live in, above, and beneath it, are again plainly heard.

Requesting to Be Heard.—The tendency to manipulate the masses is currently widespread among all political parties; because of this, they all have to transform their principles into grand al fresco spectacles and showcase them. There's no further change to be made here: in fact, it's unnecessary even to push back against it; for as Voltaire said: "Quand la populace se mêle de raisonner, tout est perdu." Since this has happened, we must adapt to the new reality, just like we must adapt when an earthquake shifts old boundaries and reshapes the land, altering property values. Furthermore, when it becomes the underlying goal of all parties to make life tolerable for the greatest possible majority, this majority will always define what they consider an acceptable life; if they believe their minds can find the right means to achieve that, why should we doubt it? They want, once and for all, to be the creators of their own fortune, whether good or bad; and if[Pg 318] their sense of choice and pride in the few ideas their minds produce makes life enjoyable enough for them to accept the negative consequences of their shortsightedness, there is little to criticize, as long as their narrow-mindedness doesn’t go so far as to demand that everything becomes political, that everyone must live and act by this standard. First of all, it must still be acceptable for some people to distance themselves from politics and adopt a somewhat separate stance. They are also motivated by the pleasure of choice, and there might even be some small pride in maintaining silence when too many, and only the majority, are speaking. This small group should be forgiven if they don’t prioritize the happiness of the majority (which could refer to nations or social classes) and occasionally display a sardonic expression; their focus is elsewhere, their idea of happiness is quite different, and their goals cannot be grasped by every clumsy hand with just five fingers. Finally, there come moments—though it’s certainly difficult to acknowledge, it must be done—when they step out from their silent solitude and test their voices again; they then call out to each other like people lost in a forest, trying to connect and encourage one another; as a result, much is heard that may sound unpleasant to ears for which it wasn’t meant.[Pg 319] However, soon silence returns to the forest, a silence where the buzzing, humming, and fluttering of the countless insects that live within, above, and below it can once again be clearly heard.

439.

439.

Culture and Caste.—A higher culture can only originate where there are two distinct castes of society: that of the working class, and that of the leisured class who are capable of true leisure; or, more strongly expressed, the caste of compulsory labour and the caste of free labour. The point of view of the division of happiness is not essential when it is a question of the production of a higher culture; in any case, however, the leisured caste is more susceptible to suffering and suffer more, their pleasure in existence is less and their task is greater. Now supposing there should be quite an interchange between the two castes, so that on the one hand the duller and less intelligent families and individuals are lowered from the higher caste into the lower, and, on the other hand, the freer men of the lower caste obtain access to the higher, a condition of things would be attained beyond which one can only perceive the open sea of vague wishes. Thus speaks to us the vanishing voice of the olden time; but where are there still ears to hear it?

Culture and Caste.—A more advanced culture can only emerge where there are two distinct social classes: the working class and the leisure class, who are able to truly enjoy leisure; or, to put it more directly, the class bound to compulsory work and the class engaged in free labor. When it comes to creating a higher culture, the division of happiness isn't crucial; however, the leisure class is more sensitive to suffering, experiences it more, finds less joy in existence, and has a greater burden. Now, if there were to be significant exchange between the two classes—where the less capable and less intelligent families and individuals drop from the higher class into the lower, and conversely, where the more liberated people from the lower class gain access to the higher class—such a situation would lead to a state beyond which we can only see the open sea of vague desires. Thus speaks to us the fading voice of the past; but where are those who can still listen?

440.

440.

Of Good Blood.—That which men and women of good blood possess much more than[Pg 320] others, and which gives them an undoubted right to be more highly appreciated, are two arts which are always increased by inheritance: the art of being able to command, and the art of proud obedience. Now wherever commanding is the business of the day (as in the great world of commerce and industry), there results something similar to these families of good blood, only the noble bearing in obedience is lacking which is an inheritance from feudal conditions and hardly grows any longer in the climate of our culture.

Of Good Blood.—What men and women from good families possess much more than[Pg 320] others, and which gives them a clear right to be valued more highly, are two skills that are usually passed down through generations: the ability to lead, and the skill of dignified submission. In environments where leadership is crucial (like in the vast world of business and industry), something similar emerges to these families of good blood; however, the noble aspect of obedience, which comes from feudal traditions, is rarely found anymore in our modern culture.

441.

441.

Subordination.—The subordination which is so highly valued in military and official ranks will soon become as incredible to us as the secret tactics of the Jesuits have already become; and when this subordination is no longer possible a multitude of astonishing results will no longer be attained, and the world will be all the poorer. It must disappear, for its foundation is disappearing, the belief in unconditional authority, in ultimate truth; even in military ranks physical compulsion is not sufficient to produce it, but only the inherited adoration of the princely as of something superhuman. In freer circumstances people subordinate themselves only on conditions, in compliance with a mutual contract, consequently with all the provisos of self-interest.

Subordination.—The subordination that is so highly valued in military and official ranks will soon seem as unbelievable to us as the secret tactics of the Jesuits already do; and when this subordination is no longer possible, many astonishing results will cease to exist, leaving the world poorer for it. It has to vanish because its foundation is crumbling—the belief in unconditional authority and ultimate truth. Even in military ranks, physical force alone can’t create it; only the inherited reverence for royalty as something superhuman can. In freer circumstances, people only subordinate themselves under certain conditions, based on a mutual agreement, therefore weighed down with all the caveats of self-interest.

442.

442.

The National Army.—The greatest disadvantage of the national army, now so much[Pg 321] glorified, lies in the squandering of men of the highest civilisation; it is only by the favourableness of all circumstances that there are such men at all; how carefully and anxiously should we deal with them, since long periods are required to create the chance conditions for the production of such delicately organised brains! But as the Greeks wallowed in the blood of Greeks, so do Europeans now in the blood of Europeans: and indeed, taken relatively, it is mostly the highly cultivated who are sacrificed, those who promise an abundant and excellent posterity; for such stand in the front of the battle as commanders, and also expose themselves to most danger, by reason of their higher ambition. At present, when quite other and higher tasks are assigned than patria and honor, the rough Roman patriotism is either something dishonourable or a sign of being behind the times.

The National Guard.—The biggest drawback of the national army, which is currently so much[Pg 321] praised, is the waste of highly developed individuals; it’s only because of favorable conditions that such people exist at all. We should handle them with great care and concern, as it takes a long time to create the circumstances needed for such finely tuned minds to thrive! Yet, just as the Greeks slaughtered each other, so do Europeans today spill the blood of their own. In fact, relatively speaking, it’s mostly the well-educated who become casualties, those who have the potential for a prosperous and exceptional future; they are the ones who lead the charge into battle and expose themselves to the greatest risks due to their higher aspirations. Nowadays, when we are called to pursue different and greater goals than patria and honor, the crude Roman sense of patriotism feels either shameful or outdated.

443.

443.

Hope As Presumption.—Our social order will slowly melt away, as all former orders have done, as soon as the suns of new opinions have shone upon mankind with a new glow. We can only wish this melting away in the hope thereof, and we are only reasonably entitled to hope when we believe that we and our equals have more strength in heart and head than the representatives of the existing state of things. As a rule, therefore, this hope will be a presumption, an over-estimation.

Hope as Assumption.—Our social order will slowly dissolve, just like all previous orders have, once new ideas bring a fresh perspective to humanity. We can only wish for this dissolution while hoping for it, and we are only justified in hoping when we believe that we and our peers possess more strength of heart and mind than those who represent the current state of affairs. Generally, therefore, this hope will be seen as a presumption, an over-estimation.

444.

444.

War.—Against war it may be said that it makes the victor stupid and the vanquished revengeful. In favour of war it may be said that it barbarises in both its above-named results, and thereby makes more natural; it is the sleep or the winter period of culture; man emerges from it with greater strength for good and for evil.

Conflict.—It can be argued against war that it dulls the victor and fuels resentment in the defeated. On the other hand, it can be argued in favor of war that it dehumanizes both sides in these ways, making them more primal; it's like a dormant phase or winter of culture; humanity comes out of it with more strength—both for good and for evil.

445.

445.

In the Prince's Service.—To be able to act quite regardlessly it is best for a statesman to carry out his work not for himself but for a prince. The eye of the spectator is dazzled by the splendour of this general disinterestedness, so that it does not see the malignancy and severity which the work of a statesman brings with it.[1]

In the Prince's Service.—For a statesman to act without restraint, it's ideal to do their work not for personal gain but for a prince. The observer is blinded by the grandeur of this overall selflessness, making it hard to notice the harmful and harsh realities that come with a statesman’s duties.[1]

446.

446.

A Question of Power, Not of Right.—As regards Socialism, in the eyes of those who always consider higher utility, if it is really a rising against their oppressors of those who for centuries have been oppressed and downtrodden, there is no problem of right involved (notwithstanding the ridiculous, effeminate question," How far ought we to grant its demands?") but only a problem of power;[Pg 323] the same, therefore, as in the case of a natural force,—steam, for instance,—which is either forced by man into his service, as a machine-god, or which, in case of defects of the machine, that is to say, defects of human calculation in its construction, destroys it and man together. In order to solve this question of power we must know how strong Socialism is, in what modification it may yet be employed as a powerful lever in the present mechanism of political forces; under certain circumstances we should do all we can to strengthen it. With every great force—be it the most dangerous—men have to think how they can make of it an instrument for their purposes. Socialism acquires a right only if war seems to have taken place between the two powers, the representatives of the old and the new, when, however, a wise calculation of the greatest possible preservation and advantageousness to both sides gives rise to a desire for a treaty. Without treaty no right. So far, however, there is neither war nor treaty on the ground in question, therefore no rights, no "ought."

A Matter of Power, Not of Right.—When it comes to Socialism, for those who focus on higher utility, if it's really a revolt against their oppressors by people who have been oppressed for centuries, there’s no question of right involved (despite the silly, weak question, "How far should we meet its demands?”); it’s solely a question of power; [Pg 323] similar to a natural force—like steam—that either gets harnessed by humans as a machine or, if the machine fails due to flaws in human design, it destroys both the machine and its operator. To address this issue of power, we need to understand how strong Socialism is and how it might still be used as a significant force in the current political landscape; in certain situations, we should do everything we can to bolster it. With any great force—even the most dangerous—people need to consider how to turn it into a tool for their own purposes. Socialism only gains right if a conflict appears to exist between the two opposing forces, the representatives of the old and the new; however, a wise calculation aimed at maximizing benefits and minimizing harm for both sides can create a desire for negotiation. Without negotiation, there is no right. As things stand, there is neither conflict nor negotiation regarding this issue, thus no rights and no "ought."

447.

447.

Utilising the Most Trivial Dishonesty.—The power of the press consists in the fact that every individual who ministers to it only feels himself bound and constrained to a very small extent. He usually expresses his opinion, but sometimes also does not express it in order to serve his party or the politics of his country, or[Pg 324] even himself. Such little faults of dishonesty, or perhaps only of a dishonest silence, are not hard to bear by the individual, but the consequences are extraordinary, because these little faults are committed by many at the same time. Each one says to himself: "For such small concessions I live better and can make my income; by the want of such little compliances I make myself impossible." Because it seems almost morally indifferent to write a line more (perhaps even without signature), or not to write it, a person who has money and influence can make any opinion a public one. He who knows that most people are weak in trifles, and wishes to attain his own ends thereby, is always dangerous.

Using the Slightest Dishonesty.—The power of the press lies in the fact that everyone involved feels only slightly bound and constrained. They usually share their opinion, but sometimes they choose not to share it in order to support their party, the politics of their country, or[Pg 324] even themselves. These small faults of dishonesty, or maybe just dishonest silence, are easy for the individual to handle, but the consequences can be significant since many people commit these small faults simultaneously. Each person thinks to themselves: "For these small concessions, I live better and can boost my income; without these little compromises, I make things difficult for myself." Because it seems almost morally neutral to write an extra line (maybe even without signing it), or to choose not to write it, a person with money and influence can turn any opinion into a public one. Those who know that most people are weak when it comes to minor things and want to use this for their own benefit are always a threat.

448.

448.

Too Loud a Tone in Grievances.—Through the fact that an account of a bad state of things (for instance, the crimes of an administration, bribery and arbitrary favour in political or learned bodies) is greatly exaggerated, it fails in its effect on intelligent people, but has all the greater effect on the unintelligent (who would have remained indifferent to an accurate and moderate account). But as these latter are considerably in the majority, and harbour in themselves stronger will-power and more impatient desire for action, the exaggeration becomes the cause of investigations, punishments, promises, and reorganisations. In so far it is useful to exaggerate the accounts of bad states of things.

Too Loud a Tone in Complaints.—When descriptions of a bad situation (like government corruption, bribery, and favoritism in politics or academia) are overly exaggerated, they lose their impact on thoughtful individuals, but they resonate even more with those who aren't as informed (who would have ignored a clear and balanced report). Since these less informed individuals make up the majority and tend to have a stronger will and a greater urgency for action, the exaggeration leads to investigations, punishments, promises, and reforms. In this way, overstating issues can be useful.

449.

449.

The Apparent WeatherMakers of Politics.—Just as people tacitly assume that he who understands the weather, and foretells it about a day in advance, makes the weather, so even the educated and learned, with a display of superstitious faith, ascribe to great statesmen as their most special work all the important changes and conjunctures that have taken place during their administration, when it is only evident that they knew something thereof a little earlier than other people and made their calculations accordingly,—thus they are also looked upon as weather-makers—and this belief is not the least important instrument of their power.

The Current WeatherPolitics Creators.—Just as people often believe that someone who understands the weather and can predict it a day in advance controls it, the educated and knowledgeable, with a hint of superstitious belief, attribute to great statesmen the credit for all the significant changes and events that have occurred during their time in office. In reality, it’s clear that these leaders simply had access to information a bit earlier than others and made their decisions based on that insight. Thus, they are also seen as weather-makers—and this belief is an important part of their power.

450.

450.

New and Old Conceptions of Government.—To draw such a distinction between Government and people as if two separate spheres of power, a stronger and higher, and a weaker and lower, negotiated and came to terms with each other, is a remnant of transmitted political sentiment, which still accurately represents the historic establishment of the conditions of power in most States. When Bismarck, for instance, describes the constitutional system as a compromise between Government and people, he speaks in accordance with a principle which has its reason in history (from whence, to be sure, it also derives its admixture of folly, without which nothing human[Pg 326] can exist). On the other hand, we must now learn—in accordance with a principle which has originated only in the brain and has still to make history—that Government is nothing but an organ of the people,—not an attentive, honourable "higher" in relation to a "lower" accustomed to modesty. Before we accept this hitherto unhistorical and arbitrary, although logical, formulation of the conception of Government, let us but consider its consequences, for the relation between people and Government is the strongest typical relation, after the pattern of which the relationship between teacher and pupil, master and servants, father and family, leader and soldier, master and apprentice, is unconsciously formed. At present, under the influence of the prevailing constitutional system of government, all these relationships are changing a little,—they are becoming compromises. But how they will have to be reversed and shifted, and change name and nature, when that newest of all conceptions has got the upper hand everywhere in people's minds!—to achieve which, however, a century may yet be required. In this matter there is nothing further to be wished for except caution and slow development.

New and Old Ideas About Government.—Making a distinction between Government and the people as if they were two separate areas of power—one stronger and higher, the other weaker and lower—reflects an outdated political belief that still accurately illustrates the historical foundations of power in most States. For example, when Bismarck characterizes the constitutional system as a compromise between the Government and the people, he speaks from a principle rooted in history (which, of course, also brings its share of folly, as nothing human[Pg 326] can escape that). However, we must now understand—in line with a principle that has emerged only from the mind and still needs to shape history—that the Government is simply an instrument of the people—not an attentive, honorable "higher" authority in relation to a "lower" class accustomed to humility. Before we adopt this previously unhistorical and arbitrary, yet logical, view of Government, let's think about its implications, for the relationship between the people and the Government is the strongest typical relationship, similar to those between teacher and student, master and servants, father and family, leader and soldiers, master and apprentice, which are unconsciously modeled after it. Currently, due to the existing constitutional system of government, all these relationships are evolving a bit—they're turning into compromises. But just imagine how they will need to be changed and transformed, altering their names and natures, when this newest idea takes full hold of the public mindset!—for which, however, a century may still be necessary. In this regard, all one can wish for is patience and gradual progress.

451.

451.

Justice As the Decoy-cry of Parties.—Well may noble (if not exactly very intelligent) representatives of the governing classes asseverate: "We will treat men equally and grant them equal rights"; so far a socialistic mode of thought[Pg 327] which is based on justice is possible; but, as has been said, only within the ranks of the governing class, which in this case practises justice with sacrifices and abnegations. On the other hand, to demand equality of rights, as do the Socialists of the subject caste, is by no means the outcome of justice, but of covetousness. If you expose bloody pieces of flesh to a beast, and withdraw them again, until it finally begins to roar, do you think that roaring implies justice?

Justice as the Decoy Cry of Parties.—It's easy for noble (if not particularly intelligent) representatives of the ruling class to say: "We will treat everyone equally and give them equal rights"; this is a socialistic way of thinking that relies on justice and is only feasible within the governing class, which, in this case, practices justice through sacrifices and self-denial. On the flip side, demanding equal rights, like the Socialists from the oppressed class do, isn't a result of justice but of greed. If you show a predator bloody pieces of meat and then take them away until it starts to roar, do you really think that roaring represents justice?

452.

452.

Possession and Justice.—When the Socialists point out that the division of property at the present day is the consequence of countless deeds of injustice and violence, and, in summa, repudiate obligation to anything with so unrighteous a basis, they only perceive something isolated. The entire past of ancient civilisation is built up on violence, slavery, deception, and error; we, however, cannot annul ourselves, the heirs of all these conditions, nay, the concrescences of all this past, and are not entitled to demand the withdrawal of a single fragment thereof. The unjust disposition lurks also in the souls of non-possessors; they are not better than the possessors and have no moral prerogative; for at one time or another their ancestors have been possessors. Not forcible new distributions, but gradual transformations of opinion are necessary; justice in all matters must become greater, the instinct of violence weaker.

Ownership and Justice.—When Socialists argue that the current division of property results from countless acts of injustice and violence, and, in summa, reject any obligation to something so unjust, they only see part of the picture. The whole history of ancient civilization is built on violence, slavery, deception, and mistakes. We cannot erase ourselves, the inheritors of all these conditions, who embody all this past, and we have no right to demand the removal of even a small part of it. The unjust mindset also exists in the hearts of those without possessions; they are not any better than those who have possessions and don’t hold any moral superiority, as at some point, their ancestors were possessors too. What we need is not forced redistributions, but gradual changes in our way of thinking; justice in all matters must increase, and the instinct for violence must decrease.

453.

453.

The Helmsman of the Passions.—The statesman excites public passions in order to have the advantage of the counter-passions thereby aroused. To give an example: a German statesman knows quite well that the Catholic Church will never have the same plans as Russia; indeed, that it would far rather be allied with the Turk than with the former country; he likewise knows that Germany is threatened with great danger from an alliance between France and Russia. If he can succeed, therefore, in making France the focus and fortress of the Catholic Church, he has averted this danger for a lengthy period. He has, accordingly, an interest in showing hatred against the Catholics in transforming, by all kinds of hostility, the supporters of the Pope's authority into an impassioned political power which is opposed to German politics, and must, as a matter of course, coalesce with France as the adversary of Germany; his aim is the catholicising of France, just as necessarily as Mirabeau saw the salvation of his native land in de-catholicising it. The one State, therefore, desires to muddle millions of minds of another State in order to gain advantage thereby. It is the same disposition which supports the republican form of government of a neighbouring State—le désordre organisé, as Mérimée says—for the sole reason that it assumes that this form of government makes the nation weaker, more distracted, less fit for war.

The Navigator of Emotions.—The politician stirs up public emotions to gain an upper hand over the resulting counter-emotions. For instance, a German politician knows full well that the Catholic Church’s interests don’t align with those of Russia; in fact, they would prefer to team up with the Turks rather than the Russians. He also realizes that Germany faces a significant threat from an alliance between France and Russia. Thus, if he can make France the center and stronghold of the Catholic Church, he can mitigate this threat for a long time. He therefore has a vested interest in fostering animosity towards Catholics, turning the Pope's supporters into a passionate political force that stands against German interests and will naturally align with France as Germany's opponent; his goal is to make France more Catholic, just as Mirabeau believed that saving his country required de-catholicizing it. One state, therefore, seeks to confuse the minds of millions in another state to gain an advantage. This same mindset supports the republican government of a neighboring state—le désordre organisé, as Mérimée puts it—simply because it believes that this form of government weakens the nation, makes it more distracted, and less capable of going to war.

454.

454.

The Dangerous Revolutionary Spirits.—Those who are bent on revolutionising society may be divided into those who seek something for themselves thereby and those who seek something for their children and grandchildren. The latter are the more dangerous, for they have the belief and the good conscience of disinterestedness. The others can be appeased by favours: those in power are still sufficiently rich and wise to adopt that expedient. The danger begins as soon as the aims become impersonal; revolutionists seeking impersonal interests may consider all defenders of the present state of things as personally interested, and may therefore feel themselves superior to their opponents.

The Risky Revolutionary Spirits.—People who are determined to change society can be divided into those who are looking for personal gain and those who are fighting for the future of their children and grandchildren. The latter group is more dangerous because they genuinely believe they are acting selflessly. The former can often be satisfied with rewards: those in power are usually wealthy and smart enough to use this tactic. The real danger arises when their goals become impersonal; revolutionaries who pursue impersonal interests may view all defenders of the current system as self-serving and may therefore see themselves as morally superior to their opponents.

455.

455.

The Political Value of Paternity.—When a man has no sons he has not a full right to join in a discussion concerning the needs of a particular community. A person must himself have staked his dearest object along with the others: that alone binds him fast to the State; he must have in view the well-being of his descendants, and must, therefore, above all, have descendants in order to take a right and natural share in all institutions and the changes thereof. The development of higher morality depends on a person's having sons; it disposes him to be un-egoistic, or, more correctly, it extends his egoism in its duration and permits him earnestly to strive after goals which lie beyond his individual lifetime.

The Political Value of Fatherhood.—When a man has no sons, he doesn't fully have the right to participate in discussions about the needs of a community. A person must have staked his most valued interests along with others; that alone ties him to the State. He must consider the well-being of his descendants, and therefore, to have a legitimate and natural role in all institutions and their changes, he must, above all, have descendants. The development of higher morality relies on a person having sons; it encourages him to be less self-centered, or more accurately, it expands his self-interest over time and allows him to sincerely pursue goals that extend beyond his individual lifetime.

456.

456.

Pride of Descent.—A man may be justly proud of an unbroken line of good ancestors down to his father,—not however of the line itself, for every one has that. Descent from good ancestors constitutes the real nobility of birth; a single break in the chain, one bad ancestor, therefore, destroys the nobility of birth. Every one who talks about his nobility should be asked: "Have you no violent, avaricious, dissolute, wicked, cruel man amongst your ancestors?" If with good cognisance and conscience he can answer No, then let his friendship be sought.

Pride in Heritage.—A person can rightfully take pride in having a continuous line of good ancestors leading back to their father—not in the lineage itself, since everyone has that. Coming from good ancestors truly represents the nobility of birth; one break in the chain, one bad ancestor, destroys that nobility. Anyone who boasts about their nobility should be asked: "Do you have no violent, greedy, immoral, wicked, or cruel person among your ancestors?" If they can sincerely answer No, then their friendship is worth pursuing.

457.

457.

Slaves and Labourers.—The fact that we regard the gratification of vanity as of more account than all other forms of well-being (security, position, and pleasures of all sorts), is shown to a ludicrous extent by every one wishing for the abolition of slavery and utterly abhorring to put any one into this position (apart altogether from political reasons), while every one must acknowledge to himself that in all respects slaves live more securely and more happily than modern labourers, and that slave labour is very easy labour compared with that of the "labourer." We protest in the name of the "dignity of man"; but, expressed more simply, that is just our darling vanity which feels non-equality, and inferiority in public estimation, to be the hardest lot of all.[Pg 331] The cynic thinks differently concerning the matter, because he despises honour:—and so Diogenes was for some time a slave and tutor.

Workers and Laborers.—The fact that we value the satisfaction of vanity more than any other type of well-being (like security, status, and various pleasures) is humorously illustrated by everyone wanting to end slavery and absolutely hating the idea of anyone being in that situation (aside from political reasons). At the same time, everyone must admit to themselves that, in every way, slaves live more safely and happily than modern laborers, and that slave labor is much easier than that of the "laborer." We make protests in the name of the "dignity of man"; but, to put it more simply, that’s just our precious vanity feeling that non-equality and inferiority in public opinion is the toughest situation of all. [Pg 331] The cynic sees things differently because he doesn’t care about honor:—and so Diogenes was a slave and tutor for a time.

458.

458.

Leading Minds and Their Instruments.—We see that great statesmen, and in general all who have to employ many people to carry out their plans, sometimes proceed one way and sometimes another; they either choose with great skill and care the people suitable for their plans, and then leave them a comparatively large amount of liberty, because they know that the nature of the persons selected impels them precisely to the point where they themselves would have them go; or else they choose badly, in fact take whatever comes to hand, but out of every piece of clay they form something useful for their purpose. These latter minds are the more high-handed; they also desire more submissive instruments; their knowledge of mankind is usually much smaller, their contempt of mankind greater than in the case of the first mentioned class, but the machines they construct generally work better than the machines from the workshops of the former.

Top Thinkers and Their Tools.—We see that great leaders, and generally anyone who has to hire a lot of people to carry out their plans, sometimes take different approaches; they either carefully select the right people for their goals and grant them a fair amount of freedom, knowing that these individuals are naturally inclined to move towards the desired outcome, or they make poor choices, taking anyone they can find, yet somehow manage to mold each individual into something useful for their needs. The latter type of leader tends to be more assertive; they also prefer more compliant helpers. Their understanding of human nature is usually much less developed, and they often hold a greater disdain for others compared to the first group, yet the systems they create often function better than those crafted by the former.

459.

459.

Arbitrary Law Necessary.—Jurists dispute whether the most perfectly thought-out law or that which is most easily understood should prevail in a nation. The former, the best model of which is Roman Law, seems incomprehensible[Pg 332] to the layman, and is therefore not the expression of his sense of justice. Popular laws, the Germanic, for instance, have been rude, superstitious, illogical, and in part idiotic, but they represented very definite, inherited national morals and sentiments. But where, as with us, law i no longer custom, it can only command and be compulsion; none of us any longer possesses a traditional sense of justice; we must therefore content ourselves with arbitrary laws, which are the expressions of the necessity that there must be law. The most logical is then in any case the most acceptable, because it is the most impartial, granting even that in every case the smallest unit of measure in the relation of crime and punishment is arbitrarily fixed.

Necessary Random Law.—Legal experts debate whether a well-thought-out law or one that is easy to understand should be prioritized in a country. The former, best exemplified by Roman Law, often feels incomprehensible[Pg 332] to the average person, and doesn't reflect their sense of justice. Popular laws, like the Germanic ones, may have been crude, superstitious, illogical, and at times foolish, but they represented clear, inherited national morals and values. However, in our case, where law is no longer based on custom, it can only command and coerce; we no longer have a traditional sense of justice. We must therefore settle for arbitrary laws, which are necessary to establish that there must be law. The most logical laws are thus the most acceptable because they are the most impartial, even if in every case, the smallest measure of crime and punishment is arbitrarily determined.

460.

460.

The Great Man of the Masses.—The recipe for what the masses call a great man is easily given. In all circumstances let a person provide them with something very pleasant, or first let him put it into their heads that this or that would be very pleasant, and then let him give it to them. On no account give it immediately, however: but let him acquire it by the greatest exertions, or seem thus to acquire it. The masses must have the impression that there is a powerful, nay indomitable strength of will operating; at least it must seem to be there operating. Everybody admires a strong will, because nobody possesses it, and everybody says[Pg 333] to himself that if he did possess it there would no longer be any bounds for him and his egoism. If, then, it becomes evident that such a strong will effects something very agreeable to the masses, instead of hearkening to the wishes of covetousness, people admire once more, and wish good luck to themselves. Moreover, if he has all the qualities of the masses, they are the less ashamed before him, and he is all the more popular. Consequently, he may be violent, envious, rapacious, intriguing, flattering, fawning, inflated, and, according to circumstances, anything whatsoever.

The Great Man of the People.—The formula for what the masses consider a great man is pretty straightforward. In any situation, let a person offer them something really enjoyable, or first let him suggest that something would be really enjoyable, and then let him provide it. However, don’t give it right away, but make him work hard for it, or at least give the impression that he did. The masses need to feel that there’s a powerful, even unstoppable, strength of will at play; it should at least seem like it’s there. Everyone admires a strong will because no one really has it, and everyone thinks[Pg 333] to themselves that if they did possess it, there would be no limits for them and their self-interest. If it becomes clear that such a strong will brings something very pleasing to the masses instead of catering to greed, people admire once again and wish themselves good fortune. Furthermore, if he shares the qualities of the masses, they feel less embarrassed around him, making him even more popular. As a result, he can be aggressive, envious, greedy, scheming, flattering, submissive, boastful, and, depending on the situation, anything at all.

461.

461.

Prince and God.—People frequently commune with their princes in the same way as with their God, as indeed the prince himself was frequently the Deity's representative, or at least His high priest. This almost uncanny disposition of veneration, disquiet, and shame, grew, and has grown, much weaker, but occasionally it flares up again, and fastens upon powerful persons generally. The cult of genius is an echo of this veneration of Gods and Princes. Wherever an effort is made to exalt particular men to the superhuman, there is also a tendency to regard whole grades of the population as coarser and baser than they really are.

Prince and God.—People often connect with their princes in the same way they do with their God, since the prince was frequently seen as a representative of the Deity, or at least His high priest. This almost eerie blend of reverence, unease, and shame has diminished over time, but it sometimes resurfaces, particularly around influential figures. The worship of genius reflects this reverence for Gods and Princes. Whenever there’s an attempt to elevate certain individuals to a superhuman status, it also tends to lead to the perception that entire groups of people are coarser and less admirable than they actually are.

462.

462.

My Utopia.—In a better arranged society the heavy work and trouble of life will be assigned to those who suffer least through it, to the most[Pg 334] obtuse, therefore; and so step by step up to those who are most sensitive to the highest and sublimest kinds of suffering, and who therefore still suffer notwithstanding the greatest alleviations of life.

My Ideal World.—In a better organized society, the hard work and challenges of life will be given to those who are least affected by them, to the most[Pg 334] unaware, and gradually up to those who are most attuned to the deepest and most profound forms of suffering, and who continue to experience pain even with the greatest comforts in life.

463.

463.

A Delusion in Subversive Doctrines.—There are political and social dreamers who ardently and eloquently call for the overthrow of all order, in the belief that the proudest fane of beautiful humanity will then rear itself immediately, almost of its own accord. In these dangerous dreams there is still an echo of Rousseau's superstition, which believes in a marvellous primordial goodness of human nature, buried up, as it were; and lays all the blame of that burying-up on the institutions of civilisation, on society, State, and education. Unfortunately, it is well known by historical experiences that every such overthrow reawakens into new life the wildest energies, the long-buried horrors and extravagances of remotest ages; that an overthrow, therefore, may possibly be a source of strength to a deteriorated humanity, but never a regulator, architect, artist, or perfecter of human nature. It was not Voltaire's moderate nature, inclined towards regulating, purifying, and reconstructing, but Rousseau's passionate follies and half-lies that aroused the optimistic spirit of the Revolution, against which I cry, "Écrasez l'infâme!" Owing to this the Spirit of enlightenment and progressive development has been long scared[Pg 335] away; let us see—each of us individually—if it is not possible to recall it!

A Misconception in Subversive Ideas.—There are political and social dreamers who passionately and articulately call for the end of all order, believing that the grandest vision of humanity will then rise right away, almost on its own. In these dangerous dreams, there's still a trace of Rousseau's belief in a miraculous original goodness of human nature, which is buried deep; and they blame this burial on the institutions of civilization—on society, the State, and education. Unfortunately, historical experiences show that each time such an overthrow happens, it revives the wildest energies, the long-buried horrors and extremities of ancient times; thus, an overthrow may very well invigorate a degraded humanity, but it can never regulate, shape, create, or perfect human nature. It was not Voltaire's moderate nature, which aimed to regulate, purify, and reconstruct, but Rousseau's passionate follies and half-truths that sparked the optimistic spirit of the Revolution, against which I cry, "Écrasez l'infâme!" Because of this, the Spirit of enlightenment and progressive development has been scared away for a long time[Pg 335]; let us see—each of us individually—if it is possible to bring it back!

464.

464.

Moderation.—When perfect resoluteness in thinking and investigating, that is to say, freedom of spirit, has become a feature of character, it produces moderation of conduct; for it weakens avidity, attracts much extant energy for the furtherance of intellectual aims, and shows the semi-usefulness, or uselessness and danger, of all sudden changes.

Moderation.—When having a strong determination in thinking and exploring, meaning freedom of spirit, becomes a part of someone's character, it leads to moderation in behavior; this reduces greed, channels a lot of existing energy towards achieving intellectual goals, and highlights the partial usefulness, or the uselessness and risks, of sudden changes.

465.

465.

The Resurrection of the Spirit.—A nation usually renews its youth on a political sick-bed, and there finds again the spirit which it had gradually lost in seeking and maintaining power. Culture is indebted most of all to politically weakened periods.

The Resurrection of the Soul.—A nation often rejuvenates during a political crisis, and in that moment, it rediscovers the spirit it had slowly lost while pursuing and holding onto power. Culture owes a great deal to times of political weakness.

466.

466.

New Opinions in the Old Home.—The overthrow of opinions is not immediately followed by the overthrow of institutions; on the contrary, the new opinions dwell for a long time in the desolate and haunted house of their predecessors, and conserve it even for want of a habitation.

New Perspectives in the Old Home.—The fall of old beliefs doesn't instantly lead to the downfall of old institutions; in fact, new beliefs often linger for quite a while in the empty and eerie home of their predecessors, holding onto it even out of necessity for a place to belong.

467.

467.

Public Education.—In large States public education will always be extremely mediocre, for[Pg 336] the same reason that in large kitchens the cooking is at best only mediocre.

Public Education.—In large states, public education will always be pretty mediocre, for[Pg 336] the same reason that in large kitchens, the cooking is usually just average.

468.

468.

Innocent Corruption.—In all institutions into which the sharp breeze of public criticism does not penetrate an innocent corruption grows up like a fungus (for instance, in learned bodies and senates).

Innocent corruption.—In all institutions where the refreshing wind of public criticism doesn’t reach, an innocent corruption develops like a fungus (for example, in academic organizations and legislative bodies).

469.

469.

Scholars As Politicians.—To scholars who become politicians the comic role is usually assigned; they have to be the good conscience of a state policy.

Academics as Politicians.—Scholars who enter politics are often given a comic role; they are expected to be the moral compass of state policy.

470.

470.

The Wolf Hidden Behind the Sheep.—Almost every politician, in certain circumstances, has such need of an honest man that he breaks into the sheep-fold like a famished wolf; not, however, to devour a stolen sheep, but to hide himself behind its woolly back.

The Wolf Concealed Among the Sheep.—Almost every politician, in certain situations, needs an honest person so desperately that they sneak into the sheepfold like a starving wolf; not to eat a stolen sheep, but to conceal themselves behind its fluffy back.

471.

471.

Happy Times.—A happy age is no longer possible, because men only wish for it but do not desire to have it; and each individual, when good days come for him, learns positively to pray for disquiet and misery. The destiny of mankind is arranged for happy moments—every life has such—but not for happy times. Nevertheless, such times will continue to exist in man's imagination[Pg 337] as "over the hills and far away," an heirloom of his earliest ancestors; for the idea of the happy age, from the earliest times to the present, has no doubt been derived from the state in which man, after violent exertions in hunting and warfare, gives himself over to repose, stretches out his limbs, and hears the wings of sleep rustle around him. It is a false conclusion when, in accordance with that old habit, man imagines that after whole periods of distress and trouble he will be able also to enjoy the state of happiness in proportionate increase and duration.

Good Times.—A truly happy age isn't possible anymore, because people only wish for it but don't actually want to achieve it; and whenever good days come their way, individuals end up praying for unrest and misery. Mankind's destiny includes happy moments—everyone experiences them—but not lasting happy times. Still, those happy times will remain in people's imaginations[Pg 337] as "over the hills and far away," a heritage from our earliest ancestors. The concept of a happy age, from ancient times to now, most likely comes from the state in which a person, after intense efforts in hunting and fighting, allows themselves to relax, stretches out, and feels the gentle embrace of sleep. It's a misguided thought when, following that old pattern, people believe that after long periods of suffering and hardship, they can also enjoy happiness in greater amounts and for longer periods.

472.

472.

Religion and Government.—So long as the State, or, more properly, the Government, regards itself as the appointed guardian of a number of minors, and on their account considers the question whether religion should be preserved or abolished, it is highly probable that it will always decide for the preservation thereof. For religion satisfies the nature of the individual in times of loss, destitution, terror, and distrust, in cases, therefore, where the Government feels itself incapable of doing anything directly for the mitigation of the spiritual sufferings of the individual; indeed, even in general unavoidable and next to inevitable evils (famines, financial crises, and wars) religion gives to the masses an attitude of tranquillity and confiding expectancy. Whenever the necessary or accidental deficiencies of the State Government, or the dangerous consequences[Pg 338] of dynastic interests, strike the eyes of the intelligent and make them refractory, the unintelligent will only think they see the finger of God therein and will submit with patience to the dispensations from on high (a conception in which divine and human modes of government usually coalesce); thus internal civil peace and continuity of development will be preserved. The power, which lies in the unity of popular feeling, in the existence of the same opinions and aims for all, is protected and confirmed by religion,—the rare cases excepted in which a priesthood cannot agree with the State about the price, and therefore comes into conflict with it. As a rule the State will know how to win over the priests, because it needs their most private and secret system for educating souls, and knows how to value servants who apparently, and outwardly, represent quite other interests. Even at present no power can become "legitimate" without the assistance of the priests; a fact which Napoleon understood. Thus, absolutely paternal government and the careful preservation of religion necessarily go hand-in-hand. In this connection it must be taken for granted that the rulers and governing classes are enlightened concerning the advantages which religion affords, and consequently feel themselves to a certain extent superior to it, inasmuch as they use it as a means; thus freedom of spirit has its origin here. But how will it be when the totally different interpretation of the idea of Government, such as is taught in democratic States, begins to prevail? When one sees in it[Pg 339] nothing but the instrument of the popular will, no "upper" in contrast to an "under," but merely a function of the sole sovereign, the people? Here also only the same attitude which the people assume towards religion can be assumed by the Government; every diffusion of enlightenment will have to find an echo even in the representatives, and the utilising and exploiting of religious impulses and consolations for State purposes will not be so easy (unless powerful party leaders occasionally exercise an influence resembling that of enlightened despotism). When, however, the State is not permitted to derive any further advantage from religion, or when people think far too variously on religious matters to allow the State to adopt a consistent and uniform procedure with respect to them, the way out of the difficulty will necessarily present itself, namely to treat religion as a private affair and leave it to the conscience and custom of each single individual. The first result of all is that religious feeling seems to be strengthened, inasmuch as hidden and suppressed impulses thereof, which the State had unintentionally or intentionally stifled, now break forth and rush to extremes; later on, however, it is found that religion is over-grown with sects, and that an abundance of dragon's teeth were sown as soon as religion was made a private affair. The spectacle of strife, and the hostile laying bare of all the weaknesses of religious confessions, admit finally of no other expedient except that every better and more talented person should make irreligiousness[Pg 340] his private affair, a sentiment which now obtains the upper hand even in the minds of the governing classes, and, almost against their will, gives an anti-religious character to their measures. As soon as this happens, the sentiment of persons still religiously disposed, who formerly adored the State as something half sacred or wholly sacred, changes into decided hostility to the State; they lie in wait for governmental measures, seeking to hinder, thwart, and disturb as much as they can, and, by the fury of their contradiction, drive the opposing parties, the irreligious ones, into an almost fanatical enthusiasm for the State; in connection with which there is also the silently co-operating influence, that since their separation from religion the hearts of persons in these circles are conscious of a void, and seek by devotion to the State to provide themselves provisionally with a substitute for religion, a kind of stuffing for the void. After these perhaps lengthy transitional struggles, it is finally decided whether the religious parties are still strong enough to revive an old condition of things, and turn the wheel backwards: in which case enlightened despotism (perhaps less enlightened and more timorous than formerly), inevitably gets the State into its hands,—or whether the non-religious parties achieve their purpose, and, possibly through schools and education, check the increase of their opponents during several generations, and finally make them no longer possible. Then, however, their enthusiasm for the State also abates: it always becomes more obvious that along with the[Pg 341] religious adoration which regards the State as a mystery and a supernatural institution, the reverent and pious relation to it has also been convulsed. Henceforth individuals see only that side of the State which may be useful or injurious to them, and press forward by all means to obtain an influence over it. But this rivalry soon becomes too great; men and parties change too rapidly, and throw each other down again too furiously from the mountain when they have only just succeeded in getting aloft. All the measures which such a Government carries out lack the guarantee of permanence; people then fight shy of undertakings which would require the silent growth of future decades or centuries to produce ripe fruit. Nobody henceforth feels any other obligation to a law than to submit for the moment to the power which introduced the law; people immediately set to work, however, to undermine it by a new power, a newly-formed majority. Finally—it may be confidently asserted—the distrust of all government, the insight into the useless and harassing nature of these short-winded struggles, must drive men to an entirely new resolution: to the abrogation of the conception of the State and the abolition of the contrast of "private and public." Private concerns gradually absorb the business of the State; even the toughest residue which is left over from the old work of governing (the business, for instance, which is meant to protect private persons from private persons) will at last some day be managed by private enterprise. The neglect, decline, and[Pg 342] death of the State, the liberation of the private person (I am careful not to say the individual), are the consequences of the democratic conception of the State; that is its mission. When it has accomplished its task,—which, like everything human, involves much rationality and irrationality,—and when all relapses into the old malady have been overcome, then a new leaf in the story-book of humanity will be unrolled, on which readers will find all kinds of strange tales and perhaps also some amount of good. To repeat shortly what has been said: the interests of the tutelary Government and the interests of religion go hand-in-hand, so that when the latter begins to decay the foundations of the State are also shaken. The belief in a divine regulation of political affairs, in a mystery in the existence of the State, is of religious origin: if religion disappears, the State will inevitably lose its old veil of Isis, and will no longer arouse veneration. The sovereignty of the people, looked at closely, serves also to dispel the final fascination and superstition in the realm of these sentiments; modern democracy is the historical form of the decay of the State. The outlook which results from this certain decay is not, however, unfortunate in every respect; the wisdom and the selfishness of men are the best developed of all their qualities; when the State no longer meets the demands of these impulses, chaos will least of all result, but a still more appropriate expedient than the State will get the mastery over the State. How man organising forces have already been seen to die[Pg 343]< out! For example, that of the gens or clan which for millennia was far mightier than the power of the family, and indeed already ruled and regulated long before the latter existed. We ourselves see the important notions of the right and might of the family, which once possessed the supremacy as far as the Roman system extended, always becoming paler and feebler. In the same way a later generation will also see the State become meaningless in certain parts of the world,—an idea which many contemporaries can hardly contemplate without alarm and horror. To labour for the propagation and realisation of this idea is, certainly, another thing; one must think very presumptuously of one's reason, and only half understand history, to set one's hand to the plough at present—when as yet no one can show us the seeds that are afterwards to be sown upon the broken soil. Let us, therefore, trust to the "wisdom and selfishness of men" that the State may yet exist a good while longer, and that the destructive attempts of over-zealous, too hasty sciolists may be in vain!

Religion and Politics.—As long as the State, or more accurately, the Government, sees itself as the designated protector of a group of minors and debates whether religion should be maintained or abolished for their sake, it's very likely that it will opt for preserving religion. Religion meets the needs of individuals during times of loss, poverty, fear, and uncertainty—situations where the Government feels unable to alleviate the spiritual suffering of individuals directly. In unavoidable crises like famines, financial downturns, and wars, religion provides the masses with a sense of calm and hopeful anticipation. Whenever the citizens, especially the educated, notice the shortcomings of the State or the harmful consequences of royal interests, the less educated will interpret these issues as divine intervention and accept them patiently as decisions from on high (a belief where divine and governmental authority often merge); hence, civil peace and a smooth development will be maintained. The unity of popular sentiment, shared opinions, and collective goals is secured and supported by religion—except in rare instances where the clergy disagrees with the State over compensation, leading to conflict. Typically, the State knows how to gain the favor of the clergy because it relies on their intimate and secretive methods for guiding souls and appreciates those who seem to advocate different interests. No authority can be deemed “legitimate” without the clergy's support—a truth Napoleon recognized. Therefore, paternal governance and the careful preservation of religion are intrinsically linked. It can be assumed that the rulers and governing classes are aware of the benefits that religion provides and feel somewhat superior to it since they use it as a tool; this is the origin of spiritual freedom. But what happens when a radically different perspective on the idea of Government, as taught in democratic states, starts to dominate? When it's viewed merely as an instrument of the people's will, with no "upper" tier opposed to an "under," but just a function of the sole sovereign, the people? The Government can only adopt an attitude mirroring that of the people towards religion; any spread of enlightenment must resonate with the representatives, and leveraging religious sentiments for State purposes won't be simple (unless powerful party leaders occasionally exert a kind of enlightened autocracy). When the State can no longer benefit from religion, or when diverse views on religion make it impossible for the State to maintain a consistent approach, the solution becomes clear: treat religion as a private matter and leave it to the conscience and customs of each individual. Initially, this may seem to strengthen religious feelings, as repressed impulses that the State either stifled intentionally or unintentionally now break free and intensify; however, it will later be evident that religion becomes overwhelmed with sects, and countless conflicts arise as soon as it is made a private issue. The resulting strife and the harsh unveiling of the weaknesses in religious beliefs lead to the conclusion that every better and more capable individual should adopt irreligion as their private concern, a feeling increasingly gaining ground even among the governing classes, inadvertently imparting an anti-religious tone to their policies. Once this shift occurs, the sentiment of those still attached to religion, who once viewed the State as semi-sacred or fully sacred, transforms into outright hostility to the State; they watch government actions closely, trying to obstruct, disrupt, and counteract as much as possible, and their vehement resistance pushes the opposing parties, the irreligious ones, into a fervent enthusiasm for the State; this is compounded by the silent influence of those in these circles feeling a void since separating from religion, seeking a temporary substitute for it in devotion to the State, a kind of filler for their emptiness. After potentially lengthy transitional struggles, the decisive question arises: Are the religious groups still strong enough to restore the previous state of affairs and reverse progress? In that case, enlightened despotism (perhaps less enlightened and more fearful than before) will inevitably regain control of the State, or whether the non-religious factions will succeed in their goal and, possibly through education and schools, curb the growth of their opponents over several generations, eventually rendering them obsolete. However, their enthusiasm for the State will also diminish: it becomes increasingly clear that alongside reverent worship viewing the State as a mystery and supernatural entity, the respectful and devout relation to it will likewise break down. From now on, individuals will only focus on the aspects of the State that can either help or hurt them, and will strive by all means to gain influence over it. Yet this competition can soon become overwhelming; people and parties shift too quickly and aggressively push each other down just as they begin to ascend. All the actions taken by such a Government lack long-term stability; people become wary of initiatives that would require a slow, organic development over many years or even decades to yield results. No one feels obligated to follow a law beyond submitting to the current power that enacted it; they quickly begin to seek to undermine it through a new power and a newly formed majority. Ultimately, it can confidently be asserted that the lack of trust in all governments, combined with an understanding of the futile and burdensome nature of these transient struggles, will compel people toward an entirely new resolution: to abolish the concept of the State and eliminate the distinction between "private and public." Private matters gradually come to encompass the functions of the State; even the remnants of the old governing tasks (for instance, those meant to protect private individuals from one another) will eventually be managed by private entities. The neglect, decline, and [Pg 342] death of the State, alongside the liberation of individuals (I refrain from saying individuals in an ideal sense), are the consequences of the democratic conception of the State; that is its purpose. When it has fulfilled its role—which, like all human endeavors, contains both rationality and irrationality—and any regressions to the previous issues have been resolved, a new chapter in the history of humanity will be opened, filled with all sorts of unusual narratives and perhaps even some positive outcomes. To summarize what has been communicated: the interests of the protective Government and those of religion align, so that when the latter begins to decline, the foundations of the State tremble as well. The belief in divine regulation of politics and the mystique surrounding the existence of the State originates from religion: if religion ceases to exist, the State will inevitably shed its former veil of secrecy and will no longer command reverence. The sovereignty of the people, when scrutinized closely, also serves to dispel the ultimate allure and superstition surrounding these sentiments; modern democracy represents the historical manifestation of the decay of the State. The perspective that emerges from this certain decay is not entirely unfortunate; the wisdom and selfishness of individuals are among their most developed traits; when the State no longer addresses these impulses, chaos is least likely to ensue, and instead, a more suitable alternative to the State will gain control. How many organizing forces have already been seen to fail[Pg 343]! For instance, the clan or gens system which was far mightier than family power for millennia, long governing and regulating even before familial structures emerged. We ourselves observe the fading prominence of family rights and authority, which once held supremacy across the extent of the Roman system. Similarly, future generations will witness the State losing significance in certain regions—an idea that many of today’s observers can hardly consider without anxiety and dread. To work towards the promotion and realization of this vision is certainly a different matter; it takes considerable arrogance to believe one fully comprehends their reasoning and history to take on the challenge now—especially when no one can currently present the seeds that might later be sown into the disturbed soil. Therefore, let us rely on the "wisdom and selfishness of individuals" so that the State may yet endure for a while longer and that the destructive efforts of impatient, overly zealous theorists ultimately fall short!

473.

473.

Socialism, With Regard to Its Means.—Socialism is the fantastic younger brother of almost decrepit despotism, which it wants to succeed; its efforts are, therefore, in the deepest sense reactionary. For it desires such an amount of State power as only despotism has possessed,—indeed, it outdoes all the past, in that it[Pg 344] aims at the complete annihilation of the individual, whom it deems an unauthorised luxury of nature, which is to be improved by it into an appropriate organ of the general community. Owing to its relationship, it always appears in proximity to excessive developments of power, like the old typical socialist, Plato, at the court of the Sicilian tyrant; it desires (and under certain circumstances furthers) the Cæsarian despotism of this century, because, as has been said, it would like to become its heir. But even this inheritance would not suffice for its objects, it requires the most submissive prostration of all citizens before the absolute State, such as has never yet been realised; and as it can no longer even count upon the old religious piety towards the State, but must rather strive involuntarily and continuously for the abolition thereof,—because it strives for the abolition of all existing States,—it can only hope for existence occasionally, here and there for short periods, by means of the extremest terrorism. It is therefore silently preparing itself for reigns of terror, and drives the word "justice" like a nail into the heads of the half-cultured masses in order to deprive them completely of their understanding (after they had already suffered seriously from the half-culture), and to provide them with a good conscience for the bad game they are to play. Socialism may serve to teach, very brutally and impressively, the danger of all accumulations of State power, and may serve so far to inspire distrust of the State itself. When its rough voice strikes up the way-cry "as much State as possible,"[Pg 345] the shout at first becomes louder than ever,—but soon the opposition cry also breaks forth, with so much greater force: "as little State as possible."

Socialism, Considering Its Methods.—Socialism is the bizarre younger sibling of almost worn-out despotism, which it seeks to replace; its efforts are, in the truest sense, a reaction. It wants a level of State power that only despotism has ever had—actually, it goes further than anything in the past, as it[Pg 344] aims to completely eliminate the individual, whom it considers an unwarranted luxury of nature, which it intends to transform into a fitting organ of the general community. Because of its ties, it often appears close to extreme displays of power, just like the classical socialist, Plato, at the court of the Sicilian tyrant; it desires (and sometimes promotes) the Cæsarian despotism of this century, as it would like to inherit that legacy. But even this inheritance wouldn’t be enough for its goals; it needs the most obedient submission from all citizens to the absolute State, something that has never been achieved; and since it can no longer rely on the old religious reverence for the State, but must instead work involuntarily and continuously to eliminate it—because it seeks to abolish all existing States,—it can only hope to exist sporadically, here and there for brief moments, through extreme terrorism. It is therefore quietly preparing for periods of terror, and drives the word "justice" like a nail into the minds of the semi-cultured masses to completely blind them to their reason (after they have already suffered greatly from half-culture), and to give them a clear conscience for the bad actions they are expected to take. Socialism can serve as a brutal and striking lesson about the dangers of concentrated State power, and can inspire skepticism about the State itself. When its harsh voice calls out the rallying cry "as much State as possible,”[Pg 345] the shout first grows louder than ever—but soon the opposing cry also emerges, with even greater force: "as little State as possible."

474.

474.

The Development of the Mind Feared by the State.—The Greek polis was, like every organising political power, exclusive and distrustful of the growth of culture; its powerful fundamental impulse seemed almost solely to have a paralysing and obstructive effect thereon. It did not want to let any history or any becoming have a place in culture; the education laid down in the State laws was meant to be obligatory on all generations to keep them at one stage of development. Plato also, later on, did not desire it to be otherwise in his ideal State. In spite of the polis culture developed itself in this manner; indirectly to be sure, and against its will, the polis furnished assistance because the ambition of individuals therein was stimulated to the utmost, so that, having once found the path of intellectual development, they followed it to its farthest extremity. On the other hand, appeal should not be made to the panegyric of Pericles, for it is only a great optimistic dream about the alleged necessary connection between the Polis and Athenian culture; immediately before the night fell over Athens the plague and the breakdown of tradition, Thucydides makes this culture flash up once more like of the evil day that had preceded.

The State's Fear of Mental Development.—The Greek polis was, like any organized political power, exclusive and suspicious of cultural growth; its strong fundamental drive seemed almost entirely to have a paralyzing and obstructive effect on it. It wanted to prevent any history or change from having a place in culture; the education mandated by State laws was intended to be compulsory for all generations to keep them at one stage of development. Plato, later on, also did not wish for it to be any different in his ideal State. Despite the polis, culture developed in this way; indirectly, to be sure, and against its own desires, the polis provided some support because the ambition of individuals within it was pushed to the limit, so that, having discovered the path of intellectual development, they pursued it to its furthest extent. On the other hand, one should not refer to the praise of Pericles, as it is merely an overly optimistic vision of the supposed necessary link between the Polis and Athenian culture; just before darkness fell over Athens, with the plague and the collapse of tradition, Thucydides shows this culture briefly shining again like the ominous day that had come before.

475.

475.

European Man and the Destruction of Nationalities.—Commerce and industry, interchange of books and letters, the universality of all higher culture, the rapid changing of locality and landscape, and the present nomadic life of all who are not landowners,—these circumstances necessarily bring with them a weakening, and finally a destruction of nationalities, at least of European nationalities; so that, in consequence of perpetual crossings, there must arise out of them all a mixed race, that of the European man. At present the isolation of nations, through the rise of national enmities, consciously or unconsciously counteracts this tendency; but nevertheless the process of fusing advances slowly, in spite of those occasional counter-currents. This artificial nationalism is, however, as dangerous as was artificial Catholicism, for it is essentially an un natural condition of extremity and martial la which has been proclaimed by the few over the many, and requires artifice, lying, and force maintain its reputation. It is not the interests the many (of the peoples), as they probably say, but it is first of all the interests of certain princely dynasties, and then of certain commercial and social classes, which impel to this nationalism; once we have recognised this fact, we should just fearlessly style ourselves good Europeans and labour actively for the amalgamation of nations; in which efforts Germans may assist by virtue of their hereditary position as interpreters and intermediaries[Pg 347] between nations. By the way, the great problem of the Jews only exists within the national States, inasmuch as their energy and higher intelligence, their intellectual and volitional capital, accumulated from generation to generation in tedious schools of suffering, must necessarily attain to universal supremacy here to an extent provocative of envy and hatred; so that the literary misconduct is becoming prevalent in almost all modern nations —and all the more so as they again set up to be national—of sacrificing the Jews as the scape-goats of all possible public and private abuses. So soon as it is no longer a question of the preservation or establishment of nations, but of the production and training of a European mixed-race of the greatest possible strength, the Jew is just as useful and desirable an ingredient as any other national remnant. Every nation, every individual, has unpleasant and even dangerous qualities,—it is cruel to require that the Jew should be an exception. Those qualities may even be dangerous and frightful in a special degree in his case; and perhaps the young Stock-Exchange Jew is in general the most repulsive invention of the human species. Nevertheless, in a general summing up, I should like to know how much must be excused in a nation which, not without blame on the part of all of us, has had the most mournful history of all nations, and to which we owe the most loving of men (Christ), the most upright of sages (Spinoza), the mightiest book, and the most effective moral law in the world? Moreover, in the darkest times of the Middle[Pg 348] Ages, when Asiatic clouds had gathered darkly over Europe, it was Jewish free-thinkers, scholars, and physicians who upheld the banner of enlightenment and of intellectual independence under the severest personal sufferings, and defended Europe against Asia; we owe it not least to their efforts that a more natural, more reasonable, at all events un-mythical, explanation of the world was finally able to get the upper hand once more, and that the link of culture which now unites us with the enlightenment of Greco-Roman antiquity has remained unbroken. If Christianity has done everything to orientalise the Occident, Judaism has assisted essentially in occidentalising it anew; which, in a certain sense, is equivalent to making Europe's mission and history a continuation of that of Greece.

European Man and the Destruction of National Identities.—Trade and industry, the exchange of books and letters, the universal nature of higher culture, the rapid changes in environment and scenery, and the current nomadic lifestyle of those who are not landowners—all of these factors inevitably lead to a weakening and eventually a destruction of national identities, particularly in Europe. As a result of constant interactions, a mixed race, that of the European man, will emerge. Right now, the isolation of nations, fueled by the rise of national conflicts, consciously or subconsciously resists this trend; however, the blending of peoples is progressing slowly, despite these occasional pushbacks. This artificial nationalism is as dangerous as artificial Catholicism, as it creates an unnatural state of extremity and martial law imposed by the few over the many, relying on deception, manipulation, and force to maintain its status. It’s not truly about the interests of the many (the people), as they likely claim, but primarily about the interests of certain royal families and some commercial and social classes that drive this nationalism. Once we recognize this, we can confidently call ourselves good Europeans and work actively toward the unification of nations; in these efforts, Germans may contribute due to their traditional role as interpreters and intermediaries[Pg 347] between nations. Additionally, the significant issue regarding the Jews only arises within national states, as their energy and intelligence—intellectual and volitional capital built up through generations of suffering—must inevitably achieve a level of universal prominence that stirs envy and resentment. Consequently, the tendency to scapegoat Jews for all public and private issues has become widespread in nearly all modern nations, especially as these nations reassert their national identities. When the focus shifts from preserving or establishing nations to creating and cultivating a strong European mixed-race, Jews are just as valuable and necessary as any other national group. Every nation and individual has unpleasant or even risky traits—it’s unjust to expect Jews to be the exception. Those traits may indeed be particularly dangerous in some cases, and perhaps the stereotype of the young Stock-Exchange Jew is among the most off-putting creations of humankind. However, in an overall assessment, I would like to know how much should be forgiven in a nation that, with some blame shared among all of us, has the most tragic history of any nation and to which we owe some of the most compassionate individuals (Christ), the wisest of philosophers (Spinoza), the most impactful book, and the most effective moral code in the world. Moreover, during the darkest periods of the Middle[Pg 348] Ages, when eastern threats loomed over Europe, it was Jewish free-thinkers, scholars, and doctors who championed enlightenment and intellectual freedom despite extreme personal suffering, defending Europe against Asia. We owe them considerable credit for enabling a more natural, reasonable, and certainly non-mythical understanding of the world to prevail again, and for ensuring the cultural connection that still links us to the enlightenment of Greco-Roman antiquity remains intact. If Christianity has done much to orient the West, Judaism has fundamentally helped to re-orient it; which, in a way, redefines Europe's mission and history as a continuation of that of Greece.

476.

476.

Apparent Superiority of the Middle Ages.—The Middle Ages present in the Church an institution with an absolutely universal aim, involving the whole of humanity,—an aim, moreover, which—presumedly—concerned man's highest interests; in comparison therewith the aims of the States and nations which modern history exhibits make a painful impression; they seem petty, base, material, and restricted in extent. But this different impression on our imagination should certainly not determine our judgment; for that universal institution corresponded to feigned and fictitiously fostered needs, such as the need of salvation, which, wherever they did not already[Pg 349] exist, it had first of all to create: the, new institutions, however, relieve actual distresses; and the time is coming when institutions will arise to minister to the common, genuine needs of all men, and to cast that fantastic prototype, the Catholic Church, into shade and oblivion.

Evident Superiority of the Middle Ages.—The Middle Ages featured the Church as an institution with an entirely universal goal, encompassing all of humanity—one that supposedly addressed mankind's highest interests. In comparison, the goals of modern states and nations leave a disappointing impression; they appear small, selfish, materialistic, and limited in scope. However, this differing impression shouldn’t dictate our judgment; that universal institution catered to fabricated and artificially nurtured needs, like the need for salvation, which it had to create wherever it didn't already exist. The new institutions, on the other hand, address real problems, and a time will come when institutions will emerge to serve the common, genuine needs of all people, overshadowing and rendering obsolete that fantastical model, the Catholic Church.

477.

477.

War Indispensable.—It is nothing but fanaticism and beautiful soulism to expect very much (or even, much only) from humanity when it has forgotten how to wage war. For the present we know of no other means whereby the rough energy of the camp, the deep impersonal hatred, the cold-bloodedness of murder with a good conscience, the general ardour of the system in the destruction of the enemy, the proud indifference to great losses, to one's own existence and that of one's friends, the hollow, earthquake-like convulsion of the soul, can be as forcibly and certainly communicated to enervated nations as is done by every great war: owing to the brooks and streams that here break forth, which, certainly, sweep stones and rubbish of all sorts along with them and destroy the meadows of delicate cultures, the mechanism in the workshops of the mind is afterwards, in favourable circumstances, rotated by new power. Culture can by no means dispense with passions, vices, and malignities. When the Romans, after having become Imperial, had grown rather tired of war, they attempted to gain new strength by beast-baitings, gladiatoral combats,[Pg 350] and Christian persecutions. The English of to-day, who appear on the whole to have also renounced war, adopt other means in order to generate anew those vanishing forces; namely, the dangerous exploring expeditions, sea voyages and mountaineerings, nominally undertaken for scientific purposes, but in reality to bring home surplus strength from adventures and dangers of all kinds. Many other such substitutes for war will be discovered, but perhaps precisely thereby it will become more and more obvious that such a highly cultivated and therefore necessarily enfeebled humanity as that of modern Europe not only needs wars, but the greatest and most terrible wars,—consequently occasional relapses into barbarism,—lest, by the means of culture, it should lose its culture and its very existence.

War is essential.—It's nothing but fanaticism and idealism to expect too much (or even just a bit) from humanity when it has forgotten how to engage in war. Right now, we know of no other way for the raw energy of battle, the deep impersonal hatred, the cold-bloodedness of killing while feeling justified, the general enthusiasm for defeating the enemy, the proud indifference to major losses, both in our own lives and those of our friends, and the hollow, earthquake-like shaking of the soul, to be communicated to weakened nations as effectively as through every major war: because in these moments, streams and rivers break forth, sweeping away stones and debris of all kinds and destroying the delicate cultural fields, yet this upheaval later turns the workings of the mind in new ways, under favorable conditions. Culture cannot afford to skip out on passions, vices, and maliciousness. When the Romans grew tired of war after becoming an empire, they tried to regain their strength through beast-baiting, gladiatorial games,[Pg 350] and persecutions of Christians. Today's English people, who overall seem to have also given up war, resort to other methods to rekindle those fading energies; indeed, they engage in dangerous exploratory expeditions, sea voyages, and mountaineering, officially for scientific purposes, but really to bring back surplus energy from all sorts of adventures and dangers. Many more substitutes for war will be found, but perhaps it will become increasingly clear that such a highly developed and therefore inevitably weakened humanity, like that of modern Europe, not only needs wars but the biggest and most dreadful wars—thus necessitating occasional returns to barbarism—so that, through culture, it doesn't lose its culture and its very existence.

478.

478.

Industry in the South and the North.—Industry arises in two entirely different ways. The artisans of the South are not industrious because of acquisitiveness but because of the constant needs of others. The smith is industrious because some one is always coming who wants a horse shod or a carriage mended. If nobody came he would loiter about in the market-place. In a fruitful land he has little trouble in supporting himself, for that purpose he requires only a very small amount of work, certainly no industry; eventually he would beg and be contented. The industry of English[Pg 351] workmen, on the contrary, has acquisitiveness behind it; it is conscious of itself and its aims; with property it wants power, and with power the greatest possible liberty and individual distinction.

Industry in the South and the North.—Industry develops in two completely different ways. The artisans in the South are not driven by greed but by the ongoing needs of others. The blacksmith is busy because there’s always someone who needs a horse shod or a carriage repaired. If no one came by, he would just hang out in the market. In a productive area, he doesn’t have much trouble supporting himself, requiring only a small amount of work; he wouldn’t need to be industrious at all; eventually, he might resort to begging and be okay with it. In contrast, the work ethic of English[Pg 351] laborers is fueled by a desire for wealth; it is self-aware and driven by specific goals; with wealth comes the desire for power, and with power, the greatest possible freedom and individuality.

479.

479.

Wealth As the Origin of a Nobility of Race.—Wealth necessarily creates an aristocracy of race, for it permits the choice of the most beautiful women and the engagement of the best teachers; it allows a man cleanliness, time for physical exercises, and, above all, immunity from dulling physical labour. So far it provides all the conditions for making man, after a few generations, move and even act nobly and handsomely: greater freedom of character and absence of niggardliness, of wretchedly petty matters, and of abasement before bread-givers. It is precisely these negative qualities which are the most profitable birthday gift, that of happiness, for the young man; a person who is quite poor usually comes to grief through nobility of disposition, he does not get on, and acquires nothing, his race is not capable of living. In this connection, however, it must be remembered that wealth produces almost the same effects whether one have three hundred or thirty thousand thalers a year; there is no further essential progression of the favourable conditions afterwards. But to have less, to beg in boyhood and to abase one's self is terrible, although it may be the proper starting-point for such as seek their happiness[Pg 352] in the splendour of courts, in subordination to the mighty, and influential, or for such as wish to be heads of the Church. (It teaches how to slink crouching into the underground passages to favour.)

Wealth as the Source of Racial Nobility.—Wealth inevitably creates a noble class, as it allows the selection of the most attractive partners and the hiring of top educators; it enables a person to maintain cleanliness, have time for physical fitness, and, most importantly, avoid exhausting manual labor. This abundance sets the stage for individuals, over a few generations, to move and even behave in a noble and dignified manner: it fosters greater personal freedom and eliminates stinginess, trivial concerns, and subservience to those who provide sustenance. These negative traits are precisely the most valuable gift for a young man—happiness; someone who is very poor often struggles because of their noble nature, unable to succeed or accumulate wealth, and their lineage cannot thrive. However, it should be noted that wealth has nearly the same effects whether one earns three hundred or thirty thousand thalers a year; beyond a certain point, there are no significant advancements in favorable conditions. But having less, being forced to beg in childhood, and lowering oneself is dreadful, even if it might serve as a starting point for those seeking happiness in the grandeur of royal courts, through submission to powerful and influential people, or for those who aspire to lead the Church. (It teaches how to sneak into backdoor dealings in a crouching manner to gain favor.)

480.

480.

Envy and Inertia in Different Courses.—The two opposing parties, the socialist and the national,—or whatever they may be called in the different countries of Europe,—are worthy of each other; envy and laziness are the motive powers in each of them. In the one camp they desire to work as little as possible with their hands, in the other as little as possible with their heads; in the latter they hate and envy prominent, self-evolving individuals, who do not willingly allow themselves to be drawn up in rank and file for the purpose of a collective effect; in the former they hate and envy the better social caste, which is more favourably circumstanced outwardly, whose peculiar mission, the production of the highest blessings of culture, makes life inwardly all the harder and more painful. Certainly, if it be possible to make the spirit of the collective effect the spirit of the higher classes of society, the socialist crowds are quite right, when they also seek outward equalisation between themselves and these classes, since they are certainly internally equalised with one another already in head and heart. Live as higher men, and always do the deeds of higher culture,—thus everything that lives will acknowledge your right, and the[Pg 353] order of society, whose summit ye are, will be safe from every evil glance and attack!

Jealousy and Stagnation in Various Paths.—The two opposing groups, the socialists and the nationalists—or whatever they may be called in different European countries—are well-matched. Envy and laziness motivate both sides. On one side, they want to do as little manual work as possible, while on the other side, they aim to think as little as possible. The latter group resents and envies the standout individuals who refuse to conform to a collective identity for the sake of a group impact. The former group resents and envies the upper social class, which enjoys better circumstances outwardly, and whose specific role—creating the highest cultural achievements—makes life more difficult and painful internally. Certainly, if it’s possible to align the spirit of group effort with the spirit of the upper classes, the socialist crowds are justified in wanting to achieve external equality with these classes, as they are already equal among themselves in mind and heart. Live as higher individuals, and always engage in actions that reflect higher culture—this way, everything that exists will acknowledge your right, and the [Pg 353] order of society, which you represent at the top, will be protected from any malicious glance or attack!

481.

481.

High Politics and Their Detriments.—Just as a nation does not suffer the greatest losses that war and readiness for war involve through the expenses of the war, or the stoppage of trade and traffic, or through the maintenance of a standing army,—however great these losses may now be, when eight European States expend yearly the sum of five milliards of marks thereon,—but owing to the fact that year after year its ablest, strongest, and most industrious men are withdrawn in extraordinary numbers from their proper occupations and callings to be turned into soldiers: in the same way, a nation that sets about practising high politics and securing a decisive voice among the great Powers does not suffer its greatest losses where they are usually supposed to be. In fact, from this time onward it constantly sacrifices a number of its most conspicuous talents upon the "Altar of the Fatherland" or of national ambition, whilst formerly other spheres of activity were open to those talents which are now swallowed up by politics. But apart from these public hecatombs, and in reality much more horrible, there is a drama which is constantly being performed simultaneously in a hundred thousand acts; every able, industrious, intellectually striving man of a nation that thus covets political laurels, is[Pg 354] swayed by this covetousness, and no longer belongs entirely to himself alone as he did formerly; the new daily questions and cares of the public welfare devour a daily tribute of the intellectual and emotional capital of every citizen; the sum of all these sacrifices and losses of, individual energy and labour is so enormous, that the political growth of a nation almost necessarily entails an intellectual impoverishment and lassitude, a diminished capacity for the performance of works that require great concentration and specialisation. The question may finally be asked: "Does it then pay, all this bloom and magnificence of the total (which indeed only manifests itself as the fear of the new Colossus in other nations, and as the compulsory favouring by them of national trade and commerce) when all the nobler, finer, and more intellectual plants and products, in which its soil was hitherto so rich, must be sacrificed to this coarse and opalescent flower of the nation?"[2]

High Politics and Its Downsides.—Just as a country doesn't suffer the greatest losses from war and military readiness solely through the war expenses, or the interruptions in trade and travel, or the upkeep of a standing army—no matter how significant these losses are, given that eight European nations spend a total of five billion marks each year on this—it's because year after year, its most talented, strongest, and most dedicated people are taken in large numbers from their rightful jobs and turned into soldiers. Similarly, a nation that engages in high-stakes politics and seeks to have a powerful voice among the major nations doesn't experience its most significant losses where they're usually thought to be. In fact, from this point forward, it continually sacrifices many of its most prominent talents on the "Altar of the Fatherland" or of national ambition, while in the past, there were other opportunities open to those talents that are now consumed by politics. But beyond these public sacrifices, and in reality even more horrifying, there's a constant drama taking place in a hundred thousand acts; every capable, hard-working, and intellectually ambitious individual in a nation that covets political glory is swayed by this desire, and no longer belongs entirely to themselves as they once did; the new daily concerns and responsibilities of public welfare consume a daily toll of the intellectual and emotional resources of each citizen. The total of these sacrifices and losses of individual energy and labor is so massive that the political growth of a nation almost inevitably leads to intellectual impoverishment and weariness, reducing its ability to accomplish tasks that require a high level of focus and specialization. Ultimately, one might ask: "Is it really worth it, all this vibrancy and grandeur of the whole (which merely presents itself as the fear of the new Colossus in other countries, and as their enforced support of national trade and commerce) when all the nobler, finer, and more intellectual elements, for which its soil was previously so rich, must be sacrificed for this coarse and showy flower of the nation?"[2]

482.

482.

Repeated Once More.—Public opinion—private laziness.

Done Again.—Public opinion—personal apathy.


[1] This aphorism may have been suggested by Nietzsche's observing the behaviour of his great contemporary, Bismarck, towards the dynasty.—J.M.K.

[1] This saying may have been inspired by Nietzsche's observation of how his notable contemporary, Bismarck, interacted with the royal family.—J.M.K.

[2] This is once more an allusion to modern Germany.—J.M.K.

[2] This refers again to present-day Germany.—J.M.K.


NINTH DIVISION.

MAN ALONE BY HIMSELF.

483.

483.

The Enemies of Truth.—Convictions are more dangerous enemies of truth than lies.

The Opponents of Truth.—Strong beliefs are more dangerous enemies of truth than falsehoods.

484.

484.

A Topsy-turvy World.—We criticise a thinker more severely when he puts an unpleasant statement before us; and yet it would be more reasonable to do so when we find his statement pleasant.

A Chaotic World.—We judge a thinker more harshly when they present an uncomfortable idea; however, it would make more sense to do so when we encounter their idea as enjoyable.

485.

485.

Decided Character.—A man far oftener appears to have a decided character from persistently following his temperament than from persistently following his principles.

Decided character.—A man often seems to have a strong character by consistently following his temperament rather than by consistently following his principles.

486.

486.

The One Thing Needful.—One thing a man must have: either a naturally light disposition or a disposition lightened by art and knowledge.

The only essential thing.—A man must have one essential thing: either a naturally cheerful personality or a personality enhanced by skills and knowledge.

487.

487.

The Passion For Things.—Whoever sets his passion on things (sciences, arts, the common weal, the interests of culture) withdraws much fervour from his passion for persons (even when they are the representatives of those things; as statesmen, philosophers, and artists are the representatives of their creations).

The Love for Stuff.—Anyone who focuses their passion on things (like sciences, arts, the common good, and cultural interests) takes away a lot of enthusiasm from their passion for people (even if those people represent those things; like statesmen, philosophers, and artists represent their creations).

488.

488.

Calmness in Action.—As a cascade in its descent becomes more deliberate and suspended, so the great man of action usually acts with more calmness than his strong passions previous to action would lead one to expect.

Chill While You Move.—Just like a waterfall becomes more measured and still as it falls, a great person of action often operates with more calmness than you might anticipate based on their intense emotions before taking action.

489.

489.

Not Too Deep.—Persons who grasp a matter in all its depth seldom remain permanently true to it. They have just brought the depth up into the light, and there is always much evil to be seen there.

Not Too Deep.—People who understand a topic in all its complexity often don't stay loyal to it for long. They've just brought the depth into the open, and there's always a lot of negativity to be seen there.

490.

490.

The Illusion of Idealists.—All idealists imagine that the cause which they serve is essentially better than all other causes, and will not believe that if their cause is really to flourish it requires precisely the same evil-smelling manure which all other human undertakings have need of.

The Myth of Idealists.—All idealists believe that the cause they support is fundamentally better than any other cause, and they refuse to accept that for their cause to truly succeed, it requires the same unpleasant realities that all other human efforts depend on.

491.

491.

Self-observation.—Man is exceedingly well protected from himself and guarded against his self-exploring and self-besieging; as a rule he can perceive nothing of himself but his outworks. The actual fortress is inaccessible, and even invisible, to him, unless friends and enemies become traitors and lead him inside by secret paths.

Self-reflection.—People are really well shielded from themselves and kept away from exploring their own thoughts and feelings; usually, they can only see their outer defenses. The real core is unreachable and even hidden from them, unless friends and foes turn against them and guide them inside through hidden ways.

492.

492.

The Right Calling.—Men can seldom hold on to a calling unless they believe or persuade themselves that it is really more important than any other. Women are the same with their lovers.

The Right Job.—Men can hardly stick to a calling unless they believe or convince themselves that it’s truly more significant than anything else. Women are the same with their partners.

493.

493.

Nobility of Disposition.—Nobility of disposition consists largely in good-nature and absence of distrust, and therefore contains precisely that upon which money-grabbing and successful men take a pleasure in walking with superiority and scorn.

Noble Character.—Nobility of disposition is mainly about having a good nature and not being distrustful, which is exactly what money-focused and successful people often take pride in looking down upon with superiority and disdain.

494.

494.

Goal and Path.—Many are obstinate with regard to the once-chosen path, few with regard to the goal.

Goal and Plan.—Many are stubborn about the path they’ve chosen, but few are stubborn about the goal.

495.

495.

The Offensiveness in an Individual Way of Life.—All specially individual lines of conduct excite irritation against him who adopts them; people feel themselves reduced to the[Pg 358] level of commonplace creatures by the extraordinary treatment he bestows on himself.

The Offensiveness in a Personal Lifestyle.—Every unique way of living tends to irritate those who choose it; people feel like they are brought down to the[Pg 358] level of ordinary beings by the exceptional way he treats himself.

496.

496.

The Privilege of Greatness.—It is the privilege of greatness to confer intense happiness with insignificant gifts.

The Perk of Greatness.—Greatness has the unique ability to bring immense joy with small gestures.

497.

497.

Unintentionally Noble.—A person behaves with unintentional nobleness when he has accustomed himself to seek naught from others and always to give to them.

Accidentally Heroic.—A person acts with unintentional nobleness when they have trained themselves to expect nothing from others and to always give to them.

498.

498.

A Condition of Heroism.—When a person wishes to become a hero, the serpent must previously have become a dragon, otherwise he lacks his proper enemy.

A Criterion of Heroism.—When someone wants to be a hero, the serpent must first have turned into a dragon; otherwise, they don’t have the right enemy.

499.

499.

Friends.—Fellowship in joy, and, not sympathy in sorrow, makes people friends.

BFFs.—Sharing joy together, rather than just feeling sorry for each other in tough times, is what truly makes people friends.

500.

500.

Making Use of Ebb and Flow.—For the purpose of knowledge we must know how to make use of the inward current which draws us towards a thing, and also of the current which after a time draws us away from it.

Utilizing Ebb and Flow.—To gain knowledge, we need to understand how to utilize the inner pull that draws us toward something, as well as the pull that eventually leads us away from it.

501.

501.

Joy in Itself.—"Joy in the Thing" people say; but in reality it is joy in itself by means of the thing.

Joy for its own sake.—"Joy in the Thing," people say; but in reality, it's joy in itself through the thing.

502.

502.

The Unassuming Man.—He who is unassuming towards persons manifests his presumption all the more with regard to things (town, State, society, time, humanity). That is his revenge.

The Humble Guy.—A person who is modest with others often shows more arrogance when it comes to things (like the town, State, society, time, and humanity). That’s his way of getting back at others.

503.

503.

Envy and Jealousy.—Envy and jealousy are the pudenda of the human soul. The comparison may perhaps be carried further.

Envy and jealousy.—Envy and jealousy are the shameful parts of the human soul. The comparison might even go deeper.

504.

504.

The Noblest Hypocrite.—It is a very noble hypocrisy not to talk of one's self at all.

The Greatest Hypocrite.—It's quite a noble form of hypocrisy to never speak about oneself at all.

505.

505.

Vexation.—Vexation is a physical disease, which is not by any means cured when its cause is subsequently removed.

Frustration.—Vexation is a physical condition, and it doesn't get better just because the cause is taken away.

506.

506.

The Champions of Truth.—Truth does not find fewest champions when it is dangerous to speak it, but when it is dull.

Champions of Truth.—Truth has fewer supporters not when it's risky to say it, but when it’s boring.

507.

507.

More Troublesome Even Than Enemies.—Persons of whose sympathetic attitude we are not, in all circumstances, convinced, while for some reason or other (gratitude, for instance) we are obliged to maintain the appearance of unqualified sympathy with them, trouble our imagination far more than our enemies do.

More Troublesome Than Enemies.—People whose supportive attitude we don't fully trust, yet for some reason (like gratitude, for example) we feel compelled to act like we completely sympathize with them, bother our minds way more than our enemies do.

508.

508.

Free Nature.—We are so fond of being out among Nature, because it has no opinions about us.

Nature Unleashed.—We love being in Nature because it doesn’t have any judgments about us.

509.

509.

Each Superior in One Thing.—In civilised intercourse every one feels himself superior to all others in at least one thing; kindly feelings generally are based thereon, inasmuch as every one can, in certain circumstances, render help, and is therefore entitled to accept help without shame.

Each Leader in One Area.—In civilized interactions, everyone believes they are better than others in at least one area; this often leads to kindness, as each person can, in certain situations, offer assistance and is therefore justified in accepting help without feeling ashamed.

510.

510.

Consolatory Arguments.—In the case of a death we mostly use consolatory arguments not so much to alleviate the grief as to make excuses for feeling so easily consoled.

Comforting Arguments.—When someone dies, we often use comforting arguments not just to ease the pain but also to justify feeling so quickly comforted.

511.

511.

Persons Loyal to Their Convictions.—Whoever is very busy retains his general views and opinions almost unchanged. So also does[Pg 361] every one who labours in the service of an idea; he will nevermore examine the idea itself, he no longer has any time to do so; indeed, it is against his interests to consider it as still admitting of discussion.

Believers in Their Principles.—Anyone who is very busy tends to keep their overall views and opinions largely the same. The same goes for[Pg 361] anyone who works hard for a certain idea; they will no longer critically evaluate the idea itself, as they simply don't have the time for that; in fact, it's against their interests to think of it as something that can still be discussed.

512.

512.

Morality and Quantity.—The higher morality of one man as compared with that of another, often lies merely in the fact that his aims are quantitively greater. The other, living in a circumscribed sphere, is dragged down by petty occupations.

Ethics and Quantity.—The higher morality of one person compared to another often comes down to the fact that their goals are significantly larger. The other person, living in a limited space, is held back by trivial tasks.

513.

513.

"The Life" As the Proceeds of Life.—A man may stretch himself out ever so far with his knowledge; he may seem to himself ever so objective, but eventually he realises nothing therefrom but his own biography.

"The Life" As the Outcomes of Life.—A person can expand their knowledge as much as they want; they may feel completely objective, but in the end, all they truly understand is their own life story.

514.

514.

Iron Necessity.—Iron necessity is a thing which has been found, in the course of history, to be neither iron nor necessary.

Iron Necessity.—Iron necessity is something that history has shown to be neither rigid nor essential.

515.

515.

From Experience.—The unreasonableness of a thing is no argument against its existence, but rather a condition thereof.

From Experience.—Just because something doesn't make sense doesn't mean it doesn't exist; in fact, it's often a sign that it does.

516.

516.

Truth.—Nobody dies nowadays of fatal truths, there are too many antidotes to them.

Truth.—Nobody dies from harsh truths these days; there are too many remedies for them.

517.

517.

A Fundamental Insight.—There is no pre-established harmony between the promotion of truth and the welfare of mankind.

A Key Insight.—There's no inherent connection between the advancement of truth and the well-being of humanity.

518.

518.

Man's Lot.—He who thinks most deeply knows that he is always in the wrong, however he may act and decide.

Man's Situation.—Those who reflect deeply understand that they are often mistaken, no matter how they choose to act or decide.

519.

519.

Truth As Circe.—Error has made animals into men; is truth perhaps capable of making man into an animal again?

Truth Like Circe.—Mistakes have turned animals into humans; could the truth possibly turn a human back into an animal again?

520.

520.

The Danger of Our Culture.—We belong to a period of which the culture is in danger of being destroyed by the appliances of culture.

The Risks of Our Culture.—We are in a time where our culture is at risk of being ruined by the very tools meant to enhance it.

521.

521.

Greatness Means Leading the Way.—No stream is large and copious of itself, but becomes great by receiving and leading on so many tributary streams. It is so, also, with all intellectual greatnesses. It is only a question of some one indicating the direction to be followed by so many affluents; not whether he was richly or poorly gifted originally.

Greatness Means Setting the Standard.—No river is wide and abundant on its own; it grows large by taking in and guiding many smaller streams. It's the same with all areas of intellectual greatness. The real question is whether someone shows the path that can be followed by all those influences, not whether they started out with a lot of talent or just a little.

522.

522.

A Feeble Conscience.—People who talk about their importance to mankind have a feeble conscience for common bourgeois rectitude, keeping of contracts, promises, etc.

A Weak Conscience.—People who brag about their significance to humanity have a weak sense of basic moral integrity, like honoring contracts, promises, and other responsibilities.

523.

523.

Desiring to Be Loved.—The demand to be loved is the greatest of presumptions.

Wanting to Be Loved.—The desire to be loved is the biggest assumption.

524.

524.

Contempt For Men.—The most unequivocal sign of contempt for man is to regard everybody merely as a means to one's own ends, or of no account whatever.

Disdain for Men.—The clearest sign of contempt for humanity is to see everyone solely as a way to achieve one's own goals or as completely unimportant.

525.

525.

Partisans Through Contradiction.—Whoever has driven men to fury against himself has also gained a party in his favour.

Partisans in Conflict.—Whoever has made people angry at him has also earned a group of supporters.

526.

526.

Forgetting Experiences.—Whoever thinks much and to good purpose easily forgets his own experiences, but not the thoughts which these experiences have called forth.

Forgetting Memories.—Anyone who reflects deeply and meaningfully tends to forget their own experiences, but not the thoughts that those experiences have inspired.

527.

527.

Sticking to an Opinion.—One person sticks to an opinion because he takes pride in having acquired it himself,—another sticks to it because he has learnt it with difficulty and is[Pg 364] proud of having understood it; both of them, therefore, out of vanity.

Holding onto an Opinion.—One person holds on to an opinion because they take pride in having formed it themselves,—another clings to it because they learned it with great effort and are[Pg 364] proud of understanding it; both of them, therefore, out of vanity.

528.

528.

Avoiding the Light.—Good deeds avoid the light just as anxiously as evil deeds; the latter fear that pain will result from publicity (as punishment), the former fear that pleasure will vanish with publicity (the pure pleasure per se, which ceases as soon as satisfaction of vanity is added to it).

Avoiding the Light.—Good deeds shy away from the spotlight just as much as bad deeds do; the latter worry that they’ll face consequences from being exposed (as punishment), while the former fear that the joy will fade in the open (the simple joy per se, which disappears once the need for recognition kicks in).

529.

529.

The Length of the Day.—When one has much to put into them, a day has a hundred pockets.

The Duration of the Day.—When you have a lot to do, a day has a hundred pockets.

530.

530.

The Genius of Tyranny.—When an invincible desire to obtain tyrannical power has been awakened in the soul, and constantly keeps up its fervour, even a very mediocre talent (in politicians, artists, etc.) gradually becomes an almost irresistible natural force.

The Brilliance of Oppression.—When an unstoppable desire to gain tyrannical power ignites within someone and maintains its intensity, even a fairly average skill (in politicians, artists, etc.) can slowly turn into an almost uncontrollable natural force.

531.

531.

The Enemy's Life.—He who lives by fighting with an enemy has an interest in the preservation of the enemy's life.[1]

The Enemy's Life.—Someone who survives by battling an enemy has a stake in keeping the enemy alive.[1]

532.

532.

More Important.—Unexplained, obscure matters are regarded as more important than explained, clear ones.

More Important.—Unexplained, unclear issues are seen as more significant than those that are explained and clear.

533.

533.

Valuation of Services Rendered.—We estimate services rendered to us according to the value set on them by those who render them, not according to the value they have for us.

Service Valuation.—We evaluate the services provided to us based on the worth assigned to them by the providers, rather than their value to us.

534.

534.

Unhappiness.—The distinction associated with unhappiness (as if it were a sign of stupidity, unambitiousness, or commonplaceness to feel happy) is so great that when any one says to us, "How happy you are!" we usually protest.

Sadness.—The stigma attached to unhappiness (as if feeling happy is a marker of ignorance, lack of ambition, or mediocrity) is so significant that when someone tells us, "How happy you are!" we typically push back.

535.

535.

Imagination in Anguish.—When one is afraid of anything, one's imagination plays the part of that evil spirit which springs on one's back just when one has the heaviest load to bear.

Imagination in Pain.—When you're afraid of something, your imagination acts like that dark force that weighs you down the hardest right when you're already carrying a heavy burden.

536.

536.

The Value of Insipid Opponents.—We sometimes remain faithful to a cause merely because its opponents never cease to be insipid.

The Value of Bland Opponents.—Sometimes we stick with a cause just because its opponents are so dull.

537.

537.

The Value of a Profession.—A profession makes us thoughtless; that is its greatest blessing.[Pg 366] For it is a bulwark behind which we are permitted to withdraw when commonplace doubts and cares assail us.

The Importance of a Career.—A profession allows us to be carefree; that’s its biggest advantage.[Pg 366] It serves as a shield where we can retreat when ordinary doubts and worries come at us.

538.

538.

Talent.—Many a man's talent appears less than it is, because he has always set himself too heavy tasks.

Skill.—A lot of a man's talent seems smaller than it actually is because he consistently takes on tasks that are too difficult for him.

539.

539.

Youth.—Youth is an unpleasant period; for then it is not possible or not prudent to be productive in any sense whatsoever.

Young people.—Youth is a tough time; it's a period where being productive in any way is either impossible or unwise.

540.

540.

Too Great Aims.—Whoever aims publicly at great things and at length perceives secretly that he is too weak to achieve them, has usually also insufficient strength to renounce his aims publicly, and then inevitably becomes a hypocrite.

Too Ambitious Goals.—Anyone who publicly strives for big goals but secretly realizes they're too weak to achieve them often lacks the courage to abandon those goals publicly, and as a result, becomes a hypocrite.

541.

541.

In the Current.—Mighty waters sweep many stones and shrubs away with them; mighty spirits many foolish and confused minds.

In the Now.—Strong currents carry away a lot of stones and shrubs; powerful spirits take many foolish and confused minds with them.

542.

542.

The Dangers of Intellectual Emancipation.—In a seriously intended intellectual emancipation a person's mute passions and cravings also hope to find their advantage.

The Risks of Intellectual Freedom.—In a genuinely intended intellectual liberation, a person's unspoken desires and longings also seek to gain from it.

543.

543.

The Incarnation of the Mind.—When any one thinks much and to good purpose, not only his face but also his body acquires a sage look.

The Manifestation of the Mind.—When someone thinks deeply and effectively, not only does their face but also their body takes on a wise appearance.

544.

544.

Seeing Badly and Hearing Badly.—The man who sees little always sees less than there is to see; the man who hears badly always hears something more than there is to hear.

Vision and Hearing Impairment.—The guy who doesn’t see much always sees less than what’s actually there; the guy who doesn’t hear well always hears more than what’s really being said.

545.

545.

Self-enjoyment in Vanity.—The vain man does not wish so much to be prominent as to feel himself prominent; he therefore disdains none of the expedients for self-deception and self-out-witting. It is not the opinion of others that he sets his heart on, but his opinion of their opinion

Self-love in vanity.—The vain person isn't as focused on being the center of attention as they are on feeling like they are. They dismiss any means of self-deception or outsmarting themselves. It's not what others think about him that matters to him, but rather what he thinks about their thoughts.

546.

546.

Exceptionally Vain.—He who is usually self-sufficient becomes exceptionally vain, and keenly alive to fame and praise when he is physically ill. The more he loses himself the more he has to endeavour to regain his position by means of the opinion of others.

Extremely Vain.—Someone who is usually self-reliant becomes overly vain and sensitive to fame and praise when they are physically unwell. The more they lose themselves, the more they try to restore their status through the opinions of others.

547.

547.

The "Witty."—Those who seek wit do not possess it.

The "Witty."—People who are looking for wit usually don't have it.

548.

548.

A Hint to the Heads of Parties.—When one can make people publicly support a cause they have also generally been brought to the point of inwardly declaring themselves in its favour, because they wish to be regarded as consistent.

A Tip for Party Leaders.—When someone can get people to publicly back a cause, it usually means those people have also come to the point of privately declaring their support for it, as they want to be seen as consistent.

549.

549.

Contempt.—Man is more sensitive to the contempt of others than to self-contempt.

Disdain.—People are more affected by others' disdain than by their own self-disdain.

550.

550.

The Tie of Gratitude.—There are servile souls who carry so far their sense of obligation for benefits received that they strangle themselves with the tie of gratitude.

The Bond of Gratitude.—There are submissive individuals who take their sense of obligation for help they’ve received to such an extent that they end up suffocating themselves with the burden of gratitude.

551.

551.

The Prophet's Knack.—In predicting beforehand the procedure of ordinary individuals, it must be taken for granted that they always make use of the smallest intellectual expenditure in freeing themselves from disagreeable situations.

The Prophet's Gift.—When predicting how ordinary people will act, it should be assumed that they consistently use the least amount of mental effort to get themselves out of unpleasant situations.

552.

552.

Man's Sole Right.—He who swerves from the traditional is a victim of the unusual; he who keeps to the traditional is its slave. The man is ruined in either case.

Man's Only Right.—Those who stray from tradition become victims of the unconventional; those who stick to tradition become its slaves. In either case, the person is left ruined.

553.

553.

Below the Beast.—When a man roars with laughter he surpasses all the animals by his vulgarity.

Below the Beast.—When a man laughs loudly, he outdoes all the animals with his crudeness.

554.

554.

Partial Knowledge.—He who speaks a foreign language imperfectly has more enjoyment therein than he who speaks it well. The enjoyment is with the partially initiated.

Limited Knowledge.—Someone who speaks a foreign language imperfectly enjoys it more than someone who speaks it fluently. The pleasure comes from those who are only partially familiar with it.

555.

555.

Dangerous Helpfulness.—There are people who wish to make human life harder for no other reason than to be able afterwards to offer men their life-alleviating recipes—their Christianity, for example.

Hazardous Assistance.—Some people seem to want to complicate life for others just so they can later present their solutions to make things easier—like their version of Christianity, for instance.

556.

556.

Industriousness and Conscientiousness.—Industriousness and conscientiousness are often antagonists, owing to the fact that industriousness wants to pluck the fruit sour from the tree while conscientiousness wants to let it hang too long, until it falls and is bruised.

Hard work and responsibility.—Industriousness and conscientiousness often conflict because industriousness seeks to pick the fruit before it's ripe, while conscientiousness prefers to wait until it's fully mature, even if it means the fruit might fall and become damaged.

557.

557.

Casting Suspicion.—We endeavour to cast suspicion on persons whom we cannot endure.

Casting Doubt.—We try to create doubt about people we can't stand.

558.

558.

The Conditions Are Lacking.—Many people wait all their lives for the opportunity to be good in their own way.

The Conditions Are Poor.—Many people wait their whole lives for the chance to be good in their own way.

559.

559.

Lack of Friends.—Lack of friends leads to the inference that a person is envious or presumptuous. Many a man owes his friends merely to the fortunate circumstance that he has no occasion for envy.

No Friends.—Not having friends suggests that someone might be jealous or arrogant. Often, a person has friends just because they don’t have any reason to feel envious.

560.

560.

Danger in Manifoldness.—With one talent more we often stand less firmly than with one less; just as a table stands better on three feet than on four.

Danger in Diversity.—With one more talent, we often feel less stable than with one less; just like a table stands better on three legs than on four.

561.

561.

An Exemplar For Others.—Whoever wants to set a good example must add a grain of folly to his virtue; people then imitate their exemplar and at the same time raise themselves above him, a thing they love to do.

A Role Model for Others.—Anyone who wants to be a good role model must mix a little foolishness with their virtue; this way, people will imitate their role model while also feeling like they surpass them, which they enjoy doing.

562.

562.

Being a Target.—The bad things others say about us are often not really aimed at us, but are the manifestations of spite or ill-humour occasioned by quite different causes.

Being a target.—The negative things people say about us often aren't truly directed at us, but are expressions of resentment or anger caused by entirely different issues.

563.

563.

Easily Resigned.—We suffer but little on account of ungratified wishes if we have exercised our imagination in distorting the past.

Easily gave up.—We barely suffer from unfulfilled desires if we have used our imagination to twist the past.

564.

564.

In Danger.—One is in greatest danger of being run over when one has just got out of the way of a carriage.

In Danger.—You are at the highest risk of getting run over when you have just moved out of the way of a carriage.

565.

565.

The Role According to the Voice.—Whoever is obliged to speak louder than he naturally does (say, to a partially deaf person or before a large audience), usually exaggerates what he has to communicate. Many a one becomes a conspirator, malevolent gossip, or intriguer, merely because his voice is best suited for whispering.

The Role According to the Voice.—Anyone who has to speak louder than they normally do (like to someone who's hard of hearing or in front of a big crowd) often ends up exaggerating what they're trying to say. Many people turn into conspirators, malicious gossips, or schemers simply because their voice is more suited for whispering.

566.

566.

Love and Hatred.—Love and hatred are not blind, but are dazzled by the fire which they carry about with them.

Love and Hate.—Love and hatred aren't blind; they are instead dazzled by the passion they carry with them.

567.

567.

Advantageously Persecuted.—People who cannot make their merits perfectly obvious to the world endeavour to awaken a strong hostility against themselves. They have then the consolation of thinking that this hostility stands between their merits and the acknowledgment thereof—-[Pg 372] and that many others think the same thing, which is very advantageous for their recognition.

Persecuted for a good reason.—People who struggle to make their strengths clear to the world often try to provoke strong negative reactions towards themselves. This gives them the comfort of believing that this negativity is what prevents their abilities from being recognized—[Pg 372] and that many others share this view, which is quite beneficial for their acknowledgment.

568.

568.

Confession.—We forget our fault when we have confessed it to another person, but he does not generally forget it.

Confession.—We often move on from our mistakes after sharing them with someone else, but that person usually doesn't forget.

569.

569.

Self-sufficiency.—The Golden Fleece of self-sufficiency is a protection against blows, but not against needle-pricks.

Self-reliance.—The ideal of self-sufficiency offers a shield against major setbacks, but it won’t shield you from minor annoyances.

570.

570.

Shadows in the Flame.—The flame is not so bright to itself as to those whom it illuminates,—so also the wise man.

Shadows in the Fire.—The flame isn't as bright to itself as it is to those it lights up,—and the same goes for the wise person.

571.

571.

Our Own Opinions.—The first opinion that occurs to us when we are suddenly asked about anything is not usually our own, but only the current opinion belonging to our caste, position, or family; our own opinions seldom float on the surface.

Our Personal Views.—The first opinion that comes to mind when we're suddenly asked about something isn't usually our own; it's typically the common opinion tied to our social group, status, or family. Our true opinions rarely just come to the surface.

572.

572.

The Origin of Courage.—The ordinary man is as courageous and invulnerable as a hero when he does not see the danger, when he has no eyes for it. Reversely, the hero has his one vulnerable spot upon the back, where he has no eyes.

The Source of Courage.—An ordinary person is just as brave and untouchable as a hero when they're unaware of the danger, when they can't see it at all. On the flip side, the hero has one weak spot on their back, where they can't see.

573.

573.

The Danger in the Physician.—One must be born for one's physician, otherwise one comes to grief through him.

The Risks of the Doctor.—A person has to be meant for their doctor; otherwise, they might end up suffering because of them.

574.

574.

Marvellous Vanity.—Whoever has courageously prophesied the weather three times and has been successful in his hits, acquires a certain amount of inward confidence in his prophetic gift. We give credence to the marvellous and irrational when it flatters our self-esteem.

Amazing Vanity.—Whoever has boldly predicted the weather three times and has been accurate in their forecasts gains a certain level of confidence in their ability to foresee. We tend to believe in the extraordinary and the illogical when it boosts our self-esteem.

575.

575.

A Profession.—A profession is the backbone of life.

A Career.—A profession is the foundation of life.

576.

576.

The Danger of Personal Influence.—Whoever feels that he exercises a great inward influence over another person must give him a perfectly free rein, must, in fact, welcome and even induce occasional opposition, otherwise he will inevitably make an enemy.

The Risk of Personal Influence.—Anyone who thinks they have a strong internal influence over someone else must allow that person complete freedom; they should even encourage and be open to occasional disagreements. Otherwise, they will surely create an enemy.

577.

577.

Recognition of the Heir.—Whoever has founded something great in an unselfish spirit is careful to rear heirs for his work. It is the sign of a tyrannical and ignoble nature to see opponents in all possible heirs, and to live in a state of self-defence against them.

Heir Recognition.—Anyone who has created something valuable with a selfless attitude makes sure to nurture successors for their legacy. It shows a tyrannical and dishonorable character to view every potential heir as an opponent and to constantly act defensively against them.

578.

578.

Partial Knowledge.—Partial knowledge is more triumphant than complete knowledge; it takes things to be simpler than they are, and so makes its theory more popular and convincing.

Partial knowledge.—Partial knowledge is often seen as more successful than complete knowledge; it assumes things are easier than they truly are, making its theory more relatable and persuasive.

579.

579.

Unsuitable For a Party-man.—Whoever thinks much is unsuitable for a party-man; his thinking leads him too quickly beyond the party.

Not Suitable For a Party Guy.—Anyone who thinks deeply is not fit to be a party member; their thoughts take them too swiftly beyond the party.

580.

580.

A Bad Memory.—The advantage of a bad memory is that one enjoys several times the same good things for the first time.

A Terrible Memory.—The benefit of a bad memory is that you can experience the same good things multiple times as if it’s the first time.

581.

581.

Self-affliction.—Want of consideration is often the sign of a discordant inner nature, which craves for stupefaction.

Self-harm.—A lack of thoughtfulness often indicates a conflicted inner self that longs for numbness.

582.

582.

Martyrs.—The disciples of a martyr suffer more than the martyr.

Martyrs.—The followers of a martyr often endure greater suffering than the martyr themselves.

583.

583.

Arrears of Vanity.—The vanity of many people who have no occasion to be vain is the inveterate habit, still surviving from the time when people had no right to the belief in[Pg 375] themselves and only begged it in small sums from others.

Vanity Arrears.—The vanity of many people who have no reason to be vain is a deeply rooted habit, still lingering from a time when people didn't believe in[Pg 375] themselves and only borrowed a little self-esteem from others.

584.

584.

Punctum Saliens of Passion.—A person falling into a rage or into a violent passion of love reaches a point when the soul is full like a hogshead, but nevertheless a drop of water has still to be added, the good will for the passion (which is also generally called the evil will). This item only is necessary, and then the hogshead overflows.

Punctum Saliens of Passion.—When someone is swept up in a fit of rage or intense love, they reach a point where their emotions feel as full as a large barrel; however, they still need just one more drop of water—the willingness to embrace that passion (often referred to as the contrary will). This single addition is all that's needed, and then the barrel overflows.

585.

585.

A Gloomy Thought.—It is with men as with the charcoal fires in the forest. It is only when young men have cooled down and have got charred, like these piles, that they become useful. As long as they fume and smoke they are perhaps more interesting, but they are useless and too often uncomfortable. Humanity ruthlessly uses every individual as material for the heating of its great machines; but what then is the purpose of the machines, when all individuals (that is, the human race) are useful only to maintain them? Machines that are ends in themselves: is that the umana commedia?

A Dark Thought.—It's like this with men and the charcoal fires in the forest. Young men only become useful when they've cooled off and become charred, just like those piles. While they’re still smoking and fuming, they might be more fascinating, but they’re also pretty useless and often uncomfortable. Society takes advantage of every individual to fuel its massive machines; but what’s the point of those machines if every person (that is, the entire human race) is only valuable for keeping them running? Machines that exist for their own sake: is that the human comedy?

586.

586.

The Hour-hand of Life.—Life consists of rare single moments of the greatest importance, and of countless intervals during which, at best, the phantoms of those moments hover around us. Love, the Spring, every fine melody, the mountains,[Pg 376] the moon, the sea—all speak but once fully to the heart, if, indeed, they ever do quite attain to speech. For many people have not those moments at all, and are themselves intervals and pauses in the symphony of actual life.

The Hour Hand of Life.—Life is made up of rare single moments that are incredibly meaningful, and countless stretches of time during which, at best, the echoes of those moments linger around us. Love, springtime, every beautiful melody, the mountains,[Pg 376] the moon, the sea—all truly connect with our hearts only once, if they ever really do. Many people don’t experience those moments at all and are merely the pauses and silence in the symphony of real life.

587.

587.

Attack Or Compromise.—We often make the mistake of showing violent enmity towards a tendency, party, or period, because we happen only to get a sight of its most exposed side, its stuntedness, or the inevitable "faults of its virtues,"—perhaps because we ourselves have taken a prominent part in them. We then turn our backs on them and seek a diametrically opposite course; but the better way would be to seek out their strong good sides, or to develop them in ourselves. To be sure, a keener glance and a better will are needed to improve the becoming and the imperfect than are required to see through it in its imperfection and to deny it.

Attack or compromise.—We often make the error of showing harsh hostility towards a tendency, group, or era because we only see its most exposed side, its shortcomings, or the inevitable "flaws that come with its strengths"—maybe because we’ve played a major role in them ourselves. We then turn away from them and pursue the exact opposite path; however, a better approach would be to identify their strong, positive aspects or to cultivate them within ourselves. Undoubtedly, it takes a sharper perspective and a more determined will to improve what is good yet flawed than it does to simply point out its flaws and dismiss it.

588.

588.

Modesty.—There is true modesty (that is the knowledge that we are not the works we create); and it is especially becoming in a great mind, because such a mind can well grasp the thought of absolute irresponsibility (even for the good it creates). People do not hate a great man's presumptuousness in so far as he feels his strength, but because he wishes to prove it by injuring[Pg 377] others, by dominating them, and seeing how long they will stand it. This, as a rule, is even a proof of the absence of a secure sense of power, and makes people doubt his greatness. We must therefore beware of presumption from the stand-point of wisdom.

Humility.—True modesty is recognizing that we are not just the things we create; it's particularly fitting for a great mind since such a mind can understand the idea of being completely unaccountable (even for the good it brings). People generally don't resent a great person's confidence as long as they acknowledge their strength, but they do dislike it when that person tries to assert their dominance by belittling others and testing how much they can take. Often, this behavior actually shows a lack of true power, leading people to question their greatness. Therefore, we should be cautious of arrogance when it comes to wisdom.

589.

589.

The Day's First Thought.—The best way to begin a day well is to think, on awakening, whether we cannot give pleasure during the day to at least one person. If this could become a substitute for the religious habit of prayer our fellow-men would benefit by the change.

Morning's First Thought.—The best way to start a day off right is to think, as soon as you wake up, about how you can bring joy to at least one person throughout the day. If this could replace the practice of prayer, it would definitely benefit those around us.

590.

590.

Presumption As the Last Consolation.—When we so interpret a misfortune, an intellectual defect, or a disease that we see therein our predestined fate, our trial, or the mysterious punishment of our former misdeeds, we thereby make our nature interesting and exalt ourselves in imagination above our fellows. The proud sinner is a well-known figure in all religious sects.

Presumption as the Final Comfort.—When we interpret a misfortune, an intellectual flaw, or an illness as our destined fate, our test, or the mysterious punishment for our past mistakes, we make our nature intriguing and elevate ourselves in our imagination above others. The proud sinner is a familiar character in all religious groups.

591.

591.

The Vegetation of Happiness.—Close beside the world's woe, and often upon its volcanic soil, man has laid out his little garden of happiness. Whether one regard life with the eyes of him who only seeks knowledge therefrom, or of him who submits and is resigned, or of him who[Pg 378] rejoices over surmounted difficulties—everywhere one will find some happiness springing up beside the evil—and in fact always the more happiness the more volcanic the soil has been,—only it would be absurd to say that suffering itself is justified by this happiness.

The Plants of Happiness.—Right next to the world's suffering, and often on its rugged terrain, people have created their own little gardens of happiness. Whether you look at life through the lens of someone who only seeks knowledge from it, or through someone who accepts and endures, or through someone who[Pg 378] celebrates overcoming challenges—happiness can always be found alongside the suffering. In fact, the harsher the circumstances, the more happiness there seems to be—but it would be ridiculous to claim that this happiness makes suffering somehow justified.

592.

592.

The Path of Our Ancestors.—It is sensible when a person develops still further in himself the talent upon which his father or grandfather spent much trouble, and does not shift to something entirely new; otherwise he deprives himself of the possibility of attaining perfection in any one craft. That is why the proverb says, "Which road shouldst thou ride?—That of thine ancestors."

The Journey of Our Ancestors.—It makes sense for a person to further develop the talent that their father or grandfather worked hard on, rather than switching to something completely different; otherwise, they miss the chance to achieve mastery in any one skill. That’s why the saying goes, "Which road should you take?—The one your ancestors did."

593.

593.

Vanity and Ambition As Educators.—As long as a person has not become an instrument of general utility, ambition may torment him; if, however, that point has been reached, if he necessarily works like a machine for the good of all, then vanity may result; it will humanise him in small matters and make him more sociable, endurable, and considerate, when ambition has completed the coarser work of making him useful.

Vanity and Ambition in Teaching.—As long as someone hasn’t become a tool for the greater good, ambition can be a source of distress for them; however, once they reach that stage, where they automatically contribute to the welfare of others, vanity may emerge. It will make them more relatable in smaller aspects and help them be more social, tolerable, and thoughtful, after ambition has done the rougher job of making them useful.

594.

594.

Philosophical Novices.—Immediately we have comprehended the wisdom of a philosopher, we go through the streets with a feeling as if we[Pg 379] had been re-created and had become great men; for we encounter only those who are ignorant of this wisdom, and have therefore to deliver new and unknown verdicts concerning everything. Because we now recognise a law-book we think we must also comport ourselves as judges.

Philosophy Beginners.—As soon as we grasp the wisdom of a philosopher, we walk through the streets feeling like we've been reborn and have become important figures; we only come across those who are unaware of this wisdom, and so we feel the need to share our new and unfamiliar judgments about everything. Since we now recognize a legal code, we think we should also act like judges.

595.

595.

Pleasing by Displeasing.—People who prefer to attract attention, and thereby to displease, desire the same thing as those who neither wish to please nor to attract attention, only they seek it more ardently and indirectly by means of a step by which they apparently move away from their goal. They desire influence and power, and therefore show their superiority, even to such an extent that it becomes disagreeable; for they know that he who has finally attained power, pleases in almost all he says and does, and that even when he displeases he still seems to please. The free spirit also, and in like manner the believer, desire power, in order some day to please thereby; when, on account of their doctrine, evil fate, persecution, dungeon, or execution threaten them, they rejoice in the thought that their teaching will thus be engraved and branded on the heart of mankind; though its effect is remote they accept their fate as a painful but powerful means of still attaining to power.

Pleasant by Unpleasant.—People who want to grab attention, even if it annoys others, want the same thing as those who neither aim to please nor seek attention. The difference is that they pursue it more intensely and in an indirect way that seems to take them away from their goal. They want influence and power, so they showcase their superiority, sometimes to the point of being unpleasant. They know that someone who finally gains power tends to please with almost everything they say and do, and even when they aren't pleasing, they still give off that impression. Similarly, the free thinker and the believer seek power, hoping it will allow them to please at some point. When faced with hardships like persecution, imprisonment, or execution because of their beliefs, they take comfort in the idea that their teachings will leave a lasting mark on humanity. Even though the impact is distant, they view their suffering as a painful but potent way to ultimately gain power.

596.

596.

casus Belli and the Like.—The prince who, for his determination to make war against[Pg 380] his neighbour, invents a casus belli, is like a father who foists on his child a mother who is henceforth to be regarded as such. And are not almost all publicly avowed motives of action just such spurious mothers?

casus belli and Similar Concepts.—The prince who decides to go to war against[Pg 380] his neighbor and creates a casus belli is like a father who imposes a new mother on his child, expecting them to accept her as if she were genuine. Aren't most publicly stated reasons for action just like those fake mothers?

597.

597.

Passion and Right.—Nobody talks more passionately of his rights than he who, in the depths of his soul, is doubtful about them. By getting passion on his side he seeks to confound his understanding and its doubts,—he thus obtains a good conscience, and along with it success with his fellow-men.

Passion and Justice.—No one speaks more passionately about their rights than someone who secretly doubts them. By rallying passion, they try to confuse their understanding and its uncertainties—this gives them a clear conscience, and with that, success with others.

598.

598.

The Trick of the Resigning One.—He who protests against marriage, after the manner of Catholic priests, will conceive of it in its lowest and vulgarest form. In the same way he who disavows the honour of his contemporaries will have a mean opinion of it; he can thus dispense with it and struggle against it more easily. Moreover, he who denies himself much in great matters will readily indulge himself in small things. It might be possible that he who is superior to the approbation of his contemporaries would nevertheless not deny himself the gratification of small vanities.

The Trick of the Resigning One.—Someone who objects to marriage, like Catholic priests often do, will see it in its most basic and crude form. Similarly, someone who dismisses the value of their peers will have a low opinion of it; this allows them to reject it and resist it more easily. Furthermore, a person who denies themselves a lot in important matters might easily indulge in minor pleasures. It's possible that someone who rises above seeking approval from their contemporaries would still indulge in small vanity.

599.

599.

The Years of Presumption.—The proper period of presumption in gifted people is between their twenty-sixth and thirtieth years; it is the time of early ripeness, with a large residue of[Pg 381] sourness. On the ground of what we feel within ourselves we demand honour and humility from men who see little or nothing of it, and because this tribute is not immediately forthcoming we revenge ourselves by the look, the gesture of arrogance, and the tone of voice, which a keen ear and eye recognise in every product of those years, whether it be poetry, philosophy, or pictures and music. Older men of experience smile thereat, and think with emotion of those beautiful years in which one resents the fate of being so much and seeming so little. Later on one really seems more,—but one has lost the good belief in being much,—unless one remain for life an incorrigible fool of vanity.

The Era of Overconfidence.—The typical time of presumption in gifted individuals is between the ages of twenty-six and thirty; this is a period of early maturity, yet there remains a considerable amount of[Pg 381] bitterness. Based on what we feel inside, we demand respect and humility from people who perceive little or nothing of it, and when this acknowledgment isn't given right away, we retaliate with looks, gestures of arrogance, and a tone that a sharp ear and eye can detect in everything created during those years, whether it's poetry, philosophy, or art and music. Older, more experienced individuals smile at this and think wistfully of those wonderful years when one resents the reality of being so much and seeming so little. Later on, one genuinely seems like more—but one loses the strong belief in being significant—unless one chooses to remain a hopelessly vain fool for life.

600.

600.

Deceptive and Yet Defensible.—Just as in order to pass by an abyss or to cross a deep stream on a plank we require a railing, not to hold fast by,—for it would instantly break down with us,—but to give the notion of security to the eye, so in youth we require persons who unconsciously render us the service of that railing. It is true they would not help us if we really wished to lean upon them in great danger, but they afford the tranquillising sensation of protection close to one (for instance, fathers, teachers, friends, as all three usually are).

Misleading but Justifiable.—Just like when we need a railing to safely pass over an abyss or cross a deep stream on a plank—not to actually hold onto, since it would break under our weight—but to make us feel secure, in our youth, we need people who unknowingly provide that sense of security. It's true they wouldn't be much help if we really needed to lean on them in dangerous situations, but they give us a comforting feeling of protection nearby (for example, fathers, teachers, friends, as all three often are).

601.

601.

Learning to Love.—One must learn to love, one must learn to be kind, and this from[Pg 382] childhood onwards; when education and chance give us no opportunity for the exercise of these feelings our soul becomes dried up, and even incapable of understanding the fine devices of loving men. In the same way hatred must be learnt and fostered, when one wants to become a proficient hater,—otherwise the germ of it will gradually die out.

Learning to Love.—We have to learn to love and to be kind, starting from[Pg 382] childhood; if education and opportunities don’t give us a chance to practice these feelings, our souls become dry and unable to grasp the subtle ways of loving people. Similarly, hatred also needs to be learned and nurtured if someone wants to become skilled at hating—otherwise, its seed will slowly fade away.

602.

602.

Ruin As Ornament.—Persons who pass through numerous mental phases retain certain sentiments and habits of their earlier states, which then project like a piece of inexplicable antiquity and grey stonework into their new thought and action, often to the embellishment of the whole surroundings.

Ruins as Decor.—People who go through various mental stages keep some feelings and habits from their earlier experiences, which then emerge like an old, mysterious relic or worn stone into their new thoughts and actions, often enhancing their entire environment.

603.

603.

Love and Honour.—Love desires, fear avoids. That is why one cannot be both loved and honoured by the same person, at least not at the same time.[2] For he who honours recognises power,—that is to say, he fears it, he is in a state of reverential fear (Ehr-furcht) But love recognises no power, nothing that divides, detaches, superordinates, or subordinates. Because it does not honour them, ambitious people secretly or openly resent being loved.

Love and Respect.—Love wants, fear avoids. That’s why you can’t be both loved and respected by the same person, at least not at the same time.[2] The one who respects acknowledges power—that is to say, they fear it and are in a state of reverential fear (Ehr-furcht). But love doesn’t recognize power or anything that creates distance, separates, elevates, or lowers. Because it doesn’t respect them, ambitious people secretly or openly resent being loved.

604.

604.

A Prejudice in Favour of Cold Natures.—People who quickly take fire grow cold quickly, and therefore are, on the whole, unreliable. For those, therefore, who are always cold, or pretend to be so, there is the favourable prejudice that they are particularly trustworthy, reliable persons; they are confounded with those who take fire slowly and retain it long.

A Preference for Cold Personalities.—People who get angry or excited quickly cool down just as fast, making them generally unreliable. For those who are always calm, or act like they are, there is a common belief that they are especially trustworthy and dependable; they are often mistaken for those who get heated slowly and stay that way longer.

605.

605.

The Danger in Free Opinions.—Frivolous occupation with free opinions has a charm, like a kind of itching; if one yields to it further, one begins to chafe the places; until at last an open, painful wound results; that is to say, until the free opinion begins to disturb and torment us in our position in life and in our human relations.

The Risk of Free Opinions.—Being overly caught up in free opinions can feel appealing, like an itch. If you give in to it, you start to irritate the sensitive spots until eventually, it turns into a raw, painful wound. In other words, free opinions can start to upset and trouble us in our lives and our relationships with others.

606.

606.

Desire For Sore Affliction.—When passion is over it leaves behind an obscure longing for it, and even in disappearing it casts a seductive glance at us. It must have afforded a kind of pleasure to have been beaten with this scourge. Compared with it, the more moderate sensations appear insipid; we still prefer, apparently, the more violent displeasure to languid delight.

Desire for Painful Suffering.—When passion fades, it leaves an unclear yearning for it, and even as it fades away, it looks back at us enticingly. There must have been a certain pleasure in enduring this pain. In comparison, the milder feelings seem dull; we seem to prefer, it seems, the more intense discomfort over subtle joy.

607.

607.

Dissatisfaction With Others and With the World.—When, as so frequently happens, we vent our dissatisfaction on others when we are really dissatisfied with ourselves, we are in fact attempting to mystify and deceive our judgment; we desire to find a motive a posteriori for this dissatisfaction, in the mistakes or deficiencies of others, and so lose sight of ourselves. Strictly religious people, who have been relentless judges of themselves, have at the same time spoken most ill of humanity generally; there has never been a saint who reserved sin for himself and virture for others, any more than a man who, according to Buddha's rule, hides his good qualities from people and only shows his bad ones.

Dissatisfaction with Others and with the World.—When we often express our dissatisfaction with others because we are really unhappy with ourselves, we are trying to confuse and mislead our own judgment; we want to find a reason afterward for this dissatisfaction in the mistakes or shortcomings of others, which makes us overlook our own issues. Very religious people, who have been harsh judges of themselves, have also often spoken poorly of humanity as a whole; there has never been a saint who kept all sin for themselves and virtue for others, just like a person who, following Buddha's teaching, hides their good qualities from others and only reveals their bad ones.

608.

608.

Confusion of Cause and Effect.—Unconsciously we seek the principles and opinions which are suited to our temperament, so that at last it seems as if these principles and opinions had formed our character and given it support and stability, whereas exactly the contrary has taken place. Our thoughts and judgments are, apparently, to be taken subsequently as the causes of our nature, but as a matter of fact our nature is the cause of our so thinking and judging. And what induces us to play this almost unconscious comedy? Inertness and convenience, and to a large extent also the vain desire to be regarded as thoroughly consistent and[Pg 385] homogeneous in nature and thought; for this wins respect and gives confidence and power.

Cause and Effect Confusion.—Without realizing it, we look for the beliefs and opinions that fit our personality. Eventually, it seems like these beliefs and opinions shape who we are and provide us with stability, when in fact, the opposite is true. Our thoughts and judgments seem to be the reasons for our character, but actually, our character is what drives us to think and judge that way. So, what makes us act out this almost unconscious drama? Laziness and convenience play a big part, as well as the empty wish to appear completely consistent and[Pg 385] uniform in nature and thought; this earns us respect and gives us confidence and influence.

609.

609.

Age in Relation to Truth.—Young people love what is interesting and exceptional, indifferent whether it is truth or falsehood. Riper minds love what is interesting and extraordinary when it is truth. Matured minds, finally, love truth even in those in whom it appears plain and simple and is found tiresome by ordinary people, because they have observed that truth is in the habit of giving utterance to its highest intellectual verities with all the appearance of simplicity.

Age and Truth.—Young people are drawn to things that are interesting and unique, not caring whether they are true or false. More developed minds appreciate what's interesting and extraordinary when it is true. Finally, mature minds value truth, even when it seems straightforward and boring to most people, because they recognize that truth often expresses its greatest insights with an air of simplicity.

610.

610.

Men As Bad Poets.—Just as bad poets seek a thought to fit the rhyme in the second half of the verse, so men in the second half of life, having become more scrupulous, are in the habit of seeking pursuits, positions, and conditions which suit those of their earlier life, so that outwardly all sounds well, but their life is no longer ruled and continuously determined anew by a powerful thought: in place thereof there is merely the intention of finding a rhyme.

Men as poor poets.—Just like bad poets try to find a thought that fits the rhyme in the second half of their verses, men in the later stages of life, having grown more careful, tend to look for pursuits, jobs, and circumstances that match those from their earlier years. So, on the surface, everything seems fine, but their lives are no longer driven and consistently shaped by a strong idea; instead, they're simply trying to find a rhyme.

611.

611.

Ennui and Play.—Necessity compels us to work, with the product of which the necessity is appeased; the ever new awakening of necessity,[Pg 386] however, accustoms us to work. But in the intervals in which necessity is appeased and asleep, as it were, we are attacked by ennui. What is this? In a word it is the habituation to work, which now makes itself felt as a new and additional necessity; it will be all the stronger the more a person has been accustomed to work, perhaps, even, the more a person has suffered from necessities. In order to escape ennui, a man either works beyond the extent of his former necessities, or he invents play, that is to say, work that is only intended to appease the general necessity for work. He who has become satiated with play, and has no new necessities impelling him to work, is sometimes attacked by the longing for a third state, which is related to play as gliding is to dancing, as dancing is to walking, a blessed, tranquil movement; it is the artists' and philosophers' vision of happiness.

Boredom and Gaming.—We are forced to work to satisfy our needs, but this constant cycle of necessity makes us used to working. Yet, during the times when our needs are met and we feel a bit idle, boredom strikes. What is boredom? In short, it's the result of getting used to work, which now feels like a new and added necessity; the more accustomed someone is to working, possibly even the more they've struggled with needs, the stronger this feeling becomes. To escape boredom, a person either works beyond what they used to need or creates play, which is work meant only to satisfy that general urge to work. Those who are tired of play and have no new needs driving them to work sometimes feel a longing for a third state, which relates to play as gliding relates to dancing, and dancing relates to walking; it's a blessed, peaceful movement—the artists' and philosophers' vision of happiness.

612.

612.

Lessons from Pictures.—If we look at a series of pictures of ourselves, from the time of later childhood to the time of mature manhood, we discover with pleased surprise that the man bears more resemblance to the child than to the youth: that probably, therefore, in accordance with this fact, there has been in the interval a temporary alienation of the fundamental character, over which the collected, concentrated force of the man has again become master. With this observation this other is also in accordance, namely, that[Pg 387] all strong influences of passions, teachers, and political events, which in our youthful years draw us hither and thither, seem later on to be referred back again to a fixed standard; of course they still continue to exist and operate within us, but our fundamental sentiments and opinions have now the upper hand, and use their influence perhaps as a source of strength, but are no longer merely regulative, as was perhaps the case in our twenties. Thus even the thoughts and sentiments of the man appear more in accordance with those of his childish years,—and this objective fact expresses itself in the above-mentioned subjective fact.

Lessons from Images.—When we look at a series of pictures of ourselves, from later childhood to mature adulthood, we’re pleasantly surprised to find that the man resembles the child more than the young adult. This suggests that during that time, our core character may have temporarily shifted, but ultimately, the strong, focused energy of the man has regained control. This observation also aligns with the idea that[Pg 387] all the powerful influences of passions, teachers, and political events that pull us in different directions during our youth seem to eventually settle into a stable foundation. They still exist and affect us, but our core beliefs and feelings now take precedence, using those influences as a source of strength rather than just a guiding force, as they likely did when we were in our twenties. So, even the thoughts and feelings of the man align more closely with those from his childhood, and this objective reality reflects the previously mentioned subjective experience.

613.

613.

The Tone of Voice of Different Ages.—The tone in which youths speak, praise, blame, and versify, displeases an older person because it is too loud, and yet at the same time dull and confused like a sound in a vault, which acquires such a loud ring owing to the emptiness; for most of the thought of youths does not gush forth out of the fulness of their own nature, but is the accord and the echo of what has been thought, said, praised or blamed around them. As their sentiments, however (their inclinations and aversions), resound much more forcibly than the reasons thereof, there is heard, whenever they divulge these sentiments, the dull, clanging tone which is a sign of the absence or scarcity of reasons. The tone of riper age is rigorous, abruptly concise, moderately loud, but, like[Pg 388] everything distinctly articulated, is heard very far off. Old age, finally, often brings a certain mildness and consideration into the tone of the voice, and as it were, sweetens it; in many cases, to be sure it also sours it.

The Tone of Voice Across Different Ages.—The way young people speak, praise, criticize, and create poetry often irritates older individuals because it's too loud, yet at the same time, it's dull and disorganized, like an echo in a vault that sounds so much louder due to the emptiness. Most of what young people think doesn’t come from their own depth, but rather reflects what they’ve heard, said, praised, or criticized around them. Their feelings (likes and dislikes), however, resonate much more powerfully than the reasons behind them, which results in a dull, clanging tone whenever they express these feelings—a sign of the lack or weakness of reasoning. The voice of older age is strict, sharply concise, moderately loud, yet everything clearly articulated can be heard from afar. In the end, old age often brings a certain gentleness and thoughtfulness to the tone of voice, almost sweetening it; though in many cases, it can also make it bitter.

614.

614.

The Atavist and the Forerunner.—The man of unpleasant character, full of distrust, envious of the success of fellow-competitors and neighbours, violent and enraged at divergent opinions, shows that he belongs to an earlier grade of culture, and is, therefore, an atavism; for the way in which he behaves to people was right and suitable only for an age of club-law; he is an atavist. The man of a different character, rich in sympathy, winning friends everywhere, finding all that is growing and becoming amiable, rejoicing at the honours and successes of others and claiming no privilege of solely knowing the truth, but full of a modest distrust,—he is a forerunner who presses upward towards a higher human culture. The man of unpleasant character dates from the times when the rude basis of human intercourse had yet to be laid, the other lives on the upper floor of the edifice of culture, removed as far as possible from the howling and raging wild beast imprisoned in the cellars.

The Atavist and the Pioneer.—A person with an unpleasant character, full of distrust, envious of the success of others, and quick to anger over differing opinions, clearly belongs to a lower level of culture and is therefore an atavism; the way he treats others is only appropriate for a time of brutality and lawlessness; he is an atavist. In contrast, a person with a different character, rich in empathy, making friends everywhere, appreciating all that is growing and becoming pleasant, celebrating the achievements of others without claiming a special right to know the truth, yet possessing a gentle sense of doubt—this person is a forerunner moving toward a higher level of human culture. The unpleasant character originates from a time when the rough foundations of human interaction were still being established, while the other resides on the upper levels of the cultural structure, as far from the howling and raging wild beast trapped in the cellar as possible.

615.

615.

Consolation For Hypochondriacs.—When a great thinker is temporarily subjected to hypochondriacal self-torture he can say to himself, by[Pg 389] way of consolation: "It is thine own great strength on which this parasite feeds and grows; if thy strength were smaller thou wouldst have less to suffer." The statesman may say just the same thing when jealousy and vengeful feeling, or, in a word, the tone of the bellum omnium contra omnes, for which, as the representative of a nation, he must necessarily have a great capacity, occasionally intrudes into his personal relations and makes his life hard.

Comfort for Hypochondriacs.—When a great thinker goes through a phase of hypochondriacal self-torture, he can comfort himself by saying: "Your own great strength is what this parasite feeds on; if your strength were weaker, you would have less to suffer." The statesman can think the same way when jealousy and vengeful feelings, or in other words, the mood of the bellum omnium contra omnes, for which he, as the representative of a nation, must have substantial capacity, occasionally disrupt his personal life and make things difficult.

616.

616.

Estranged from the Present.—There are great advantages in estranging one's self for once to a large extent from one's age, and being as it were driven back from its shores into the ocean of past views of things. Looking thence towards the coast one commands a view, perhaps for the first time, of its aggregate formation, and when one again approaches the land one has the advantage of understanding it better, on the whole, than those who have never left it.

Estranged from the Present.—There are significant benefits to stepping back from your time and immersing yourself in the broader ocean of past perspectives. From that viewpoint, you can see the overall makeup of your era, and when you return to the shore, you’ll have a better understanding of it, overall, than those who have never ventured away.

617.

617.

Sowing and Reaping on the Field of Personal Defects.—Men like Rousseau understand how to use their weaknesses, defects, and vices as manure for their talent. When Rousseau bewails the corruption and degeneration of society as the evil results of culture, there is a personal experience at the bottom of it, the bitterness which gives sharpness to his general condemnation and poisons[Pg 390] the arrows with which he shoots; he unburdens himself first as an individual, and thinks of getting a remedy which, while benefiting society directly, will also benefit himself indirectly by means of society.

Sowing and Reaping in the Area of Personal Flaws.—People like Rousseau know how to use their weaknesses, flaws, and vices as fertilizer for their talent. When Rousseau laments the corruption and decline of society as the negative outcomes of culture, there's a personal experience behind it—the bitterness that sharpens his overall criticism and poisons[Pg 390] the arrows he aims; he expresses his feelings first as an individual and thinks about finding a solution that, while directly benefiting society, will also indirectly benefit him through society.

618.

618.

Philosophically Minded.—We usually endeavour to acquire one attitude of mind, one set of opinions for all situations and events of life—it is mostly called being philosophically minded. But for the acquisition of knowledge it may be of greater importance not to make ourselves thus uniform, but to hearken to the low voice of the different situations in life; these bring their own opinions with them. We thus take an intelligent interest in the life and nature of many persons by not treating ourselves as rigid, persistent single individuals.

Philosophically Oriented.—We usually try to adopt one mindset, one set of views for all situations and events in life—it's generally referred to as being philosophically minded. However, for gaining knowledge, it might be more important not to make ourselves so uniform, but to listen to the subtle voice of different life situations; they bring their own perspectives. By doing this, we take an intelligent interest in the lives and nature of many people instead of treating ourselves as rigid, unchanging individuals.

619.

619.

In the Fire of Contempt.—It is a fresh step towards independence when one first dares to give utterance to opinions which it is considered as disgraceful for a person to entertain; even friends and acquaintances are then accustomed to grow anxious. The gifted nature must also pass through this fire; it afterwards belongs far more to itself.

In the Fire of Hatred.—It's a significant leap towards independence when someone first finds the courage to express opinions that society deems embarrassing or shameful; even friends and acquaintances often start to feel uneasy. A talented individual must also endure this challenge; afterward, they truly belong to themselves much more.

620.

620.

Self-sacrifice.—In the event of choice, a great sacrifice is preferred to a small one, because we compensate ourselves for the great sacrifice by[Pg 391] self-admiration, which is not possible in the case of a small one.

Selflessness.—When given a choice, a big sacrifice is better than a small one, because we reward ourselves for the big sacrifice with[Pg 391] self-admiration, which we can’t achieve with a small sacrifice.

621.

621.

Love As an Artifice.—Whoever really wishes to become acquainted with something new (whether it be a person, an event, or a book), does well to take up the matter with all possible love, and to avert his eye quickly from all that seems hostile, objectionable, and false therein,—in fact to forget such things; so that, for instance, he gives the author of a book the best start possible, and straightway, just as in a race, longs with beating heart that he may reach the goal. In this manner one penetrates to the heart of the new thing, to its moving point, and this is called becoming acquainted with it. This stage having been arrived at, the understanding afterwards makes its restrictions; the over-estimation and the temporary suspension of the critical pendulum were only artifices to lure forth the soul of the matter.

Love as a Construct.—Anyone who truly wants to get to know something new (whether it’s a person, an event, or a book) should approach it with as much love as possible and quickly look away from anything that seems hostile, off-putting, or false—essentially, forget such things; for example, this way, the reader gives the author of a book the best chance possible and immediately, like in a race, feels a racing heart wishing to reach the finish line. This approach allows one to dive into the essence of the new thing, to its core, and that’s what we call getting to know it. Once this stage is reached, understanding can then start to impose limits; the initial over-enthusiasm and temporary suspension of critical judgment were simply strategies to draw out the essence of the matter.

622.

622.

Thinking Too Well and Too Ill of the World.—Whether we think too well or too ill of things, we always have the advantage of deriving therefrom a greater pleasure, for with a too good preconception we usually put more sweetness into things (experiences) than they actually contain. A too bad preconception causes a pleasant disappointment, the pleasantness that lay in the things themselves is increased by the pleasantness of the[Pg 392] surprise. A gloomy temperament, however, will have the reverse experience in both cases.

Thinking Too Highly and Too Lowly of the World.—Whether we have overly positive or negative views about things, we always benefit from experiencing greater pleasure because with an overly positive mindset, we tend to find more sweetness in experiences than they actually have. A negative expectation leads to a nice surprise, as the enjoyment that exists in the experiences themselves is heightened by the joy of the[Pg 392] unexpected outcome. On the other hand, a pessimistic attitude will lead to the opposite experience in both situations.

623.

623.

Profound People.—Those whose strength lies in the deepening of impressions—they are usually called profound people—are relatively self-possessed and decided in all sudden emergencies, for in the first moment the impression is still shallow, it only then becomes deep. Long foreseen, long expected events or persons, however, excite such natures most, and make them almost incapable of eventually having presence of mind on the arrival thereof.

Deep Thinkers.—Those whose strength comes from their ability to deepen impressions—often referred to as profound people—are usually calm and resolute in sudden emergencies. In those first moments, the impression is still shallow; it only begins to deepen then. However, events or people that have been anticipated for a long time tend to agitate these individuals the most, making them almost unable to stay composed when the moment finally arrives.

624.

624.

Intercourse With the Higher Self.—Every one has his good day, when he finds his higher self; and true humanity demands that a person shall be estimated according to this state and not according to his work-days of constraint and bondage. A painter, for instance, should be appraised and honoured according to the most exalted vision he could see and represent. But men themselves commune very differently with this their higher self, and are frequently their own playactors, in so far as they repeatedly imitate what they are in those moments. Some stand in awe and humility before their ideal, and would fain deny it; they are afraid of their higher self because, when it speaks, it speaks pretentiously. Besides, it has a ghost-like freedom of coming and staying away just as it pleases; on that account it[Pg 393] is often called a gift of the gods, while in fact everything else is a gift of the gods (of chance); this, however, is the man himself.

Connecting with your higher self.—Everyone has their good days when they discover their higher self; true humanity requires that a person be valued based on this state rather than on the days spent in constraint and bondage. For example, a painter should be recognized and honored for the highest vision they can see and create. However, people engage with their higher selves very differently, often acting as their own performers by repeatedly mimicking what they feel in those moments. Some approach their ideals with awe and humility and may even want to deny them; they fear their higher self because, when it expresses itself, it does so with a sense of grandeur. Moreover, it has a ghostly freedom to appear and disappear as it wishes; for this reason, it[Pg 393] is often referred to as a gift from the gods, while in reality, everything else is a gift from the gods (or luck); this, however, is truly the essence of a person.

625.

625.

Lonely People.—Some people are so much accustomed to being alone in self-communion that they do not at all compare themselves with others, but spin out their soliloquising life in a quiet, happy mood, conversing pleasantly, and even hilariously, with themselves. If, however, they are brought to the point of comparing themselves with others, they are inclined to a brooding under-estimation of their own worth, so that they have first to be compelled by others to form once more a good and just opinion of themselves, and even from this acquired opinion they will always want to subtract and abate something. We must not, therefore, grudge certain persons their loneliness or foolishly commiserate them on that account, as is so often done.

Lonely individuals.—Some people are so used to being alone in their own thoughts that they don’t really compare themselves to others; instead, they live a quiet, happy life, happily talking and even laughing with themselves. However, if they start comparing themselves to others, they tend to underestimate their own value, needing others to help them regain a fair and positive view of themselves. Even with this newfound perspective, they'll often feel the urge to downplay it. Therefore, we shouldn’t resent certain individuals for their loneliness or pity them unnecessarily, as is often the case.

626.

626.

Without Melody.—There are persons to whom a constant repose in themselves and the harmonious ordering of all their capacities is so natural that every definite activity is repugnant to them. They resemble music which consists of nothing but prolonged, harmonious accords, without even the tendency to an organised and animated melody showing itself. All external movement serves only to restore to the boat its equilibrium[Pg 394] on the sea of harmonious euphony. Modern men usually become excessively impatient when they meet such natures, who will never be anything in the world, only it is not allowable to say of them that they are nothing. But in certain moods the sight of them raises the unusual question: "Why should there be melody at all? Why should it not suffice us when life mirrors itself peacefully in a deep lake?" The Middle Ages were richer in such natures than our times. How seldom one now meets with any one who can live on so peacefully and happily with himself even in the midst of the crowd, saying to himself, like Goethe, "The best thing of all is the deep calm in which I live and grow in opposition to the world, and gain what it cannot take away from me with fire and sword."

No Melody.—There are people who find a constant inner peace and a harmonious arrangement of all their abilities to be so natural that any specific action feels uncomfortable for them. They are like music that consists solely of prolonged, harmonious chords, lacking even the hint of a structured and lively melody. Any external movement just helps to return the boat to its balance[Pg 394] on the sea of harmonious sound. Modern individuals often become extremely impatient when they encounter such personalities, who will never amount to anything in the world, though it’s not right to say they are nothing. Yet, in certain moods, seeing them raises the intriguing question: "Why does there need to be melody at all? Why is it not enough for life to reflect itself peacefully in a deep lake?" The Middle Ages had more of these people than our time does. It's rare to meet anyone today who can live so calmly and happily with themselves even in a crowd, thinking to themselves, like Goethe, "The best thing of all is the deep calm in which I live and grow in opposition to the world, and gain what it cannot take away from me with fire and sword."

627.

627.

To Live and Experience.—If we observe how some people can deal with their experiences—their unimportant, everyday experiences—so that these become soil which yields fruit thrice a year; whilst others—and how many!—are driven through the surf of the most exciting adventures, the most diversified movements of times and peoples, and yet always remain light, always remain on the surface, like cork; we are finally tempted to divide mankind into a minority (minimality) of those who know how to make much out of little, and a majority of those who know how to make little out of much; indeed, we even meet with the counter-sorcerers who, instead[Pg 395] of making the world out of nothing, make a nothing out of the world.

Live and Experience.—If we look at how some people handle their experiences—those ordinary, everyday moments—turning them into rich opportunities that yield rewards three times a year, while others—and there are many!—get swept away by the thrill of exciting adventures, by a variety of times and cultures, yet still remain superficial, floating on the surface like cork; we might find ourselves wanting to classify humanity into a small group (a minority) of those who can create a lot from a little, and a large group of those who can create very little from a lot; in fact, we even encounter those who, instead[Pg 395] of conjuring something from nothing, turn the world into nothing.

628.

628.

Seriousness in Play.—-In Genoa one evening, in the twilight, I heard from a tower a long chiming of bells; it was never like to end, and sounded as if insatiable above the noise of the streets, out into the evening sky and sea-air, so thrilling, and at the same time so childish and so sad. I then remembered the words of Plato, and suddenly felt the force of them in my heart: "Human matters, one and all, are not worthy of great seriousness; nevertheless ..."

Seriousness in Gaming.—-One evening in Genoa, at dusk, I heard a long, continuous ringing of bells from a tower; it seemed like it would never stop and resonated above the street noise, reaching out into the evening sky and sea air, so exciting yet also so innocent and melancholic. I then recalled Plato's words and suddenly felt their impact in my heart: "Human matters, one and all, are not worthy of great seriousness; nevertheless ..."

629.

629.

Conviction and Justice.—The requirement that a person must afterwards, when cool and sober, stand by what he says, promises, and resolves during passion, is one of the heaviest burdens that weigh upon mankind. To have to acknowledge for all future time the consequences of anger, of fiery revenge, of enthusiastic devotion, may lead to a bitterness against these feelings proportionate to the idolatry with which they are idolised, especially by artists. These cultivate to its full extent the esteem of the passions, and have always done so; to be sure, they also glorify the terrible satisfaction of the passions which a person affords himself, the outbreaks of vengeance, with death, mutilation, or voluntary banishment in their train, and the resignation of the broken heart.[Pg 396] In any case they keep alive curiosity about the passions; it is as if they said: "Without passions you have no experience whatever." Because we have sworn fidelity (perhaps even to a purely fictitious being, such as a god), because we have surrendered our heart to a prince, a party, a woman, a priestly order, an artist, or a thinker, in a state of infatuated delusion that threw a charm over us and made those beings appear worthy of all veneration, and every sacrifice—are we, therefore, firmly and inevitably bound? Or did we not, after all, deceive ourselves then? Was there not a hypothetical promise, under the tacit presupposition that those beings to whom we consecrated ourselves were really the beings they seemed to be in our imagination? Are we under obligation to be faithful to our errors, even with the knowledge that by this fidelity we shall cause injury to our higher selves? No, there is no law, no obligation of that sort; we must become traitors, we must act unfaithfully and abandon our ideals again and again. We cannot advance from one period of life into another without causing these pains of treachery and also suffering from them. Might it be necessary to guard against the ebullitions of our feelings in order to escape these pains? Would not the world then become too arid, too ghost-like for us? Rather will we ask ourselves whether these pains are necessary on a change of convictions, or whether they do not depend on a mistaken opinion and estimate. Why do we admire a person who remains true to his convictions and despise him who changes them? I fear[Pg 397] the answer must be, "because every one takes for granted that such a change is caused only by motives of more general utility or of personal trouble." That is to say, we believe at bottom that nobody alters his opinions as long as they are advantageous to him, or at least as long as they do not cause him any harm. If it is so, however, it furnishes a bad proof of the intellectual significance of all convictions. Let us once examine how convictions arise, and let us see whether their importance is not greatly over-estimated; it will thereby be seen that the change of convictions also is in all circumstances judged according to a false standard, that we have hitherto been accustomed to suffer too much from this change.

Justice and Accountability.—The expectation that a person must later, when calm and sober, uphold what they say, promise, and decide in moments of passion is one of the heaviest burdens on humanity. Having to accept the lasting consequences of anger, fiery revenge, or intense devotion can create a bitterness towards these emotions that matches the reverence with which they are often revered, especially by artists. These individuals fully embrace the value of passions, and they always have; of course, they also glorify the intense satisfaction that comes from the passions, including acts of vengeance accompanied by death, injury, or self-imposed exile, as well as the heartache that follows. [Pg 396] Regardless, they fuel curiosity about passions; it’s as if they claim, "Without passions, you have no real experience." Because we have pledged loyalty (maybe even to an entirely imaginary entity, like a god), because we have given our hearts to a prince, a movement, a woman, a religious group, an artist, or a thinker, under a cloud of infatuation that made them seem worthy of all worship and sacrifice—are we truly and unavoidably bound? Or did we perhaps deceive ourselves back then? Was there not an implied promise, based on the assumption that those we committed ourselves to were actually the beings they appeared to be in our minds? Are we obligated to remain loyal to our misconceptions, even if that loyalty harms our higher selves? No, there is no law or obligation like that; we must become traitors; we must act disloyally and abandon our ideals repeatedly. We cannot transition from one phase of life to another without experiencing these feelings of betrayal and also suffering from them. Might it be necessary to control the outbursts of our feelings to avoid this suffering? Wouldn’t the world then become too dry and ghostly for us? Instead, we should ask ourselves whether this pain is essential with changes in beliefs, or whether it comes from a misguided perspective. Why do we admire someone who stays true to their beliefs while despising someone who shifts theirs? I fear[Pg 397] the answer is, "because everyone assumes such a change is only due to more practical needs or personal issues." Essentially, we believe that fundamentally, no one changes their opinions as long as they are beneficial for them, or at least as long as they don't cause harm. However, if that’s the case, it suggests a poor measure of the intellectual value of all beliefs. Let’s examine how beliefs form and see if their significance is not vastly exaggerated; it will reveal that the change of beliefs is, in every circumstance, judged by an inaccurate standard and that we have been too burdened by this change until now.

630.

630.

Conviction is belief in the possession of absolute truth on any matter of knowledge. This belief takes it for granted, therefore, that there are absolute truths; also, that perfect methods have been found for attaining to them; and finally, that every one who has convictions makes use of these perfect methods. All three notions show at once that the man of convictions is not the man of scientific thought; he seems to us still in the age of theoretical innocence, and is practically a child, however grown-up he may be. Whole centuries, however, have been lived under the influence of those childlike presuppositions, and out of them have flowed the mightiest sources of human strength. The countless numbers who[Pg 398] sacrificed themselves for their convictions believed they were doing it for the sake of absolute truth. They were all wrong, however; probably no one has ever sacrificed himself for Truth; at least, the dogmatic expression of the faith of any such person has been unscientific or only partly scientific. But really, people wanted to carry their point because they believed that they must be in the right. To allow their belief to be wrested from them probably meant calling in question their eternal salvation. In an affair of such extreme importance the "will" was too audibly the prompter of the intellect. The presupposition of every believer of every shade of belief has been that he could not be confuted; if the counter-arguments happened to be very strong, it always remained for him to decry intellect generally, and, perhaps, even to set up the "credo quia absurdum est" as the standard of extreme fanaticism. It is not the struggle of opinions that has made history so turbulent; but the struggle of belief in opinions,—that is to say, of convictions. If all those who thought so highly of their convictions, who made sacrifices of all kinds for them, and spared neither honour, body, nor life in their service, had only devoted half of their energy to examining their right to adhere to this or that conviction and by what road they arrived at it, how peaceable would the history of mankind now appear! How much more knowledge would there be! All the cruel scenes in connection with the persecution of heretics of all kinds would have been avoided, for two reasons: firstly, because the inquisitors would above all have[Pg 399] inquired of themselves, and would have recognised the presumption of defending absolute truth; and secondly, because the heretics themselves would, after examination, have taken no more interest in such badly established doctrines as those of all religious sectarians and "orthodox" believers.

Conviction is the belief in having absolute truth about any knowledge. This belief assumes that absolute truths exist, that perfect methods to reach them have been discovered, and that everyone with convictions uses these perfect methods. All three ideas show that a person with strong convictions isn't someone who thinks scientifically; they seem stuck in a naive theoretical age and are basically a child, no matter how grown-up they are. Yet, entire centuries have been lived under these childlike assumptions, producing some of humanity's greatest strengths. The countless individuals who sacrificed themselves for their beliefs thought they were doing it for absolute truth. However, they were all mistaken; probably no one has sacrificed themselves for Truth. At least, the dogmatic expressions of their faith were unscientific or only partially scientific. But really, people wanted to prove their point because they believed they had to be right. Allowing their beliefs to be challenged likely meant questioning their eternal salvation. In such a critical matter, the "will" was clearly driving the intellect. Every believer, no matter their belief, has assumed they could not be disproven; if counter-arguments were very strong, it was always up to them to dismiss intellect altogether and maybe even adopt the notion of "credo quia absurdum est" as a marker of extreme fanaticism. It's not the clash of opinions that has made history chaotic, but the clash of beliefs in those opinions—that is, of convictions. If all those who held their convictions so dearly, who sacrificed everything for them and put their honor, bodies, and lives on the line, had spent just half that effort checking whether they were justified in holding this or that belief and how they came to that conclusion, how peaceful human history would look today! How much more knowledge there would be! All the horrific incidents related to the persecution of heretics would have been avoided for two reasons: first, because the inquisitors would have primarily questioned themselves and recognized the arrogance in defending absolute truth; and second, because the heretics would have, after reflection, shown no interest in such poorly established doctrines like those of various religious sects and "orthodox" believers.

631.

631.

From the ages in which it was customary to believe in the possession of absolute truth, people have inherited a profound dislike of all sceptical and relative attitudes with regard to questions of knowledge; they mostly prefer to acquiesce, for good or evil, in the convictions of those in authority (fathers, friends, teachers, princes), and they have a kind of remorse of conscience when they do not do so. This tendency is quite comprehensible, and its results furnish no ground for condemnation of the course of the development of human reason. The scientific spirit in man, however, has gradually to bring to maturity the virtue of cautious forbearance, the wise moderation, which is better known in practical than in theoretical life, and which, for instance, Goethe has represented in "Antonio," as an object of provocation for all Tassos,—that is to say, for unscientific and at the same time inactive natures. The man of convictions has in himself the right not to comprehend the man of cautious thought, the theoretical Antonio; the scientific man, on the other hand, has no right to blame the former on that account, he takes no notice thereof, and[Pg 400] knows, moreover, that in certain cases the former will yet cling to him, as Tasso finally clung to Antonio.

From the time when it was common to believe in absolute truth, people have developed a deep dislike for any skeptical or relative views about knowledge. They mostly prefer to go along with the beliefs of those in authority (fathers, friends, teachers, rulers), and they feel a sort of guilt if they don’t. This tendency is understandable, and its outcomes don’t justify condemning the path of human reason’s development. However, the scientific spirit in people gradually matures the virtue of cautious forbearance, the wise moderation that is more familiar in practical life than in theoretical matters. For example, Goethe illustrates this in "Antonio," as a challenge for all Tassos—meaning those who are unscientific and also inactive. A person with strong convictions is entitled not to understand the cautious thinker, the theoretical Antonio; however, the scientific person has no right to criticize the former for this, as he remains indifferent, and[Pg 400] also knows that in some cases, the former will still cling to him, just as Tasso eventually held onto Antonio.

632.

632.

He who has not passed through different phases of conviction, but sticks to the faith in whose net he was first caught, is, under all circumstances, just on account of this unchangeableness, a representative of atavistic culture; in accordance with this lack of culture (which always presupposes plasticity for culture), he is severe, unintelligent, unteachable, without liberality, an ever suspicious person, an unscrupulous person who has recourse to all expedients for enforcing his opinions because he cannot conceive that there must be other opinions; he is, in such respects, perhaps a source of strength, and even wholesome in cultures that have become too emancipated and languid, but only because he strongly incites to opposition: for thereby the delicate organisation of the new culture, which is forced to struggle with him, becomes strong itself.

The person who hasn't experienced different stages of belief but clings to the faith they first adopted is, in every situation, simply due to their unchanging nature, a representative of outdated culture. This lack of cultural development, which always requires adaptability, makes them harsh, unwise, unteachable, narrow-minded, and constantly suspicious. They are often unscrupulous, resorting to any means necessary to impose their views because they can't imagine that there could be other perspectives. In some ways, they might provide a sense of strength, even being beneficial in societies that have become too liberated and weak, but only because they provoke resistance. This opposition helps the fragile structure of the new culture, which must struggle against them, to grow stronger.

633.

633.

In essential respects we are still the same men as those of the time of the Reformation; how could it be otherwise? But the fact that we no longer allow ourselves certain means for promoting the triumph of our opinions distinguishes us from that age, and proves that we belong to a higher culture. He who still combats and overthrows opinions with calumnies and outbursts[Pg 401] of rage, after the manner of the Reformation men, obviously betrays the fact that he would have burnt his adversaries had he lived in other times, and that he would have resorted to all the methods of the Inquisition if he had been an opponent of the Reformation. The Inquisition was rational at that time; for it represented nothing else than the universal application of martial law, which had to be proclaimed throughout the entire domain of the Church, and which, like all martial law, gave a right to the extremest methods, under the presupposition, of course, (which we now no longer share with those people), that the Church possessed truth and had to preserve it at all costs, and at any sacrifice, for the salvation of mankind. Now, however, one does not so readily concede to any one that he possesses the truth; strict methods of investigation have diffused enough of distrust and precaution, so that every one who violently advocates opinions in word and deed is looked upon as an enemy of our modern culture, or, at least, as an atavist. As a matter of fact the pathos that man possesses truth is now of very little consequence in comparison with the certainly milder and less noisy pathos of the search for truth, which is never weary of learning afresh and examining anew.

In many ways, we are still the same people as those from the time of the Reformation; how could it be any different? But the fact that we no longer use certain means to promote our beliefs sets us apart from that era and shows that we belong to a higher culture. Those who still fight against and dismantle ideas with lies and fits of rage, like the Reformation-era individuals, clearly reveal that they would have burned their opponents if they had lived in those times, and that they would have used all the methods of the Inquisition if they had been against the Reformation. The Inquisition made sense back then; it was nothing more than the widespread enforcement of martial law, which had to be declared throughout the entire Church’s territory, and, like all martial law, it justified extreme measures based on the assumption, which we no longer share with those people, that the Church held the truth and had to protect it at all costs for the salvation of humanity. Now, however, it’s not so easy to claim that anyone possesses the truth; rigorous methods of investigation have created sufficient skepticism and caution, so that anyone who aggressively promotes their views in word and action is seen as an enemy of our modern culture, or at the very least, as a relic of the past. In fact, the belief that one possesses the truth is now much less important compared to the certainly gentler and quieter pursuit of truth, which never tires of learning anew and reviewing once again.

634.

634.

Moreover, the methodical search for truth is itself the outcome of those ages in which convictions were at war with each other. If the[Pg 402] individual had not cared about his "truth," that is to say, about carrying his point, there would have been no method of investigation; thus, however, by the eternal struggle of the claims of different individuals to absolute truth, people went on step by step to find irrefragable principles according to which the rights of the claims could be tested and the dispute settled. At first people decided according to authorities; later on they criticised one another's ways and means of finding the presumed truth; in the interval there was a period when people deduced the consequences of the adverse theory, and perhaps found them to be productive of injury and unhappiness; from which it was then to be inferred by every one that the conviction of the adversary involved an error. The personal struggle of the thinker at last so sharpened his methods that real truths could be discovered, and the mistakes of former methods exposed before the eyes of all.

Moreover, the systematic search for truth is itself the result of those times when beliefs were clashing with one another. If the[Pg 402]individual hadn’t cared about their "truth," meaning about proving their point, there would have been no method of investigation. However, through the ongoing struggle of different individuals claiming absolute truth, people gradually found undeniable principles to test the validity of those claims and resolve disputes. Initially, people relied on authorities for their decisions; later, they started to critique each other’s methods of seeking the presumed truth. There was a time when people inferred the consequences of opposing theories and may have found them harmful and unhappy, leading everyone to conclude that the opponent's belief must be mistaken. The personal struggle of the thinker ultimately refined their methods so that real truths could be uncovered and the flaws of earlier methods revealed to everyone.

635.

635.

On the whole, scientific methods are at least as important results of investigation as any other results, for the scientific spirit is based upon a knowledge of method, and if the methods were lost, all the results of science could not prevent the renewed prevalence of superstition and absurdity. Clever people may learn as much as they like of the results of science, but one still notices in their conversation, and especially in the hypotheses they make, that they lack the[Pg 403] scientific spirit; they have not the instinctive distrust of the devious courses of thinking which, in consequence of long training, has taken root in the soul of every scientific man. It is enough for them to find any kind of hypothesis on a subject, they are then all on fire for it, and imagine the matter is thereby settled. To have an opinion is with them equivalent to immediately becoming fanatical for it, and finally taking it to heart as a conviction. In the case of an unexplained matter they become heated for the first idea that comes into their head which has any resemblance to an explanation—a course from which the worst results constantly follow, especially in the field of politics. On that account everybody should nowadays have become thoroughly acquainted with at least one science, for then surely he knows what is meant by method, and how necessary is the extremest carefulness. To women in particular this advice is to be given at present; as to those who are irretrievably the victims of all hypotheses, especially when these have the appearance of being witty, attractive, enlivening, and invigorating. Indeed, on close inspection one sees that by far the greater number of educated people still desire convictions from a thinker and nothing but convictions, and that only a small minority want certainty. The former want to be forcibly carried away in order thereby to obtain an increase of strength; the latter few have the real interest which disregards personal advantages and the increase of strength also. The former class, who[Pg 404] greatly predominate, are always reckoned upon when the thinker comports himself and labels himself as a genius, and thus views himself as a higher being to whom authority belongs. In so far as genius of this kind upholds the ardour of convictions, and arouses distrust of the cautious and modest spirit of science, it is an enemy of truth, however much it may think itself the wooer thereof.

Overall, scientific methods are just as important as any other findings from research because the scientific spirit relies on understanding these methods. If we were to lose these methods, no amount of scientific results would stop the resurgence of superstition and nonsense. Intelligent people can learn as much as they want about scientific findings, but it's still evident in their discussions, especially in the theories they propose, that they lack the scientific spirit; they don't possess the inherent skepticism about flawed reasoning that becomes ingrained in every trained scientist. For them, discovering any kind of theory on a topic sparks immediate excitement, and they think that settles the matter. For them, forming an opinion is synonymous with becoming fanatical about it and eventually adopting it as a firm belief. When faced with an unanswered question, they get excited about the first idea that remotely resembles an explanation—a tendency that often leads to disastrous consequences, especially in politics. Therefore, it's crucial for everyone nowadays to be well-acquainted with at least one science, as this knowledge helps them grasp the concept of method and the importance of extreme caution. This advice is particularly directed toward women; those who are hopelessly trapped by all sorts of theories, especially those that seem clever, appealing, entertaining, and refreshing. Upon closer examination, it's clear that many educated individuals still seek convictions from thinkers and nothing but convictions, with only a small minority desiring certainty. The former group wants to be swept away to gain strength, while the latter few have genuine interests that overlook personal benefits and the quest for power. The former class, which vastly outnumbers the latter, tends to support thinkers who present themselves as geniuses, viewing themselves as superior beings deserving of authority. As long as this type of genius promotes fervent beliefs and fosters distrust of the cautious and humble nature of science, it poses a threat to truth, no matter how much it believes it is pursuing it.

636.

636.

There is, certainly, also an entirely different species of genius, that of justice; and I cannot make up my mind to estimate it lower than any kind of philosophical, political, or artistic genius. Its peculiarity is to go, with heartfelt aversion, out of the way of everything that blinds and confuses people's judgment of things; it is consequently an adversary of convictions, for it wants to give their own to all, whether they be living or dead, real or imaginary—and for that purpose it must know thoroughly; it therefore places everything in the best light and goes around it with careful eyes. Finally, it will even give to its adversary the blind or short-sighted "conviction" (as men call it,—among women it is called "faith"), what is due to conviction—for the sake of truth.

There’s definitely another type of genius, which is justice, and I can't bring myself to value it any less than any form of philosophical, political, or artistic genius. Its unique quality is to steer clear with genuine distaste from anything that clouds and confuses people's judgment about things; it's therefore an adversary of convictions, because it aims to provide everyone, whether they're alive or dead, real or imaginary, with their own perspectives—and to do that, it must understand everything deeply. It presents everything in the best possible light and examines it closely. In the end, it will even acknowledge its opponent's blind or narrow "conviction" (as people call it—among women, it’s referred to as "faith"), granting it what’s due for the sake of truth.

637.

637.

Opinions evolve out of passions; indolence of intellect allows those to congeal into convictions. He, however, who is conscious of himself as a free, restless, lively spirit can prevent this[Pg 405] congelation by constant change; and if he is altogether a thinking snowball, he will not have opinions in his head at all, but only certainties and properly estimated probabilities. But we, who are of a mixed nature, alternately inspired with ardour and chilled through and through by the intellect, want to kneel before justice, as the only goddess we acknowledge. The fire in us generally makes us unjust, and impure in the eyes of our goddess; in this condition we are not permitted to take her hand, and the serious smile of her approval never rests upon us. We reverence her as the veiled Isis of our life; with shame we offer her our pain as penance and sacrifice when the fire threatens to burn and consume us. It is the intellect that saves us from being utterly burnt and reduced to ashes; it occasionally drags us away from the sacrificial altar of justice or enwraps us in a garment of asbestos. Liberated from the fire, and impelled by the intellect, we then pass from opinion to opinion, through the change of parties, as noble betrayers of all things that can in any way be betrayed—and nevertheless without a feeling of guilt.

Opinions come from passions; a lazy mind lets them turn into convictions. However, someone who sees themselves as a free, restless, lively spirit can prevent this [Pg 405] solidification through constant change; and if they happen to be a constantly thinking entity, they won't have opinions at all but just certainties and properly assessed probabilities. But we, with our mixed nature, are alternately fueled by passion and cooled by intellect, wanting to bow before justice, the only goddess we recognize. The fire within us usually makes us unjust and seen as impure in her eyes; in this state, we can't take her hand, and the serious smile of her approval never shines upon us. We honor her as the veiled Isis of our life; with shame, we offer her our pain as atonement and sacrifice when the fire threatens to burn and engulf us. It is the intellect that saves us from being completely burned and turned to ash; it sometimes pulls us away from the sacrificial altar of justice or wraps us in a protective layer. Freed from the fire and guided by intellect, we then move from one opinion to another, switching parties like noble betrayers of all things that can be betrayed—and still without feeling guilty.

638.

638.

The Wanderer.—He who has attained intellectual emancipation to any extent cannot, for a long time, regard himself otherwise than as a wanderer on the face of the earth—and not even as a traveller towards a final goal, for there is no such thing. But he certainly wants to observe and[Pg 406] keep his eyes open to whatever actually happens in the world; therefore he cannot attach his heart too firmly to anything individual; he must have in himself something wandering that takes pleasure in change and transitoriness. To be sure such a man will have bad nights, when he is weary and finds the gates of the town that should offer him rest closed; perhaps he may also find that, as in the East, the desert reaches to the gates, that wild beasts howl far and near, that a strong wind arises, and that robbers take away his beasts of burden. Then the dreadful night closes over him like a second desert upon the desert, and his heart grows weary of wandering. Then when the morning sun rises upon him, glowing like a Deity of anger, when the town is opened, he sees perhaps in the faces of the dwellers therein still more desert, uncleanliness, deceit, and insecurity than outside the gates—and the day is almost worse than the night. Thus it may occasionally happen to the wanderer; but then there come as, compensation the delightful mornings of other lands and days, when already in the grey of the dawn he sees the throng of muses dancing by, close to him, in the mist of the mountain; when afterwards, in the symmetry of his ante-meridian soul, he strolls silently under the trees, out of whose crests and leafy hiding-places all manner of good and bright things are flung to him, the gifts of all the free spirits who are at home in mountains, forests, and solitudes, and who, like himself, alternately merry and thoughtful, are wanderers and philosophers. Born[Pg 407] of the secrets of the early dawn, they ponder the question how the day, between the hours of ten and twelve, can have such a pure, transparent, and gloriously cheerful countenance: they seek the ante-meridian philosophy.

The Wanderer.—Someone who has gained even a little intellectual freedom can’t help but see themselves as a wanderer on this earth—not even as a traveler heading towards a final destination, because that doesn’t exist. However, they definitely want to observe and[Pg 406] keep their eyes open to what really happens in the world; therefore, they can't attach their heart too strongly to anything specific; they must have something within themselves that enjoys wandering, change, and impermanence. Of course, this person will have rough nights, feeling tired and finding the town gates that should offer rest closed; they might also discover that, like in the East, the desert stretches to the gates, wild animals howl nearby, strong winds rise, and robbers take away their pack animals. Then the dreadful night closes in on them like a second desert on the first, and their heart grows weary of wandering. But when the morning sun rises, blazing like an angry deity, and the town opens up, they may see in the faces of the locals even more desert, dirt, deceit, and insecurity than outside the gates—and the day can be almost worse than the night. This may happen to the wanderer sometimes; but then, as compensation, there come the delightful mornings of other lands and days, when even in the early dawn they see the muses dancing nearby, wrapped in the mist of the mountains; when later, in the clarity of their morning spirit, they stroll quietly under the trees, from whose branches and leafy hiding places all kinds of good and bright things are thrown to them, the gifts of all the free spirits who feel at home in mountains, forests, and solitude, who, like them, oscillate between joy and contemplation, being both wanderers and philosophers. Born[Pg 407] of the secrets of the early dawn, they contemplate why the day, between ten and noon, can have such a pure, clear, and wonderfully cheerful appearance: they seek the ante-meridian philosophy.


[1] This is why Nietzsche pointed out later on that he had an interest in the preservation of Christianity, and that he was sure his teaching would not undermine this faith—just as little as anarchists have undermined kings; but have left them seated all the more firmly on their thrones.—J.M.K.

[1] This is why Nietzsche later noted that he was interested in maintaining Christianity and believed his teachings wouldn’t threaten this faith—just like anarchists haven’t toppled kings; instead, they have made them sit even more firmly on their thrones.—J.M.K.

[2] Women never understand this.—J.M.K.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Women never get this.—J.M.K.


AN EPODE.

AMONG FRIENDS.

WITH FRIENDS.

(Translated by T. COMMON.)

(Translated by T. COMMON.)

Nice, when mute we lie a-dreaming,
Nicer still when we are laughing,
'Neath the sky heaven's chariot speeding,
On the moss the book a-reading,
Sweetly loud with friends all laughing
Joyous, with white teeth a-gleaming.
Do I well, we're mute and humble;
Do I ill—we'll laugh exceeding;
Make it worse and worse, unheeding,
Worse proceeding, more laughs needing,
Till into the grave we stumble.
Friends! Yea! so shall it obtain?
Amen! Till we meet again.


II.

No excuses need be started!
Give, ye glad ones, open hearted,
To this foolish book before you
Ear and heart and lodging meet;
Trust me, 'twas not meant to bore you,
Though of folly I may treat!
What I find, seek, and am needing,
Was it e'er in book for reading?
Honour now fools in my name,
Learn from out this book by reading
How "our sense" from reason came.
Thus, my friends, shall it obtain?
Amen! Till we meet again.

Nice, when we lie quietly dreaming,
Even nicer when we’re laughing,
Beneath the sky as heaven's chariot speeds,
On the moss with a book to read,
Happily loud with friends all laughing,
Joyful, with bright smiles gleaming.
If I'm doing well, we're quiet and humble;
If I'm not—we'll laugh a lot;
Making it worse and worse, not caring,
Getting worse, needing more laughs,
Until we stumble into the grave.
Friends! Yes! So it shall be?
Amen! Until we meet again.


II.

No excuses need to be made!
Give, you cheerful ones, with open hearts,
To this silly book in front of you
Ear and heart and home; please engage;
Trust me, it wasn’t meant to bore you,
Though it might deal with foolishness!
What I seek, find, and need,
Has it ever been in a book to read?
Honor the fools in my name,
Learn from this book by reading
How “our sense” came from reason.
So, my friends, shall it be?
Amen! Until we meet again.


Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!