This is a modern-English version of Principia Ethica, originally written by Moore, G. E. (George Edward).
It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling,
and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If
you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.
Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.

[p. i]
[p. i]
PRINCIPIA ETHICA
[p. ii]
[p. ii]
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
C. F. CLAY, Manager
LONDON: FETTER LANE, E.C. 4
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
C. F. CLAY, Manager
LONDON: FETTER LANE, E.C. 4

NEW YORK: MACMILLAN CO. | ||
BOMBAY | MACMILLAN AND CO., Ltd. | |
CALCUTTA | ||
MADRAS | ||
TORONTO: THE MACMILLAN CO. OF TORONTO: THE MACMILLAN CO. OF CANADA, Ltd. CANADA, Ltd. |
||
TOKYO: MARUZEN-KABUSHIKI-KAISHA |
ALL RIGHTS RESERVED
All rights reserved.
[p. iii]
[p. iii]
PRINCIPIA ETHICA
Principles of Ethics
BY
BY
GEORGE EDWARD MOORE
George Edward Moore
LITT.D. CAMBRIDGE, HON. LL.D. ST ANDREWS,
FELLOW OF THE BRITISH ACADEMY,
LECTURER IN MORAL SCIENCE IN THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE
LITT.D. CAMBRIDGE, HON. LL.D. ST ANDREWS,
FELLOW OF THE BRITISH ACADEMY,
LECTURER IN MORAL SCIENCE AT THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE
“Everything is what it is,
and not another thing”
“Everything is what it is,
and not something else.”
Bishop Butler
Bishop Butler
CAMBRIDGE
AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS
1922
CAMBRIDGE
AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS
1922
[p. iv]
[p. iv]
First Edition 1903
First Edition 1903
Reprinted 1922
Reprinted 1922
[p. v]
[p. v]
DOCTORIBUS AMICISQUE CANTABRIGIENSIBUS
To Cambridge Friends and Doctors
DISCIPULUS AMICUS CANTABRIGIENSIS
Cambridge Student Friend
PRIMITIAS
PRIMITIAS
D. D. D.
D. D. D.
AUCTOR
AUTHOR
[p. vii]
[p. vii]
PREFACE.
It appears to me that in Ethics, as in all other philosophical studies, the difficulties and disagreements, of which its history is full, are mainly due to a very simple cause: namely to the attempt to answer questions, without first discovering precisely what question it is which you desire to answer. I do not know how far this source of error would be done away, if philosophers would try to discover what question they were asking, before they set about to answer it; for the work of analysis and distinction is often very difficult: we may often fail to make the necessary discovery, even though we make a definite attempt to do so. But I am inclined to think that in many cases a resolute attempt would be sufficient to ensure success; so that, if only this attempt were made, many of the most glaring difficulties and disagreements in philosophy would disappear. At all events, philosophers seem, in general, not to make the attempt; and, whether in consequence of this omission or not, they are constantly endeavouring to prove that ‘Yes’ or ‘No’ will answer questions, to which neither answer is correct, owing to the fact that what they have before their minds is not one question, but several, to some of which the true answer is ‘No,’ to others ‘Yes.’
It seems to me that in Ethics, just like in all other philosophical studies, the difficulties and disagreements found throughout its history mostly stem from a very simple issue: the attempt to answer questions without first identifying exactly what question you want to answer. I’m not sure how much this source of confusion would be eliminated if philosophers would try to clarify what question they were addressing before attempting to answer it; the work of analyzing and distinguishing can often be quite challenging, and we might struggle to make the necessary identification even if we genuinely try. However, I believe that in many instances, a determined effort would be enough to achieve clarity; thus, if only this effort were made, many of the most obvious difficulties and disagreements in philosophy would fade away. In any case, philosophers generally seem not to make this effort; and whether this lack of effort is the cause or not, they persistently try to prove that ‘Yes’ or ‘No’ can answer questions for which neither response is correct, because what they are dealing with is not a single question, but multiple ones, to which some require the answer ‘No’ and others ‘Yes.’
I have tried in this book to distinguish clearly two kinds of question, which moral philosophers have always professed to[p. viii] answer, but which, as I have tried to shew, they have almost always confused both with one another and with other questions. These two questions may be expressed, the first in the form: What kind of things ought to exist for their own sakes? the second in the form: What kind of actions ought we to perform? I have tried to shew exactly what it is that we ask about a thing, when we ask whether it ought to exist for its own sake, is good in itself or has intrinsic value; and exactly what it is that we ask about an action, when we ask whether we ought to do it, whether it is a right action or a duty.
In this book, I've aimed to clearly distinguish between two types of questions that moral philosophers have always claimed to answer. However, as I've attempted to demonstrate, they often get these questions mixed up with each other and with other questions. The first question can be framed as: What kinds of things should exist for their own sake? The second question is: What types of actions should we carry out? I've worked to clarify what we’re really asking about something when we question whether it should exist for its own sake, if it’s good in itself, or if it has intrinsic value. Similarly, I've aimed to clarify what we’re inquiring about an action when we ask whether we should perform it, and whether it's the right thing to do or a duty.
But from a clear insight into the nature of these two questions, there appears to me to follow a second most important result: namely, what is the nature of the evidence, by which alone any ethical proposition can be proved or disproved, confirmed or rendered doubtful. Once we recognise the exact meaning of the two questions, I think it also becomes plain exactly what kind of reasons are relevant as arguments for or against any particular answer to them. It becomes plain that, for answers to the first question, no relevant evidence whatever can be adduced: from no other truth, except themselves alone, can it be inferred that they are either true or false. We can guard against error only by taking care, that, when we try to answer a question of this kind, we have before our minds that question only, and not some other or others; but that there is great danger of such errors of confusion I have tried to shew, and also what are the chief precautions by the use of which we may guard against them. As for the second question, it becomes equally plain, that any answer to it is capable of proof or disproof—that, indeed, so many different considerations are relevant to its truth or falsehood, as to make the attainment of probability very difficult, and the attainment of certainty impossible. Nevertheless the kind of evidence, which is both necessary and alone relevant to such proof and disproof, is capable of exact[p. ix] definition. Such evidence must contain propositions of two kinds and of two kinds only: it must consist, in the first place, of truths with regard to the results of the action in question—of causal truths—but it must also contain ethical truths of our first or self-evident class. Many truths of both kinds are necessary to the proof that any action ought to be done; and any other kind of evidence is wholly irrelevant. It follows that, if any ethical philosopher offers for propositions of the first kind any evidence whatever, or if, for propositions of the second kind, he either fails to adduce both causal and ethical truths, or adduces truths that are neither, his reasoning has not the least tendency to establish his conclusions. But not only are his conclusions totally devoid of weight: we have, moreover, reason to suspect him of the error of confusion; since the offering of irrelevant evidence generally indicates that the philosopher who offers it has had before his mind, not the question which he professes to answer, but some other entirely different one. Ethical discussion, hitherto, has perhaps consisted chiefly in reasoning of this totally irrelevant kind.
But from a clear understanding of the nature of these two questions, I think a second, very important conclusion follows: specifically, what type of evidence is required to prove or disprove any ethical proposition, confirming or raising doubt about it. Once we grasp the exact meaning of the two questions, it becomes clear what types of reasons are relevant as arguments for or against each specific answer. It's evident that, for answers to the first question, no relevant evidence can be presented: we cannot infer their truth or falsehood from any other truths besides themselves. We can avoid mistakes only by ensuring that when we attempt to address a question like this, we focus solely on that question and not on any others; however, I’ve shown that there is a significant risk of such confusion, along with the main precautions we can take to prevent it. As for the second question, it’s equally clear that any answer can be proven or disproven—that many different factors are relevant to its truth or falsehood, making it very difficult to achieve probability and impossible to achieve certainty. Nevertheless, the type of evidence that is both necessary and relevant for such proof and disproof can be precisely defined. Such evidence must consist of two kinds of propositions: first, it must contain truths regarding the results of the action in question—causal truths—but it must also include ethical truths of our foundational or self-evident category. Many truths from both categories are necessary to prove that any action should be taken; any other type of evidence is completely irrelevant. Therefore, if any ethical philosopher provides any evidence for propositions of the first kind, or if, for propositions of the second kind, he fails to present both causal and ethical truths or presents truths that are neither, his reasoning has no chance of supporting his conclusions. Not only are his conclusions entirely unsubstantiated, but we also have reason to suspect him of confusion; because the presentation of irrelevant evidence usually indicates that the philosopher has been focused not on the question he claims to answer, but on an entirely different one. Ethical discussions so far have likely been mostly comprised of this completely irrelevant type of reasoning.
One main object of this book may, then, be expressed by slightly changing one of Kant’s famous titles. I have endeavoured to write ‘Prolegomena to any future Ethics that can possibly pretend to be scientific.’ In other words, I have endeavoured to discover what are the fundamental principles of ethical reasoning; and the establishment of these principles, rather than of any conclusions which may be attained by their use, may be regarded as my main object. I have, however, also attempted, in Chapter VI, to present some conclusions, with regard to the proper answer of the question ‘What is good in itself?’ which are very different from any which have commonly been advocated by philosophers. I have tried to define the classes within which all great goods and evils fall; and I have maintained that very many different things are good and evil[p. x] in themselves, and that neither class of things possesses any other property which is both common to all its members and peculiar to them.
One main goal of this book can be expressed by slightly changing one of Kant’s famous titles. I have tried to write ‘Prolegomena to any future Ethics that can genuinely claim to be scientific.’ In other words, I have sought to discover the fundamental principles of ethical reasoning; establishing these principles, rather than any conclusions that may arise from them, is my primary focus. However, I have also attempted, in Chapter VI, to present some conclusions regarding the question ‘What is good in itself?’ that differ significantly from those commonly promoted by philosophers. I have sought to define the categories within which all significant goods and evils fall; and I have argued that many different things are good and evil in themselves, and that neither category of things has any other characteristic that is both common to all its members and unique to them.[p. x]
In order to express the fact that ethical propositions of my first class are incapable of proof or disproof, I have sometimes followed Sidgwick’s usage in calling them ‘Intuitions.’ But I beg it may be noticed that I am not an ‘Intuitionist,’ in the ordinary sense of the term. Sidgwick himself seems never to have been clearly aware of the immense importance of the difference which distinguishes his Intuitionism from the common doctrine, which has generally been called by that name. The Intuitionist proper is distinguished by maintaining that propositions of my second class—propositions which assert that a certain action is right or a duty—are incapable of proof or disproof by any enquiry into the results of such actions. I, on the contrary, am no less anxious to maintain that propositions of this kind are not ‘Intuitions,’ than to maintain that propositions of my first class are Intuitions.
To show that the ethical propositions in my first class can’t be proven or disproven, I sometimes follow Sidgwick’s lead in calling them ‘Intuitions.’ However, I want to clarify that I am not an ‘Intuitionist’ in the usual sense of the word. Sidgwick himself doesn’t seem to have fully recognized how important the distinction is between his Intuitionism and the common view that is usually labeled with that term. A true Intuitionist is characterized by the belief that the propositions in my second class—those that state a particular action is right or a duty—cannot be proven or disproven by examining the consequences of those actions. In contrast, I am equally eager to assert that propositions of this type are not ‘Intuitions,’ just as I assert that propositions in my first class are Intuitions.
Again, I would wish it observed that, when I call such propositions ‘Intuitions,’ I mean merely to assert that they are incapable of proof; I imply nothing whatever as to the manner or origin of our cognition of them. Still less do I imply (as most Intuitionists have done) that any proposition whatever is true, because we cognise it in a particular way or by the exercise of any particular faculty: I hold, on the contrary, that in every way in which it is possible to cognise a true proposition, it is also possible to cognise a false one.
Again, I want to point out that when I refer to such propositions as ‘Intuitions,’ I simply mean that they cannot be proven; I don’t suggest anything about how we know them or where that knowledge comes from. Even less do I suggest (as many Intuitionists have) that any proposition is true because we understand it in a specific way or through a certain ability: I believe, on the contrary, that in every possible way of understanding a true proposition, we can also understand a false one.
When this book had been already completed, I found, in Brentano’s ‘Origin of the Knowledge of Right and Wrong[1],[p. xi]’ opinions far more closely resembling my own, than those of any other ethical writer with whom I am acquainted. Brentano appears to agree with me completely (1) in regarding all ethical propositions as defined by the fact that they predicate a single unique objective concept; (2) in dividing such propositions sharply into the same two kinds; (3) in holding that the first kind are incapable of proof; and (4) with regard to the kind of evidence which is necessary and relevant to the proof of the second kind. But he regards the fundamental ethical concept as being, not the simple one which I denote by ‘good,’ but the complex one which I have taken to define ‘beautiful’; and he does not recognise, but even denies by implication, the principle which I have called the principle of organic unities. In consequence of these two differences, his conclusions as to what things are good in themselves, also differ very materially from mine. He agrees, however, that there are many different goods, and that the love of good and beautiful objects constitutes an important class among them.
When I finished this book, I came across Brentano’s ‘Origin of the Knowledge of Right and Wrong[1],[p. xi]’, and I found his opinions aligned more closely with mine than those of any other ethical writer I know. Brentano seems to completely agree with me (1) in viewing all ethical propositions as defined by the fact that they assert a single unique objective concept; (2) in sharply dividing these propositions into the same two categories; (3) in believing that the first category cannot be proven; and (4) regarding the type of evidence needed and relevant for proving the second category. However, he considers the fundamental ethical concept as not the simple one I refer to as ‘good,’ but the complex one I define as ‘beautiful’; and he does not acknowledge, but even implicitly denies, the principle I call the principle of organic unities. Because of these two differences, his conclusions about what things are good in themselves also differ significantly from mine. He does agree, though, that there are many different goods, and that the love of good and beautiful things is an important category among them.
I wish to refer to one oversight, of which I became aware only when it was too late to correct it, and which may, I am afraid, cause unnecessary trouble to some readers. I have omitted to discuss directly the mutual relations of the several different notions, which are all expressed by the word ‘end.’ The consequences of this omission may perhaps be partially avoided by a reference to my article on ‘Teleology’ in Baldwin’s Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology.
I want to mention one oversight that I realized too late to fix, and I’m afraid it might cause some confusion for readers. I didn’t directly address the relationships between the various ideas that the term ‘end’ represents. The impact of this omission might be somewhat mitigated by referring to my article on ‘Teleology’ in Baldwin’s Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology.
If I were to rewrite my work now, I should make a very different, and I believe that I could make a much better book. But it may be doubted whether, in attempting to satisfy myself, I might not merely render more obscure the ideas which I am most anxious to convey, without a corresponding gain in completeness and accuracy. However that may be, my belief that[p. xii] to publish the book as it stands was probably the best thing I could do, does not prevent me from being painfully aware that it is full of defects.
If I were to rewrite my work now, I would create something very different, and I believe I could write a much better book. But I wonder if, in trying to satisfy myself, I might just make the ideas I'm eager to communicate even more unclear, without actually improving their completeness and accuracy. Regardless, my belief that[p. xii] publishing the book as it is was probably the best decision I could make doesn’t stop me from feeling painfully aware that it has many flaws.
Trinity College, Cambridge.
Trinity College, Cambridge.
August, 1903.
August 1903.
[This book is now reprinted without any alteration whatever, except that a few misprints and grammatical mistakes have been corrected. It is reprinted, because I am still in agreement with its main tendency and conclusions; and it is reprinted without alteration, because I found that, if I were to begin correcting what in it seemed to me to need correction, I could not stop short of rewriting the whole book.
[This book is now reprinted without any changes at all, except for a few corrected typos and grammatical errors. I'm reprinting it because I still agree with its main ideas and conclusions; and I'm reprinting it without changes because I realized that if I started fixing what I thought needed correction, I wouldn't be able to stop without rewriting the entire book.]
G. E. M.]
G. E. M.
Cambridge, 1922.
Cambridge, 1922.
[p. xiii]
[p. xiii]
TABLE OF CONTENTS.
CHAPTER 1. | ||
THE SUBJECT-MATTER OF ETHICS. | ||
A. | ||
SECTION. | PAGE | |
---|---|---|
1. | In order to define Ethics, we must discover what is both common and peculiar to all undoubted ethical judgments; | 1 |
2. | but this is not that they are concerned with human conduct, but that they are concerned with a certain predicate ‘good,’ and its converse ‘bad,’ which may be applied both to conduct and to other things. | 1 |
3. | The subjects of the judgments of a scientific Ethics are not, like those of some studies, ‘particular things’; | 3 |
4. | but it includes all universal judgments which assert the relation of ‘goodness’ to any subject, and hence includes Casuistry. | 3 |
B. | ||
5. | It must, however, enquire not only what things are universally related to goodness, but also, what this predicate, to which they are related, is: | 5 |
6. | and the answer to this question is that it is indefinable | 6 |
7. | or simple: for if by definition be meant the analysis of an object of thought, only complex objects can be defined; | 7 |
8. | and of the three senses in which ‘definition’ can be used, this is the most important. | 8 |
9. | What is thus indefinable is not ‘the good,’ or the whole of that which always possesses the predicate ‘good,’ but this predicate itself. | 8 |
10. | ‘Good,’ then, denotes one unique simple object of thought among innumerable others; but this object has very commonly been identified with some other—a fallacy which may be called ‘the naturalistic fallacy’ | 9 |
[p. xiv]11. | and which reduces what is used as a fundamental principle of Ethics either to a tautology or to a statement about the meaning of a word. | 10 |
12. | The nature of this fallacy is easily recognised; | 12 |
13. | and if it were avoided, it would be plain that the only alternatives to the admission that ‘good’ is indefinable, are either that it is complex or that there is no notion at all peculiar to Ethics—alternatives which can only be refuted by an appeal to inspection, but which can be so refuted. | 15 |
14. | The ‘naturalistic fallacy’ illustrated by Bentham; and the importance of avoiding it pointed out. | 17 |
C. | ||
15. | The relations which ethical judgments assert to hold universally between ‘goodness’ and other things are of two kinds: a thing may be asserted either to be good itself or to be causally related to something else which is itself good—to be ‘good as a means.’ | 21 |
16. | Our investigations of the latter kind of relation cannot hope to establish more than that a certain kind of action will generally be followed by the best possible results; | 22 |
17. | but a relation of the former kind, if true at all, will be true of all cases. All ordinary ethical judgments assert causal relations, but they are commonly treated as if they did not, because the two kinds of relation are not distinguished. | 23 |
D. | ||
18. | The investigation of intrinsic values is complicated by the fact that the value of a whole may be different from the sum of the values of its parts, | 27 |
19. | in which case the part has to the whole a relation, which exhibits an equally important difference from and resemblance to that of means to end. | 29 |
20. | The term ‘organic whole’ might well be used to denote that a whole has this property, since, of the two other properties which it is commonly used to imply, | 30 |
21. | one that of reciprocal causal dependence between parts, has no necessary relation to this one, | 31 |
22. | and the other, upon which most stress has been laid, can be true of no whole whatsoever, being a self-contradictory conception due to confusion. | 33 |
23. | Summary of chapter. | 36 |
[p. xv]CHAPTER 2. | ||
NATURALISTIC ETHICS. | ||
24. | This and the two following chapters will consider certain proposed answers to the second of ethical questions: What is good in itself? These proposed answers are characterised by the facts (1) that they declare some one kind of thing to be alone good in itself; and (2) that they do so, because they suppose this one thing to define the meaning of ‘good.’ | 37 |
25. | Such theories may be divided into two groups (1) Metaphysical, (2) Naturalistic: and the second group may be subdivided into two others, (a) theories which declare some natural object, other than pleasure, to be sole good, (b) Hedonism. The present chapter will deal with (a). | 38 |
26. | Definition of what is meant by ‘Naturalism.’ | 39 |
27. | The common argument that things are good, because they are ‘natural,’ may involve either (1) the false proposition that the ‘normal,’ as such, is good; | 41 |
28. | or (2) the false proposition that the ‘necessary,’ as such, is good. | 44 |
29. | But a systematised appeal to Nature is now most prevalent in connection with the term ‘Evolution.’ An examination of Mr Herbert Spencer’s Ethics will illustrate this form of Naturalism. | 45 |
30. | Darwin’s scientific theory of ‘natural selection,’ which has mainly caused the modern vogue of the term ‘Evolution,’ must be carefully distinguished from certain ideas which are commonly associated with the latter term. | 47 |
31. | Mr Spencer’s connection of Evolution with Ethics seems to shew the influence of the naturalistic fallacy; | 48 |
32. | but Mr Spencer is vague as to the ethical relations of ‘pleasure’ and ‘evolution,’ and his Naturalism may be mainly Naturalistic Hedonism. | 49 |
33. | A discussion of the third chapter of the Data of Ethics serves to illustrate these two points and to shew that Mr Spencer is in utter confusion with regard to the fundamental principles of Ethics. | 51 |
34. | Three possible views as to the relation of Evolution to Ethics are distinguished from the naturalistic view to which it is proposed to confine the name ‘Evolutionistic Ethics.’ On any of these three views the relation would be unimportant, and the ‘Evolutionistic’ view, which makes it important, involves a double fallacy. | 54 |
35. | Summary of chapter. | 58 |
[p. xvi]CHAPTER 3. | ||
HEDONISM. | ||
36. | The prevalence of Hedonism is mainly due to the naturalistic fallacy. | 59 |
37. | Hedonism may be defined as the doctrine that ‘Pleasure is the sole good’: this doctrine has always been held by Hedonists and used by them as a fundamental ethical principle, although it has commonly been confused with others. | 61 |
38. | The method pursued in this chapter will consist in exposing the reasons commonly offered for the truth of Hedonism and in bringing out the reasons, which suffice to shew it untrue, by a criticism of J. S. Mill & H. Sidgwick. | 63 |
A. | ||
39. | Mill declares that ‘Happiness is the only thing desirable as an end,’ and insists that ‘Questions of ultimate ends are not amenable to direct proof’; | 64 |
40. | yet he gives a proof of the first proposition, which consists in (1) the fallacious confusion of ‘desirable’ with ‘desired,’ | 66 |
41. | (2) an attempt to shew that nothing but pleasure is desired. | 67 |
42. | The theory that nothing but pleasure is desired seems largely due to a confusion between the cause and the object of desire: pleasure is certainly not the sole object of desire, and, even if it is always among the causes of desire, that fact would not tempt anyone to think it a good. | 68 |
43. | Mill attempts to reconcile his doctrine that pleasure is the sole object of desire with his admission that other things are desired, by the absurd declaration that what is a means to happiness is ‘part’ of happiness. | 71 |
44. | Summary of Mill’s argument and of my criticism. | 72 |
B. | ||
45. | We must now proceed to consider the principle of Hedonism as an ‘Intuition,’ as which it has been clearly recognised by Prof. Sidgwick alone. That it should be thus incapable of proof is not, in itself, any reason for dissatisfaction. | 74 |
46. | In thus beginning to consider what things are good in themselves, we leave the refutation of Naturalism behind, and enter on the second division of ethical questions. | 76 |
[p. xvii]47. | Mill’s doctrine that some pleasures are superior ‘in quality’ to others implies both (1) that judgments of ends must be ‘intuitions’; | 77 |
48. | and (2) that pleasure is not the sole good. | 79 |
49. | Prof. Sidgwick has avoided these confusions made by Mill: in considering his arguments we shall, therefore, merely consider the question ‘Is pleasure the sole good?’ | 81 |
50. | Prof. Sidgwick first tries to shew that nothing outside of Human Existence can be good. Reasons are given for doubting this. | 81 |
51. | He then goes on to the far more important proposition that no part of Human Existence, except pleasure, is desirable. | 85 |
52. | But pleasure must be distinguished from consciousness of pleasure, and (1) it is plain that, when so distinguished, pleasure is not the sole good; | 87 |
53. | and (2) it may be made equally plain that consciousness of pleasure is not the sole good, if we are equally careful to distinguish it from its usual accompaniments. | 90 |
54. | Of Prof. Sidgwick’s two arguments for the contrary view, the second is equally compatible with the supposition that pleasure is a mere criterion of what is right; | 91 |
55. | and in his first, the appeal to reflective intuition, he fails to put the question clearly (1) in that he does not recognise the principle of organic unities; | 92 |
56. | and (2) in that he fails to emphasize that the agreement, which he has tried to shew, between hedonistic judgments and those of Common Sense, only holds of judgments of means: hedonistic judgments of ends are flagrantly paradoxical. | 94 |
57. | I conclude, then, that a reflective intuition, if proper precautions are taken, will agree with Common Sense that it is absurd to regard mere consciousness of pleasure as the sole good. | 95 |
C. | ||
58. | It remains to consider Egoism and Utilitarianism. It is important to distinguish the former, as the doctrine that ‘my own pleasure is sole good,’ from the doctrine, opposed to Altruism, that to pursue my own pleasure exclusively is right as a means. | 96 |
59. | Egoism proper is utterly untenable, being self-contradictory: it fails to perceive that when I declare a thing to be my own good, I must be declaring it to be good absolutely or else not good at all. | 97 |
[p. xviii]60. | This confusion is further brought out by an examination of Prof. Sidgwick’s contrary view; | 99 |
61. | and it is shewn that, in consequence of this confusion, his representation of ‘the relation of Rational Egoism to Rational Benevolence’ as ‘the profoundest problem of Ethics,’ and his view that a certain hypothesis is required to ‘make Ethics rational,’ are grossly erroneous. | 102 |
62. | The same confusion is involved in the attempt to infer Utilitarianism from Psychological Hedonism, as commonly held, e.g. by Mill. | 104 |
63. | Egoism proper seems also to owe its plausibility to its confusion with Egoism, as a doctrine of means. | 105 |
64. | Certain ambiguities in the conception of Utilitarianism are noticed; and it is pointed out (1) that, as a doctrine of the end to be pursued, it is finally refuted by the refutation of Hedonism, and (2) that, while the arguments most commonly urged in its favour could, at most, only shew it to offer a correct criterion of right action, they are quite insufficient even for this purpose. | 105 |
65. | Summary of chapter. | 108 |
CHAPTER 4. | ||
METAPHYSICAL ETHICS. | ||
A. | ||
66. | The term ‘metaphysical’ is defined as having reference primarily to any object of knowledge which is not a part of Nature—does not exist in time, as an object of perception; but since metaphysicians, not content with pointing out the truth about such entities, have always supposed that what does not exist in Nature, must, at least, exist, the term also has reference to a supposed ‘supersensible reality’: | 110 |
67. | and by ‘metaphysical Ethics’ I mean those systems which maintain or imply that the answer to the question ‘What is good?’ logically depends upon the answer to the question ‘What is the nature of supersensible reality?.’ All such systems obviously involve the same fallacy—the ‘naturalistic fallacy’—by the use of which Naturalism was also defined. | 113 |
68. | Metaphysics, as dealing with a ‘supersensible reality,’ may have a bearing upon practical Ethics (1) if its supersensible reality is conceived as something future, which our actions[p. xix] can affect; and (2) since it will prove that every proposition of practical Ethics is false, if it can shew that an eternal reality is either the only real thing or the only good thing. Most metaphysical writers, believing in a reality of the latter kind, do thus imply the complete falsehood of every practical proposition, although they fail to see that their Metaphysics thus contradicts their Ethics. | 115 |
B. | ||
69. | But the theory, by which I have defined Metaphysical Ethics, is not that Metaphysics has a logical bearing upon the question involved in practical Ethics ‘What effects will my action produce?,’ but that it has such a bearing upon the fundamental ethical question ‘What is good in itself?.’ This theory has been refuted by the proof, in Chap. I, that the naturalistic fallacy is a fallacy: it only remains to discuss certain confusions which seem to have lent it plausibility. | 118 |
70. | One such source of confusion seems to lie in the failure to distinguish between the proposition ‘This is good,’ when it means ‘This existing thing is good,’ and the same proposition, when it means ‘The existence of this kind of thing would be good’; | 118 |
71. | and another seems to lie in the failure to distinguish between that which suggests a truth, or is a cause of our knowing it, and that upon which it logically depends, or which is a reason for believing it: in the former sense fiction has a more important bearing upon Ethics than Metaphysics can have. | 121 |
C. | ||
72. | But a more important source of confusion seems to lie in the supposition that ‘to be good’ is identical with the possession of some supersensible property, which is also involved in the definition of ‘reality.’ | 122 |
73. | One cause of this supposition seems to be the logical prejudice that all propositions are of the most familiar type—that in which subject and predicate are both existents. | 123 |
74. | But ethical propositions cannot be reduced to this type: in particular, they are obviously to be distinguished | 125 |
75. | (1) from Natural Laws; with which one of Kant’s most famous doctrines confuses them, | 126 |
76. | and (2) from Commands; with which they are confused both by Kant and by others. | 127 |
[p. xx]D. | ||
77. | This latter confusion is one of the sources of the prevalent modern doctrine that ‘being good’ is identical with ‘being willed’; but the prevalence of this doctrine seems to be chiefly due to other causes. I shall try to shew with regard to it (1) what are the chief errors which seem to have led to its adoption; and (2) that, apart from it, the Metaphysics of Volition can hardly have the smallest logical bearing upon Ethics. | 128 |
78. | (1) It has been commonly held, since Kant, that ‘goodness’ has the same relation to Will or Feeling, which ‘truth’ or ‘reality’ has to Cognition: that the proper method for Ethics is to discover what is implied in Will or Feeling, just as, according to Kant, the proper method for Metaphysics was to discover what is implied in Cognition. | 129 |
79. | The actual relations between ‘goodness’ and Will or Feeling, from which this false doctrine is inferred, seem to be mainly (a) the causal relation consisting in the fact that it is only by reflection upon the experiences of Will and Feeling that we become aware of ethical distinctions; (b) the facts that a cognition of goodness is perhaps always included in certain kinds of Willing and Feeling, and is generally accompanied by them: | 130 |
80. | but from neither of these psychological facts does it follow that ‘to be good’ is identical with being willed or felt in a certain way: the supposition that it does follow is an instance of the fundamental contradiction of modern Epistemology—the contradiction involved in both distinguishing and identifying the object and the act of Thought, ‘truth’ itself and its supposed criterion: | 131 |
81. | and, once this analogy between Volition and Cognition is accepted, the view that ethical propositions have an essential reference to Will or Feeling, is strengthened by another error with regard to the nature of Cognition—the error of supposing that ‘perception’ denotes merely a certain way of cognising an object, whereas it actually includes the assertion that the object is also true. | 133 |
82. | The argument of the last three §§ is recapitulated; and it is pointed out (1) that Volition and Feeling are not analogous to Cognition, (2) that, even if they were, still ‘to be good’ could not mean ‘to be willed or felt in a certain way.’ | 135 |
83. | (2) If ‘being good’ and ‘being willed’ are not identical, then the latter could only be a criterion of the former; and, in[p. xxi] order to shew that it was so, we should have to establish independently that many things were good—that is to say, we should have to establish most of our ethical conclusions, before the Metaphysics of Volition could possibly give us the smallest assistance. | 137 |
84. | The fact that the metaphysical writers who, like Green, attempt to base Ethics on Volition, do not even attempt this independent investigation, shews that they start from the false assumption that goodness is identical with being willed, and hence that their ethical reasonings have no value whatsoever. | 138 |
85. | Summary of chapter. | 139 |
CHAPTER 5. | ||
ETHICS IN RELATION TO CONDUCT. | ||
86. | The question to be discussed in this chapter must be clearly distinguished from the two questions hitherto discussed, namely (1) What is the nature of the proposition: ‘This is good in itself’? | 142 |
87. | and (2) What things are good in themselves? to which we gave one answer in deciding that pleasure was not the only thing good in itself. | 144 |
88. | In this chapter we shall deal with the third object of ethical enquiry: namely answers to the question ‘What conduct is a means to good results?’ or ‘What ought we to do?’ This is the question of Practical Ethics, and its answer involves an assertion of causal connection. | 146 |
89. | It is shewn that the assertions ‘This action is right’ or ‘is my duty’ are equivalent to the assertion that the total results of the action in question will be the best possible; | 146 |
90. | and the rest of the chapter will deal with certain conclusions, upon which light is thrown by this fact. Of which the first is (1) that Intuitionism is mistaken; since no proposition with regard to duty can be self-evident. | 148 |
91. | (2) It is plain that we cannot hope to prove which among all the actions, which it is possible for us to perform on every occasion, will produce the best total results: to discover what is our ‘duty,’ in this strict sense, is impossible. It may, however, be possible to shew which among the actions, which we are likely to perform, will produce the best results. | 149 |
[p. xxii]92. | The distinction made in the last § is further explained; and it is insisted that all that Ethics has done or can do, is, not to determine absolute duties, but to point out which, among a few of the alternatives, possible under certain circumstances, will have the better results. | 150 |
93. | (3) Even this latter task is immensely difficult, and no adequate proof that the total results of one action are superior to those of another, has ever been given. For (a) we can only calculate actual results within a comparatively near future: we must, therefore, assume that no results of the same action in the infinite future beyond, will reverse the balance—an assumption which perhaps can be, but certainly has not been, justified; | 152 |
94. | and (b) even to decide that, of any two actions, one has a better total result than the other in the immediate future, is very difficult; and it is very improbable, and quite impossible to prove, that any single action is in all cases better as means than its probable alternative. Rules of duty, even in this restricted sense, can only, at most, be general truths. | 154 |
95. | But (c) most of the actions, most universally approved by Common Sense, may perhaps be shewn to be generally better as means than any probable alternative, on the following principles. (1) With regard to some rules it may be shewn that their general observance would be useful in any state of society, where the instincts to preserve and propagate life and to possess property were as strong as they seem always to be; and this utility may be shewn, independently of a right view as to what is good in itself, since the observance is a means to things which are a necessary condition for the attainment of any great goods in considerable quantities. | 155 |
96. | (2) Other rules are such that their general observance can only be shewn to be useful, as means to the preservation of society, under more or less temporary conditions: if any of these are to be proved useful in all societies, this can only be done by shewing their causal relation to things good or evil in themselves, which are not generally recognised to be such. | 158 |
97. | It is plain that rules of class (1) may also be justified by the existence of such temporary conditions as justify those of class (2); and among such temporary conditions must be reckoned the so-called sanctions. | 159 |
98. | In this way, then, it may be possible to prove the general utility, for the present, of those actions, which in our society[p. xxiii] are both generally recognised as duties and generally practised; but it seems very doubtful whether a conclusive case can be established for any proposed change in social custom, without an independent investigation of what things are good or bad in themselves. | 159 |
99. | And (d) if we consider the distinct question of how a single individual should decide to act (α) in cases where the general utility of the action in question is certain, (β) in other cases: there seems reason for thinking that, with regard to (α), where the generally useful rule is also generally observed, he should always conform to it; but these reasons are not conclusive, if either the general observance or the general utility is wanting: | 162 |
100. | and that (β) in all other cases, rules of action should not be followed at all, but the individual should consider what positive goods, he, in his particular circumstances, seems likely to be able to effect, and what evils to avoid. | 164 |
101. | (4) It follows further that the distinction denoted by the terms ‘duty’ and ‘expediency’ is not primarily ethical: when we ask ‘Is this really expedient?’ we are asking precisely the same question as when we ask ‘Is this my duty?,’ viz. ‘Is this a means to the best possible?.’ ‘Duties’ are mainly distinguished by the non-ethical marks (1) that many people are often tempted to avoid them, (2) that their most prominent effects are on others than the agent, (3) that they excite the moral sentiments: so far as they are distinguished by an ethical peculiarity, this is not that they are peculiarly useful to perform, but that they are peculiarly useful to sanction. | 167 |
102. | The distinction between ‘duty’ and ‘interest’ is also, in the main, the same non-ethical distinction: but the term ‘interested’ does also refer to a distinct ethical predicate—that an action is to ‘my interest’ asserts only that it will have the best possible effects of one particular kind, not that its total effects will be the best possible. | 170 |
103. | (5) We may further see that ‘virtues’ are not to be defined as dispositions that are good in themselves: they are not necessarily more than dispositions to perform actions generally good as means, and of these, for the most part, only those classed as ‘duties’ in accordance with section (4). It follows that to decide whether a disposition is or is not ‘virtuous’ involves the difficult causal investigation discussed in section (3); and that what is a virtue in one state of society may not be so in another. | 171 |
[p. xxiv]104. | It follows also that we have no reason to presume, as has commonly been done, that the exercise of virtue in the performance of ‘duties’ is ever good in itself—far less, that it is the sole good: | 173 |
105. | and, if we consider the intrinsic value of such exercise, it will appear (1) that, in most cases, it has no value, and (2) that even the cases, where it has some value, are far from constituting the sole good. The truth of the latter proposition is generally inconsistently implied, even by those who deny it; | 174 |
106. | but in order fairly to decide upon the intrinsic value of virtue, we must distinguish three different kinds of disposition, each of which is commonly so called and has been maintained to be the only kind deserving the name. Thus (a) the mere unconscious ‘habit’ of performing duties, which is the commonest type, has no intrinsic value whatsoever; Christian moralists are right in implying that mere ‘external rightness’ has no intrinsic value, though they are wrong in saying that it is therefore not ‘virtuous,’ since this implies that it has no value even as a means: | 175 |
107. | (b) where virtue consists in a disposition to have, and be moved by, a sentiment of love towards really good consequences of an action and of hatred towards really evil ones, it has some intrinsic value, but its value may vary greatly in degree: | 177 |
108. | finally (c) where virtue consists in ‘conscientiousness,’ i.e. the disposition not to act, in certain cases, until we believe and feel that our action is right, it seems to have some intrinsic value: the value of this feeling has been peculiarly emphasized by Christian Ethics, but it certainly is not, as Kant would lead us to think, either the sole thing of value, or always good even as a means. | 178 |
109. | Summary of chapter. | 180 |
CHAPTER 6. | ||
THE IDEAL. | ||
110. | By an ‘ideal’ state of things may be meant either (1) the Summum Bonum or absolutely best, or (2) the best which the laws of nature allow to exist in this world, or (3) anything greatly good in itself: this chapter will be principally occupied with what is ideal in sense (3)—with answering the fundamental question of Ethics; | 183 |
[p. xxv]111. | but a correct answer to this question is an essential step towards a correct view as to what is ‘ideal’ in senses (1) and (2). | 184 |
112. | In order to obtain a correct answer to the question ‘What is good in itself?’ we must consider what value things would have if they existed absolutely by themselves; | 187 |
113. | and, if we use this method, it is obvious that personal affection and aesthetic enjoyments include by far the greatest goods with which we are acquainted. | 188 |
114. | If we begin by considering I. Aesthetic Enjoyments, it is plain (1) that there is always essential to these some one of a great variety of different emotions, though these emotions may have little value by themselves: | 189 |
115. | and (2) that a cognition of really beautiful qualities is equally essential, and has equally little value by itself. | 190 |
116. | But (3) granted that the appropriate combination of these two elements is always a considerable good and may be a very great one, we may ask whether, where there is added to this a true belief in the existence of the object of the cognition, the whole thus formed is not much more valuable still. | 192 |
117. | I think that this question should be answered in the affirmative; but in order to ensure that this judgment is correct, we must carefully distinguish it | 194 |
118. | from the two judgments (a) that knowledge is valuable as a means, (b) that, where the object of the cognition is itself a good thing, its existence, of course, adds to the value of the whole state of things: | 195 |
119. | if, however, we attempt to avoid being biassed by these two facts, it still seems that mere true belief may be a condition essential to great value. | 197 |
120. | We thus get a third essential constituent of many great goods; and in this way we are able to justify (1) the attribution of value to knowledge, over and above its value as a means, and (2) the intrinsic superiority of the proper appreciation of a real object over the appreciation of an equally valuable object of mere imagination: emotions directed towards real objects may thus, even if the object be inferior, claim equality with the highest imaginative pleasures. | 198 |
121. | Finally (4) with regard to the objects of the cognition which is essential to these good wholes, it is the business of Aesthetics to analyse their nature: it need only be here remarked (1) that, by calling them ‘beautiful,’ we mean that they have this relation to a good whole; and (2) that they are, for the most part, themselves complex wholes, such that the ad[p. xxvi]miring contemplation of the whole greatly exceeds in value the sum of the values of the admiring contemplation of the parts. | 200 |
122. | With regard to II. Personal Affection, the object is here not merely beautiful but also good in itself; it appears, however, that the appreciation of what is thus good in itself, viz. the mental qualities of a person, is certainly, by itself, not so great a good as the whole formed by the combination with it of an appreciation of corporeal beauty; it is doubtful whether it is even so great a good as the mere appreciation of corporeal beauty; but it is certain that the combination of both is a far greater good than either singly. | 203 |
123. | It follows from what has been said that we have every reason to suppose that a cognition of material qualities, and even their existence, is an essential constituent of the Ideal or Summum Bonum: there is only a bare possibility that they are not included in it. | 205 |
124. | It remains to consider positive evils and mixed goods. I. Evils may be divided into three classes, namely | 207 |
125. | (1) evils which consist in the love, or admiration, or enjoyment of what is evil or ugly | 208 |
126. | (2) evils which consist in the hatred or contempt of what is good or beautiful | 211 |
127. | and (3) the consciousness of intense pain: this appears to be the only thing, either greatly good or greatly evil, which does not involve both a cognition and an emotion directed towards its object; and hence it is not analogous to pleasure in respect of its intrinsic value, while it also seems not to add to the vileness of a whole, as a whole, in which it is combined with another bad thing, whereas pleasure does add to the goodness of a whole, in which it is combined with another good thing; | 212 |
128. | but pleasure and pain are completely analogous in this, that pleasure by no means always increases, and pain by no means always decreases, the total value of a whole in which it is included: the converse is often true. | 213 |
129. | In order to consider II. Mixed Goods, we must first distinguish between (1) the value of a whole as a whole, and (2) its value on the whole or total value: (1) = the difference between (2) and the sum of the values of the parts. In view of this distinction, it then appears: | 214 |
130. | (1) That the mere combination of two or more evils is never positively good on the whole, although it may certainly have great intrinsic value as a whole; | 216 |
[p. xxvii]131. | but (2) That a whole which includes a cognition of something evil or ugly may yet be a great positive good on the whole: most virtues, which have any intrinsic value whatever, seem to be of this kind, e.g. (a) courage and compassion, and (b) moral goodness; all these are instances of the hatred or contempt of what is evil or ugly; | 216 |
132. | but there seems no reason to think that, where the evil object exists, the total state of things is ever positively good on the whole, although the existence of the evil may add to its value as a whole. | 219 |
133. | Hence (1) no actually existing evil is necessary to the Ideal, (2) the contemplation of imaginary evils is necessary to it, and (3) where evils already exist, the existence of mixed virtues has a value independent both of its consequences and of the value which it has in common with the proper appreciation of imaginary evils. | 220 |
134. | Concluding remarks. | 222 |
135. | Summary of chapter. | 224 |
[p. 1]
[p. 1]
CHAPTER I.
THE SUBJECT-MATTER OF ETHICS.
Ethics topics.
1. It is very easy to point out some among our every-day judgments, with the truth of which Ethics is undoubtedly concerned. Whenever we say, ‘So and so is a good man,’ or ‘That fellow is a villain’; whenever we ask, ‘What ought I to do?’ or ‘Is it wrong for me to do like this?’; whenever we hazard such remarks as ‘Temperance is a virtue and drunkenness a vice’—it is undoubtedly the business of Ethics to discuss such questions and such statements; to argue what is the true answer when we ask what it is right to do, and to give reasons for thinking that our statements about the character of persons or the morality of actions are true or false. In the vast majority of cases, where we make statements involving any of the terms ‘virtue,’ ‘vice,’ ‘duty,’ ‘right,’ ‘ought,’ ‘good,’ ‘bad,’ we are making ethical judgments; and if we wish to discuss their truth, we shall be discussing a point of Ethics.
1. It is very easy to point out some of our everyday judgments that relate to Ethics. Whenever we say, ‘So and so is a good person,’ or ‘That guy is a villain’; whenever we ask, ‘What should I do?’ or ‘Is it wrong for me to do this?’; whenever we make statements like ‘Being moderate is a virtue, and being drunk is a vice’—it is definitely the role of Ethics to explore these questions and statements; to argue what the correct answer is when we ask what it is right to do, and to provide reasons for believing our judgments about people’s character or the morality of actions are true or false. In most cases, when we use terms like ‘virtue,’ ‘vice,’ ‘duty,’ ‘right,’ ‘ought,’ ‘good,’ ‘bad,’ we’re making ethical judgments; and if we want to discuss their accuracy, we’ll be engaging with a point of Ethics.
So much as this is not disputed; but it falls very far short of defining the province of Ethics. That province may indeed be defined as the whole truth about that which is at the same time common to all such judgments and peculiar to them. But we have still to ask the question: What is it that is thus common and peculiar? And this is a question to which very different answers have been given by ethical philosophers of acknowledged reputation, and none of them, perhaps, completely satisfactory.
This is generally accepted; however, it still doesn’t sufficiently define the scope of Ethics. We can define that scope as the complete truth about what is both common to all such judgments and unique to them. Yet, we still need to ask: What is it that is both common and unique? This question has received various answers from well-known ethical philosophers, and none of them are, perhaps, entirely satisfactory.
2. If we take such examples as those given above, we shall not be far wrong in saying that they are all of them concerned[p. 2] with the question of ‘conduct’—with the question, what, in the conduct of us, human beings, is good, and what is bad, what is right, and what is wrong. For when we say that a man is good, we commonly mean that he acts rightly; when we say that drunkenness is a vice, we commonly mean that to get drunk is a wrong or wicked action. And this discussion of human conduct is, in fact, that with which the name ‘Ethics’ is most intimately associated. It is so associated by derivation; and conduct is undoubtedly by far the commonest and most generally interesting object of ethical judgments.
2. If we consider examples like the ones mentioned above, we can confidently say that they all relate[p. 2] to the topic of ‘conduct’—specifically, what is considered good or bad behavior among us humans, what is right, and what is wrong. When we say someone is a good person, we usually mean they act appropriately; when we say that drunkenness is a vice, we typically mean that getting drunk is a wrong or immoral action. This examination of human behavior is, in fact, what the term ‘Ethics’ is most closely linked to. It is tied to the concept by definition, and conduct is undoubtedly the most common and widely interesting subject of ethical judgments.
Accordingly, we find that many ethical philosophers are disposed to accept as an adequate definition of ‘Ethics’ the statement that it deals with the question what is good or bad in human conduct. They hold that its enquiries are properly confined to ‘conduct’ or to ‘practice’; they hold that the name ‘practical philosophy’ covers all the matter with which it has to do. Now, without discussing the proper meaning of the word (for verbal questions are properly left to the writers of dictionaries and other persons interested in literature; philosophy, as we shall see, has no concern with them), I may say that I intend to use ‘Ethics’ to cover more than this—a usage, for which there is, I think, quite sufficient authority. I am using it to cover an enquiry for which, at all events, there is no other word: the general enquiry into what is good.
Many ethical philosophers tend to define ‘Ethics’ as the study of what is considered good or bad in human behavior. They believe that its discussions should be limited to ‘conduct’ or ‘practice’; they assert that the term ‘practical philosophy’ encompasses all related topics. Without getting into the exact meaning of the word (since those discussions are best left to dictionary writers and others interested in language; philosophy, as we will see, doesn’t engage with them), I want to clarify that I plan to use ‘Ethics’ in a broader sense— a definition that I believe has enough support. I’m using it to refer to an inquiry for which there isn't a better term: the general exploration of what is good.
Ethics is undoubtedly concerned with the question what good conduct is; but, being concerned with this, it obviously does not start at the beginning, unless it is prepared to tell us what is good as well as what is conduct. For ‘good conduct’ is a complex notion: all conduct is not good; for some is certainly bad and some may be indifferent. And on the other hand, other things, beside conduct, may be good; and if they are so, then, ‘good’ denotes some property, that is common to them and conduct; and if we examine good conduct alone of all good things, then we shall be in danger of mistaking for this property, some property which is not shared by those other things: and thus we shall have made a mistake about Ethics even in this limited sense; for we shall not know what good conduct really is. This is a mistake which many writers have actually made,[p. 3] from limiting their enquiry to conduct. And hence I shall try to avoid it by considering first what is good in general; hoping, that if we can arrive at any certainty about this, it will be much easier to settle the question of good conduct: for we all know pretty well what ‘conduct’ is. This, then, is our first question: What is good? and What is bad? and to the discussion of this question (of these questions) I give the name of Ethics, since that science must, at all events, include it.
Ethics is clearly focused on the question of what good behavior is; however, it cannot simply start from scratch unless it aims to define both what is good and what constitutes behavior. The term ‘good behavior’ is complex: not all actions are good; some are definitely bad, and some may be neutral. Additionally, there are other things beyond behavior that can be considered good; if that's the case, then ‘good’ refers to a quality that is common to both those things and behavior. If we only look at good behavior out of all good things, we risk misidentifying this quality as something that may not be shared by other good things, leading to a misunderstanding of Ethics in this narrower sense, as we won’t fully grasp what good behavior actually is. This is a mistake that many writers have made by restricting their focus to behavior. To avoid this, I will first examine what is good in general, hoping that if we can reach any clarity on this, it will be much simpler to determine what good behavior is, since we're all generally familiar with the concept of ‘behavior.’ So, our first questions are: What is good? And what is bad? I will refer to this discussion (of these questions) as Ethics, as that field must certainly encompass it.
3. But this is a question which may have many meanings. If, for example, each of us were to say ‘I am doing good now’ or ‘I had a good dinner yesterday,’ these statements would each of them be some sort of answer to our question, although perhaps a false one. So, too, when A asks B what school he ought to send his son to, B’s answer will certainly be an ethical judgment. And similarly all distribution of praise or blame to any personage or thing that has existed, now exists, or will exist, does give some answer to the question ‘What is good?’ In all such cases some particular thing is judged to be good or bad: the question ‘What?’ is answered by ‘This.’ But this is not the sense in which a scientific Ethics asks the question. Not one, of all the many million answers of this kind, which must be true, can form a part of an ethical system; although that science must contain reasons and principles sufficient for deciding on the truth of all of them. There are far too many persons, things and events in the world, past, present, or to come, for a discussion of their individual merits to be embraced in any science. Ethics, therefore, does not deal at all with facts of this nature, facts that are unique, individual, absolutely particular; facts with which such studies as history, geography, astronomy, are compelled, in part at least, to deal. And, for this reason, it is not the business of the ethical philosopher to give personal advice or exhortation.
3. But this is a question that can have many meanings. For example, if each of us were to say "I'm doing well now" or "I had a great dinner yesterday," these statements would each be a kind of response to our question, even if they might be misleading. Similarly, when A asks B which school he should send his son to, B's answer will definitely involve an ethical judgment. In the same way, any distribution of praise or blame to any person or thing that has existed, currently exists, or will exist provides some answer to the question "What is good?" In these cases, a specific thing is judged as good or bad: the question "What?" is answered by "This." However, this is not how a scientific Ethics approaches the question. None of the countless answers of this kind, which must be true, can be part of an ethical system; although that science must have reasons and principles adequate for determining the truth of them all. There are simply too many people, things, and events in the world, past, present, or future, for a discussion of their individual merits to be included in any science. Ethics, therefore, does not address facts of this nature, which are unique, individual, and completely specific; facts that studies like history, geography, and astronomy are partially required to engage with. For this reason, it is not the role of the ethical philosopher to provide personal advice or encouragement.
4. But there is another meaning which may be given to the question ‘What is good?’ ‘Books are good’ would be an answer to it, though an answer obviously false; for some books are very bad indeed. And ethical judgments of this kind do indeed belong to Ethics; though I shall not deal with many of them. Such is the judgment ‘Pleasure is good’—a judgment,[p. 4] of which Ethics should discuss the truth, although it is not nearly as important as that other judgment, with which we shall be much occupied presently—‘Pleasure alone is good.’ It is judgments of this sort, which are made in such books on Ethics as contain a list of ‘virtues’—in Aristotle’s ‘Ethics’ for example. But it is judgments of precisely the same kind, which form the substance of what is commonly supposed to be a study different from Ethics, and one much less respectable—the study of Casuistry. We may be told that Casuistry differs from Ethics, in that it is much more detailed and particular, Ethics much more general. But it is most important to notice that Casuistry does not deal with anything that is absolutely particular—particular in the only sense in which a perfectly precise line can be drawn between it and what is general. It is not particular in the sense just noticed, the sense in which this book is a particular book, and A’s friend’s advice particular advice. Casuistry may indeed be more particular and Ethics more general; but that means that they differ only in degree and not in kind. And this is universally true of ‘particular’ and ‘general,’ when used in this common, but inaccurate, sense. So far as Ethics allows itself to give lists of virtues or even to name constituents of the Ideal, it is indistinguishable from Casuistry. Both alike deal with what is general, in the sense in which physics and chemistry deal with what is general. Just as chemistry aims at discovering what are the properties of oxygen, wherever it occurs, and not only of this or that particular specimen of oxygen; so Casuistry aims at discovering what actions are good, whenever they occur. In this respect Ethics and Casuistry alike are to be classed with such sciences as physics, chemistry and physiology, in their absolute distinction from those of which history and geography are instances. And it is to be noted that, owing to their detailed nature, casuistical investigations are actually nearer to physics and to chemistry than are the investigations usually assigned to Ethics. For just as physics cannot rest content with the discovery that light is propagated by waves of ether, but must go on to discover the particular nature of the ether-waves corresponding to each several colour; so Casuistry, not content with the general law[p. 5] that charity is a virtue, must attempt to discover the relative merits of every different form of charity. Casuistry forms, therefore, part of the ideal of ethical science: Ethics cannot be complete without it. The defects of Casuistry are not defects of principle; no objection can be taken to its aim and object. It has failed only because it is far too difficult a subject to be treated adequately in our present state of knowledge. The casuist has been unable to distinguish, in the cases which he treats, those elements upon which their value depends. Hence he often thinks two cases to be alike in respect of value, when in reality they are alike only in some other respect. It is to mistakes of this kind that the pernicious influence of such investigations has been due. For Casuistry is the goal of ethical investigation. It cannot be safely attempted at the beginning of our studies, but only at the end.
4. But there’s another interpretation of the question ‘What is good?’ An answer like ‘Books are good’ would fit, even though it’s clearly incorrect; some books are really bad. Ethical judgments like this do belong to Ethics, though I won’t discuss many of them. Take the judgment ‘Pleasure is good’—that’s a statement that Ethics should examine for its truth, yet it’s not nearly as significant as the other judgment we’ll focus on soon—‘Pleasure alone is good.’ Judgments like these appear in various ethics texts with lists of ‘virtues’—for example, Aristotle’s ‘Ethics.’ But similar judgments also make up what many consider a different and less respectable study—Casuistry. We might be told that Casuistry differs from Ethics in that it’s more detailed and specific, while Ethics is broader. However, it’s crucial to recognize that Casuistry doesn’t deal with anything that’s absolutely specific—in the only way that you could draw a clear line between it and what is general. It is not particular in the way this book is a particular book, or in the way that A’s friend’s advice is particular advice. Yes, Casuistry might be more particular, and Ethics more general; but this just means they differ in degree, not in type. This distinction between ‘particular’ and ‘general’ holds true universally when used in this common but misleading way. As long as Ethics provides lists of virtues or identifies components of the Ideal, it’s indistinguishable from Casuistry. Both deal with what is general in the same way that physics and chemistry do. Just as chemistry seeks to discover the properties of oxygen, wherever it occurs, not just in specific examples, Casuistry aims to find out what actions are good, whenever they occur. In this regard, both Ethics and Casuistry belong with sciences like physics, chemistry, and physiology, which are fundamentally different from fields like history and geography. It’s also worth noting that, due to their detailed nature, casuistical investigations are actually closer to physics and chemistry than the typical investigations assigned to Ethics. Just like physics cannot be satisfied with the simple fact that light travels in waves of ether, but must explore the unique nature of the ether waves that correspond to different colors; similarly, Casuistry can’t be satisfied with the general principle that charity is a virtue; it must try to evaluate the merits of every distinct form of charity. Therefore, Casuistry is an essential part of ethical science: Ethics cannot fully exist without it. The shortcomings of Casuistry are not due to a flaw in principle; no objections can be made against its goals and objectives. Its failures arise simply because it’s a challenging subject to address adequately given our current level of knowledge. The casuist often struggles to identify the elements that determine the value of the cases they analyze. As a result, they might mistakenly think two cases are equal in value when they only resemble each other in some other aspect. It’s these kinds of errors that have led to the negative influence of such studies. Ultimately, Casuistry is the pinnacle of ethical investigation. It’s not something that can be effectively tackled at the start of our studies, but only at the end.
5. But our question ‘What is good?’ may have still another meaning. We may, in the third place, mean to ask, not what thing or things are good, but how ‘good’ is to be defined. This is an enquiry which belongs only to Ethics, not to Casuistry; and this is the enquiry which will occupy us first.
5. However, our question "What is good?" might have another meaning. Thirdly, we might be asking not what things are good, but how to define "good." This inquiry belongs solely to Ethics, not to Casuistry; and this is the inquiry that will be our focus first.
It is an enquiry to which most special attention should be directed; since this question, how ‘good’ is to be defined, is the most fundamental question in all Ethics. That which is meant by ‘good’ is, in fact, except its converse ‘bad,’ the only simple object of thought which is peculiar to Ethics. Its definition is, therefore, the most essential point in the definition of Ethics; and moreover a mistake with regard to it entails a far larger number of erroneous ethical judgments than any other. Unless this first question be fully understood, and its true answer clearly recognised, the rest of Ethics is as good as useless from the point of view of systematic knowledge. True ethical judgments, of the two kinds last dealt with, may indeed be made by those who do not know the answer to this question as well as by those who do; and it goes without saying that the two classes of people may lead equally good lives. But it is extremely unlikely that the most general ethical judgments will be equally valid, in the absence of a true answer to this question: I shall presently try to shew that the gravest errors have been largely due to[p. 6] beliefs in a false answer. And, in any case, it is impossible that, till the answer to this question be known, any one should know what is the evidence for any ethical judgment whatsoever. But the main object of Ethics, as a systematic science, is to give correct reasons for thinking that this or that is good; and, unless this question be answered, such reasons cannot be given. Even, therefore, apart from the fact that a false answer leads to false conclusions, the present enquiry is a most necessary and important part of the science of Ethics.
This is an inquiry that deserves significant attention because figuring out how to define “good” is the most fundamental question in all of Ethics. What we mean by “good” is actually, aside from its opposite “bad,” the only simple concept that’s specific to Ethics. Its definition is, therefore, the key aspect of what Ethics is all about; and any misunderstanding regarding it leads to many more incorrect ethical judgments than any other issue. If we don't fully understand this initial question and recognize its true answer, the rest of Ethics becomes pretty much useless from a systematic knowledge perspective. True ethical judgments, of the two types just discussed, can indeed be made by individuals who don't know the answer to this question as well as by those who do; it's obvious that both groups can lead equally good lives. However, it’s very unlikely that the most general ethical judgments will be equally valid without a true answer to this question. I'll soon demonstrate that many serious errors have resulted from beliefs in a false answer. Plus, until we know the answer to this question, no one can understand what the evidence is for any ethical judgment at all. The main goal of Ethics, as a systematic science, is to provide correct reasons for believing that something is good; and without answering this question, those reasons can't be established. So, aside from the fact that a false answer leads to false conclusions, this inquiry is a crucial and essential part of the science of Ethics.
6. What, then, is good? How is good to be defined? Now, it may be thought that this is a verbal question. A definition does indeed often mean the expressing of one word’s meaning in other words. But this is not the sort of definition I am asking for. Such a definition can never be of ultimate importance in any study except lexicography. If I wanted that kind of definition I should have to consider in the first place how people generally used the word ‘good’; but my business is not with its proper usage, as established by custom. I should, indeed, be foolish, if I tried to use it for something which it did not usually denote: if, for instance, I were to announce that, whenever I used the word ‘good,’ I must be understood to be thinking of that object which is usually denoted by the word ‘table.’ I shall, therefore, use the word in the sense in which I think it is ordinarily used; but at the same time I am not anxious to discuss whether I am right in thinking that it is so used. My business is solely with that object or idea, which I hold, rightly or wrongly, that the word is generally used to stand for. What I want to discover is the nature of that object or idea, and about this I am extremely anxious to arrive at an agreement.
6. So, what is good? How should we define good? It might seem like this is just a question of wording. A definition often means explaining one word’s meaning using other words. But that’s not the definition I’m looking for. That kind of definition is only really important in dictionaries. If I wanted that kind of definition, I’d first need to look at how people generally use the word ‘good’; however, I'm not focused on its proper usage as defined by tradition. It would be silly for me to use it to mean something it doesn’t usually refer to. For example, if I said that every time I used the word ‘good,’ I actually meant ‘table.’ So, I will use the word in the way I believe it is commonly used; but I’m not concerned with debating whether I’m right about that. I’m solely focused on the object or idea that I believe the word typically represents. My goal is to understand the nature of that object or idea, and I’m very eager to reach a consensus on it.
But, if we understand the question in this sense, my answer to it may seem a very disappointing one. If I am asked ‘What is good?’ my answer is that good is good, and that is the end of the matter. Or if I am asked ‘How is good to be defined?’ my answer is that it cannot be defined, and that is all I have to say about it. But disappointing as these answers may appear, they are of the very last importance. To readers who are familiar with philosophic terminology, I can express their im[p. 7]portance by saying that they amount to this: That propositions about the good are all of them synthetic and never analytic; and that is plainly no trivial matter. And the same thing may be expressed more popularly, by saying that, if I am right, then nobody can foist upon us such an axiom as that ‘Pleasure is the only good’ or that ‘The good is the desired’ on the pretence that this is ‘the very meaning of the word.’
But if we understand the question this way, my answer might seem really disappointing. If someone asks me, “What is good?” my answer is simply that good is good, and that’s the end of it. Or if I’m asked, “How should we define good?” my response is that it can't be defined, and that’s all I have to say about it. But as disappointing as these answers might seem, they are extremely important. For readers who are familiar with philosophical language, I can put their importance this way: All statements about what is good are synthetic rather than analytic, and that’s definitely not a trivial issue. We can also say more commonly, that if I'm correct, then no one can impose an idea on us like “Pleasure is the only good” or “The good is what is desired,” claiming this is simply “the very meaning of the word.”
7. Let us, then, consider this position. My point is that ‘good’ is a simple notion, just as ‘yellow’ is a simple notion; that, just as you cannot, by any manner of means, explain to any one who does not already know it, what yellow is, so you cannot explain what good is. Definitions of the kind that I was asking for, definitions which describe the real nature of the object or notion denoted by a word, and which do not merely tell us what the word is used to mean, are only possible when the object or notion in question is something complex. You can give a definition of a horse, because a horse has many different properties and qualities, all of which you can enumerate. But when you have enumerated them all, when you have reduced a horse to his simplest terms, then you can no longer define those terms. They are simply something which you think of or perceive, and to any one who cannot think of or perceive them, you can never, by any definition, make their nature known. It may perhaps be objected to this that we are able to describe to others, objects which they have never seen or thought of. We can, for instance, make a man understand what a chimaera is, although he has never heard of one or seen one. You can tell him that it is an animal with a lioness’s head and body, with a goat’s head growing from the middle of its back, and with a snake in place of a tail. But here the object which you are describing is a complex object; it is entirely composed of parts, with which we are all perfectly familiar—a snake, a goat, a lioness; and we know, too, the manner in which those parts are to be put together, because we know what is meant by the middle of a lioness’s back, and where her tail is wont to grow. And so it is with all objects, not previously known, which we are able to define: they are all complex; all composed of parts, which may themselves, in the[p. 8] first instance, be capable of similar definition, but which must in the end be reducible to simplest parts, which can no longer be defined. But yellow and good, we say, are not complex: they are notions of that simple kind, out of which definitions are composed and with which the power of further defining ceases.
7. Let's consider this idea. My point is that ‘good’ is a straightforward concept, just like ‘yellow’ is a straightforward concept; just as you can't explain to someone who doesn't already know it what yellow is, you also can't explain what good is. The kind of definitions I was looking for—definitions that describe the true nature of the object or idea that a word represents, rather than just telling us what the word usually means—are only possible when the object or idea is something complex. You can define a horse because a horse has many different characteristics and qualities that you can list. But once you've listed them all, once you've broken a horse down to its simplest elements, you can no longer define those elements. They are simply things that you think of or perceive, and to anyone who can't visualize or understand them, you can never convey their nature through any definition. Some might argue against this, saying that we can describe to others objects they have never seen or thought of. For example, we can explain what a chimera is to someone who has never heard of one or seen one. You can tell him it's an animal with a lioness's head and body, a goat's head in the middle of its back, and a snake for a tail. But in this case, the object being described is complex; it consists entirely of parts we all know well—a snake, a goat, a lioness—and we also understand how those parts fit together, because we know what the middle of a lioness's back is and where her tail grows. This applies to all previously unknown objects that we can define: they are all complex, made up of parts that may themselves be capable of similar definitions, but ultimately must be reducible to simpler components that can no longer be defined. But we say that yellow and good are not complex; they are straightforward concepts that form the basis of definitions, and the ability to define further stops there.
8. When we say, as Webster says, ‘The definition of horse is “A hoofed quadruped of the genus Equus,”’ we may, in fact, mean three different things. (1) We may mean merely: ‘When I say “horse,” you are to understand that I am talking about a hoofed quadruped of the genus Equus.’ This might be called the arbitrary verbal definition: and I do not mean that good is indefinable in that sense. (2) We may mean, as Webster ought to mean: ‘When most English people say “horse,” they mean a hoofed quadruped of the genus Equus.’ This may be called the verbal definition proper, and I do not say that good is indefinable in this sense either; for it is certainly possible to discover how people use a word: otherwise, we could never have known that ‘good’ may be translated by ‘gut’ in German and by ‘bon’ in French. But (3) we may, when we define horse, mean something much more important. We may mean that a certain object, which we all of us know, is composed in a certain manner: that it has four legs, a head, a heart, a liver, etc., etc., all of them arranged in definite relations to one another. It is in this sense that I deny good to be definable. I say that it is not composed of any parts, which we can substitute for it in our minds when we are thinking of it. We might think just as clearly and correctly about a horse, if we thought of all its parts and their arrangement instead of thinking of the whole: we could, I say, think how a horse differed from a donkey just as well, just as truly, in this way, as now we do, only not so easily; but there is nothing whatsoever which we could so substitute for good; and that is what I mean, when I say that good is indefinable.
8. When we say, as Webster states, ‘The definition of horse is “A hoofed quadruped of the genus Equus,”’ we might actually mean three different things. (1) We could mean simply: ‘When I say “horse,” you should understand that I'm talking about a hoofed quadruped of the genus Equus.’ This could be called the arbitrary verbal definition, and I don't mean that good is indefinable in that sense. (2) We might mean, as Webster should mean: ‘When most English speakers say “horse,” they refer to a hoofed quadruped of the genus Equus.’ This could be called the proper verbal definition, and I’m not saying good is indefinable in this sense either; it’s certainly possible to figure out how people use a word; otherwise, we’d never know that ‘good’ can be translated as ‘gut’ in German and ‘bon’ in French. But (3) when we define horse, we may mean something much deeper. We might mean that a certain object we all recognize has a specific makeup: that it has four legs, a head, a heart, a liver, etc., all arranged in definite relationships to one another. It’s in this sense that I argue good is indefinable. I claim that it isn’t made up of any parts that we can substitute in our minds when we think about it. We could think just as clearly and accurately about a horse by considering all its parts and their arrangement instead of the whole: we could, I say, understand how a horse is different from a donkey just as well, just as truly, in this way, although not as easily; but there is absolutely nothing we could substitute for good in that way; and that’s what I mean when I say that good is indefinable.
9. But I am afraid I have still not removed the chief difficulty which may prevent acceptance of the proposition that good is indefinable. I do not mean to say that the good, that which is good, is thus indefinable; if I did think so, I should not[p. 9] be writing on Ethics, for my main object is to help towards discovering that definition. It is just because I think there will be less risk of error in our search for a definition of ‘the good,’ that I am now insisting that good is indefinable. I must try to explain the difference between these two. I suppose it may be granted that ‘good’ is an adjective. Well ‘the good,’ ‘that which is good,’ must therefore be the substantive to which the adjective ‘good’ will apply: it must be the whole of that to which the adjective will apply, and the adjective must always truly apply to it. But if it is that to which the adjective will apply, it must be something different from that adjective itself; and the whole of that something different, whatever it is, will be our definition of the good. Now it may be that this something will have other adjectives, beside ‘good,’ that will apply to it. It may be full of pleasure, for example; it may be intelligent: and if these two adjectives are really part of its definition, then it will certainly be true, that pleasure and intelligence are good. And many people appear to think that, if we say ‘Pleasure and intelligence are good,’ or if we say ‘Only pleasure and intelligence are good,’ we are defining ‘good.’ Well, I cannot deny that propositions of this nature may sometimes be called definitions; I do not know well enough how the word is generally used to decide upon this point. I only wish it to be understood that that is not what I mean when I say there is no possible definition of good, and that I shall not mean this if I use the word again. I do most fully believe that some true proposition of the form ‘Intelligence is good and intelligence alone is good’ can be found; if none could be found, our definition of the good would be impossible. As it is, I believe the good to be definable; and yet I still say that good itself is indefinable.
9. But I’m afraid I still haven’t addressed the main challenge that might stop us from accepting the idea that good is indefinable. I’m not saying that the good, or what is good, is indefinable; if I believed that, I wouldn’t be writing about Ethics, since my main goal is to help discover that definition. It's precisely because I think there’s less chance of making a mistake in our quest for a definition of ‘the good’ that I’m insisting good is indefinable. I need to clarify the difference between these two concepts. I think we can agree that ‘good’ is an adjective. So, ‘the good’ or ‘that which is good’ must be the noun that the adjective ‘good’ describes: it has to be the entirety of what the adjective applies to, and the adjective must always truly apply to it. But if it’s what the adjective describes, it has to be something different from the adjective itself; and the entirety of that different thing, whatever it may be, will be our definition of the good. Now, this something might have other adjectives besides ‘good’ that describe it. For instance, it might be full of pleasure; it might be intelligent: and if these two adjectives are truly part of its definition, then it would certainly follow that pleasure and intelligence are good. Many people seem to think that if we say ‘Pleasure and intelligence are good,’ or ‘Only pleasure and intelligence are good,’ we are defining ‘good.’ Well, I can’t deny that statements like these might sometimes be referred to as definitions; I’m not sure enough about how the word is generally used to settle this. I just want to make it clear that this isn’t what I mean when I say there’s no possible definition of good, and I won’t mean this if I use the word again. I definitely believe that we can find a true statement in the form ‘Intelligence is good and intelligence alone is good’; if we couldn’t, defining the good would be impossible. As it stands, I believe the good is definable; yet I still insist that good itself is indefinable.
10. ‘Good,’ then, if we mean by it that quality which we assert to belong to a thing, when we say that the thing is good, is incapable of any definition, in the most important sense of that word. The most important sense of ‘definition’ is that in which a definition states what are the parts which invariably compose a certain whole; and in this sense ‘good’ has no definition because it is simple and has no parts. It is one of[p. 10] those innumerable objects of thought which are themselves incapable of definition, because they are the ultimate terms by reference to which whatever is capable of definition must be defined. That there must be an indefinite number of such terms is obvious, on reflection; since we cannot define anything except by an analysis, which, when carried as far as it will go, refers us to something, which is simply different from anything else, and which by that ultimate difference explains the peculiarity of the whole which we are defining: for every whole contains some parts which are common to other wholes also. There is, therefore, no intrinsic difficulty in the contention that ‘good’ denotes a simple and indefinable quality. There are many other instances of such qualities.
10. ‘Good,’ then, if we mean the quality we claim belongs to something when we call it good, can't really be defined in the most important sense of that word. The most important sense of ‘definition’ is when a definition specifies the parts that always make up a certain whole; and in this sense, ‘good’ can’t be defined because it is simple and has no parts. It is one of[p. 10] those countless concepts that can't be defined because they are the ultimate terms by which anything that can be defined must be described. It’s clear, on reflection, that there must be an endless number of such terms; since we can’t define anything without analysis, which, when pushed to its limits, leads us to something that is simply different from anything else, and that ultimate difference clarifies the uniqueness of the whole we are defining: every whole contains some parts that overlap with other wholes as well. So, there’s no real difficulty in arguing that ‘good’ represents a simple and indefinable quality. There are many other examples of such qualities.
Consider yellow, for example. We may try to define it, by describing its physical equivalent; we may state what kind of light-vibrations must stimulate the normal eye, in order that we may perceive it. But a moment’s reflection is sufficient to shew that those light-vibrations are not themselves what we mean by yellow. They are not what we perceive. Indeed we should never have been able to discover their existence, unless we had first been struck by the patent difference of quality between the different colours. The most we can be entitled to say of those vibrations is that they are what corresponds in space to the yellow which we actually perceive.
Consider yellow, for example. We might try to define it by describing its physical equivalent; we might explain what type of light vibrations need to stimulate a normal eye for us to see it. But a moment's thought makes it clear that those light vibrations are not what we mean by yellow. They are not what we actually perceive. In fact, we would never have discovered their existence unless we were first struck by the obvious difference in quality between the various colors. The most we can claim about those vibrations is that they are what corresponds in space to the yellow that we actually perceive.
Yet a mistake of this simple kind has commonly been made about ‘good.’ It may be true that all things which are good are also something else, just as it is true that all things which are yellow produce a certain kind of vibration in the light. And it is a fact, that Ethics aims at discovering what are those other properties belonging to all things which are good. But far too many philosophers have thought that when they named those other properties they were actually defining good; that these properties, in fact, were simply not ‘other,’ but absolutely and entirely the same with goodness. This view I propose to call the ‘naturalistic fallacy’ and of it I shall now endeavour to dispose.
Yet a simple mistake like this is commonly made about 'good.' It may be true that everything good is also something else, just as it’s true that all things yellow produce a certain kind of vibration in light. And it's a fact that ethics aims to discover what those other properties are that belong to everything good. However, way too many philosophers have thought that when they identified those other properties, they were actually defining goodness; that these properties were not 'other' but were completely and totally the same as goodness. I propose to call this view the 'naturalistic fallacy,' and I will now attempt to address it.
11. Let us consider what it is such philosophers say. And first it is to be noticed that they do not agree among themselves.[p. 11] They not only say that they are right as to what good is, but they endeavour to prove that other people who say that it is something else, are wrong. One, for instance, will affirm that good is pleasure, another, perhaps, that good is that which is desired; and each of these will argue eagerly to prove that the other is wrong. But how is that possible? One of them says that good is nothing but the object of desire, and at the same time tries to prove that it is not pleasure. But from his first assertion, that good just means the object of desire, one of two things must follow as regards his proof:
11. Let's examine what these philosophers say. First, it's important to note that they don't agree with each other.[p. 11] They not only claim to be right about what goodness is, but they also try to show that those who argue it’s something else are wrong. For example, one might insist that good is pleasure, while another might argue that good is whatever is desired; each of them will passionately argue to prove the other wrong. But how can that be? One claims that good is strictly the object of desire, yet still attempts to prove it is not pleasure. From this initial assertion that good just means the object of desire, one of two things has to follow regarding his proof:
(1) He may be trying to prove that the object of desire is not pleasure. But, if this be all, where is his Ethics? The position he is maintaining is merely a psychological one. Desire is something which occurs in our minds, and pleasure is something else which so occurs; and our would-be ethical philosopher is merely holding that the latter is not the object of the former. But what has that to do with the question in dispute? His opponent held the ethical proposition that pleasure was the good, and although he should prove a million times over the psychological proposition that pleasure is not the object of desire, he is no nearer proving his opponent to be wrong. The position is like this. One man says a triangle is a circle: another replies ‘A triangle is a straight line, and I will prove to you that I am right: for’ (this is the only argument) ‘a straight line is not a circle.’ ‘That is quite true,’ the other may reply; ‘but nevertheless a triangle is a circle, and you have said nothing whatever to prove the contrary. What is proved is that one of us is wrong, for we agree that a triangle cannot be both a straight line and a circle: but which is wrong, there can be no earthly means of proving, since you define triangle as straight line and I define it as circle.’—Well, that is one alternative which any naturalistic Ethics has to face; if good is defined as something else, it is then impossible either to prove that any other definition is wrong or even to deny such definition.
(1) He might be trying to show that what we really desire isn't pleasure. But if that's the case, where's his Ethics? His argument is purely psychological. Desire happens in our minds, and pleasure is something different that also occurs in our minds; the ethical philosopher is just saying that pleasure isn't what we desire. But what does that have to do with the main argument? His opponent claims that pleasure is the good, and even if he proves a million times that pleasure isn’t what we desire, it doesn't get him any closer to proving his opponent wrong. The situation is like this: One person says a triangle is a circle, while another responds, “A triangle is a straight line, and I’ll show you I’m right: because” (this is his only argument), “a straight line isn’t a circle.” The other might agree, “That’s true, but a triangle is still a circle, and you haven't said anything to prove otherwise. What’s clear is that one of us is mistaken because we both agree a triangle can't be both a straight line and a circle. However, there’s no way to determine who is wrong, since you define a triangle as a straight line and I define it as a circle.” —Well, that’s one challenge any naturalistic Ethics has to confront; if good is defined as something else, then it’s impossible to prove that any other definition is wrong or even to dismiss such a definition.
(2) The other alternative will scarcely be more welcome. It is that the discussion is after all a verbal one. When A says ‘Good means pleasant’ and B says ‘Good means desired,’ they may merely wish to assert that most people have used the word[p. 12] for what is pleasant and for what is desired respectively. And this is quite an interesting subject for discussion: only it is not a whit more an ethical discussion than the last was. Nor do I think that any exponent of naturalistic Ethics would be willing to allow that this was all he meant. They are all so anxious to persuade us that what they call the good is what we really ought to do. ‘Do, pray, act so, because the word “good” is generally used to denote actions of this nature’: such, on this view, would be the substance of their teaching. And in so far as they tell us how we ought to act, their teaching is truly ethical, as they mean it to be. But how perfectly absurd is the reason they would give for it! ‘You are to do this, because most people use a certain word to denote conduct such as this.’ ‘You are to say the thing which is not, because most people call it lying.’ That is an argument just as good!—My dear sirs, what we want to know from you as ethical teachers, is not how people use a word; it is not even, what kind of actions they approve, which the use of this word ‘good’ may certainly imply: what we want to know is simply what is good. We may indeed agree that what most people do think good, is actually so; we shall at all events be glad to know their opinions: but when we say their opinions about what is good, we do mean what we say; we do not care whether they call that thing which they mean ‘horse’ or ‘table’ or ‘chair,’ ‘gut’ or ‘bon’ or ‘ἀγαθός’; we want to know what it is that they so call. When they say ‘Pleasure is good,’ we cannot believe that they merely mean ‘Pleasure is pleasure’ and nothing more than that.
(2) The other option won't be much more welcomed. It's that the discussion is, after all, just a verbal one. When A says "Good means pleasant" and B says "Good means desired," they might just be trying to point out that most people have used the word[p. 12] to mean what is pleasant and what is desired, respectively. And this is an interesting topic for discussion, but it’s not really any more ethical than the last one was. I also don't think any advocate of naturalistic Ethics would agree that this is all they meant. They all seem eager to convince us that what they call the good is what we should really do. "Please act this way because the word 'good' is generally applied to actions like this": that would be the gist of their teaching, according to this perspective. And to the extent that they tell us how we should act, their guidance is truly ethical, as they intend it to be. But how completely ridiculous is the reasoning they would provide for it! "You should do this because most people use a certain word to describe conduct like this." "You are to say something that isn't true because most people call it lying." That’s just as valid!—My dear sirs, what we want to learn from you as ethical teachers isn't how people use a word; it’s not even about what kind of actions they approve of, which the use of the word "good" may suggest: what we really want to know is simply what is good. We might agree that what most people think is good actually is; we'll certainly be interested in knowing their opinions. But when we refer to their opinions on what is good, we mean just that; we don't care whether they label what they mean as "horse" or "table" or "chair," "gut" or "bon" or "ἀγαθός"; we want to know what it is that they are referring to. When they say "Pleasure is good," we can’t believe they just mean "Pleasure is pleasure" and nothing more than that.
12. Suppose a man says ‘I am pleased’; and suppose that is not a lie or a mistake but the truth. Well, if it is true, what does that mean? It means that his mind, a certain definite mind, distinguished by certain definite marks from all others, has at this moment a certain definite feeling called pleasure. ‘Pleased’ means nothing but having pleasure, and though we may be more pleased or less pleased, and even, we may admit for the present, have one or another kind of pleasure; yet in so far as it is pleasure we have, whether there be more or less of it, and whether it be of one kind or another, what we have is[p. 13] one definite thing, absolutely indefinable, some one thing that is the same in all the various degrees and in all the various kinds of it that there may be. We may be able to say how it is related to other things: that, for example, it is in the mind, that it causes desire, that we are conscious of it, etc., etc. We can, I say, describe its relations to other things, but define it we can not. And if anybody tried to define pleasure for us as being any other natural object; if anybody were to say, for instance, that pleasure means the sensation of red, and were to proceed to deduce from that that pleasure is a colour, we should be entitled to laugh at him and to distrust his future statements about pleasure. Well, that would be the same fallacy which I have called the naturalistic fallacy. That ‘pleased’ does not mean ‘having the sensation of red,’ or anything else whatever, does not prevent us from understanding what it does mean. It is enough for us to know that ‘pleased’ does mean ‘having the sensation of pleasure,’ and though pleasure is absolutely indefinable, though pleasure is pleasure and nothing else whatever, yet we feel no difficulty in saying that we are pleased. The reason is, of course, that when I say ‘I am pleased,’ I do not mean that ‘I’ am the same thing as ‘having pleasure.’ And similarly no difficulty need be found in my saying that ‘pleasure is good’ and yet not meaning that ‘pleasure’ is the same thing as ‘good,’ that pleasure means good, and that good means pleasure. If I were to imagine that when I said ‘I am pleased,’ I meant that I was exactly the same thing as ‘pleased,’ I should not indeed call that a naturalistic fallacy, although it would be the same fallacy as I have called naturalistic with reference to Ethics. The reason of this is obvious enough. When a man confuses two natural objects with one another, defining the one, by the other, if for instance, he confuses himself, who is one natural object, with ‘pleased’ or with ‘pleasure’ which are others, then there is no reason to call the fallacy naturalistic. But if he confuses ‘good,’ which is not in the same sense a natural object, with any natural object whatever, then there is a reason for calling that a naturalistic fallacy; its being made with regard to ‘good’ marks it as something quite specific, and this specific mistake deserves a name because it is so common.[p. 14] As for the reasons why good is not to be considered a natural object, they may be reserved for discussion in another place. But, for the present, it is sufficient to notice this: Even if it were a natural object, that would not alter the nature of the fallacy nor diminish its importance one whit. All that I have said about it would remain quite equally true: only the name which I have called it would not be so appropriate as I think it is. And I do not care about the name: what I do care about is the fallacy. It does not matter what we call it, provided we recognise it when we meet with it. It is to be met with in almost every book on Ethics; and yet it is not recognised: and that is why it is necessary to multiply illustrations of it, and convenient to give it a name. It is a very simple fallacy indeed. When we say that an orange is yellow, we do not think our statement binds us to hold that ‘orange’ means nothing else than ‘yellow,’ or that nothing can be yellow but an orange. Supposing the orange is also sweet! Does that bind us to say that ‘sweet’ is exactly the same thing as ‘yellow,’ that ‘sweet’ must be defined as ‘yellow’? And supposing it be recognised that ‘yellow’ just means ‘yellow’ and nothing else whatever, does that make it any more difficult to hold that oranges are yellow? Most certainly it does not: on the contrary, it would be absolutely meaningless to say that oranges were yellow, unless yellow did in the end mean just ‘yellow’ and nothing else whatever—unless it was absolutely indefinable. We should not get any very clear notion about things, which are yellow—we should not get very far with our science, if we were bound to hold that everything which was yellow, meant exactly the same thing as yellow. We should find we had to hold that an orange was exactly the same thing as a stool, a piece of paper, a lemon, anything you like. We could prove any number of absurdities; but should we be the nearer to the truth? Why, then, should it be different with ‘good’? Why, if good is good and indefinable, should I be held to deny that pleasure is good? Is there any difficulty in holding both to be true at once? On the contrary, there is no meaning in saying that pleasure is good, unless good is something different from pleasure. It is absolutely useless, so far as Ethics is concerned, to prove, as Mr Spencer[p. 15] tries to do, that increase of pleasure coincides with increase of life, unless good means something different from either life or pleasure. He might just as well try to prove that an orange is yellow by shewing that it always is wrapped up in paper.
12. Imagine a guy says, “I’m pleased”; and let’s say that's not a lie or a mistake, but the truth. If that's true, what does it mean? It means that his mind, which is a specific mind distinguished by certain clear traits from all others, is currently experiencing a specific feeling called pleasure. ‘Pleased’ simply means having pleasure, and while we might feel more or less pleased, or even different types of pleasure, what we have, at the core, is one distinct thing—something that is absolutely indefinable, yet the same across all its various levels and forms. We might explain how it relates to other things: for example, that it exists in the mind, that it sparks desire, that we are aware of it, and so on. We can talk about its relations to other things, but we cannot define it. If someone tried to define pleasure in terms of another natural object, like claiming pleasure means the sensation of red and then arguing that pleasure is a color, we would be right to laugh at him and doubt his future claims about pleasure. That would be the same mistake I call the naturalistic fallacy. The fact that 'pleased' doesn't mean 'having the sensation of red' or anything else doesn't stop us from understanding what it does mean. It’s enough for us to know that ‘pleased’ means ‘having the sensation of pleasure’; and even though pleasure is totally indefinable, and pleasure is simply pleasure and nothing else, we have no trouble saying we are pleased. The reason is that when I say “I’m pleased,” I do not mean that 'I' am the same as 'having pleasure.' Similarly, there's no issue with me saying “pleasure is good” while not meaning that 'pleasure' is the same as 'good,' or that pleasure means good, and good means pleasure. If I thought that saying “I’m pleased” meant I was exactly the same as 'pleased,' I wouldn’t call that a naturalistic fallacy, even though it reflects the same mistake I’ve referred to as naturalistic regarding Ethics. This is quite clear. When someone confuses two natural objects with each other, defining one by the other—for example, if he confuses himself, who is one natural object, with 'pleased' or 'pleasure,' which are others—there's no reason to label that a naturalistic fallacy. However, if he confuses 'good,' which isn’t considered in the same way a natural object, with any natural object at all, then there's reason to call that a naturalistic fallacy; the fact that it concerns 'good' makes it something specific, and this specific mistake deserves a name because it's so common.[p. 14] As for why good shouldn't be viewed as a natural object, that's a topic for another time. For now, it’s enough to note this: Even if it were a natural object, it wouldn’t change the nature of the fallacy or lessen its significance one bit. Everything I’ve said about it would still hold true; the only difference would be that the name I’ve given it would not be as fitting as I think it is. I don’t care about the name; what matters to me is the fallacy. It doesn’t matter what we call it as long as we recognize it when we encounter it. It appears in almost every book on Ethics, yet it often goes unrecognized; that's why it's necessary to provide multiple examples of it, and it's helpful to have a name for it. It’s a very simple mistake. When we say an orange is yellow, we don’t assume that this means ‘orange’ can only mean ‘yellow,’ or that only oranges can be yellow. What if the orange is also sweet? Does that mean 'sweet' is the same as 'yellow,' or that 'sweet' must be defined as 'yellow'? Even if we recognize that 'yellow' just means 'yellow' and nothing else, does that make it harder to say oranges are yellow? Absolutely not; in fact, it would be pointless to say oranges are yellow if 'yellow' didn’t just mean 'yellow' and nothing else—if it were completely indefinable. We wouldn’t have a clear understanding of things that are yellow, and we wouldn’t get very far with our science, if we insisted that everything yellow means exactly the same thing as yellow. We’d end up saying that an orange is exactly the same thing as a stool, a piece of paper, a lemon, or anything else. We could demonstrate countless absurdities, but would that bring us closer to the truth? So why should it be any different with 'good'? If good is good and indefinable, why should I have to deny that pleasure is good? Is there a problem with holding both to be true at the same time? On the contrary, it wouldn't make sense to say pleasure is good, unless good is something distinct from pleasure. It’s completely pointless, for Ethics, to prove, as Mr. Spencer[p. 15] attempts to do, that more pleasure equals more life, unless good means something different from either life or pleasure. He might as well try to prove that an orange is yellow by showing that it’s always wrapped in paper.
13. In fact, if it is not the case that ‘good’ denotes something simple and indefinable, only two alternatives are possible: either it is a complex, a given whole, about the correct analysis of which there may be disagreement; or else it means nothing at all, and there is no such subject as Ethics. In general, however, ethical philosophers have attempted to define good, without recognising what such an attempt must mean. They actually use arguments which involve one or both of the absurdities considered in § 11. We are, therefore, justified in concluding that the attempt to define good is chiefly due to want of clearness as to the possible nature of definition. There are, in fact, only two serious alternatives to be considered, in order to establish the conclusion that ‘good’ does denote a simple and indefinable notion. It might possibly denote a complex, as ‘horse’ does; or it might have no meaning at all. Neither of these possibilities has, however, been clearly conceived and seriously maintained, as such, by those who presume to define good; and both may be dismissed by a simple appeal to facts.
13. In fact, if ‘good’ doesn’t refer to something simple and indefinable, there are only two alternatives: either it’s a complex idea, a whole that people might disagree on when analyzing it, or it doesn’t mean anything at all, and Ethics doesn’t exist. Generally, ethical philosophers have tried to define good without recognizing what such an attempt actually implies. They use arguments that involve one or both of the absurdities discussed in § 11. So, we can conclude that the effort to define good mainly comes from a lack of clarity about what definition means. There are really only two serious alternatives to consider to show that ‘good’ actually represents a simple and indefinable concept. It might refer to a complex idea, like ‘horse’ does; or it might not have any meaning at all. However, neither of these possibilities has been clearly thought out or convincingly argued by those trying to define good, and both can be dismissed simply by looking at the facts.
(1) The hypothesis that disagreement about the meaning of good is disagreement with regard to the correct analysis of a given whole, may be most plainly seen to be incorrect by consideration of the fact that, whatever definition be offered, it may be always asked, with significance, of the complex so defined, whether it is itself good. To take, for instance, one of the more plausible, because one of the more complicated, of such proposed definitions, it may easily be thought, at first sight, that to be good may mean to be that which we desire to desire. Thus if we apply this definition to a particular instance and say ‘When we think that A is good, we are thinking that A is one of the things which we desire to desire,’ our proposition may seem quite plausible. But, if we carry the investigation further, and ask ourselves ‘Is it good to desire to desire A?’ it is apparent, on a little reflection, that this question is itself as intelligible, as the original question ‘Is A good?’—that we are,[p. 16] in fact, now asking for exactly the same information about the desire to desire A, for which we formerly asked with regard to A itself. But it is also apparent that the meaning of this second question cannot be correctly analysed into ‘Is the desire to desire A one of the things which we desire to desire?’: we have not before our minds anything so complicated as the question ‘Do we desire to desire to desire to desire A?’ Moreover any one can easily convince himself by inspection that the predicate of this proposition—‘good’—is positively different from the notion of ‘desiring to desire’ which enters into its subject: ‘That we should desire to desire A is good’ is not merely equivalent to ‘That A should be good is good.’ It may indeed be true that what we desire to desire is always also good; perhaps, even the converse may be true: but it is very doubtful whether this is the case, and the mere fact that we understand very well what is meant by doubting it, shews clearly that we have two different notions before our minds.
(1) The idea that disagreement about what "good" means is just a disagreement about the right analysis of a whole can be clearly seen as incorrect when we consider that, no matter what definition we provide, we can always ask about the defined complex whether it is, in fact, good. For example, one of the more plausible and complicated definitions might suggest that being good means being something we want to want. So, if we apply this definition to a specific case and say, "When we think that A is good, we mean that A is one of the things we want to want," our statement might seem quite reasonable at first. However, if we dig deeper and ask ourselves, "Is it good to want to want A?" it becomes clear, with a bit of thought, that this question is just as understandable as the original question, "Is A good?"—we are essentially asking for the same information about the desire to want A, as we did about A itself. But it is also clear that the meaning of this second question can’t be correctly broken down into "Is the desire to want A one of the things we want to want?" We don't have something as complex as the question "Do we want to want to want to want A?" in front of us. Furthermore, anyone can easily realize by looking closely that the term “good” in this proposition is fundamentally different from the idea of “wanting to want” that’s part of it: "To want to want A is good" is not simply the same as "For A to be good is good." It may indeed be true that what we want to want is always good; maybe the opposite could also be true: but it’s quite uncertain whether that’s the case, and the simple fact that we clearly understand what it means to doubt this shows that we have two different ideas in mind.
(2) And the same consideration is sufficient to dismiss the hypothesis that ‘good’ has no meaning whatsoever. It is very natural to make the mistake of supposing that what is universally true is of such a nature that its negation would be self-contradictory: the importance which has been assigned to analytic propositions in the history of philosophy shews how easy such a mistake is. And thus it is very easy to conclude that what seems to be a universal ethical principle is in fact an identical proposition; that, if, for example, whatever is called ‘good’ seems to be pleasant, the proposition ‘Pleasure is the good’ does not assert a connection between two different notions, but involves only one, that of pleasure, which is easily recognised as a distinct entity. But whoever will attentively consider with himself what is actually before his mind when he asks the question ‘Is pleasure (or whatever it may be) after all good?’ can easily satisfy himself that he is not merely wondering whether pleasure is pleasant. And if he will try this experiment with each suggested definition in succession, he may become expert enough to recognise that in every case he has before his mind a unique object, with regard to the connection of which with any other object, a distinct question may be asked. Every[p. 17] one does in fact understand the question ‘Is this good?’ When he thinks of it, his state of mind is different from what it would be, were he asked ‘Is this pleasant, or desired, or approved?’ It has a distinct meaning for him, even though he may not recognise in what respect it is distinct. Whenever he thinks of ‘intrinsic value,’ or ‘intrinsic worth,’ or says that a thing ‘ought to exist,’ he has before his mind the unique object—the unique property of things—which I mean by ‘good.’ Everybody is constantly aware of this notion, although he may never become aware at all that it is different from other notions of which he is also aware. But, for correct ethical reasoning, it is extremely important that he should become aware of this fact; and, as soon as the nature of the problem is clearly understood, there should be little difficulty in advancing so far in analysis.
(2) The same reasoning is enough to reject the idea that ‘good’ has no meaning at all. It’s quite common to mistakenly think that what is universally true must be such that its opposite would be self-contradictory: the significance placed on analytic propositions throughout the history of philosophy shows how easily this error can be made. Therefore, it's easy to conclude that what appears to be a universal ethical principle is actually an identical proposition; for instance, if everything labeled as ‘good’ seems to be pleasant, the statement ‘Pleasure is the good’ doesn't suggest a connection between two different concepts but revolves around just one—pleasure—which is clearly identifiable as a separate entity. However, anyone who carefully reflects on what they're thinking when they ask, ‘Is pleasure (or whatever it may be) genuinely good?’ can easily realize they’re not just questioning whether pleasure is pleasant. If they try this with each proposed definition in turn, they might become skilled enough to see that in every case, there’s a distinct object in mind, about which a separate question can be raised regarding its connection to another object. Everyone knows what the question ‘Is this good?’ means. When they consider it, their mindset is different from what it would be if they were asked, ‘Is this pleasant, desired, or approved?’ It holds a specific meaning for them, even if they don’t recognize how it differs. Whenever they think of ‘intrinsic value’ or ‘intrinsic worth,’ or say that something ‘ought to exist,’ they have in mind the unique object—the unique property of things—that I refer to as ‘good.’ Everyone is intuitively aware of this concept, even if they never become conscious of it being distinct from other concepts they also know. However, for proper ethical reasoning, it’s crucial that they become aware of this fact; and once the nature of the problem is clearly understood, there should be little trouble making progress in analysis.
14. ‘Good,’ then, is indefinable; and yet, so far as I know, there is only one ethical writer, Prof. Henry Sidgwick, who has clearly recognised and stated this fact. We shall see, indeed, how far many of the most reputed ethical systems fall short of drawing the conclusions which follow from such a recognition. At present I will only quote one instance, which will serve to illustrate the meaning and importance of this principle that ‘good’ is indefinable, or, as Prof. Sidgwick says, an ‘unanalysable notion.’ It is an instance to which Prof. Sidgwick himself refers in a note on the passage, in which he argues that ‘ought’ is unanalysable[2].
14. ‘Good’ is something we can't define; however, as far as I know, there’s only one ethical writer, Prof. Henry Sidgwick, who has clearly acknowledged and articulated this fact. We will see how many of the most respected ethical systems fail to draw the conclusions that arise from this acknowledgment. For now, I'll just mention one example that illustrates the meaning and significance of the idea that ‘good’ is indefinable, or, as Prof. Sidgwick puts it, an ‘unanalysable notion.’ This example is one that Prof. Sidgwick himself mentions in a note on the passage, where he argues that ‘ought’ is unanalysable[2].
‘Bentham,’ says Sidgwick, ‘explains that his fundamental principle “states the greatest happiness of all those whose interest is in question as being the right and proper end of human action”’; and yet ‘his language in other passages of the same chapter would seem to imply’ that he means by the word “right” “conducive to the general happiness.” Prof. Sidgwick sees that, if you take these two statements together, you get the absurd result that ‘greatest happiness is the end of human action, which is conducive to the general happiness’; and so absurd does it seem to him to call this result, as Bentham calls it, ‘the fundamental principle of a moral system,’ that he suggests that Bentham cannot have meant it. Yet Prof. Sidgwick[p. 18] himself states elsewhere[3] that Psychological Hedonism is ‘not seldom confounded with Egoistic Hedonism’; and that confusion, as we shall see, rests chiefly on that same fallacy, the naturalistic fallacy, which is implied in Bentham’s statements. Prof. Sidgwick admits therefore that this fallacy is sometimes committed, absurd as it is; and I am inclined to think that Bentham may really have been one of those who committed it. Mill, as we shall see, certainly did commit it. In any case, whether Bentham committed it or not, his doctrine, as above quoted, will serve as a very good illustration of this fallacy, and of the importance of the contrary proposition that good is indefinable.
‘Bentham,’ says Sidgwick, ‘explains that his fundamental principle “states the greatest happiness of all those whose interest is in question as being the right and proper end of human action”; and yet ‘his language in other passages of the same chapter would seem to imply’ that he means by the word “right” “conducive to the general happiness.” Prof. Sidgwick sees that, if you take these two statements together, you get the absurd result that ‘greatest happiness is the end of human action, which is conducive to the general happiness’; and so absurd does it seem to him to call this result, as Bentham calls it, ‘the fundamental principle of a moral system,’ that he suggests that Bentham cannot have meant it. Yet Prof. Sidgwick[p. 18] himself states elsewhere[3] that Psychological Hedonism is ‘not seldom confounded with Egoistic Hedonism’; and that confusion, as we shall see, rests chiefly on that same fallacy, the naturalistic fallacy, which is implied in Bentham’s statements. Prof. Sidgwick admits therefore that this fallacy is sometimes committed, absurd as it is; and I am inclined to think that Bentham may really have been one of those who committed it. Mill, as we shall see, certainly did commit it. In any case, whether Bentham committed it or not, his doctrine, as above quoted, will serve as a very good illustration of this fallacy, and of the importance of the contrary proposition that good is indefinable.
Let us consider this doctrine. Bentham seems to imply, so Prof. Sidgwick says, that the word ‘right’ means ‘conducive to general happiness.’ Now this, by itself, need not necessarily involve the naturalistic fallacy. For the word ‘right’ is very commonly appropriated to actions which lead to the attainment of what is good; which are regarded as means to the ideal and not as ends-in-themselves. This use of ‘right,’ as denoting what is good as a means, whether or not it be also good as an end, is indeed the use to which I shall confine the word. Had Bentham been using ‘right’ in this sense, it might be perfectly consistent for him to define right as ‘conducive to the general happiness,’ provided only (and notice this proviso) he had already proved, or laid down as an axiom, that general happiness was the good, or (what is equivalent to this) that general happiness alone was good. For in that case he would have already defined the good as general happiness (a position perfectly consistent, as we have seen, with the contention that ‘good’ is indefinable), and, since right was to be defined as ‘conducive to the good,’ it would actually mean ‘conducive to general happiness.’ But this method of escape from the charge of having committed the naturalistic fallacy has been closed by Bentham himself. For his fundamental principle is, we see, that the greatest happiness of all concerned is the right and proper end of human action. He applies the word ‘right,’ therefore, to the end, as such, not only to the means which are[p. 19] conducive to it; and, that being so, right can no longer be defined as ‘conducive to the general happiness,’ without involving the fallacy in question. For now it is obvious that the definition of right as conducive to general happiness can be used by him in support of the fundamental principle that general happiness is the right end; instead of being itself derived from that principle. If right, by definition, means conducive to general happiness, then it is obvious that general happiness is the right end. It is not necessary now first to prove or assert that general happiness is the right end, before right is defined as conducive to general happiness—a perfectly valid procedure; but on the contrary the definition of right as conducive to general happiness proves general happiness to be the right end—a perfectly invalid procedure, since in this case the statement that ‘general happiness is the right end of human action’ is not an ethical principle at all, but either, as we have seen, a proposition about the meaning of words, or else a proposition about the nature of general happiness, not about its rightness or goodness.
Let’s take a look at this idea. Bentham seems to suggest, as Professor Sidgwick points out, that the term ‘right’ refers to ‘conducive to general happiness.’ Now, this alone doesn’t necessarily lead to the naturalistic fallacy. The term ‘right’ is often applied to actions that help achieve what is good; these actions are seen as means toward the ideal rather than ends in themselves. This usage of ‘right’ to indicate what is good as a means, whether or not it is also good as an end, is exactly how I will use the word. If Bentham had used ‘right’ in this way, it could be perfectly logical for him to define right as ‘conducive to general happiness,’ as long as (and pay attention to this condition) he had already demonstrated, or stated as a basic truth, that general happiness was the good, or (which means the same) that general happiness alone was good. In that case, he would have already defined the good as general happiness (a position that, as we have seen, is perfectly consistent with the claim that ‘good’ cannot be defined), and since right was to be defined as ‘conducive to the good,’ it would actually mean ‘conducive to general happiness.’ However, Bentham himself has closed off this way of avoiding the accusation of the naturalistic fallacy. His fundamental principle, as we see, is that the greatest happiness of everyone involved is the right and proper end of human action. Therefore, he applies the term ‘right’ to the end itself, not just to the means that help achieve it; and with that in mind, right can no longer be defined as ‘conducive to general happiness’ without involving the fallacy in question. Now it is clear that defining right as conducive to general happiness can support his fundamental principle that general happiness is the right end, instead of being derived from that principle. If right, by definition, means conducive to general happiness, then it follows that general happiness is the right end. It is no longer necessary to first prove or claim that general happiness is the right end before right is defined as conducive to general happiness—a perfectly valid process; rather, in this case, defining right as conducive to general happiness proves that general happiness is the right end—a perfectly invalid process, since in this situation the assertion that ‘general happiness is the right end of human action’ is not an ethical principle at all, but rather, as we have seen, either a statement about the meaning of words or a statement about the nature of general happiness, not about its rightness or goodness.
Now, I do not wish the importance I assign to this fallacy to be misunderstood. The discovery of it does not at all refute Bentham’s contention that greatest happiness is the proper end of human action, if that be understood as an ethical proposition, as he undoubtedly intended it. That principle may be true all the same; we shall consider whether it is so in succeeding chapters. Bentham might have maintained it, as Professor Sidgwick does, even if the fallacy had been pointed out to him. What I am maintaining is that the reasons which he actually gives for his ethical proposition are fallacious ones so far as they consist in a definition of right. What I suggest is that he did not perceive them to be fallacious; that, if he had done so, he would have been led to seek for other reasons in support of his Utilitarianism; and that, had he sought for other reasons, he might have found none which he thought to be sufficient. In that case he would have changed his whole system—a most important consequence. It is undoubtedly also possible that he would have thought other reasons to be sufficient, and in that case his ethical system,[p. 20] in its main results, would still have stood. But, even in this latter case, his use of the fallacy would be a serious objection to him as an ethical philosopher. For it is the business of Ethics, I must insist, not only to obtain true results, but also to find valid reasons for them. The direct object of Ethics is knowledge and not practice; and any one who uses the naturalistic fallacy has certainly not fulfilled this first object, however correct his practical principles may be.
Now, I don’t want the importance I place on this fallacy to be misunderstood. Discovering it doesn’t refute Bentham’s claim that the greatest happiness is the ultimate goal of human action, if taken as an ethical statement as he clearly intended. That principle might still be true; we will examine whether it is in the following chapters. Bentham could have maintained it, just like Professor Sidgwick does, even if someone had pointed out the fallacy to him. What I’m arguing is that the reasons he actually provides for his ethical proposition are flawed, at least when they rely on a definition of right. I suggest that he didn’t realize these reasons were flawed; had he done so, he would have looked for other justifications to support his Utilitarianism and, had he searched for those, he might not have found any he considered sufficient. If that were the case, he would have had to change his entire system—a very significant outcome. It's also possible that he would have found other reasons sufficient, in which case his ethical system,[p. 20] in its main conclusions, would have remained intact. However, even in this scenario, his reliance on the fallacy would be a serious issue for him as an ethical philosopher. I must emphasize that it's Ethics’ role not only to achieve true outcomes but also to uncover valid reasons for them. The primary goal of Ethics is knowledge, not practice; and anyone who employs the naturalistic fallacy certainly hasn’t met this first goal, regardless of how accurate their practical principles may be.
My objections to Naturalism are then, in the first place, that it offers no reason at all, far less any valid reason, for any ethical principle whatever; and in this it already fails to satisfy the requirements of Ethics, as a scientific study. But in the second place I contend that, though it gives a reason for no ethical principle, it is a cause of the acceptance of false principles—it deludes the mind into accepting ethical principles, which are false; and in this it is contrary to every aim of Ethics. It is easy to see that if we start with a definition of right conduct as conduct conducive to general happiness; then, knowing that right conduct is universally conduct conducive to the good, we very easily arrive at the result that the good is general happiness. If, on the other hand, we once recognise that we must start our Ethics without a definition, we shall be much more apt to look about us, before we adopt any ethical principle whatever; and the more we look about us, the less likely are we to adopt a false one. It may be replied to this: Yes, but we shall look about us just as much, before we settle on our definition, and are therefore just as likely to be right. But I will try to shew that this is not the case. If we start with the conviction that a definition of good can be found, we start with the conviction that good can mean nothing else than some one property of things; and our only business will then be to discover what that property is. But if we recognise that, so far as the meaning of good goes, anything whatever may be good, we start with a much more open mind. Moreover, apart from the fact that, when we think we have a definition, we cannot logically defend our ethical principles in any way whatever, we shall also be much less apt to defend them well, even if illogically. For we shall start with the conviction that good[p. 21] must mean so and so, and shall therefore be inclined either to misunderstand our opponent’s arguments or to cut them short with the reply, ‘This is not an open question: the very meaning of the word decides it; no one can think otherwise except through confusion.’
My objections to Naturalism are, first of all, that it provides no reason at all, much less any valid reason, for any ethical principle whatsoever; and in this way, it fails to meet the standards of Ethics as a scientific study. Secondly, I argue that while it doesn’t give a reason for any ethical principle, it does influence the acceptance of incorrect principles—it misleads the mind into accepting ethical principles that are false; and in this, it goes against every purpose of Ethics. It’s clear that if we define right conduct as behavior that leads to general happiness, then knowing that right conduct is universally behavior that promotes the good, we easily conclude that the good equals general happiness. Conversely, if we acknowledge that we should start our Ethics without a definition, we’re much more likely to examine our surroundings before adopting any ethical principle at all; and the more we observe, the less likely we are to choose a false one. One might respond: Yes, but we’ll observe just as much before we establish our definition, so we’re equally likely to be correct. However, I’ll argue that this isn’t true. If we begin with the belief that a definition of good can be found, we assume that good can only mean one specific property of things; and our only task then becomes to figure out what that property is. But if we understand that, regarding the meaning of good, anything could potentially be good, we start with a much broader perspective. Furthermore, aside from the fact that when we think we have a definition, we can’t logically defend our ethical principles in any way, we are also much less likely to defend them well, even if our arguments are illogical. This is because we start with the belief that good must mean something specific, leading us to either misunderstand our opponent’s arguments or to dismiss them with a response like, ‘This is not an open question: the very meaning of the word makes it clear; no one can think otherwise except in confusion.’
15. Our first conclusion as to the subject-matter of Ethics is, then, that there is a simple, indefinable, unanalysable object of thought by reference to which it must be defined. By what name we call this unique object is a matter of indifference, so long as we clearly recognise what it is and that it does differ from other objects. The words which are commonly taken as the signs of ethical judgments all do refer to it; and they are expressions of ethical judgments solely because they do so refer. But they may refer to it in two different ways, which it is very important to distinguish, if we are to have a complete definition of the range of ethical judgments. Before I proceeded to argue that there was such an indefinable notion involved in ethical notions, I stated (§ 4) that it was necessary for Ethics to enumerate all true universal judgments, asserting that such and such a thing was good, whenever it occurred. But, although all such judgments do refer to that unique notion which I have called ‘good,’ they do not all refer to it in the same way. They may either assert that this unique property does always attach to the thing in question, or else they may assert only that the thing in question is a cause or necessary condition for the existence of other things to which this unique property does attach. The nature of these two species of universal ethical judgments is extremely different; and a great part of the difficulties, which are met with in ordinary ethical speculation, are due to the failure to distinguish them clearly. Their difference has, indeed, received expression in ordinary language by the contrast between the terms ‘good as means’ and ‘good in itself,’ ‘value as a means’ and ‘intrinsic value.’ But these terms are apt to be applied correctly only in the more obvious instances; and this seems to be due to the fact that the distinction between the conceptions which they denote has not been made a separate object of investigation. This distinction may be briefly pointed out as follows.
15. Our first conclusion about Ethics is that there is a simple, undefinable, and unbreakable object of thought that we need to refer to in order to define it. What we name this unique object doesn’t really matter, as long as we understand what it is and acknowledge that it is different from other objects. The terms we typically use to express ethical judgments all point to it, and they represent ethical judgments solely because of that reference. However, they can refer to it in two distinct ways, which is crucial to distinguish for a complete definition of ethical judgments. Before I argued that there is an indefinable notion involved in ethical concepts, I stated (§ 4) that Ethics needs to list all true universal judgments that assert that something is good whenever it appears. While all of these judgments refer to the unique notion I call ‘good,’ they do not all reference it in the same manner. They may either claim that this unique quality always belongs to the thing in question, or they might only state that the thing in question is a cause or necessary condition for the existence of other things that do possess this unique quality. The nature of these two types of universal ethical judgments is quite different; much of the confusion encountered in typical ethical discussions arises from not clearly distinguishing between them. This distinction is expressed in everyday language through the contrast between the phrases ‘good as means’ and ‘good in itself,’ ‘value as a means’ and ‘intrinsic value.’ However, these terms are often only used correctly in the more obvious cases, likely because the distinction between the concepts they represent hasn’t been thoroughly investigated as a separate topic. This distinction can be briefly highlighted as follows.
[p. 22]
[p. 22]
16. Whenever we judge that a thing is ‘good as a means,’ we are making a judgment with regard to its causal relations: we judge both that it will have a particular kind of effect, and that that effect will be good in itself. But to find causal judgments that are universally true is notoriously a matter of extreme difficulty. The late date at which most of the physical sciences became exact, and the comparative fewness of the laws which they have succeeded in establishing even now, are sufficient proofs of this difficulty. With regard, then, to what are the most frequent objects of ethical judgments, namely actions, it is obvious that we cannot be satisfied that any of our universal causal judgments are true, even in the sense in which scientific laws are so. We cannot even discover hypothetical laws of the form ‘Exactly this action will always, under these conditions, produce exactly that effect.’ But for a correct ethical judgment with regard to the effects of certain actions we require more than this in two respects. (1) We require to know that a given action will produce a certain effect, under whatever circumstances it occurs. But this is certainly impossible. It is certain that in different circumstances the same action may produce effects which are utterly different in all respects upon which the value of the effects depends. Hence we can never be entitled to more than a generalisation—to a proposition of the form ‘This result generally follows this kind of action’; and even this generalisation will only be true, if the circumstances under which the action occurs are generally the same. This is in fact the case, to a great extent, within any one particular age and state of society. But, when we take other ages into account, in many most important cases the normal circumstances of a given kind of action will be so different, that the generalisation which is true for one will not be true for another. With regard then to ethical judgments which assert that a certain kind of action is good as a means to a certain kind of effect, none will be universally true; and many, though generally true at one period, will be generally false at others. But (2) we require to know not only that one good effect will be produced, but that, among all subsequent events affected by the action in question, the balance of good will be greater[p. 23] than if any other possible action had been performed. In other words, to judge that an action is generally a means to good is to judge not only that it generally does some good, but that it generally does the greatest good of which the circumstances admit. In this respect ethical judgments about the effects of action involve a difficulty and a complication far greater than that involved in the establishment of scientific laws. For the latter we need only consider a single effect; for the former it is essential to consider not only this, but the effects of that effect, and so on as far as our view into the future can reach. It is, indeed, obvious that our view can never reach far enough for us to be certain that any action will produce the best possible effects. We must be content, if the greatest possible balance of good seems to be produced within a limited period. But it is important to notice that the whole series of effects within a period of considerable length is actually taken account of in our common judgments that an action is good as a means; and that hence this additional complication, which makes ethical generalisations so far more difficult to establish than scientific laws, is one which is involved in actual ethical discussions, and is of practical importance. The commonest rules of conduct involve such considerations as the balancing of future bad health against immediate gains; and even if we can never settle with any certainty how we shall secure the greatest possible total of good, we try at least to assure ourselves that probable future evils will not be greater than the immediate good.
16. Whenever we believe that something is ‘good as a means,’ we are making a judgment about its causal relationships: we judge both that it will have a specific effect, and that effect will be good in itself. However, finding causal judgments that are universally true is notoriously difficult. The late development of most physical sciences into exact fields, along with the relatively few laws they've managed to establish even now, clearly demonstrates this challenge. Regarding the most common subjects of ethical judgments—namely actions—it’s evident that we can't be sure any of our universal causal judgments are true, even in the sense that scientific laws are. We can't even establish hypothetical laws like ‘This action will always, under these conditions, produce this exact effect.’ For a correct ethical judgment concerning the outcomes of certain actions, we need more than this in two ways. (1) We need to know that a specific action will produce a certain effect, regardless of the circumstances. But this is surely impossible. It's certain that under different circumstances, the same action may produce results that are completely different in all respects that matter to the value of those effects. Therefore, we can only claim a generalization—a statement of the form ‘This result generally follows this kind of action’; and even this generalization will only hold true if the circumstances surrounding the action are generally similar. This is often the case within a specific time and society. However, when we look at different times, in many important cases, the typical circumstances of a certain kind of action will differ so much that the generalization true for one will not hold for another. Thus, ethical judgments stating that a particular kind of action is good as a means to achieve a certain effect cannot be universally true; and many that are generally true in one period will be generally false in others. Additionally, (2) we need to know not only that one good effect will result, but also that, among all subsequent events influenced by the action in question, the overall good will be greater[p. 23] than if any alternative action had been taken. In other words, to judge that an action generally leads to good means evaluating not just that it generally produces some good, but that it generally produces the greatest good possible given the circumstances. In this way, ethical judgments about the impact of actions involve much greater difficulty and complexity than establishing scientific laws. For the latter, we only need to consider a single effect; for the former, we must also consider not only this effect but the ramifications of that effect, and continue as far into the future as we can foresee. It’s clear that our perspective can never reach far enough to guarantee that any action will yield the best possible results. We can only be satisfied if the greatest possible overall good seems to be attained over a limited timeframe. However, it’s important to point out that the entire series of effects over a significant period is actually factored into our common judgments that an action is good as a means; and thus, this additional complexity, which makes ethical generalizations much more difficult to establish than scientific laws, is inherent in real ethical discussions and holds practical importance. The most common rules of conduct take into account such considerations as weighing potential future health issues against immediate benefits; and even if we can never conclusively determine how to achieve the greatest possible total of good, we at least try to ensure that expected future harms will not outweigh the immediate benefits.
17. There are, then, judgments which state that certain kinds of things have good effects; and such judgments, for the reasons just given, have the important characteristics (1) that they are unlikely to be true, if they state that the kind of thing in question always has good effects, and (2) that, even if they only state that it generally has good effects, many of them will only be true of certain periods in the world’s history. On the other hand there are judgments which state that certain kinds of things are themselves good; and these differ from the last in that, if true at all, they are all of them universally true. It is, therefore, extremely important to distinguish these two kinds[p. 24] of possible judgments. Both may be expressed in the same language: in both cases we commonly say ‘Such and such a thing is good.’ But in the one case ‘good’ will mean ‘good as means,’ i.e. merely that the thing is a means to good—will have good effects: in the other case it will mean ‘good as end’—we shall be judging that the thing itself has the property which, in the first case, we asserted only to belong to its effects. It is plain that these are very different assertions to make about a thing; it is plain that either or both of them may be made, both truly and falsely, about all manner of things; and it is certain that unless we are clear as to which of the two we mean to assert, we shall have a very poor chance of deciding rightly whether our assertion is true or false. It is precisely this clearness as to the meaning of the question asked which has hitherto been almost entirely lacking in ethical speculation. Ethics has always been predominantly concerned with the investigation of a limited class of actions. With regard to these we may ask both how far they are good in themselves and how far they have a general tendency to produce good results. And the arguments brought forward in ethical discussion have always been of both classes—both such as would prove the conduct in question to be good in itself and such as would prove it to be good as a means. But that these are the only questions which any ethical discussion can have to settle, and that to settle the one is not the same thing as to settle the other—these two fundamental facts have in general escaped the notice of ethical philosophers. Ethical questions are commonly asked in an ambiguous form. It is asked ‘What is a man’s duty under these circumstances?’ or ‘Is it right to act in this way?’ or ‘What ought we to aim at securing?’ But all these questions are capable of further analysis; a correct answer to any of them involves both judgments of what is good in itself and causal judgments. This is implied even by those who maintain that we have a direct and immediate judgment of absolute rights and duties. Such a judgment can only mean that the course of action in question is the best thing to do; that, by acting so, every good that can be secured will have been secured. Now we are not concerned with the question whether such a judgment will ever be true.[p. 25] The question is: What does it imply, if it is true? And the only possible answer is that, whether true or false, it implies both a proposition as to the degree of goodness of the action in question, as compared with other things, and a number of causal propositions. For it cannot be denied that the action will have consequences: and to deny that the consequences matter is to make a judgment of their intrinsic value, as compared with the action itself. In asserting that the action is the best thing to do, we assert that it together with its consequences presents a greater sum of intrinsic value than any possible alternative. And this condition may be realised by any of the three cases:—(a) If the action itself has greater intrinsic value than any alternative, whereas both its consequences and those of the alternatives are absolutely devoid either of intrinsic merit or intrinsic demerit; or (b) if, though its consequences are intrinsically bad, the balance of intrinsic value is greater than would be produced by any alternative; or (c) if, its consequences being intrinsically good, the degree of value belonging to them and it conjointly is greater than that of any alternative series. In short, to assert that a certain line of conduct is, at a given time, absolutely right or obligatory, is obviously to assert that more good or less evil will exist in the world, if it be adopted, than if anything else be done instead. But this implies a judgment as to the value both of its own consequences and of those of any possible alternative. And that an action will have such and such consequences involves a number of causal judgments.
17. There are judgments that claim certain things have good effects; and these judgments have key characteristics (1) they are unlikely to be true if they assert that the thing always has good effects, and (2) even if they state that it generally has good effects, many will only apply to specific times in history. On the other hand, there are judgments that claim certain things are inherently good; and these differ in that, if they are true at all, they are universally true. Therefore, it’s crucial to distinguish between these two types[p. 24] of possible judgments. Both types can be expressed in similar language: we often say, ‘Such and such a thing is good.’ But in one case, ‘good’ means ‘good as a means,’ meaning the thing is just a means to something good—it will have good effects. In the other case, it means ‘good as an end’—we’re claiming that the thing itself has the quality that, in the first case, we only attributed to its effects. It’s clear that these are very different claims about a thing; it’s evident that either or both can be made, both truthfully and falsely, about all sorts of things; and it’s certain that unless we’re clear about which of the two we intend to assert, we’ll have a slim chance of determining whether our assertion is true or false. This clarity regarding the question being asked has been largely absent in ethical discussions. Ethics has mostly focused on a specific class of actions. For these actions, we can ask both how far they are good in themselves and how far they generally tend to produce good outcomes. The arguments in ethical discussions have always included both types—those that prove the conduct is good in itself and those that prove it is good as a means. However, these being the only questions that any ethical discussion must resolve, and recognizing that resolving one is not the same as resolving the other—these two fundamental points have generally escaped ethical philosophers' attention. Ethical questions are often posed in a vague manner. People ask, ‘What is a person’s duty in this situation?’ or ‘Is it right to act this way?’ or ‘What should we aim to achieve?’ But all these questions can be further analyzed; providing a correct answer to any of them involves both judgments about what is good in itself and causal judgments. This is even acknowledged by those who argue we have a direct and immediate sense of absolute rights and duties. Such a judgment can only mean that the action in question is the best thing to do; that by acting in that way, every good that can be achieved will be achieved. Now, we aren’t addressing whether such a judgment will ever be true.[p. 25] The question is: What does it imply if it is true? The only possible answer is that, whether true or false, it implies both a proposition regarding the degree of goodness of the action compared to others and several causal propositions. For we cannot deny that the action will have consequences; to claim that the consequences don’t matter is to make a judgment about their intrinsic value compared to the action itself. By asserting that the action is the best option, we are claiming that it and its consequences present a greater overall intrinsic value than any potential alternative. This situation can be realized in any of three scenarios:—(a) If the action itself has greater intrinsic value than any alternative while both its consequences and those of the alternatives lack intrinsic merit or demerit; or (b) if, although its consequences are intrinsically bad, the overall intrinsic value is greater than any alternative option would provide; or (c) if, with its consequences being intrinsically good, the combined value of them and the action is greater than any alternative series. Ultimately, claiming that a particular course of action is, at a certain time, absolutely right or mandatory, clearly asserts that more good or less evil will exist in the world if it is taken than if anything else is done. But this entails a judgment about the value of its consequences and those of any potential alternative. Recognizing that an action will have certain consequences involves multiple causal judgments.
Similarly, in answering the question ‘What ought we to aim at securing?’ causal judgments are again involved, but in a somewhat different way. We are liable to forget, because it is so obvious, that this question can never be answered correctly except by naming something which can be secured. Not everything can be secured; and, even if we judge that nothing which cannot be obtained would be of equal value with that which can, the possibility of the latter, as well as its value, is essential to its being a proper end of action. Accordingly neither our judgments as to what actions we ought to perform, nor even our judgments as to the ends which they ought to produce, are[p. 26] pure judgments of intrinsic value. With regard to the former, an action which is absolutely obligatory may have no intrinsic value whatsoever; that it is perfectly virtuous may mean merely that it causes the best possible effects. And with regard to the latter, these best possible results which justify our action can, in any case, have only so much of intrinsic value as the laws of nature allow us to secure; and they in their turn may have no intrinsic value whatsoever, but may merely be a means to the attainment (in a still further future) of something that has such value. Whenever, therefore, we ask ‘What ought we to do?’ or ‘What ought we to try to get?’ we are asking questions which involve a correct answer to two others, completely different in kind from one another. We must know both what degree of intrinsic value different things have, and how these different things may be obtained. But the vast majority of questions which have actually been discussed in Ethics—all practical questions, indeed—involve this double knowledge; and they have been discussed without any clear separation of the two distinct questions involved. A great part of the vast disagreements prevalent in Ethics is to be attributed to this failure in analysis. By the use of conceptions which involve both that of intrinsic value and that of causal relation, as if they involved intrinsic value only, two different errors have been rendered almost universal. Either it is assumed that nothing has intrinsic value which is not possible, or else it is assumed that what is necessary must have intrinsic value. Hence the primary and peculiar business of Ethics, the determination what things have intrinsic value and in what degrees, has received no adequate treatment at all. And on the other hand a thorough discussion of means has been also largely neglected, owing to an obscure perception of the truth that it is perfectly irrelevant to the question of intrinsic values. But however this may be, and however strongly any particular reader may be convinced that some one of the mutually contradictory systems which hold the field has given a correct answer either to the question what has intrinsic value, or to the question what we ought to do, or to both, it must at least be admitted that the questions what is best in itself and what will bring about the best possible, are[p. 27] utterly distinct; that both belong to the actual subject-matter of Ethics; and that the more clearly distinct questions are distinguished, the better is our chance of answering both correctly.
Similarly, when we answer the question, "What should we aim to achieve?" causal judgments are involved again, but in a slightly different way. We often forget, because it's so obvious, that this question can only be answered correctly by identifying something that can be achieved. Not everything can be achieved; and even if we conclude that nothing unattainable is as valuable as what is achievable, the possibility of the latter, along with its value, is crucial for it to be a valid goal for action. Therefore, neither our judgments about what actions we should take nor our judgments about the goals they should produce are[p. 26] purely judgments of intrinsic value. Regarding the former, an action that is absolutely necessary might have no intrinsic value at all; that it is perfectly virtuous might just mean that it leads to the best possible outcomes. And concerning the latter, these best possible results, which justify our actions, can only have as much intrinsic value as the laws of nature allow us to achieve; and they might in fact have no intrinsic value at all, merely serving as a means to attain (eventually) something that does have such value. Whenever we ask, "What should we do?" or "What should we strive to obtain?" we are posing questions that rely on correctly answering two others, which are completely different from each other. We need to know both the degree of intrinsic value that different things possess, and how these different things can be achieved. Most questions discussed in Ethics—indeed, all practical questions—involve this dual knowledge; yet they have often been addressed without clearly separating the two different questions. Much of the widespread disagreement in Ethics stems from this lack of analytical clarity. By using concepts that combine intrinsic value and causal relationships as if they only involved intrinsic value, two different errors have become almost universal. One assumption is that nothing possesses intrinsic value unless it is achievable, while the other is that what is necessary must inherently have intrinsic value. Consequently, the primary and unique task of Ethics—determining which things have intrinsic value and to what degree—has not been adequately addressed at all. On the flip side, a thorough exploration of means has largely been overlooked, due to a vague understanding of the fact that it is completely irrelevant to questions of intrinsic values. However, regardless of this, and regardless of how strongly any particular reader believes that any of the conflicting systems currently in discussion has correctly answered either the question about what has intrinsic value, what we ought to do, or both, it must be acknowledged that the questions regarding what is best in itself and what will lead to the best possible outcomes are[p. 27] entirely distinct; both are part of the actual subject matter of Ethics; and the clearer we define these distinct questions, the better our chances of answering both correctly.
18. There remains one point which must not be omitted in a complete description of the kind of questions which Ethics has to answer. The main division of those questions is, as I have said, into two; the question what things are good in themselves, and the question to what other things these are related as effects. The first of these, which is the primary ethical question and is presupposed by the other, includes a correct comparison of the various things which have intrinsic value (if there are many such) in respect of the degree of value which they have; and such comparison involves a difficulty of principle which has greatly aided the confusion of intrinsic value with mere ‘goodness as a means.’ It has been pointed out that one difference between a judgment which asserts that a thing is good in itself, and a judgment which asserts that it is a means to good, consists in the fact that the first, if true of one instance of the thing in question, is necessarily true of all; whereas a thing which has good effects under some circumstances may have bad ones under others. Now it is certainly true that all judgments of intrinsic value are in this sense universal; but the principle which I have now to enunciate may easily make it appear as if they were not so but resembled the judgment of means in being merely general. There is, as will presently be maintained, a vast number of different things, each of which has intrinsic value; there are also very many which are positively bad; and there is a still larger class of things, which appear to be indifferent. But a thing belonging to any of these three classes may occur as part of a whole, which includes among its other parts other things belonging both to the same and to the other two classes; and these wholes, as such, may also have intrinsic value. The paradox, to which it is necessary to call attention, is that the value of such a whole bears no regular proportion to the sum of the values of its parts. It is certain that a good thing may exist in such a relation to another good thing that the value of the whole thus formed is immensely greater[p. 28] than the sum of the values of the two good things. It is certain that a whole formed of a good thing and an indifferent thing may have immensely greater value than that good thing itself possesses. It is certain that two bad things or a bad thing and an indifferent thing may form a whole much worse than the sum of badness of its parts. And it seems as if indifferent things may also be the sole constituents of a whole which has great value, either positive or negative. Whether the addition of a bad thing to a good whole may increase the positive value of the whole, or the addition of a bad thing to a bad may produce a whole having positive value, may seem more doubtful; but it is, at least, possible, and this possibility must be taken into account in our ethical investigations. However we may decide particular questions, the principle is clear. The value of a whole must not be assumed to be the same as the sum of the values of its parts.
18. There’s one more point that needs to be included in a complete description of the types of questions that Ethics has to address. As I mentioned, these questions are primarily divided into two categories: the question of what things are good in themselves, and the question of how these relate to other things as their effects. The first question is the core ethical question that the second assumes; it involves a proper comparison of various things that have intrinsic value (if there are many) based on the degree of value they possess. This comparison brings about a fundamental challenge that has contributed to the confusion of intrinsic value with mere "goodness as a means." It has been noted that a key difference between a judgment claiming that something is good in itself and one claiming it's a means to good lies in the fact that if the first is true for one instance of that thing, it must be true for all instances; whereas a thing that yields good effects in some situations may yield bad ones in others. It is undoubtedly true that all judgments of intrinsic value are universal in this sense; however, the principle I’m about to state could easily make it seem like they are not and more closely resemble judgments about means, which are simply general. As will be argued shortly, there are many different things, each possessing intrinsic value; there are also many that are definitively bad; and there’s an even larger group of things that seem to be neutral. However, a thing from any of these three categories can be part of a larger whole, which can include other parts from the same or the other two categories; and such wholes, in their entirety, can also have intrinsic value. The paradox that needs highlighting is that the value of such a whole does not consistently correlate with the sum of the values of its parts. It’s certain that two good things can come together in such a way that the value of the whole is significantly greater[p. 28] than just the sum of their individual values. It’s also true that a whole made up of a good thing and a neutral thing can have a value that far exceeds that of the good thing alone. Additionally, it’s possible for two bad things or a bad thing and a neutral thing to together create a whole that is much worse than the total badness of its components. Furthermore, indifferent things can also solely make up a whole that carries significant value, whether positive or negative. Whether adding a bad thing to a good whole increases its positive value, or whether adding a bad thing to another bad one can produce a whole with positive value seems more uncertain; however, it remains a possibility that must be acknowledged in our ethical analyses. Regardless of how we resolve specific questions, the principle is clear. The value of a whole should not be assumed to equal the sum of the values of its parts.
A single instance will suffice to illustrate the kind of relation in question. It seems to be true that to be conscious of a beautiful object is a thing of great intrinsic value; whereas the same object, if no one be conscious of it, has certainly comparatively little value, and is commonly held to have none at all. But the consciousness of a beautiful object is certainly a whole of some sort in which we can distinguish as parts the object on the one hand and the being conscious on the other. Now this latter factor occurs as part of a different whole, whenever we are conscious of anything; and it would seem that some of these wholes have at all events very little value, and may even be indifferent or positively bad. Yet we cannot always attribute the slightness of their value to any positive demerit in the object which differentiates them from the consciousness of beauty; the object itself may approach as near as possible to absolute neutrality. Since, therefore, mere consciousness does not always confer great value upon the whole of which it forms a part, even though its object may have no great demerit, we cannot attribute the great superiority of the consciousness of a beautiful thing over the beautiful thing itself to the mere addition of the value of consciousness to that of the beautiful thing. Whatever the intrinsic value of consciousness may be, it does not give to[p. 29] the whole of which it forms a part a value proportioned to the sum of its value and that of its object. If this be so, we have here an instance of a whole possessing a different intrinsic value from the sum of that of its parts; and whether it be so or not, what is meant by such a difference is illustrated by this case.
One example will help illustrate the type of relationship being discussed. It seems true that being aware of a beautiful object has significant intrinsic value, while the same object, if no one is aware of it, holds very little value, and is generally considered to have none at all. However, being aware of a beautiful object is clearly a whole of some kind, which we can break down into two parts: the object itself and the awareness of it. This awareness occurs as part of a different whole whenever we are conscious of anything, and some of these wholes seem to have very little value, and may even be neutral or outright negative. Yet we can't always attribute their low value to any fault in the object that sets it apart from the awareness of beauty; the object may be nearly completely neutral. Therefore, since mere awareness doesn’t automatically give great value to the whole it belongs to, even when the object itself has no significant faults, we can't say that the higher value of being aware of something beautiful compared to the beautiful object itself is just about adding the value of awareness to that of the beautiful object. Whatever intrinsic value awareness has, it doesn’t grant the whole it’s part of a value that matches the combined value of the consciousness and the object. If this is the case, we see an instance where a whole has a different intrinsic value than the sum of its parts, and whether this is true or not, this case illustrates what such a difference means.
19. There are, then, wholes which possess the property that their value is different from the sum of the values of their parts; and the relations which subsist between such parts and the whole of which they form a part have not hitherto been distinctly recognised or received a separate name. Two points are especially worthy of notice. (1) It is plain that the existence of any such part is a necessary condition for the existence of that good which is constituted by the whole. And exactly the same language will also express the relation between a means and the good thing which is its effect. But yet there is a most important difference between the two cases, constituted by the fact that the part is, whereas the means is not, a part of the good thing for the existence of which its existence is a necessary condition. The necessity by which, if the good in question is to exist, the means to it must exist is merely a natural or causal necessity. If the laws of nature were different, exactly the same good might exist, although what is now a necessary condition of its existence did not exist. The existence of the means has no intrinsic value; and its utter annihilation would leave the value of that which it is now necessary to secure entirely unchanged. But in the case of a part of such a whole as we are now considering, it is otherwise. In this case the good in question cannot conceivably exist, unless the part exist also. The necessity which connects the two is quite independent of natural law. What is asserted to have intrinsic value is the existence of the whole; and the existence of the whole includes the existence of its part. Suppose the part removed, and what remains is not what was asserted to have intrinsic value; but if we suppose a means removed, what remains is just what was asserted to have intrinsic value. And yet (2) the existence of the part may itself have no more intrinsic value than that of the means. It is this fact which constitutes the paradox of the relation which we are discussing.[p. 30] It has just been said that what has intrinsic value is the existence of the whole, and that this includes the existence of the part; and from this it would seem a natural inference that the existence of the part has intrinsic value. But the inference would be as false as if we were to conclude that, because the number of two stones was two, each of the stones was also two. The part of a valuable whole retains exactly the same value when it is, as when it is not, a part of that whole. If it had value under other circumstances, its value is not any greater, when it is part of a far more valuable whole; and if it had no value by itself, it has none still, however great be that of the whole of which it now forms a part. We are not then justified in asserting that one and the same thing is under some circumstances intrinsically good, and under others not so; as we are justified in asserting of a means that it sometimes does and sometimes does not produce good results. And yet we are justified in asserting that it is far more desirable that a certain thing should exist under some circumstances than under others; namely when other things will exist in such relations to it as to form a more valuable whole. It will not have more intrinsic value under these circumstances than under others; it will not necessarily even be a means to the existence of things having more intrinsic value: but it will, like a means, be a necessary condition for the existence of that which has greater intrinsic value, although, unlike a means, it will itself form a part of this more valuable existent.
19. There are, then, wholes that have the property that their value is different from the total of the values of their parts, and the relationships between those parts and the whole they contribute to have not yet been clearly recognized or given a separate name. Two points deserve special attention. (1) It's clear that the presence of any such part is a necessary condition for the existence of the good that the whole represents. The same wording can also describe the relationship between a means and the good that results from it. However, there is a significant difference between the two situations: the part is, while the means is not, a component of the good whose existence depends on its presence. The necessity linked to a means is merely a natural or causal necessity. If the laws of nature were different, it’s possible that the same good could exist even if that currently necessary condition were absent. The means itself has no intrinsic value; completely removing it would leave the value of what it helps secure entirely unchanged. In contrast, for a part of a whole like we're discussing, it's different. In this case, the good in question cannot possibly exist unless the part also exists. The necessity connecting them is entirely independent of natural law. What is claimed to have intrinsic value is the existence of the whole, which includes the existence of its part. If you remove the part, what's left is not what was claimed to have intrinsic value; if you remove a means, what remains is exactly what was asserted to have intrinsic value. And yet (2) the existence of the part may itself hold no more intrinsic value than that of the means. This fact creates the paradox of the relationship we are analyzing.[p. 30] It was just mentioned that what has intrinsic value is the existence of the whole, which includes the existence of the part; from this, it might seem natural to conclude that the existence of the part has intrinsic value. But that conclusion would be as incorrect as saying that because the number of two stones is two, each stone is also two. The part of a valuable whole maintains exactly the same value whether it is part of that whole or not. If it had value in other situations, it doesn't gain any additional value when it becomes part of a much more valuable whole; and if it had no value on its own, it still has none, no matter how great the whole’s value is that it's now part of. Therefore, we aren't justified in claiming that the same thing is intrinsically good in some cases and not in others, unlike a means that may or may not produce good results. However, we can assert that it's much more desirable for a certain thing to exist under some conditions than others; specifically, when other things exist in such a way as to create a more valuable whole. It won't have more intrinsic value in these circumstances than in others; it won't necessarily even serve as a means to the existence of things with greater intrinsic value: but it will, like a means, be a necessary condition for the existence of that which has greater intrinsic value, although, unlike a means, it will itself be part of this more valuable entity.
20. I have said that the peculiar relation between part and whole which I have just been trying to define is one which has received no separate name. It would, however, be useful that it should have one; and there is a name, which might well be appropriated to it, if only it could be divorced from its present unfortunate usage. Philosophers, especially those who profess to have derived great benefit from the writings of Hegel, have latterly made much use of the terms ‘organic whole,’ ‘organic unity,’ ‘organic relation.’ The reason why these terms might well be appropriated to the use suggested is that the peculiar relation of parts to whole, just defined, is one of the properties which distinguishes the wholes to which they are actually applied[p. 31] with the greatest frequency. And the reason why it is desirable that they should be divorced from their present usage is that, as at present used, they have no distinct sense and, on the contrary, both imply and propagate errors of confusion.
20. I’ve mentioned that the unique relationship between parts and the whole that I’ve been trying to explain doesn’t have a specific name. It would be helpful if it did; there is actually a name that could be used, if only it could be separated from its current unfortunate context. Recently, philosophers—especially those who claim to have gained significant insights from Hegel’s writings—have frequently used the terms ‘organic whole,’ ‘organic unity,’ and ‘organic relation.’ The reason these terms could be appropriately assigned to the suggested use is that the unique relationship of parts to the whole, as defined, is one of the key characteristics that distinguish the wholes to which they are most commonly applied[p. 31]. Additionally, it’s important to remove these terms from their current context because, as they are used now, they lack a clear meaning and instead contribute to misunderstandings and confusion.
To say that a thing is an ‘organic whole’ is generally understood to imply that its parts are related to one another and to itself as means to end; it is also understood to imply that they have a property described in some such phrase as that they have ‘no meaning or significance apart from the whole’; and finally such a whole is also treated as if it had the property to which I am proposing that the name should be confined. But those who use the term give us, in general, no hint as to how they suppose these three properties to be related to one another. It seems generally to be assumed that they are identical; and always, at least, that they are necessarily connected with one another. That they are not identical I have already tried to shew; to suppose them so is to neglect the very distinctions pointed out in the last paragraph; and the usage might well be discontinued merely because it encourages such neglect. But a still more cogent reason for its discontinuance is that, so far from being necessarily connected, the second is a property which can attach to nothing, being a self-contradictory conception; whereas the first, if we insist on its most important sense, applies to many cases, to which we have no reason to think that the third applies also, and the third certainly applies to many to which the first does not apply.
Saying that something is an "organic whole" generally suggests that its parts are connected to each other and to the whole as means to an end; it also implies that these parts have a property often described as having "no meaning or significance apart from the whole"; finally, such a whole is usually treated as if it possesses the property that I believe the term should exclusively refer to. However, those who use the term typically don’t explain how they think these three properties are related to one another. It seems to be commonly assumed that they are the same; at the very least, there’s an assumption that they are necessarily linked. I have already argued that they are not the same; to assume they are is to overlook the distinctions mentioned in the last paragraph, and the term could rightly be abandoned simply because it promotes such oversight. An even stronger reason for dropping it is that, instead of being necessarily connected, the second property cannot apply to anything, as it is a self-contradictory idea; meanwhile, the first property, if we focus on its most significant interpretation, fits many scenarios where we have no reason to believe the third applies as well, and the third definitely applies to many cases that the first does not fit.
21. These relations between the three properties just distinguished may be illustrated by reference to a whole of the kind from which the name ‘organic’ was derived—a whole which is an organism in the scientific sense—namely the human body.
21. These connections between the three properties we've just identified can be illustrated by referring to a whole that inspired the term 'organic'—a whole that is an organism in the scientific sense—specifically, the human body.
(1) There exists between many parts of our body (though not between all) a relation which has been familiarised by the fable, attributed to Menenius Agrippa, concerning the belly and its members. We can find in it parts such that the continued existence of the one is a necessary condition for the continued existence of the other; while the continued existence of this latter is also a necessary condition for the continued existence of the former. This amounts to no more than saying[p. 32] that in the body we have instances of two things, both enduring for some time, which have a relation of mutual causal dependence on one another—a relation of ‘reciprocity.’ Frequently no more than this is meant by saying that the parts of the body form an ‘organic unity,’ or that they are mutually means and ends to one another. And we certainly have here a striking characteristic of living things. But it would be extremely rash to assert that this relation of mutual causal dependence was only exhibited by living things and hence was sufficient to define their peculiarity. And it is obvious that of two things which have this relation of mutual dependence, neither may have intrinsic value, or one may have it and the other lack it. They are not necessarily ‘ends’ to one another in any sense except that in which ‘end’ means ‘effect.’ And moreover it is plain that in this sense the whole cannot be an end to any of its parts. We are apt to talk of ‘the whole’ in contrast to one of its parts, when in fact we mean only the rest of the parts. But strictly the whole must include all its parts and no part can be a cause of the whole, because it cannot be a cause of itself. It is plain, therefore, that this relation of mutual causal dependence implies nothing with regard to the value of either of the objects which have it; and that, even if both of them happen also to have value, this relation between them is one which cannot hold between part and whole.
(1) There is a relationship between many parts of our body (though not all) that has been popularized by the story attributed to Menenius Agrippa about the belly and its members. We can find parts where the continued existence of one is necessary for the continued existence of the other; and the continued existence of this latter part is also necessary for the continued existence of the former. This simply means[p. 32] that in the body, we have instances of two things that endure for some time and are mutually dependent on each other—a relationship of ‘reciprocity.’ Often, this is what is meant when we say the body parts form an ‘organic unity’ or that they function as means and ends to one another. And indeed, this is a notable characteristic of living things. However, it would be very misleading to claim that this mutual causal dependence exists only in living things, making it sufficient to define what makes them unique. Clearly, among two things with this mutual dependence, neither might have intrinsic value, or one may have value while the other does not. They are not necessarily ‘ends’ to each other in any sense other than where ‘end’ means ‘effect.’ Moreover, it's clear that in this sense, the whole cannot be an end to any of its parts. We often refer to ‘the whole’ in contrast to a part when we really mean just the rest of the parts. But technically, the whole must include all its parts, and no part can be a cause of the whole because it cannot cause itself. Therefore, this mutual causal dependence implies nothing about the value of either object that holds this relation; and even if both happen to have value, this relation cannot exist between a part and a whole.
But (2) it may also be the case that our body as a whole has a value greater than the sum of values of its parts; and this may be what is meant when it is said that the parts are means to the whole. It is obvious that if we ask the question ‘Why should the parts be such as they are?’ a proper answer may be ‘Because the whole they form has so much value.’ But it is equally obvious that the relation which we thus assert to exist between part and whole is quite different from that which we assert to exist between part and part when we say ‘This part exists, because that one could not exist without it.’ In the latter case we assert the two parts to be causally connected; but, in the former, part and whole cannot be causally connected, and the relation which we assert to exist between them may exist even though the parts are not causally connected either.[p. 33] All the parts of a picture do not have that relation of mutual causal dependence, which certain parts of the body have, and yet the existence of those which do not have it may be absolutely essential to the value of the whole. The two relations are quite distinct in kind, and we cannot infer the existence of the one from that of the other. It can, therefore, serve no useful purpose to include them both under the same name; and if we are to say that a whole is organic because its parts are (in this sense) ‘means’ to the whole, we must not say that it is organic because its parts are causally dependent on one another.
But it could also be true that our body as a whole has more value than just the sum of its parts; this may be what is meant when we say the parts are means to the whole. It's clear that if we ask, "Why should the parts be what they are?" a suitable answer could be, "Because the whole they create has significant value." But it's equally clear that the relationship we claim exists between part and whole is very different from that between part and part when we say, "This part exists because that one couldn't exist without it." In the latter case, we assert that the two parts are causally linked; however, in the former, part and whole cannot be causally connected, and the relationship we say exists between them might exist even if the parts aren't causally linked either. All the parts of a picture do not share that mutual causal dependence, which some parts of the body do, yet the existence of those parts that don’t have it can still be crucial to the whole's value. The two relationships are fundamentally different, and we can't deduce the existence of one from the other. Thus, there's no point in grouping them under the same name; if we're going to say that a whole is organic because its parts are (in this sense) "means" to the whole, we must not say it is organic because its parts are causally dependent on one another.[p. 33]
22. But finally (3) the sense which has been most prominent in recent uses of the term ‘organic whole’ is one whereby it asserts the parts of such a whole to have a property which the parts of no whole can possibly have. It is supposed that just as the whole would not be what it is but for the existence of the parts, so the parts would not be what they are but for the existence of the whole; and this is understood to mean not merely that any particular part could not exist unless the others existed too (which is the case where relation (1) exists between the parts), but actually that the part is no distinct object of thought—that the whole, of which it is a part, is in its turn a part of it. That this supposition is self-contradictory a very little reflection should be sufficient to shew. We may admit, indeed, that when a particular thing is a part of a whole, it does possess a predicate which it would not otherwise possess—namely that it is a part of that whole. But what cannot be admitted is that this predicate alters the nature or enters into the definition of the thing which has it. When we think of the part itself, we mean just that which we assert, in this case, to have the predicate that it is part of the whole; and the mere assertion that it is a part of the whole involves that it should itself be distinct from that which we assert of it. Otherwise we contradict ourselves since we assert that, not it, but something else—namely it together with that which we assert of it—has the predicate which we assert of it. In short, it is obvious that no part contains analytically the whole to which it belongs, or any other parts of that whole. The relation of part to whole is not the same as that of whole to part; and the very definition[p. 34] of the latter is that it does contain analytically that which is said to be its part. And yet this very self-contradictory doctrine is the chief mark which shews the influence of Hegel upon modern philosophy—an influence which pervades almost the whole of orthodox philosophy. This is what is generally implied by the cry against falsification by abstraction: that a whole is always a part of its part! ‘If you want to know the truth about a part,’ we are told, ‘you must consider not that part, but something else—namely the whole: nothing is true of the part, but only of the whole.’ Yet plainly it must be true of the part at least that it is a part of the whole; and it is obvious that when we say it is, we do not mean merely that the whole is a part of itself. This doctrine, therefore, that a part can have ‘no meaning or significance apart from its whole’ must be utterly rejected. It implies itself that the statement ‘This is a part of that whole’ has a meaning; and in order that this may have one, both subject and predicate must have a distinct meaning. And it is easy to see how this false doctrine has arisen by confusion with the two relations (1) and (2) which may really be properties of wholes.
22. But finally (3) the idea that has come up most often in recent discussions of the term ‘organic whole’ is one that claims the parts of such a whole possess a property that no parts of any whole could possibly have. It is suggested that just as the whole wouldn’t be what it is without the existence of the parts, the parts wouldn’t be what they are without the existence of the whole; and this is understood to imply not just that a specific part couldn’t exist without the others (which is the case when relation (1) exists among the parts), but that the part itself isn’t a distinct object of thought—meaning the whole, which it is a part of, is also part of it. A little reflection should be enough to show that this assumption is self-contradictory. We can agree that when a specific thing is part of a whole, it does have a quality it wouldn’t have otherwise—specifically, that it is a part of that whole. However, what can’t be accepted is that this quality changes the nature of or becomes part of the definition of the thing that has it. When we think of the part itself, we refer to that which we assert, in this case, to have the quality of being part of the whole; and simply saying that it is part of the whole implies that it must be distinct from what we assert about it. Otherwise, we contradict ourselves since we claim that, not it, but something else—namely it along with what we assert about it—has the quality we claim for it. In short, it is clear that no part analytically contains the whole to which it belongs, or any other parts of that whole. The relationship of part to whole is not the same as that of whole to part; and the very definition[p. 34] of the latter is that it does analytically contain what is said to be its part. And yet this very self-contradictory idea is a key aspect that shows Hegel's influence on modern philosophy—an influence that permeates almost all mainstream philosophy. This is what is generally meant by the outcry against falsification through abstraction: that a whole is always part of its part! ‘If you want to know the truth about a part,’ we are told, ‘you must consider not that part, but something else—namely the whole: nothing is true of the part, but only of the whole.’ Yet, it must be true of the part at least that it is a part of the whole; and it is clear that when we say it is, we do not mean merely that the whole is part of itself. Therefore, this idea that a part can have ‘no meaning or significance apart from its whole’ must be completely rejected. It itself implies that the statement ‘This is a part of that whole’ has meaning; and for this to happen, both subject and predicate must have distinct meanings. It’s easy to see how this false idea has come about due to confusion with the two relations (1) and (2) that may actually be properties of wholes.
(a) The existence of a part may be connected by a natural or causal necessity with the existence of the other parts of its whole; and further what is a part of a whole and what has ceased to be such a part, although differing intrinsically from one another, may be called by one and the same name. Thus, to take a typical example, if an arm be cut off from the human body, we still call it an arm. Yet an arm, when it is a part of the body, undoubtedly differs from a dead arm: and hence we may easily be led to say ‘The arm which is a part of the body would not be what it is, if it were not such a part,’ and to think that the contradiction thus expressed is in reality a characteristic of things. But, in fact, the dead arm never was a part of the body; it is only partially identical with the living arm. Those parts of it which are identical with parts of the living arm are exactly the same, whether they belong to the body or not; and in them we have an undeniable instance of one and the same thing at one time forming a part, and at another not forming a part of the presumed ‘organic whole.[p. 35]’ On the other hand those properties which are possessed by the living, and not by the dead, arm, do not exist in a changed form in the latter: they simply do not exist there at all. By a causal necessity their existence depends on their having that relation to the other parts of the body which we express by saying that they form part of it. Yet, most certainly, if they ever did not form part of the body, they would be exactly what they are when they do. That they differ intrinsically from the properties of the dead arm and that they form part of the body are propositions not analytically related to one another. There is no contradiction in supposing them to retain such intrinsic differences and yet not to form part of the body.
(a) The existence of a part can be naturally or causally connected to the existence of the other parts of its whole; additionally, what defines a part of a whole and what has stopped being such a part, despite being fundamentally different, can be referred to by the same name. For example, if an arm is severed from the human body, we still call it an arm. However, an arm that is part of the body is clearly different from a dead arm: and this might lead us to say, ‘The arm that is part of the body wouldn't be what it is if it were not such a part,’ believing that this contradiction is actually a reflection of reality. In truth, the dead arm was never a part of the body; it is only partially identical to the living arm. The parts of it that are identical to parts of the living arm are exactly the same, whether they belong to the body or not; and here we have a clear example of something being a part at one time and not a part at another of the supposed ‘organic whole.[p. 35]’ On the other hand, the properties that the living arm has and the dead arm does not do not exist in a different form in the latter: they simply don’t exist there at all. Causally, their existence relies on their relationship to the other parts of the body, which we describe by saying they are part of it. Yet, if they ever did not form part of the body, they would be exactly what they are when they do. That they are fundamentally different from the properties of the dead arm and that they form part of the body are statements not analytically linked. There is no contradiction in assuming they maintain such intrinsic differences and still do not form part of the body.
But (b) when we are told that a living arm has no meaning or significance apart from the body to which it belongs, a different fallacy is also suggested. ‘To have meaning or significance’ is commonly used in the sense of ‘to have importance’; and this again means ‘to have value either as a means or as an end.’ Now it is quite possible that even a living arm, apart from its body, would have no intrinsic value whatever; although the whole of which it is a part has great intrinsic value owing to its presence. Thus we may easily come to say that, as a part of the body, it has great value, whereas by itself it would have none; and thus that its whole ‘meaning’ lies in its relation to the body. But in fact the value in question obviously does not belong to it at all. To have value merely as a part is equivalent to having no value at all, but merely being a part of that which has it. Owing, however, to neglect of this distinction, the assertion that a part has value, as a part, which it would not otherwise have, easily leads to the assumption that it is also different, as a part, from what it would otherwise be; for it is, in fact, true that two things which have a different value must also differ in other respects. Hence the assumption that one and the same thing, because it is a part of a more valuable whole at one time than at another, therefore has more intrinsic value at one time than at another, has encouraged the self-contradictory belief that one and the same thing may be two different things, and that only in one of its forms is it truly what it is.
But (b) when we are told that a living arm has no meaning or significance apart from the body it belongs to, a different misconception is also implied. ‘To have meaning or significance’ is often understood as ‘to have importance’; and this again means ‘to have value either as a means or as an end.’ Now it’s entirely possible that even a living arm, separate from its body, would have no intrinsic value whatsoever; although the whole that it is part of has great intrinsic value because of its existence. Thus we may easily say that, as a part of the body, it has great value, whereas by itself it would have none; and that its whole ‘meaning’ lies in its relationship to the body. But in reality, the value in question obviously does not belong to it at all. To have value only as a part is equivalent to having no value at all, but merely being a part of something that does. However, due to neglect of this distinction, the claim that a part has value, as a part, which it wouldn’t have otherwise, easily leads to the assumption that it is also different, as a part, from what it would be otherwise; for it is indeed true that two things which have different values must also vary in other ways. Hence, the assumption that one and the same thing, because it is part of a more valuable whole at one time than at another, therefore has more intrinsic value at one time compared to another, has fostered the contradictory belief that one and the same thing may be two different things, and that only in one of its forms is it truly what it is.
For these reasons, I shall, where it seems convenient, take[p. 36] the liberty to use the term ‘organic’ with a special sense. I shall use it to denote the fact that a whole has an intrinsic value different in amount from the sum of the values of its parts. I shall use it to denote this and only this. The term will not imply any causal relation whatever between the parts of the whole in question. And it will not imply either, that the parts are inconceivable except as parts of that whole, or that, when they form parts of such a whole, they have a value different from that which they would have if they did not. Understood in this special and perfectly definite sense the relation of an organic whole to its parts is one of the most important which Ethics has to recognise. A chief part of that science should be occupied in comparing the relative values of various goods; and the grossest errors will be committed in such comparison if it be assumed that wherever two things form a whole, the value of that whole is merely the sum of the values of those two things. With this question of ‘organic wholes,’ then, we complete the enumeration of the kind of problems, with which it is the business of Ethics to deal.
For these reasons, I will, where it seems appropriate, take the liberty to use the term ‘organic’ in a specific way. I will use it to indicate that a whole has an intrinsic value that is different from the sum of the values of its parts. I will use it to denote this and only this. The term will not imply any causal relationship between the parts of the whole in question. Nor will it suggest that the parts can only be understood as parts of that whole, or that when they are part of such a whole, they have a different value than they would have if they were separate. Understood in this specific and clear sense, the relationship of an organic whole to its parts is one of the most important aspects that Ethics must acknowledge. A key part of that field should focus on comparing the relative values of various goods; significant mistakes will occur in such comparisons if it is assumed that whenever two things create a whole, the value of that whole is simply the sum of the values of those two things. With this issue of ‘organic wholes,’ we conclude the list of problems that Ethics is concerned with.
23. In this chapter I have endeavoured to enforce the following conclusions. (1) The peculiarity of Ethics is not that it investigates assertions about human conduct, but that it investigates assertions about that property of things which is denoted by the term ‘good,’ and the converse property denoted by the term ‘bad.’ It must, in order to establish its conclusions, investigate the truth of all such assertions, except those which assert the relation of this property only to a single existent (1-4). (2) This property, by reference to which the subject-matter of Ethics must be defined, is itself simple and indefinable (5-14). And (3) all assertions about its relation to other things are of two, and only two, kinds: they either assert in what degree things themselves possess this property, or else they assert causal relations between other things and those which possess it (15-17). Finally, (4) in considering the different degrees in which things themselves possess this property, we have to take account of the fact that a whole may possess it in a degree different from that which is obtained by summing the degrees in which its parts possess it (18-22).
23. In this chapter, I have aimed to emphasize the following conclusions. (1) The unique aspect of Ethics is not that it examines statements about human behavior, but that it explores statements about what we call 'good' and its opposite, 'bad.' To support its conclusions, it must investigate the truth of all such statements, except those that only refer to the relationship of this property to a single entity (1-4). (2) This property, which is essential for defining the subject matter of Ethics, is itself simple and cannot be clearly defined (5-14). And (3) all statements about its relationship to other things fall into two, and only two, categories: they either state to what extent things have this property, or they describe causal relationships between other things and those that have it (15-17). Finally, (4) when considering the various degrees to which things possess this property, we need to recognize that a whole may possess it at a level different from the total gained by adding the degrees of its parts (18-22).
[p. 37]
[p. 37]
CHAPTER II.
NATURALISTIC ETHICS.
Naturalistic ethics.
24. It results from the conclusions of Chapter I, that all ethical questions fall under one or other of three classes. The first class contains but one question—the question What is the nature of that peculiar predicate, the relation of which to other things constitutes the object of all other ethical investigations? or, in other words, What is meant by good? This first question I have already attempted to answer. The peculiar predicate, by reference to which the sphere of Ethics must be defined, is simple, unanalysable, indefinable. There remain two classes of questions with regard to the relation of this predicate to other things. We may ask either (1) To what things and in what degree does this predicate directly attach? What things are good in themselves? or (2) By what means shall we be able to make what exists in the world as good as possible? What causal relations hold between what is best in itself and other things?
24. It follows from the conclusions of Chapter I that all ethical questions can be grouped into one of three categories. The first category contains just one question—the question of what is the nature of that unique concept, the relationship of which to other things forms the basis of all ethical inquiries? In other words, what do we mean by good? I have already tried to answer this first question. The unique concept, which defines the scope of Ethics, is simple, cannot be broken down, and is impossible to define. There are two more categories of questions regarding how this concept relates to other things. We can ask either (1) What things does this concept apply to, and to what extent? What things are good in themselves? or (2) How can we make what exists in the world as good as possible? What causal connections are there between what is best in itself and other things?
In this and the two following chapters, I propose to discuss certain theories, which offer us an answer to the question What is good in itself? I say advisedly—an answer: for these theories are all characterised by the fact that, if true, they would simplify the study of Ethics very much. They all hold that there is only one kind of fact, of which the existence has any value at all. But they all also possess another characteristic, which is my reason for grouping them together and treating them first: namely that the main reason why the single kind of fact they name has been held to define the sole good, is that it has been[p. 38] held to define what is meant by ‘good’ itself. In other words they are all theories of the end or ideal, the adoption of which has been chiefly caused by the commission of what I have called the naturalistic fallacy: they all confuse the first and second of the three possible questions which Ethics can ask. It is, indeed, this fact which explains their contention that only a single kind of thing is good. That a thing should be good, it has been thought, means that it possesses this single property: and hence (it is thought) only what possesses this property is good. The inference seems very natural; and yet what is meant by it is self-contradictory. For those who make it fail to perceive that their conclusion ‘what possesses this property is good’ is a significant proposition: that it does not mean either ‘what possesses this property, possesses this property’ or ‘the word “good” denotes that a thing possesses this property.’ And yet, if it does not mean one or other of these two things, the inference contradicts its own premise.
In this chapter and the next two, I plan to talk about certain theories that answer the question: What is good in itself? I say “an” answer because these theories all share the idea that if they are true, they would make studying Ethics much simpler. They all claim there is only one kind of fact that has any value at all. However, they also share another trait, which is why I’m discussing them first: the main reason this one type of fact is thought to define the only good is that it’s been taken to define what ‘good’ really means. In other words, they are all theories about the end or ideal, which have mostly arisen because of what I call the naturalistic fallacy: they all mix up the first and second of the three possible questions Ethics can ask. This confusion is what leads them to argue that only one kind of thing is good. It has been believed that for something to be good means it has this one property: so only things with that property are good. The conclusion seems very reasonable, yet it is self-contradictory. Those who draw this conclusion fail to recognize that the statement ‘what possesses this property is good’ is a meaningful assertion: it does not mean either ‘what possesses this property possesses this property’ or ‘the word “good” indicates that a thing has this property.’ And yet, if it does not mean one of those two things, the conclusion contradicts its own premise.
I propose, therefore, to discuss certain theories of what is good in itself, which are based on the naturalistic fallacy, in the sense that the commission of this fallacy has been the main cause of their wide acceptance. The discussion will be designed both (1) further to illustrate the fact that the naturalistic fallacy is a fallacy, or, in other words, that we are all aware of a certain simple quality, which (and not anything else) is what we mainly mean by the term ‘good’; and (2) to shew that not one, but many different things, possess this property. For I cannot hope to recommend the doctrine that things which are good do not owe their goodness to their common possession of any other property, without a criticism of the main doctrines, opposed to this, whose power to recommend themselves is proved by their wide prevalence.
I propose to discuss some theories about what is good in itself, which are based on the naturalistic fallacy, meaning that this fallacy has been the main reason for their widespread acceptance. The discussion aims to (1) further illustrate that the naturalistic fallacy is indeed a fallacy, or, in other words, that we all recognize a specific simple quality that is primarily what we mean by the term ‘good’; and (2) show that not just one, but many different things have this quality. I cannot hope to support the idea that things that are good do not derive their goodness from sharing any other characteristic, without critiquing the main doctrines that oppose this view, whose ability to gain acceptance is evidenced by their widespread popularity.
25. The theories I propose to discuss may be conveniently divided into two groups. The naturalistic fallacy always implies that when we think ‘This is good,’ what we are thinking is that the thing in question bears a definite relation to some one other thing. But this one thing, by reference to which good is defined, may be either what I may call a natural object—something of which the existence is admittedly an object of experience—or[p. 39] else it may be an object which is only inferred to exist in a supersensible real world. These two types of ethical theory I propose to treat separately. Theories of the second type may conveniently be called ‘metaphysical,’ and I shall postpone consideration of them till Chapter IV. In this and the following chapter, on the other hand, I shall deal with theories which owe their prevalence to the supposition that good can be defined by reference to a natural object; and these are what I mean by the name, which gives the title to this chapter, ‘Naturalistic Ethics.’ It should be observed that the fallacy, by reference to which I define ‘Metaphysical Ethics,’ is the same in kind; and I give it but one name, the naturalistic fallacy. But when we regard the ethical theories recommended by this fallacy, it seems convenient to distinguish those which consider goodness to consist in a relation to something which exists here and now, from those which do not. According to the former, Ethics is an empirical or positive science: its conclusions could be all established by means of empirical observation and induction. But this is not the case with Metaphysical Ethics. There is, therefore, a marked distinction between these two groups of ethical theories based on the same fallacy. And within Naturalistic theories, too, a convenient division may also be made. There is one natural object, namely pleasure, which has perhaps been as frequently held to be the sole good as all the rest put together. And there is, moreover, a further reason for treating Hedonism separately. That doctrine has, I think, as plainly as any other, owed its prevalence to the naturalistic fallacy; but it has had a singular fate in that the writer, who first clearly exposed the fallacy of the naturalistic arguments by which it had been attempted to prove that pleasure was the sole good, has maintained that nevertheless it is the sole good. I propose, therefore, to divide my discussion of Hedonism from that of other Naturalistic theories; treating of Naturalistic Ethics in general in this chapter, and of Hedonism, in particular, in the next.
25. The theories I plan to discuss can be grouped into two categories. The naturalistic fallacy suggests that when we say ‘This is good,’ we’re indicating that the thing in question has a specific connection to another thing. This other thing, which defines what is good, could be either a natural object—something we can experience—or[p. 39] an object that we believe to exist in a non-physical reality. I intend to address these two types of ethical theories separately. Theories of the second kind can be called ‘metaphysical,’ and I will set them aside until Chapter IV. In this chapter and the next, I will focus on theories that believe good can be defined in terms of a natural object; this is what I refer to as ‘Naturalistic Ethics,’ which gives this chapter its title. It's important to note that the fallacy underlying ‘Metaphysical Ethics’ is similar, and I will refer to it as the naturalistic fallacy. However, when we consider the ethical theories influenced by this fallacy, it’s useful to differentiate between those that view goodness as related to something that exists in the present and those that don’t. According to the first group, Ethics is an empirical or positive science: its conclusions can be established through observation and induction. This isn’t true for Metaphysical Ethics. Thus, there is a clear distinction between these two groups of ethical theories that stem from the same fallacy. Within Naturalistic theories, we can also make a useful distinction. One natural object, pleasure, has often been regarded as the only good, as much as all others combined. Additionally, there’s another reason to discuss Hedonism separately. This doctrine, like others, gained traction due to the naturalistic fallacy; however, it has an interesting twist in that the writer who first clearly pointed out the flaws in the naturalistic arguments claiming that pleasure was the sole good also argued that it indeed is the sole good. Therefore, I will separate my discussion of Hedonism from that of other Naturalistic theories, addressing Naturalistic Ethics in general here and specifically focusing on Hedonism in the next chapter.
26. The subject of the present chapter is, then, ethical theories which declare that no intrinsic value is to be found except in the possession of some one natural property, other than pleasure; and which declare this because it is supposed that to[p. 40] be ‘good’ means to possess the property in question. Such theories I call ‘Naturalistic.’ I have thus appropriated the name Naturalism to a particular method of approaching Ethics—a method which, strictly understood, is inconsistent with the possibility of any Ethics whatsoever. This method consists in substituting for ‘good’ some one property of a natural object or of a collection of natural objects; and in thus replacing Ethics by some one of the natural sciences. In general, the science thus substituted is one of the sciences specially concerned with man, owing to the general mistake (for such I hold it to be) of regarding the matter of Ethics as confined to human conduct. In general, Psychology has been the science substituted, as by J. S. Mill; or Sociology, as by Professor Clifford, and other modern writers. But any other science might equally well be substituted. It is the same fallacy which is implied, when Professor Tyndall recommends us to ‘conform to the laws of matter’: and here the science which it is proposed to substitute for Ethics is simply Physics. The name then is perfectly general; for, no matter what the something is that good is held to mean, the theory is still Naturalism. Whether good be defined as yellow or green or blue, as loud or soft, as round or square, as sweet or bitter, as productive of life or productive of pleasure, as willed or desired or felt: whichever of these or of any other object in the world, good may be held to mean, the theory, which holds it to mean them, will be a naturalistic theory. I have called such theories naturalistic because all of these terms denote properties, simple or complex, of some simple or complex natural object; and, before I proceed to consider them, it will be well to define what is meant by ‘nature’ and by ‘natural objects.’
26. This chapter discusses ethical theories that claim intrinsic value is found only in the possession of a specific natural property, excluding pleasure. These theories assert that being ‘good’ means having that particular property. I refer to these theories as 'Naturalistic.' I've adopted the term Naturalism to describe a specific approach to Ethics—an approach that ultimately contradicts the very possibility of Ethics existing at all. This method involves replacing 'good' with a specific property of a natural object or a group of natural objects, effectively transforming Ethics into a branch of a natural science. Generally, the science used as a substitute is one that focuses on humans, due to the common misconception (which I consider a misunderstanding) that Ethics is limited to human behavior. Typically, Psychology has been the science used for this purpose, as in the case of J. S. Mill; or Sociology, as suggested by Professor Clifford and other contemporary writers. However, any science could be substituted. The same fallacy is evident when Professor Tyndall advises us to ‘conform to the laws of matter’; here, the proposed substitute for Ethics is simply Physics. The term is therefore quite broad; regardless of what 'good' is said to represent, the theory remains Naturalism. Whether 'good' is defined as yellow, green, blue, loud, soft, round, square, sweet, bitter, life-producing, pleasure-producing, willed, desired, or felt: whatever object in the world 'good' is thought to represent, the theory that claims it represents them is a naturalistic theory. I've labeled these theories naturalistic because all of these terms indicate properties, whether simple or complex, of some simple or complex natural object; and before I proceed to analyze them, it’s important to clarify what is meant by ‘nature’ and ‘natural objects.’
By ‘nature,’ then, I do mean and have meant that which is the subject-matter of the natural sciences and also of psychology. It may be said to include all that has existed, does exist, or will exist in time. If we consider whether any object is of such a nature that it may be said to exist now, to have existed, or to be about to exist, then we may know that that object is a natural object, and that nothing, of which this is not true, is a natural object. Thus for instance, of our minds we should say that they did exist yesterday, that they do exist to-day, and[p. 41] probably will exist in a minute or two. We shall say that we had thoughts yesterday, which have ceased to exist now, although their effects may remain: and in so far as those thoughts did exist, they too are natural objects.
By "nature," I mean what is studied in the natural sciences and psychology. It includes everything that has ever existed, exists now, or will exist in the future. If we think about whether something can be said to exist now, have existed, or be about to exist, we can understand that it is a natural object; if it doesn't fit this description, then it isn't a natural object. For example, we can say our minds existed yesterday, they exist today, and probably will exist in a minute or two. We might say that we had thoughts yesterday that no longer exist, even though their effects might still be around; and since those thoughts did exist, they too are natural objects.
There is, indeed, no difficulty about the ‘objects’ themselves, in the sense in which I have just used the term. It is easy to say which of them are natural, and which (if any) are not natural. But when we begin to consider the properties of objects, then I fear the problem is more difficult. Which among the properties of natural objects are natural properties and which are not? For I do not deny that good is a property of certain natural objects: certain of them, I think, are good; and yet I have said that ‘good’ itself is not a natural property. Well, my test for these too also concerns their existence in time. Can we imagine ‘good’ as existing by itself in time, and not merely as a property of some natural object? For myself, I cannot so imagine it, whereas with the greater number of properties of objects—those which I call the natural properties—their existence does seem to me to be independent of the existence of those objects. They are, in fact, rather parts of which the object is made up than mere predicates which attach to it. If they were all taken away, no object would be left, not even a bare substance: for they are in themselves substantial and give to the object all the substance that it has. But this is not so with good. If indeed good were a feeling, as some would have us believe, then it would exist in time. But that is why to call it so is to commit the naturalistic fallacy. It will always remain pertinent to ask, whether the feeling itself is good; and if so, then good cannot itself be identical with any feeling.
There’s really no issue with the ‘objects’ themselves, in the way I just used the term. It’s easy to tell which ones are natural and which (if any) are not natural. But when we start looking at the properties of objects, I worry the problem gets trickier. Which properties of natural objects are natural properties, and which are not? I don’t deny that good is a property of certain natural objects: some of them, I believe, are good; yet I’ve also said that ‘good’ itself isn’t a natural property. My test for these also relates to their existence in time. Can we imagine ‘good’ existing by itself in time, and not just as a property of some natural object? I can’t see it that way, while most of the properties of objects—those I call natural properties—do seem to exist independently of those objects. They’re more like parts that make up the object rather than just descriptors attached to it. If all of them were removed, no object would remain, not even a bare substance: they are substantial in themselves and give the object all its substance. But that’s not the case with good. If good were indeed a feeling, as some claim, then it would exist in time. But that’s why calling it such is the naturalistic fallacy. It’s always relevant to ask whether the feeling itself is good; and if so, then good can’t be identical to any feeling.
27. Those theories of Ethics, then, are ‘naturalistic’ which declare the sole good to consist in some one property of things, which exists in time; and which do so because they suppose that ‘good’ itself can be defined by reference to such a property. And we may now proceed to consider such theories.
27. Ethical theories that are considered ‘naturalistic’ claim that the only good is found in a specific property of things that exists in time, and they do this because they believe that ‘good’ can be defined by referring to that property. Now, we can move on to examine these theories.
And, first of all, one of the most famous of ethical maxims is that which recommends a ‘life according to nature.’ That was the principle of the Stoic Ethics; but, since their Ethics[p. 42] has some claim to be called metaphysical, I shall not attempt to deal with it here. But the same phrase reappears in Rousseau; and it is not unfrequently maintained even now that what we ought to do is to live naturally. Now let us examine this contention in its general form. It is obvious, in the first place, that we cannot say that everything natural is good, except perhaps in virtue of some metaphysical theory, such as I shall deal with later. If everything natural is equally good, then certainly Ethics, as it is ordinarily understood, disappears: for nothing is more certain, from an ethical point of view, than that some things are bad and others good; the object of Ethics is, indeed, in chief part, to give you general rules whereby you may avoid the one and secure the other. What, then, does ‘natural’ mean, in this advice to live naturally, since it obviously cannot apply to everything that is natural?
And, first of all, one of the most well-known ethical principles is the idea of a ‘life according to nature.’ This was the foundation of Stoic Ethics; however, since their Ethics[p. 42] can be somewhat considered metaphysical, I won’t delve into it here. The same phrase appears in Rousseau, and it is still often argued today that we should live naturally. Now let’s examine this claim in its general form. It is clear, to begin with, that we can’t say everything natural is good, unless perhaps based on some metaphysical theory, which I will discuss later. If everything natural is equally good, then certainly Ethics, as it is generally understood, ceases to exist: for nothing is more certain, from an ethical standpoint, than that some things are bad and others are good; the main purpose of Ethics is, indeed, to provide you with general rules to help you avoid the bad and secure the good. So, what does ‘natural’ really mean in this advice to live naturally, since it clearly doesn’t apply to everything that is natural?
The phrase seems to point to a vague notion that there is some such thing as natural good; to a belief that Nature may be said to fix and decide what shall be good, just as she fixes and decides what shall exist. For instance, it may be supposed that ‘health’ is susceptible of a natural definition, that Nature has fixed what health shall be: and health, it may be said, is obviously good; hence in this case Nature has decided the matter; we have only to go to her and ask her what health is, and we shall know what is good: we shall have based an ethics upon science. But what is this natural definition of health? I can only conceive that health should be defined in natural terms as the normal state of an organism for undoubtedly disease is also a natural product. To say that health is what is preserved by evolution, and what itself tends to preserve, in the struggle for existence, the organism which possesses it, comes to the same thing: for the point of evolution is that it pretends to give a causal explanation of why some forms of life are normal and others are abnormal; it explains the origin of species. When therefore we are told that health is natural, we may presume that what is meant is that it is normal; and that when we are told to pursue health as a natural end, what is implied is that the normal[p. 43] must be good. But is it so obvious that the normal must be good? Is it really obvious that health, for instance, is good? Was the excellence of Socrates or of Shakespeare normal? Was it not rather abnormal, extraordinary? It is, I think, obvious in the first place, that not all that is good is normal; that, on the contrary, the abnormal is often better than the normal: peculiar excellence, as well as peculiar viciousness, must obviously be not normal but abnormal. Yet it may be said that nevertheless the normal is good; and I myself am not prepared to dispute that health is good. What I contend is that this must not be taken to be obvious; that it must be regarded as an open question. To declare it to be obvious is to suggest the naturalistic fallacy: just as, in some recent books, a proof that genius is diseased, abnormal, has been used in order to suggest that genius ought not to be encouraged. Such reasoning is fallacious, and dangerously fallacious. The fact is that in the very words ‘health’ and ‘disease’ we do commonly include the notion that the one is good and the other bad. But, when a so-called scientific definition of them is attempted, a definition in natural terms, the only one possible is that by way of ‘normal’ and ‘abnormal.’ Now, it is easy to prove that some things commonly thought excellent are abnormal; and it follows that they are diseased. But it does not follow, except by virtue of the naturalistic fallacy, that those things, commonly thought good, are therefore bad. All that has really been shewn is that in some cases there is a conflict between the common judgment that genius is good, and the common judgment that health is good. It is not sufficiently recognised that the latter judgment has not a whit more warrant for its truth than the former; that both are perfectly open questions. It may be true, indeed, that by ‘healthy’ we do commonly imply ‘good’; but that only shews that when we so use the word, we do not mean the same thing by it as the thing which is meant in medical science. That health, when the word is used to denote something good, is good, goes no way at all to shew that health, when the word is used to denote something normal, is also good. We might as well say that, because ‘bull’ denotes an Irish joke and[p. 44] also a certain animal, the joke and the animal must be the same thing. We must not, therefore, be frightened by the assertion that a thing is natural into the admission that it is good; good does not, by definition, mean anything that is natural; and it is therefore always an open question whether anything that is natural is good.
The phrase seems to suggest a vague idea that there is such a thing as natural good; that Nature might determine what is good, just as she determines what exists. For example, it could be argued that ‘health’ has a natural definition, that Nature has defined what health should be: and health is clearly good; thus in this case, Nature has made the decision; we simply need to consult her to find out what health is, and we’ll know what is good: we would essentially be establishing an ethics based on science. But what is this natural definition of health? I can only think that health could be defined in natural terms as the normal state of an organism since disease is also a natural occurrence. To claim that health is what evolution preserves, and what tends to support the survival of the organism possessing it, amounts to the same thing: because the essence of evolution is that it aims to provide a causal explanation for why some forms of life are considered normal and others abnormal; it explains the origins of species. Therefore, when we are told that health is natural, we can assume it means that it is normal; and when we are encouraged to pursue health as a natural goal, it implies that what is normal must be good. However, is it so clear that the normal must be good? Is it really evident that health, for instance, is good? Was the greatness of Socrates or Shakespeare normal? Wasn’t it rather abnormal, extraordinary? It seems clear to me, first of all, that not everything good is normal; in fact, the abnormal is often better than the normal: unique excellence, as well as unique viciousness, must clearly be seen as abnormal rather than normal. Yet, one might argue that the normal is still good; and I’m not ready to dispute that health is good. What I argue is that this shouldn’t be assumed as obvious; it should be treated as an open question. To claim it is obvious suggests the naturalistic fallacy: just as, in some recent writings, a claim that genius is diseased, abnormal, has been used to imply that genius should not be nurtured. Such reasoning is flawed and quite dangerous. The truth is that in the very words ‘health’ and ‘disease’ we usually carry the idea that one is good and the other bad. However, when trying to define them scientifically in natural terms, the only possible definition is through ‘normal’ and ‘abnormal.’ Now, it’s easy to demonstrate that some things commonly considered excellent are abnormal; and this leads to the idea that they are diseased. But it doesn’t follow, except through the naturalistic fallacy, that those things commonly thought of as good are therefore bad. All that has really been shown is that in some cases there is a conflict between the common belief that genius is good and the common belief that health is good. It is not sufficiently recognized that this latter belief does not have any more justification for its truth than the former; that both are genuinely open questions. It may be true, indeed, that by ‘healthy’ we typically imply ‘good’; but that only shows that when we use the word, we do not mean the same thing as what is meant in medical science. That health, when the term is used to refer to something good, is good, does not prove that health, when used to describe something normal, is also good. We might as well say that, because ‘bull’ refers to an Irish joke and[p. 44] also to a specific animal, the joke and the animal must be the same. Therefore, we should not be intimidated by the assertion that something is natural into accepting that it is good; good does not, by definition, mean anything that is natural; and it remains an open question whether anything that is natural is good.
28. But there is another slightly different sense in which the word ‘natural’ is used with an implication that it denotes something good. This is when we speak of natural affections, or unnatural crimes and vices. Here the meaning seems to be, not so much that the action or feeling in question is normal or abnormal, as that it is necessary. It is in this connection that we are advised to imitate savages and beasts. Curious advice certainly; but, of course, there may be something in it. I am not here concerned to enquire under what circumstances some of us might with advantage take a lesson from the cow. I have really no doubt that such exist. What I am concerned with is a certain kind of reason, which I think is sometimes used to support this doctrine—a naturalistic reason. The notion sometimes lying at the bottom of the minds of preachers of this gospel is that we cannot improve on nature. This notion is certainly true, in the sense that anything we can do, that may be better than the present state of things, will be a natural product. But that is not what is meant by this phrase; nature is again used to mean a mere part of nature; only this time the part meant is not so much the normal as an arbitrary minimum of what is necessary for life. And when this minimum is recommended as ‘natural’—as the way of life to which Nature points her finger—then the naturalistic fallacy is used. Against this position I wish only to point out that though the performance of certain acts, not in themselves desirable, may be excused as necessary means to the preservation of life, that is no reason for praising them, or advising us to limit ourselves to those simple actions which are necessary, if it is possible for us to improve our condition even at the expense of doing what is in this sense unnecessary. Nature does indeed set limits to what is possible; she does control the means we have at our disposal for obtaining what is good;[p. 45] and of this fact, practical Ethics, as we shall see later, must certainly take account: but when she is supposed to have a preference for what is necessary, what is necessary means only what is necessary to obtain a certain end, presupposed as the highest good; and what the highest good is Nature cannot determine. Why should we suppose that what is merely necessary to life is ipso facto better than what is necessary to the study of metaphysics, useless as that study may appear? It may be that life is only worth living, because it enables us to study metaphysics—is a necessary means thereto. The fallacy of this argument from nature has been discovered as long ago as Lucian. ‘I was almost inclined to laugh,’ says Callicratidas, in one of the dialogues imputed to him[4], ‘just now, when Charicles was praising irrational brutes and the savagery of the Scythians: in the heat of his argument he was almost repenting that he was born a Greek. What wonder if lions and bears and pigs do not act as I was proposing? That which reasoning would fairly lead a man to choose, cannot be had by creatures that do not reason, simply because they are so stupid. If Prometheus or some other god had given each of them the intelligence of a man, then they would not have lived in deserts and mountains nor fed on one another. They would have built temples just as we do, each would have lived in the centre of his family, and they would have formed a nation bound by mutual laws. Is it anything surprising that brutes, who have had the misfortune to be unable to obtain by forethought any of the goods, with which reasoning provides us, should have missed love too? Lions do not love; but neither do they philosophise; bears do not love; but the reason is they do not know the sweets of friendship. It is only men, who, by their wisdom and their knowledge, after many trials, have chosen what is best.’
28. But there is another slightly different sense in which the word ‘natural’ is used, implying that it refers to something good. This is when we talk about natural affections or unnatural crimes and vices. Here, the meaning seems to be less about whether the action or feeling is normal or abnormal, and more about whether it’s necessary. In this context, we get advice to imitate savages and animals. It’s certainly odd advice; but there could be some truth in it. I’m not here to explore under what circumstances some of us might benefit from learning from cows. I have no doubt that such situations exist. What I am focused on is a specific kind of reasoning that sometimes underpins this idea—a naturalistic reasoning. The idea often lurking in the minds of those promoting this belief is that we cannot improve upon nature. This idea is true in the sense that anything we do that might be better than the current state of affairs will be a natural outcome. But that isn’t what this phrase means; nature is again understood as merely a part of nature; this time, it refers not so much to what is normal, but to an arbitrary minimum of what is essential for life. When this minimum is presented as ‘natural’—as the way of life that Nature endorses—then the naturalistic fallacy is at play. Against this viewpoint, I simply want to point out that although performing certain actions, which are not desirable in themselves, may be excused as necessary for preserving life, that doesn’t mean we should praise them or suggest that we limit ourselves to those basic actions that are necessary, especially if we can enhance our condition even if it means doing what is, in this sense, unnecessary. Nature indeed places limits on what is possible; she controls the means we have available to achieve what is good;[p. 45] and practical Ethics, as we will see later, must account for this fact. But when it is assumed that she has a preference for what is necessary, what is necessary is defined solely as what is essential for achieving a certain goal, which is assumed to be the highest good; and what the highest good is, Nature cannot decide. Why should we assume that what is merely necessary for life is ipso facto better than what is required for the study of metaphysics, no matter how useless that study may seem? It could be that life is only worth living because it allows us to study metaphysics—is a necessary means to that end. The fallacy of this argument from nature has been acknowledged since the time of Lucian. ‘I was almost inclined to laugh,’ says Callicratidas, in one of the dialogues attributed to him[4], ‘just now, when Charicles was praising irrational creatures and the savagery of the Scythians: in his enthusiasm, he was practically regretting that he was born a Greek. What’s surprising if lions and bears and pigs don’t behave as I suggested? What reason would lead a man to choose, cannot be pursued by creatures that don’t reason simply because they lack understanding. If Prometheus or some other god had granted each of them human intelligence, they wouldn’t dwell in deserts and mountains or feed on each other. They would have built temples just like we do, each would live at the center of their family, and they would have formed a nation bound by mutual laws. Is it surprising that animals, which have been unfortunate enough not to obtain the blessings that reasoning provides, would miss out on love too? Lions don’t love; but they also don’t philosophize; bears don’t love; but that’s because they don’t know the joys of friendship. It’s only humans, who through their wisdom and knowledge, after many trials, have chosen what is best.’
29. To argue that a thing is good because it is ‘natural,’ or bad because it is ‘unnatural,’ in these common senses of the term, is therefore certainly fallacious: and yet such arguments are very frequently used. But they do not commonly pretend to give a systematic theory of Ethics. Among attempts to[p. 46] systematise an appeal to nature, that which is now most prevalent is to be found in the application to ethical questions of the term ‘Evolution’—in the ethical doctrines which have been called ‘Evolutionistic.’ These doctrines are those which maintain that the course of ‘evolution,’ while it shews us the direction in which we are developing, thereby and for that reason shews us the direction in which we ought to develop. Writers, who maintain such a doctrine, are at present very numerous and very popular; and I propose to take as my example the writer, who is perhaps the best known of them all—Mr Herbert Spencer. Mr Spencer’s doctrine, it must be owned, does not offer the clearest example of the naturalistic fallacy as used in support of Evolutionistic Ethics. A clearer example might be found in the doctrine of Guyau[5], a writer who has lately had considerable vogue in France, but who is not so well known as Spencer. Guyau might almost be called a disciple of Spencer; he is frankly evolutionistic, and frankly naturalistic; and I may mention that he does not seem to think that he differs from Spencer by reason of his naturalism. The point in which he has criticised Spencer concerns the question how far the ends of ‘pleasure’ and of ‘increased life’ coincide as motives and means to the attainment of the ideal: he does not seem to think that he differs from Spencer in the fundamental principle that the ideal is ‘Quantity of life, measured in breadth as well as in length,’ or, as Guyau says, ‘Expansion and intensity of life’; nor in the naturalistic reason which he gives for this principle. And I am not sure that he does differ from Spencer in these points. Spencer does, as I shall shew, use the naturalistic fallacy in details; but with regard to his fundamental principles, the following doubts occur: Is he fundamentally a Hedonist? And, if so, is he a naturalistic Hedonist? In that case he would better have been treated in my next chapter. Does he hold that a tendency to increase quantity of life is merely a criterion of good conduct? Or does he hold that such increase of life is marked out by nature as an end at which we ought to aim?
29. Arguing that something is good because it is ‘natural’ or bad because it is ‘unnatural’—in these common interpretations of the terms—is definitely flawed. However, such arguments are often used. They usually don’t claim to provide a systematic theory of Ethics. Among the attempts to [p. 46] systematize a natural appeal, the most prevalent today is the application of the term ‘Evolution’ to ethical questions—in what are called ‘Evolutionistic’ ethical theories. These doctrines argue that the path of ‘evolution’ not only shows us the direction in which we are developing but also indicates the direction in which we ought to develop. Presently, there are many writers who support this view, and they are quite popular; I will take as my example the writer who is perhaps the best known of them all—Mr. Herbert Spencer. It's important to note that Mr. Spencer's doctrine does not provide the clearest example of the naturalistic fallacy in support of Evolutionistic Ethics. A clearer example can be found in the work of Guyau—who has recently gained considerable popularity in France but is not as well known as Spencer. Guyau can almost be considered a follower of Spencer; he is openly evolutionistic and naturalistic. It’s worth mentioning that he doesn’t seem to believe he differs from Spencer due to his naturalism. His criticism of Spencer revolves around how the goals of ‘pleasure’ and ‘increased life’ overlap as motivations and means to achieve the ideal: he does not appear to think he diverges from Spencer’s core belief that the ideal is ‘Quantity of life, measured in breadth as well as in length,’ or, as Guyau puts it, ‘Expansion and intensity of life’; nor in the naturalistic rationale he provides for this principle. I’m not entirely convinced that he does differ from Spencer on these points. Spencer does, as I will demonstrate, employ the naturalistic fallacy in specific details; but concerning his fundamental principles, several doubts arise: Is he fundamentally a Hedonist? And, if he is, does he conform to a naturalistic Hedonism? In that case, he should have been discussed in my next chapter. Does he believe that a tendency to increase life’s quantity is merely a criterion of good conduct? Or does he assert that such an increase in life is defined by nature as an end we should strive for?
I think his language in various places would give colour to[p. 47] all these hypotheses; though some of them are mutually inconsistent. I will try to discuss the main points.
I think his language in several instances would add depth to[p. 47] all these theories; although some of them contradict each other. I'll attempt to go over the key points.
30. The modern vogue of ‘Evolution’ is chiefly owing to Darwin’s investigations as to the origin of species. Darwin formed a strictly biological hypothesis as to the manner in which certain forms of animal life became established, while others died out and disappeared. His theory was that this might be accounted for, partly at least, in the following way. When certain varieties occurred (the cause of their occurrence is still, in the main, unknown), it might be that some of the points, in which they varied from their parent species or from other species then existing, made them better able to persist in the environment in which they found themselves—less liable to be killed off. They might, for instance, be better able to endure the cold or heat or changes of the climate; better able to find nourishment from what surrounded them; better able to escape from or resist other species which fed upon them; better fitted to attract or to master the other sex. Being thus less liable to die, their numbers relatively to other species would increase; and that very increase in their numbers might tend towards the extinction of those other species. This theory, to which Darwin gave the name ‘Natural Selection,’ was also called the theory of survival of the fittest. The natural process which it thus described was called evolution. It was very natural to suppose that evolution meant evolution from what was lower into what was higher; in fact it was observed that at least one species, commonly called higher—the species man—had so survived, and among men again it was supposed that the higher races, ourselves for example, had shewn a tendency to survive the lower, such as the North American Indians. We can kill them more easily than they can kill us. The doctrine of evolution was then represented as an explanation of how the higher species survives the lower. Spencer, for example, constantly uses ‘more evolved’ as equivalent to ‘higher.’ But it is to be noted that this forms no part of Darwin’s scientific theory. That theory will explain, equally well, how by an alteration in the environment (the gradual cooling of the earth, for example) quite a different species from man, a species which we think[p. 48] infinitely lower, might survive us. The survival of the fittest does not mean, as one might suppose, the survival of what is fittest to fulfil a good purpose best adapted to a good end: at the last, it means merely the survival of the fittest to survive; and the value of the scientific theory, and it is a theory of great value, just consists in shewing what are the causes which produce certain biological effects. Whether these effects are good or bad, it cannot pretend to judge.
30. The current popularity of 'Evolution' is mainly due to Darwin’s research on the origin of species. Darwin developed a strictly biological hypothesis about how some forms of animal life became established while others went extinct. He theorized that this could be explained, at least in part, in the following way. When certain varieties appeared (the reason for their appearance remains largely unknown), it might be that some of the traits in which they differed from their parent species or other existing species helped them survive better in their environment—making them less likely to be eliminated. For example, they might be better able to endure cold or heat or changes in climate; find nourishment more effectively from their surroundings; escape from or resist predators; or attract or dominate the opposite sex. Being less likely to die, their numbers compared to other species would increase, and this increase could contribute to the extinction of those other species. This theory, which Darwin labeled 'Natural Selection,' is also referred to as the survival of the fittest. The natural process it describes is called evolution. It was logical to assume that evolution meant progressing from lower forms to higher ones; in fact, it was observed that at least one species, commonly considered higher—the human species—had survived, and among humans, it was believed that higher races, ourselves for instance, tended to survive the lower ones, like the North American Indians. We can eliminate them more easily than they can eliminate us. The idea of evolution was then presented as an explanation of how higher species outlast lower ones. Spencer, for example, often uses 'more evolved' interchangeably with 'higher.' However, it’s important to note that this is not part of Darwin’s scientific theory. That theory can equally explain how, due to environmental changes (like the gradual cooling of the earth, for instance), a very different species from humans, which we might consider infinitely lower, could survive us. The survival of the fittest does not mean, as one might think, the survival of what is best suited to achieve a good purpose for a beneficial outcome: ultimately, it simply means the survival of those best able to survive; and the value of the scientific theory, which is indeed very valuable, lies in showing what causes produce specific biological effects. It makes no claim about whether these effects are good or bad.
31. But now let us hear what Mr Spencer says about the application of Evolution to Ethics.
31. But now let’s see what Mr. Spencer says about applying Evolution to Ethics.
‘I recur,’ he says[6], ‘to the main proposition set forth in these two chapters, which has, I think, been fully justified. Guided by the truth that as the conduct with which Ethics deals is part of conduct at large, conduct at large must be generally understood before this part can be specially understood; and guided by the further truth that to understand conduct at large we must understand the evolution of conduct; we have been led to see that Ethics has for its subject-matter, that form which universal conduct assumes during the last stages of its evolution. We have also concluded that these last stages in the evolution of conduct are those displayed by the highest[7] type of being when he is forced, by increase of numbers, to live more and more in presence of his fellows. And there has followed the corollary that conduct gains ethical sanction[7] in proportion as the activities, becoming less and less militant and more and more industrial, are such as do not necessitate mutual injury or hindrance, but consist with, and are furthered by, co-operation and mutual aid.
‘I repeat,’ he says[6], ‘the main idea presented in these two chapters, which I believe has been thoroughly justified. Following the understanding that the behavior addressed by Ethics is part of broader behavior, we need to grasp general behavior before we can specifically understand this part; and further, to understand general behavior, we must grasp its evolution. This has led us to recognize that Ethics focuses on the form that universal behavior takes in the later stages of its evolution. We also concluded that these later stages in the evolution of behavior are exhibited by the highest[7] type of being when he is compelled, due to population growth, to live increasingly among his peers. This leads to the conclusion that behavior gains ethical approval[7] as activities become less aggressive and more industrial, fostering cooperation and mutual support rather than causing harm or obstacles to one another.
‘These implications of the Evolution-Hypothesis, we shall now see harmonize with the leading moral ideas men have otherwise reached.’
‘These implications of the Evolution Hypothesis, we will now see, align with the main moral concepts that people have otherwise arrived at.’
Now, if we are to take the last sentence strictly—if the propositions which precede it are really thought by Mr Spencer to be implications of the Evolution-Hypothesis—there can be no doubt that Mr Spencer has committed the naturalistic fallacy. All that the Evolution-Hypothesis tells us is that certain kinds of conduct are more evolved than others; and[p. 49] this is, in fact, all that Mr Spencer has attempted to prove in the two chapters concerned. Yet he tells us that one of the things it has proved is that conduct gains ethical sanction in proportion as it displays certain characteristics. What he has tried to prove is only that, in proportion as it displays those characteristics, it is more evolved. It is plain, then, that Mr Spencer identifies the gaining of ethical sanction with the being more evolved: this follows strictly from his words. But Mr Spencer’s language is extremely loose; and we shall presently see that he seems to regard the view it here implies as false. We cannot, therefore, take it as Mr Spencer’s definite view that ‘better’ means nothing but ‘more evolved’; or even that what is ‘more evolved’ is therefore ‘better.’ But we are entitled to urge that he is influenced by these views, and therefore by the naturalistic fallacy. It is only by the assumption of such influence that we can explain his confusion as to what he has really proved, and the absence of any attempt to prove, what he says he has proved, that conduct which is more evolved is better. We shall look in vain for any attempt to shew that ‘ethical sanction’ is in proportion to ‘evolution,’ or that it is the ‘highest’ type of being which displays the most evolved conduct; yet Mr Spencer concludes that this is the case. It is only fair to assume that he is not sufficiently conscious how much these propositions stand in need of proof—what a very different thing is being ‘more evolved’ from being ‘higher’ or ‘better.’ It may, of course, be true that what is more evolved is also higher and better. But Mr Spencer does not seem aware that to assert the one is in any case not the same thing as to assert the other. He argues at length that certain kinds of conduct are ‘more evolved,’ and then informs us that he has proved them to gain ethical sanction in proportion, without any warning that he has omitted the most essential step in such a proof. Surely this is sufficient evidence that he does not see how essential that step is.
Now, if we interpret the last sentence literally—if Mr. Spencer actually believes that the points made before it are truly implications of the Evolution-Hypothesis—there’s no doubt that he has fallen into the naturalistic fallacy. The Evolution-Hypothesis only indicates that some types of behavior are more evolved than others; and[p. 49] this is essentially all that Mr. Spencer has sought to demonstrate in the two chapters in question. Yet he claims that one of the conclusions reached is that conduct gains ethical approval based on its display of certain traits. What he actually tries to show is that, as it displays those traits, it is more evolved. Clearly, Mr. Spencer equates the gaining of ethical approval with being more evolved: this is a straightforward implication of what he says. However, Mr. Spencer’s language is very loose; and we will soon find that he seems to consider the view that follows from it to be incorrect. Therefore, we can't accept it as Mr. Spencer’s clear position that ‘better’ simply means ‘more evolved’; or even that what is ‘more evolved’ is therefore ‘better.’ Yet, we can argue that he is affected by these ideas, and thus by the naturalistic fallacy. It’s only by assuming this influence that we can make sense of his confusion about what he has really proven, as well as his failure to demonstrate what he claims to have established: that conduct which is more evolved is better. We will look in vain for any effort to show that ‘ethical approval’ correlates with ‘evolution,’ or that it is the ‘highest’ type of being that exhibits the most advanced conduct; yet Mr. Spencer concludes this is the case. It’s reasonable to assume that he doesn’t fully realize how much these claims require proof—how fundamentally different it is to be ‘more evolved’ from being ‘higher’ or ‘better.’ It might indeed be the case that what is more evolved is also higher and better. But Mr. Spencer doesn’t appear to recognize that asserting one does not necessarily mean asserting the other. He elaborates that certain kinds of behavior are ‘more evolved,’ and then tells us he has proven them to gain ethical approval in proportion, without acknowledging that he has skipped the most critical step in such a proof. Surely this is clear evidence that he does not grasp how crucial that step is.
32. Whatever be the degree of Mr Spencer’s own guilt, what has just been said will serve to illustrate the kind of fallacy which is constantly committed by those who profess to ‘base’ Ethics on Evolution. But we must hasten to add[p. 50] that the view which Mr Spencer elsewhere most emphatically recommends is an utterly different one. It will be useful briefly to deal with this, in order that no injustice may be done to Mr Spencer. The discussion will be instructive partly from the lack of clearness, which Mr Spencer displays, as to the relation of this view to the ‘evolutionistic’ one just described; and partly because there is reason to suspect that in this view also he is influenced by the naturalistic fallacy.
32. Regardless of how guilty Mr. Spencer may be, what has just been mentioned highlights the kind of mistake often made by those who claim to ground Ethics in Evolution. However, we should quickly point out[p. 50] that the perspective which Mr. Spencer strongly advocates elsewhere is completely different. It will be helpful to briefly address this, so as not to misrepresent Mr. Spencer. The discussion will be enlightening, partly due to Mr. Spencer's lack of clarity regarding the connection between this perspective and the 'evolutionistic' view just described; and partly because there is reason to believe that he may also be influenced by the naturalistic fallacy in this perspective.
We have seen that, at the end of his second chapter, Mr Spencer seems to announce that he has already proved certain characteristics of conduct to be a measure of its ethical value. He seems to think that he has proved this merely by considering the evolution of conduct; and he has certainly not given any such proof, unless we are to understand that ‘more evolved’ is a mere synonym for ‘ethically better.’ He now promises merely to confirm this certain conclusion by shewing that it ‘harmonizes with the leading moral ideas men have otherwise reached.’ But, when we turn to his third chapter, we find that what he actually does is something quite different. He here asserts that to establish the conclusion ‘Conduct is better in proportion as it is more evolved’ an entirely new proof is necessary. That conclusion will be false, unless a certain proposition, of which we have heard nothing so far, is true—unless it be true that life is pleasant on the whole. And the ethical proposition, for which he claims the support of the ‘leading moral ideas’ of mankind, turns out to be that ‘life is good or bad, according as it does, or does not, bring a surplus of agreeable feeling’ (§ 10). Here, then, Mr Spencer appears, not as an Evolutionist, but as a Hedonist, in Ethics. No conduct is better, because it is more evolved. Degree of evolution can at most be a criterion of ethical value; and it will only be that, if we can prove the extremely difficult generalisation that the more evolved is always, on the whole, the pleasanter. It is plain that Mr Spencer here rejects the naturalistic identification of ‘better’ with ‘more evolved’; but it is possible that he is influenced by another naturalistic identification—that of ‘good’ with ‘pleasant.’ It is possible that Mr Spencer is a naturalistic Hedonist.
We’ve seen that at the end of his second chapter, Mr. Spencer seems to suggest that he’s already proven certain traits of behavior to be a measure of its ethical value. He appears to believe he’s proven this simply by looking at the evolution of behavior; and he certainly hasn’t provided any such proof, unless we interpret ‘more evolved’ as just another way of saying ‘ethically better.’ He now promises to confirm this conclusion by showing that it ‘fits with the key moral ideas people have otherwise reached.’ However, when we look at his third chapter, we find that what he actually does is quite different. He asserts that to establish the conclusion ‘Conduct is better as it is more evolved,’ a completely new proof is required. That conclusion will be false unless a certain proposition, which we haven’t heard about so far, is true—unless it’s true that life is pleasant overall. And the ethical proposition for which he seeks support from the ‘key moral ideas’ of humanity turns out to be that ‘life is good or bad depending on whether it brings a surplus of pleasant feelings’ (§ 10). Here, Mr. Spencer appears not as an Evolutionist, but as a Hedonist in Ethics. No behavior is better, because it is more evolved. The degree of evolution can at most serve as a criterion of ethical value; and it will only be that if we can prove the very difficult generalization that the more evolved is generally, more pleasant. It’s clear that Mr. Spencer here rejects the naturalistic equation of ‘better’ with ‘more evolved’; but it’s possible that he’s influenced by another naturalistic equation—that of ‘good’ with ‘pleasant.’ It’s possible that Mr. Spencer is a naturalistic Hedonist.
[p. 51]33. Let us examine Mr Spencer’s own words. He begins this third chapter by an attempt to shew that we call ‘good the acts conducive to life, in self or others, and bad those which directly or indirectly tend towards death, special or general’ (§ 9). And then he asks: ‘Is there any assumption made’ in so calling them? ‘Yes’; he answers, ‘an assumption of extreme significance has been made—an assumption underlying all moral estimates. The question to be definitely raised and answered before entering on any ethical discussion, is the question of late much agitated—Is life worth living? Shall we take the pessimist view? or shall we take the optimist view?... On the answer to this question depends every decision concerning the goodness or badness of conduct.’ But Mr Spencer does not immediately proceed to give the answer. Instead of this, he asks another question: ‘But now, have these irreconcilable opinions [pessimist and optimist] anything in common?’ And this question he immediately answers by the statement: ‘Yes, there is one postulate in which pessimists and optimists agree. Both their arguments assume it to be self-evident that life is good or bad, according as it does, or does not, bring a surplus of agreeable feeling’ (§ 10). It is to the defence of this statement that the rest of the chapter is devoted; and at the end Mr Spencer formulates his conclusion in the following words: ‘No school can avoid taking for the ultimate moral aim a desirable state of feeling called by whatever name—gratification, enjoyment, happiness. Pleasure somewhere, at some time, to some being or beings, is an inexpugnable element of the conception’ (§ 16 ad fin.).
[p. 51]33. Let's look at Mr. Spencer’s own words. He starts this third chapter by trying to show that we call ‘good the actions that promote life, either for ourselves or for others, and bad those that lead to death, either directly or indirectly’ (§ 9). Then he asks: ‘Is there any assumption made’ in labeling them this way? ‘Yes,’ he answers, ‘an assumption of great importance has been made—an assumption that underpins all moral judgments. The question that needs to be raised and answered before we dive into any ethical discussion is one that has recently sparked a lot of debate—Is life worth living? Should we adopt a pessimistic view? Or should we take an optimistic view?... The answer to this question affects every decision about whether actions are good or bad.’ But Mr. Spencer doesn’t directly provide the answer. Instead, he poses another question: ‘But now, do these opposing opinions [pessimists and optimists] have anything in common?’ He answers this by stating: ‘Yes, there is one assumption that both pessimists and optimists share. Both of their arguments assume it is self-evident that life is good or bad depending on whether it brings a surplus of positive feelings’ (§ 10). The rest of the chapter is dedicated to defending this statement, and at the end, Mr. Spencer sums up his conclusion with these words: ‘No school can avoid taking as its ultimate moral aim a desirable state of feeling, called by whatever name—gratification, enjoyment, happiness. Pleasure somewhere, at some time, for some individual or individuals, is an essential element of the concept’ (§ 16 ad fin.).
Now in all this, there are two points to which I wish to call attention. The first is that Mr Spencer does not, after all, tell us clearly what he takes to be the relation of Pleasure and Evolution in ethical theory. Obviously he should mean that pleasure is the only intrinsically desirable thing; that other good things are ‘good’ only in the sense that they are means to its existence. Nothing but this can properly be meant by asserting it to be ‘the ultimate moral aim,’ or, as he subsequently says (§ 62 ad fin.), ‘the ultimately supreme end.’ And, if this were so, it would follow that the more evolved conduct was[p. 52] better than the less evolved, only because, and in proportion as, it gave more pleasure. But Mr Spencer tells us that two conditions are, taken together, sufficient to prove the more evolved conduct better: (1) That it should tend to produce more life; (2) That life should be worth living or contain a balance of pleasure. And the point I wish to emphasise is that if these conditions are sufficient, then pleasure cannot be the sole good. For though to produce more life is, if the second of Mr Spencer’s propositions be correct, one way of producing more pleasure, it is not the only way. It is quite possible that a small quantity of life, which was more intensely and uniformly present, should give a greater quantity of pleasure than the greatest possible quantity of life that was only just ‘worth living.’ And in that case, on the hedonistic supposition that pleasure is the only thing worth having, we should have to prefer the smaller quantity of life and therefore, according to Mr Spencer, the less evolved conduct. Accordingly, if Mr Spencer is a true Hedonist, the fact that life gives a balance of pleasure is not, as he seems to think, sufficient to prove that the more evolved conduct is the better. If Mr Spencer means us to understand that it is sufficient, then his view about pleasure can only be, not that it is the sole good or ‘ultimately supreme end,’ but that a balance of it is a necessary constituent of the supreme end. In short, Mr Spencer seems to maintain that more life is decidedly better than less, if only it give a balance of pleasure: and that contention is inconsistent with the position that pleasure is ‘the ultimate moral aim.’ Mr Spencer implies that of two quantities of life, which gave an equal amount of pleasure, the larger would nevertheless be preferable to the less. And if this be so, then he must maintain that quantity of life or degree of evolution is itself an ultimate condition of value. He leaves us, therefore, in doubt whether he is not still retaining the Evolutionistic proposition, that the more evolved is better, simply because it is more evolved, alongside of the Hedonistic proposition, that the more pleasant is better, simply because it is more pleasant.
Now, there are two points I want to highlight. First, Mr. Spencer doesn’t clearly explain what he believes is the relationship between pleasure and evolution in ethical theory. It seems he intends to imply that pleasure is the only thing inherently desirable; that other good things are 'good' only as means to pleasure's existence. This is the proper interpretation of his claim that it is ‘the ultimate moral aim,’ or, as he later states (§ 62 ad fin.), ‘the ultimately supreme end.’ If this were the case, then more evolved behavior would only be better than less evolved behavior because, and to the extent that, it provides more pleasure. However, Mr. Spencer argues that two conditions together are sufficient to prove that more evolved behavior is better: (1) It should tend to produce more life; (2) That life should be worth living or contain a balance of pleasure. What I want to emphasize is that if these conditions are sufficient, then pleasure cannot be the only good. Even if producing more life is, assuming Mr. Spencer’s second condition is correct, one way to produce more pleasure, it’s not the only way. It's entirely possible that a smaller amount of life, when experienced more intensely and consistently, could provide greater pleasure than the largest amount of life that is only barely ‘worth living.’ In that case, based on the hedonistic idea that pleasure is the only thing worth pursuing, we would have to choose the smaller quantity of life and therefore, according to Mr. Spencer, the less evolved behavior. Thus, if Mr. Spencer is a true hedonist, the fact that life offers a balance of pleasure is not, as he seems to believe, enough to prove that more evolved behavior is better. If he intends for us to understand that it is sufficient, then his view on pleasure must be that it is not the sole good or ‘ultimately supreme end,’ but rather that a balance of it is a necessary component of the supreme end. In summary, Mr. Spencer appears to argue that more life is definitely better than less, as long as it provides a balance of pleasure: and this claim contradicts the idea that pleasure is ‘the ultimate moral aim.’ Mr. Spencer suggests that if two amounts of life provide equal pleasure, the larger amount would still be preferable to the smaller. If that’s the case, he must assert that the quantity of life or level of evolution is itself an ultimate value condition. This leaves us uncertain whether he is still holding onto the Evolutionistic belief that the more evolved is better merely because it is more evolved, alongside the Hedonistic belief that the more pleasurable is better simply because it is more pleasurable.
But the second question which we have to ask is: What[p. 53] reasons has Mr Spencer for assigning to pleasure the position which he does assign to it? He tells us, we saw, that the ‘arguments’ both of pessimists and of optimists ‘assume it to be self-evident that life is good or bad, according as it does, or does not, bring a surplus of agreeable feeling’; and he betters this later by telling us that ‘since avowed or implied pessimists, and optimists of one or other shade, taken together constitute all men, it results that this postulate is universally accepted’ (§ 16). That these statements are absolutely false is, of course, quite obvious: but why does Mr Spencer think them true? and, what is more important (a question which Mr Spencer does not distinguish too clearly from the last), why does he think the postulate itself to be true? Mr Spencer himself tells us his ‘proof is’ that ‘reversing the application of the words’ good and bad—applying the word ‘good’ to conduct, the ‘aggregate results’ of which are painful, and the word ‘bad’ to conduct, of which the ‘aggregate results’ are pleasurable—‘creates absurdities’ (§ 16). He does not say whether this is because it is absurd to think that the quality, which we mean by the word ‘good,’ really applies to what is painful. Even, however, if we assume him to mean this, and if we assume that absurdities are thus created, it is plain he would only prove that what is painful is properly thought to be so far bad, and what is pleasant to be so far good: it would not prove at all that pleasure is ‘the supreme end.’ There is, however, reason to think that part of what Mr Spencer means is the naturalistic fallacy: that he imagines ‘pleasant’ or ‘productive of pleasure’ is the very meaning of the word ‘good,’ and that ‘the absurdity’ is due to this. It is at all events certain that he does not distinguish this possible meaning from that which would admit that ‘good’ denotes an unique indefinable quality. The doctrine of naturalistic Hedonism is, indeed, quite strictly implied in his statement that ‘virtue’ cannot ‘be defined otherwise than in terms of happiness’ (§ 13); and, though, as I remarked above, we cannot insist upon Mr Spencer’s words as a certain clue to any definite meaning, that is only because he generally expresses by them several inconsistent alternatives—the naturalistic fallacy being, in this case, one such alternative. It is certainly[p. 54] impossible to find any further reasons given by Mr Spencer for his conviction that pleasure both is the supreme end, and is universally admitted to be so. He seems to assume throughout that we must mean by good conduct what is productive of pleasure, and by bad what is productive of pain. So far, then, as he is a Hedonist, he would seem to be a naturalistic Hedonist.
But the second question we need to ask is: What[p. 53] reasons does Mr. Spencer have for assigning pleasure the position he does? He tells us, as we saw, that the ‘arguments’ of both pessimists and optimists ‘assume it to be self-evident that life is good or bad, depending on whether it brings a surplus of pleasurable feelings’; and he improves on this later by stating that ‘since both open and subtle pessimists, along with optimists of various sorts, make up all of humanity, it follows that this assumption is universally accepted’ (§ 16). It is clearly obvious that these statements are completely false: but why does Mr. Spencer think they are true? And, more importantly (a question he doesn’t clearly distinguish from the last), why does he believe the assumption itself is true? Mr. Spencer himself tells us his ‘proof is’ that ‘reversing the application of the terms’ good and bad—applying the term ‘good’ to actions that produce painful outcomes and the term ‘bad’ to actions that yield pleasurable outcomes—‘creates absurdities’ (§ 16). He doesn’t specify whether this is because it is absurd to think that the quality we mean by the word ‘good’ really applies to what is painful. Even if we assume this is what he means, and if we assume that absurdities are indeed created, it’s clear he would only demonstrate that what is painful is rightly considered so far bad, and what is pleasurable so far good: it wouldn’t prove at all that pleasure is ‘the supreme end.’ There is, however, reason to believe that part of what Mr. Spencer means is the naturalistic fallacy: that he thinks ‘pleasant’ or ‘productive of pleasure’ is the very definition of the word ‘good,’ and that ‘the absurdity’ comes from this. It is certainly clear that he does not differentiate this possible meaning from a perspective that would allow for ‘good’ to refer to a unique indefinable quality. The doctrine of naturalistic Hedonism is indeed implied in his assertion that ‘virtue’ cannot ‘be defined any other way than in terms of happiness’ (§ 13); and though, as I mentioned earlier, we can’t take Mr. Spencer’s words as a definite guide to any clear meaning, that’s only because he often expresses multiple inconsistent alternatives—one of which includes the naturalistic fallacy. It is certainly[p. 54] impossible to find any additional reasons from Mr. Spencer for his belief that pleasure is both the supreme end and that it is universally recognized as such. He seems to assume throughout that we must mean good conduct as that which produces pleasure, and bad conduct as that which produces pain. Thus, as much as he is a Hedonist, he appears to be a naturalistic Hedonist.
So much for Mr Spencer. It is, of course, quite possible that his treatment of Ethics contains many interesting and instructive remarks. It would seem, indeed, that Mr Spencer’s main view, that of which he is most clearly and most often conscious, is that pleasure is the sole good, and that to consider the direction of evolution is by far the best criterion of the way in which we shall get most of it: and this theory, if he could establish that amount of pleasure is always in direct proportion to amount of evolution and also that it was plain what conduct was more evolved, would be a very valuable contribution to the science of Sociology; it would even, if pleasure were the sole good, be a valuable contribution to Ethics. But the above discussion should have made it plain that, if what we want from an ethical philosopher is a scientific and systematic Ethics, not merely an Ethics professedly ‘based on science’; if what we want is a clear discussion of the fundamental principles of Ethics, and a statement of the ultimate reasons why one way of acting should be considered better than another—then Mr Spencer’s ‘Data of Ethics’ is immeasurably far from satisfying these demands.
So much for Mr. Spencer. It's certainly possible that his treatment of Ethics includes many interesting and helpful insights. It seems that Mr. Spencer's main perspective, the one he is most aware of and expresses the most, is that pleasure is the only good, and that examining the direction of evolution is by far the best criterion for understanding how we can maximize it. This theory, if he can prove that the amount of pleasure is always directly proportional to the amount of evolution and also demonstrate that it's clear which conduct is more evolved, would be a significant contribution to the science of Sociology; it could even be a valuable contribution to Ethics if pleasure is truly the only good. However, the discussion above should make it clear that if we are looking for a scientific and systematic approach to Ethics from an ethical philosopher—not just an Ethics that claims to be ‘based on science’—and if we want a straightforward discussion of the fundamental principles of Ethics along with an explanation of why one way of acting should be seen as better than another, then Mr. Spencer’s ‘Data of Ethics’ falls far short of meeting those expectations.
34. It remains only to state clearly what is definitely fallacious in prevalent views as to the relation of Evolution to Ethics—in those views with regard to which it seems so uncertain how far Mr Spencer intends to encourage them. I proposed to confine the term ‘Evolutionistic Ethics’ to the view that we need only to consider the tendency of ‘evolution’ in order to discover the direction in which we ought to go. This view must be carefully distinguished from certain others, which may be commonly confused with it. (1) It might, for instance, be held that the direction in which living things have hitherto developed is, as a matter of fact, the direction of[p. 55] progress. It might be held that the ‘more evolved’ is, as a matter of fact, also better. And in such a view no fallacy is involved. But, if it is to give us any guidance as to how we ought to act in the future, it does involve a long and painful investigation of the exact points in which the superiority of the more evolved consists. We cannot assume that, because evolution is progress on the whole, therefore every point in which the more evolved differs from the less is a point in which it is better than the less. A simple consideration of the course of evolution will therefore, on this view, by no means suffice to inform us of the course we ought to pursue. We shall have to employ all the resources of a strictly ethical discussion in order to arrive at a correct valuation of the different results of evolution—to distinguish the more valuable from the less valuable, and both from those which are no better than their causes, or perhaps even worse. In fact it is difficult to see how, on this view—if all that be meant is that evolution has on the whole been a progress—the theory of evolution can give any assistance to Ethics at all. The judgment that evolution has been a progress is itself an independent ethical judgment; and even if we take it to be more certain and obvious than any of the detailed judgments upon which it must logically depend for confirmation, we certainly cannot use it as a datum from which to infer details. It is, at all events, certain that, if this had been the only relation held to exist between Evolution and Ethics, no such importance would have been attached to the bearing of Evolution on Ethics as we actually find claimed for it. (2) The view, which, as I have said, seems to be Mr Spencer’s main view, may also be held without fallacy. It may be held that the more evolved, though not itself the better, is a criterion, because a concomitant, of the better. But this view also obviously involves an exhaustive preliminary discussion of the fundamental ethical question what, after all, is better. That Mr Spencer entirely dispenses with such a discussion in support of his contention that pleasure is the sole good, I have pointed out; and that, if we attempt such a discussion, we shall arrive at no such simple result, I shall presently try to shew. If however the good is not simple, it is by no means likely that[p. 56] we shall be able to discover Evolution to be a criterion of it. We shall have to establish a relation between two highly complicated sets of data; and, moreover, if we had once settled what were goods, and what their comparative values, it is extremely unlikely that we should need to call in the aid of Evolution as a criterion of how to get the most. It is plain, then, again, that if this were the only relation imagined to exist between Evolution and Ethics, it could hardly have been thought to justify the assignment of any importance in Ethics to the theory of Evolution. Finally, (3) it may be held that, though Evolution gives us no help in discovering what results of our efforts will be best, it does give some help in discovering what it is possible to attain and what are the means to its attainment. That the theory really may be of service to Ethics in this way cannot be denied. But it is certainly not common to find this humble, ancillary bearing clearly and exclusively assigned to it. In the mere fact, then, that these non-fallacious views of the relation of Evolution to Ethics would give so very little importance to that relation, we have evidence that what is typical in the coupling of the two names is the fallacious view to which I propose to restrict the name ‘Evolutionistic Ethics.’ This is the view that we ought to move in the direction of evolution simply because it is the direction of evolution. That the forces of Nature are working on that side is taken as a presumption that it is the right side. That such a view, apart from metaphysical presuppositions, with which I shall presently deal, is simply fallacious, I have tried to shew. It can only rest on a confused belief that somehow the good simply means the side on which Nature is working. And it thus involves another confused belief which is very marked in Mr Spencer’s whole treatment of Evolution. For, after all, is Evolution the side on which Nature is working? In the sense, which Mr Spencer gives to the term, and in any sense in which it can be regarded as a fact that the more evolved is higher, Evolution denotes only a temporary historical process. That things will permanently continue to evolve in the future, or that they have always evolved in the past, we have not the smallest reason to believe. For Evolution does not, in this[p. 57] sense, denote a natural law, like the law of gravity. Darwin’s theory of natural selection does indeed state a natural law: it states that, given certain conditions, certain results will always happen. But Evolution, as Mr Spencer understands it and as it is commonly understood, denotes something very different. It denotes only a process which has actually occurred at a given time, because the conditions at the beginning of that time happened to be of a certain nature. That such conditions will always be given, or have always been given, cannot be assumed; and it is only the process which, according to natural law, must follow from these conditions and no others, that appears to be also on the whole a progress. Precisely the same natural laws—Darwin’s, for instance—would under other conditions render inevitable not Evolution—not a development from lower to higher—but the converse process, which has been called Involution. Yet Mr Spencer constantly speaks of the process which is exemplified in the development of man as if it had all the augustness of a universal Law of Nature: whereas we have no reason to believe it other than a temporary accident, requiring not only certain universal natural laws, but also the existence of a certain state of things at a certain time. The only laws concerned in the matter are certainly such as, under other circumstances, would allow us to infer, not the development, but the extinction of man. And that circumstances will always be favourable to further development, that Nature will always work on the side of Evolution, we have no reason whatever to believe. Thus the idea that Evolution throws important light on Ethics seems to be due to a double confusion. Our respect for the process is enlisted by the representation of it as the Law of Nature. But, on the other hand, our respect for Laws of Nature would be speedily diminished, did we not imagine that this desirable process was one of them. To suppose that a Law of Nature is therefore respectable, is to commit the naturalistic fallacy; but no one, probably, would be tempted to commit it, unless something which is respectable, were represented as a Law of Nature. If it were clearly recognised that there is no evidence for supposing Nature to be on the side of the Good, there would probably be less tendency to hold the opinion, which on other grounds is demonstrably false, that[p. 58] no such evidence is required. And if both false opinions were clearly seen to be false, it would be plain that Evolution has very little indeed to say to Ethics.
34. It's important to clearly state what is definitely wrong in the common beliefs about the connection between Evolution and Ethics—specifically those beliefs that raise questions about how far Mr. Spencer intends to support them. I aim to limit the term ‘Evolutionistic Ethics’ to the idea that we only need to look at the trend of ‘evolution’ to figure out the direction we ought to take. This idea must be carefully separated from other views that may often be confused with it. (1) For example, it might be argued that the direction in which living things have developed up to now is, in fact, the direction of[p. 55] progress. Some might claim that the ‘more evolved’ is, in fact, also better. In this belief, there is no fallacy present. However, if this idea is to guide our future actions, it would require a lengthy and difficult investigation into exactly what makes the more evolved superior. We cannot simply assume that because evolution is progress overall, every difference between the more evolved and the less evolved indicates that the former is better. A straightforward examination of evolution will not adequately inform us about the path we should take. We would need to engage in comprehensive ethical discussions to properly assess the various outcomes of evolution—differentiating the more valuable from the less valuable, and both from those results that are not better than their origins or may even be worse. In fact, it’s hard to see how, on this view—if all it means is that evolution has been overall a progress—evolution can assist Ethics in any way. The assertion that evolution has been a progress is itself an independent ethical judgment; even if we regard it as more certain and obvious than any of the specific judgments it depends on for validation, we can’t use it as a basis for inferring those details. It is clear that, if this had been the only relationship assumed between Evolution and Ethics, the significance attached to Evolution's impact on Ethics would not be as pronounced as it is. (2) The position, which I mentioned earlier seems to be Mr. Spencer’s main stance, can also be held without fallacy. One could argue that the more evolved, even if not better, serves as a criterion because it is a companion to the better. However, this perspective also clearly requires an extensive initial discussion regarding the fundamental ethical question of what, ultimately, is considered better. I've noted that Mr. Spencer completely skips such a discussion to support his claim that pleasure is the sole good; and I will soon illustrate that if we do engage in such a discussion, we will not arrive at a simple conclusion. If the good is not straightforward, it’s unlikely we will successfully identify Evolution as a criterion for it. We will need to analyze two highly complex sets of information, and furthermore, if we had already determined what constitutes goods and their relative values, it seems improbable that we would need to invoke Evolution as a standard for achieving the most. Thus, it is evident, again, that if this were the only imagined relationship between Evolution and Ethics, it could hardly be considered significant in the field of Ethics. Finally, (3) one could argue that while Evolution doesn’t help us figure out which outcomes of our efforts will be the best, it may assist us in understanding what it is possible to achieve and how to achieve it. It's undeniable that the theory could genuinely aid Ethics in that way. However, it is certainly uncommon to find this modest, supportive role attributed to it exclusively. Therefore, the fact that these non-fallacious views of the relationship between Evolution and Ethics would lend so little significance to that connection indicates that what is typically being discussed in the pairing of the two terms is the fallacious view I aim to define as ‘Evolutionistic Ethics.’ This view suggests we should move in the direction of evolution simply because it aligns with the path of evolution. The idea that natural forces are driving us that way is taken as proof that it’s the right path. I’ve attempted to demonstrate that such a perspective, aside from metaphysical assumptions—which I will address shortly—is simply flawed. It relies on a muddled belief that the good simply means the direction in which Nature is moving. This belief entails another confusion that is particularly evident in Mr. Spencer’s overall approach to Evolution. After all, is Evolution truly the direction in which Nature is working? In the sense that Mr. Spencer describes it, and in any sense that can be understood as a fact that the more evolved is superior, Evolution only signifies a temporary historical process. We have no solid reason to believe that things will keep evolving in the future or that they have consistently evolved in the past. Evolution does not, in this[p. 57] sense, imply a natural law, like the law of gravity. Darwin's theory of natural selection does describe a natural law: it asserts that, under certain conditions, certain outcomes will always occur. But Evolution, as Mr. Spencer interprets it and as it is generally understood, indicates something quite different. It refers to a process that has occurred at a specific time due to the conditions present at that moment. We cannot assume that such conditions will always been present or have always existed; it is only the process that must logically follow from these conditions and no others that appears to generally be a progress. The same natural laws—like Darwin's—could under different conditions make it inevitable not to have Evolution—not a progression from lower to higher—but rather the reverse process, termed Involution. Yet Mr. Spencer often discusses the process exemplified by human development as though it possesses the dignity of a universal Law of Nature: while we have no reason to view it as anything other than a temporary occurrence, needing not just certain universal natural laws but also a specific state of affairs at a particular time. The only laws implicated are certainly those that, under different circumstances, would suggest not development, but the extinction of humanity. And we have no reason to believe that conditions will always favor further development, that Nature will always support Evolution. Therefore, the notion that Evolution provides significant insight into Ethics seems rooted in a dual confusion. Our admiration for this process is sparked by its portrayal as a Law of Nature. Conversely, our respect for Laws of Nature would quickly wane if we didn't have the impression that this favorable process was among them. To assume that a Law of Nature is therefore respectable is to fall into the naturalistic fallacy; yet it's unlikely anyone would be tempted to commit it unless something that is respectable was framed as a Law of Nature. If we fully recognized that there's no evidence to support the belief that Nature aligns with the Good, it’s likely we would see less inclination to hold the demonstrably false view that[p. 58] no such evidence is needed. If both false beliefs were clearly understood as false, it would become evident that Evolution has very little to contribute to Ethics.
35. In this chapter I have begun the criticism of certain ethical views, which seem to owe their influence mainly to the naturalistic fallacy—the fallacy which consists in identifying the simple notion which we mean by ‘good’ with some other notion. They are views which profess to tell us what is good in itself; and my criticism of them is mainly directed (1) to bring out the negative result, that we have no reason to suppose that which they declare to be the sole good, really to be so, (2) to illustrate further the positive result, already established in Chapter I, that the fundamental principles of Ethics must be synthetic propositions, declaring what things, and in what degree, possess a simple and unanalysable property which may be called ‘intrinsic value’ or ‘goodness.’ The chapter began (1) by dividing the views to be criticised into (a) those which, supposing ‘good’ to be defined by reference to some supersensible reality, conclude that the sole good is to be found in such a reality, and may therefore be called ‘Metaphysical,’ (b) those which assign a similar position to some natural object, and may therefore be called ‘Naturalistic.’ Of naturalistic views, that which regards ‘pleasure’ as the sole good has received far the fullest and most serious treatment and was therefore reserved for Chapter III: all other forms of Naturalism may be first dismissed, by taking typical examples (24-26). (2) As typical of naturalistic views, other than Hedonism, there was first taken the popular commendation of what is ‘natural’: it was pointed out that by ‘natural’ there might here be meant either ‘normal’ or ‘necessary,’ and that neither the ‘normal’ nor the ‘necessary’ could be seriously supposed to be either always good or the only good things (27-28). (3) But a more important type, because one which claims to be capable of system, is to be found in ‘Evolutionistic Ethics.’ The influence of the fallacious opinion that to be ‘better’ means to be ‘more evolved’ was illustrated by an examination of Mr Herbert Spencer’s Ethics; and it was pointed out that, but for the influence of this opinion, Evolution could hardly have been supposed to have any important bearing upon Ethics (29-34).
35. In this chapter, I've started to critique certain ethical perspectives that seem to gain their influence primarily from the naturalistic fallacy—the mistake of equating what we mean by ‘good’ with some other concept. These perspectives claim to define what is inherently good; my critique focuses on (1) revealing the negative point that we have no grounds to believe what they claim to be the only good actually is, and (2) further illustrating the positive conclusion established in Chapter I that the fundamental principles of Ethics must be synthetic propositions, explaining what things, and to what extent, possess an inherent and unbreakable quality that can be referred to as ‘intrinsic value’ or ‘goodness.’ The chapter begins by dividing the views to be critiqued into (a) those that, assuming ‘good’ is defined by reference to some supersensible reality, conclude that the only good can be found in that reality, which can be labeled ‘Metaphysical,’ and (b) those that assign a similar position to some natural object, which can be termed ‘Naturalistic.’ Of the naturalistic views, the one that considers ‘pleasure’ as the sole good has received the most thorough and serious examination and was therefore saved for Chapter III; all other forms of Naturalism can be initially dismissed by looking at typical examples (24-26). (2) As an example of naturalistic views aside from Hedonism, I first looked at the common praise for what is ‘natural.’ It was noted that by ‘natural,’ it could mean either ‘normal’ or ‘necessary,’ and that neither the ‘normal’ nor the ‘necessary’ can be seriously assumed to always be good or the only good things (27-28). (3) However, a more significant type that claims to be systematic is found in ‘Evolutionistic Ethics.’ The misleading belief that being ‘better’ means being ‘more evolved’ was illustrated through an analysis of Mr. Herbert Spencer’s Ethics, and it was pointed out that without the impact of this belief, Evolution would hardly have been thought to have any significant implications for Ethics (29-34).
[p. 59]
[p. 59]
CHAPTER III.
HEDONISM.
Pleasure-seeking.
36. In this chapter we have to deal with what is perhaps the most famous and the most widely held of all ethical principles—the principle that nothing is good but pleasure. My chief reason for treating of this principle in this place is, as I said, that Hedonism appears in the main to be a form of Naturalistic Ethics: in other words, that pleasure has been so generally held to be the sole good, is almost entirely due to the fact that it has seemed to be somehow involved in the definition of ‘good’—to be pointed out by the very meaning of the word. If this is so, then the prevalence of Hedonism has been mainly due to what I have called the naturalistic fallacy—the failure to distinguish clearly that unique and indefinable quality which we mean by good. And that it is so, we have very strong evidence in the fact that, of all hedonistic writers, Prof. Sidgwick alone has clearly recognised that by ‘good’ we do mean something unanalysable, and has alone been led thereby to emphasise the fact that, if Hedonism be true, its claims to be so must be rested solely on its self-evidence—that we must maintain ‘Pleasure is the sole good’ to be a mere intuition. It appeared to Prof. Sidgwick as a new discovery that what he calls the ‘method’ of Intuitionism must be retained as valid alongside of, and indeed as the foundation of, what he calls the alternative ‘methods’ of Utilitarianism and Egoism. And that it was a new discovery can hardly be doubted. In previous Hedonists we find no clear and consistent recognition of the fact that their fundamental proposition involves the assumption that a[p. 60] certain unique predicate can be directly seen to belong to pleasure alone among existents: they do not emphasise, as they could hardly have failed to have done had they perceived it, how utterly independent of all other truths this truth must be.
36. In this chapter, we need to discuss what is arguably the most famous and widely accepted ethical principle—the idea that the only thing that is truly good is pleasure. The main reason I’m addressing this principle here is that Hedonism seems to primarily represent a form of Naturalistic Ethics. In other words, the widespread belief that pleasure is the sole good is largely because it seems to be connected to the very definition of ‘good’—indicated by the meaning of the word itself. If this is the case, then the prevalence of Hedonism can be mainly attributed to what I call the naturalistic fallacy—the failure to clearly distinguish that unique and indefinable quality we refer to as good. We have strong evidence for this in the fact that among all hedonistic writers, only Prof. Sidgwick has recognized that when we say ‘good,’ we mean something that cannot be broken down or analyzed, and he is the only one led by this realization to emphasize that if Hedonism is true, its claims must rest solely on its self-evidence—meaning we should see 'Pleasure is the sole good' as just an intuition. Prof. Sidgwick saw it as a new discovery that what he calls the ‘method’ of Intuitionism must remain valid alongside, and essentially as the foundation of, what he calls the alternative ‘methods’ of Utilitarianism and Egoism. It can hardly be doubted that this was indeed a new discovery. Previous Hedonists show no clear or consistent acknowledgment of the fact that their core proposition assumes a certain unique quality can be directly seen to apply only to pleasure among all existents; they fail to emphasize, as they surely would have if they had recognized it, how completely independent this truth is from all other truths.
Moreover it is easy to see how this unique position should have been assigned to pleasure without any clear consciousness of the assumption involved. Hedonism is, for a sufficiently obvious reason, the first conclusion at which any one who begins to reflect upon Ethics naturally arrives. It is very easy to notice the fact that we are pleased with things. The things we enjoy and the things we do not, form two unmistakable classes, to which our attention is constantly directed. But it is comparatively difficult to distinguish the fact that we approve a thing from the fact that we are pleased with it. Although, if we look at the two states of mind, we must see that they are different, even though they generally go together, it is very difficult to see in what respect they are different, or that the difference can in any connection be of more importance than the many other differences, which are so patent and yet so difficult to analyse, between one kind of enjoyment and another. It is very difficult to see that by ‘approving’ of a thing we mean feeling that it has a certain predicate—the predicate, namely, which defines the peculiar sphere of Ethics; whereas in the enjoyment of a thing no such unique object of thought is involved. Nothing is more natural than the vulgar mistake, which we find expressed in a recent book on Ethics[8]: ‘The primary ethical fact is, we have said, that something is approved or disapproved: that is, in other words, the ideal representation of certain events in the way of sensation, perception, or idea, is attended with a feeling of pleasure or of pain.’ In ordinary speech, ‘I want this,’ ‘I like this,’ ‘I care about this’ are constantly used as equivalents for ‘I think this good.’ And in this way it is very natural to be led to suppose that there is no distinct class of ethical judgments, but only the class ‘things enjoyed’; in spite of the fact, which is very clear, if not very common, that we do not always approve what we enjoy. It is[p. 61] of course, very obvious that from the supposition that ‘I think this good’ is identical with ‘I am pleased with this,’ it cannot be logically inferred that pleasure alone is good. But, on the other hand, it is very difficult to see what could be logically inferred from such a supposition; and it seems natural enough that such an inference should suggest itself. A very little examination of what is commonly written on the subject will suffice to shew that a logical confusion of this nature is very common. Moreover the very commission of the naturalistic fallacy involves that those who commit it should not recognise clearly the meaning of the proposition ‘This is good’—that they should not be able to distinguish this from other propositions which seem to resemble it; and, where this is so, it is, of course, impossible that its logical relations should be clearly perceived.
Moreover, it’s easy to see why this unique position has been assigned to pleasure without a clear awareness of the assumption involved. Hedonism is, for an obvious reason, the first conclusion anyone who starts to think about Ethics naturally arrives at. It's very easy to notice that we find pleasure in things. The things we enjoy and the things we don't form two clear categories that capture our attention. However, it’s comparatively harder to recognize the distinction between the fact that we approve of something and the fact that we enjoy it. Although, if we examine these two states of mind, we must recognize that they are different, even though they typically occur together; it is hard to see in what way they differ, or that this difference can be more significant than the many other differences, which are quite obvious yet so difficult to analyze, between one kind of enjoyment and another. It is challenging to see that when we say we ‘approve’ of something, we mean feeling that it possesses a certain quality—the quality that defines the unique realm of Ethics; whereas in enjoying something, no such unique object of thought is involved. One can easily make the common mistake, expressed in a recent book on Ethics[8]: ‘The primary ethical fact is, we have said, that something is approved or disapproved: that is, in other words, the ideal representation of certain events in terms of sensation, perception, or idea, is accompanied by a feeling of pleasure or pain.’ In everyday language, ‘I want this,’ ‘I like this,’ ‘I care about this’ are often used interchangeably with ‘I think this is good.’ Hence, it’s very natural to suppose that there’s no distinct category of ethical judgments, just the category of ‘things enjoyed’; despite the fact, which is quite clear, if not very common, that we don’t always approve of what we enjoy. It is[p. 61] of course, quite obvious that from the assumption that ‘I think this is good’ is the same as ‘I am pleased with this,’ it cannot be logically inferred that pleasure alone is good. However, on the other hand, it’s challenging to see what could logically be inferred from such an assumption, and it seems natural enough that such an inference might come to mind. A brief examination of what is commonly written on the topic will show that this kind of logical confusion is very common. Moreover, the naturalistic fallacy involves that those who commit it do not clearly understand the meaning of the statement ‘This is good’—they cannot distinguish it from other statements that seem similar; and where this is the case, it is obviously impossible for its logical relationships to be clearly perceived.
37. There is, therefore, ample reason to suppose that Hedonism is in general a form of Naturalism—that its acceptance is generally due to the naturalistic fallacy. It is, indeed, only when we have detected this fallacy, when we have become clearly aware of the unique object which is meant by ‘good,’ that we are able to give to Hedonism the precise definition used above, ‘Nothing is good but pleasure’: and it may, therefore, be objected that, in attacking this doctrine under the name of Hedonism, I am attacking a doctrine which has never really been held. But it is very common to hold a doctrine, without being clearly aware what it is you hold; and though, when Hedonists argue in favour of what they call Hedonism, I admit that, in order to suppose their arguments valid, they must have before their minds something other than the doctrine I have defined, yet, in order to draw the conclusions that they draw, it is necessary that they should also have before their minds this doctrine. In fact, my justification for supposing that I shall have refuted historical Hedonism, if I refute the proposition ‘Nothing is good but pleasure,’ is, that although Hedonists have rarely stated their principle in this form and though its truth, in this form, will certainly not follow from their arguments, yet their ethical method will follow logically from nothing else. Any pretence of the hedonistic method, to[p. 62] discover to us practical truths which we should not otherwise have known, is founded on the principle that the course of action which will bring the greatest balance of pleasure is certainly the right one; and, failing an absolute proof that the greatest balance of pleasure always coincides with the greatest balance of other goods, which it is not generally attempted to give, this principle can only be justified if pleasure be the sole good. Indeed it can hardly be doubted that Hedonists are distinguished by arguing, in disputed practical questions, as if pleasure were the sole good; and that it is justifiable, for this among other reasons, to take this as the ethical principle of Hedonism will, I hope, be made further evident by the whole discussion of this chapter.
37. There is plenty of reason to think that Hedonism is generally a form of Naturalism—that its acceptance often comes from the naturalistic fallacy. It is only when we spot this fallacy and understand clearly what is meant by ‘good’ that we can give Hedonism the precise definition used above: ‘Nothing is good but pleasure.’ Thus, one might argue that by critiquing this view under the name of Hedonism, I'm challenging a doctrine that hasn’t really been held. However, it’s quite common to hold a belief without being fully aware of what it is. While I agree that when Hedonists support what they call Hedonism, they must have something other than the definition I provided in mind for their arguments to be valid, they also must keep this doctrine in mind to draw the conclusions they make. In fact, my reason for thinking I will have refuted historical Hedonism if I disprove the claim ‘Nothing is good but pleasure’ is that even though Hedonists rarely articulate their principle in that way and its truth won’t necessarily follow from their arguments, their ethical method can logically stem from nothing else. Any claim from the hedonistic method to uncover practical truths we wouldn’t otherwise know is based on the idea that the action leading to the greatest balance of pleasure is undoubtedly the right one; and without absolute proof that the greatest balance of pleasure always aligns with the greatest balance of other goods—which is not usually attempted—this principle can only be justified if pleasure is the only good. Indeed, it’s hard to deny that Hedonists are characterized by arguing in debated practical issues as if pleasure were the only good; and I hope that it becomes clearer throughout this chapter why it is justifiable to consider this as the ethical principle of Hedonism.
By Hedonism, then, I mean the doctrine that pleasure alone is good as an end—‘good’ in the sense which I have tried to point out as indefinable. The doctrine that pleasure, among other things, is good as an end, is not Hedonism; and I shall not dispute its truth. Nor again is the doctrine that other things, beside pleasure, are good as means, at all inconsistent with Hedonism: the Hedonist is not bound to maintain that ‘Pleasure alone is good,’ if under good he includes, as we generally do, what is good as means to an end, as well as the end itself. In attacking Hedonism, I am therefore simply and solely attacking the doctrine that ‘Pleasure alone is good as an end or in itself’: I am not attacking the doctrine that ‘Pleasure is good as an end or in itself,’ nor am I attacking any doctrine whatever as to what are the best means we can take in order to obtain pleasure or any other end. Hedonists do, in general, recommend a course of conduct which is very similar to that which I should recommend. I do not quarrel with them about most of their practical conclusions, I quarrel only with the reasons by which they seem to think their conclusions can be supported; and I do emphatically deny that the correctness of their conclusions is any ground for inferring the correctness of their principles. A correct conclusion may always be obtained by fallacious reasoning; and the good life or virtuous maxims of a Hedonist afford absolutely no presumption that his ethical philosophy is also good. It is his ethical philosophy alone with[p. 63] which I am concerned: what I dispute is the excellence of his reasoning, not the excellence of his character as a man or even as moral teacher. It may be thought that my contention is unimportant, but that is no ground for thinking that I am not in the right. What I am concerned with is knowledge only—that we should think correctly and so far arrive at some truth, however unimportant: I do not say that such knowledge will make us more useful members of society. If any one does not care for knowledge for its own sake, then I have nothing to say to him; only it should not be thought that a lack of interest in what I have to say is any ground for holding it untrue.
By Hedonism, I mean the belief that pleasure only is good as a goal—‘good’ in a way that I’ve tried to explain as hard to define. The belief that pleasure, among other things, is good as a goal isn't Hedonism, and I won't argue against its truth. Nor is the notion that other things besides pleasure can be good as means inconsistent with Hedonism: the Hedonist doesn’t have to claim that ‘Pleasure alone is good,’ if by good they include, as we generally do, what is good as a means to an end, as well as the end itself. So when I challenge Hedonism, I'm solely challenging the idea that ‘Pleasure alone is good as a goal or in itself’: I'm not disputing the idea that ‘Pleasure is good as a goal or in itself,’ nor am I questioning any views on the best ways to achieve pleasure or any other goal. Generally, Hedonists recommend a way of living that's very similar to what I would suggest. I don't disagree with most of their practical conclusions; I only argue with the reasons they think support their conclusions; and I firmly deny that the accuracy of their conclusions shows their principles are correct. A correct conclusion can always arise from faulty reasoning; and the good life or virtuous guidelines of a Hedonist provide absolutely no guarantee that their ethical philosophy is also sound. I'm only interested in his ethical philosophy: what I'm disputing is the strength of his reasoning, not the quality of his character as a person or even as a moral teacher. It may seem that my point is insignificant, but that doesn’t mean I'm wrong. My focus is purely on knowledge—that we should think correctly and, to some extent, reach some truth, no matter how trivial: I’m not claiming that such knowledge will make us more useful members of society. If someone doesn’t care about knowledge for its own sake, then I have nothing to say to them; just remember that disinterest in my views doesn’t mean they’re untrue.
38. Hedonists, then, hold that all other things but pleasure, whether conduct or virtue or knowledge, whether life or nature or beauty, are only good as means to pleasure or for the sake of pleasure, never for their own sakes or as ends in themselves. This view was held by Aristippus, the disciple of Socrates, and by the Cyrenaic school which he founded; it is associated with Epicurus and the Epicureans; and it has been held in modern times, chiefly by those philosophers who call themselves ‘Utilitarians’—by Bentham, and by Mill, for instance. Herbert Spencer, as we have seen, also says he holds it; and Professor Sidgwick, as we shall see, holds it too.
38. Hedonists believe that everything except for pleasure—whether it's actions, virtue, knowledge, life, nature, or beauty—is only valuable as a way to achieve pleasure or for the sake of pleasure itself, not for their own sake or as ends in themselves. This idea was supported by Aristippus, a student of Socrates, and by the Cyrenaic school he started; it is also linked to Epicurus and the Epicureans. In modern times, this view has been embraced mostly by philosophers who identify as ‘Utilitarians’—like Bentham and Mill, for example. Herbert Spencer, as we’ve seen, claims to agree with this view, and Professor Sidgwick, as we’ll see, holds it as well.
Yet all these philosophers, as has been said, differ from one another more or less, both as to what they mean by Hedonism, and as to the reasons for which it is to be accepted as a true doctrine. The matter is therefore obviously not quite so simple as it might at first appear. My own object will be to shew quite clearly what the theory must imply, if it is made precise, if all confusions and inconsistencies are removed from the conception of it; and, when this is done, I think it will appear that all the various reasons given for holding it to be true, are really quite inadequate; that they are not reasons for holding Hedonism, but only for holding some other doctrine which is confused therewith. In order to attain this object I propose to take first Mill’s doctrine, as set forth in his book called Utilitarianism: we shall find in Mill a conception of Hedonism, and arguments in its favour, which fairly represent those of a large class of hedonistic writers. To these representative[p. 64] conceptions and arguments grave objections, objections which appear to me to be conclusive, have been urged by Professor Sidgwick. These I shall try to give in my own words; and shall then proceed to consider and refute Professor Sidgwick’s own much more precise conceptions and arguments. With this, I think, we shall have traversed the whole field of Hedonistic doctrine. It will appear, from the discussion, that the task of deciding what is or is not good in itself is by no means an easy one; and in this way the discussion will afford a good example of the method which it is necessary to pursue in attempting to arrive at the truth with regard to this primary class of ethical principles. In particular it will appear that two principles of method must be constantly kept in mind: (1) that the naturalistic fallacy must not be committed; (2) that the distinction between means and ends must be observed.
Yet all these philosophers, as has been said, differ from one another more or less, both in what they mean by Hedonism and in the reasons for which it should be regarded as a true doctrine. The issue is clearly not as simple as it might seem at first. My goal is to clarify what the theory must imply if it is made precise, removing all confusion and inconsistencies from the concept. When this is done, I believe it will become evident that all the various reasons given for believing it to be true are actually quite inadequate; they aren’t reasons for accepting Hedonism but just for accepting some other doctrine that gets mixed up with it. To achieve this, I will first examine Mill’s doctrine as presented in his book Utilitarianism: we will find in Mill a representation of Hedonism and arguments in its favor that accurately reflect those of a broad group of hedonistic writers. To these representative[p. 64] concepts and arguments, serious objections, which I believe are conclusive, have been raised by Professor Sidgwick. I will attempt to express these in my own words and then move on to consider and refute Professor Sidgwick’s own much more precise ideas and arguments. With this, I think we will have covered the entire field of Hedonistic doctrine. The discussion will reveal that determining what is or isn’t good in itself is far from easy; thus, it will serve as a good example of the method needed to seek the truth regarding this fundamental class of ethical principles. In particular, it will show that two methodological principles must always be kept in mind: (1) the naturalistic fallacy must not be committed; (2) the distinction between means and ends must be respected.
39. I propose, then, to begin by an examination of Mill’s Utilitarianism. That is a book which contains an admirably clear and fair discussion of many ethical principles and methods. Mill exposes not a few simple mistakes which are very likely to be made by those who approach ethical problems without much previous reflection. But what I am concerned with is the mistakes which Mill himself appears to have made, and these only so far as they concern the Hedonistic principle. Let me repeat what that principle is. It is, I said, that pleasure is the only thing at which we ought to aim, the only thing that is good as an end and for its own sake. And now let us turn to Mill and see whether he accepts this description of the question at issue. ‘Pleasure,’ he says at the outset, ‘and freedom from pain, are the only things desirable as ends’ (p. 10[9]); and again, at the end of his argument, ‘To think of an object as desirable (unless for the sake of its consequences) and to think of it as pleasant are one and the same thing’ (p. 58). These statements, taken together, and apart from certain confusions which are obvious in them, seem to imply the principle I have stated; and if I succeed in shewing that Mill’s reasons for them do not prove them, it must at least be admitted that I have not been fighting with shadows or demolishing a man of straw.
39. I propose to start by examining Mill’s Utilitarianism. It’s a book that offers a clear and fair discussion of many ethical principles and methods. Mill points out several simple mistakes that those who tackle ethical problems without much previous thought are likely to make. However, what I’m focused on are the mistakes Mill himself seems to have made, specifically regarding the Hedonistic principle. Let me restate what that principle is: it claims that pleasure is the only thing we should aim for, the only thing that is good in itself and for its own sake. Now, let’s look at Mill and see if he agrees with this characterization of the issue. He states at the beginning, ‘Pleasure and freedom from pain are the only things desirable as ends’ (p. 10[9]); and again, at the conclusion of his argument, ‘To think of an object as desirable (unless for the sake of its consequences) and to think of it as pleasant are one and the same thing’ (p. 58). Together, these statements, despite some obvious confusions in them, seem to support the principle I’ve outlined. If I can demonstrate that Mill’s reasons for these statements do not substantiate them, it must at least be acknowledged that I haven’t been fighting with shadows or dismantling a straw man.
[p. 65]
[p. 65]
It will be observed that Mill adds ‘absence of pain’ to ‘pleasure’ in his first statement, though not in his second. There is, in this, a confusion, with which, however, we need not deal. I shall talk of ‘pleasure’ alone, for the sake of conciseness; but all my arguments will apply à fortiori to ‘absence of pain’: it is easy to make the necessary substitutions.
It will be noted that Mill adds ‘absence of pain’ to ‘pleasure’ in his first statement, but not in his second. There’s a bit of confusion here, which we won't address. I will discuss ‘pleasure’ alone for the sake of clarity; however, all my arguments will also apply to ‘absence of pain’: it’s simple to make the necessary substitutions.
Mill holds, then, that ‘happiness is desirable, and the only thing desirable[10], as an end; all other things being only desirable as means to that end’ (p. 52). Happiness he has already defined as ‘pleasure, and the absence of pain’ (p. 10); he does not pretend that this is more than an arbitrary verbal definition; and, as such, I have not a word to say against it. His principle, then, is ‘pleasure is the only thing desirable,’ if I may be allowed, when I say ‘pleasure,’ to include in that word (so far as necessary) absence of pain. And now what are his reasons for holding that principle to be true? He has already told us (p. 6) that ‘Questions of ultimate ends are not amenable to direct proof. Whatever can be proved to be good, must be so by being shewn to be a means to something admitted to be good without proof.’ With this, I perfectly agree: indeed the chief object of my first chapter was to shew that this is so. Anything which is good as an end must be admitted to be good without proof. We are agreed so far. Mill even uses the same examples which I used in my second chapter. ‘How,’ he says, ‘is it possible to prove that health is good?’ ‘What proof is it possible to give that pleasure is good?’ Well, in Chapter IV, in which he deals with the proof of his Utilitarian principle, Mill repeats the above statement in these words: ‘It has already,’ he says, ‘been remarked, that questions of ultimate ends do not admit of proof, in the ordinary acceptation of the term’ (p. 52). ‘Questions about ends,’ he goes on in this same passage, ‘are, in other words, questions what things are desirable.’ I am quoting these repetitions, because they make it plain what otherwise might have been doubted, that Mill is using the words ‘desirable’ or ‘desirable as an end’ as absolutely and precisely equivalent to the words ‘good as an end.’ We are,[p. 66] then, now to hear, what reasons he advances for this doctrine that pleasure alone is good as an end.
Mill argues that "happiness is desirable, and the only thing desirable[10], as an end; all other things are only desirable as means to that end" (p. 52). He has already defined happiness as "pleasure, and the absence of pain" (p. 10); he doesn’t claim this is anything more than an arbitrary verbal definition, and as such, I have no objections to it. His principle, then, is "pleasure is the only thing desirable," provided that when I say "pleasure," I also include, as necessary, the absence of pain. So, what are his reasons for believing this principle to be true? He previously mentioned (p. 6) that "Questions of ultimate ends are not subject to direct proof. Whatever can be proven to be good must be shown to be a means to something admitted to be good without proof." I completely agree with this: in fact, the main focus of my first chapter was to demonstrate this point. Anything that is good as an end must be acknowledged as good without proof. So far, we are in agreement. Mill even references the same examples that I presented in my second chapter. "How," he asks, "is it possible to prove that health is good?" "What proof is possible to provide that pleasure is good?" Well, in Chapter IV, where he discusses the proof of his Utilitarian principle, Mill reiterates the earlier statement by saying, "It has already been noted that questions of ultimate ends do not admit proof in the usual sense of the word" (p. 52). He continues in that same passage, "Questions about ends, in other words, are questions about what things are desirable." I quote these repetitions to clarify what might otherwise be uncertain, that Mill uses the terms "desirable" or "desirable as an end" as completely and exactly equivalent to the term "good as an end." We are,[p. 66] now ready to hear what reasons he offers for this belief that pleasure alone is good as an end.
40. ‘Questions about ends,’ he says (pp. 52-3), ‘are, in other words, questions what things are desirable. The utilitarian doctrine is, that happiness is desirable, and the only thing desirable, as an end; all other things being only desirable as means to that end. What ought to be required of this doctrine—what conditions is it requisite that the doctrine should fulfil—to make good its claim to be believed?
40. “Questions about ends,” he says (pp. 52-3), “are, in other words, questions about what things are desirable. The utilitarian belief is that happiness is desirable and the only thing that is truly desirable as an end; everything else is only desirable as a means to that end. What should we require from this belief—what conditions must it meet—to justify its claim to be accepted?”
‘The only proof capable of being given that a thing is visible, is that people actually see it. The only proof that a sound is audible, is that people hear it; and so of the other sources of our experience. In like manner, I apprehend, the sole evidence it is possible to produce that anything is desirable, is that people do actually desire it. If the end which the utilitarian doctrine proposes to itself were not, in theory and in practice, acknowledged to be an end, nothing could ever convince any person that it was so. No reason can be given why the general happiness is desirable, except that each person, so far as he believes it to be attainable, desires his own happiness. This, however, being the fact, we have not only all the proof which the case admits of, but all which it is possible to require, that happiness is a good: that each person’s happiness is a good to that person, and the general happiness, therefore, a good to the aggregate of all persons. Happiness has made out its title as one of the ends of conduct, and consequently one of the criteria of morality.’
"The only proof that something is visible is that people can actually see it. The only proof that a sound is audible is that people can hear it; the same goes for all other sources of our experiences. Similarly, I believe the only evidence we can provide that something is desirable is that people actually desire it. If the goal that the utilitarian doctrine aims for were not recognized as a goal, both theoretically and practically, nothing could convince anyone that it is. There’s no reason to argue that general happiness is desirable, except that every person, as long as they believe it can be achieved, desires their own happiness. This being the case, we have not only all the proof we need but also everything anyone could require to show that happiness is a good: that each person's happiness is a good for them, and thus general happiness is a good for everyone combined. Happiness has established its claim as one of the goals of conduct, and therefore one of the standards of morality."
There, that is enough. That is my first point. Mill has made as naïve and artless a use of the naturalistic fallacy as anybody could desire. ‘Good,’ he tells us, means ‘desirable,’ and you can only find out what is desirable by seeking to find out what is actually desired. This is, of course, only one step towards the proof of Hedonism; for it may be, as Mill goes on to say, that other things beside pleasure are desired. Whether or not pleasure is the only thing desired is, as Mill himself admits (p. 58), a psychological question, to which we shall presently proceed. The important step for Ethics is this one just taken, the step which pretends to prove that ‘good’ means ‘desired.[p. 67]’ Well, the fallacy in this step is so obvious, that it is quite wonderful how Mill failed to see it. The fact is that ‘desirable’ does not mean ‘able to be desired’ as ‘visible’ means ‘able to be seen.’ The desirable means simply what ought to be desired or deserves to be desired; just as the detestable means not what can be but what ought to be detested and the damnable what deserves to be damned. Mill has, then, smuggled in, under cover of the word ‘desirable,’ the very notion about which he ought to be quite clear. ‘Desirable’ does indeed mean ‘what it is good to desire’; but when this is understood, it is no longer plausible to say that our only test of that, is what is actually desired. Is it merely a tautology when the Prayer Book talks of good desires? Are not bad desires also possible? Nay, we find Mill himself talking of a ‘better and nobler object of desire’ (p. 10), as if, after all, what is desired were not ipso facto good, and good in proportion to the amount it is desired. Moreover, if the desired is ipso facto the good; then the good is ipso facto the motive of our actions, and there can be no question of finding motives for doing it, as Mill is at such pains to do. If Mill’s explanation of ‘desirable’ be true, then his statement (p. 26) that the rule of action may be confounded with the motive of it is untrue: for the motive of action will then be according to him ipso facto its rule; there can be no distinction between the two, and therefore no confusion, and thus he has contradicted himself flatly. These are specimens of the contradictions, which, as I have tried to shew, must always follow from the use of the naturalistic fallacy; and I hope I need now say no more about the matter.
There, that’s enough. That’s my first point. Mill has made a simplistic and straightforward use of the naturalistic fallacy that anyone could notice. "Good," he tells us, means "desirable," and you can only find out what is desirable by figuring out what is actually desired. This is, of course, just one step toward proving Hedonism; it may be, as Mill goes on to say, that there are other things besides pleasure that people desire. Whether pleasure is the only thing desired is, as Mill himself admits (p. 58), a psychological question that we will address soon. The important step for Ethics is this one just taken, the step that claims to prove that "good" means "desired."[p. 67] The flaw in this step is so obvious that it’s surprising how Mill didn’t see it. The fact is that "desirable" does not mean "able to be desired" in the same way that "visible" means "able to be seen." "Desirable" simply refers to what ought to be desired or deserves to be desired; just as "detestable" means not what can be detested but what ought to be detested, and "damnable" means what deserves to be damned. Mill has, then, smuggled in, under the guise of the word "desirable," the very concept he should be clear about. "Desirable" does indeed mean "what is good to desire"; but once this is understood, it’s no longer reasonable to say that our only test of that is what is actually desired. Is it just a tautology when the Prayer Book mentions good desires? Aren’t bad desires also possible? In fact, we find Mill himself referring to a "better and nobler object of desire" (p. 10), as if what is desired were not ipso facto good and good in proportion to how much it is desired. Moreover, if what is desired is ipso facto the good, then the good is ipso facto the motive of our actions, and there can be no question of finding motives for doing it, as Mill is so concerned to do. If Mill’s explanation of "desirable" is true, then his statement (p. 26) that the rule of action may be confounded with the motive behind it is incorrect; because according to him, the motive of action would then ipso facto be its rule; there can be no distinction between the two, and thus no confusion, and so he has contradicted himself outright. These are examples of the contradictions that, as I have tried to show, always result from the use of the naturalistic fallacy; and I hope I need not say more about it now.
41. Well, then, the first step by which Mill has attempted to establish his Hedonism is simply fallacious. He has attempted to establish the identity of the good with the desired, by confusing the proper sense of ‘desirable,’ in which it denotes that which it is good to desire, with the sense which it would bear, if it were analogous to such words as ‘visible.’ If ‘desirable’ is to be identical with ‘good,’ then it must bear one sense; and if it is to be identical with ‘desired,’ then it must bear quite another sense. And yet to Mill’s contention that the desired is necessarily good, it is quite essential that these two senses of[p. 68] ‘desirable’ should be the same. If he holds they are the same, then he has contradicted himself elsewhere; if he holds they are not the same, then the first step in his proof of Hedonism is absolutely worthless.
41. Well, the first step Mill took to support his Hedonism is simply flawed. He tried to equate the good with what is desired by mixing up the proper meaning of ‘desirable,’ which refers to what is good to desire, with a meaning that would be similar to words like ‘visible.’ If ‘desirable’ is to mean the same as ‘good,’ then it has to have one meaning; and if it’s to mean the same as ‘desired,’ then it has to have a completely different meaning. Yet, for Mill's argument that the desired is necessarily good to hold up, these two meanings of[p. 68] ‘desirable’ must be the same. If he insists they are the same, then he has contradicted himself in other parts; if he insists they are not the same, then his initial argument for Hedonism is completely useless.
But now we must deal with the second step. Having proved, as he thinks, that the good means the desired, Mill recognises that, if he is further to maintain that pleasure alone is good, he must prove that pleasure alone is really desired. This doctrine that ‘pleasure alone is the object of all our desires’ is the doctrine which Prof. Sidgwick has called Psychological Hedonism: and it is a doctrine which most eminent psychologists are now agreed in rejecting. But it is a necessary step in the proof of any such Naturalistic Hedonism as Mill’s; and it is so commonly held, by people not expert either in psychology or in philosophy, that I wish to treat it at some length. It will be seen that Mill does not hold it in this bare form. He admits that other things than pleasure are desired; and this admission is at once a contradiction of his Hedonism. One of the shifts by which he seeks to evade this contradiction we shall afterwards consider. But some may think that no such shifts are needed: they may say of Mill, what Callicles says of Polus in the Gorgias[11], that he has made this fatal admission through a most unworthy fear of appearing paradoxical; that they, on the other hand, will have the courage of their convictions, and will not be ashamed to go to any lengths of paradox, in defence of what they hold to be the truth.
But now we need to address the second step. After believing he has proven that good means what we desire, Mill acknowledges that if he wants to claim that only pleasure is good, he must show that only pleasure is truly desired. This idea that "pleasure alone is the goal of all our desires" is what Professor Sidgwick calls Psychological Hedonism, a concept that most leading psychologists currently reject. However, it's a crucial step in supporting any form of Naturalistic Hedonism like Mill’s. It's also widely accepted by people who aren’t experts in psychology or philosophy, so I’d like to discuss it in detail. It will become clear that Mill doesn't support this idea in its simplest form. He concedes that we desire things other than pleasure, which contradicts his Hedonism. We'll later examine one of the ways he tries to navigate this contradiction. Some might argue that no such tactics are necessary: they might echo what Callicles says about Polus in the Gorgias[11], claiming that Mill's misguided acknowledgment is rooted in a fear of looking paradoxical; meanwhile, they assert their commitment to their beliefs and embrace any degree of paradox to defend what they see as the truth.
42. Well, then, we are supposing it held that pleasure is the object of all desire, that it is the universal end of all human activity. Now I suppose it will not be denied that people are commonly said to desire other things: for instance, we usually talk of desiring food and drink, of desiring money, approbation, fame. The question, then, must be of what is meant by desire, and by the object of desire. There is obviously asserted some sort of necessary or universal relation between something which is called desire, and another thing which is called pleasure. The question is of what sort this relation is; whether in conjunction with the naturalistic fallacy above mentioned, it will justify[p. 69] Hedonism. Now I am not prepared to deny that there is some universal relation between pleasure and desire; but I hope to shew, that, if there is, it is of such sort as will rather make against than for Hedonism. It is urged that pleasure is always the object of desire, and I am ready to admit that pleasure is always, in part at least, the cause of desire. But this distinction is very important. Both views might be expressed in the same language; both might be said to hold that whenever we desire, we always desire because of some pleasure: if I asked my supposed Hedonist, ‘Why do you desire that?’ he might answer, quite consistently with his contention, ‘Because there is pleasure there,’ and if he asked me the same question, I might answer, equally consistently with my contention, ‘Because there is pleasure here.’ Only our two answers would not mean the same thing. It is this use of the same language to denote quite different facts, which I believe to be the chief cause why Psychological Hedonism is so often held, just as it was also the cause of Mill’s naturalistic fallacy.
42. Well, let's assume that pleasure is the goal of all desire and that it is the ultimate aim of all human actions. Now, I think no one can deny that people often say they desire other things: for example, we commonly talk about wanting food and drink, wanting money, approval, and fame. The key question, then, is what we mean by desire and the object of desire. Clearly, there is something suggested about a necessary or universal connection between what we call desire and what we call pleasure. The question is what kind of connection this is; whether, alongside the naturalistic fallacy mentioned earlier, it supports[p. 69] Hedonism. I’m not going to deny that there is some universal link between pleasure and desire, but I hope to show that, if it exists, it’s actually more against Hedonism than for it. It's argued that pleasure is always the object of desire, and I can agree that pleasure is always, at least in part, the cause of desire. However, this distinction is very important. Both points of view could use the same language; both might say that whenever we desire, we always desire because of some pleasure: if I asked my hypothetical Hedonist, ‘Why do you want that?’ he could respond, consistent with his view, ‘Because there is pleasure in it,’ and if he asked me the same question, I might answer, equally consistent with my view, ‘Because there is pleasure in it.’ However, our two answers wouldn’t mean the same thing. It’s this use of the same language to signify completely different facts that I believe is the main reason why Psychological Hedonism is so often accepted, just as it was the reason for Mill’s naturalistic fallacy.
Let us try to analyse the psychological state which is called ‘desire.’ That name is usually confined to a state of mind in which the idea of some object or event, not yet existing, is present to us. Suppose, for instance, I am desiring a glass of port wine. I have the idea of drinking such a glass before my mind, although I am not yet drinking it. Well, how does pleasure enter in to this relation? My theory is that it enters in, in this way. The idea of the drinking causes a feeling of pleasure in my mind, which helps to produce that state of incipient activity, which is called ‘desire.’ It is, therefore, because of a pleasure, which I already have—the pleasure excited by a mere idea—that I desire the wine, which I have not. And I am ready to admit that a pleasure of this kind, an actual pleasure, is always among the causes of every desire, and not only of every desire, but of every mental activity, whether conscious or sub-conscious. I am ready to admit this, I say: I cannot vouch that it is the true psychological doctrine; but, at all events, it is not primâ facie quite absurd. And now, what is the other doctrine, the doctrine which I am supposing held, and which is at all events essential to Mill’s argument?[p. 70] It is this. That when I desire the wine, it is not the wine which I desire but the pleasure which I expect to get from it. In other words, the doctrine is that the idea of a pleasure not actual is always necessary to cause desire; whereas my doctrine was that the actual pleasure caused by the idea of something else was always necessary to cause desire. It is these two different theories which I suppose the Psychological Hedonists to confuse: the confusion is, as Mr Bradley puts it[12], between ‘a pleasant thought’ and ‘the thought of a pleasure.’ It is in fact only where the latter, the ‘thought of a pleasure,’ is present, that pleasure can be said to be the object of desire, or the motive to action. On the other hand, when only a pleasant thought is present, as, I admit, may always be the case, then it is the object of the thought—that which we are thinking about—which is the object of desire and the motive to action; and the pleasure, which that thought excites, may, indeed, cause our desire or move us to action, but it is not our end or object nor our motive.
Let's analyze the psychological state known as ‘desire.’ This term typically refers to a mental state where we have in mind the idea of a certain object or event that doesn’t exist yet. For example, if I desire a glass of port wine, I imagine drinking that glass, even though I’m not actually drinking it yet. So, how does pleasure fit into this? My theory is that pleasure comes into play in this way. The idea of drinking creates a feeling of pleasure in my mind, which helps to trigger the state of initial activity we call ‘desire.’ Therefore, it’s the pleasure I already have—the pleasure sparked by just the idea—that makes me desire the wine I don’t have. I’m willing to acknowledge that this kind of pleasure, actual pleasure, is always one of the reasons for every desire and not just every desire but for all mental activities, whether we're aware of them or not. I’m ready to admit this; I can’t guarantee it’s the true psychological theory, but, at least, it’s not outright absurd. Now, what’s the other theory I’m assuming is held, which is essential to Mill’s argument? It’s this: when I desire the wine, it’s not the wine itself I desire, but the pleasure I expect to gain from it. In other words, the theory is that the idea of a pleasure that isn’t actual is always needed to create desire, while my theory suggests that the actual pleasure caused by the thought of something else is always needed to create desire. These are the two different theories I believe Psychological Hedonists confuse: the confusion, as Mr. Bradley puts it, is between ‘a pleasant thought’ and ‘the thought of a pleasure.’ In reality, it’s only when the latter, the ‘thought of a pleasure,’ is present that pleasure can be regarded as the object of desire or the motive for action. Conversely, when only a pleasant thought exists, as I admit may often be the case, then it’s the object of that thought—what we’re thinking about—that becomes the object of desire and the motive for action; and the pleasure that thought generates may indeed incite our desire or prompt us to act, but it’s not our ultimate goal or objective nor our motive.
Well, I hope this distinction is sufficiently clear. Now let us see how it bears upon Ethical Hedonism. I assume it to be perfectly obvious that the idea of the object of desire is not always and only the idea of a pleasure. In the first place, plainly, we are not always conscious of expecting pleasure, when we desire a thing. We may be only conscious of the thing which we desire, and may be impelled to make for it at once, without any calculation as to whether it will bring us pleasure or pain. And, in the second place, even when we do expect pleasure, it can certainly be very rarely pleasure only which we desire. For instance, granted that, when I desire my glass of port wine, I have also an idea of the pleasure I expect from it, plainly that pleasure cannot be the only object of my desire; the port wine must be included in my object, else I might be led by my desire to take wormwood instead of wine. If the desire were directed solely towards the pleasure, it could not lead me to take the wine; if it is to take a definite direction, it is absolutely necessary that the idea of the object, from which the pleasure is expected, should also be present and[p. 71] should control my activity. The theory then that what is desired is always and only pleasure must break down: it is impossible to prove that pleasure alone is good, by that line of argument. But, if we substitute for this theory, that other, possibly true, theory, that pleasure is always the cause of desire, then all the plausibility of our ethical doctrine that pleasure alone is good straightway disappears. For in this case, pleasure is not what I desire, it is not what I want: it is something which I already have, before I can want anything. And can any one feel inclined to maintain, that that which I already have, while I am still desiring something else, is always and alone the good?
Well, I hope this distinction is clear enough. Now let’s explore how it relates to Ethical Hedonism. It seems obvious that the object of desire isn’t always just the prospect of pleasure. First, it’s clear that we’re not always aware of expecting pleasure when we want something. We might simply be aware of what we desire and feel compelled to go after it right away, without considering whether it will bring us joy or discomfort. Secondly, even when we do foresee pleasure, it’s rare that pleasure is the only thing we want. For example, when I crave my glass of port wine, I also have an idea of the pleasure I expect from it, but that pleasure can’t be the only object of my desire; I need the port wine itself to be part of my desire, or else I might be led to choose wormwood instead of wine. If my desire were aimed solely at the pleasure, it wouldn't lead me to select the wine; to have a specific aim, the idea of the object, which is expected to bring pleasure, must also be present and should guide my actions. Therefore, the theory that what we desire is always just pleasure must be flawed: it can't be proven that pleasure alone is good using that reasoning. However, if we replace this theory with another possibly true one—that pleasure is always the trigger for desire—then the credibility of our ethical argument that only pleasure is good completely vanishes. In this case, pleasure isn’t what I desire or want; it’s something I already have before I can desire anything. Can anyone really argue that what I already possess while I’m still wanting something else is always and solely the good?
43. But now let us return to consider another of Mill’s arguments for his position that ‘happiness is the sole end of human action.’ Mill admits, as I have said, that pleasure is not the only thing we actually desire. ‘The desire of virtue,’ he says, ‘is not as universal, but it is as authentic a fact, as the desire of happiness[13].’ And again, ‘Money is, in many cases, desired in and for itself[14].’ These admissions are, of course, in naked and glaring contradiction with his argument that pleasure is the only thing desirable, because it is the only thing desired. How then does Mill even attempt to avoid this contradiction? His chief argument seems to be that ‘virtue,’ ‘money’ and other such objects, when they are thus desired in and for themselves, are desired only as ‘a part of happiness[15].’ Now what does this mean? Happiness, as we saw, has been defined by Mill, as ‘pleasure and the absence of pain.’ Does Mill mean to say that ‘money,’ these actual coins, which he admits to be desired in and for themselves, are a part either of pleasure or of the absence of pain? Will he maintain that those coins themselves are in my mind, and actually a part of my pleasant feelings? If this is to be said, all words are useless: nothing can possibly be distinguished from anything else; if these two things are not distinct, what on earth is? We shall hear next that this table is really and truly the same thing as this room; that a cab-horse is in fact indistinguishable from St Paul’s Cathedral; that this book of Mill’s which I hold in[p. 72] my hand, because it was his pleasure to produce it, is now and at this moment a part of the happiness which he felt many years ago and which has so long ceased to be. Pray consider a moment what this contemptible nonsense really means. ‘Money,’ says Mill, ‘is only desirable as a means to happiness.’ Perhaps so; but what then? ‘Why,’ says Mill, ‘money is undoubtedly desired for its own sake.’ ‘Yes, go on,’ say we. ‘Well,’ says Mill, ‘if money is desired for its own sake, it must be desirable as an end-in-itself: I have said so myself.’ ‘Oh,’ say we, ‘but you also said just now that it was only desirable as a means.’ ‘I own I did,’ says Mill, ‘but I will try to patch up matters, by saying that what is only a means to an end, is the same thing as a part of that end. I daresay the public won’t notice.’ And the public haven’t noticed. Yet this is certainly what Mill has done. He has broken down the distinction between means and ends, upon the precise observance of which his Hedonism rests. And he has been compelled to do this, because he has failed to distinguish ‘end’ in the sense of what is desirable, from ‘end’ in the sense of what is desired: a distinction which, nevertheless, both the present argument and his whole book presupposes. This is a consequence of the naturalistic fallacy.
43. But now let’s go back to examine another of Mill’s arguments for his claim that ‘happiness is the only goal of human actions.’ Mill acknowledges, as I mentioned before, that pleasure isn’t the only thing we desire. ‘The desire for virtue,’ he states, ‘is not as universal, but it is just as genuine a fact as the desire for happiness[13].’ And again, ‘Money is often desired for its own sake[14].’ These admissions clearly contradict his argument that pleasure is the only thing that is desirable because it’s the only thing we seek. So how does Mill try to avoid this contradiction? His main argument seems to be that ‘virtue,’ ‘money,’ and other such things, when desired for themselves, are sought only as ‘a part of happiness[15].’ But what does this mean? Happiness, as we’ve seen, has been defined by Mill as ‘pleasure and the absence of pain.’ Is Mill suggesting that ‘money,’ these actual coins, which he admits are desired for themselves, are part of either pleasure or the absence of pain? Does he claim that those coins exist in my mind and are actually part of my pleasurable feelings? If that’s the case, then all language is meaningless: nothing can really be distinguished from anything else; if these two things aren’t separate, then what on earth is? We will soon hear that this table is actually the same as this room; that a cab-horse is indistinguishable from St Paul’s Cathedral; that this book of Mill’s that I hold in[p. 72] my hand, simply because he felt happy producing it, is now, at this moment, part of the happiness he experienced many years ago and that has long since passed. Take a moment to think about what this ridiculous nonsense actually means. ‘Money,’ says Mill, ‘is only desirable as a means to happiness.’ Maybe so; but then what? ‘Well,’ Mill says, ‘money is definitely desired for its own sake.’ ‘Yes, keep going,’ we reply. ‘Okay,’ Mill continues, ‘if money is desired for its own sake, it has to be desirable as an end in itself: I’ve said that myself.’ ‘Oh,’ we respond, ‘but you also just said that it was only desirable as a means.’ ‘I admit I did,’ says Mill, ‘but I’ll try to fix things by saying that what is just a means to an end is the same as a part of that end. I’m sure the public won’t notice.’ And the public hasn’t noticed. Yet this is exactly what Mill has done. He has collapsed the distinction between means and ends, a distinction that his Hedonism relies on. He was forced to do this because he failed to differentiate ‘end’ in the sense of what is desirable from ‘end’ in the sense of what is desired: a distinction that both this argument and his entire book presupposes. This is a result of the naturalistic fallacy.
44. Mill, then, has nothing better to say for himself than this. His two fundamental propositions are, in his own words, ‘that to think of an object as desirable (unless for the sake of its consequences), and to think of it as pleasant, are one and the same thing; and that to desire anything except in proportion as the idea of it is pleasant, is a physical and metaphysical impossibility[16].’ Both of these statements are, we have seen, merely supported by fallacies. The first seems to rest on the naturalistic fallacy; the second rests partly on this, partly on the fallacy of confusing ends and means, and partly on the fallacy of confusing a pleasant thought with the thought of a pleasure. His very language shews this. For that the idea of a thing is pleasant, in his second clause, is obviously meant to be the same fact which he denotes by ‘thinking of it as pleasant,’ in his first.
44. So, Mill doesn't really have anything better to say for himself than this. His two main points are, in his own words, ‘to think of something as desirable (unless it's about its consequences), and to think of it as pleasant, are basically the same thing; and to want anything unless the idea of it is pleasant is an impossible physical and metaphysical situation[16].’ We've seen that both of these claims are supported only by logical errors. The first one seems to rely on the naturalistic fallacy; the second relies partly on that, partly on confusing ends and means, and partly on mixing up a pleasant thought with the thought of pleasure. His choice of words makes this clear. For him, the idea of something being pleasant in his second point is obviously meant to refer to the same thing as ‘thinking of it as pleasant’ in his first point.
[p. 73]
[p. 73]
Accordingly, Mill’s arguments for the proposition that pleasure is the sole good, and our refutation of those arguments, may be summed up as follows:
Accordingly, Mill’s arguments for the idea that pleasure is the only good, and our rebuttal of those arguments, can be summarized as follows:
First of all, he takes ‘the desirable,’ which he uses as a synonym for ‘the good,’ to mean what can be desired. The test, again, of what can be desired, is, according to him, what actually is desired: if, therefore, he says, we can find some one thing which is always and alone desired, that thing will necessarily be the only thing that is desirable, the only thing that is good as an end. In this argument the naturalistic fallacy is plainly involved. That fallacy, I explained, consists in the contention that good means nothing but some simple or complex notion, that can be defined in terms of natural qualities. In Mill’s case, good is thus supposed to mean simply what is desired; and what is desired is something which can thus be defined in natural terms. Mill tells us that we ought to desire something (an ethical proposition), because we actually do desire it; but if his contention that ‘I ought to desire’ means nothing but ‘I do desire’ were true, then he is only entitled to say, ‘We do desire so and so, because we do desire it’; and that is not an ethical proposition at all; it is a mere tautology. The whole object of Mill’s book is to help us to discover what we ought to do; but, in fact, by attempting to define the meaning of this ‘ought,’ he has completely debarred himself from ever fulfilling that object: he has confined himself to telling us what we do do.
First of all, he takes ‘the desirable,’ which he uses as a synonym for ‘the good,’ to mean what can be desired. The test, according to him, of what can be desired is what actually is desired: if he can find one thing that is always and only desired, that thing will necessarily be the only thing that is desirable, the only thing that is good as an end. In this argument, the naturalistic fallacy is clearly involved. That fallacy, as I explained, consists of the claim that good means nothing more than some simple or complex concept that can be defined in terms of natural qualities. In Mill’s case, good is supposed to mean simply what is desired; and what is desired can be defined in natural terms. Mill tells us that we should desire something (an ethical proposition) because we actually do desire it; but if his claim that ‘I ought to desire’ means nothing more than ‘I do desire’ were true, then he would only be able to say, ‘We do desire this and that because we desire it’; and that is not an ethical proposition at all; it is just a tautology. The whole purpose of Mill’s book is to help us discover what we should do; but, in fact, by trying to define the meaning of this ‘ought,’ he has completely locked himself out of ever achieving that purpose: he has limited himself to telling us what we do.
Mill’s first argument then is that, because good means desired, therefore the desired is good; but having thus arrived at an ethical conclusion, by denying that any ethical conclusion is possible, he still needs another argument to make his conclusion a basis for Hedonism. He has to prove that we always do desire pleasure or freedom from pain, and that we never desire anything else whatever. This second doctrine, which Professor Sidgwick has called Psychological Hedonism, I accordingly discussed. I pointed out how obviously untrue it is that we never desire anything but pleasure; and how there is not a shadow of ground for saying even that, whenever we desire anything, we always desire pleasure as well as that thing.[p. 74] I attributed the obstinate belief in these untruths partly to a confusion between the cause of desire and the object of desire. It may, I said, be true that desire can never occur unless it be preceded by some actual pleasure; but even if this is true, it obviously gives no ground for saying that the object of desire is always some future pleasure. By the object of desire is meant that, of which the idea causes desire in us; it is some pleasure, which we anticipate, some pleasure which we have not got, which is the object of desire, whenever we do desire pleasure. And any actual pleasure, which may be excited by the idea of this anticipated pleasure, is obviously not the same pleasure as that anticipated pleasure, of which only the idea is actual. This actual pleasure is not what we want; what we want is always something which we have not got; and to say that pleasure always causes us to want is quite a different thing from saying that what we want is always pleasure.
Mill’s first argument is that since good means what we desire, then what is desired is good; however, having reached this ethical conclusion while claiming that no ethical conclusion is possible, he still needs another argument to support Hedonism. He must prove that we always desire pleasure or freedom from pain and that we never desire anything else. This second idea, which Professor Sidgwick called Psychological Hedonism, I addressed. I pointed out how obviously false it is that we only desire pleasure, and how there is no evidence to support the claim that whenever we desire anything, we always desire pleasure along with that thing.[p. 74] I attributed the stubborn belief in these falsehoods partly to a mix-up between the cause of desire and the object of desire. I noted that it might be true that desire can never happen unless it's preceded by some actual pleasure; but even if that's true, it doesn’t support the idea that the object of desire is always some future pleasure. The object of desire refers to that which inspires desire in us; it is some pleasure we anticipate, some pleasure we don’t have, which becomes the object of desire whenever we do seek pleasure. And any actual pleasure that might arise from the thought of this anticipated pleasure is clearly not the same as that anticipated pleasure, of which only the idea is real. This actual pleasure is not what we want; what we want is always something we don’t have; and to say that pleasure always makes us want is very different from saying that what we want is always pleasure.
Finally, we saw, Mill admits all this. He insists that we do actually desire other things than pleasure, and yet he says we do really desire nothing else. He tries to explain away this contradiction, by confusing together two notions, which he has before carefully distinguished—the notions of means and of end. He now says that a means to an end is the same thing as a part of that end. To this last fallacy special attention should be given, as our ultimate decision with regard to Hedonism will largely turn upon it.
Finally, we see that Mill admits all of this. He insists that we do actually want things other than pleasure, and yet he claims we do really want nothing else. He tries to explain this contradiction by blending two ideas that he had previously distinguished—the ideas of means and ends. He now states that a means to an end is the same as a part of that end. This last error deserves special attention, as our final judgment regarding Hedonism will mostly depend on it.
45. It is this ultimate decision with regard to Hedonism at which we must now try to arrive. So far I have been only occupied with refuting Mill’s naturalistic arguments for Hedonism; but the doctrine that pleasure alone is desirable may still be true, although Mill’s fallacies cannot prove it so. This is the question which we have now to face. This proposition, ‘pleasure alone is good or desirable,’ belongs undoubtedly to that class of propositions, to which Mill at first rightly pretended it belonged, the class of first principles, which are not amenable to direct proof. But in this case, as he also rightly says, ‘considerations may be presented capable of determining the intellect either to give or withhold its assent to the doctrine’ (p. 7). It is such considerations that Professor[p. 75] Sidgwick presents, and such also that I shall try to present for the opposite view. This proposition that ‘pleasure alone is good as an end,’ the fundamental proposition of Ethical Hedonism, will then appear, in Professor Sidgwick’s language, as an object of intuition. I shall try to shew you why my intuition denies it, just as his intuition affirms it. It may always be true notwithstanding; neither intuition can prove whether it is true or not; I am bound to be satisfied, if I can ‘present considerations capable of determining the intellect’ to reject it.
45. We now need to reach a final decision regarding Hedonism. Until now, I have focused solely on disproving Mill’s naturalistic arguments for Hedonism; however, the idea that pleasure is the only thing worth having may still be valid, even if Mill’s errors can’t support it. This is the issue we must confront. The statement, ‘pleasure alone is good or desirable,’ certainly falls into that category of statements which Mill correctly claimed it belonged to, those fundamental principles that can't be proven directly. But, as he also rightly noted, ‘considerations may be presented capable of determining the intellect either to agree or disagree with the doctrine’ (p. 7). It’s these considerations that Professor[p. 75] Sidgwick offers, and I will also present arguments for the opposing view. This proposition that ‘pleasure alone is good as an end,’ which is the fundamental claim of Ethical Hedonism, will then come across, in Professor Sidgwick’s terminology, as something to be intuitively understood. I will demonstrate why my intuition rejects it, just as his intuition supports it. It may still be true regardless; neither intuition can prove its truth, but I must find satisfaction if I can ‘present considerations capable of determining the intellect’ to dismiss it.
Now it may be said that this is a very unsatisfactory state of things. It is indeed; but it is important to make a distinction between two different reasons, which may be given for calling it unsatisfactory. Is it unsatisfactory because our principle cannot be proved? or is it unsatisfactory merely because we do not agree with one another about it? I am inclined to think that the latter is the chief reason. For the mere fact that in certain cases proof is impossible does not usually give us the least uneasiness. For instance, nobody can prove that this is a chair beside me; yet I do not suppose that any one is much dissatisfied for that reason. We all agree that it is a chair, and that is enough to content us, although it is quite possible we may be wrong. A madman, of course, might come in and say that it is not a chair but an elephant. We could not prove that he was wrong, and the fact that he did not agree with us might then begin to make us uneasy. Much more, then, shall we be uneasy, if some one, whom we do not think to be mad, disagrees with us. We shall try to argue with him, and we shall probably be content if we lead him to agree with us, although we shall not have proved our point. We can only persuade him by shewing him that our view is consistent with something else which he holds to be true, whereas his original view is contradictory to it. But it will be impossible to prove that that something else, which we both agree to be true, is really so; we shall be satisfied to have settled the matter in dispute by means of it, merely because we are agreed on it. In short, our dissatisfaction in these cases is almost always of the type felt by the poor lunatic in[p. 76] the story. ‘I said the world was mad,’ says he, ‘and the world said that I was mad; and, confound it, they outvoted me.’ It is, I say, almost always such a disagreement, and not the impossibility of proof, which makes us call the state of things unsatisfactory. For, indeed, who can prove that proof itself is a warrant of truth? We are all agreed that the laws of logic are true and therefore we accept a result which is proved by their means; but such a proof is satisfactory to us only because we are all so fully agreed that it is a warrant of truth. And yet we cannot, by the nature of the case, prove that we are right in being so agreed.
Now it can be said that this is a really unsatisfactory situation. It is, indeed; but it’s important to distinguish between two different reasons for calling it unsatisfactory. Is it unsatisfactory because our principle can’t be proven? Or is it unsatisfactory simply because we disagree with each other about it? I tend to think that the latter is the main reason. The mere fact that proof is impossible in certain cases usually doesn’t bother us at all. For example, nobody can prove that this is a chair next to me; yet I don’t think anyone is very dissatisfied for that reason. We all agree that it’s a chair, and that’s enough to satisfy us, even though it’s entirely possible we could be wrong. A madman could come in and say that it’s not a chair but an elephant. We couldn’t prove that he was wrong, and the fact that he disagrees with us might start to make us uneasy. Even more so, we’d be uneasy if someone we don’t think is crazy disagrees with us. We’d try to argue with him, and we’d probably feel satisfied if we got him to agree with us, even though we wouldn’t have proven our point. We can only persuade him by showing him that our view is consistent with something else he believes to be true, while his original view contradicts it. But it would be impossible to prove that the something else, which we both agree is true, really is so; we’d be satisfied to have settled the disagreement because we both agree on it. In short, our dissatisfaction in these cases is almost always like what the poor lunatic in [p. 76] the story feels. ‘I said the world was mad,’ he says, ‘and the world said that I was mad; and, damn it, they outvoted me.’ It is, I say, almost always that kind of disagreement, and not the imposs
Accordingly, I do not think we need be much distressed by our admission that we cannot prove whether pleasure alone is good or not. We may be able to arrive at an agreement notwithstanding; and if so, I think it will be satisfactory. And yet I am not very sanguine about our prospects of such satisfaction. Ethics, and philosophy in general, have always been in a peculiarly unsatisfactory state. There has been no agreement about them, as there is about the existence of chairs and lights and benches. I should therefore be a fool if I hoped to settle one great point of controversy, now and once for all. It is extremely improbable I shall convince. It would be highly presumptuous even to hope that in the end, say two or three centuries hence, it will be agreed that pleasure is not the sole good. Philosophical questions are so difficult, the problems they raise are so complex, that no one can fairly expect, now, any more than in the past, to win more than a very limited assent. And yet I confess that the considerations which I am about to present appear to me to be absolutely convincing. I do think that they ought to convince, if only I can put them well. In any case, I can but try. I shall try now to put an end to that unsatisfactory state of things, of which I have been speaking. I shall try to produce an agreement that the fundamental principle of Hedonism is very like an absurdity, by shewing what it must mean, if it is clearly thought out, and how that clear meaning is in conflict with other beliefs, which will, I hope, not be so easily given up.
I don’t think we should be too upset about admitting that we can’t prove whether pleasure is good on its own. We might still reach some level of agreement, and if we do, I believe it will be satisfying. However, I’m not overly optimistic about our chances for that satisfaction. Ethics and philosophy have always been in a strangely unsatisfactory state. There’s been no consensus on them, unlike our agreement on the existence of chairs, lights, and benches. So, it would be foolish of me to expect to settle one major point of debate once and for all. It’s highly unlikely I’ll convince anyone. It would be quite arrogant to even think that, say, in two or three centuries, there will be agreement that pleasure isn’t the only good. Philosophical questions are incredibly difficult, and the issues they raise are so complex that no one can reasonably expect, now or in the past, to gain more than limited agreement. Still, I admit that the points I’m about to present seem completely convincing to me. I do believe they should convince, if only I can express them well. In any case, I can only try. I will now attempt to put an end to the unsatisfactory situation I’ve been discussing. I aim to show that the core principle of Hedonism is quite absurd by clarifying what it must mean when thought out clearly, and how that clear meaning conflicts with other beliefs that I hope won’t be easily dismissed.
46. Well, then, we now proceed to discuss Intuitionistic[p. 77] Hedonism. And the beginning of this discussion marks, it is to be observed, a turning-point in my ethical method. The point I have been labouring hitherto, the point that ‘good is indefinable,’ and that to deny this involves a fallacy, is a point capable of strict proof: for to deny it involves contradictions. But now we are coming to the question, for the sake of answering which Ethics exists, the question what things or qualities are good. Of any answer to this question no direct proof is possible, and that, just because of our former answer, as to the meaning of good, direct proof was possible. We are now confined to the hope of what Mill calls ‘indirect proof,’ the hope of determining one another’s intellect; and we are now so confined, just because, in the matter of the former question we are not so confined. Here, then, is an intuition to be submitted to our verdict—the intuition that ‘pleasure alone is good as an end—good in and for itself.’
46. Well, now let's discuss Intuitionistic[p. 77] Hedonism. This marks a turning point in my ethical approach. Up until now, I've argued that 'good is indefinable,' and denying this leads to a fallacy. This argument can be strictly proven, as denying it results in contradictions. But now we're addressing the question that ethics aims to answer: what things or qualities are good. For this question, no direct proof is possible, and that's precisely because of our earlier conclusion about the meaning of good, where direct proof was possible. We are now limited to what Mill refers to as 'indirect proof,' the hope of understanding each other’s reasoning; and we find ourselves in this situation because, regarding the previous question, we were not limited. So, here’s an intuition for us to evaluate—the intuition that 'pleasure alone is good as an end—good in and of itself.'
47. Well, in this connection it seems first desirable to touch on another doctrine of Mill’s—another doctrine which, in the interest of Hedonism, Professor Sidgwick has done very wisely to reject. This is the doctrine of ‘difference of quality in pleasures.’ ‘If I am asked,’ says Mill[17], ‘what I mean by difference of quality in pleasures, or what makes one pleasure more valuable than another, merely as a pleasure, except its being greater in amount, there is but one possible answer. Of two pleasures, if there be one to which all or almost all who have experience of both give a decided preference, irrespective of any feeling of moral obligation to prefer it, that is the more desirable pleasure. If one of the two is, by those who are competently acquainted with both, placed so far above the other that they prefer it, even though knowing it to be attended with a greater amount of discontent, and would not resign it for any quantity of the other pleasure which their nature is capable of, we are justified in ascribing to the preferred enjoyment a superiority in quality, so far outweighing quantity as to render it, in comparison, of small account.’
47. In this context, it seems important to address another of Mill’s ideas—one that Professor Sidgwick has wisely chosen to reject for the sake of Hedonism. This idea is about the “difference in quality of pleasures.” Mill says, “If you ask me what I mean by the difference in quality of pleasures, or what makes one pleasure more valuable than another, aside from quantity, there's only one answer. Of two pleasures, if there’s one that almost everyone who has experienced both prefers, regardless of any sense of moral duty to choose it, that is the more desirable pleasure. If one of the two is viewed by those who really know both as significantly better than the other, to the point where they would prefer it—even knowing it brings more dissatisfaction, and wouldn’t give it up for any amount of the other pleasure they could enjoy—we can conclude that the preferred pleasure has a quality that outweighs the quantity enough to make the other seem insignificant by comparison.”
Now it is well known that Bentham rested his case for Hedonism on ‘quantity of pleasure’ alone. It was his maxim,[p. 78] that ‘quantity of pleasure being equal, pushpin is as good as poetry.’ And Mill apparently considers Bentham to have proved that nevertheless poetry is better than pushpin; that poetry does produce a greater quantity of pleasure. But yet, says Mill, the Utilitarians ‘might have taken the other and, as it may be called, higher ground, with entire consistency’ (p. 11). Now we see from this that Mill acknowledges ‘quality of pleasure’ to be another or different ground for estimating pleasures, than Bentham’s quantity; and moreover, by that question-begging ‘higher,’ which he afterwards translates into ‘superior,’ he seems to betray an uncomfortable feeling, that, after all, if you take quantity of pleasure for your only standard, something may be wrong and you may deserve to be called a pig. And it may presently appear that you very likely would deserve that name. But, meanwhile, I only wish to shew that Mill’s admissions as to quality of pleasure are either inconsistent with his Hedonism, or else afford no other ground for it than would be given by mere quantity of pleasure.
Now it’s well known that Bentham based his case for Hedonism solely on ‘quantity of pleasure.’ His principle was that ‘if the quantity of pleasure is the same, pushpin is as good as poetry.’ Mill apparently believes Bentham showed that poetry is still better than pushpin, as poetry provides a greater amount of pleasure. However, Mill argues that the Utilitarians ‘could have taken the other and, as one might say, higher ground, without being inconsistent’ (p. 11). This indicates that Mill recognizes 'quality of pleasure' as a different criterion for evaluating pleasures compared to Bentham’s quantity; and furthermore, by using the somewhat loaded term ‘higher,’ which he later rephrases as ‘superior,’ he seems to reveal a nagging worry that if you only focus on the quantity of pleasure as your standard, something might be off, and you could be labeled a pig. It may soon become clear that you very well might deserve such a label. Meanwhile, I just want to show that Mill’s acknowledgments regarding the quality of pleasure are either inconsistent with his Hedonism or provide no additional basis for it beyond what is offered by mere quantity of pleasure.
It will be seen that Mill’s test for one pleasure’s superiority in quality over another is the preference of most people who have experienced both. A pleasure so preferred, he holds, is more desirable. But then, as we have seen, he holds that ‘to think of an object as desirable and to think of it as pleasant are one and the same thing’ (p. 58). He holds, therefore, that the preference of experts merely proves that one pleasure is pleasanter than another. But if that is so, how can he distinguish this standard from the standard of quantity of pleasure? Can one pleasure be pleasanter than another, except in the sense that it gives more pleasure? ‘Pleasant’ must, if words are to have any meaning at all, denote some one quality common to all the things that are pleasant; and, if so, then one thing can only be more pleasant than another, according as it has more or less of this one quality. But, then, let us try the other alternative, and suppose that Mill does not seriously mean that this preference of experts merely proves one pleasure to be pleasanter than another. Well, in this case what does ‘preferred’ mean? It cannot mean ‘more desired,’ since, as we know, the degree of desire is always, according[p. 79] to Mill, in exact proportion to the degree of pleasantness. But, in that case, the basis of Mill’s Hedonism collapses, for he is admitting that one thing may be preferred over another, and thus proved more desirable, although it is not more desired. In this case Mill’s judgment of preference is just a judgment of that intuitional kind which I have been contending to be necessary to establish the hedonistic or any other principle. It is a direct judgment that one thing is more desirable, or better than another; a judgment utterly independent of all considerations as to whether one thing is more desired or pleasanter than another. This is to admit that good is good and indefinable.
It will be shown that Mill’s test for determining one pleasure's superiority in quality over another is based on the preference of most people who have experienced both. A pleasure that is preferred, he argues, is more desirable. However, as we have noted, he believes that 'to think of an object as desirable and to think of it as pleasant are one and the same thing' (p. 58). He therefore claims that the preference of experts simply demonstrates that one pleasure is more pleasant than another. But if that’s the case, how can he differentiate this standard from the standard of the quantity of pleasure? Can one pleasure really be more pleasant than another if not in the sense that it provides more pleasure? 'Pleasant' must, if words are to mean anything at all, indicate some common quality shared by all pleasant things; and if this is true, then one thing can only be more pleasant than another based on having more or less of this single quality. However, let's consider the other possibility and suppose that Mill doesn't genuinely mean that the preference of experts only shows one pleasure to be more pleasant than another. In that case, what does 'preferred' actually mean? It can't mean 'more desired,' since, as we know, according to Mill, the level of desire is always directly proportional to the level of pleasantness. If that's the case, then the foundation of Mill’s Hedonism collapses, because he would be acknowledging that one thing may be preferred over another and thus deemed more desirable, even if it is not more desired. In this situation, Mill’s judgment of preference is simply an intuitive judgment that I argue is necessary to establish the hedonistic or any other principle. It is a direct judgment that one thing is more desirable or better than another, completely independent of whether one thing is more desired or more pleasant than another. This suggests that good is simply good and cannot be defined.
48. And note another point that is brought out by this discussion. Mill’s judgment of preference, so far from establishing the principle that pleasure alone is good, is obviously inconsistent with it. He admits that experts can judge whether one pleasure is more desirable than another, because pleasures differ in quality. But what does this mean? If one pleasure can differ from another in quality, that means, that a pleasure is something complex, something composed, in fact, of pleasure in addition to that which produces pleasure. For instance, Mill speaks of ‘sensual indulgences’ as ‘lower pleasures.’ But what is a sensual indulgence? It is surely a certain excitement of some sense together with the pleasure caused by such excitement. Mill, therefore, in admitting that a sensual indulgence can be directly judged to be lower than another pleasure, in which the degree of pleasure involved may be the same, is admitting that other things may be good, or bad, quite independently of the pleasure which accompanies them. A pleasure is, in fact, merely a misleading term which conceals the fact that what we are dealing with is not pleasure but something else, which may indeed necessarily produce pleasure, but is nevertheless quite distinct from it.
48. Also, consider another point highlighted by this discussion. Mill’s view on preference doesn’t support the idea that pleasure alone is good; in fact, it contradicts it. He acknowledges that experts can assess whether one pleasure is more desirable than another, since pleasures vary in quality. But what does this really mean? If one pleasure can differ from another in quality, then it means that a pleasure is complex, made up of something more than just the pleasure itself. For example, Mill refers to ‘sensual indulgences’ as ‘lower pleasures.’ But what is a sensual indulgence? It clearly involves some level of excitement from a sense along with the pleasure that comes from that excitement. By admitting that a sensual indulgence can be judged to be lower than another pleasure, even if the amount of pleasure might be the same, Mill is acknowledging that other factors can be good or bad, separately from the pleasure they bring. A pleasure is really just a term that obscures the reality that what we’re discussing isn’t pleasure itself, but something else that may produce pleasure but is, in essence, completely different from it.
Mill, therefore, in thinking that to estimate quality of pleasure is quite consistent with his hedonistic principle that pleasure and absence of pain alone are desirable as ends, has again committed the fallacy of confusing ends and means. For take even the most favourable supposition of his meaning; let[p. 80] us suppose that by a pleasure he does not mean, as his words imply, that which produces pleasure and the pleasure produced. Let us suppose him to mean that there are various kinds of pleasure, in the sense in which there are various kinds of colour—blue, red, green, etc. Even in this case, if we are to say that our end is colour alone, then, although it is impossible we should have colour without having some particular colour, yet the particular colour we must have, is only a means to our having colour, if colour is really our end. And if colour is our only possible end, as Mill says pleasure is, then there can be no possible reason for preferring one colour to another, red, for instance, to blue, except that the one is more of a colour than the other. Yet the opposite of this is what Mill is attempting to hold with regard to pleasures.
Mill, therefore, in thinking that assessing the quality of pleasure aligns with his hedonistic principle that pleasure and the absence of pain are the only desirable ends, has once again fallen into the error of confusing ends with means. Even if we take the most favorable interpretation of his meaning; let us assume that by pleasure he does not mean, as his words suggest, what produces pleasure and the pleasure that results. Let’s say he means that there are different kinds of pleasure, similar to how there are different colors—blue, red, green, etc. Even in this scenario, if we say that our end is color alone, then, although we cannot have color without having a specific color, the particular color we must choose is only a means to having color if color is truly our end. And if color is our only possible end, as Mill claims pleasure is, then there’s no valid reason for preferring one color over another, like red over blue, except that one is just more of a color than the other. Yet, this is the opposite of what Mill is trying to argue regarding pleasures.
Accordingly a consideration of Mill’s view that some pleasures are superior to others in quality brings out one point which may ‘help to determine the intellect’ with regard to the intuition ‘Pleasure is the only good.’ For it brings out the fact that if you say ‘pleasure,’ you must mean ‘pleasure’: you must mean some one thing common to all different ‘pleasures,’ some one thing, which may exist in different degrees, but which cannot differ in kind. I have pointed out that, if you say, as Mill does, that quality of pleasure is to be taken into account, then you are no longer holding that pleasure alone is good as an end, since you imply that something else, something which is not present in all pleasures, is also good as an end. The illustration I have given from colour expresses this point in its most acute form. It is plain that if you say ‘Colour alone is good as an end,’ then you can give no possible reason for preferring one colour to another. Your only standard of good and bad will then be ‘colour’; and since red and blue both conform equally to this, the only standard, you can have no other whereby to judge whether red is better than blue. It is true that you cannot have colour unless you also have one or all of the particular colours: they, therefore, if colour is the end, will all be good as means, but none of them can be better than another even as a means, far less can any one of them be regarded as an end in itself. Just so with pleasure: If we do[p. 81] really mean ‘Pleasure alone is good as an end,’ then we must agree with Bentham that ‘Quantity of pleasure being equal, pushpin is as good as poetry.’ To have thus dismissed Mill’s reference to quality of pleasure, is therefore to have made one step in the desired direction. The reader will now no longer be prevented from agreeing with me, by any idea that the hedonistic principle ‘Pleasure alone is good as an end’ is consistent with the view that one pleasure may be of a better quality than another. These two views, we have seen, are contradictory to one another. We must choose between them: and if we choose the latter, then we must give up the principle of Hedonism.
Therefore, considering Mill's belief that some pleasures are better than others in quality highlights one point that may ‘help determine the intellect’ regarding the idea that ‘Pleasure is the only good.’ It reveals that when you say ‘pleasure,’ you have to mean ‘pleasure’: you must refer to something common to all various ‘pleasures,’ something that may exist in different degrees but cannot differ in kind. I have pointed out that if you state, as Mill does, that the quality of pleasure matters, then you are no longer claiming that pleasure alone is good as an end, since you suggest that something else, something not present in all pleasures, is also good as an end. The example I've given using color illustrates this point sharply. It is clear that if you say ‘Color alone is good as an end,’ you can't provide a valid reason for preferring one color over another. Your only standard for good and bad would then be ‘color’; and since red and blue both fit equally into this single standard, you would have no other way to judge whether red is better than blue. While it's true that you can't have color without having one or all of the specific colors, they, therefore, will all be good as means if color is the end, but none can be considered better than another even as a means, let alone one of them being seen as an end in itself. The same applies to pleasure: If we truly mean ‘Pleasure alone is good as an end,’ then we must agree with Bentham that ‘If the quantity of pleasure is equal, pushpin is as good as poetry.’ By dismissing Mill's reference to the quality of pleasure, we have taken a step in the right direction. The reader will no longer be hindered from agreeing with me by any notion that the hedonistic principle ‘Pleasure alone is good as an end’ is compatible with the idea that one pleasure might be of a higher quality than another. As we've seen, these two ideas are contradictory. We must choose between them: and if we choose the latter, then we must abandon the principle of Hedonism.
49. But, as I said, Professor Sidgwick has seen that they are inconsistent. He has seen that he must choose between them. He has chosen. He has rejected the test by quality of pleasure, and has accepted the hedonistic principle. He still maintains that ‘Pleasure alone is good as an end.’ I propose therefore to discuss the considerations which he has offered in order to convince us. I shall hope by that discussion to remove some more of such prejudices and misunderstandings as might prevent agreement with me. If I can shew that some of the considerations which Professor Sidgwick urges are such as we need by no means agree with, and that others are actually rather in my favour than in his, we may have again advanced a few steps nearer to the unanimity which we desire.
49. But, as I mentioned, Professor Sidgwick has recognized that they are contradictory. He understands he must choose between them. He has made his choice. He has dismissed the test based on the quality of pleasure and embraced the hedonistic principle. He still argues that 'Pleasure alone is good as an end.' Therefore, I intend to discuss the reasons he has provided to persuade us. I hope that through this discussion, I can clear up some of the prejudices and misunderstandings that might prevent agreement with my viewpoint. If I can show that some of the reasons Professor Sidgwick presents are ones we don't necessarily need to accept, and that others actually support my position rather than his, we may have taken a few steps closer to the consensus we aim for.
50. The passages in the Methods of Ethics to which I shall now invite attention are to be found in I. IX. 4 and in III. XIV. 4-5.
50. The sections in the Methods of Ethics that I want to focus on are located in I. IX. 4 and in III. XIV. 4-5.
The first of these two passages runs as follows:
The first of these two passages goes like this:
“I think that if we consider carefully such permanent results as are commonly judged to be good, other than qualities of human beings, we can find nothing that, on reflection, appears to possess this quality of goodness out of relation to human existence, or at least to some consciousness or feeling.
“I believe that if we carefully consider the lasting results that are typically seen as good, aside from the qualities of humans, we won’t find anything that, upon reflection, seems to have this quality of goodness independent of human existence, or at least some form of consciousness or feeling.”
“For example, we commonly judge some inanimate objects, scenes, etc. to be good as possessing beauty, and others bad from ugliness: still no one would consider it rational to aim at the production of beauty in external nature, apart from any[p. 82] possible contemplation of it by human beings. In fact when beauty is maintained to be objective, it is not commonly meant that it exists as beauty out of relation to any mind whatsoever: but only that there is some standard of beauty valid for all minds.
For example, we often judge some inanimate objects and scenes as good because they are beautiful, while we see others as bad because they are ugly. However, no one would think it makes sense to aim for beauty in nature if there’s no one around to appreciate it. When beauty is said to be objective, it usually doesn’t mean that it exists as beauty independent of any mind; rather, it means that there’s a standard of beauty that is valid for everyone.[p. 82]
“It may, however, be said that beauty and other results commonly judged to be good, though we do not conceive them to exist out of relation to human beings (or at least minds of some kind), are yet so far separable as ends from the human beings on whom their existence depends, that their realization may conceivably come into competition with the perfection or happiness of these beings. Thus, though beautiful things cannot be thought worth producing except as possible objects of contemplation, still a man may devote himself to their production without any consideration of the persons who are to contemplate them. Similarly knowledge is a good which cannot exist except in minds; and yet one may be more interested in the development of knowledge than in its possession by any particular minds; and may take the former as an ultimate end without regarding the latter.
“It can be said that beauty and other things we typically view as good, even though we don’t think they can exist without humans (or at least some sort of minds), are still separable enough as goals from the humans who depend on their existence. Therefore, the pursuit of beauty might compete with the well-being or happiness of those humans. So, while beautiful things are only worth creating if they can be appreciated, a person might focus on creating them without considering who will appreciate them. Likewise, knowledge is valuable only if it exists in minds; yet, someone might care more about advancing knowledge than about having it in the hands of any specific individuals, treating the advancement as a final goal without considering the latter.”
“Still, as soon as the alternatives are clearly apprehended, it will, I think, be generally held that beauty, knowledge, and other ideal goods, as well as all external material things, are only reasonably to be sought by men in so far as they conduce (1) to Happiness or (2) to the Perfection or Excellence of human existence. I say ‘human,’ for though most utilitarians consider the pleasure (and freedom from pain) of the inferior animals to be included in the Happiness which they take as the right and proper end of conduct, no one seems to contend that we ought to aim at perfecting brutes except as a means to our ends, or at least as objects of scientific or æsthetic contemplation for us. Nor, again, can we include, as a practical end, the existence of beings above the human. We certainly apply the idea of Good to the Divine Existence, just as we do to His work, and indeed in a preeminent manner: and when it is said that, ‘we should do all things to the glory of God,’ it may seem to be implied that the existence of God is made better by our glorifying Him. Still this inference when explicitly drawn appears somewhat impious; and theologians generally recoil from[p. 83] it, and refrain from using the notion of a possible addition to the Goodness of the Divine Existence as a ground of human duty. Nor can the influence of our actions on other extra-human intelligences besides the Divine be at present made matter of scientific discussion.
“However, once the options are clearly understood, I believe it will generally be accepted that beauty, knowledge, and other ideal goods, along with all physical things, should only be pursued by people to the extent that they contribute (1) to Happiness or (2) to the Perfection or Excellence of human life. I say 'human,' because while most utilitarians believe that the pleasure (and absence of pain) of lower animals falls under the Happiness that they consider the rightful aim of behavior, no one seems to argue that we should strive to perfect animals except as a means to our goals, or at least as subjects for our scientific or aesthetic contemplation. Furthermore, we can’t include the existence of higher beings as a practical goal. We definitely apply the concept of Good to the Divine Existence, just as we do to His creations, and even in a more prominent way: and when it is said that 'we should do everything to glorify God,' it may imply that God's existence is improved by our glorifying Him. Still, when this assumption is explicitly stated, it seems somewhat disrespectful; and theologians generally shy away from it and avoid using the idea of a possible enhancement of the Divine Goodness as a basis for human duty. Additionally, the effect of our actions on other non-human intelligences, aside from the Divine, cannot currently be a topic of scientific discussion.”
“I shall therefore confidently lay down, that if there be any Good other than Happiness to be sought by man, as an ultimate practical end, it can only be the Goodness, Perfection, or Excellence of Human Existence. How far this notion includes more than Virtue, what its precise relation to Pleasure is, and to what method we shall be logically led if we accept it as fundamental, are questions which we shall more conveniently discuss after the detailed examination of these two other notions, Pleasure and Virtue, in which we shall be engaged in the two following Books.”
“I will confidently state that if there’s any good other than happiness that humans should strive for as a final practical goal, it can only be the goodness, perfection, or excellence of human existence. How much this idea goes beyond virtue, what its exact relationship to pleasure is, and what approach we’ll logically follow if we accept it as fundamental are questions we’ll discuss more conveniently after examining these two other concepts, pleasure and virtue, which we’ll tackle in the next two books.”
It will be observed that in this passage Prof. Sidgwick tries to limit the range of objects among which the ultimate end may be found. He does not yet say what that end is, but he does exclude from it everything but certain characters of Human Existence. And the possible ends, which he thus excludes, do not again come up for consideration. They are put out of court once for all by this passage and by this passage only. Now is this exclusion justified?
It can be seen that in this passage, Prof. Sidgwick attempts to narrow down the range of objects where the ultimate goal may be found. He doesn't specify what that goal is yet, but he does rule out everything except certain aspects of human existence. The possible goals he excludes aren't revisited later. They are dismissed once and for all by this passage and only by this passage. So, is this exclusion justified?
I cannot think it is. ‘No one,’ says Prof. Sidgwick, ‘would consider it rational to aim at the production of beauty in external nature, apart from any possible contemplation of it by human beings.’ Well, I may say at once, that I, for one, do consider this rational; and let us see if I cannot get any one to agree with me. Consider what this admission really means. It entitles us to put the following case. Let us imagine one world exceedingly beautiful. Imagine it as beautiful as you can; put into it whatever on this earth you most admire—mountains, rivers, the sea; trees, and sunsets, stars and moon. Imagine these all combined in the most exquisite proportions, so that no one thing jars against another, but each contributes to increase the beauty of the whole. And then imagine the ugliest world you can possibly conceive. Imagine it simply one heap of filth, containing everything that is most disgusting[p. 84] to us, for whatever reason, and the whole, as far as may be, without one redeeming feature. Such a pair of worlds we are entitled to compare: they fall within Prof. Sidgwick’s meaning, and the comparison is highly relevant to it. The only thing we are not entitled to imagine is that any human being ever has or ever, by any possibility, can, live in either, can ever see and enjoy the beauty of the one or hate the foulness of the other. Well, even so, supposing them quite apart from any possible contemplation by human beings; still, is it irrational to hold that it is better that the beautiful world should exist, than the one which is ugly? Would it not be well, in any case, to do what we could to produce it rather than the other? Certainly I cannot help thinking that it would; and I hope that some may agree with me in this extreme instance. The instance is extreme. It is highly improbable, not to say, impossible, we should ever have such a choice before us. In any actual choice we should have to consider the possible effects of our action upon conscious beings, and among these possible effects there are always some, I think, which ought to be preferred to the existence of mere beauty. But this only means that in our present state, in which but a very small portion of the good is attainable, the pursuit of beauty for its own sake must always be postponed to the pursuit of some greater good, which is equally attainable. But it is enough for my purpose, if it be admitted that, supposing no greater good were at all attainable, then beauty must in itself be regarded as a greater good than ugliness; if it be admitted that, in that case, we should not be left without any reason for preferring one course of action to another, we should not be left without any duty whatever, but that it would then be our positive duty to make the world more beautiful, so far as we were able, since nothing better than beauty could then result from our efforts. If this be once admitted, if in any imaginable case you do admit that the existence of a more beautiful thing is better in itself than that of one more ugly, quite apart from its effects on any human feeling, then Prof. Sidgwick’s principle has broken down. Then we shall have to include in our ultimate end something beyond the limits of human existence. I admit,[p. 85] of course, that our beautiful world would be better still, if there were human beings in it to contemplate and enjoy its beauty. But that admission makes nothing against my point. If it be once admitted that the beautiful world in itself is better than the ugly, then it follows, that however many beings may enjoy it, and however much better their enjoyment may be than it is itself, yet its mere existence adds something to the goodness of the whole: it is not only a means to our end, but also itself a part thereof.
I can't believe that's true. "No one," says Prof. Sidgwick, "would think it's reasonable to aim for the production of beauty in nature if humans can't appreciate it." Well, I can say right away that I, for one, do think it's reasonable; and let’s see if I can find someone to agree with me. Consider what this claim actually means. It allows us to present the following scenario. Let's imagine one world that's incredibly beautiful. Picture it as beautifully as you can; include everything you admire on this earth—mountains, rivers, the sea; trees, sunsets, stars, and the moon. Imagine all these elements combined in the most exquisite proportions, so that nothing clashes with anything else, but rather each part enhances the overall beauty. Now imagine the ugliest world you can think of. Picture it as just a heap of filth containing all the things that disgust us for any reason, and the whole thing, as far as possible, without a single redeeming quality. These two worlds can be compared: they fit within Prof. Sidgwick’s definition, and the comparison is very relevant. The only thing we can't imagine is that any human being has ever lived in either world, or could ever, in any situation, experience the beauty of one or detest the foulness of the other. Even so, assuming these worlds exist independent of human perception; is it really unreasonable to believe that the beautiful world is preferable to the ugly one? Wouldn't it be worthwhile, in any case, to do what we could to create the beautiful world instead of the ugly one? I certainly think so, and I hope some might agree with me on this extreme example. The example is extreme. It’s very unlikely, if not impossible, that we'd ever face such a choice. In any real decision, we’d have to consider the potential effects of our actions on conscious beings, and among these effects, I believe some should always be favored over simply achieving beauty. But this only means that in our current situation, where only a tiny portion of the good is attainable, the pursuit of beauty for its own sake must be placed after seeking some greater good, which is also attainable. However, for my argument, it suffices to say that, assuming no greater good were attainable, beauty itself should be considered a greater good than ugliness; if this is accepted, we would still have reasons to prefer one course of action over another, and we wouldn't be left without any duty at all. It would then be our responsibility to make the world more beautiful, to the extent we can, since nothing better than beauty could come from our efforts. If this is accepted, if you agree in any conceivable situation that the existence of something more beautiful is better in itself than something uglier, regardless of its impact on human feelings, then Prof. Sidgwick’s principle has failed. We would have to incorporate something beyond human existence into our ultimate goal. I acknowledge, of course, that our beautiful world would be even better if there were humans in it to appreciate and enjoy its beauty. However, that acknowledgment doesn't contradict my argument. If we accept that a beautiful world is inherently better than an ugly one, then it follows that no matter how many beings enjoy it, and however much more fulfilling their enjoyment may be, its mere existence contributes something to the overall goodness: it’s not just a means to our end, but also a part of it.
51. In the second passage to which I referred above, Prof. Sidgwick returns from the discussion of Virtue and Pleasure, with which he has meanwhile been engaged, to consider what among the parts of Human Existence to which, as we saw, he has limited the ultimate end, can really be considered as such end. What I have just said, of course, appears to me to destroy the force of this part of his argument too. If, as I think, other things than any part of Human Existence can be ends-in-themselves, then Prof. Sidgwick cannot claim to have discovered the Summum Bonum, when he has merely determined what parts of Human Existence are in themselves desirable. But this error may be admitted to be utterly insignificant in comparison with that which we are now about to discuss.
51. In the second passage I mentioned earlier, Prof. Sidgwick shifts from his discussion of Virtue and Pleasure to examine which aspects of Human Existence he has identified as the ultimate goal. What I’ve just pointed out seems to undermine this part of his argument as well. If, as I believe, there are things beyond any aspect of Human Existence that can be ends in themselves, then Prof. Sidgwick cannot claim to have found the Summum Bonum when he has just established what parts of Human Existence are desirable in and of themselves. However, this mistake is relatively minor compared to what we are about to discuss.
“It may be said,” says Prof. Sidgwick (III. XIV. §§ 4-5), “that we may ... regard cognition of Truth, contemplation of Beauty, Free or Virtuous action, as in some measure preferable alternatives to Pleasure or Happiness—even though we admit that Happiness must be included as a part of Ultimate Good.... I think, however, that this view ought not to commend itself to the sober judgment of reflective persons. In order to shew this, I must ask the reader to use the same twofold procedure that I before requested him to employ in considering the absolute and independent validity of common moral precepts. I appeal firstly to his intuitive judgment after due consideration of the question when fairly placed before it: and secondly to a comprehensive comparison of the ordinary judgments of mankind. As regards the first argument, to me at least it seems clear after reflection that these objective relations of the conscious[p. 86] subject, when distinguished from the consciousness accompanying and resulting from them, are not ultimately and intrinsically desirable; any more than material or other objects are, when considered apart from any relation to conscious existence. Admitting that we have actual experience of such preferences as have just been described, of which the ultimate object is something that is not merely consciousness: it still seems to me that when (to use Butler’s phrase) we ‘sit down in a cool hour,’ we can only justify to ourselves the importance that we attach to any of these objects by considering its conduciveness, in one way or another, to the happiness of sentient beings.
“It may be said,” says Prof. Sidgwick (III. XIV. §§ 4-5), “that we can ... see the pursuit of Truth, the appreciation of Beauty, and Free or Virtuous actions as somewhat better options than Pleasure or Happiness—even if we acknowledge that Happiness should be part of the Ultimate Good.... However, I believe this view should not appeal to the careful judgment of thoughtful individuals. To demonstrate this, I need to ask the reader to use the same two-step approach that I previously suggested for evaluating the absolute and independent validity of common moral principles. First, I appeal to their intuitive judgment after reflecting on the question when it's fairly presented: and second, to a broad comparison of the typical views of humanity. Regarding the first argument, it seems clear to me, after reflection, that these objective relationships of the conscious subject, when separated from the consciousness that accompanies and arises from them, are not ultimately or intrinsically desirable; no more than physical or other objects are when considered apart from any connection to conscious existence. While we do have actual experiences of such preferences that lead to something beyond mere consciousness, it still seems to me that when (to borrow Butler’s phrase) we ‘take a moment to reflect,’ we can only justify the significance we give any of these objects by considering how they contribute, in one way or another, to the happiness of sentient beings.”
“The second argument, that refers to the common sense of mankind, obviously cannot be made completely cogent; since, as above stated, several cultivated persons do habitually judge that knowledge, art, etc.,—not to speak of Virtue—are ends independently of the pleasure derived from them. But we may urge not only that all these elements of ‘ideal good’ are productive of pleasure in various ways; but also that they seem to obtain the commendation of Common Sense, roughly speaking, in proportion to the degree of this productiveness. This seems obviously true of Beauty; and will hardly be denied in respect of any kind of social ideal: it is paradoxical to maintain that any degree of Freedom, or any form of social order, would still be commonly regarded as desirable even if we were certain that it had no tendency to promote the general happiness. The case of Knowledge is rather more complex; but certainly Common Sense is most impressed with the value of knowledge, when its ‘fruitfulness’ has been demonstrated. It is, however, aware that experience has frequently shewn how knowledge, long fruitless, may become unexpectedly fruitful, and how light may be shed on one part of the field of knowledge from another apparently remote: and even if any particular branch of scientific pursuit could be shewn to be devoid of even this indirect utility, it would still deserve some respect on utilitarian grounds; both as furnishing to the inquirer the refined and innocent pleasures of curiosity, and because the intellectual disposition which it exhibits and sustains is likely on the whole to produce fruitful knowledge. Still in cases approximating to this last, Common[p. 87] Sense is somewhat disposed to complain of the mis-direction of valuable effort; so that the meed of honour commonly paid to Science seems to be graduated, though perhaps unconsciously, by a tolerably exact utilitarian scale. Certainly the moment the legitimacy of any branch of scientific inquiry is seriously disputed, as in the recent case of vivisection, the controversy on both sides is generally conducted on an avowedly utilitarian basis.
The second argument, which refers to common sense, clearly can’t be fully convincing; as mentioned earlier, some educated people often believe that knowledge, art, and even Virtue are valuable in themselves, apart from any pleasure they might bring. However, we can argue that all these aspects of the 'ideal good' actually create pleasure in different ways; and they seem to earn the approval of Common Sense roughly in relation to how much pleasure they produce. This is clearly true for Beauty and is hard to deny for any social ideal: it's contradictory to claim that any amount of Freedom or any form of social order would still be viewed as desirable if we were certain it wouldn’t promote overall happiness. The situation with Knowledge is a bit more complicated; still, Common Sense values knowledge most when it's proven to be productive. Nevertheless, it recognizes that experience has often shown how knowledge, even if initially unproductive, can become unexpectedly useful, and how insights from one area of knowledge can shed light on another area that seems unrelated. Even if a specific field of scientific study is shown to lack direct usefulness, it would still deserve some respect from a utilitarian perspective; it provides the inquirer with the pure, innocent pleasures of curiosity and is likely to foster productive knowledge overall. However, in cases that come close to this last point, Common Sense tends to grumble about the misallocation of valuable effort; so the respect given to Science appears to be, albeit perhaps unconsciously, measured against a fairly precise utilitarian scale. Certainly, the moment the legitimacy of any scientific inquiry is seriously questioned, as seen recently with vivisection, the debate on both sides tends to be framed on an explicitly utilitarian basis.
“The case of Virtue requires special consideration: since the encouragement in each other of virtuous impulses and dispositions is a main aim of men’s ordinary moral discourse; so that even to raise the question whether this encouragement can go too far has a paradoxical air. Still, our experience includes rare and exceptional cases in which the concentration of effort on the cultivation of virtue has seemed to have effects adverse to general happiness, through being intensified to the point of moral fanaticism, and so involving a neglect of other conditions of happiness. If, then, we admit as actual or possible such ‘infelicific’ effects of the cultivation of Virtue, I think we shall also generally admit that, in the case supposed, conduciveness to general happiness should be the criterion for deciding how far the cultivation of Virtue should be carried.”
“The topic of Virtue needs special attention: since encouraging each other’s virtuous actions and traits is a main goal of our everyday moral discussions, it seems contradictory to even question if this encouragement can go too far. However, our experiences do include rare and exceptional situations where focusing intensely on cultivating virtue has negatively impacted overall happiness, becoming so extreme that it leads to moral fanaticism and overlooks other important aspects of happiness. Therefore, if we accept that there can be such 'unhappiness-inducing' effects from promoting Virtue, I believe we should generally agree that when this occurs, the ability to contribute to overall happiness should be the standard for determining how far we should promote the cultivation of Virtue.”
There we have Prof. Sidgwick’s argument completed. We ought not, he thinks, to aim at knowing the Truth, or at contemplating Beauty, except in so far as such knowledge or such contemplation contributes to increase the pleasure or to diminish the pain of sentient beings. Pleasure alone is good for its own sake: knowledge of the Truth is good only as a means to pleasure.
There we have Prof. Sidgwick’s argument wrapped up. He believes we shouldn’t aim to know the Truth or appreciate Beauty unless that knowledge or appreciation helps to increase pleasure or reduce the pain of sentient beings. Pleasure is valuable in itself; knowledge of the Truth is only valuable as a way to achieve pleasure.
52. Let us consider what this means. What is pleasure? It is certainly something of which we may be conscious, and which, therefore, may be distinguished from our consciousness of it. What I wish first to ask is this: Can it really be said that we value pleasure, except in so far as we are conscious of it? Should we think that the attainment of pleasure, of which we never were and never could be conscious, was something to be aimed at for its own sake? It may be impossible that such pleasure should ever exist, that it should ever be thus[p. 88] divorced from consciousness; although there is certainly much reason to believe that it is not only possible but very common. But, even supposing that it were impossible, that is quite irrelevant. Our question is: Is it the pleasure, as distinct from the consciousness of it, that we set value on? Do we think the pleasure valuable in itself, or must we insist that, if we are to think the pleasure good, we must have consciousness of it too?
52. Let’s think about what this means. What is pleasure? It’s definitely something we can be aware of, and which can be separated from our awareness of it. What I want to ask first is this: Can we really say that we value pleasure, except to the extent that we are aware of it? Should we believe that pursuing pleasure, which we were never aware of and never could be, is something worth aiming for just for the sake of it? It might be impossible for such pleasure to exist, entirely separate from awareness; although there’s certainly a good reason to think that it’s not only possible but very common. But even if it were impossible, that doesn’t really matter. Our question is: Do we value pleasure itself, separate from the awareness of it? Do we see pleasure as valuable on its own, or do we have to insist that if we’re to appreciate pleasure, we also need to be aware of it?
This consideration is very well put by Socrates in Plato’s dialogue Philebus (21 A).
This idea is expressed very clearly by Socrates in Plato's dialogue Philebus (21 A).
‘Would you accept, Protarchus,’ says Socrates, ‘to live your whole life in the enjoyment of the greatest pleasures?’ ‘Of course I would,’ says Protarchus.
‘Would you be okay with living your entire life indulging in the greatest pleasures?’ says Socrates. ‘Of course I would,’ replies Protarchus.
Socrates. Then would you think you needed anything else besides, if you possessed this one blessing in completeness?
Socrates. So, do you think you would need anything else if you had this one blessing fully?
Protarchus. Certainly not.
Protarchus. Definitely not.
Socrates. Consider what you are saying. You would not need to be wise and intelligent and reasonable, nor anything like this? Would you not even care to keep your sight?
Socrates. Think about what you're saying. You wouldn’t need to be smart, intelligent, or rational, or anything like that? Would you not even want to maintain your vision?
Protarchus. Why should I? I suppose I should have all I want, if I was pleased.
Protarchus. Why should I? I guess I’d have everything I need if I was happy.
Socrates. Well, then, supposing you lived so, you would enjoy always throughout your life the greatest pleasure?
Socrates. Well, if you lived like that, would you always experience the greatest pleasure throughout your life?
Protarchus. Of course.
Protarchus. Sure thing.
Socrates. But, on the other hand, inasmuch as you would not possess intelligence and memory and knowledge and true opinion, you would, in the first place, necessarily be without the knowledge whether you were pleased or not. For you would be devoid of any kind of wisdom. You admit this?
Socrates. But, on the flip side, since you would not have intelligence, memory, knowledge, or a true opinion, you would, first of all, definitely lack the awareness of whether you were pleased or not. You would be without any form of wisdom. Do you agree with this?
Protarchus. I do. The consequence is absolutely necessary.
Protarchus. I do. The outcome is completely necessary.
Socrates. Well, then, besides this, not having memory, you must also be unable to remember even that you ever were pleased; of the pleasure which falls upon you at the moment not the least vestige must afterwards remain. And again, not having true opinion, you cannot think that you are pleased when you are; and, being bereft of your reasoning faculties, you cannot even have the power to reckon that you will be pleased in future. You must live the life of an oyster, or of some other of those living creatures, whose home is the seas[p. 89] and whose souls are concealed in shelly bodies. Is all this so, or can we think otherwise than this?
Socrates. So, apart from that, if you lack memory, you won't even be able to remember that you were ever happy; the pleasure you experience in the moment won't leave any trace afterward. And again, without true belief, you can't even feel that you are happy while you are; without your reasoning skills, you can't even anticipate that you will be happy in the future. You must live like an oyster, or some other sea creature, whose home is in the ocean and whose essence is hidden in its shell. Is all this true, or can we think differently?
Protarchus. How can we?
Protarchus. How can we do that?
Socrates. Well, then, can we think such a life desirable?
Socrates. So, can we really consider such a life worth wanting?
Protarchus. Socrates, your reasoning has left me utterly dumb.’
Protarchus. Socrates, your argument has completely stunned me.
Socrates, we see, persuades Protarchus that Hedonism is absurd. If we are really going to maintain that pleasure alone is good as an end, we must maintain that it is good, whether we are conscious of it or not. We must declare it reasonable to take as our ideal (an unattainable ideal it may be) that we should be as happy as possible, even on condition that we never know and never can know that we are happy. We must be willing to sell in exchange for the mere happiness every vestige of knowledge, both in ourselves and in others, both of happiness itself and of every other thing. Can we really still disagree? Can any one still declare it obvious that this is reasonable? That pleasure alone is good as an end?
Socrates convinces Protarchus that Hedonism is ridiculous. If we truly believe that pleasure is the only good goal, we have to say it’s good, whether we realize it or not. We should accept that our ideal (even if it’s impossible to reach) should be to be as happy as possible, even if we never know and can never know that we are happy. We must be ready to trade away every bit of knowledge, both about ourselves and others, about happiness itself and about everything else, just for the sake of mere happiness. Can we still disagree? Is there anyone who can honestly say that this makes sense? That pleasure alone is the ultimate good?
The case, it is plain, is just like that of the colours[18], only, as yet, not nearly so strong. It is far more possible that we should some day be able to produce the intensest pleasure, without any consciousness that it is there, than that we should be able to produce mere colour, without its being any particular colour. Pleasure and consciousness can be far more easily distinguished from one another, than colour from the particular colours. And yet even if this were not so, we should be bound to distinguish them if we really wished to declare pleasure alone to be our ultimate end. Even if consciousness were an inseparable accompaniment of pleasure, a sine quâ non of its existence, yet, if pleasure is the only end, we are bound to call consciousness a mere means to it, in any intelligible sense that can be given to the word means. And if, on the other hand, as I hope is now plain, the pleasure would be comparatively valueless without the consciousness, then we are bound to say that pleasure is not the only end, that some consciousness at least must be included with it as a veritable part of the end.
The situation is clearly similar to that of colors[18], but it's not nearly as strong yet. It's much more likely that one day we could create the most intense pleasure without even being aware of it, than that we could create a color without it being a specific color. Pleasure and consciousness can be distinguished from each other much more easily than we can distinguish a color from specific colors. Even if that weren't the case, we would still need to make the distinction if we genuinely want to claim that pleasure alone is our ultimate goal. Even if consciousness is an essential part of pleasure, if pleasure is the only goal, we must recognize consciousness as just a means to that end in any sensible way of understanding the word means. On the other hand, as I believe is now clear, if pleasure is worth significantly less without consciousness, then we must conclude that pleasure is not the only goal and that at least some consciousness must be included as a genuine part of the goal.
[p. 90]
[p. 90]
For our question now is solely what the end is: it is quite another question how far that end may be attainable by itself, or must involve the simultaneous attainment of other things. It may well be that the practical conclusions at which Utilitarians do arrive, and even those at which they ought logically to arrive, are not far from the truth. But in so far as their reason for holding these conclusions to be true is that ‘Pleasure alone is good as an end,’ they are absolutely wrong: and it is with reasons that we are chiefly concerned in any scientific Ethics.
For our question now is simply what the goal is: it’s a different question how achievable that goal might be on its own, or if it must include the simultaneous achievement of other things. It could be that the practical conclusions that Utilitarians reach, and even those they should logically reach, are not far from the truth. However, as far as their reason for believing these conclusions to be true is that 'Pleasure alone is good as a goal,' they are completely mistaken: and it is reasons that we are mainly concerned with in any scientific Ethics.
53. It seems, then, clear that Hedonism is in error, so far as it maintains that pleasure alone, and not the consciousness of pleasure, is the sole good. And this error seems largely due to the fallacy which I pointed out above in Mill—the fallacy of confusing means and end. It is falsely supposed that, since pleasure must always be accompanied by consciousness (which is, itself, extremely doubtful), therefore it is indifferent whether we say that pleasure or the consciousness of pleasure is the sole good. Practically, of course, it would be indifferent at which we aimed, if it were certain that we could not get the one without the other; but where the question is of what is good in itself—where we ask: For the sake of what is it desirable to get that which we aim at?—the distinction is by no means unimportant. Here we are placed before an exclusive alternative. Either pleasure by itself (even though we can’t get it) would be all that is desirable, or a consciousness of it would be more desirable still. Both these propositions cannot be true; and I think it is plain that the latter is true; whence it follows that pleasure is not the sole good.
53. So, it’s clear that Hedonism is mistaken in claiming that pleasure alone, and not the awareness of pleasure, is the only good. This mistake seems to stem largely from the fallacy I mentioned earlier regarding Mill—the confusion between means and ends. It’s incorrectly assumed that since pleasure must always come with awareness (which itself is highly questionable), it doesn’t matter whether we call pleasure or the awareness of pleasure the sole good. In practice, it might seem indifferent which one we pursue if it were certain that we could not have one without the other; but when discussing what is good in itself—when we ask: What makes it worthwhile to seek what we aim for?—the distinction is quite significant. Here we face an exclusive choice. Either pleasure alone (even if we can't attain it) is all that is desirable, or being aware of it is even more desirable. Both of these statements cannot be true; and I believe it’s clear that the latter is true; thus, it follows that pleasure is not the only good.
Still it may be said that, even if consciousness of pleasure, and not pleasure alone, is the sole good, this conclusion is not very damaging to Hedonism. It may be said that Hedonists have always meant by pleasure the consciousness of pleasure, though they have not been at pains to say so; and this, I think is, in the main, true. To correct their formula in this respect could, therefore, only be a matter of practical importance, if it is possible to produce pleasure without producing consciousness of it. But even this importance, which I think our conclusion so far really has, is, I admit, comparatively slight.[p. 91] What I wish to maintain is that even consciousness of pleasure is not the sole good: that, indeed, it is absurd so to regard it. And the chief importance of what has been said so far lies in the fact that the same method, which shews that consciousness of pleasure is more valuable than pleasure, seems also to shew that consciousness of pleasure is itself far less valuable than other things. The supposition that consciousness of pleasure is the sole good is due to a neglect of the same distinctions which have encouraged the careless assertion that pleasure is the sole good.
It can still be argued that even if being aware of pleasure, rather than pleasure itself, is the only true good, this conclusion isn't really a big blow to Hedonism. It's fair to say that Hedonists have always considered pleasure to mean the awareness of pleasure, even if they haven't explicitly stated it; and I think this is mostly true. To adjust their definition in this way would only matter practically if it's possible to have pleasure without being aware of it. However, I admit that even this significance is relatively minor. What I want to emphasize is that even the awareness of pleasure isn't the only good, and in fact, it's ridiculous to think of it that way. The main takeaway from what we’ve discussed so far is that the same reasoning that demonstrates the awareness of pleasure is more valuable than pleasure itself also suggests that the awareness of pleasure is actually far less valuable than other things. The idea that awareness of pleasure is the only good stems from overlooking the same distinctions that have led to the careless claim that pleasure is the only good.[p. 91]
The method which I employed in order to shew that pleasure itself was not the sole good, was that of considering what value we should attach to it, if it existed in absolute isolation, stripped of all its usual accompaniments. And this is, in fact, the only method that can be safely used, when we wish to discover what degree of value a thing has in itself. The necessity of employing this method will be best exhibited by a discussion of the arguments used by Prof. Sidgwick in the passage last quoted, and by an exposure of the manner in which they are calculated to mislead.
The way I approached showing that pleasure alone isn’t the only good was by thinking about what value we would give it if it existed completely on its own, without any of its usual companions. This is really the only reliable method we can use when we want to find out what value something has in itself. The need to use this method will be best demonstrated by discussing the arguments made by Prof. Sidgwick in the previous quote and by revealing how they can be misleading.
54. With regard to the second of them, it only maintains that other things, which might be supposed to share with pleasure the attribute of goodness, ‘seem to obtain the commendation of Common Sense, roughly speaking, in proportion to the degree’ of their productiveness of pleasure. Whether even this rough proportion holds between the commendation of Common Sense and the felicific effects of that which it commends is a question extremely difficult to determine; and we need not enter into it here. For, even assuming it to be true, and assuming the judgments of Common Sense to be on the whole correct, what would it shew? It would shew, certainly, that pleasure was a good criterion of right action—that the same conduct which produced most pleasure would also produce most good on the whole. But this would by no means entitle us to the conclusion that the greatest pleasure constituted what was best on the whole: it would still leave open the alternative that the greatest quantity of pleasure was as a matter of fact, under actual conditions, generally accompanied by the greatest[p. 92] quantity of other goods, and that it therefore was not the sole good. It might indeed seem to be a strange coincidence that these two things should always, even in this world, be in proportion to one another. But the strangeness of this coincidence will certainly not entitle us to argue directly that it does not exist—that it is an illusion, due to the fact that pleasure is really the sole good. The coincidence may be susceptible of other explanations; and it would even be our duty to accept it unexplained, if direct intuition seemed to declare that pleasure was not the sole good. Moreover it must be remembered that the need for assuming such a coincidence rests in any case upon the extremely doubtful proposition that felicific effects are roughly in proportion to the approval of Common Sense. And it should be observed that, though Prof. Sidgwick maintains this to be the case, his detailed illustrations only tend to shew the very different proposition that a thing is not held to be good, unless it gives a balance of pleasure; not that the degree of commendation is in proportion to the quantity of pleasure.
54. Regarding the second point, it simply argues that other things, which might be thought to share the quality of goodness with pleasure, ‘seem to receive the approval of Common Sense, generally speaking, in proportion to how much pleasure they produce.’ Whether this rough proportion actually exists between the approval of Common Sense and the happiness that it endorses is a very challenging question to answer; we don’t need to delve into it here. Even if we assume this is true and that the judgments of Common Sense are largely correct, what would that show? It would indicate that pleasure is a good indicator of right action—that the same behavior that generates the most pleasure would also bring about the most good overall. However, this wouldn’t justify the conclusion that the greatest pleasure defined what was best overall; it would still leave open the possibility that the highest quantity of pleasure was, under actual conditions, typically linked with the greatest[p. 92] amount of other goods, thus it was not the only good. It might indeed seem odd that these two aspects should always, even in this world, align with each other. But the peculiarity of this alignment certainly wouldn’t allow us to argue directly that it does not exist—that it’s an illusion because pleasure is really the only good. This alignment might have other explanations; and we would even be obliged to accept it as unexplained if our direct intuition suggested that pleasure was not the only good. Furthermore, it should be noted that the need to assume such an alignment relies on the extremely questionable claim that happiness effects are roughly proportionate to the approval of Common Sense. Additionally, although Prof. Sidgwick argues that this is the case, his detailed examples tend to illustrate a very different idea: that something is not considered good unless it yields a balance of pleasure; not that the degree of approval corresponds to the amount of pleasure.
55. The decision, then, must rest upon Prof. Sidgwick’s first argument—‘the appeal’ to our ‘intuitive judgment after due consideration of the question when fairly placed before it.’ And here it seems to me plain that Prof. Sidgwick has failed, in two essential respects, to place the question fairly before either himself or his reader.
55. The decision, then, must depend on Prof. Sidgwick’s first argument—‘the appeal’ to our ‘intuitive judgment after careful consideration of the question when presented correctly.’ And it seems to me clear that Prof. Sidgwick has not succeeded, in two key ways, in presenting the question fairly to either himself or his reader.
(1) What he has to shew is, as he says himself, not merely that ‘Happiness must be included as a part of Ultimate Good.’ This view, he says, ‘ought not to commend itself to the sober judgment of reflective persons.’ And why? Because ‘these objective relations, when distinguished from the consciousness accompanying and resulting from them, are not ultimately and intrinsically desirable.’ Now, this reason, which is offered as shewing that to consider Happiness as a mere part of Ultimate Good does not meet the facts of intuition, is, on the contrary, only sufficient to shew that it is a part of Ultimate Good. For from the fact that no value resides in one part of a whole, considered by itself, we cannot infer that all the value belonging to the whole does reside in the other part, considered by itself. Even if we admit that there is much value in the enjoyment of[p. 93] Beauty, and none in the mere contemplation of it, which is one of the constituents of that complex fact, it does not follow that all the value belongs to the other constituent, namely, the pleasure which we take in contemplating it. It is quite possible that this constituent also has no value in itself; that the value belongs to the whole state, and to that only: so that both the pleasure and the contemplation are mere parts of the good, and both of them equally necessary parts. In short, Prof. Sidgwick’s argument here depends upon the neglect of that principle, which I tried to explain in my first chapter and which I said I should call the principle of ‘organic relations[19].’ The argument is calculated to mislead, because it supposes that, if we see a whole state to be valuable, and also see that one element of that state has no value by itself, then the other element, by itself, must have all the value which belongs to the whole state. The fact is, on the contrary, that, since the whole may be organic, the other element need have no value whatever, and that even if it have some, the value of the whole may be very much greater. For this reason, as well as to avoid confusion between means and end, it is absolutely essential to consider each distinguishable quality, in isolation, in order to decide what value it possesses. Prof. Sidgwick, on the other hand, applies this method of isolation only to one element in the wholes he is considering. He does not ask the question: If consciousness of pleasure existed absolutely by itself, would a sober judgment be able to attribute much value to it? It is, in fact, always misleading to take a whole, that is valuable (or the reverse), and then to ask simply: To which of its constituents does this whole owe its value or its vileness? It may well be that it owes it to none; and, if one of them does appear to have some value in itself, we shall be led into the grave error of supposing that all the value of the whole belongs to it alone. It seems to me that this error has commonly been committed with regard to pleasure. Pleasure does seem to be a necessary constituent of most valuable wholes; and, since the other constituents, into which we may analyse them, may easily seem not to have any value, it is natural to suppose that all the value belongs to pleasure. That[p. 94] this natural supposition does not follow from the premises is certain; and that it is, on the contrary, ridiculously far from the truth appears evident to my ‘reflective judgment.’ If we apply either to pleasure or to consciousness of pleasure the only safe method, that of isolation, and ask ourselves: Could we accept, as a very good thing, that mere consciousness of pleasure, and absolutely nothing else, should exist, even in the greatest quantities? I think we can have no doubt about answering: No. Far less can we accept this as the sole good. Even if we accept Prof. Sidgwick’s implication (which yet appears to me extremely doubtful) that consciousness of pleasure has a greater value by itself than Contemplation of Beauty, it seems to me that a pleasurable Contemplation of Beauty has certainly an immeasurably greater value than mere Consciousness of Pleasure. In favour of this conclusion I can appeal with confidence to the ‘sober judgment of reflective persons.’
(1) What he needs to show is, as he puts it, not just that ‘Happiness must be included as a part of Ultimate Good.’ He claims that this view ‘should not appeal to the sound judgment of thoughtful individuals.’ And why? Because ‘these objective relations, when separated from the awareness that accompanies and results from them, are not ultimately and intrinsically desirable.’ Now, this reasoning, which is presented to demonstrate that viewing Happiness as just a part of Ultimate Good doesn’t align with intuitive facts, actually only proves that it is a part of Ultimate Good. The fact that no value is found in one part of a whole when considered on its own doesn’t mean that the entire value of the whole resides in the other part when looked at in isolation. Even if we accept that there is significant value in enjoying[p. 93] Beauty, and none in simply contemplating it, which is one part of that complex situation, it doesn’t follow that all value belongs to the other part, namely, the pleasure we derive from contemplating it. It’s entirely possible that this part also has no value in itself; that the value belongs to the entire experience, and to that only: so both the pleasure and the contemplation are merely components of the good, and both are equally necessary parts. In short, Prof. Sidgwick’s argument here ignores a principle that I tried to explain in my first chapter, which I referred to as the principle of ‘organic relations[19].’ The argument is misleading because it assumes that if we recognize a whole situation as valuable, and also see that one component of that situation has no value by itself, then the other component by itself must contain all the value of the whole situation. The reality is, on the contrary, that since the whole may be organic, the other component might not have any value at all, and even if it does, the overall value of the whole could be significantly greater. For this reason, as well as to prevent confusion between means and ends, it’s crucial to evaluate each distinct quality in isolation to determine its value. Conversely, Prof. Sidgwick applies this isolation method to only one component in the wholes he analyzes. He doesn’t ask the question: If the awareness of pleasure existed entirely by itself, would a sound judgment attribute much value to it? It is misleading to take a whole that has value (or doesn’t) and simply ask: Which of its components does this whole owe its value or lack thereof? It’s possible that it owes it to none; and if one of them seems to have some value on its own, we might fall into the serious mistake of thinking that all the value of the whole belongs to it alone. It seems to me that this mistake is often made concerning pleasure. Pleasure appears to be a necessary part of most valuable wholes; and since the other components, into which we might break them down, may easily seem to lack value, it's natural to assume that all value belongs to pleasure. That[p. 94] this assumption doesn’t follow from the premises is certain; and that it is, in fact, ridiculously far from the truth is evident to my ‘reflective judgment.’ If we apply the only reliable method, which is isolation, to either pleasure or the awareness of pleasure, and ask ourselves: Could we consider just that mere awareness of pleasure, and absolutely nothing else, to be a really good thing, even in the largest amounts? I think there’s no doubt in answering: No. Far less can we accept this as the only good. Even if we accept Prof. Sidgwick’s suggestion (which seems highly questionable to me) that the awareness of pleasure holds greater value on its own than the Contemplation of Beauty, it seems clear to me that a pleasurable Contemplation of Beauty certainly has immeasurably greater value than mere Consciousness of Pleasure. I can confidently refer to the ‘sober judgment of reflective individuals’ in support of this conclusion.
56. (2) That the value of a pleasurable whole does not belong solely to the pleasure which it contains, may, I think, be made still plainer by consideration of another point in which Prof. Sidgwick’s argument is defective. Prof. Sidgwick maintains, as we saw, the doubtful proposition, that the conduciveness to pleasure of a thing is in rough proportion to its commendation by Common Sense. But he does not maintain, what would be undoubtedly false, that the pleasantness of every state is in proportion to the commendation of that state. In other words, it is only when you take into account the whole consequences of any state, that he is able to maintain the coincidence of quantity of pleasure with the objects approved by Common Sense. If we consider each state by itself, and ask what is the judgment of Common Sense as to its goodness as an end, quite apart from its goodness as a means, there can be no doubt that Common Sense holds many much less pleasant states to be better than many far more pleasant: that it holds, with Mill, that there are higher pleasures, which are more valuable, though less pleasant, than those which are lower. Prof. Sidgwick might, of course, maintain that in this Common Sense is merely confusing means and ends: that what it holds to be better as an end, is in reality only better as a means. But I think his argument is[p. 95] defective in that he does not seem to see sufficiently plainly that, as far as intuitions of goodness as an end are concerned, he is running grossly counter to Common Sense; that he does not emphasise sufficiently the distinction between immediate pleasantness and conduciveness to pleasure. In order to place fairly before us the question what is good as an end we must take states that are immediately pleasant and ask if the more pleasant are always also the better; and whether, if some that are less pleasant appear to be so, it is only because we think they are likely to increase the number of the more pleasant. That Common Sense would deny both these suppositions, and rightly so, appears to me indubitable. It is commonly held that certain of what would be called the lowest forms of sexual enjoyment, for instance, are positively bad, although it is by no means clear that they are not the most pleasant states we ever experience. Common Sense would certainly not think it a sufficient justification for the pursuit of what Prof. Sidgwick calls the ‘refined pleasures’ here and now, that they are the best means to the future attainment of a heaven, in which there would be no more refined pleasures—no contemplation of beauty, no personal affections—but in which the greatest possible pleasure would be obtained by a perpetual indulgence in bestiality. Yet Prof. Sidgwick would be bound to hold that, if the greatest possible pleasure could be obtained in this way, and if it were attainable, such a state of things would be a heaven indeed, and that all human endeavours should be devoted to its realisation. I venture to think that this view is as false as it is paradoxical.
56. (2) I believe it can be made clearer that the value of a pleasurable whole doesn't come solely from the pleasure it contains by examining another flaw in Prof. Sidgwick’s argument. As we noted, Prof. Sidgwick supports the uncertain idea that the conduciveness to pleasure of something roughly correlates with how it's viewed by Common Sense. However, he doesn't claim—though that would clearly be incorrect—that the pleasantness of every state corresponds to how that state is judged. In other words, only when you consider all the consequences of any state can he argue that the amount of pleasure aligns with what Common Sense approves. If we look at each state individually and ask what Common Sense thinks of its goodness as an end, separate from its goodness as a means, it's clear that Common Sense considers many states that are less pleasant to be better than many that are much more pleasant. It agrees with Mill that there are higher pleasures, which, while less pleasant, are more valuable than lower ones. Of course, Prof. Sidgwick might argue that Common Sense is merely confusing means and ends; that what it sees as better as an end is actually just better as a means. But I think his argument is[p. 95] flawed because he doesn't seem to recognize clearly that, in terms of intuitions of goodness as an end, he strongly opposes Common Sense. He doesn't adequately highlight the difference between immediate pleasantness and conduciveness to pleasure. To fairly address what is good as an end, we need to look at states that are immediately pleasant and ask if the more pleasant ones are always better; also, whether some that are less pleasant seem better only because they might increase the number of the more pleasant ones. Common Sense would likely reject both of these assumptions, and rightly so. It's widely believed that certain of the lowest forms of sexual enjoyment are actually bad, even though they might be some of the most pleasant experiences we have. Common Sense would definitely not see it as a sufficient reason to pursue what Prof. Sidgwick calls ‘refined pleasures’ now if they are the best route to a future heaven where there would be no more refined pleasures—no appreciation of beauty, no personal connections—but where one would get maximum pleasure through constant indulgence in base acts. Yet Prof. Sidgwick would have to argue that if the greatest pleasure could be achieved this way, and if it were possible, then that situation would indeed be heaven, and all human efforts should aim for that. I believe this perspective is as misguided as it is paradoxical.
57. It seems to me, then, that if we place fairly before us the question: Is consciousness of pleasure the sole good? the answer must be: No. And with this the last defence of Hedonism has been broken down. In order to put the question fairly we must isolate consciousness of pleasure. We must ask: Suppose we were conscious of pleasure only, and of nothing else, not even that we were conscious, would that state of things, however great the quantity, be very desirable? No one, I think, can suppose it so. On the other hand, it seems quite plain, that we do regard as very desirable, many complicated states[p. 96] of mind in which the consciousness of pleasure is combined with consciousness of other things—states which we call ‘enjoyment of’ so and so. If this is correct, then it follows that consciousness of pleasure is not the sole good, and that many other states, in which it is included as a part, are much better than it. Once we recognise the principle of organic unities, any objection to this conclusion, founded on the supposed fact that the other elements of such states have no value in themselves, must disappear. And I do not know that I need say any more in refutation of Hedonism.
57. It seems to me that if we consider the question: Is the awareness of pleasure the only good? the answer must be: No. With this, the final defense of Hedonism has been dismantled. To fairly pose the question, we need to isolate the awareness of pleasure. We should ask: What if we were aware of pleasure only, and nothing else, not even the fact that we were aware? Would that situation, no matter how much pleasure there was, be very desirable? I don't think anyone could believe it would be. On the flip side, it’s pretty clear that we find many complex mental states very desirable, where the awareness of pleasure occurs alongside awareness of other things—states we refer to as the 'enjoyment of' this or that. If this is true, then it follows that the awareness of pleasure is not the only good, and that many other states, where it is just one part, are actually much better. Once we accept the principle of organic unities, any objections to this conclusion, based on the idea that the other elements of such states have no value on their own, should vanish. I don't think I need to say anything more to refute Hedonism.
58. It only remains to say something of the two forms in which a hedonistic doctrine is commonly held—Egoism and Utilitarianism.
58. It’s important to mention the two common ways that hedonistic beliefs are typically expressed—Egoism and Utilitarianism.
Egoism, as a form of Hedonism, is the doctrine which holds that we ought each of us to pursue our own greatest happiness as our ultimate end. The doctrine will, of course, admit that sometimes the best means to this end will be to give pleasure to others; we shall, for instance, by so doing, procure for ourselves the pleasures of sympathy, of freedom from interference, and of self-esteem; and these pleasures, which we may procure by sometimes aiming directly at the happiness of other persons, may be greater than any we could otherwise get. Egoism in this sense must therefore be carefully distinguished from Egoism in another sense, the sense in which Altruism is its proper opposite. Egoism, as commonly opposed to Altruism, is apt to denote merely selfishness. In this sense, a man is an egoist, if all his actions are actually directed towards gaining pleasure for himself; whether he holds that he ought to act so, because he will thereby obtain for himself the greatest possible happiness on the whole, or not. Egoism may accordingly be used to denote the theory that we should always aim at getting pleasure for ourselves, because that is the best means to the ultimate end, whether the ultimate end be our own greatest pleasure or not. Altruism, on the other hand, may denote the theory that we ought always to aim at other people’s happiness, on the ground that this is the best means of securing our own as well as theirs. Accordingly an Egoist, in the sense in which I am now going to talk of Egoism, an Egoist, who holds that his own greatest[p. 97] happiness is the ultimate end, may at the same time be an Altruist: he may hold that he ought to ‘love his neighbour,’ as the best means to being happy himself. And conversely an Egoist, in the other sense, may at the same time be a Utilitarian. He may hold that he ought always to direct his efforts towards getting pleasure for himself on the ground that he is thereby most likely to increase the general sum of happiness.
Egoism, as a type of Hedonism, is the belief that each of us should pursue our own greatest happiness as our ultimate goal. This belief acknowledges that sometimes the best way to achieve this goal is by bringing pleasure to others; for instance, in doing so, we gain the pleasures of empathy, freedom from interference, and self-respect. These pleasures, which we can obtain by directly aiming for the happiness of others, may be greater than any pleasure we could get otherwise. Therefore, egoism in this context must be clearly differentiated from egoism in another context, where altruism is its true opposite. Egoism, as it is often contrasted with altruism, tends to imply mere selfishness. In this sense, a person is considered an egoist if all their actions are focused on gaining pleasure for themselves, regardless of whether they believe they should act this way to achieve the highest overall happiness for themselves. Egoism may therefore refer to the theory that we should always strive to attain pleasure for ourselves, as that is the best means to the ultimate goal, whether that ultimate goal is our own greatest pleasure or not. Altruism, on the other hand, may refer to the idea that we should always aim for the happiness of others, since this is the best means of ensuring our own happiness as well as theirs. Thus, an egoist, in the sense that I will discuss egoism, who believes that their own greatest happiness is the ultimate goal, may also be an altruist: they might believe they should ‘love their neighbor’ as the best means to their own happiness. Conversely, an egoist in the other sense may also be a utilitarian. They may believe they should always focus their efforts on gaining pleasure for themselves because this approach is most likely to increase the overall happiness.
59. I shall say more later about this second kind of Egoism, this anti-altruistic Egoism, this Egoism as a doctrine of means. What I am now concerned with is that utterly distinct kind of Egoism, which holds that each man ought rationally to hold: My own greatest happiness is the only good thing there is; my actions can only be good as means, in so far as they help to win me this. This is a doctrine which is not much held by writers now-a-days. It is a doctrine that was largely held by English Hedonists in the 17th and 18th centuries: it is, for example, at the bottom of Hobbes’ Ethics. But even the English school appear to have made one step forward in the present century: they are most of them now-a-days Utilitarians. They do recognise that if my own happiness is good, it would be strange that other people’s happiness should not be good too.
59. I'll discuss this second type of Egoism, this anti-altruistic Egoism, which sees Egoism as a means to an end, later. Right now, I'm focused on a completely different kind of Egoism, which asserts that every person should rationally believe: My own greatest happiness is the only real good; my actions can only be considered good as long as they help achieve this. This view isn’t widely accepted by writers today. It was commonly held by English Hedonists in the 17th and 18th centuries; for instance, it's a key point in Hobbes’ Ethics. However, even the English school seems to have made some progress this century: most of them are now Utilitarians. They acknowledge that if my own happiness is valuable, it would be odd if other people's happiness wasn't valuable as well.
In order fully to expose the absurdity of this kind of Egoism, it is necessary to examine certain confusions upon which its plausibility depends.
To fully reveal the absurdity of this type of Egoism, it's important to look at specific misunderstandings that make it seem plausible.
The chief of these is the confusion involved in the conception of ‘my own good’ as distinguished from ‘the good of others.’ This is a conception which we all use every day; it is one of the first to which the plain man is apt to appeal in discussing any question of Ethics: and Egoism is commonly advocated chiefly because its meaning is not clearly perceived. It is plain, indeed, that the name ‘Egoism’ more properly applies to the theory that ‘my own good’ is the sole good, than that my own pleasure is so. A man may quite well be an Egoist, even if he be not a Hedonist. The conception which is, perhaps, most closely associated with Egoism is that denoted by the words ‘my own interest.’ The Egoist is the man who holds that a tendency to promote his own interest is the sole possible, and sufficient, justification of all his actions. But this conception of ‘my own[p. 98] interest’ plainly includes, in general, very much more than my own pleasure. It is, indeed, only because and in so far as ‘my own interest’ has been thought to consist solely in my own pleasure, that Egoists have been led to hold that my own pleasure is the sole good. Their course of reasoning is as follows: The only thing I ought to secure is my own interest; but my own interest consists in my greatest possible pleasure; and therefore the only thing I ought to pursue is my own pleasure. That it is very natural, on reflection, thus to identify my own pleasure with my own interest; and that it has been generally done by modern moralists, may be admitted. But, when Prof. Sidgwick points this out (III. XIV. § 5, Div. III.), he should have also pointed out that this identification has by no means been made in ordinary thought. When the plain man says ‘my own interest,’ he does not mean ‘my own pleasure’—he does not commonly even include this—he means my own advancement, my own reputation, the getting of a better income etc., etc. That Prof. Sidgwick should not have noticed this, and that he should give the reason he gives for the fact that the ancient moralists did not identify ‘my own interest’ with my own pleasure, seems to be due to his having failed to notice that very confusion in the conception of ‘my own good’ which I am now to point out. That confusion has, perhaps, been more clearly perceived by Plato than by any other moralist, and to point it out suffices to refute Prof. Sidgwick’s own view that Egoism is rational.
The main issue here is the confusion between 'my own good' and 'the good of others.' This is something we all deal with daily; it's one of the first things that a regular person might mention when talking about any ethical issue. Egoism is often promoted mainly because its meaning isn't clearly understood. It's clear that the term 'Egoism' is better suited for the idea that 'my own good' is the only good, rather than just my own pleasure being so. A person can definitely be an Egoist without being a Hedonist. The idea most linked with Egoism is what we mean by 'my own interest.' An Egoist is someone who believes that the only justification for all his actions is the tendency to promote his own interest. However, this idea of 'my own interest' includes a lot more than just my own pleasure. The reason Egoists tend to think that my own pleasure is the only good is that they’ve come to believe ‘my own interest’ consists exclusively of my own pleasure. Their reasoning goes like this: The only thing I should focus on is my own interest; but my own interest is about maximizing my pleasure; therefore, the only thing I should pursue is my own pleasure. It’s understandable, upon reflection, that people might equate my own pleasure with my own interest; and indeed, this has generally been accepted by modern moralists. However, when Prof. Sidgwick points this out (III. XIV. § 5, Div. III.), he should also mention that this connection isn't typically made in everyday thinking. When the average person says 'my own interest,' they do not mean 'my own pleasure'—it's common for them to even exclude this—they mean my own progress, my own reputation, getting a better salary, etc. It seems that Prof. Sidgwick overlooked this and didn’t notice the confusion in the concept of 'my own good' that I’m highlighting. This confusion, perhaps, has been more acutely recognized by Plato than by any other moralist, and addressing it is enough to challenge Prof. Sidgwick’s claim that Egoism is rational.
What, then, is meant by ‘my own good’? In what sense can a thing be good for me? It is obvious, if we reflect, that the only thing which can belong to me, which can be mine, is something which is good, and not the fact that it is good. When, therefore, I talk of anything I get as ‘my own good,’ I must mean either that the thing I get is good, or that my possessing it is good. In both cases it is only the thing or the possession of it which is mine, and not the goodness of that thing or that possession. There is no longer any meaning in attaching the ‘my’ to our predicate, and saying: The possession of this by me is my good. Even if we interpret this by ‘My possession of this is what I think good,’ the same still holds: for what I think is that my possession of it is good simply; and, if I think rightly,[p. 99] then the truth is that my possession of it is good simply—not, in any sense, my good; and, if I think wrongly, it is not good at all. In short, when I talk of a thing as ‘my own good’ all that I can mean is that something which will be exclusively mine, as my own pleasure is mine (whatever be the various senses of this relation denoted by ‘possession’), is also good absolutely; or rather that my possession of it is good absolutely. The good of it can in no possible sense be ‘private’ or belong to me; any more than a thing can exist privately or for one person only. The only reason I can have for aiming at ‘my own good,’ is that it is good absolutely that what I so call should belong to me—good absolutely that I should have something, which, if I have it, others cannot have. But if it is good absolutely that I should have it, then everyone else has as much reason for aiming at my having it, as I have myself. If, therefore, it is true of any single man’s ‘interest’ or ‘happiness’ that it ought to be his sole ultimate end, this can only mean that that man’s ‘interest’ or ‘happiness’ is the sole good, the Universal Good, and the only thing that anybody ought to aim at. What Egoism holds, therefore, is that each man’s happiness is the sole good—that a number of different things are each of them the only good thing there is—an absolute contradiction! No more complete and thorough refutation of any theory could be desired.
What does “my own good” really mean? In what way can something be good for me? It's clear if we think about it that the only thing that can truly belong to me, that can be mine, is something that is good, and not just the fact that it is good. So, when I refer to something I receive as “my own good,” I must be talking about either the thing itself being good, or the fact that I have it being good. In both scenarios, it’s only the thing or the fact of having it that is mine, not the goodness of that thing or that fact. It doesn't make sense to attach “my” to our description and say: The possession of this by me is my good. Even if we interpret it as “My possession of this is what I consider good,” the same idea holds: what I think is that my having it is good simply; and if I’m thinking correctly,[p. 99] then the reality is that my possessing it is good simply—not, in any way, my good; and if I’m thinking incorrectly, it isn’t good at all. In short, when I refer to something as “my own good,” all I can mean is that something that will be solely mine, like my own pleasure (regardless of the various interpretations of the term “possession”), is also good absolutely; or rather that my possessing it is good absolutely. The good of it cannot possibly be “private” or just belong to me; just as a thing cannot exist privately or for only one person. The only reason I could have for striving at “my own good” is that it is good absolutely for what I refer to as such to belong to me—good absolutely that I should have something, which, if I have it, others cannot also possess. But if it is good absolutely that I should have it, then everyone else has as much reason to want my having it as I do. Therefore, if it’s true that any single person’s “interest” or “happiness” should be their only ultimate goal, this can only mean that that person’s “interest” or “happiness” is the sole good, the Universal Good, and the only thing anyone should strive for. What Egoism claims, then, is that each person's happiness is the only good—that multiple different things are each the only good thing there is—an absolute contradiction! There couldn’t be a more complete and thorough disproof of any theory.
60. Yet Prof. Sidgwick holds that Egoism is rational; and it will be useful briefly to consider the reasons which he gives for this absurd conclusion. ‘The Egoist,’ he says (last Chap. § 1), ‘may avoid the proof of Utilitarianism by declining to affirm,’ either ‘implicitly or explicitly, that his own greatest happiness is not merely the ultimate rational end for himself, but a part of Universal Good.’ And in the passage to which he here refers us, as having there ‘seen’ this, he says: ‘It cannot be proved that the difference between his own happiness and another’s happiness is not for him all-important’ (IV. ii. § 1). What does Prof. Sidgwick mean by these phrases ‘the ultimate rational end for himself,’ and ‘for him all-important’? He does not attempt to define them; and it is largely the use of such undefined phrases which causes absurdities to be committed in philosophy.
60. Yet Prof. Sidgwick argues that Egoism is rational, and it will be helpful to briefly look at the reasons he gives for this questionable conclusion. “The Egoist,” he states (last Chap. § 1), “can avoid the proof of Utilitarianism by choosing not to affirm,” either “implicitly or explicitly, that his own greatest happiness is not just the ultimate rational goal for himself but also part of the Universal Good.” In the passage he references, where he claims to have “seen” this, he states: “It cannot be proven that the difference between his own happiness and someone else’s happiness is not for him incredibly important” (IV. ii. § 1). What does Prof. Sidgwick mean by the phrases “the ultimate rational goal for himself” and “for him incredibly important”? He doesn’t define them, and it's primarily the vague use of such undefined phrases that leads to absurdities in philosophy.
[p. 100]
[p. 100]
Is there any sense in which a thing can be an ultimate rational end for one person and not for another? By ‘ultimate’ must be meant at least that the end is good-in-itself—good in our undefinable sense; and by ‘rational,’ at least, that it is truly good. That a thing should be an ultimate rational end means, then, that it is truly good in itself; and that it is truly good in itself means that it is a part of Universal Good. Can we assign any meaning to that qualification ‘for himself,’ which will make it cease to be a part of Universal Good? The thing is impossible: for the Egoist’s happiness must either be good in itself, and so a part of Universal Good, or else it cannot be good in itself at all: there is no escaping this dilemma. And if it is not good at all, what reason can he have for aiming at it? how can it be a rational end for him? That qualification ‘for himself’ has no meaning unless it implies ‘not for others’; and if it implies ‘not for others,’ then it cannot be a rational end for him, since it cannot be truly good in itself: the phrase ‘an ultimate rational end for himself’ is a contradiction in terms. By saying that a thing is an end for one particular person, or good for him, can only be meant one of four things. Either (1) it may be meant that the end in question is something which will belong exclusively to him; but in that case, if it is to be rational for him to aim at it, that he should exclusively possess it must be a part of Universal Good. Or (2) it may be meant that it is the only thing at which he ought to aim; but this can only be, because, by so doing, he will do the most he can towards realising Universal Good: and this, in our case, will only give Egoism as a doctrine of means. Or (3) it may be meant that the thing is what he desires or thinks good; and then, if he thinks wrongly, it is not a rational end at all, and, if he thinks rightly, it is a part of Universal Good. Or (4) it may be meant that it is peculiarly appropriate that a thing which will belong exclusively to him should also by him be approved or aimed at; but, in this case, both that it should belong to him and that he should aim at it must be parts of Universal Good: by saying that a certain relation between two things is fitting or appropriate, we can only mean that the existence of that relation is absolutely good[p. 101] in itself (unless it be so as a means, which gives case (2)). By no possible meaning, then, that can be given to the phrase that his own happiness is the ultimate rational end for himself can the Egoist escape the implication that his own happiness is absolutely good; and by saying that it is the ultimate rational end, he must mean that it is the only good thing—the whole of Universal Good: and, if he further maintains, that each man’s happiness is the ultimate rational end for him, we have the fundamental contradiction of Egoism—that an immense number of different things are, each of them, the sole good.—And it is easy to see that the same considerations apply to the phrase that ‘the difference between his own happiness and another’s is for him all-important.’ This can only mean either (1) that his own happiness is the only end which will affect him, or (2) that the only important thing for him (as a means) is to look to his own happiness, or (3) that it is only his own happiness which he cares about, or (4) that it is good that each man’s happiness should be the only concern of that man. And none of these propositions, true as they may be, have the smallest tendency to shew that if his own happiness is desirable at all, it is not a part of Universal Good. Either his own happiness is a good thing or it is not; and, in whatever sense it may be all-important for him, it must be true that, if it is not good, he is not justified in pursuing it, and that, if it is good, everyone else has an equal reason to pursue it, so far as they are able and so far as it does not exclude their attainment of other more valuable parts of Universal Good. In short it is plain that the addition of ‘for him’ ‘for me’ to such words as ‘ultimate rational end,’ ‘good,’ ‘important’ can introduce nothing but confusion. The only possible reason that can justify any action is that by it the greatest possible amount of what is good absolutely should be realised. And if anyone says that the attainment of his own happiness justifies his actions, he must mean that this is the greatest possible amount of Universal Good which he can realise. And this again can only be true either because he has no power to realise more, in which case he only holds Egoism as a doctrine of means; or else because his own happiness is the[p. 102] greatest amount of Universal Good which can be realised at all, in which case we have Egoism proper, and the flagrant contradiction that every person’s happiness is singly the greatest amount of Universal Good which can be realised at all.
Is there a way in which something can be an ultimate rational goal for one person and not for another? By ‘ultimate,’ we mean at least that the goal is good in itself—good in an indescribable way; and by ‘rational,’ at least that it is genuinely good. If something is an ultimate rational goal, it means it is genuinely good in itself, and that being genuinely good in itself means it is part of the Universal Good. Can we give any meaning to the phrase ‘for himself’ that makes it stop being part of the Universal Good? It's impossible: the Egoist’s happiness must either be good in itself, making it part of the Universal Good, or it cannot be good in itself at all—there's no way around this dilemma. If it’s not good at all, what reason does he have for pursuing it? How can it be a rational goal for him? The phrase ‘for himself’ loses meaning unless it implies ‘not for others’; and if it implies ‘not for others,’ then it cannot be a rational goal for him, since it can't be genuinely good in itself: saying ‘an ultimate rational goal for himself’ is contradictory. Claiming that something is an end for a specific person or good for him can only mean one of four things. Either (1) it might mean that the goal in question is something that will belong only to him; but in that case, for it to be rational for him to pursue it, it must be part of the Universal Good. Or (2) it might mean that it is the only thing he should aim for; but this can only be true if by doing so, he does the most he can to realize the Universal Good, making Egoism merely a theory of means. Or (3) it could mean that the thing is what he desires or thinks is good; and if he thinks wrongly, it’s not a rational goal at all, but if he thinks rightly, it is part of the Universal Good. Or (4) it may mean that it is especially fitting for something that will belong only to him to be approved or pursued by him; but if that's the case, both that it should belong to him and that he should pursue it must be parts of the Universal Good: when we say that a certain relationship between two things is fitting or appropriate, we can only mean that the existence of that relationship is absolutely good in itself (unless it’s so as a means, which fits case (2)). Thus, by no possible meaning attached to the phrase that his own happiness is the ultimate rational goal for himself can the Egoist escape the implication that his own happiness is absolutely good; and by claiming it is the ultimate rational goal, he must mean that it is the only good thing—the entirety of Universal Good: and if he further insists that each person’s happiness is the ultimate rational goal for him, we encounter the fundamental contradiction of Egoism—that an immense number of different things are, each one of them, the sole good. It is also clear that the same reasoning applies to the idea that ‘the difference between his own happiness and someone else’s is for him all-important.’ This can only mean either (1) that his own happiness is the only goal that will affect him, or (2) that the only important thing for him (as a means) is to focus on his own happiness, or (3) that it is only his own happiness that he cares about, or (4) that it is good for each person’s happiness to be the only concern of that person. None of these statements, however valid they may be, suggest that if his own happiness is desirable at all, it isn’t a part of the Universal Good. Either his own happiness is a good thing or it isn’t; and whatever sense it may have of being all-important for him, it must be true that if it’s not good, he isn’t justified in pursuing it, and if it is good, everyone else has just as good a reason to pursue it, as much as they can, and as long as it doesn’t prevent them from attaining other more valuable aspects of the Universal Good. In short, it’s obvious that adding ‘for him’ or ‘for me’ to terms like ‘ultimate rational goal,’ ‘good,’ or ‘important’ only leads to confusion. The only meaningful reason that can justify any action is that it should bring about the greatest possible amount of what is absolutely good. If someone claims that achieving his own happiness justifies his actions, he must mean that this is the greatest possible amount of Universal Good he can achieve. And this can only be true either because he has no power to achieve more, in which case he only regards Egoism as a theory of means; or because his own happiness is the greatest total of Universal Good that can be achieved at all, which leads us to the core of Egoism: the blatant contradiction that everyone's happiness is, individually, the greatest amount of Universal Good that can be achieved.
61. It should be observed that, since this is so, ‘the relation of Rational Egoism to Rational Benevolence,’ which Prof. Sidgwick regards ‘as the profoundest problem of Ethics’ (III. XIII. § 5, n. 1), appears in quite a different light to that in which he presents it. ‘Even if a man,’ he says, ‘admits the self-evidence of the principle of Rational Benevolence, he may still hold that his own happiness is an end which it is irrational for him to sacrifice to any other; and that therefore a harmony between the maxim of Prudence and the maxim of Rational Benevolence must be somehow demonstrated, if morality is to be made completely rational. This latter view is that which I myself hold’ (last Chap. § 1). Prof. Sidgwick then goes on to shew ‘that the inseparable connection between Utilitarian Duty and the greatest happiness of the individual who conforms to it cannot be satisfactorily demonstrated on empirical grounds’ (Ib. § 3). And the final paragraph of his book tells us that, since ‘the reconciliation of duty and self-interest is to be regarded as a hypothesis logically necessary to avoid a fundamental contradiction in one chief department of our thought, it remains to ask how far this necessity constitutes a sufficient reason for accepting this hypothesis[20]’ (Ib. § 5). To ‘assume the existence of such a Being, as God, by the consensus of theologians, is conceived to be’ would, he has already argued, ensure the required reconciliation; since the Divine Sanctions of such a God ‘would, of course, suffice to make it always every one’s interest to promote universal happiness to the best of his knowledge’ (Ib. § 5).
61. It should be noted that, given this situation, “the relationship between Rational Egoism and Rational Benevolence,” which Professor Sidgwick considers “the most significant issue in Ethics” (III. XIII. § 5, n. 1), appears quite different from how he presents it. “Even if a person,” he states, “acknowledges the obviousness of the principle of Rational Benevolence, they might still argue that their own happiness is an objective that it is unreasonable for them to sacrifice for any other; and that therefore a balance between the principle of Prudence and the principle of Rational Benevolence must somehow be proven if morality is to be completely rational. This latter perspective is the one I personally hold” (last Chap. § 1). Professor Sidgwick then explains “that the unavoidable link between Utilitarian Duty and the greatest happiness of the individual who practices it cannot be adequately demonstrated on empirical grounds” (Ib. § 3). The final paragraph of his book informs us that, since “the reconciliation of duty and self-interest is to be seen as a hypothesis logically necessary to avoid a fundamental contradiction in one major area of our thinking, it remains to explore how much this necessity serves as a sufficient reason for accepting this hypothesis[20]” (Ib. § 5). To “assume the existence of such a Being, as God, as conceived by the consensus of theologians” would, he has previously argued, guarantee the required reconciliation; since the Divine Sanctions of such a God “would, of course, ensure that it is always in everyone’s interest to promote universal happiness to the best of their knowledge” (Ib. § 5).
Now what is this ‘reconciliation of duty and self-interest,’ which Divine Sanctions could ensure? It would consist in the mere fact that the same conduct which produced the greatest possible happiness of the greatest number would always also produce the greatest possible happiness of the agent. If this were the case (and our empirical knowledge shews that it is not[p. 103] the case in this world), ‘morality’ would, Prof. Sidgwick thinks, be ‘completely rational’: we should avoid ‘an ultimate and fundamental contradiction in our apparent intuitions of what is Reasonable in conduct.’ That is to say, we should avoid the necessity of thinking that it is as manifest an obligation to secure our own greatest Happiness (maxim of Prudence), as to secure the greatest Happiness on the whole (maxim of Benevolence). But it is perfectly obvious we should not. Prof. Sidgwick here commits the characteristic fallacy of Empiricism—the fallacy of thinking that an alteration in facts could make a contradiction cease to be a contradiction. That a single man’s happiness should be the sole good, and that also everybody’s happiness should be the sole good, is a contradiction which cannot be solved by the assumption that the same conduct will secure both: it would be equally contradictory, however certain we were that that assumption was justified. Prof. Sidgwick strains at a gnat and swallows a camel. He thinks the Divine Omnipotence must be called into play to secure that what gives other people pleasure should also give it to him—that only so can Ethics be made rational; while he overlooks the fact that even this exercise of Divine Omnipotence would leave in Ethics a contradiction, in comparison with which his difficulty is a trifle—a contradiction, which would reduce all Ethics to mere nonsense, and before which the Divine Omnipotence must be powerless to all eternity. That each man’s happiness should be the sole good, which we have seen to be the principle of Egoism, is in itself a contradiction: and that it should also be true that the Happiness of all is the sole good, which is the principle of Universalistic Hedonism, would introduce another contradiction. And that these propositions should all be true might well be called ‘the profoundest problem in Ethics’: it would be a problem necessarily insoluble. But they cannot all be true, and there is no reason, but confusion, for the supposition that they are. Prof. Sidgwick confuses this contradiction with the mere fact (in which there is no contradiction) that our own greatest happiness and that of all do not seem always attainable by the same means. This fact, if Happiness were the sole good, would indeed be of some importance; and,[p. 104] on any view, similar facts are of importance. But they are nothing but instances of the one important fact that in this world the quantity of good which is attainable is ridiculously small compared to that which is imaginable. That I cannot get the most possible pleasure for myself, if I produce the most possible pleasure on the whole, is no more the profoundest problem of Ethics, than that in any case I cannot get as much pleasure altogether as would be desirable. It only states that, if we get as much good as possible in one place, we may get less on the whole, because the quantity of attainable good is limited. To say that I have to choose between my own good and that of all is a false antithesis: the only rational question is how to choose between my own and that of others, and the principle on which this must be answered is exactly the same as that on which I must choose whether to give pleasure to this other person or to that.
Now, what does “reconciliation of duty and self-interest” mean, which Divine Sanctions could guarantee? It would simply mean that the same actions leading to the greatest possible happiness for the greatest number would also lead to the greatest happiness for the individual acting. If this were true (and our experience shows that it isn’t[p. 103] in this world), then, according to Prof. Sidgwick, “morality” would be “completely rational”: we would avoid “an ultimate and fundamental contradiction in our apparent intuitions of what is reasonable in conduct.” In other words, we wouldn’t need to think that it’s just as clear an obligation to seek our own greatest happiness (the maxim of Prudence) as it is to seek the greatest happiness overall (the maxim of Benevolence). However, it’s very clear that we do need to. Prof. Sidgwick makes the typical mistake of Empiricism—the mistake of believing that a change in facts could resolve a contradiction. The idea that one person's happiness is the sole good, and that everyone’s happiness is also the sole good, is a contradiction that cannot be resolved by assuming that the same actions can achieve both: it remains contradictory, no matter how confident we are that assumption is valid. Prof. Sidgwick gets caught up in a minor detail while overlooking a much larger issue. He believes that Divine Omnipotence needs to be invoked to ensure that what pleases others also brings him joy—only then can Ethics be considered rational; meanwhile, he ignores that this invocation of Divine Omnipotence would still leave a contradiction in Ethics that makes his concern seem trivial—a contradiction that could render all Ethics meaningless and is a problem that Divine Omnipotence could never resolve. The idea that each person’s happiness is the sole good, representing the principle of Egoism, is inherently contradictory. The notion that the happiness of all is the sole good, which aligns with the principle of Universalistic Hedonism, introduces another contradiction. The idea that all these propositions could be true might be considered “the deepest problem in Ethics”: it is a problem that is necessarily unsolvable. But they cannot all be true, and any suggestion that they are results only in confusion. Prof. Sidgwick confuses this contradiction with the straightforward fact (which is not contradictory) that our own greatest happiness and that of everyone else don’t always seem to be achievable by the same means. This fact, if happiness were the sole good, would indeed matter; and,[p. 104] in any case, similar facts hold significance. Yet, they are just examples of the one crucial fact that in this world, the amount of good we can actually achieve is laughably small compared to what is conceivable. The fact that I can’t secure maximum pleasure for myself if I create maximum pleasure for everyone isn’t the deepest problem in Ethics, just like not being able to obtain as much pleasure overall as I would like isn’t either. It merely indicates that if we gain as much good as possible in one area, we may end up with less overall because the quantity of achievable good is limited. To say that I have to choose between my own good and that of all is a misleading dilemma: the real question is how to choose between my own and that of others, and the principle that governs this choice is the same as the one guiding my decision to give pleasure to one person rather than another.
62. It is plain, then, that the doctrine of Egoism is self-contradictory; and that one reason why this is not perceived, is a confusion with regard to the meaning of the phrase ‘my own good.’ And it may be observed that this confusion and the neglect of this contradiction are necessarily involved in the transition from Naturalistic Hedonism, as ordinarily held, to Utilitarianism. Mill, for instance, as we saw, declares: ‘Each person, so far as he believes it to be attainable, desires his own happiness’ (p. 53). And he offers this as a reason why the general happiness is desirable. We have seen that to regard it as such, involves, in the first place, the naturalistic fallacy. But moreover, even if that fallacy were not a fallacy, it could only be a reason for Egoism and not for Utilitarianism. Mill’s argument is as follows: A man desires his own happiness; therefore his own happiness is desirable. Further: A man desires nothing but his own happiness; therefore his own happiness is alone desirable. We have next to remember, that everybody, according to Mill, so desires his own happiness: and then it will follow that everybody’s happiness is alone desirable. And this is simply a contradiction in terms. Just consider what it means. Each man’s happiness is the only thing desirable: several different things are each of them the[p. 105] only thing desirable. This is the fundamental contradiction of Egoism. In order to think that what his arguments tend to prove is not Egoism but Utilitarianism, Mill must think that he can infer from the proposition ‘Each man’s happiness is his own good,’ the proposition ‘The happiness of all is the good of all’; whereas in fact, if we understand what ‘his own good’ means, it is plain that the latter can only be inferred from ‘The happiness of all is the good of each.’ Naturalistic Hedonism, then, logically leads only to Egoism. Of course, a Naturalist might hold that what we aimed at was simply ‘pleasure’ not our own pleasure; and that, always assuming the naturalistic fallacy, would give an unobjectionable ground for Utilitarianism. But more commonly he will hold that it is his own pleasure he desires, or at least will confuse this with the other; and then he must logically be led to adopt Egoism and not Utilitarianism.
62. It’s clear that the concept of Egoism is self-contradictory, and one reason this isn’t recognized is confusion about the phrase “my own good.” This confusion and the oversight of the contradiction are inherently part of the shift from the commonly accepted Naturalistic Hedonism to Utilitarianism. Mill, for example, states: “Each person, as far as he believes it to be attainable, desires his own happiness” (p. 53). He presents this as an argument for why general happiness is desirable. We’ve already seen that considering it this way involves the naturalistic fallacy. Moreover, even if that fallacy weren’t a fallacy, it could only support Egoism and not Utilitarianism. Mill’s argument is as follows: A person desires his own happiness; therefore, his happiness is worthwhile. Next: A person desires nothing but his own happiness; therefore, his happiness is the only thing that matters. We also need to remember that, according to Mill, everyone desires their own happiness: thus, it follows that everyone’s happiness is the only thing that matters. This is simply a contradiction. Think about what it implies. Each person’s happiness is the only thing worth wanting: several different things are each the[p. 105] only thing worth wanting. This is the core contradiction of Egoism. To believe that his arguments intend to prove Utilitarianism rather than Egoism, Mill must assume that he can derive from the statement “Each man’s happiness is his own good” the statement “The happiness of all is the good of all”; whereas, in reality, if we understand what “his own good” means, it’s clear that the latter can only be derived from “The happiness of all is the good of each.” Thus, Naturalistic Hedonism logically leads only to Egoism. Certainly, a Naturalist might argue that what we seek is simply “pleasure” rather than our own pleasure; and that, while assuming the naturalistic fallacy, would provide a valid basis for Utilitarianism. However, more often they will claim that it’s their own pleasure they desire, or at least confuse this with the other; and then they must logically gravitate toward Egoism rather than Utilitarianism.
63. The second cause I have to give why Egoism should be thought reasonable, is simply its confusion with that other kind of Egoism—Egoism as a doctrine of means. This second Egoism has a right to say: You ought to pursue your own happiness, sometimes at all events; it may even say: Always. And when we find it saying this we are apt to forget its proviso: But only as a means to something else. The fact is we are in an imperfect state; we cannot get the ideal all at once. And hence it is often our bounden duty, we often absolutely ‘ought,’ to do things which are good only or chiefly as means: we have to do the best we can, what is absolutely ‘right,’ but not what is absolutely good. Of this I shall say more hereafter. I only mention it here because I think it is much more plausible to say that we ought to pursue our own pleasure as a means than as an end, and that this doctrine, through confusion, lends some of its plausibility to the utterly different doctrine of Egoism proper: My own greatest pleasure is the only good thing.
63. The second reason I have for considering Egoism reasonable is simply its mix-up with another type of Egoism—Egoism as a doctrine of means. This second Egoism can rightly argue: You should pursue your own happiness, sometimes at least; it might even claim: Always. And when it does, we tend to forget its condition: But only as a means to something else. The truth is we live in an imperfect world; we can’t achieve the ideal all at once. Therefore, it is often our clear duty, we sometimes absolutely ‘ought’ to do things that are good only or primarily as means: we have to do our best, what is absolutely ‘right,’ but not necessarily what is absolutely good. I’ll elaborate on this later. I mention it here because I think it’s much more reasonable to say that we should pursue our own pleasure as a means rather than as an end, and that this idea, through confusion, gives some of its credibility to the completely different idea of true Egoism: My own greatest pleasure is the only good thing.
64. So much for Egoism. Of Utilitarianism not much need be said; but two points may seem deserving of notice.
64. That's enough about Egoism. There's not much to say about Utilitarianism, but two points might be worth mentioning.
The first is that this name, like that of Egoism, does not naturally suggest that all our actions are to be judged according to the degree in which they are a means to pleasure. Its[p. 106] natural meaning is that the standard of right and wrong in conduct is its tendency to promote the interest of everybody. And by interest is commonly meant a variety of different goods, classed together only because they are what a man commonly desires for himself, so far as his desires have not that psychological quality which is meant by ‘moral.’ The ‘useful’ thus means, and was in ancient Ethics systematically used to mean, what is a means to the attainment of goods other than moral goods. It is quite an unjustifiable assumption that these goods are only good as means to pleasure or that they are commonly so regarded. The chief reason for adopting the name ‘Utilitarianism’ was, indeed, merely to emphasize the fact that right and wrong conduct must be judged by its results—as a means, in opposition to the strictly Intuitionistic view that certain ways of acting were right and others wrong, whatever their results might be. In thus insisting that what is right must mean what produces the best possible results Utilitarianism is fully justified. But with this correct contention there has been historically, and very naturally, associated a double error. (1) The best possible results were assumed to consist only in a limited class of goods, roughly coinciding with those which were popularly distinguished as the results of merely ‘useful’ or ‘interested’ actions; and these again were hastily assumed to be good only as means to pleasure. (2) The Utilitarians tend to regard everything as a mere means, neglecting the fact that some things which are good as means are also good as ends. Thus, for instance, assuming pleasure to be a good, there is a tendency to value present pleasure only as a means to future pleasure, and not, as is strictly necessary if pleasure is good as an end, also to weigh it against possible future pleasures. Much utilitarian argument involves the logical absurdity that what is here and now, never has any value in itself, but is only to be judged by its consequences; which again, of course, when they are realised, would have no value in themselves, but would be mere means to a still further future, and so on ad infinitum.
The first issue is that this name, like Egoism, doesn’t naturally imply that all our actions should be evaluated based on how much they contribute to pleasure. Its[p. 106] meaning suggests that the standard for right and wrong in behavior is its ability to promote the interest of everyone. By interest, people usually refer to various kinds of good things, grouped together simply because they are what a person typically wants for themselves, as long as their desires don’t have the psychological aspect referred to as ‘moral.’ The term ‘useful’ thus refers to, and was historically used in ethics to indicate, what serves as a means to achieve goods other than moral goods. It’s completely unfounded to assume that these goods are good only as pathways to pleasure or that they are generally seen that way. The main reason for using the term ‘Utilitarianism’ was simply to highlight the idea that right and wrong actions should be assessed by their outcomes—as means—contrasting with the strictly Intuitionistic view that certain actions were right or wrong regardless of their results. By insisting that what is right must lead to the best possible outcomes, Utilitarianism is entirely justified. However, this accurate position has historically, and understandably, been linked to a dual misconception. (1) The best possible outcomes were assumed to consist solely of a limited set of goods, roughly corresponding to what people typically termed the results of merely ‘useful’ or ‘self-interested’ actions; and these were quickly assumed to be good only as a means to pleasure. (2) Utilitarians tend to view everything merely as a means, overlooking that some things which are good as means are also good as ends. For example, if we consider pleasure to be good, there is a tendency to evaluate present pleasure only as a means to future pleasure, rather than, as it should be if pleasure is good as an end, also to compare it with potential future pleasures. Much of the utilitarian argument includes the logical absurdity that what exists in the here and now has no inherent value, but should solely be judged by its outcomes; which, of course, when they are realized, would hold no value in themselves, but would be mere means to yet another future, and so on ad infinitum.
The second point deserving notice with regard to Utilitarianism is that, when the name is used for a form of Hedonism, it does not commonly, even in its description of its end,[p. 107] accurately distinguish between means and end. Its best-known formula is that the result by which actions are to be judged is ‘the greatest happiness of the greatest number.’ But it is plain that, if pleasure is the sole good, provided the quantity be equally great, an equally desirable result will have been obtained whether it be enjoyed by many or by few, or even if it be enjoyed by nobody. It is plain that, if we ought to aim at the greatest happiness of the greatest number, this can only, on the hedonistic principle, be because the existence of pleasure in a great number of persons seems to be the best means available for attaining the existence of the greatest quantity of pleasure. This may actually be the case; but it is fair to suspect that Utilitarians have been influenced, in their adoption of the hedonistic principle, by this failure to distinguish clearly between pleasure or consciousness of pleasure and its possession by a person. It is far easier to regard the possession of pleasure by a number of persons as the sole good, than so to regard the mere existence of an equally great quantity of pleasure. If, indeed, we were to take the Utilitarian principle strictly, and to assume them to mean that the possession of pleasure by many persons was good in itself, the principle is not hedonistic: it includes as a necessary part of the ultimate end, the existence of a number of persons, and this will include very much more than mere pleasure.
The second point that deserves attention regarding Utilitarianism is that when the term is used to refer to a type of Hedonism, it doesn't usually, even in its description of its end,[p. 107] accurately differentiate between means and end. Its most famous formula states that actions should be judged by ‘the greatest happiness of the greatest number.’ However, it's clear that if pleasure is the only good, as long as the quantity is equally substantial, an equally desirable outcome will have been achieved whether it is experienced by many, by a few, or even by no one at all. It becomes evident that if we aim for the greatest happiness of the greatest number, this can only be, according to the hedonistic principle, because having pleasure among a large number of people seems to be the best means to achieve the highest amount of pleasure. This may actually be true; however, it is reasonable to suspect that Utilitarians have been swayed in their acceptance of the hedonistic principle by this confusion between experiencing pleasure and actually possessing it. It is much simpler to view the possession of pleasure by a group of people as the sole good than to view the mere existence of an equally large amount of pleasure that is not possessed. If we were to take the Utilitarian principle literally and assume they mean that the possession of pleasure by many people is good in itself, then the principle is not hedonistic: it inherently includes as part of the ultimate goal the presence of a number of individuals, which entails much more than just pleasure.
Utilitarianism, however, as commonly held, must be understood to maintain that either mere consciousness of pleasure, or consciousness of pleasure together with the minimum adjunct which may be meant by the existence of such consciousness in at least one person, is the sole good. This is its significance as an ethical doctrine; and as such it has already been refuted in my refutation of Hedonism. The most that can be said for it is that it does not seriously mislead in its practical conclusions, on the ground that, as an empirical fact, the method of acting which brings most good on the whole does also bring most pleasure. Utilitarians do indeed generally devote most of their arguments to shewing that the course of action which will bring most pleasure is in general such as common sense would approve. We have seen that Prof. Sidgwick appeals to this[p. 108] fact as tending to shew that pleasure is the sole good; and we have also seen that it does not tend to shew this. We have seen how very flimsy the other arguments advanced for this proposition are; and that, if it be fairly considered by itself, it appears to be quite ridiculous. And, moreover, that the actions which produce most good on the whole do also produce most pleasure is extremely doubtful. The arguments tending to shew it are all more or less vitiated by the assumption that what appear to be necessary conditions for the attainment of most pleasure in the near future, will always continue so to be. And, even with this vicious assumption, they only succeed in making out a highly problematical case. How, therefore, this fact is to be explained, if it be a fact, need not concern us. It is sufficient to have shewn that many complex states of mind are much more valuable than the pleasure they contain. If this be so, no form of Hedonism can be true. And, since the practical guidance afforded by pleasure as a criterion is small in proportion as the calculation attempts to be accurate, we can well afford to await further investigation, before adopting a guide, whose utility is very doubtful and whose trustworthiness we have grave reason to suspect.
Utilitarianism, as it’s commonly understood, has to be seen as claiming that either just being aware of pleasure or being aware of pleasure along with the essential component that comes from at least one person having that awareness is the only good. This is its significance as an ethical theory; and since it has already been challenged in my refutation of Hedonism, that’s worth noting. The most that can be said for it is that it doesn’t lead to serious misinterpretations in its practical conclusions, because, empirically speaking, the actions that generally produce the most good also tend to bring about the most pleasure. Utilitarians usually focus most of their arguments on showing that the actions which will yield the most pleasure are often in line with what common sense would endorse. We have seen how Prof. Sidgwick uses this[p. 108] idea to suggest that pleasure is the only good, yet we’ve also noted that it doesn’t actually support this claim. The other arguments made for this idea are quite weak, and when considered on their own, they come off as rather absurd. Moreover, it's highly questionable whether the actions that result in the greatest overall good truly yield the most pleasure. The arguments that try to prove this are all flawed to some degree, based on the assumption that what seem to be essential conditions for attaining the most pleasure in the near future will always remain the same. Even with this flawed assumption, they only manage to present a very uncertain case. Thus, we need not worry about how this fact, if it is indeed a fact, can be explained. It’s enough to show that many complex mental states are far more valuable than the pleasure they include. If this is true, no form of Hedonism can be true. And since the practical guidance offered by pleasure as a criterion diminishes the more precise the calculations try to be, we can certainly take our time before relying on a guide whose usefulness is very questionable and whose reliability we have serious reasons to doubt.
65. The most important points which I have endeavoured to establish in this chapter are as follows. (1) Hedonism must be strictly defined as the doctrine that ‘Pleasure is the only thing which is good in itself’: this view seems to owe its prevalence mainly to the naturalistic fallacy, and Mill’s arguments may be taken as a type of those which are fallacious in this respect; Sidgwick alone has defended it without committing this fallacy, and its final refutation must therefore point out the errors in his arguments (36-38). (2) Mill’s ‘Utilitarianism’ is criticised: it being shewn (a) that he commits the naturalistic fallacy in identifying ‘desirable’ with ‘desired’; (b) that pleasure is not the only object of desire. The common arguments for Hedonism seem to rest on these two errors (39-44). (3) Hedonism is considered as an ‘Intuition,’ and it is pointed out (a) that Mill’s allowance that some pleasures are inferior in quality to others implies both that it is an Intuition and that it is a false one (46-48); (b) that[p. 109] Sidgwick fails to distinguish ‘pleasure’ from ‘consciousness of pleasure,’ and that it is absurd to regard the former, at all events, as the sole good (49-52); (c) that it seems equally absurd to regard ‘consciousness of pleasure’ as the sole good, since, if it were so, a world in which nothing else existed might be absolutely perfect: Sidgwick fails to put to himself this question, which is the only clear and decisive one (53-57). (4) What are commonly considered to be the two main types of Hedonism, namely, Egoism and Utilitarianism, are not only different from, but strictly contradictory of, one another; since the former asserts ‘My own greatest pleasure is the sole good,’ the latter ‘The greatest pleasure of all is the sole good.’ Egoism seems to owe its plausibility partly to the failure to observe this contradiction—a failure which is exemplified by Sidgwick; partly to a confusion of Egoism as doctrine of end, with the same as doctrine of means. If Hedonism is true, Egoism cannot be so; still less can it be so, if Hedonism is false. The end of Utilitarianism, on the other hand, would, if Hedonism were true, be, not indeed the best conceivable, but the best possible for us to promote; but it is refuted by the refutation of Hedonism (58-64).
65. The key points I’ve tried to establish in this chapter are as follows. (1) Hedonism should be clearly defined as the belief that ‘Pleasure is the only thing that is good in itself.’ This view seems to be widespread mainly because of the naturalistic fallacy, and Mill’s arguments can be seen as examples that are problematic in this regard. Sidgwick is the only one who defends it without falling into this fallacy, so the final refutation must highlight the mistakes in his arguments (36-38). (2) Mill’s ‘Utilitarianism’ is critiqued: it is shown that (a) he commits the naturalistic fallacy by equating ‘desirable’ with ‘desired’; (b) pleasure is not the only thing people desire. The usual arguments for Hedonism seem to rely on these two errors (39-44). (3) Hedonism is viewed as an ‘Intuition,’ and it is pointed out that (a) Mill’s allowance that some pleasures are of lower quality than others suggests both that it is an Intuition and that it is a mistaken one (46-48); (b) Sidgwick fails to differentiate ‘pleasure’ from ‘awareness of pleasure,’ and it’s unreasonable to consider the former, at least, as the sole good (49-52); (c) it also seems equally unreasonable to regard ‘awareness of pleasure’ as the sole good, since, if that were the case, a world with nothing else might still be considered absolutely perfect. Sidgwick doesn’t ask himself this question, which is the only clear and decisive one (53-57). (4) The two main types of Hedonism, Egoism and Utilitarianism, are not only different; they are fundamentally contradictory. The former claims ‘My own greatest pleasure is the only good,’ while the latter claims ‘The greatest pleasure of all is the only good.’ Egoism seems plausible partly due to the failure to recognize this contradiction—a failure exemplified by Sidgwick; and partly due to confusing Egoism as an end doctrine with the same as a means doctrine. If Hedonism is true, then Egoism cannot be; even less so if Hedonism is false. The goal of Utilitarianism, on the other hand, would, if Hedonism were true, be not the best conceivable but the best we could realistically promote; however, it is disproven by the downfall of Hedonism (58-64).
[p. 110]
[p. 110]
CHAPTER IV.
METAPHYSICAL ETHICS.
Metaphysical Ethics.
66. In this chapter I propose to deal with a type of ethical theory which is exemplified in the ethical views of the Stoics, of Spinoza, of Kant, and especially of a number of modern writers, whose views in this respect are mainly due to the influence of Hegel. These ethical theories have this in common, that they use some metaphysical proposition as a ground for inferring some fundamental proposition of Ethics. They all imply, and many of them expressly hold, that ethical truths follow logically from metaphysical truths—that Ethics should be based on Metaphysics. And the result is that they all describe the Supreme Good in metaphysical terms.
66. In this chapter, I plan to discuss a type of ethical theory found in the views of the Stoics, Spinoza, Kant, and particularly in several modern writers who are largely influenced by Hegel. These ethical theories share a common feature: they use a metaphysical proposition as a basis for inferring a fundamental principle of Ethics. They all suggest, and many explicitly state, that ethical truths logically follow from metaphysical truths—that Ethics should be rooted in Metaphysics. Consequently, they all describe the Supreme Good in metaphysical terms.
What, then, is to be understood by ‘metaphysical’? I use the term, as I explained in Chapter II., in opposition to ‘natural.’ I call those philosophers preeminently ‘metaphysical’ who have recognised most clearly that not everything which is is a ‘natural object.’ ‘Metaphysicians’ have, therefore, the great merit of insisting that our knowledge is not confined to the things which we can touch and see and feel. They have always been much occupied, not only with that other class of natural objects which consists in mental facts, but also with the class of objects or properties of objects, which certainly do not exist in time, are not therefore parts of Nature, and which, in fact, do not exist at all. To this class, as I have said, belongs what we mean by the adjective ‘good.’ It is not goodness, but only the things or qualities which are good, which can exist in time—can have[p. 111] duration, and begin and cease to exist—can be objects of perception. But the most prominent members of this class are perhaps numbers. It is quite certain that two natural objects may exist; but it is equally certain that two itself does not exist and never can. Two and two are four. But that does not mean that either two or four exists. Yet it certainly means something. Two is somehow, although it does not exist. And it is not only simple terms of propositions—the objects about which we know truths—that belong to this class. The truths which we know about them form, perhaps, a still more important subdivision. No truth does, in fact, exist; but this is peculiarly obvious with regard to truths like ‘Two and two are four,’ in which the objects, about which they are truths, do not exist either. It is with the recognition of such truths as these—truths which have been called ‘universal’—and of their essential unlikeness to what we can touch and see and feel, that metaphysics proper begins. Such ‘universal’ truths have always played a large part in the reasonings of metaphysicians from Plato’s time till now; and that they have directed attention to the difference between these truths and what I have called ‘natural objects’ is the chief contribution to knowledge which distinguishes them from that other class of philosophers—‘empirical’ philosophers—to which most Englishmen have belonged.
What should we understand by ‘metaphysical’? I use the term, as I mentioned in Chapter II, in contrast to ‘natural.’ I consider those philosophers to be primarily ‘metaphysical’ who have clearly recognized that not everything that is is a ‘natural object.’ ‘Metaphysicians’ deserve significant credit for emphasizing that our understanding isn't limited to things we can touch, see, and feel. They have always been deeply engaged not only with the other category of natural objects, which includes mental facts, but also with objects or properties that certainly do not exist in time, are therefore not parts of Nature, and, in fact, do not exist at all. This category includes what we denote by the word ‘good.’ It is not goodness, but only the things or qualities that are good, which can exist in time—can have[p. 111] duration, and begin and cease to exist—can be objects of perception. But perhaps the most notable examples of this category are numbers. It's entirely clear that two natural objects can exist; but it’s equally clear that two itself does not exist and never can. Two and two are four. But that doesn’t imply that either two or four exists. Still, it definitely means something. Two is somehow, even though it does not exist. It’s not just simple terms of propositions—the objects about which we know truths—that belong to this category. The truths we know about them form, perhaps, an even more important subdivision. No truth does, in fact, exist; but this is particularly evident with truths like ‘Two and two are four,’ where the objects about which they are truths do not exist either. The recognition of such truths—truths that have been called ‘universal’—and their essential difference from what we can touch, see, and feel, marks the true beginning of metaphysics. These ‘universal’ truths have consistently played a significant role in the reasoning of metaphysicians from Plato’s time to the present; the attention they have drawn to the distinction between these truths and what I refer to as ‘natural objects’ is the main contribution to knowledge that sets them apart from that other group of philosophers—‘empirical’ philosophers—most Englishmen belong to.
But though, if we are to define ‘metaphysics’ by the contribution which it has actually made to knowledge, we should have to say that it has emphasized the importance of objects which do not exist at all, metaphysicians themselves have not recognised this. They have indeed recognised and insisted that there are, or may be, objects of knowledge which do not exist in time, or at least which we cannot perceive; and in recognising the possibility of these, as an object of investigation, they have, it may be admitted, done a service to mankind. But they have in general supposed that whatever does not exist in time, must at least exist elsewhere, if it is to be at all—that, whatever does not exist in Nature, must exist in some supersensible reality, whether timeless or not. Consequently they have held that the truths with which they have been occupied, over and above[p. 112] the objects of perception, were in some way truths about such supersensible reality. If, therefore, we are to define ‘metaphysics’ not by what it has attained, but by what it has attempted, we should say that it consists in the attempt to obtain knowledge, by processes of reasoning, of what exists but is not a part of Nature. Metaphysicians have actually held that they could give us such knowledge of non-natural existence. They have held that their science consists in giving us such knowledge as can be supported by reasons, of that supersensible reality of which religion professes to give us a fuller knowledge, without any reasons. When, therefore, I spoke above of ‘metaphysical’ propositions, I meant propositions about the existence of something supersensible—of something which is not an object of perception, and which cannot be inferred from what is an object of perception by the same rules of inference by which we infer the past and future of what we call ‘Nature.’ And when I spoke of ‘metaphysical’ terms, I meant terms which refer to qualities of such a supersensible reality, which do not belong to anything ‘natural.’ I admit that ‘metaphysics’ should investigate what reasons there may be for belief in such a supersensible reality; since I hold that its peculiar province is the truth about all objects which are not natural objects. And I think that the most prominent characteristic of metaphysics, in history, has been its profession to prove the truth about non-natural existents. I define ‘metaphysical,’ therefore, by a reference to supersensible reality; although I think that the only non-natural objects, about which it has succeeded in obtaining truth, are objects which do not exist at all.
But if we're going to define 'metaphysics' by what it has actually contributed to knowledge, we have to acknowledge that it has highlighted the significance of things that don't exist at all, even though metaphysicians themselves haven't recognized this. They have acknowledged and insisted that there are, or could be, objects of knowledge that don't exist in time, or at least that we can't perceive; by acknowledging the possibility of these as subjects for study, they've, it can be agreed, provided a service to humanity. However, they generally assumed that anything that doesn’t exist in time must at least exist somewhere else to be at all—that anything that doesn't exist in Nature must exist in some supersensible reality, whether it's timeless or not. As a result, they believed that the truths they've explored, beyond[p. 112] those of perception, were somehow truths about that supersensible reality. Therefore, if we define 'metaphysics' not by what it has achieved but by what it has tried to do, we would say it consists of the effort to gain knowledge, through reasoning processes, about what exists but is not part of Nature. Metaphysicians have actually claimed that they could provide us with knowledge of non-natural existence. They believed their discipline involves giving us knowledge that can be supported by reasoning, about that supersensible reality which religion claims to provide a fuller understanding of, without any reasons. So when I previously referred to 'metaphysical' propositions, I meant propositions about the existence of something supersensible—something that isn't a perceptible object, and that can't be inferred from what is a perceptible object using the same rules of inference we use to infer the past and future of what we call 'Nature.' Similarly, when I referred to 'metaphysical' terms, I meant terms that describe qualities of such a supersensible reality, which do not apply to anything 'natural.' I agree that 'metaphysics' should explore the reasons for believing in such a supersensible reality; since I believe its unique domain is the truth about all objects that are not natural objects. I think the most significant aspect of metaphysics, throughout history, has been its claim to prove the truth about non-natural existents. Thus, I define 'metaphysical' by referencing supersensible reality; although I believe that the only non-natural objects about which it has succeeded in uncovering truth are objects that do not exist at all.
So much, I hope, will suffice to explain what I mean by the term ‘metaphysical,’ and to shew that it refers to a clear and important distinction. It was not necessary for my purpose to make the definition exhaustive or to shew that it corresponds in essentials with established usage. The distinction between ‘Nature’ and a supersensible reality is very familiar and very important: and since the metaphysician endeavours to prove things with regard to a supersensible reality, and since he deals largely in truths which are not mere natural facts, it is plain that his arguments, and errors (if any), will be of a more subtle[p. 113] kind than those which I have dealt with under the name of ‘Naturalism.’ For these two reasons it seemed convenient to treat ‘Metaphysical Ethics’ by themselves.
Hopefully, this will help clarify what I mean by the term ‘metaphysical’ and show that it refers to a clear and important distinction. It wasn’t necessary for me to make the definition thorough or to demonstrate that it aligns with established usage. The difference between ‘Nature’ and a supersensible reality is well-known and significant: since metaphysicians aim to prove aspects related to a supersensible reality, and since they often engage with truths that are not just natural facts, it’s clear that their arguments, and any mistakes (if there are any), will be more subtle[p. 113] than those I've addressed under the term ‘Naturalism.’ For these two reasons, it seemed appropriate to discuss ‘Metaphysical Ethics’ on their own.
67. I have said that those systems of Ethics, which I propose to call ‘Metaphysical,’ are characterised by the fact that they describe the Supreme Good in ‘metaphysical’ terms; and this has now been explained as meaning that they describe it in terms of something which (they hold) does exist, but does not exist in Nature—in terms of a supersensible reality. A ‘Metaphysical Ethics’ is marked by the fact that it makes the assertion: That which would be perfectly good is something which exists, but is not natural; that which has some characteristic possessed by a supersensible reality. Such an assertion was made by the Stoics when they asserted that a life in accordance with Nature was perfect. For they did not mean by ‘Nature,’ what I have so defined, but something supersensible which they inferred to exist, and which they held to be perfectly good. Such an assertion, again, is made by Spinoza when he tells us that we are more or less perfect, in proportion as we are more or less closely united with Absolute Substance by the ‘intellectual love’ of God. Such an assertion is made by Kant when he tells us that his ‘Kingdom of Ends’ is the ideal. And such, finally, is made by modern writers who tell us that the final and perfect end is to realise our true selves—a self different both from the whole and from any part of that which exists here and now in Nature.
67. I have said that the systems of Ethics I call ‘Metaphysical’ are characterized by describing the Supreme Good in ‘metaphysical’ terms; and this means they explain it in terms of something that they believe exists, but not in Nature—in terms of a supersensible reality. A ‘Metaphysical Ethics’ is defined by the assertion: What would be perfectly good is something that exists, but is not natural; it has some characteristics of a supersensible reality. The Stoics made a similar assertion when they claimed that living in accordance with Nature was perfect. However, by ‘Nature,’ they didn’t mean what I have defined, but rather something supersensible that they believed existed and considered to be perfectly good. Spinoza also made this assertion when he told us that we are more or less perfect, depending on how closely we are united with Absolute Substance through the ‘intellectual love’ of God. Kant made a similar claim when he stated that his ‘Kingdom of Ends’ represents the ideal. Lastly, modern writers suggest that the ultimate and perfect goal is to realize our true selves—a self that is different from both the whole and any part of what exists here and now in Nature.
Now it is plain that such ethical principles have a merit, not possessed by Naturalism, in recognising that for perfect goodness much more is required than any quantity of what exists here and now or can be inferred as likely to exist in the future. And moreover it is quite possible that their assertions should be true, if we only understand them to assert that something which is real possesses all the characteristics necessary for perfect goodness. But this is not all that they assert. They also imply, as I said, that this ethical proposition follows from some proposition which is metaphysical: that the question ‘What is real?’ has some logical bearing upon the question ‘What is good?’ It was for this reason that I described ‘Meta[p. 114]physical Ethics’ in Chapter II. as based upon the naturalistic fallacy. To hold that from any proposition asserting ‘Reality is of this nature’ we can infer, or obtain confirmation for, any proposition asserting ‘This is good in itself’ is to commit the naturalistic fallacy. And that a knowledge of what is real supplies reasons for holding certain things to be good in themselves is either implied or expressly asserted by all those who define the Supreme Good in metaphysical terms. This contention is part of what is meant by saying that Ethics should be ‘based’ on Metaphysics. It is meant that some knowledge of supersensible reality is necessary as a premise for correct conclusions as to what ought to exist. This view is, for instance, plainly expressed in the following statements: ‘The truth is that the theory of Ethics which seems most satisfactory has a metaphysical basis.... If we rest our view of Ethics on the idea of the development of the ideal self or of the rational universe, the significance of this cannot be made fully apparent without a metaphysical examination of the nature of self; nor can its validity be established except by a discussion of the reality of the rational universe[21].’ The validity of an ethical conclusion about the nature of the ideal, it is here asserted, cannot be established except by considering the question whether that ideal is real. Such an assertion involves the naturalistic fallacy. It rests upon the failure to perceive that any truth which asserts ‘This is good in itself’ is quite unique in kind—that it cannot be reduced to any assertion about reality, and therefore must remain unaffected by any conclusions we may reach about the nature of reality. This confusion as to the unique nature of ethical truths is, I have said, involved in all those ethical theories which I have called metaphysical. It is plain that, but for some confusion of the sort, no-one would think it worth while even to describe the Supreme Good in metaphysical terms. If, for instance, we are told that the ideal consists in the realisation of the ‘true self,’ the very words suggest that the fact that the self in question is true is supposed to have some bearing on the fact that it is good. All the ethical truth[p. 115] which can possibly be conveyed by such an assertion would be just as well conveyed by saying that the ideal consisted in the realisation of a particular kind of self, which might be either real or purely imaginary. ‘Metaphysical Ethics,’ then, involve the supposition that Ethics can be based on Metaphysics; and our first concern with them is to make clear that this supposition must be false.
Now it's clear that these ethical principles have an advantage over Naturalism by recognizing that achieving perfect goodness requires much more than just what currently exists or what might exist in the future. Additionally, it's possible for their claims to be true, if we understand them to mean that something real embodies all the qualities necessary for perfect goodness. But that's not all they claim. They also imply, as I mentioned, that this ethical statement follows from some metaphysical statement: that the question "What is real?" has some logical connection to the question "What is good?" This is why I referred to 'Meta[p. 114]physical Ethics' in Chapter II as founded on the naturalistic fallacy. To assert that from any statement saying "Reality is this way" we can deduce or validate any statement saying "This is good in itself" is to commit the naturalistic fallacy. Moreover, the belief that knowing what is real provides reasons for believing certain things are good in themselves is either implied or explicitly stated by everyone who defines the Supreme Good in metaphysical terms. This argument is part of what it means to say that Ethics should be ‘based’ on Metaphysics. It suggests that some understanding of a reality beyond what we can sense is necessary as a premise to draw accurate conclusions about what ought to exist. This perspective is clearly articulated in the following statements: "The truth is that the most satisfactory theory of Ethics has a metaphysical foundation... If we base our view of Ethics on the idea of developing the ideal self or the rational universe, we can’t fully understand its significance without a metaphysical exploration of the nature of self; nor can we validate it without discussing the reality of the rational universe[21]." Here, it is argued that the validity of an ethical conclusion regarding the nature of the ideal cannot be established without addressing whether that ideal is real. Such a claim involves the naturalistic fallacy. It relies on misunderstanding that any truth asserting "This is good in itself" is fundamentally unique—that it can't be simplified to any claim about reality and therefore must remain unaffected by any conclusions we may reach about what reality is like. This confusion about the unique nature of ethical truths is, as I’ve explained, present in all those ethical theories I categorized as metaphysical. Clearly, without this kind of confusion, no one would find it worthwhile to even describe the Supreme Good in metaphysical terms. For example, if we are told that the ideal consists in realizing the "true self," the wording suggests that the fact that this self is true somehow relates to its goodness. All the ethical truth that could be conveyed by such a statement could just as easily be expressed by saying that the ideal consists in realizing a particular kind of self, which may be either real or purely imaginary. Therefore, 'Metaphysical Ethics' involve the assumption that Ethics can be based on Metaphysics, and our primary concern is to clarify that this assumption must be false.
68. In what way can the nature of supersensible reality possibly have a bearing upon Ethics?
68. How could the nature of supersensible reality possibly relate to Ethics?
I have distinguished two kinds of ethical questions, which are far too commonly confused with one another. Ethics, as commonly understood, has to answer both the question ‘What ought to be?’ and the question ‘What ought we to do?’ The second of these questions can only be answered by considering what effects our actions will have. A complete answer to it would give us that department of Ethics which may be called the doctrine of means or practical Ethics. And upon this department of ethical enquiry it is plain that the nature of a supersensible reality may have a bearing. If, for instance, Metaphysics could tell us not only that we are immortal, but also, in any degree, what effects our actions in this life will have upon our condition in a future one, such information would have an undoubted bearing upon the question what we ought to do. The Christian doctrines of heaven and hell are in this way highly relevant to practical Ethics. But it is worthy of notice that the most characteristic doctrines of Metaphysics are such as either have no such bearing upon practical Ethics or have a purely negative bearing—involving the conclusion that there is nothing which we ought to do at all. They profess to tell us the nature not of a future reality, but of one that is eternal and which therefore no actions of ours can have power to alter. Such information may indeed have relevance to practical Ethics, but it must be of a purely negative kind. For, if it holds, not only that such an eternal reality exists, but also, as is commonly the case, that nothing else is real—that nothing either has been, is now, or will be real in time—then truly it will follow that nothing we can do will ever bring any good to pass. For it is certain that our actions can only affect the future; and if[p. 116] nothing can be real in the future, we can certainly not hope ever to make any good thing real. It would follow, then, that there can be nothing which we ought to do. We cannot possibly do any good; for neither our efforts, nor any result which they may seem to effect, have any real existence. But this consequence, though it follows strictly from many metaphysical doctrines, is rarely drawn. Although a metaphysician may say that nothing is real but that which is eternal, he will generally allow that there is some reality also in the temporal: and his doctrine of an eternal reality need not interfere with practical Ethics, if he allows that, however good the eternal reality may be, yet some things will also exist in time, and that the existence of some will be better than that of others. It is, however, worth while to insist upon this point, because it is rarely fully realised.
I’ve identified two types of ethical questions that are often mixed up. Ethics, as it's commonly understood, needs to address both “What should exist?” and “What should we do?” The second question can only be answered by looking at the effects our actions will have. A complete answer would lead us to that area of Ethics known as the doctrine of means or practical Ethics. Clearly, the nature of a supersensible reality can influence this area of ethical inquiry. For example, if Metaphysics could inform us not just that we are immortal, but also in some way how our actions in this life will impact our situation in a future life, that knowledge would certainly affect what we should do. The Christian ideas of heaven and hell are highly relevant to practical Ethics in this way. However, it's important to note that the most distinctive ideas in Metaphysics either have no connection to practical Ethics or only a negative impact—suggesting that there’s nothing we ought to do at all. These ideas aim to describe not a future reality, but an eternal one, which our actions cannot change. Such information may be relevant to practical Ethics, but it would be purely negative. If it asserts that such an eternal reality exists, and as is usually claimed, that nothing else is real—that nothing ever has been, is, or will be real in time—then it would indeed follow that nothing we can do will ever lead to anything good. Our actions impact only the future; if nothing can be real in the future, we can’t expect to ever make anything good real. Therefore, it follows that there isn’t anything we ought to do. We can't achieve any good because neither our efforts nor any outcomes they might appear to create have any real existence. However, although this conclusion logically follows from many metaphysical doctrines, it’s rarely expressed. Even if a metaphysician says that nothing is real except what is eternal, they typically accept that there is some reality in the temporal realm as well: and their idea of an eternal reality doesn’t need to contradict practical Ethics if they acknowledge that, while the eternal reality may be good, some things will also exist in time, and some of those will be better than others. It’s important to emphasize this point because it’s often not fully recognized.
If it is maintained that there is any validity at all in practical Ethics—that any proposition which asserts ‘We ought to do so and so’ can have any truth—this contention can only be consistent with the Metaphysics of an eternal reality, under two conditions. One of these is, (1) that the true eternal reality, which is to be our guide, cannot, as is implied by calling it true, be the only true reality. For a moral rule, bidding us realise a certain end, can only be justified, if it is possible that that end should, at least partially, be realised. Unless our efforts can effect the real existence of some good, however little, we certainly have no reason for making them. And if the eternal reality is the sole reality, then nothing good can possibly exist in time: we can only be told to try to bring into existence something which we know beforehand cannot possibly exist. If it is said that what exists in time can only be a manifestation of the true reality, it must at least be allowed that that manifestation is another true reality—a good which we really can cause to exist; for the production of something quite unreal, even if it were possible, cannot be a reasonable end of action. But if the manifestation of that which eternally exists is real, then that which eternally exists is not the sole reality.
If we claim that practical Ethics has any validity—that any statement saying ‘We should do this and that’ can hold any truth—this claim can only align with the Metaphysics of an eternal reality under two conditions. One of these is, (1) that the true eternal reality, which is supposed to guide us, cannot, as implied by calling it true, be the only true reality. For a moral rule that instructs us to achieve a specific goal can only be justified if it’s possible for that goal to be achieved, at least in part. Unless our efforts can actually result in the real existence of some good, no matter how small, we have no reason to pursue them. If the eternal reality is the only reality, then nothing good can exist in time: we can only be told to try to create something that we know in advance cannot possibly exist. If it is argued that what exists in time is merely a manifestation of the true reality, it must be acknowledged that this manifestation itself is another true reality—a good that we can actually help to bring into existence; because aiming to create something entirely unreal, even if it were possible, cannot be a rational goal for our actions. But if the manifestation of what exists eternally is real, then that which exists eternally is not the sole reality.
And the second condition which follows from such a metaphysical principle of Ethics, is (2) that the eternal reality cannot[p. 117] be perfect—cannot be the sole good. For just as a reasonable rule of conduct requires that what we are told to realise should be capable of being truly real, so it requires that the realisation of this ideal shall be truly good. It is just that which can be realised by our efforts—the appearance of the eternal in time, or whatsoever else is allowed to be attainable—which must be truly good, if it is to be worth our efforts. That the eternal reality is good, will by no means justify us in aiming at its manifestation, unless that manifestation itself be also good. For the manifestation is different from the reality: its difference is allowed, when we are told that it can be made to exist, whereas the reality itself exists unalterably. And the existence of this manifestation is the only thing which we can hope to effect: that also is admitted. If, therefore, the moral maxim is to be justified, it is the existence of this manifestation, as distinguished from the existence of its corresponding reality, which must be truly good. The reality may be good too: but to justify the statement that we ought to produce anything, it must be maintained, that just that thing itself, and not something else which may be like it, is truly good. If it is not true that the existence of the manifestation will add something to the sum of good in the Universe, then we have no reason to aim at making it exist; and if it is true that it will add something to the sum of good, then the existence of that which is eternal cannot be perfect by itself—it cannot include the whole of possible goods.
And the second condition that follows from this metaphysical principle of Ethics is (2) that eternal reality cannot[p. 117] be perfect—it can't be the only good. Just like a reasonable rule of conduct requires that what we are encouraged to achieve should truly be real, it also requires that the realization of this ideal should be genuinely good. It's precisely what can be achieved through our efforts—the manifestation of the eternal in time, or whatever else is deemed attainable—that must be truly good if it's worth our efforts. The idea that the eternal reality is good doesn't justify our pursuit of its manifestation unless that manifestation itself is also good. The manifestation is different from the reality: its difference is acknowledged when we say it can come into being, while the reality itself exists unchangingly. The existence of this manifestation is the only thing we can hope to create: that much is agreed. Therefore, if the moral principle is to be justified, it must be the existence of this manifestation, as separate from the existence of its corresponding reality, that must be truly good. The reality might be good too, but to justify saying we should create anything, we must assert that that specific thing itself—rather than something similar—is genuinely good. If it isn’t true that the existence of the manifestation will add to the overall good in the Universe, then we have no reason to strive to make it happen; if it is true that it will contribute to the overall good, then the existence of what is eternal cannot be perfect on its own—it cannot encompass all possible goods.
Metaphysics, then, will have a bearing upon practical Ethics—upon the question what we ought to do—if it can tell us anything about the future consequences of our actions beyond what can be established by ordinary inductive reasoning. But the most characteristic metaphysical doctrines, those which profess to tell us not about the future but about the nature of an eternal reality, can either have no bearing upon this practical question or else must have a purely destructive bearing. For it is plain that what exists eternally cannot be affected by our actions; and only what is affected by our actions can have a bearing on their value as means. But the nature of an eternal reality either admits no inference as to the results of[p. 118] our actions, except in so far as it can also give us information about the future (and how it can do this is not plain), or else, if, as is usual, it is maintained to be the sole reality and the sole good, it shews that no results of our actions can have any value whatever.
Metaphysics, then, will relate to practical ethics—specifically to the question of what we should do—if it can provide insights about the future consequences of our actions beyond what ordinary inductive reasoning can establish. However, the most distinctive metaphysical theories, which claim to describe not the future but the nature of an eternal reality, can either be irrelevant to this practical question or only serve a purely destructive purpose. It’s clear that what exists eternally cannot be influenced by our actions; only what can be affected by our actions can impact their value as means. Yet, the nature of an eternal reality either does not allow for any conclusions about the outcomes of our actions, unless it can also provide information about the future (and it's unclear how it could do this), or, if it is typically claimed to be the only reality and the only good, it shows that no results of our actions can have any real value at all.
69. But this bearing upon practical Ethics, such as it is, is not what is commonly meant when it is maintained that Ethics must be based on Metaphysics. It is not the assertion of this relation which I have taken to be characteristic of Metaphysical Ethics. What metaphysical writers commonly maintain is not merely that Metaphysics can help us to decide what the effects of our actions will be, but that it can tell us which among possible effects will be good and which will be bad. They profess that Metaphysics is a necessary basis for an answer to that other and primary ethical question: What ought to be? What is good in itself? That no truth about what is real can have any logical bearing upon the answer to this question has been proved in Chapter I. To suppose that it has, implies the naturalistic fallacy. All that remains for us to do is, therefore, to expose the main errors which seem to have lent plausibility to this fallacy in its metaphysical form. If we ask: What bearing can Metaphysics have upon the question, What is good? the only possible answer is: Obviously and absolutely none. We can only hope to enforce conviction that this answer is the only true one by answering the question: Why has it been supposed to have such a bearing? We shall find that metaphysical writers seem to have failed to distinguish this primary ethical question: What is good? from various other questions; and to point out these distinctions will serve to confirm the view that their profession to base Ethics on Metaphysics is solely due to confusion.
69. However, this connection to practical Ethics, as it stands, isn’t what people usually mean when they argue that Ethics needs to be grounded in Metaphysics. It’s not the claim of this relationship that I consider characteristic of Metaphysical Ethics. What metaphysical writers typically assert is not just that Metaphysics can help us determine the outcomes of our actions, but that it can also identify which potential outcomes are good and which are bad. They argue that Metaphysics is essential for answering another primary ethical question: What should be? What is inherently good? It has been demonstrated in Chapter I that no truth about reality can logically influence the answer to this question. To believe otherwise is to assume the naturalistic fallacy. Therefore, our task is to identify the main misconceptions that have made this fallacy seem reasonable in its metaphysical form. If we ask: What relevance can Metaphysics have regarding the question, What is good? the only reasonable answer is: Clearly and absolutely none. We can hope to reinforce the belief that this answer is the only correct one by addressing the question: Why has it been thought to have such relevance? We will find that metaphysical writers seem to have mixed up this fundamental ethical question: What is good? with various other inquiries; clarifying these distinctions will help confirm that their claim to ground Ethics in Metaphysics stems solely from confusion.
70. And, first of all, there is an ambiguity in the very question: What is good? to which it seems some influence must be attributed. The question may mean either: Which among existing things are good? or else: What sort of things are good, what are the things which, whether they are real or not, ought to be real? And of these two questions it is plain that to answer the first, we must know both the answer to the[p. 119] second and also the answer to the question: What is real? It asks us for a catalogue of all the good things in the Universe; and to answer it we must know both what things there are in the Universe and also which of them are good. Upon this question then our Metaphysics would have a bearing, if it can tell us what is real. It would help us to complete the list of things which are both real and good. But to make such a list is not the business of Ethics. So far as it enquires What is good? its business is finished when it has completed the list of things which ought to exist, whether they do exist or not. And if our Metaphysics is to have any bearing upon this part of the ethical problem, it must be because the fact that something is real gives a reason for thinking that it or something else is good, whether it be real or not. That any such fact can give any such reason is impossible; but it may be suspected that the contrary supposition has been encouraged by the failure to distinguish between the assertion ‘This is good,’ when it means ‘This sort of thing is good,’ or ‘This would be good, if it existed,’ and the assertion ‘This existing thing is good.’ The latter proposition obviously cannot be true, unless the thing exists; and hence the proof of the thing’s existence is a necessary step to its proof. Both propositions, however, in spite of this immense difference between them, are commonly expressed in the same terms. We use the same words, when we assert an ethical proposition about a subject that is actually real, and when we assert it about a subject considered as merely possible.
70. First of all, there's a bit of confusion in the question: What is good? It seems that some influence must come into play here. The question could mean either: Which of the things that exist are good? or: What type of things are good, what are the things that, whether they actually exist or not, should exist? To answer the first question, we clearly need to know the answer to the second question as well as the question: What is real? It’s asking us to create a list of all the good things in the Universe; to answer it, we need to know not only what exists in the Universe but also which of those things are good. Our Metaphysics would help with this question if it can tell us what is real. It would assist us in completing the list of things that are both real and good. However, creating such a list isn't the job of Ethics. When it asks, What is good? its task is complete when it has listed the things that should exist, regardless of whether they actually do. If our Metaphysics is to relate to this part of the ethical issue, it must be because the fact that something is real gives us a reason to think that it—or something else—is good, regardless of whether it exists. It’s unlikely that any fact could provide such a reason, but it might seem that this misunderstanding has been encouraged by not distinguishing between saying 'This is good,' when we mean 'This kind of thing is good' or 'This would be good if it existed,' and saying 'This actual thing is good.' The latter statement clearly can't be true unless the thing exists, so proving that it exists is a necessary step toward proving its goodness. Despite the significant difference between them, both statements are usually expressed in the same way. We use the same words when we make an ethical claim about something that is actually real and when we make one about something that is only considered possible.
In this ambiguity of language we have, then, a possible source of error with regard to the bearing of truths that assert reality upon truths that assert goodness. And that this ambiguity is actually neglected by those metaphysical writers who profess that the Supreme Good consists in an eternal reality may be shewn in the following way. We have seen, in considering the possible bearing of Metaphysics upon Practical Ethics, that, since what exists eternally cannot possibly be affected by our actions, no practical maxim can possibly be true, if the sole reality is eternal. This fact, as I said, is commonly neglected by metaphysical writers: they assert both[p. 120] of the two contradictory propositions that the sole reality is eternal and that its realisation in the future is a good too. Prof. Mackenzie, we saw, asserts that we ought to aim at the realisation of ‘the true self’ or ‘the rational universe’: and yet Prof. Mackenzie holds, as the word ‘true’ plainly implies, that both ‘the true self’ and ‘the rational universe’ are eternally real. Here we have already a contradiction in the supposition that what is eternally real can be realised in the future; and it is comparatively unimportant whether or not we add to this the further contradiction involved in the supposition that the eternal is the sole reality. That such a contradiction should be supposed valid can only be explained by a neglect of the distinction between a real subject and the character which that real subject possesses. What is eternally real may, indeed, be realised in the future, if by this be only meant the sort of thing which is eternally real. But when we assert that a thing is good, what we mean is that its existence or reality is good; and the eternal existence of a thing cannot possibly be the same good as the existence in time of what, in a necessary sense, is nevertheless the same thing. When, therefore, we are told that the future realisation of the true self is good, this can at most only mean that the future realisation of a self exactly like the self, which is true and exists eternally, is good. If this fact were clearly stated, instead of consistently ignored, by those who advocate the view that the Supreme Good can be defined in these metaphysical terms, it seems probable that the view that a knowledge of reality is necessary to a knowledge of the Supreme Good would lose part of its plausibility. That that at which we ought to aim cannot possibly be that which is eternally real, even if it be exactly like it; and that the eternal reality cannot possibly be the sole good—these two propositions seem sensibly to diminish the probability that Ethics must be based on Metaphysics. It is not very plausible to maintain that because one thing is real, therefore something like it, which is not real, would be good. It seems, therefore, that some of the plausibility of Metaphysical Ethics may be reasonably attributed to the failure to observe that verbal ambiguity, whereby ‘This is good’ may mean either ‘This real thing is good’ or ‘The[p. 121] existence of this thing (whether it exists or not) would be good.’
In this uncertainty of language, we have a potential source of confusion about how truths that claim reality relate to truths that claim goodness. It's clear that this confusion is overlooked by those metaphysical writers who claim that the Supreme Good is an eternal reality. This can be demonstrated in the following way. In looking at how Metaphysics relates to Practical Ethics, we see that since what exists eternally cannot be influenced by our actions, no practical guideline can be true if the only reality is eternal. This fact is often ignored by metaphysical writers: they assert both of the contradictory statements that the only reality is eternal and that its realization in the future is also good. For example, Professor Mackenzie claims that we should aim for the realization of “the true self” or “the rational universe.” Yet, Professor Mackenzie also believes, as the term “true” clearly indicates, that both “the true self” and “the rational universe” are eternally real. Here we already face a contradiction by suggesting that what is eternally real can be realized in the future; it’s less important whether we add another contradiction by assuming that the eternal is the only reality. This contradiction can only be seen as valid due to a failure to recognize the difference between a real subject and the qualities that real subject has. What is eternally real might indeed be realized in the future, but only if we mean the type of thing that is eternally real. However, when we say that something is good, we imply that its existence or reality is good; and the eternal existence of something cannot be equated with the existence in time of what is, in a necessary sense, still the same thing. Thus, when we are told that the future realization of the true self is good, it can only mean that the future realization of a self exactly like the eternally true self is good. If this were clearly stated rather than consistently ignored by those who argue that the Supreme Good can be defined in these metaphysical terms, it seems likely that the idea that knowing reality is necessary for understanding the Supreme Good would lose some of its appeal. It’s not possible for what we should aim for to be something that is eternally real, even if it is exactly like that; and the eternal reality cannot be the sole good—these two claims seem to reasonably reduce the likelihood that Ethics must be grounded in Metaphysics. It’s not very convincing to say that just because one thing is real, something similar that is not real would still be good. Therefore, it appears that some of the persuasiveness of Metaphysical Ethics can be justifiably linked to the oversight of that verbal ambiguity, where “This is good” can mean either “This real thing is good” or “The existence of this thing (whether it exists or not) would be good.”
71. By exposing this ambiguity, then, we are enabled to see more clearly what must be meant by the question: Can Ethics be based on Metaphysics? and we are, therefore, more likely to find the correct answer. It is now plain that a metaphysical principle of Ethics which says ‘This eternal reality is the Supreme Good’ can only mean ‘Something like this eternal reality would be the Supreme Good.’ We are now to understand such principles as having the only meaning which they can consistently have, namely, as describing the kind of thing which ought to exist in the future, and which we ought to try to bring about. And, when this is clearly recognised, it seems more evident that the knowledge that such a kind of thing is also eternally real, cannot help us at all towards deciding the properly ethical question: Is the existence of that kind of good thing? If we can see that an eternal reality is good, we can see, equally easily, once the idea of such a thing has been suggested to us, that it would be good. The metaphysical construction of Reality would therefore be quite as useful, for the purposes of Ethics, if it were a mere construction of an imaginary Utopia: provided the kind of thing suggested is the same, fiction is as useful as truth, for giving us matter, upon which to exercise the judgment of value. Though, therefore, we admit that Metaphysics may serve an ethical purpose, in suggesting things, which would not otherwise have occurred to us, but which, when they are suggested, we see to be good; yet, it is not as Metaphysics—as professing to tell us what is real—that it has this use. And, in fact, the pursuit of truth must limit the usefulness of Metaphysics in this respect. Wild and extravagant as are the assertions which metaphysicians have made about reality, it is not to be supposed but that they have been partially deterred from making them wilder still, by the idea that it was their business to tell nothing but the truth. But the wilder they are, and the less useful for Metaphysics, the more useful will they be for Ethics; since, in order to be sure that we have neglected nothing in the description of our ideal, we should have had before us as wide a[p. 122] field as possible of suggested goods. It is probable that this utility of Metaphysics, in suggesting possible ideals, may sometimes be what is meant by the assertion that Ethics should be based on Metaphysics. It is not uncommon to find that which suggests a truth confused with that on which it logically depends; and I have already pointed out that Metaphysical have, in general, this superiority over Naturalistic systems, that they conceive the Supreme Good as something differing more widely from what exists here and now. But, if it be recognised that, in this sense, Ethics should, far more emphatically, be based on fiction, metaphysicians will, I think, admit that a connection of this kind between Metaphysics and Ethics would by no means justify the importance which they attribute to the bearing of the one study on the other.
71. By pointing out this ambiguity, we can see more clearly what the question really means: Can Ethics be grounded in Metaphysics? This clarity makes it more likely for us to find the right answer. It’s now obvious that a metaphysical principle of Ethics that states “This eternal reality is the Supreme Good” can only be interpreted as “Something like this eternal reality would be the Supreme Good.” We should understand such principles as having the only consistent meaning they can have, which is describing the kind of thing that should exist in the future and which we should strive to create. When we recognize this clearly, it becomes more evident that knowing such a kind of thing is also eternally real doesn’t help us at all with the ethical question: Does that kind of good thing exist? If we understand that an eternal reality is good, we can equally easily see, once the idea of such a thing has been presented to us, that it would be good. Therefore, the metaphysical construction of Reality would serve Ethics just as well if it were simply an imaginary Utopia: as long as the kind of thing suggested is the same, fiction is as valuable as truth for giving us material on which to exercise our judgment of value. So, while we acknowledge that Metaphysics may serve an ethical purpose by suggesting ideas that we might not have thought of otherwise, which when suggested we recognize as good; it’s not as Metaphysics—claiming to reveal what is real—that it has this utility. In fact, the pursuit of truth must limit the usefulness of Metaphysics in this context. As wild and extravagant as the claims made by metaphysicians about reality are, it shouldn’t be assumed that they haven’t been partially restrained from making even wilder claims by the obligation to speak only the truth. Yet, the wilder these claims are, the less useful they become for Metaphysics, but the more they can be useful for Ethics; since, to ensure that we don't overlook anything in describing our ideal, we should consider as broad a[p. 122] range of suggested goods as possible. It's likely that this usefulness of Metaphysics in presenting possible ideals is sometimes what people mean when they say that Ethics should be based on Metaphysics. It’s not uncommon to confuse what suggests a truth with what it logically depends on; and I’ve already noted that Metaphysical systems generally have an edge over Naturalistic systems because they envision the Supreme Good as something that is more distinct from what exists here and now. However, if it’s acknowledged that, in this sense, Ethics should, even more strongly, be based on fiction, I believe metaphysicians would agree that such a connection between Metaphysics and Ethics would not justify the significance they attribute to the relationship between the two studies.
72. We may, then, attribute the obstinate prejudice that a knowledge of supersensible reality is a necessary step to a knowledge of what is good in itself, partly to a failure to perceive that the subject of the latter judgment is not anything real as such, and partly to a failure to distinguish the cause of our perception of a truth from the reason why it is true. But these two causes will carry us only a very little way in our explanation of why Metaphysics should have been supposed to have a bearing upon Ethics. The first explanation which I have given would only account for the supposition that a thing’s reality is a necessary condition for its goodness. This supposition is, indeed, commonly made; we find it commonly presupposed that unless a thing can be shewn to be involved in the constitution of reality, it cannot be good. And it is, therefore, worth while to insist that this is not the case; that Metaphysics is not even necessary to furnish part of the basis of Ethics. But when metaphysicians talk of basing Ethics on Metaphysics they commonly mean much more than this. They commonly mean that Metaphysics is the sole basis of Ethics—that it furnishes not only one necessary condition but all the conditions necessary to prove that certain things are good. And this view may, at first sight, appear to be held in two different forms. It may be asserted that merely to prove a thing supersensibly real is sufficient to prove it good: that the truly[p. 123] real must, for that reason alone, be truly good. But more commonly it appears to be held that the real must be good because it possesses certain characters. And we may, I think, reduce the first kind of assertion to no more than this. When it is asserted that the real must be good, because it is real, it is commonly also held that this is only because, in order to be real, it must be of a certain kind. The reasoning by which it is thought that a metaphysical enquiry can give an ethical conclusion is of the following form. From a consideration of what it is to be real, we can infer that what is real must have certain supersensible properties: but to have these properties is identical with being good—it is the very meaning of the word: it follows therefore that what has these properties is good: and from a consideration of what it is to be real, we can again infer what it is that has these properties. It is plain that, if such reasoning were correct, any answer which could be given to the question ‘What is good in itself?’ could be arrived at by a purely metaphysical discussion and by that alone. Just as, when Mill supposed that ‘to be good’ meant ‘to be desired,’ the question ‘What is good?’ could be and must be answered solely by an empirical investigation of the question what was desired; so here, if to be good means to have some supersensible property, the ethical question can and must be answered by a metaphysical enquiry into the question, What has this property? What, then, remains to be done in order to destroy the plausibility of Metaphysical Ethics, is to expose the chief errors which seem to have led metaphysicians to suppose that to be good means to possess some supersensible property.
72. We can attribute the stubborn belief that understanding a higher reality is essential for knowing what is inherently good, partly to a failure to realize that the subject of that judgment isn't anything real in itself, and partly to a failure to differentiate the cause of our perception of a truth from the reason why it is true. However, these two reasons only take us a short way in explaining why Metaphysics was thought to relate to Ethics. The first explanation I provided accounts only for the assumption that a thing’s reality is a necessary condition for its goodness. This assumption is often made; people generally assume that unless something can be shown to be part of the constitution of reality, it can't be good. Therefore, it's important to emphasize that this isn't true; Metaphysics isn't even necessary to provide part of the foundation of Ethics. Yet, when metaphysicians discuss basing Ethics on Metaphysics, they usually mean much more than that. They often mean that Metaphysics is the sole basis of Ethics—that it provides not just one necessary condition but all the conditions required to prove that certain things are good. At first glance, this view may appear in two different forms. It may be claimed that merely proving a thing to be supersensibly real is sufficient to prove it good: that what is truly[p. 123] real must, for that reason alone, also be truly good. More commonly, however, it's argued that the real must be good because it has certain characteristics. I believe we can reduce the first type of assertion to this: when it is claimed that the real must be good because it is real, it is usually also held that this is only true because, to be real, it must be of a certain kind. The reasoning that leads to the belief that a metaphysical inquiry can yield ethical conclusions typically goes like this: By considering what it means to be real, we can infer that what is real must have certain supersensible properties; having these properties is identical to being good—it’s the very definition of the term: therefore, whatever has these properties is good; and by once again considering what it means to be real, we can deduce what possesses these properties. It is clear that if this reasoning were correct, any answer to the question ‘What is good in itself?’ could be reached purely through metaphysical discussion alone. Just as Mill thought that ‘to be good’ meant ‘to be desired,’ the question ‘What is good?’ could only and must be answered through empirical investigation of what is desired; similarly, if to be good means possessing some supersensible property, the ethical question can and must be answered by a metaphysical inquiry into what has this property. Therefore, to undermine the credibility of Metaphysical Ethics, we must expose the main errors that seem to have led metaphysicians to believe that being good means possessing some supersensible property.
73. What, then, are the chief reasons which have made it seem plausible to maintain that to be good must mean to possess some supersensible property or to be related to some supersensible reality?
73. So, what are the main reasons that make it seem reasonable to believe that being good must mean having some higher property or being connected to some higher reality?
We may, first of all, notice one, which seems to have had some influence in causing the view that good must be defined by some such property, although it does not suggest any particular property as the one required. This reason lies in the supposition that the proposition ‘This is good’ or ‘This would be good, if it existed’ must, in a certain respect, be of the[p. 124] same type as other propositions. The fact is that there is one type of proposition so familiar to everyone, and therefore having such a strong hold upon the imagination, that philosophers have always supposed that all other types must be reducible to it. This type is that of the objects of experience—of all those truths which occupy our minds for the immensely greater part of our waking lives: truths such as that somebody is in the room, that I am writing or eating or talking. All these truths, however much they may differ, have this in common that in them both the grammatical subject and the grammatical predicate stand for something which exists. Immensely the commonest type of truth, then, is one which asserts a relation between two existing things. Ethical truths are immediately felt not to conform to this type, and the naturalistic fallacy arises from the attempt to make out that, in some roundabout way, they do conform to it. It is immediately obvious that when we see a thing to be good, its goodness is not a property which we can take up in our hands, or separate from it even by the most delicate scientific instruments, and transfer to something else. It is not, in fact, like most of the predicates which we ascribe to things, a part of the thing to which we ascribe it. But philosophers suppose that the reason why we cannot take goodness up and move it about, is not that it is a different kind of object from any which can be moved about, but only that it necessarily exists together with anything with which it does exist. They explain the type of ethical truths by supposing it identical with the type of scientific laws. And it is only when they have done this that the naturalistic philosophers proper—those who are empiricists—and those whom I have called ‘metaphysical’ part company. These two classes of philosophers do, indeed, differ with regard to the nature of scientific laws. The former class tend to suppose that when they say ‘This always accompanies that’ they mean only ‘This has accompanied, does now, and will accompany that in these particular instances’: they reduce the scientific law quite simply and directly to the familiar type of proposition which I have pointed out. But this does not satisfy the metaphysicians. They see that when you say ‘This would accompany that, if that existed,’ you don’t mean only that this[p. 125] and that have existed and will exist together so many times. But it is beyond even their powers to believe that what you do mean is merely what you say. They still think you must mean, somehow or other, that something does exist, since that is what you generally mean when you say anything. They are as unable as the empiricists to imagine that you can ever mean that 2 + 2 = 4. The empiricists say this means that so many couples of couples of things have in each case been four things; and hence that 2 and 2 would not make 4, unless precisely those things had existed. The metaphysicians feel that this is wrong; but they themselves have no better account of its meaning to give than either, with Leibniz, that God’s mind is in a certain state, or, with Kant, that your mind is in a certain state, or finally, with Mr Bradley, that something is in a certain state. Here, then, we have the root of the naturalistic fallacy. The metaphysicians have the merit of seeing that when you say ‘This would be good, if it existed,’ you can’t mean merely ‘This has existed and was desired,’ however many times that may have been the case. They will admit that some good things have not existed in this world, and even that some may not have been desired. But what you can mean, except that something exists, they really cannot see. Precisely the same error which leads them to suppose that there must exist a supersensible Reality, leads them to commit the naturalistic fallacy with regard to the meaning of ‘good.’ Every truth, they think, must mean somehow that something exists; and since, unlike the empiricists, they recognise some truths which do not mean that anything exists here and now, these they think must mean that something exists not here and now. On the same principle, since ‘good’ is a predicate which neither does nor can exist, they are bound to suppose either that ‘to be good’ means to be related to some other particular thing which can exist and does exist ‘in reality’; or else that it means merely ‘to belong to the real world’—that goodness is transcended or absorbed in reality.
We can first notice one factor that seems to have influenced the belief that good must be defined by some property, even though it doesn't specify any particular property as required. This reason comes from the assumption that the statement ‘This is good’ or ‘This would be good if it existed’ must, in some way, relate to other types of statements. The truth is that there is one type of statement so familiar to everyone, with such a strong hold on our imagination, that philosophers have always believed all other types must fit into it. This type involves objects of experience—truths about things that occupy our minds for most of our waking hours, like that someone is in the room, or that I am writing, eating, or talking. All these truths, no matter how different they are, share the fact that both the grammatical subject and the grammatical predicate refer to something that exists. The most common type of truth, then, asserts a relationship between two existing things. Ethical truths are felt not to conform to this type immediately, and the naturalistic fallacy stems from the effort to argue that, in some indirect way, they do conform to it. It’s clear that when we recognize something as good, its goodness is not a property we can physically handle, or separate even with the finest scientific tools, and move to something else. It's not like most of the attributes we assign to things; it’s not a part of the thing we apply it to. But philosophers think that the reason we can’t grasp goodness and move it around is not that it’s a different kind of object, but just that it necessarily exists together with whatever it does exist with. They explain the nature of ethical truths by assuming it’s the same as the nature of scientific laws. It’s only after they’ve done this that the naturalistic philosophers—those who are empiricists—and the ones I’ve called ‘metaphysical’ begin to differ. These two groups of philosophers indeed differ on the nature of scientific laws. The empiricists tend to think that when they say ‘This always goes with that,’ they mean only ‘This has gone with, is now going with, and will go with that in these specific instances’: they simplify the scientific law directly to the familiar type of statement I mentioned. But this doesn’t satisfy the metaphysicians. They understand that when you say ‘This would go with that, if that existed,’ you’re not merely saying that this[p. 125] and that have existed and will exist together many times. However, they can’t believe that what you mean is just what you say. They still think you must imply that something exists, since that’s what you generally mean when you make a statement. They struggle as much as the empiricists to accept that you could ever mean that 2 + 2 = 4. The empiricists argue that this means that so many pairs of pairs of things have, in each case, been four things; and therefore, that 2 and 2 wouldn’t equal 4 unless those specific things had existed. The metaphysicians feel this is incorrect; yet, they don’t have a clearer explanation for its meaning to offer than either, following Leibniz, that God’s mind is in a particular state, or, following Kant, that your mind is in a certain state, or finally, following Mr. Bradley, that something exists in a specific state. Here, we see the root of the naturalistic fallacy. The metaphysicians deserve credit for recognizing that when you say ‘This would be good if it existed,’ you can’t simply mean ‘This has existed and was desired,’ no matter how often that may have been true. They would agree that some good things haven’t existed in this world, and even that some may not have been desired. But they really can’t see what you could mean, except that something exists. The same mistake that leads them to believe in a supersensible Reality also causes them to commit the naturalistic fallacy regarding the meaning of ‘good.’ They think every truth must mean in some way that something exists; and since, unlike the empiricists, they acknowledge some truths that don’t mean anything exists here and now, they believe those must mean something exists not here and now. According to the same idea, since ‘good’ is a predicate that neither does nor can exist, they’re compelled to assume that ‘to be good’ means to relate to some other specific thing that can exist and does exist ‘in reality’; or that it means simply ‘to belong to the real world’—that goodness is surpassed or incorporated into reality.
74. That such a reduction of all propositions to the type of those which assert either that something exists or that something which exists has a certain attribute (which means, that both exist in a certain relation to one another), is erroneous,[p. 126] may easily be seen by reference to the particular class of ethical propositions. For whatever we may have proved to exist, and whatever two existents we may have proved to be necessarily connected with one another, it still remains a distinct and different question whether what thus exists is good; whether either or both of the two existents is so; and whether it is good that they should exist together. To assert the one is plainly and obviously not the same thing as to assert the other. We understand what we mean by asking: Is this, which exists, or necessarily exists, after all, good? and we perceive that we are asking a question which has not been answered. In face of this direct perception that the two questions are distinct, no proof that they must be identical can have the slightest value. That the proposition ‘This is good’ is thus distinct from every other proposition was proved in Chapter I.; and I may now illustrate this fact by pointing out how it is distinguished from two particular propositions with which it has commonly been identified. That so and so ought to be done is commonly called a moral law, and this phrase naturally suggests that this proposition is in some way analogous either to a natural law, or to a law in the legal sense, or to both. All three are, in fact, really analogous in one respect, and in one respect only: that they include a proposition which is universal. A moral law asserts ‘This is good in all cases’; a natural law asserts ‘This happens in all cases’; and a law, in the legal sense, ‘It is commanded that this be done, or be left undone, in all cases.’ But since it is very natural to suppose that the analogy extends further, and that the assertion ‘This is good in all cases’ is equivalent to the assertion ‘This happens in all cases’ or to the assertion ‘It is commanded that this be done in all cases,’ it may be useful briefly to point out that they are not equivalent.
74. It's clear that reducing all propositions to those that claim either something exists or that something existing has a certain attribute (which implies that both exist in relation to each other) is incorrect,[p. 126] especially when we look at ethical propositions. No matter what we have established to exist, and no matter which two existents we have shown to be necessarily connected, it remains a separate and different question whether what exists is good; whether either or both of the existents are; and whether it's good for them to exist together. To claim one is clearly not the same as claiming the other. We know what we mean when we ask: Is this thing that exists, or necessarily exists, actually good? and we realize we are asking a question that has not been answered. Given this clear understanding that the two questions are separate, no argument that they must be the same can hold any weight. The fact that the statement ‘This is good’ is unique from other propositions was shown in Chapter I.; and I can now illustrate this by comparing it to two specific propositions it is often confused with. The statement that something ought to be done is typically referred to as a moral law, and this term naturally implies that this proposition is somewhat similar to a natural law or a legal law, or both. All three are, in fact, similar in one respect and one respect only: they contain a proposition that is universal. A moral law asserts ‘This is good in all cases’; a natural law asserts ‘This happens in all cases’; and a legal law states ‘It is commanded that this be done, or not done, in all cases.’ However, it’s common to assume that the analogy goes further, and that the claim ‘This is good in all cases’ is the same as ‘This happens in all cases’ or ‘It is commanded that this be done in all cases,’ so it’s worth noting that they are not equivalent.
75. The fallacy of supposing moral law to be analogous to natural law in respect of asserting that some action is one which is always necessarily done is contained in one of the most famous doctrines of Kant. Kant identifies what ought to be with the law according to which a Free or Pure Will must act—with the only kind of action which is possible for it. And by this identification he does not mean merely to assert that the Free[p. 127] Will is also under the necessity of doing what it ought; he means that what it ought to do means nothing but its own law—the law according to which it must act. It differs from the human will just in that, what we ought to do, is what it necessarily does. It is ‘autonomous’; and by this is meant (among other things) that there is no separate standard by which it can be judged: that the question ‘Is the law by which this Will acts a good one?’ is, in its case, meaningless. It follows that what is necessarily willed by this Pure Will is good, not because that Will is good, nor for any other reason; but merely because it is what is necessarily willed by a Pure Will.
75. The mistake of thinking that moral law is like natural law in claiming that some actions are always necessarily performed is captured in one of Kant's most famous ideas. Kant equates what should be done with the law that a Free or Pure Will must follow—this is the only type of action possible for it. By this, he doesn't simply mean that the Free[p. 127] Will is also required to do what it should; instead, he suggests that what it should do only refers to its own law—the law that dictates how it must act. It differs from human will in that what we should do is what it must do. It is ‘autonomous’; and this implies (among other things) that there is no outside standard against which it can be assessed: the question ‘Is the law that this Will follows a good one?’ is meaningless in this context. Thus, what is necessarily willed by this Pure Will is good, not because that Will is good, nor for any other reason; but simply because it is what a Pure Will necessarily wills.
Kant’s assertion of the ‘Autonomy of the Practical Reason’ thus has the very opposite effect to that which he desired; it makes his Ethics ultimately and hopelessly ‘heteronomous.’ His Moral Law is ‘independent’ of Metaphysics only in the sense that according to him we can know it independently; he holds that we can only infer that there is Freedom, from the fact that the Moral Law is true. And so far as he keeps strictly to this view, he does avoid the error, into which most metaphysical writers fall, of allowing his opinions as to what is real to influence his judgments of what is good. But he fails to see that on his view the Moral Law is dependent upon Freedom in a far more important sense than that in which Freedom depends on the Moral Law. He admits that Freedom is the ratio essendi of the Moral Law, whereas the latter is only ratio cognoscendi of Freedom. And this means that, unless Reality be such as he says, no assertion that ‘This is good’ can possibly be true: it can indeed have no meaning. He has, therefore, furnished his opponents with a conclusive method of attacking the validity of the Moral Law. If they can only shew by some other means (which he denies to be possible but leaves theoretically open) that the nature of Reality is not such as he says, he cannot deny that they will have proved his ethical principle to be false. If that ‘This ought to be done’ means ‘This is willed by a Free Will,’ then, if it can be shewn that there is no Free Will which wills anything, it will follow that nothing ought to be done.
Kant's claim about the 'Autonomy of Practical Reason' ends up having the opposite effect of what he intended; it ultimately makes his Ethics hopelessly 'heteronomous.' His Moral Law is 'independent' of Metaphysics only in the sense that he believes we can know it without relying on it; he argues that we can only conclude that there is Freedom based on the truth of the Moral Law. As long as he sticks to this view, he avoids the common mistake of other metaphysical writers, who let their ideas about what is real influence their judgments about what is good. However, he fails to recognize that, under his view, the Moral Law depends on Freedom in a more significant way than Freedom depends on the Moral Law. He acknowledges that Freedom is the ratio essendi of the Moral Law, while the latter is merely the ratio cognoscendi of Freedom. This means that, unless Reality is as he describes, any claim that 'This is good' cannot be true; it would have no meaning. Thus, he has given his critics a solid way to challenge the validity of the Moral Law. If they can prove through other means (which he thinks is impossible but leaves theoretically open) that Reality is not as he claims, he cannot deny that they have shown his ethical principle to be false. If 'This ought to be done' means 'This is willed by a Free Will,' then, if it can be demonstrated that there is no Free Will that wills anything, it will follow that nothing ought to be done.
76. And Kant also commits the fallacy of supposing that[p. 128] ‘This ought to be’ means ‘This is commanded.’ He conceives the Moral Law to be an Imperative. And this is a very common mistake. ‘This ought to be,’ it is assumed, must mean ‘This is commanded’; nothing, therefore, would be good unless it were commanded; and since commands in this world are liable to be erroneous, what ought to be in its ultimate sense means ‘what is commanded by some real supersensible authority.’ With regard to this authority it is, then, no longer possible to ask ‘Is it righteous?’ Its commands cannot fail to be right, because to be right means to be what it commands. Here, therefore, law, in the moral sense, is supposed analogous to law, in the legal sense, rather than, as in the last instance, to law in the natural sense. It is supposed that moral obligation is analogous to legal obligation, with this difference only that whereas the source of legal obligation is earthly, that of moral obligation is heavenly. Yet it is obvious that if by a source of obligation is meant only a power which binds you or compels you to do a thing, it is not because it does do this that you ought to obey it. It is only if it be itself so good, that it commands and enforces only what is good, that it can be a source of moral obligation. And in that case what it commands and enforces would be good, whether commanded and enforced or not. Just that which makes an obligation legal, namely the fact that it is commanded by a certain kind of authority, is entirely irrelevant to a moral obligation. However an authority be defined, its commands will be morally binding only if they are—morally binding; only if they tell us what ought to be or what is a means to that which ought to be.
76. And Kant also makes the mistake of thinking that[p. 128] ‘This ought to be’ means ‘This is commanded.’ He views the Moral Law as an Imperative. This is a very common error. It’s assumed that ‘This ought to be’ must mean ‘This is commanded’; thus, nothing would be considered good unless it was commanded. Since commands in this world can be wrong, what ought to be ultimately means ‘what is commanded by some real higher authority.’ When it comes to this authority, it’s no longer possible to ask ‘Is it right?’ Its commands can’t help but be right, because being right means being what it commands. Here, therefore, law in the moral sense is thought to be similar to law in the legal sense, instead of, as it should be, similar to law in the natural sense. It is assumed that moral obligation is similar to legal obligation, with the only difference being that the source of legal obligation is earthly while that of moral obligation is heavenly. However, it’s clear that if by a source of obligation we mean only a power that binds or compels you to do something, it’s not because it does this that you ought to obey it. You should only obey it if it is itself good enough to command and enforce only what is good; in that case, what it commands and enforces would be good, whether it’s commanded and enforced or not. The very thing that makes an obligation legal, namely the fact that it is commanded by a specific kind of authority, is completely irrelevant to a moral obligation. No matter how an authority is defined, its commands will be morally binding only if they are—morally binding; only if they tell us what ought to be or what is a means to what ought to be.
77. In this last error, in the supposition that when I say ‘You ought to do this’ I must mean ‘You are commanded to do this,’ we have one of the reasons which has led to the supposition that the particular supersensible property by reference to which good must be defined is Will. And that ethical conclusions may be obtained by enquiring into the nature of a fundamentally real Will seems to be by far the commonest assumption of Metaphysical Ethics at the present day. But this assumption seems to owe its plausibility, not so much to the supposition that ‘ought’ expresses a ‘command,’ as to a far more funda[p. 129]mental error. This error consists in supposing that to ascribe certain predicates to a thing is the same thing as to say that that thing is the object of a certain kind of psychical state. It is supposed that to say that a thing is real or true is the same thing as to say that it is known in a certain way; and that the difference between the assertion that it is good and the assertion that it is real—between an ethical, therefore, and a metaphysical proposition—consists in the fact that whereas the latter asserts its relation to Cognition the former asserts its relation to Will.
77. In this final mistake, the assumption that when I say ‘You ought to do this’ I mean ‘You are commanded to do this’ is one of the reasons that has led to the belief that the specific non-physical quality defining goodness is Will. Today, it seems like the most common assumption in Metaphysical Ethics is that ethical conclusions can be drawn by examining the nature of a fundamentally real Will. However, this belief seems to be more convincing not because ‘ought’ indicates a ‘command,’ but due to a more basic error. This error consists of thinking that assigning certain qualities to something is the same as stating that this thing is the subject of a specific type of mental state. It is assumed that saying something is real or true is the same as saying it is understood in a particular way; and the difference between the claim that it is good and the claim that it is real—between an ethical and a metaphysical statement—lies in the fact that while the latter asserts its connection to Cognition, the former asserts its connection to Will.
Now that this is an error has been already shewn in Chapter I. That the assertion ‘This is good’ is not identical with the assertion ‘This is willed,’ either by a supersensible will, or otherwise, nor with any other proposition, has been proved; nor can I add anything to that proof. But in face of this proof it may be anticipated that two lines of defence may be taken up. (1) It may be maintained that, nevertheless, they really are identical, and facts may be pointed out which seem to prove that identity. Or else (2) it may be said that an absolute identity is not maintained: that it is only meant to assert that there is some special connection between will and goodness, such as makes an enquiry into the real nature of the former an essential step in the proof of ethical conclusions. In order to meet these two possible objections, I propose first to shew what possible connections there are or may be between goodness and will; and that none of these can justify us in asserting that ‘This is good’ is identical with ‘This is willed.’ On the other hand it will appear that some of them may be easily confused with this assertion of identity; and that therefore the confusion is likely to have been made. This part of my argument will, therefore, already go some way towards meeting the second objection. But what must be conclusive against this is to shew that any possible connection between will and goodness except the absolute identity in question, would not be sufficient to give an enquiry into Will the smallest relevance to the proof of any ethical conclusion.
Now that an error has already been shown in Chapter I, it has been proven that the statement ‘This is good’ is not the same as the statement ‘This is willed,’ whether by a supra-sensible will or otherwise, and it’s also not the same as any other assertion; I can't add anything to that proof. In light of this proof, it's reasonable to expect two types of defenses. (1) One might argue that they really are identical, pointing out facts that seem to support that identity. Or (2) one could claim that an absolute identity is not being argued: that it only suggests there’s a specific connection between will and goodness, which makes exploring the true nature of the former essential for proving ethical conclusions. To address these two possible objections, I will first demonstrate what possible connections there are or could be between goodness and will; and that none of these can justify the assertion that ‘This is good’ is identical to ‘This is willed.’ On the flip side, it will be clear that some of these connections may easily be mistaken for this claim of identity; thus, it’s likely that confusion could have occurred. This part of my argument will, therefore, already address the second objection to some extent. However, what must decisively counter this is demonstrating that any potential connection between will and goodness except for the absolute identity in question would not make an inquiry into Will remotely relevant to proving any ethical conclusion.
78. It has been customary, since Kant’s time, to assert that Cognition, Volition, and Feeling are three fundamentally[p. 130] distinct attitudes of the mind towards reality. They are three distinct ways of experiencing, and each of them informs us of a distinct aspect under which reality may be considered. The ‘Epistemological’ method of approaching Metaphysics rests on the assumption that by considering what is ‘implied in’ Cognition—what is its ‘ideal’—we may discover what properties the world must have, if it is to be true. And similarly it is held that by considering what is ‘implied in’ the fact of Willing or Feeling—what is the ‘ideal’ which they presuppose—we may discover what properties the world must have, if it is to be good or beautiful. The orthodox Idealistic Epistemologist differs from the Sensationalist or Empiricist in holding that what we directly cognise is neither all true nor yet the whole truth: in order to reject the false and to discover further truths we must, he says, not take cognition merely as it presents itself, but discover what is implied in it. And similarly the orthodox Metaphysical Ethicist differs from the mere Naturalist, in holding that not everything which we actually will is good, nor, if good, completely good: what is really good is that which is implied in the essential nature of will. Others again think that Feeling, and not Will, is the fundamental datum for Ethics. But, in either case, it is agreed that Ethics has some relation to Will or Feeling which it has not to Cognition, and which other objects of study have to Cognition. Will or Feeling, on the one hand, and Cognition, on the other, are regarded as in some sense coordinate sources of philosophical knowledge—the one of Practical, the other of Theoretical philosophy.
78. Since Kant’s time, it has been common to argue that Cognition, Volition, and Feeling are three fundamentally distinct mindsets towards reality. They represent three different ways of experiencing the world, each revealing a unique aspect of how we can perceive reality. The ‘Epistemological’ approach to Metaphysics is based on the idea that by examining what is ‘implied in’ Cognition—what its ‘ideal’ is—we can uncover what properties the world must have to be considered true. Similarly, it is believed that by looking at what is ‘implied in’ the act of Willing or Feeling—what ‘ideal’ they assume—we can identify what characteristics the world needs to be regarded as good or beautiful. The conventional Idealistic Epistemologist differs from the Sensationalist or Empiricist by asserting that what we directly perceive is neither entirely true nor the complete truth: to discard false information and discover further truths, we must not simply accept cognition as it appears but seek to identify what is implied within it. Likewise, the traditional Metaphysical Ethicist differs from the pure Naturalist by claiming that not everything we genuinely will is good, nor is it completely good if it is: what is truly good is determined by the essential nature of will. Some argue that Feeling, rather than Will, forms the basic datum for Ethics. However, in both perspectives, there is a consensus that Ethics has a connection to Will or Feeling that it does not have to Cognition, which is distinct from the connections other fields of study have to Cognition. Will or Feeling, on one hand, and Cognition, on the other, are considered as in some way parallel sources of philosophical knowledge—one related to Practical philosophy, the other to Theoretical philosophy.
What, that is true, can possibly be meant by this view?
What could this perspective possibly mean?
79. First of all, it may be meant that, just as, by reflection on our perceptual and sensory experience, we become aware of the distinction between truth and falsehood, so it is by reflection on our experiences of feeling and willing that we become aware of ethical distinctions. We should not know what was meant by thinking one thing better than another unless the attitude of our will or feeling towards one thing was different from its attitude towards another. All this may be admitted. But so far we have only the psychological fact that it is only because we will or feel things in a certain way, that we ever come to[p. 131] think them good; just as it is only because we have certain perceptual experiences, that we ever come to think things true. Here, then, is a special connection between willing and goodness; but it is only a causal connection—that willing is a necessary condition for the cognition of goodness.
79. First of all, it could be suggested that, similar to how we recognize the difference between truth and falsehood through reflecting on our sensory experiences, we become aware of ethical distinctions by reflecting on our feelings and desires. We wouldn’t understand why we think one thing is better than another unless our feelings or desires toward one thing were different from those toward another. This can be accepted. However, up to this point, we only have the psychological fact that it is only because we feel or desire things in a certain way that we come to[p. 131] consider them good; just as it is only because we have specific sensory experiences that we determine things to be true. Therefore, there is a unique link between desire and goodness; however, it is only a causal connection—desire is a necessary condition for understanding goodness.
But it may be said further that willing and feeling are not only the origin of cognitions of goodness; but that to will a thing, or to have a certain feeling towards a thing, is the same thing as to think it good. And it may be admitted that even this is generally true in a sense. It does seem to be true that we hardly ever think a thing good, and never very decidedly, without at the same time having a special attitude of feeling or will towards it; though it is certainly not the case that this is true universally. And the converse may possibly be true universally: it may be the case that a perception of goodness is included in the complex facts which we mean by willing and by having certain kinds of feeling. Let us admit then, that to think a thing good and to will it are the same thing in this sense, that, wherever the latter occurs, the former also occurs as a part of it; and even that they are generally the same thing in the converse sense, that when the former occurs it is generally a part of the latter.
But it can also be said that wanting and feeling not only serve as the source of our understanding of goodness, but that wanting something or having a particular feeling toward it is the same thing as thinking it’s good. This seems to be generally true to some extent. It appears that we rarely consider something to be good, and never strongly, without also having a specific attitude of feeling or desire toward it; although it’s definitely not the case that this is true in every situation. The opposite might actually hold true in all cases: it could be that the perception of goodness is part of the complex realities that we refer to when we talk about wanting and experiencing certain feelings. So let’s agree that thinking something is good and wanting it are the same thing in the sense that whenever the latter occurs, the former is also a part of it; and even that they are generally the same thing in the reverse sense, meaning that when the former takes place, it is usually a part of the latter.
80. These facts may seem to give countenance to the general assertion that to think a thing good is to prefer it or approve it, in the sense in which preference and approval denote certain kinds of will or feeling. It seems to be always true that when we thus prefer or approve, there is included in that fact the fact that we think good; and it is certainly true, in an immense majority of instances, that when we think good, we also prefer or approve. It is natural enough, then, to say that to think good is to prefer. And what more natural than to add: When I say a thing is good, I mean that I prefer it? And yet this natural addition involves a gross confusion. Even if it be true that to think good is the same thing as to prefer (which, as we have seen, is never true in the sense that they are absolutely identical; and not always true, even in the sense that they occur together), yet it is not true that what you think, when you think a thing good, is that you prefer it.[p. 132] Even if your thinking the thing good is the same thing as your preference of it, yet the goodness of the thing—that of which you think—is, for that very reason, obviously not the same thing as your preference of it. Whether you have a certain thought or not is one question; and whether what you think is true is quite a different one, upon which the answer to the first has not the least bearing. The fact that you prefer a thing does not tend to shew that the thing is good; even if it does shew that you think it so.
80. These facts might seem to support the general claim that thinking something is good means you prefer it or approve of it, in the way preference and approval suggest certain kinds of will or feelings. It seems consistently true that when we prefer or approve something, it includes the fact that we think it’s good; and it’s certainly true, in the vast majority of cases, that if we think something is good, we also prefer or approve of it. So, it’s quite natural to say that thinking something is good means you prefer it. And what could be more natural than to add: When I say something is good, I mean that I prefer it? Yet, this seemingly obvious addition leads to a serious misunderstanding. Even if it’s true that thinking something is good is the same as preferring it (which, as we’ve seen, is never true in the sense of being absolutely identical; and not always true, even in the sense that they happen together), it still isn’t true that what you think when you consider something good is that you prefer it.[p. 132] Even if thinking something is good is the same as your preference for it, the goodness of the thing—that which you think about—is, for that very reason, clearly not the same as your preference for it. Whether you have a certain thought is one question; and whether what you think is true is quite another, with the answer to the first having no impact on the second. The fact that you prefer something doesn’t necessarily prove that the thing is good; even if it does show that you think it is.
It seems to be owing to this confusion, that the question ‘What is good?’ is thought to be identical with the question ‘What is preferred?’ It is said, with sufficient truth, that you would never know a thing was good unless you preferred it, just as you would never know a thing existed unless you perceived it. But it is added, and this is false, that you would never know a thing was good unless you knew that you preferred it, or that it existed unless you knew that you perceived it. And it is finally added, and this is utterly false, that you cannot distinguish the fact that a thing is good from the fact that you prefer it, or the fact that it exists from the fact that you perceive it. It is often pointed out that I cannot at any given moment distinguish what is true from what I think so: and this is true. But though I cannot distinguish what is true from what I think so, I always can distinguish what I mean by saying that it is true from what I mean by saying that I think so. For I understand the meaning of the supposition that what I think true may nevertheless be false. When, therefore, I assert that it is true I mean to assert something different from the fact that I think so. What I think, namely that something is true, is always quite distinct from the fact that I think it. The assertion that it is true does not even include the assertion that I think it so; although, of course, whenever I do think a thing true, it is, as a matter of fact, also true that I do think it. This tautologous proposition that for a thing to be thought true it is necessary that it should be thought, is, however, commonly identified with the proposition that for a thing to be true it is necessary that it should be thought. A very little reflection should suffice to convince[p. 133] anyone that this identification is erroneous; and a very little more will shew that, if so, we must mean by ‘true’ something which includes no reference to thinking or to any other psychical fact. It may be difficult to discover precisely what we mean—to hold the object in question before us, so as to compare it with other objects: but that we do mean something distinct and unique can no longer be matter of doubt. That ‘to be true’ means to be thought in a certain way is, therefore, certainly false. Yet this assertion plays the most essential part in Kant’s ‘Copernican revolution’ of philosophy, and renders worthless the whole mass of modern literature, to which that revolution has given rise, and which is called Epistemology. Kant held that what was unified in a certain manner by the synthetic activity of thought was ipso facto true: that this was the very meaning of the word. Whereas it is plain that the only connection which can possibly hold between being true and being thought in a certain way, is that the latter should be a criterion or test of the former. In order, however, to establish that it is so, it would be necessary to establish by the methods of induction that what was true was always thought in a certain way. Modern Epistemology dispenses with this long and difficult investigation at the cost of the self-contradictory assumption that ‘truth’ and the criterion of truth are one and the same thing.
It seems that this confusion is why the question “What is good?” is seen as the same as “What is preferred?” It’s often said, quite accurately, that you would never know something was good unless you preferred it, just like you wouldn’t know a thing existed unless you perceived it. However, it’s falsely claimed that you would never know something was good unless you knew that you preferred it, or that it existed unless you knew that you perceived it. And it’s even more falsely claimed that you cannot separate the idea of something being good from the idea of preferring it, or the idea of something existing from the idea of perceiving it. It’s frequently pointed out that I cannot distinguish what is true from what I think is true, and that’s correct. But while I can’t separate what is true from what I think is true, I can always differentiate what I mean by saying that it is true from what I mean by saying that I think so. Because I understand that what I think to be true could actually be false. Therefore, when I say it is true, I mean to assert something different from the fact that I think so. What I think, specifically that something is true, is always distinct from the fact that I think it. Saying that it is true doesn’t even include saying that I think it is true; although, of course, whenever I do think something is true, it is also true that I think it. This redundant statement that for something to be thought true it must be thought is often confused with the statement that for something to be true it has to be thought. A bit of reflection should be enough to convince[p. 133] anyone that this confusion is wrong; and a bit more will show that if that’s the case, we must mean by ‘true’ something that doesn’t involve thinking or any other mental fact. It might be tough to pin down exactly what we mean—to hold the object in question in front of us so we can compare it with other objects: but there’s no doubt that we do mean something distinct and unique. The idea that ‘to be true’ means to be thought in a certain way is, therefore, definitely false. Yet this idea plays a crucial role in Kant’s “Copernican revolution” in philosophy, rendering the entire body of modern literature that has emerged from that revolution, called Epistemology, worthless. Kant believed that what was unified in a certain way by the synthetic activity of thought was ipso facto true: that this was the very meaning of the term. However, it’s clear that the only connection between being true and being thought in a certain way is that the latter serves as a criterion or test of the former. To prove that it is so, it would be necessary to demonstrate through induction that what was true was always thought in a certain way. Modern Epistemology sidesteps this long and challenging investigation by relying on the self-contradictory assumption that ‘truth’ and the criterion for truth are one and the same thing.
81. It is, then, a very natural, though an utterly false supposition that for a thing to be true is the same thing as for it to be perceived or thought of in a certain way. And since, for the reasons given above, the fact of preference seems roughly to stand in the same relation to thinking things good, in which the fact of perception stands to thinking that they are true or exist, it is very natural that for a thing to be good should be supposed identical with its being preferred in a certain way. But once this coordination of Volition and Cognition has been accepted, it is again very natural that every fact which seems to support the conclusion that being true is identical with being cognised should confirm the corresponding conclusion that being good is identical with being willed. It will, therefore, be in place to point out another confusion, which[p. 134] seems to have had great influence in causing acceptance of the view that to be true is the same thing as to be cognised.
81. It's a common but completely incorrect assumption that for something to be true is the same as it being perceived or thought of in a certain way. And since, for the reasons mentioned earlier, the idea of preference seems to relate to thinking something is good in a similar way that perception relates to thinking something is true or exists, it’s easy to assume that for something to be good is identical to it being preferred in a certain manner. But once we accept this connection between will and thought, it’s also natural that any evidence supporting the idea that being true is the same as being recognized would lend support to the idea that being good is the same as being desired. Therefore, it’s important to highlight another misunderstanding that[p. 134] seems to have significantly contributed to the belief that being true is the same as being recognized.
This confusion is due to a failure to observe that when we say we have a sensation or perception or that we know a thing, we mean to assert not only that our mind is cognitive, but also that that which it cognises is true. It is not observed that the usage of these words is such that, if a thing be untrue, that fact alone is sufficient to justify us in saying that the person who says he perceives or knows it, does not perceive or know it, without our either enquiring whether, or assuming that, his state of mind differs in any respect from what it would have been had he perceived or known. By this denial we do not accuse him of an error in introspection, even if there was such an error: we do not deny that he was aware of a certain object, nor even that his state of mind was exactly such as he took it to be: we merely deny that the object, of which he was aware, had a certain property. It is, however, commonly supposed that when we assert a thing to be perceived or known, we are asserting one fact only; and since of the two facts which we really assert, the existence of a psychical state is by far the easier to distinguish, it is supposed that this is the only one which we do assert. Thus perception and sensation have come to be regarded as if they denoted certain states of mind and nothing more; a mistake which was the easier to make since the commonest state of mind, to which we give a name which does not imply that its object is true, namely imagination, may, with some plausibility, be supposed to differ from sensation and perception not only in the property possessed by its object, but also in its character as a state of mind. It has thus come to be supposed that the only difference between perception and imagination, by which they can be defined, must be a merely psychical difference: and, if this were the case, it would follow at once that to be true was identical with being cognised in a certain way; since the assertion that a thing is perceived does certainly include the assertion that it is true, and if, nevertheless, that it is perceived means only that the mind has a certain attitude towards it, then its truth must be identical with the fact that it is regarded in this way. We may, then, attribute[p. 135] the view that to be true means to be cognised in a certain way partly to the failure to perceive that certain words, which are commonly supposed to stand for nothing more than a certain kind of cognitive state, do, in fact, also include a reference to the truth of the object of such states.
This confusion comes from not noticing that when we say we have a sensation or perception or that we know something, we’re not just saying our mind is aware; we’re also asserting that what we are aware of is true. It’s overlooked that the way we use these words means that if something is untrue, that fact alone is enough to justify saying the person who claims to perceive or know it doesn’t actually perceive or know it. This doesn’t require us to investigate whether their state of mind differs in any way from what it would have been had they truly perceived or known it. By denying this, we’re not accusing them of an error in self-reflection, even if such an error exists: we’re not disputing that they were aware of a certain object, or that their state of mind was precisely as they believed it to be; we’re simply denying that the object they were aware of had a particular property. However, it’s commonly thought that when we say something is perceived or known, we’re asserting just one fact; and since the existence of a mental state is much easier to recognize, it’s assumed that this is the only assertion being made. As a result, perception and sensation have been considered as if they only represent specific mental states and nothing more; a misunderstanding reinforced because the most common mental state we refer to, which doesn’t imply its object is true—namely imagination—feels like it differs from sensation and perception not just in the property of its object but also in its nature as a mental state. Hence, it has come to be believed that the only way to define the difference between perception and imagination is through a purely psychological distinction: if that were true, it would mean being true is the same as being recognized in a particular way; since saying something is perceived does indeed include the claim that it is true, and if “being perceived” only means the mind has a certain attitude towards it, then its truth must align with the fact that it’s viewed this way. Therefore, we can attribute[p. 135] the idea that being true means being recognized in a certain way to the failure to recognize that certain words, which are generally thought to refer solely to a particular type of mental state, actually also point to the truth of the object of those states.
82. I will now sum up my account of the apparent connections between will and ethical propositions, which seem to support the vague conviction that ‘This is good’ is somehow identical with ‘This is willed in a certain way.’ (1) It may be maintained, with sufficient show of truth, that it is only because certain things were originally willed, that we ever came to have ethical convictions at all. And it has been too commonly assumed that to shew what was the cause of a thing is the same thing as to shew what the thing itself is. It is, however, hardly necessary to point out that this is not the case. (2) It may be further maintained, with some plausibility, that to think a thing good and to will it in a certain way are now as a matter of fact identical. We must, however, distinguish certain possible meanings of this assertion. It may be admitted that when we think a thing good, we generally have a special attitude of will or feeling towards it; and that, perhaps, when we will it in a certain way, we do always think it good. But the very fact that we can thus distinguish the question whether, though the one is always accompanied by the other, yet this other may not always be accompanied by the first, shews that the two things are not, in the strict sense, identical. The fact is that, whatever we mean by will, or by any form of will, the fact we mean by it certainly always includes something else beside the thinking a thing good: and hence that, when willing and thinking good are asserted to be identical, the most that can be meant is that this other element in will always both accompanies and is accompanied by the thinking good; and this, as has been said, is of very doubtful truth. Even, however, if it were strictly true, the fact that the two things can be distinguished is fatal to the assumed coordination between will and cognition, in one of the senses in which that assumption is commonly made. For it is only in respect of the other element in will, that volition differs from cognition; whereas it is only[p. 136] in respect of the fact that volition, or some form of volition, includes a cognition of goodness, that will can have the same relation to ethical, which cognition has to metaphysical, propositions. Accordingly the fact of volition, as a whole, that is, if we include in it the element which makes it volition and distinguishes it from cognition, has not the same relation to ethical propositions which cognition has to those which are metaphysical. Volition and cognition are not coordinate ways of experiencing, since it is only in so far as volition denotes a complex fact, which includes in it the one identical simple fact, which is meant by cognition, that volition is a way of experiencing at all.
82. I will now summarize my discussion about the connections between will and ethical statements, which seem to support the vague idea that ‘This is good’ is somehow the same as ‘This is willed in a certain way.’ (1) It can be argued, with enough justification, that it’s only because certain things were originally willed that we even have ethical beliefs. It has also been commonly assumed that showing the cause of something is the same as showing what that thing actually is. However, it’s hardly necessary to point out that this isn’t true. (2) It can be further argued, with some reason, that thinking something is good and willing it in a certain way are now actually the same. However, we need to distinguish different possible meanings of this claim. We can agree that when we think something is good, we generally have a specific attitude of will or feeling towards it; and that perhaps, when we will it in a certain way, we always think it’s good. But the very fact that we can distinguish whether the first is always accompanied by the second shows that the two are not strictly the same. The truth is that, whatever we mean by will, or any form of will, it certainly always involves something else besides just thinking something is good: and so when willing and thinking good are said to be the same, the most that can be meant is that this other element in will always accompanies and is accompanied by thinking good; and this, as mentioned, is very questionable. Even if it were completely true, the fact that we can distinguish the two is fatal to the assumed coordination between will and cognition in one of the ways that assumption is often made. Because it’s only concerning the other element in will that volition differs from cognition; while it’s only[p. 136] in regard to the fact that volition, or some form of volition, includes a cognition of goodness that will can relate to ethical propositions in the same way that cognition relates to metaphysical propositions. Therefore, the fact of volition, as a whole, meaning if we include the element that makes it volition and distinguishes it from cognition, does not relate to ethical propositions in the same way that cognition relates to metaphysical ones. Volition and cognition are not equivalent ways of experiencing, since volition only qualifies as a way of experiencing to the extent that it signifies a complex fact that includes the single simple fact represented by cognition.
But, (3) if we allow the terms ‘volition’ or ‘will’ to stand for ‘thinking good,’ although they certainly do not commonly stand for this, there still remains the question: What connection would this fact establish between volition and Ethics? Could the enquiry into what was willed be identical with the ethical enquiry into what was good? It is plain enough that they could not be identical; though it is also plain why they should be thought so. The question ‘What is good?’ is confused with the question ‘What is thought good?’ and the question ‘What is true?’ with the question ‘What is thought true?’ for two main reasons. (1) One of these is the general difficulty that is found in distinguishing what is cognised from the cognition of it. It is observed that I certainly cannot cognise anything that is true without cognising it. Since, therefore, whenever I know a thing that is true, the thing is certainly cognised, it is assumed that for a thing to be true at all is the same thing as for it to be cognised. And (2) it is not observed that certain words, which are supposed to denote only peculiar species of cognition, do as a matter of fact also denote that the object cognised is true. Thus if ‘perception’ be taken to denote only a certain kind of mental fact, then, since the object of it is always true, it becomes easy to suppose that to be true means only to be object to a mental state of that kind. And similarly it is easy to suppose that to be truly good differs from being falsely thought so, solely in respect of the fact that to be the former is to be the object of a volition differing from that[p. 137] of which an apparent good is the object, in the same way in which a perception (on this supposition) differs from an illusion.
But, (3) if we let the terms 'volition' or 'will' mean 'thinking good,' even though they don't actually mean this commonly, there still remains the question: What connection does this create between volition and Ethics? Could the investigation into what was willed be the same as the ethical investigation into what was good? It's clear that they can't be the same; however, it's also clear why they might be perceived that way. The question 'What is good?' gets mixed up with the question 'What is thought good?' and the question 'What is true?' with the question 'What is thought true?' for two main reasons. (1) One reason is the general difficulty in distinguishing what is recognized from the recognition of it. It's observed that I certainly can't recognize anything that is true without recognizing it. Since, therefore, whenever I know something that is true, it is certainly recognized, it's assumed that for something to be true at all is the same as for it to be recognized. And (2) it's not noted that certain words, which are thought to denote only specific types of recognition, actually also suggest that the recognized object is true. So if 'perception' is taken to mean only a certain kind of mental state, then, since the object of it is always true, it becomes easy to think that to be true means only to be an object of that kind of mental state. Similarly, it’s easy to think that being truly good differs from being falsely thought so, only in the fact that to be the former means to be the object of a volition that differs from that[p. 137] of which an apparent good is the object, just as a perception (assuming this) differs from an illusion.
83. Being good, then, is not identical with being willed or felt in any kind of way, any more than being true is identical with being thought in any kind of way. But let us suppose this to be admitted: Is it still possible that an enquiry into the nature of will or feeling should be a necessary step to the proof of ethical conclusions? If being good and being willed are not identical, then the most that can be maintained with regard to the connection of goodness with will is that what is good is always also willed in a certain way, and that what is willed in a certain way is always also good. And it may be said that this is all that is meant by those metaphysical writers who profess to base Ethics upon the Metaphysics of Will. What would follow from this supposition?
83. Being good isn’t the same as being desired or felt in any way, just as being true isn’t the same as being thought of in any way. But let’s assume this is accepted: Is it still possible that exploring the nature of will or feeling is a necessary step in proving ethical conclusions? If being good and being desired are not the same, then the most we can say about the connection between goodness and will is that what is good is always also desired in a certain way, and that what is desired in a certain way is always also good. It might be suggested that this is what those metaphysical writers mean when they claim to base Ethics on the Metaphysics of Will. What would follow from this assumption?
It is plain that if what is willed in a certain way were always also good, then the fact that a thing was so willed would be a criterion of its goodness. But in order to establish that will is a criterion of goodness, we must be able to shew first and separately that in a great number of the instances in which we find a certain kind of will we also find that the objects of that will are good. We might, then, perhaps, be entitled to infer that in a few instances, where it was not obvious whether a thing was good or not but was obvious that it was willed in the way required, the thing was really good, since it had the property which in all other instances we had found to be accompanied by goodness. A reference to will might thus, just conceivably, become of use towards the end of our ethical investigations, when we had already been able to shew, independently, of a vast number of different objects that they were really good and in what degree they were so. And against even this conceivable utility it may be urged (1) That it is impossible to see why it should not be as easy (and it would certainly be the more secure way) to prove that the thing in question was good, by the same methods which we had used in proving that other things were good, as by reference to our criterion; and (2) That, if we set ourselves seriously to find out what things are good, we shall see reason to think (as[p. 138] will appear in Chapter VI.) that they have no other property, both common and peculiar to them, beside their goodness—that, in fact, there is no criterion of goodness.
It's clear that if what is willed in a certain way were always also good, then the fact that something is willed that way would be a criterion for its goodness. However, to prove that will is a measure of goodness, we need to first demonstrate that in many instances where we see a specific kind of will, the objects of that will are also good. We might then be justified in concluding that in a few cases, where it wasn't obvious whether something was good or not but it was clear that it was willed as needed, that thing was actually good, since it shared a property we found in many other instances to be associated with goodness. A reference to will could potentially become useful toward the end of our ethical studies, having already shown independently that a wide range of different objects were genuinely good and to what extent. Against this possible usefulness, however, one might argue (1) that there’s no reason to believe it would be any easier (and it would certainly be a more secure approach) to prove that the thing in question is good by employing the same methods we used to establish the goodness of other things instead of referencing our criterion; and (2) that if we genuinely try to determine which things are good, we will understand (as[p. 138] will be discussed in Chapter VI.) that they possess no other property, both common and unique to them, apart from their goodness—that, in fact, there is no criterion for goodness.
84. But to consider whether any form of will is or is not a criterion of goodness is quite unnecessary for our purpose here; since none of those writers who profess to base their Ethics on an investigation of will have ever recognised the need of proving directly and independently that all the things which are willed in a certain way are good. They make no attempt to shew that will is a criterion of goodness; and no stronger evidence could be given that they do not recognise that this, at most, is all it can be. As has been just pointed out, if we are to maintain that whatever is willed in a certain way is also good, we must in the first place be able to shew that certain things have one property ‘goodness,’ and that the same things also have the other property that they are willed in a certain way. And secondly we must be able to shew this in a very large number of instances, if we are to be entitled to claim any assent for the proposition that these two properties always accompany one another: even when this was shewn it would still be doubtful whether the inference from ‘generally’ to ‘always’ would be valid, and almost certain that this doubtful principle would be useless. But the very question which it is the business of Ethics to answer is this question what things are good; and, so long as Hedonism retains its present popularity, it must be admitted that it is a question upon which there is scarcely any agreement and which therefore requires the most careful examination. The greatest and most difficult part of the business of Ethics would therefore require to have been already accomplished before we could be entitled to claim that anything was a criterion of goodness. If, on the other hand, to be willed in a certain way was identical with being good, then indeed we should be entitled to start our ethical investigations by enquiring what was willed in the way required. That this is the way in which metaphysical writers start their investigations seems to shew conclusively that they are influenced by the idea that ‘goodness’ is identical with ‘being willed.’ They do not recognise that the question ‘What is good?’ is[p. 139] a different one from the question ‘What is willed in a certain way?’ Thus we find Green explicitly stating that ‘the common characteristic of the good is that it satisfies some desire[22].’ If we are to take this statement strictly, it obviously asserts that good things have no characteristic in common, except that they satisfy some desire—not even, therefore, that they are good. And this can only be the case, if being good is identical with satisfying desire: if ‘good’ is merely another name for ‘desire-satisfying.’ There could be no plainer instance of the naturalistic fallacy. And we cannot take the statement as a mere verbal slip, which does not affect the validity of Green’s main argument. For he nowhere either gives or pretends to give any reason for believing anything to be good in any sense, except that it is what would satisfy a particular kind of desire—the kind of desire which he tries to shew to be that of a moral agent. An unhappy alternative is before us. Such reasoning would give valid reasons for his conclusions, if, and only if, being good and being desired in a particular way were identical: and in this case, as we have seen in Chapter I., his conclusions would not be ethical. On the other hand, if the two are not identical, his conclusions may be ethical and may even be right, but he has not given us a single reason for believing them. The thing which a scientific Ethics is required to shew, namely that certain things are really good, he has assumed to begin with, in assuming that things which are willed in a certain way are always good. We may, therefore, have as much respect for Green’s conclusions as for those of any other man who details to us his ethical convictions: but that any of his arguments are such as to give us any reason for holding that Green’s convictions are more likely to be true than those of any other man, must be clearly denied. The Prolegomena to Ethics is quite as far as Mr Spencer’s Data of Ethics, from making the smallest contribution to the solution of ethical problems.
84. But considering whether any form of will is or is not a measure of goodness is really unnecessary for our purposes here; since none of the writers who claim to base their Ethics on an exploration of will have ever acknowledged the necessity of proving directly and independently that all things willed in a certain way are good. They make no effort to demonstrate that will is a measure of goodness; and no stronger evidence could show that they do not recognize that this, at most, is all it can be. As was just pointed out, if we are to argue that whatever is willed in a certain way is also good, we must first be able to show that certain things have the common quality of ‘goodness,’ and that the same things also have the quality of being willed in a certain way. Secondly, we must be able to demonstrate this in a significant number of instances if we are to claim any agreement for the assertion that these two qualities always go together: even if this were shown, it would still be uncertain whether the leap from ‘generally’ to ‘always’ is valid, and quite likely that this uncertain principle would be useless. But the very question that Ethics aims to answer is what things are good; and, as long as Hedonism remains popular, we must admit that this is a question on which there is hardly any consensus and which therefore demands thorough examination. The most challenging and significant part of the work in Ethics would thus need to be largely completed before we could claim that anything is a measure of goodness. On the other hand, if being willed in a certain way was identical with being good, then we could start our ethical inquiries by exploring what is willed in the required manner. The way in which metaphysical writers begin their inquiries seems to clearly indicate that they are influenced by the notion that ‘goodness’ is identical with ‘being willed.’ They do not recognize that the question ‘What is good?’ is[p. 139] a different question from ‘What is willed in a certain way?’ Thus we find Green explicitly stating that ‘the common characteristic of the good is that it satisfies some desire[22].’ If we interpret this statement strictly, it clearly claims that good things have no quality in common, except that they satisfy some desire—not even, therefore, that they are good. And this can only be true if being good is identical with satisfying desire: if ‘good’ is simply another term for ‘desire-satisfying.’ There could be no clearer example of the naturalistic fallacy. And we cannot regard this statement as merely a verbal error, which does not impact the validity of Green’s main argument. For he neither provides nor pretends to provide any reason for believing anything to be good in any sense, except that it is what would satisfy a certain kind of desire—the kind of desire he tries to demonstrate to be that of a moral agent. An unhappy choice lies before us. Such reasoning would provide valid justifications for his conclusions if, and only if, being good and being desired in a specific way were identical: and in that case, as we have discussed in Chapter I., his conclusions would not be ethical. Conversely, if the two are not identical, his conclusions may be ethical and may even be correct, but he has not given us a single reason to believe them. The task that a scientific Ethics is required to fulfill, namely that certain things are genuinely good, he has simply assumed from the start by asserting that things which are willed in a certain way are always good. Therefore, we may respect Green’s conclusions as much as we would respect those of any other person who describes their ethical beliefs: but claiming that any of his arguments provide us with reasons to believe that Green’s convictions are more likely to be true than anyone else's is clearly to be denied. The Prolegomena to Ethics is just as far as Mr. Spencer’s Data of Ethics from making the slightest contribution to resolving ethical issues.
85. The main object of this chapter has been to shew that Metaphysics, understood as the investigation of a supposed supersensible reality, can have no logical bearing whatever upon[p. 140] the answer to the fundamental ethical question ‘What is good in itself?’ That this is so, follows at once from the conclusion of Chapter I., that ‘good’ denotes an ultimate, unanalysable predicate; but this truth has been so systematically ignored, that it seemed worth while to discuss and distinguish, in detail, the principal relations, which do hold, or have been supposed to hold, between Metaphysics and Ethics. With this view I pointed out:—(1) That Metaphysics may have a bearing on practical Ethics—on the question ‘What ought we to do?’—so far as it may be able to tell us what the future effects of our action will be: what it can not tell us is whether those effects are good or bad in themselves. One particular type of metaphysical doctrine, which is very frequently held, undoubtedly has such a bearing on practical Ethics: for, if it is true that the sole reality is an eternal, immutable Absolute, then it follows that no actions of ours can have any real effect, and hence that no practical proposition can be true. The same conclusion follows from the ethical proposition, commonly combined with this metaphysical one—namely that this eternal Reality is also the sole good (68). (2) That metaphysical writers, as where they fail to notice the contradiction just noticed between any practical proposition and the assertion that an eternal reality is the sole good, seem frequently to confuse the proposition that one particular existing thing is good, with the proposition that the existence of that kind of thing would be good, wherever it might occur. To the proof of the former proposition Metaphysics might be relevant, by shewing that the thing existed; to the proof of the latter it is wholly irrelevant: it can only serve the psychological function of suggesting things which may be valuable—a function which would be still better performed by pure fiction (69-71).
85. The main goal of this chapter has been to show that Metaphysics, understood as the exploration of a supposed higher reality, has no logical connection whatsoever to the fundamental ethical question ‘What is good in itself?’ This conclusion follows directly from the insights of Chapter I, which states that ‘good’ represents an ultimate, unbreakable concept; however, this fact has often been overlooked, making it worthwhile to discuss and differentiate the main relationships that do exist—or are thought to exist—between Metaphysics and Ethics. To this end, I highlighted: (1) That Metaphysics may have an impact on practical Ethics—on the question ‘What should we do?’—to the extent that it can inform us about the future consequences of our actions: what it cannot provide is an answer to whether those consequences are inherently good or bad. A specific type of metaphysical belief, which is commonly accepted, clearly has such an influence on practical Ethics: if it is true that the only reality is an eternal, unchanging Absolute, then it follows that our actions can have no real effect, meaning that no practical statement can be true. The same conclusion is supported by the ethical claim that is often linked to this metaphysical belief—specifically, that this eternal Reality is also the only good (68). (2) That metaphysical writers, when they overlook the contradiction just mentioned between any practical statement and the claim that an eternal reality is the sole good, seem to often confuse the statement that one specific existing thing is good with the statement that the existence of that kind of thing would be good, no matter where it might appear. To prove the former statement, Metaphysics might be relevant by demonstrating that the thing exists; to prove the latter, it is entirely irrelevant: it can only provide the psychological function of suggesting things that may have value—a role that could be better fulfilled by pure fiction (69-71).
But the most important source of the supposition that Metaphysics is relevant to Ethics, seems to be the assumption that ‘good’ must denote some real property of things—an assumption which is mainly due to two erroneous doctrines, the first logical, the second epistemological. Hence (3) I discussed the logical doctrine that all propositions assert a relation[p. 141] between existents; and pointed out that the assimilation of ethical propositions either to natural laws or to commands are instances of this logical fallacy (72-76). And finally (4) I discussed the epistemological doctrine that to be good is equivalent to being willed or felt in some particular way; a doctrine which derives support from the analogous error, which Kant regarded as the cardinal point of his system and which has received immensely wide acceptance—the erroneous view that to be ‘true’ or ‘real’ is equivalent to being thought in a particular way. In this discussion the main points to which I desire to direct attention are these: (a) That Volition and Feeling are not analogous to Cognition in the manner assumed; since in so far as these words denote an attitude of the mind towards an object, they are themselves merely instances of Cognition: they differ only in respect of the kind of object of which they take cognisance, and in respect of the other mental accompaniments of such cognitions: (b) That universally the object of a cognition must be distinguished from the cognition of which it is the object; and hence that in no case can the question whether the object is true be identical with the question how it is cognised or whether it is cognised at all: it follows that even if the proposition ‘This is good’ were always the object of certain kinds of will or feeling, the truth of that proposition could in no case be established by proving that it was their object; far less can that proposition itself be identical with the proposition that its subject is the object of a volition or a feeling (77-84).
But the most important reason for thinking that Metaphysics is related to Ethics seems to be the belief that ‘good’ must refer to some real property of things—this belief mainly comes from two incorrect ideas: the first is logical, and the second is epistemological. So (3) I discussed the logical idea that all statements express a relationship[p. 141] between existing things; and I pointed out that comparing ethical statements either to natural laws or to commands is an example of this logical mistake (72-76). Lastly (4) I examined the epistemological idea that being good is the same as being desired or felt in a certain way; this idea is supported by a similar mistake, which Kant considered central to his system and which has gained widespread acceptance—the mistaken belief that to be ‘true’ or ‘real’ is the same as being thought about in a certain way. In this discussion, the key points I want to highlight are these: (a) That Volition and Feeling are not similar to Cognition in the way assumed; since as far as these terms denote a mental attitude toward an object, they are themselves just examples of Cognition: they only differ in the type of object they refer to and in the other mental aspects that accompany such cognitions: (b) That generally the object of a cognition must be distinguished from the cognition itself; and therefore, in no case can the question of whether the object is true be the same as the question of how it is perceived or whether it is perceived at all: this means that even if the statement ‘This is good’ was always the focus of certain types of will or feeling, the truth of that statement could not be established by showing that it was their focus; even less can that statement itself be the same as saying that its subject is the focus of a volition or a feeling (77-84).
[p. 142]
[p. 142]
CHAPTER V.
ETHICS IN RELATION TO CONDUCT.
Ethics in relation to behavior.
86. In the present chapter we have again to take a great step in ethical method. My discussion hitherto has fallen under two main heads. Under the first, I tried to shew what ‘good’—the adjective ‘good’—means. This appeared to be the first point to be settled in any treatment of Ethics, that should aim at being systematic. It is necessary we should know this, should know what good means, before we can go on to consider what is good—what things or qualities are good. It is necessary we should know it for two reasons. The first reason is that ‘good’ is the notion upon which all Ethics depends. We cannot hope to understand what we mean, when we say that this is good or that is good, until we understand quite clearly, not only what ‘this’ is or ‘that’ is (which the natural sciences and philosophy can tell us) but also what is meant by calling them good, a matter which is reserved for Ethics only. Unless we are quite clear on this point, our ethical reasoning will be always apt to be fallacious. We shall think that we are proving that a thing is ‘good,’ when we are really only proving that it is something else; since unless we know what ‘good’ means, unless we know what is meant by that notion in itself, as distinct from what is meant by any other notion, we shall not be able to tell when we are dealing with it and when we are dealing with something else, which is perhaps like it, but yet not the same. And the second reason why we should settle first of all this question ‘What good means?’ is a reason of method. It is this, that we can never[p. 143] know on what evidence an ethical proposition rests, until we know the nature of the notion which makes the proposition ethical. We cannot tell what is possible, by way of proof, in favour of one judgment that ‘This or that is good,’ or against another judgment ‘That this or that is bad,’ until we have recognised what the nature of such propositions must always be. In fact, it follows from the meaning of good and bad, that such propositions are all of them, in Kant’s phrase, ‘synthetic’: they all must rest in the end upon some proposition which must be simply accepted or rejected, which cannot be logically deduced from any other proposition. This result, which follows from our first investigation, may be otherwise expressed by saying that the fundamental principles of Ethics must be self-evident. But I am anxious that this expression should not be misunderstood. The expression ‘self-evident’ means properly that the proposition so called is evident or true, by itself alone; that it is not an inference from some proposition other than itself. The expression does not mean that the proposition is true, because it is evident to you or me or all mankind, because in other words it appears to us to be true. That a proposition appears to be true can never be a valid argument that true it really is. By saying that a proposition is self-evident, we mean emphatically that its appearing so to us, is not the reason why it is true: for we mean that it has absolutely no reason. It would not be a self-evident proposition, if we could say of it: I cannot think otherwise and therefore it is true. For then its evidence or proof would not lie in itself, but in something else, namely our conviction of it. That it appears true to us may indeed be the cause of our asserting it, or the reason why we think and say that it is true: but a reason in this sense is something utterly different from a logical reason, or reason why something is true. Moreover, it is obviously not a reason of the same thing. The evidence of a proposition to us is only a reason for our holding it to be true: whereas a logical reason, or reason in the sense in which self-evident propositions have no reason, is a reason why the proposition itself must be true, not why we hold it so to be. Again that a proposition is evident to us may not only be the reason why we do think or[p. 144] affirm it, it may even be a reason why we ought to think it or affirm it. But a reason, in this sense too, is not a logical reason for the truth of the proposition, though it is a logical reason for the rightness of holding the proposition. In our common language, however, these three meanings of ‘reason’ are constantly confused, whenever we say ‘I have a reason for thinking that true.’ But it is absolutely essential, if we are to get clear notions about Ethics or, indeed, about any other, especially any philosophical, study, that we should distinguish them. When, therefore, I talk of Intuitionistic Hedonism, I must not be understood to imply that my denial that ‘Pleasure is the only good’ is based on my Intuition of its falsehood. My Intuition of its falsehood is indeed my reason for holding and declaring it untrue; it is indeed the only valid reason for so doing. But that is just because there is no logical reason for it; because there is no proper evidence or reason of its falsehood except itself alone. It is untrue, because it is untrue, and there is no other reason: but I declare it untrue, because its untruth is evident to me, and I hold that that is a sufficient reason for my assertion. We must not therefore look on Intuition, as if it were an alternative to reasoning. Nothing whatever can take the place of reasons for the truth of any proposition: intuition can only furnish a reason for holding any proposition to be true: this however it must do when any proposition is self-evident, when, in fact, there are no reasons which prove its truth.
86. In this chapter, we need to make an important advance in ethical methodology. Up to now, my discussion has focused on two main areas. First, I aimed to clarify what the term 'good'—the adjective 'good'—actually means. Establishing this understanding is crucial for any systematic study of Ethics. We must grasp what 'good' signifies before we can evaluate what is good—what things or qualities are good. There are two reasons for this necessity. The first reason is that the concept of 'good' is the foundation of all Ethics. We cannot hope to comprehend what we mean when we claim that something is good, until we thoroughly understand not just what 'this' is or 'that' is (as the natural sciences and philosophy can tell us), but also what we mean when we label them good—a question that belongs solely to Ethics. Without clarity on this point, our ethical reasoning may likely be flawed. We might mistakenly think we are proving that something is 'good,' when in reality we are only demonstrating that it is something else; if we don't know what 'good' means, if we don't understand what that concept signifies on its own, distinct from other ideas, we won’t be able to identify when we are discussing it versus when we are discussing something similar, but not the same. The second reason for addressing the question 'What does good mean?' first is methodological. We cannot determine the evidence behind an ethical statement until we understand the nature of what makes the statement ethical. We can’t evaluate what kind of proof supports a claim that 'This or that is good,' or counters another claim that 'This or that is bad,' until we recognize the inherent nature of such propositions. In fact, it follows from the definitions of good and bad that all such propositions are in Kant’s words, ‘synthetic’: they ultimately rest on a proposition that must be simply accepted or rejected, which cannot be logically derived from any other proposition. This conclusion from our earlier investigation can also be framed as saying that the fundamental principles of Ethics must be self-evident. However, I want to make sure this phrase isn’t misunderstood. The term ‘self-evident’ means that the stated proposition is evident or true, by itself; it is not an inference from some other proposition. It does not mean that the proposition is true because it is obvious to you, me, or everyone else—because it seems true to us. Just because something seems true does not make it valid evidence that it actually is true. By calling a proposition self-evident, we mean decisively that its seeming truth to us is not the reason why it is true: we suggest that it has no reason at all. A proposition wouldn’t be self-evident if we could say of it: I can’t think otherwise, and therefore it’s true. Because then its evidence or proof would not reside in itself, but in something else, namely our belief in it. That it appears true to us might indeed be the cause of our affirming it, or the reason we consider or state that it is true: but in this context, a reason is entirely different from a logical reason, or the reason that explains why something is true. Furthermore, it clearly isn’t a reason for the same concept. The evidence of a proposition’s truth for us only serves as a reason for us to believe it to be true: while a logical reason—in the sense that self-evident propositions have no reason—is a reason why the proposition itself must be true, not just why we hold it to be so. Also, that a proposition is evident to us might not only explain why we think or [p. 144] affirm it, but it might even serve as a reason why we should think or affirm it. Yet, that reason, too, isn’t a logical reason for the proposition’s truth, although it is a logical reason for the appropriateness of accepting the proposition. In everyday language, we often mix up these three meanings of ‘reason’ whenever we say, ‘I have a reason for thinking that’s true.’ But it is absolutely crucial, for us to grasp clear concepts about Ethics, or any other philosophical study, that we distinguish among them. Thus, when I discuss Intuitionistic Hedonism, I don't want to imply that my rejection of ‘Pleasure is the only good’ is based on my Intuition of its falsehood. My Intuition of its falsehood is indeed my reason for holding and asserting it is untrue; it is the only valid reason for doing so. However, that's only because there is no logical reason for it; because there is no genuine evidence or reason for its falsehood beyond itself alone. It is untrue simply because it is untrue, and there is no other reason: but I assert it is untrue because its untruth is evident to me, and I believe that suffices as my justification. Therefore, we shouldn’t view Intuition as an alternative to reasoning. Nothing can substitute for reasons supporting the truth of any proposition: intuition can merely provide a reason for holding any proposition to be true; this must happen when a proposition is self-evident, when, in fact, there are no reasons that validate its truth.
87. So much, then, for the first step in our ethical method, the step which established that good is good and nothing else whatever, and that Naturalism was a fallacy. A second step was taken when we began to consider proposed self-evident principles of Ethics. In this second division, resting on our result that good means good, we began the discussion of propositions asserting that such and such a thing or quality or concept was good. Of such a kind was the principle of Intuitionistic or Ethical Hedonism—the principle that ‘Pleasure alone is good.’ Following the method established by our first discussion, I claimed that the untruth of this proposition was self-evident. I could do nothing to prove that it was untrue;[p. 145] I could only point out as clearly as possible what it means, and how it contradicts other propositions which appear to be equally true. My only object in all this was, necessarily, to convince. But even if I did convince, that does not prove that we are right. It justifies us in holding that we are so; but nevertheless we may be wrong. On one thing, however, we may justly pride ourselves. It is that we have had a better chance of answering our question rightly, than Bentham or Mill or Sidgwick or others who have contradicted us. For we have proved that these have never even asked themselves the question which they professed to answer. They have confused it with another question: small wonder, therefore, if their answer is different from ours. We must be quite sure that the same question has been put, before we trouble ourselves at the different answers that are given to it. For all we know, the whole world would agree with us, if they could once clearly understand the question upon which we want their votes. Certain it is, that in all those cases where we found a difference of opinion, we found also that the question had not been clearly understood. Though, therefore, we cannot prove that we are right, yet we have reason to believe that everybody, unless he is mistaken as to what he thinks, will think the same as we. It is as with a sum in mathematics. If we find a gross and palpable error in the calculations, we are not surprised or troubled that the person who made this mistake has reached a different result from ours. We think he will admit that his result is wrong, if his mistake is pointed out to him. For instance if a man has to add up 5 + 7 + 9, we should not wonder that he made the result to be 34, if he started by making 5 + 7 = 25. And so in Ethics, if we find, as we did, that ‘desirable’ is confused with ‘desired,’ or that ‘end’ is confused with ‘means,’ we need not be disconcerted that those who have committed these mistakes do not agree with us. The only difference is that in Ethics, owing to the intricacy of its subject-matter, it is far more difficult to persuade anyone either that he has made a mistake or that that mistake affects his result.
87. So, that's the first step in our ethical approach, which established that good is simply good and nothing else, and that Naturalism is a misunderstanding. The second step was to examine suggested self-evident principles of Ethics. In this second phase, building on the idea that good means good, we started discussing statements claiming that certain things, qualities, or concepts were good. One such principle is Intuitionistic or Ethical Hedonism—the idea that 'Pleasure alone is good.' Following the method from our first discussion, I argued that the falsehood of this statement is self-evident. I can't prove that it’s false;[p. 145] I can only clarify what it means and show how it contradicts other statements that seem equally true. My sole goal in this was to persuade. But even if I do persuade, that doesn't prove we're right. It just gives us reason to believe we are; however, we could still be wrong. One thing we can justifiably take pride in is that we have a better chance of answering our question correctly than Bentham, Mill, Sidgwick, or others who disagree with us. We've shown that these figures never even considered the question they claimed to answer. They've confused it with another question: it's no surprise their answers differ from ours. We must be entirely sure that the same question has been asked before we worry about the different answers given. For all we know, the whole world might agree with us, if they could clearly understand the question we want their opinions on. It's clear that in all cases where we've found disagreement, we've also discovered that the question wasn't clearly understood. So, while we can't prove we're right, we have reason to believe that everyone, assuming they understand their own thoughts, will think the same way we do. It’s similar to solving a math problem. If we find a glaring and obvious error in someone's calculations, we aren’t surprised or bothered that their result differs from ours. We expect they'll recognize their result is wrong once we point out their error. For example, if a person needs to add 5 + 7 + 9, we wouldn't be shocked if they say the answer is 34, if they started by calculating 5 + 7 as 25. Similarly, in Ethics, if we find that 'desirable' is confused with 'desired,' or that 'end' is confused with 'means,' we shouldn’t be unsettled that those who made these errors don't agree with us. The only difference is that in Ethics, due to the complexity of its subject, it’s much harder to convince someone they made a mistake or that their mistake affects their conclusion.
In this second division of my subject—the division which is occupied with the question, ‘What is good in itself?’—I have[p. 146] hitherto only tried to establish one definite result, and that a negative one: namely that pleasure is not the sole good. This result, if true, refutes half, or more than half, of the ethical theories which have ever been held, and is, therefore, not without importance. It will, however, be necessary presently to deal positively with the question: What things are good and in what degrees?
In this second part of my topic—the part that addresses the question, ‘What is good in itself?’—I have[p. 146] so far only attempted to establish one clear conclusion, which is a negative one: namely that pleasure is not the only good. This conclusion, if correct, challenges many, if not most, of the ethical theories that have ever been proposed, and is, therefore, quite significant. However, it will soon be necessary to positively address the question: What things are good and to what extent?
88. But before proceeding to this discussion I propose, first, to deal with the third kind of ethical question—the question: What ought we to do?
88. But before moving on to this discussion, I want to first address the third type of ethical question—the question: What should we do?
The answering of this question constitutes the third great division of ethical enquiry; and its nature was briefly explained in Chap. I. (§§ 15-17). It introduces into Ethics, as was there pointed out, an entirely new question—the question what things are related as causes to that which is good in itself; and this question can only be answered by an entirely new method—the method of empirical investigation; by means of which causes are discovered in the other sciences. To ask what kind of actions we ought to perform, or what kind of conduct is right, is to ask what kind of effects such action and conduct will produce. Not a single question in practical Ethics can be answered except by a causal generalisation. All such questions do, indeed, also involve an ethical judgment proper—the judgment that certain effects are better, in themselves, than others. But they do assert that these better things are effects—are causally connected with the actions in question. Every judgment in practical Ethics may be reduced to the form: This is a cause of that good thing.
The answer to this question makes up the third main area of ethical inquiry, and its nature was briefly explained in Chapter I. (§§ 15-17). It brings into Ethics, as mentioned there, a completely new question—the question of which things are related as causes to what is inherently good; and this question can only be answered using a brand new method—the method of empirical investigation, through which causes are identified in other sciences. Asking what kinds of actions we should take or what types of conduct are right is essentially asking what effects those actions and conduct will have. Not a single question in practical Ethics can be resolved without a causal generalization. All such questions also involve an ethical judgment—the judgment that certain effects are better, in themselves, than others. However, they do assert that these better outcomes are effects—are causally linked to the actions being considered. Every judgment in practical Ethics can be reduced to the form: This is a cause of that good thing.
89. That this is the case, that the questions, What is right? what is my duty? what ought I to do? belong exclusively to this third branch of ethical enquiry, is the first point to which I wish to call attention. All moral laws, I wish to shew, are merely statements that certain kinds of actions will have good effects. The very opposite of this view has been generally prevalent in Ethics. ‘The right’ and ‘the useful’ have been supposed to be at least capable of conflicting with one another, and, at all events, to be essentially distinct. It has been characteristic of a certain school of moralists, as of moral[p. 147] common sense, to declare that the end will never justify the means. What I wish first to point out is that ‘right’ does and can mean nothing but ‘cause of a good result,’ and is thus identical with ‘useful’; whence it follows that the end always will justify the means, and that no action which is not justified by its results can be right. That there may be a true proposition, meant to be conveyed by the assertion ‘The end will not justify the means,’ I fully admit: but that, in another sense, and a sense far more fundamental for ethical theory, it is utterly false, must first be shewn.
89. It's important to recognize that the questions, What is right? what is my duty? what should I do? are exclusively tied to this third area of ethical inquiry. I want to demonstrate that all moral laws are simply statements that certain actions will lead to good outcomes. The opposite belief has been widely accepted in ethics. ‘Right’ and ‘useful’ have been thought to at least possibly conflict with one another and are, in any case, seen as fundamentally distinct. A certain group of moralists and common sense ethics have claimed that the end will never justify the means. What I want to emphasize first is that ‘right’ means nothing more than ‘a cause of a good result,’ making it identical to ‘useful’; therefore, it follows that the end will always justify the means, and no action can be deemed right unless justified by its outcomes. I fully acknowledge that there may be a true idea conveyed by the statement ‘The end will not justify the means’; however, it must first be demonstrated that, in a different and far more fundamental sense for ethical theory, this idea is completely false.
That the assertion ‘I am morally bound to perform this action’ is identical with the assertion ‘This action will produce the greatest possible amount of good in the Universe’ has already been briefly shewn in Chap. I. (§ 17); but it is important to insist that this fundamental point is demonstrably certain. This may, perhaps, be best made evident in the following way. It is plain that when we assert that a certain action is our absolute duty, we are asserting that the performance of that action at that time is unique in respect of value. But no dutiful action can possibly have unique value in the sense that it is the sole thing of value in the world; since, in that case, every such action would be the sole good thing, which is a manifest contradiction. And for the same reason its value cannot be unique in the sense that it has more intrinsic value than anything else in the world; since every act of duty would then be the best thing in the world, which is also a contradiction. It can, therefore, be unique only in the sense that the whole world will be better, if it be performed, than if any possible alternative were taken. And the question whether this is so cannot possibly depend solely on the question of its own intrinsic value. For any action will also have effects different from those of any other action; and if any of these have intrinsic value, their value is exactly as relevant to the total goodness of the Universe as that of their cause. It is, in fact, evident that, however valuable an action may be in itself, yet, owing to its existence, the sum of good in the Universe may conceivably be made less than if some other action, less valuable in itself, had been performed. But to say that this is the case is to say that it would have[p. 148] been better that the action should not have been done; and this again is obviously equivalent to the statement that it ought not to have been done—that it was not what duty required. ‘Fiat iustitia, ruat caelum’ can only be justified on the ground that by the doing of justice the Universe gains more than it loses by the falling of the heavens. It is, of course, possible that this is the case: but, at all events, to assert that justice is a duty, in spite of such consequences, is to assert that it is the case.
The claim “I have a moral obligation to perform this action” is equivalent to saying “This action will create the greatest possible amount of good in the Universe,” as briefly discussed in Chapter I. (§ 17); however, it's essential to emphasize that this core point is demonstrably true. This can perhaps be best illustrated in the following way. It’s clear that when we say a particular action is our absolute duty, we imply that carrying out that action at that moment is unique in terms of value. But no dutiful action can have unique value in the sense that it is the only thing of value in the world; if that were true, every such action would be the only good thing, which is a clear contradiction. Similarly, its value can’t be unique in the sense that it has more intrinsic value than anything else in the world; this would mean that every act of duty would then be the best thing in the world, which is also contradictory. Therefore, it can only be unique in the sense that the world will be better if it is performed than if any possible alternative is chosen. The question of whether this is true cannot solely rely on its intrinsic value. Every action will have different effects from any other action; if any of these have intrinsic value, their value is just as relevant to the overall goodness of the Universe as that of their cause. In fact, it’s clear that, no matter how valuable an action might be on its own, its existence could make the total goodness in the Universe less than if another action, which is less valuable in itself, had been performed. To claim this is the case implies that it would have been better for that action not to have been taken; and this, in turn, is essentially the same as saying that it ought not to have been done—that it was not what duty required. ‘Fiat iustitia, ruat caelum’ can only be justified if by doing justice, the Universe gains more than it loses from the heavens falling. It’s certainly possible that this is true: however, asserting that justice is a duty, despite such consequences, means claiming that it is indeed the case.
Our ‘duty,’ therefore, can only be defined as that action, which will cause more good to exist in the Universe than any possible alternative. And what is ‘right’ or ‘morally permissible’ only differs from this, as what will not cause less good than any possible alternative. When, therefore, Ethics presumes to assert that certain ways of acting are ‘duties’ it presumes to assert that to act in those ways will always produce the greatest possible sum of good. If we are told that to ‘do no murder’ is a duty, we are told that the action, whatever it may be, which is called murder, will under no circumstances cause so much good to exist in the Universe as its avoidance.
Our ‘duty’ can only be defined as the action that will create more good in the Universe than any other possible option. What is considered ‘right’ or ‘morally okay’ only differs in that it will not cause less good than any other alternative. When Ethics claims that certain actions are ‘duties,’ it is asserting that acting in those ways will always result in the greatest possible amount of good. If we are told that to ‘not commit murder’ is a duty, we are being told that the act known as murder will never create as much good in the Universe as avoiding it will.
90. But, if this be recognised, several most important consequences follow, with regard to the relation of Ethics to conduct.
90. But if this is recognized, several very important consequences follow regarding the relationship between ethics and behavior.
(1) It is plain that no moral law is self-evident, as has commonly been held by the Intuitional school of moralists. The Intuitional view of Ethics consists in the supposition that certain rules, stating that certain actions are always to be done or to be omitted, may be taken as self-evident premisses. I have shewn with regard to judgments of what is good in itself, that this is the case; no reason can be given for them. But it is the essence of Intuitionism to suppose that rules of action—statements not of what ought to be, but of what we ought to do—are in the same sense intuitively certain. Plausibility has been lent to this view by the fact that we do undoubtedly make immediate judgments that certain actions are obligatory or wrong: we are thus often intuitively certain of our duty, in a psychological sense. But, nevertheless, these judgments are not self-evident and cannot be taken as ethical premisses, since, as has now been shewn, they are capable of being[p. 149] confirmed or refuted by an investigation of causes and effects. It is, indeed, possible that some of our immediate intuitions are true; but since what we intuit, what conscience tells us, is that certain actions will always produce the greatest sum of good possible under the circumstances, it is plain that reasons can be given, which will shew the deliverances of conscience to be true or false.
(1) It's clear that no moral law is self-evident, despite what the Intuitional school of moralists commonly claims. The Intuitional view of Ethics suggests that certain rules indicating which actions should always be performed or avoided can be seen as self-evident premises. I've shown regarding judgments of what is good in itself that this is not the case; no reason can be provided for them. However, Intuitionism assumes that rules of action—statements not about what ought to be, but about what we should do—are intuitively certain in the same way. This perspective gains some credibility because we do indeed make immediate judgments about certain actions being obligatory or wrong: we often feel intuitively certain about our duty, in a psychological sense. Nevertheless, these judgments are not self-evident and cannot be accepted as ethical premises, since, as has now been demonstrated, they can be confirmed or disproven through an investigation of causes and effects. It is, in fact, possible that some of our immediate intuitions are correct; but since what we intuit, what conscience tells us, is that certain actions will always yield the greatest amount of good possible under the circumstances, it is evident that reasons can be provided that will show whether conscience's conclusions are true or false.
91. (2) In order to shew that any action is a duty, it is necessary to know both what are the other conditions, which will, conjointly with it, determine its effects; to know exactly what will be the effects of these conditions; and to know all the events which will be in any way affected by our action throughout an infinite future. We must have all this causal knowledge, and further we must know accurately the degree of value both of the action itself and of all these effects; and must be able to determine how, in conjunction with the other things in the Universe, they will affect its value as an organic whole. And not only this: we must also possess all this knowledge with regard to the effects of every possible alternative; and must then be able to see by comparison that the total value due to the existence of the action in question will be greater than that which would be produced by any of these alternatives. But it is obvious that our causal knowledge alone is far too incomplete for us ever to assure ourselves of this result. Accordingly it follows that we never have any reason to suppose that an action is our duty: we can never be sure that any action will produce the greatest value possible.
91. (2) To prove that an action is a duty, we need to understand the other conditions that will, together with it, determine its effects; we also need to know exactly what the effects of these conditions will be; and we must consider all the events that could be influenced by our action over an infinite future. We need all this causal knowledge, and on top of that, we must accurately assess the value of both the action itself and all its effects; we should also be able to determine how they, along with everything else in the Universe, will impact its value as a whole. Furthermore, we must have all this knowledge concerning the effects of every possible alternative; we then have to compare and see that the total value resulting from the action in question is greater than what any of these alternatives would produce. However, it’s clear that our causal knowledge is far too incomplete for us to be certain of this outcome. Consequently, we can never really assume that an action is our duty; we can never be sure that any action will yield the greatest possible value.
Ethics, therefore, is quite unable to give us a list of duties: but there still remains a humbler task which may be possible for Practical Ethics. Although we cannot hope to discover which, in a given situation, is the best of all possible alternative actions, there may be some possibility of shewing which among the alternatives, likely to occur to any one, will produce the greatest sum of good. This second task is certainly all that Ethics can ever have accomplished: and it is certainly all that it has ever collected materials for proving; since no one has ever attempted to exhaust the possible alternative actions in any particular case. Ethical philosophers have in fact confined their[p. 150] attention to a very limited class of actions, which have been selected because they are those which most commonly occur to mankind as possible alternatives. With regard to these they may possibly have shewn that one alternative is better, i.e. produces a greater total of value, than others. But it seems desirable to insist, that though they have represented this result as a determination of duties, it can never really have been so. For the term duty is certainly so used that, if we are subsequently persuaded that any possible action would have produced more good than the one we adopted, we admit that we failed to do our duty. It will, however, be a useful task if Ethics can determine which among alternatives likely to occur will produce the greatest total value. For, though this alternative cannot be proved to be the best possible, yet it may be better than any course of action which we should otherwise adopt.
Ethics can't really give us a list of duties, but there is a simpler task that Practical Ethics might be able to tackle. While we can’t expect to find out which action is the absolute best in any situation, we might be able to show which of the alternatives that someone is likely to consider will result in the greatest overall good. This secondary task is definitely all that Ethics could ever hope to achieve, and it’s all that it has gathered evidence to support; since no one has ever tried to explore all possible actions in a specific case. Ethical philosophers have actually focused on a very limited set of actions, chosen because they are the ones that people most commonly think of as possible options. Regarding these, they may have shown that one option is better, meaning it generates a greater total value, than others. However, it’s important to emphasize that even though they’ve presented this conclusion as a definition of duties, it can never truly be that. The term "duty" is commonly understood to mean that if we later realize that a different action would have generated more good than the one we chose, we acknowledge that we failed to fulfill our duty. Nevertheless, it would be a valuable effort for Ethics to identify which of the likely alternatives will generate the greatest total value. While this option might not be proven to be the best overall, it could still be better than any other course of action we might consider.
92. A difficulty in distinguishing this task, which Ethics may perhaps undertake with some hope of success, from the hopeless task of finding duties, arises from an ambiguity in the use of the term ‘possible.’ An action may, in one perfectly legitimate sense, be said to be ‘impossible’ solely because the idea of doing it does not occur to us. In this sense, then, the alternatives which do actually occur to a man would be the only possible alternatives; and the best of these would be the best possible action under the circumstances, and hence would conform to our definition of ‘duty.’ But when we talk of the best possible action as our duty, we mean by the term any action which no other known circumstance would prevent, provided the idea of it occurred to us. And this use of the term is in accordance with popular usage. For we admit that a man may fail to do his duty, through neglecting to think of what he might have done. Since, therefore, we say that he might have done, what nevertheless did not occur to him, it is plain that we do not limit his possible actions to those of which he thinks. It might be urged, with more plausibility, that we mean by a man’s duty only the best of those actions of which he might have thought. And it is true that we do not blame any man very severely for omitting an action of[p. 151] which, as we say, ‘he could not be expected to think.’ But even here it is plain that we recognise a distinction between what he might have done and what he might have thought of doing: we regard it as a pity that he did not do otherwise. And ‘duty’ is certainly used in such a sense, that it would be a contradiction in terms to say it was a pity that a man did his duty.
92. A challenge in separating this task, which Ethics might take on with some hope of success, from the impossible task of identifying duties, comes from a confusion in how we use the term ‘possible.’ An action can be considered ‘impossible’ simply because it hasn’t occurred to us to do it. In this way, the choices that actually come to mind for a person would be the only possible choices, and the best of these would be the best possible action given the circumstances, therefore aligning with our definition of ‘duty.’ However, when we refer to the best possible action as our duty, we mean any action that no other known circumstance would block, provided we had the idea of it in the first place. This usage fits with common understanding. We acknowledge that a person might fail to fulfill their duty by not considering what they might have done. So, when we say they might have done something that didn’t occur to them, it’s clear that we don't restrict their possible actions to those they are aware of. It could be argued, more convincingly, that we define a person’s duty as only the best of the actions they might have considered. And it’s true that we don’t hold someone to a high standard for failing to take an action that, as we say, ‘they couldn’t be expected to think about.’ But even in that case, we see a difference between what they could have done and what they could have thought about doing: we feel it’s unfortunate that they didn’t choose otherwise. And ‘duty’ is certainly used in such a way that it would contradict itself to say it’s a shame that someone fulfilled their duty.
We must, therefore, distinguish a possible action from an action of which it is possible to think. By the former we mean an action which no known cause would prevent, provided the idea of it occurred to us: and that one among such actions, which will produce the greatest total good, is what we mean by duty. Ethics certainly cannot hope to discover what kind of action is always our duty in this sense. It may, however, hope to decide which among one or two such possible actions is the best: and those which it has chosen to consider are, as a matter of fact, the most important of those with regard to which men deliberate whether they shall or shall not do them. A decision with regard to these may therefore be easily confounded with a decision with regard to which is the best possible action. But it is to be noted that even though we limit ourselves to considering which is the better among alternatives likely to be thought of, the fact that these alternatives might be thought of is not included is what we mean by calling them possible alternatives. Even if in any particular case it was impossible that the idea of them should have occurred to a man, the question we are concerned with is, which, if it had occurred, would have been the best alternative? If we say that murder is always a worse alternative, we mean to assert that it is so, even where it was impossible for the murderer to think of doing anything else.
We need to distinguish between a possible action and an action that can be imagined. By a possible action, we mean one that no known cause would prevent, as long as we consider the idea of it: and the action that leads to the greatest overall good is what we refer to as duty. Ethics can't determine what action is always our duty in this sense. However, it can help us figure out which of a couple of possible actions is the best: and the ones we've chosen to analyze are actually the most important in terms of what people think about doing or not doing. A decision about these actions can easily be confused with a decision about which action is the best possible. It's important to note that even if we limit ourselves to evaluating which option is better among the alternatives likely to be imagined, the fact that these alternatives could be thought of is what we mean by calling them possible alternatives. Even if in a specific case it was impossible for someone to think of them, the question we are focusing on is, which, had the idea occurred, would have been the best alternative? When we say that murder is always a worse option, we assert that it's true, even when it was impossible for the murderer to think of doing anything else.
The utmost, then, that Practical Ethics can hope to discover is which, among a few alternatives possible under certain circumstances, will, on the whole, produce the best result. It may tell us which is the best, in this sense, of certain alternatives about which we are likely to deliberate; and since we may also know that, even if we choose none of these, what we shall, in that case, do is unlikely to be as good as one of[p. 152] them, it may thus tell us which of the alternatives, among which we can choose, it is best to choose. If it could do this it would be sufficient for practical guidance.
The most that Practical Ethics can hope to find out is which of a few possible options under specific circumstances will, overall, lead to the best outcome. It can show us which is the best choice among certain alternatives we might consider; and since we also recognize that if we choose none of these, what we decide to do instead is probably not as good as one of them, it can help us determine which of the options we can choose is the best one to select. If it could accomplish this, it would be enough for practical guidance.[p. 152]
93. But (3) it is plain that even this is a task of immense difficulty. It is difficult to see how we can establish even a probability that by doing one thing we shall obtain a better total result than by doing another. I shall merely endeavour to point out how much is assumed, when we assume that there is such a probability, and on what lines it seems possible that this assumption may be justified. It will be apparent that it has never yet been justified—that no sufficient reason has ever yet been found for considering one action more right or more wrong than another.
93. But (3) it’s clear that this is an incredibly challenging task. It's hard to see how we can even establish a likelihood that by choosing one option we’ll achieve a better overall outcome than by choosing another. I will simply attempt to highlight how much we take for granted when we assume that such a likelihood exists, and what criteria might make this assumption justifiable. It will be evident that it has never truly been justified—that no solid reason has been found to deem one action more right or wrong than another.
(a) The first difficulty in the way of establishing a probability that one course of action will give a better total result than another, lies in the fact that we have to take account of the effects of both throughout an infinite future. We have no certainty but that, if we do one action now, the Universe will, throughout all time, differ in some way from what it would have been, if we had done another; and, if there is such a permanent difference, it is certainly relevant to our calculation. But it is quite certain that our causal knowledge is utterly insufficient to tell us what different effects will probably result from two different actions, except within a comparatively short space of time; we can certainly only pretend to calculate the effects of actions within what may be called an ‘immediate’ future. No one, when he proceeds upon what he considers a rational consideration of effects, would guide his choice by any forecast that went beyond a few centuries at most; and, in general, we consider that we have acted rationally, if we think we have secured a balance of good within a few years or months or days. Yet, if a choice guided by such considerations is to be rational, we must certainly have some reason to believe that no consequences of our action in a further future will generally be such as to reverse the balance of good that is probable in the future which we can foresee. This large postulate must be made, if we are ever to assert that the results of one[p. 153] action will be even probably better than those of another. Our utter ignorance of the far future gives us no justification for saying that it is even probably right to choose the greater good within the region over which a probable forecast may extend. We do, then, assume that it is improbable that effects, after a certain time, will, in general, be such as to reverse the comparative value of the alternative results within that time. And that this assumption is justified must be shewn before we can claim to have given any reason whatever for acting in one way rather than in another. It may, perhaps, be justified by some such considerations as the following. As we proceed further and further from the time at which alternative actions are open to us, the events of which either action would be part cause become increasingly dependent on those other circumstances, which are the same, whichever action we adopt. The effects of any individual action seem, after a sufficient space of time, to be found only in trifling modifications spread over a very wide area, whereas its immediate effects consist in some prominent modification of a comparatively narrow area. Since, however, most of the things which have any great importance for good or evil are things of this prominent kind, there may be a probability that after a certain time all the effects of any particular action become so nearly indifferent, that any difference between their value and that of the effects of another action, is very unlikely to outweigh an obvious difference in the value of the immediate effects. It does in fact appear to be the case that, in most cases, whatever action we now adopt, ‘it will be all the same a hundred years hence,’ so far as the existence at that time of anything greatly good or bad is concerned: and this might, perhaps, be shewn to be true, by an investigation of the manner in which the effects of any particular event become neutralised by lapse of time. Failing such a proof, we can certainly have no rational ground for asserting that one of two alternatives is even probably right and another wrong. If any of our judgments of right and wrong are to pretend to probability, we must have reason to think that the effects of our actions in the far future will not have value sufficient to outweigh[p. 154] any superiority of one set of effects over another in the immediate future.
(a) The first challenge in determining whether one course of action will lead to better overall results than another is that we need to consider the effects of both actions over an infinite future. We can’t be certain that if we choose one action now, the Universe won’t be different at some point in the future compared to if we had taken a different course; if there is such a lasting difference, it certainly matters for our analysis. However, our understanding of causality is clearly inadequate to tell us what different outcomes will likely result from two different actions, except within a relatively short timeframe; we can only realistically calculate the effects of actions in what we can call the ‘immediate’ future. No one, when making what they think is a rational choice based on effects, would rely on predictions that extend beyond a few centuries at most; generally, we feel we've acted rationally if we believe we’ve secured a balance of good within a few years, months, or even days. Yet, for a choice guided by such reasoning to be rational, we must have some justification to believe that the long-term consequences of our actions won’t typically reverse the balance of good that we predict in the foreseeable future. This significant assumption must be made if we are ever to claim that the outcomes of one action will likely be better than those of another. Our complete lack of knowledge about the distant future does not provide grounds for saying that it is even probably right to choose the greater good based on the short-term predictions we can make. We do assume that it is unlikely the effects, after a certain time, will generally reverse the comparative value of the alternative outcomes during that time. And this assumption must be demonstrated as justified before we can assert any reasons for favoring one action over another. Perhaps it can be justified by some thoughts like the following: As we move further away from the time when we have options available, the events influenced by either action become increasingly reliant on circumstances that remain the same, regardless of which action we choose. The effects of any specific action seem to fade over time into minor effects spread across a large area, while its immediate effects are more prominent and localized. Since many important factors for good or bad outcomes tend to be these significant immediate effects, there may be a good chance that after a certain period, all the consequences of a particular action become so nearly neutral that any difference in their overall value compared to another action's effects is unlikely to outweigh a clear difference in the value of their immediate outcomes. In fact, it seems to be true that, in most situations, whatever action we take now, ‘it will be the same a hundred years later,’ in regards to the presence of anything significantly good or bad at that time: and this could likely be proven by examining how the effects of specific events diminish over time. Without such proof, we certainly have no reasonable basis for claiming that one of two options is even probably right while the other is wrong. If any of our judgments about right and wrong are to have any claim to probability, we must have a reason to believe that the effects of our actions in the distant future will not have enough value to outweigh any advantages of one set of outcomes over another in the immediate future.
94. (b) We must assume, then, that if the effects of one action are generally better than those of another, so far forward in the future as we are able to foresee any probable difference in their effects at all, then the total effect upon the Universe of the former action is also generally better. We certainly cannot hope directly to compare their effects except within a limited future; and all the arguments, which have ever been used in Ethics, and upon which we commonly act in common life, directed to shewing that one course is superior to another, are (apart from theological dogmas) confined to pointing out such probable immediate advantages. The question remains, then: Can we lay down any general rules to the effect that one among a few alternative actions will generally produce a greater total of good in the immediate future?
94. (b) We must assume that if the outcomes of one action are generally better than those of another, as far into the future as we can predict any likely differences in their effects, then the overall impact on the Universe of the first action is also generally better. We definitely can't directly compare their outcomes beyond a limited timeframe; and all the arguments that have ever been made in Ethics, which we typically rely on in everyday life, aimed at showing that one choice is better than another, are (aside from religious beliefs) limited to highlighting such likely immediate benefits. The question still stands: Can we establish any general rules stating that one among several alternative actions will usually lead to a greater amount of good in the near future?
It is important to insist that this question, limited as it is, is the utmost, to which, with any knowledge we have at present or are likely to have for a long time to come, Practical Ethics can hope to give an answer. I have already pointed out that we cannot hope to discover which is the best possible alternative in any given circumstances, but only which, among a few, is better than the others. And I have also pointed out that there is certainly no more than a probability, even if we are entitled to assert so much, that what is better in regard to its immediate effects will also be better on the whole. It now remains to insist that, even with regard to these immediate effects, we can only hope to discover which, among a few alternatives, will generally produce the greatest balance of good in the immediate future. We can secure no title to assert that obedience to such commands as ‘Thou shalt not lie,’ or even ‘Thou shalt do no murder,’ is universally better than the alternatives of lying and murder. Reasons why no more than a general knowledge is possible have been already given in Chap. I. (§ 16); but they may be recapitulated here. In the first place, of the effects, which principally concern us in ethical discussions, as having intrinsic value, we know the causes so little, that we can scarcely claim, with regard to any[p. 155] single one, to have obtained even a hypothetical universal law, such as has been obtained in the exact sciences. We cannot even say: If this action is performed, under exactly these circumstances, and if no others interfere, this important effect, at least, will always be produced. But, in the second place, an ethical law is not merely hypothetical. If we are to know that it will always be better to act in a certain way, under certain circumstances, we must know not merely what effects such actions will produce, provided no other circumstances interfere, but also that no other circumstances will interfere. And this it is obviously impossible to know with more than probability. An ethical law has the nature not of a scientific law but of a scientific prediction: and the latter is always merely probable, although the probability may be very great. An engineer is entitled to assert that, if a bridge be built in a certain way, it will probably bear certain loads for a certain time; but he can never be absolutely certain that it has been built in the way required, nor that, even if it has, some accident will not intervene to falsify his prediction. With any ethical law, the same must be the case; it can be no more than a generalisation: and here, owing to the comparative absence of accurate hypothetical knowledge, on which the prediction should be based, the probability is comparatively small. But finally, for an ethical generalisation, we require to know not only what effects will be produced, but also what are the comparative values of those effects; and on this question too, it must be admitted, considering what a prevalent opinion Hedonism has been, that we are very liable to be mistaken. It is plain, then, that we are not soon likely to know more than that one kind of action will generally produce better effects than another; and that more than this has certainly never been proved. In no two cases will all the effects of any kind of action be precisely the same, because in each case some of the circumstances will differ; and although the effects, that are important for good or evil, may be generally the same, it is extremely unlikely that they will always be so.
It’s important to emphasize that this question, as limited as it is, is the most significant one that Practical Ethics can hope to answer with the knowledge we have now or are likely to have for a long time. I've already mentioned that we can't expect to find which is the best possible option in any given situation, but only which one, among a few, is better than the others. I've also noted that we can only claim a probability, if we are justified in doing so, that what is better in terms of immediate effects will also be better overall. It now remains to stress that, even regarding these immediate effects, we can only hope to determine which, among a few options, will generally result in the best outcome in the short term. We can't definitively say that following commands like ‘Thou shalt not lie’ or even ‘Thou shalt do no murder’ is universally better than the alternatives of lying and murder. I already provided reasons for why we can only achieve general knowledge in Chapter I. (§ 16); but they can be summarized here. First, concerning the effects that matter most in ethical discussions, as they have intrinsic value, we understand the causes so little that we can scarcely claim to have established even a hypothetical universal law, similar to those found in the exact sciences. We can’t even say: If this action is taken in exactly these circumstances, and if no other factors come into play, this significant effect will always occur. Secondly, an ethical law isn’t merely hypothetical. To know that acting in a certain way under specific circumstances is always better, we must understand not only what effects those actions will produce, assuming no other circumstances interfere, but also that no other factors will interfere. And obviously, it’s impossible to know this with more than a probability. An ethical law is more like a scientific prediction, which is always merely probable, though the likelihood might be very high. An engineer can confidently state that if a bridge is built in a certain manner, it will probably support certain weights for a specific duration; however, he can never be completely certain that it has been constructed correctly, nor that, even if it has, some unforeseen event won’t occur to invalidate his prediction. The same applies to any ethical law; it can only be a generalization: and due to the relative lack of precise hypothetical knowledge on which the prediction should rely, the probability is comparatively low. Finally, for an ethical generalization, we need to know not just what effects will be produced, but also how those effects compare in value; and regarding this question, given how prevalent Hedonism has been, it must be acknowledged that we can easily be mistaken. It is evident, then, that we are unlikely to soon know more than that one type of action will generally yield better outcomes than another; anything beyond this has certainly never been proven. In no two instances will all the effects of any action be exactly the same, because in each case, some circumstances will differ; and even though the effects that are crucial for good or evil may generally be the same, it is extremely unlikely that they will always be consistent.
95. (c) If, now, we confine ourselves to a search for actions which are generally better as means than any probable alter[p. 156]native, it seems possible to establish as much as this in defence of most of the rules most universally recognised by Common Sense. I do not propose to enter upon this defence in detail, but merely to point out what seem to be the chief distinct principles by the use of which it can be made.
95. (c) If we focus on finding actions that are generally better options than any likely alternatives, it seems possible to support most of the rules that are widely accepted by Common Sense. I don’t intend to go into this defense in detail, but I just want to highlight what appear to be the main principles that can be used to support it.
In the first place, then, we can only shew that one action is generally better than another as a means, provided that certain other circumstances are given. We do, as a matter of fact, only observe its good effects under certain circumstances; and it may be easily seen that a sufficient change in these would render doubtful what seem the most universally certain of general rules. Thus, the general disutility of murder can only be proved, provided the majority of the human race will certainly persist in existing. In order to prove that murder, if it were so universally adopted as to cause the speedy extermination of the race, would not be good as a means, we should have to disprove the main contention of pessimism—namely that the existence of human life is on the whole an evil. And the view of pessimism, however strongly we may be convinced of its truth or falsehood, is one which never has been either proved or refuted conclusively. That universal murder would not be a good thing at this moment can therefore not be proved. But, as a matter of fact, we can and do assume with certainty that, even if a few people are willing to murder, most people will not be willing. When, therefore, we say that murder is in general to be avoided, we only mean that it is so, so long as the majority of mankind will certainly not agree to it, but will persist in living. And that, under these circumstances, it is generally wrong for any single person to commit murder seems capable of proof. For, since there is in any case no hope of exterminating the race, the only effects which we have to consider are those which the action will have upon the increase of the goods and the diminution of the evils of human life. Where the best is not attainable (assuming extermination to be the best) one alternative may still be better than another. And, apart from the immediate evils which murder generally produces, the fact that, if it were a common practice, the feeling of insecurity, thus caused, would[p. 157] absorb much time, which might be spent to better purpose, is perhaps conclusive against it. So long as men desire to live as strongly as they do, and so long as it is certain that they will continue to do so, anything which hinders them from devoting their energy to the attainment of positive goods, seems plainly bad as a means. And the general practice of murder, falling so far short of universality as it certainly must in all known conditions of society, seems certainly to be a hindrance of this kind.
First, we can only show that one action is generally better than another as a means, given that certain other circumstances are in place. In reality, we only see its positive effects under specific conditions, and it’s easy to see that a significant change in these would challenge what seem like the most universally accepted general rules. For example, the general negative impact of murder can only be proven if most of humanity is likely to continue existing. To demonstrate that if murder were adopted on a large scale leading to the rapid extinction of the human race, it wouldn't be a good means, we would need to disprove the main argument of pessimism—that human life is ultimately an evil. The pessimistic view, regardless of how strongly we may believe in its truth or falsehood, has never been conclusively proven or disproven. Therefore, we cannot prove that universal murder would be a bad thing at this moment. However, we can confidently assume that, even if a few people might choose to murder, most people would not. Thus, when we assert that murder should generally be avoided, we mean this only as long as the majority of people are expected to disagree with it and continue to live. Under these circumstances, it seems provable that it is generally wrong for any individual to commit murder. Since there’s no possibility of exterminating the human race, the only effects we need to consider are those that the action will have on increasing the goods and reducing the evils of human life. When the best outcome isn't achievable (assuming extermination is the best), one alternative may still be better than another. Besides the immediate harms that murder typically causes, the fact that, if it became common, the feeling of insecurity resulting from it would consume a lot of time that could be spent more productively, is perhaps conclusive against it. As long as people have a strong desire to live, and as long as it is certain they will continue to do so, anything that prevents them from focusing their energy on achieving positive goods seems clearly bad as a means. The widespread practice of murder, which must fall far short of universality in any known social conditions, certainly appears to hinder this.
A similar defence seems possible for most of the rules, most universally enforced by legal sanctions, such as respect of property; and for some of those most commonly recognised by Common Sense, such as industry, temperance and the keeping of promises. In any state of society in which men have that intense desire for property of some sort, which seems to be universal, the common legal rules for the protection of property must serve greatly to facilitate the best possible expenditure of energy. And similarly: Industry is a means to the attainment of those necessaries, without which the further attainment of any great positive goods is impossible; temperance merely enjoins the avoidance of those excesses, which, by injuring health, would prevent a man from contributing as much as possible to the acquirement of these necessaries; and the keeping of promises greatly facilitates cooperation in such acquirement.
A similar defense seems possible for most of the rules, which are mostly enforced by legal consequences, like respecting property; and for some of the things widely acknowledged by common sense, like hard work, moderation, and keeping promises. In any society where people have that strong desire for some form of property, which appears to be universal, the common legal rules protecting property must greatly help to make the best use of energy. Similarly, hard work is a way to secure the essentials needed to achieve any significant positive goods; moderation simply encourages avoiding excesses that could harm health and prevent someone from contributing as much as possible to obtaining these essentials; and keeping promises makes cooperation in acquiring these essentials much easier.
Now all these rules seem to have two characteristics to which it is desirable to call attention. (1) They seem all to be such that, in any known state of society, a general observance of them would be good as a means. The conditions upon which their utility depends, namely the tendency to preserve and propagate life and the desire of property, seem to be so universal and so strong, that it would be impossible to remove them; and, this being so, we can say that, under any conditions which could actually be given, the general observance of these rules would be good as a means. For, while there seems no reason to think that their observance ever makes a society worse than one in which they are not observed, it is certainly necessary as a means for any state of things in which the greatest[p. 158] possible goods can be attained. And (2) these rules, since they can be recommended as a means to that which is itself only a necessary condition for the existence of any great good, can be defended independently of correct views upon the primary ethical question of what is good in itself. On any view commonly taken, it seems certain that the preservation of civilised society, which these rules are necessary to effect, is necessary for the existence, in any great degree, of anything which may be held to be good in itself.
Now, all these rules seem to have two key characteristics worth highlighting. (1) They all appear to be such that, in any known society, a general observance of them would be beneficial as a means. The conditions that determine their usefulness—specifically, the tendency to preserve and promote life and the desire for property—seem to be so universal and so strong that it would be impossible to eliminate them; thus, we can say that under any conditions that could actually exist, the general observance of these rules would be beneficial as a means. While there seems to be no reason to believe that following these rules ever makes a society worse than one that does not follow them, it is definitely necessary for achieving any situation where the greatest[p. 158] possible benefits can be attained. And (2) these rules can be justified as a means to something that is itself only a necessary condition for the existence of any significant good, and can be defended independently of correct views on the primary ethical question of what is good in itself. From any commonly accepted perspective, it seems clear that the preservation of civilized society—something these rules are essential to achieve—is necessary for the existence, to any significant degree, of anything that might be considered good in itself.
96. But not by any means all the rules commonly recognised combine these two characteristics. The arguments offered in defence of Common Sense morality very often presuppose the existence of conditions, which cannot be fairly assumed to be so universally necessary as the tendency to continue life and to desire property. Such arguments, accordingly, only prove the utility of the rule, so long as certain conditions, which may alter, remain the same: it cannot be claimed of the rules thus defended, that they would be generally good as means in every state of society: in order to establish this universal general utility, it would be necessary to arrive at a correct view of what is good or evil in itself. This, for instance, seems to be the case with most of the rules comprehended under the name of Chastity. These rules are commonly defended, by Utilitarian writers or writers who assume as their end the conservation of society, with arguments which presuppose the necessary existence of such sentiments as conjugal jealousy and paternal affection. These sentiments are no doubt sufficiently strong and general to make the defence valid for many conditions of society. But it is not difficult to imagine a civilised society existing without them; and, in such a case, if chastity were still to be defended, it would be necessary to establish that its violation produced evil effects, other than those due to the assumed tendency of such violation to disintegrate society. Such a defence may, no doubt, be made; but it would require an examination into the primary ethical question of what is good and bad in itself, far more thorough than any ethical writer has ever offered to us. Whether this be so in this particular case or not, it is certain that a distinction, not commonly recognised,[p. 159] should be made between those rules, of which the social utility depends upon the existence of circumstances, more or less likely to alter, and those of which the utility seems certain under all possible conditions.
96. However, not all commonly accepted rules share these two characteristics. The arguments used to defend Common Sense morality often assume the presence of conditions that can't be fairly considered universally necessary, like the desire to live and own property. Therefore, these arguments only demonstrate the usefulness of the rules as long as certain conditions, which might change, remain the same. It can't be claimed that the rules being defended would generally be beneficial in every social context. To establish this universal general utility, we would need to have a clear understanding of what is inherently good or bad. For example, this appears to be true for most rules associated with Chastity. These rules are typically supported by Utilitarian writers or those who prioritize the preservation of society, using arguments that assume the unavoidable presence of feelings like marital jealousy and parental love. While these feelings are indeed strong and widespread enough to make the defense valid for many social conditions, it's not hard to envision a civilized society existing without them. In such a scenario, if chastity were to be defended, it would be necessary to demonstrate that its violation leads to harmful effects beyond just the assumed tendency of such violations to destabilize society. While this defense could certainly be made, it would require a deeper exploration of the fundamental ethical question of what is good and bad in itself, much more thorough than what any ethical writer has provided us. Whether this is true in this specific instance or not, it is clear that a distinction, not commonly recognized,[p. 159] should be made between those rules whose social utility depends on the existence of circumstances that may change and those whose utility appears certain under all possible conditions.
97. It is obvious that all the rules, which were enumerated above as likely to be useful in almost any state of society, can also be defended owing to results which they produce under conditions which exist only in particular states of society. And it should be noticed that we are entitled to reckon among these conditions the sanctions of legal penalties, of social disapproval, and of private remorse, where these exist. These sanctions are, indeed, commonly treated by Ethics only as motives for the doing of actions of which the utility can be proved independently of the existence of these sanctions. And it may be admitted that sanctions ought not to be attached to actions which would not be right independently. Nevertheless it is plain that, where they do exist, they are not only motives but also justifications for the actions in question. One of the chief reasons why an action should not be done in any particular state of society is that it will be punished; since the punishment is in general itself a greater evil than would have been caused by the omission of the action punished. Thus the existence of a punishment may be an adequate reason for regarding an action as generally wrong, even though it has no other bad effects but even slightly good ones. The fact that an action will be punished is a condition of exactly the same kind as others of more or less permanence, which must be taken into account in discussing the general utility or disutility of an action in a particular state of society.
97. It's clear that all the rules mentioned earlier, which are likely to be useful in almost any society, can also be justified based on the outcomes they create under specific conditions that only occur in certain social contexts. We should note that among these conditions, we include the consequences of legal penalties, social disapproval, and private guilt, where they are present. Ethics typically considers these consequences merely as motivations for actions that can be proven beneficial regardless of whether these factors are at play. It can be agreed that penalties should not be applied to actions that would still be wrong on their own. However, it is evident that where penalties exist, they serve not only as motivations but also as justifications for the actions involved. One of the main reasons an action shouldn't be taken in a given society is that it will lead to punishment; since the punishment is usually a greater harm than what would occur from not performing the action. So, the fact that an action will be punished can be a sufficient reason to consider it generally wrong, even if it only has minor positive effects. The reality that an action will be punished is a factor of the same type as other more or less permanent conditions that must be considered when evaluating the overall utility or harm of an action in a specific society.
98. It is plain, then, that the rules commonly recognised by Common Sense, in the society in which we live, and commonly advocated as if they were all equally and universally right and good, are of very different orders. Even those which seem to be most universally good as means, can only be shewn to be so, because of the existence of conditions, which, though perhaps evils, may be taken to be necessary; and even these owe their more obvious utilities to the existence of other conditions, which cannot be taken to be necessary except over longer or shorter[p. 160] periods of history, and many of which are evils. Others seem to be justifiable solely by the existence of such more or less temporary conditions, unless we abandon the attempt to shew that they are means to that preservation of society, which is itself a mere means, and are able to establish that they are directly means to things good or evil in themselves, but which are not commonly recognised to be such.
98. It's clear that the rules generally accepted by common sense in our society, and often promoted as if they are all equally right and good, are actually very different from one another. Even those that appear to be universally good means can only be shown to be so because of certain conditions, which, while possibly negative, may be seen as necessary; and even these derive their more evident usefulness from other conditions, which can only be deemed necessary over varying periods of history, many of which are problematic. Others seem to be justifiable only by the existence of these somewhat temporary conditions, unless we give up trying to prove that they are means to the preservation of society, which itself is merely a means, and instead show that they are directly related to things that are good or evil in themselves, but are not commonly recognized as such.
If, then, we ask what rules are or would be useful to be observed in the society in which we live, it seems possible to prove a definite utility in most of those which are in general both recognised and practised. But a great part of ordinary moral exhortation and social discussion consists in the advocating of rules, which are not generally practised; and with regard to these it seems very doubtful whether a case for their general utility can ever be conclusively made out. Such proposed rules commonly suffer from three main defects. In the first place, (1) the actions which they advocate are very commonly such as it is impossible for most individuals to perform by any volition. It is far too usual to find classed together with actions, which can be performed, if only they be willed, others, of which the possibility depends upon the possession of a peculiar disposition, which is given to few and cannot even be acquired. It may, no doubt, be useful to point out that those who have the necessary disposition should obey these rules; and it would, in many cases, be desirable that everybody should have this disposition. But it should be recognised that, when we regard a thing as a moral rule or law, we mean that it is one which almost everybody can observe by an effort of volition, in that state of society to which the rule is supposed to apply. (2) Actions are often advocated, of which, though they themselves are possible, yet the proposed good effects are not possible, because the conditions necessary for their existence are not sufficiently general. A rule, of which the observance would produce good effects, if human nature were in other respects different from what it is, is advocated as if its general observance would produce the same effects now and at once. In fact, however, by the time that the conditions necessary to make its observance useful have arisen, it is quite as likely that other conditions,[p. 161] rendering its observance unnecessary or positively harmful, may also have arisen; and yet this state of things may be a better one than that in which the rule in question would have been useful. (3) There also occurs the case in which the usefulness of a rule depends upon conditions likely to change, or of which the change would be as easy and more desirable than the observance of the proposed rule. It may even happen that the general observance of the proposed rule would itself destroy the conditions upon which its utility depends.
If we ask what rules would be useful for the society we live in, it seems possible to show that most of the commonly recognized and practiced rules have definite utility. However, a significant portion of everyday moral advice and social discussions involves promoting rules that are not widely practiced, and for these, it's quite uncertain whether we can ever prove their general usefulness. These proposed rules typically have three main issues. First, (1) the actions they promote are often impossible for most individuals to carry out by their own will. It's common to see actions that can be done if willed grouped with others that depend on having a particular quality, which only a few possess and can't even be acquired. While it might be helpful to point out that those with the necessary qualities should follow these rules, and it would often be ideal for everyone to have this quality, we must understand that when we refer to something as a moral rule or law, we mean it’s something that almost everyone can follow with a bit of willpower, in the societal context it applies to. (2) Sometimes, actions are promoted that, although they are possible, their intended good effects aren’t achievable because the necessary conditions for those effects are not widespread enough. A rule suggested to produce good results, if human nature were different, is presented as if following it would lead to the same immediate effects. In reality, by the time the conditions needed for its usefulness are present, it's just as likely that other conditions that make following the rule unnecessary or even harmful may also come into play; and this situation might be better than the one in which the rule would have been useful. (3) There are also situations where a rule's usefulness relies on conditions that are likely to change, or where changing those conditions would be easier and more desirable than following the proposed rule. It may even be the case that wide adherence to the suggested rule would undermine the very conditions that make it useful.
One or other of these objections seems generally to apply to proposed changes in social custom, advocated as being better rules to follow than those now actually followed; and, for this reason, it seems doubtful whether Ethics can establish the utility of any rules other than those generally practised. But its inability to do so is fortunately of little practical moment. The question whether the general observance of a rule not generally observed, would or would not be desirable, cannot much affect the question how any individual ought to act; since, on the one hand, there is a large probability that he will not, by any means, be able to bring about its general observance, and, on the other hand, the fact that its general observance would be useful could, in any case, give him no reason to conclude that he himself ought to observe it, in the absence of such general observance.
One or another of these objections usually applies to proposed changes in social customs, which are promoted as better rules to follow than those currently in practice; for this reason, it seems questionable whether Ethics can prove the usefulness of any rules other than those commonly practiced. However, its inability to do so is fortunately of little practical significance. The question of whether the widespread observance of a rule that isn't generally followed would be desirable doesn't really impact the question of how any individual should act; on one hand, there's a high chance that they won't be able to make it widely followed, and on the other hand, the fact that its general observance would be beneficial doesn't, in any case, give them a reason to think they should follow it if it's not already commonly observed.
With regard, then, to the actions commonly classed in Ethics, as duties, crimes, or sins, the following points seem deserving of notice. (1) By so classing them we mean that they are actions which it is possible for an individual to perform or avoid, if he only wills to do so; and that they are actions which everybody ought to perform or avoid, when occasion arises. (2) We can certainly not prove of any such action that it ought to be done or avoided under all circumstances; we can only prove that its performance or avoidance will generally produce better results than the alternative. (3) If further we ask of what actions as much as this can be proved, it seems only possible to prove it with regard to those which are actually generally practised among us. And of these some only are such that their general performance would be useful in any state of society that seems[p. 162] possible; of others the utility depends upon conditions which exist now, but which seem to be more or less alterable.
In terms of actions typically classified in Ethics as duties, crimes, or sins, the following points are worth noting. (1) By classifying them this way, we mean that these are actions an individual can choose to do or avoid if they just want to; and that these are actions that everyone should do or avoid when the situation calls for it. (2) We definitely can't prove that any of these actions should be done or avoided under every circumstance; we can only show that doing or not doing them will usually lead to better outcomes than the alternatives. (3) If we further ask which actions can be proven to have this quality, it seems we can only prove it for those actions that are commonly practiced among us. Among these, some are beneficial regardless of the type of society we find ourselves in, while others depend on current conditions that seem to be somewhat changeable.
99. (d) So much, then, for moral rules or laws, in the ordinary sense—rules which assert that it is generally useful, under more or less common circumstances, for everybody to perform or omit some definite kind of action. It remains to say something with regard to the principles by which the individual should decide what he ought to do, (α) with regard to those actions as to which some general rule is certainly true, and (β) with regard to those where such a certain rule is wanting.
99. (d) So much for moral rules or laws in the usual sense—rules that claim it's generally beneficial, in various common situations, for everyone to either do or not do a specific type of action. Next, we need to discuss the principles that an individual should use to determine what they should do, (α) in relation to those actions that are covered by a clear general rule, and (β) regarding those where no definite rule exists.
(α) Since, as I have tried to shew, it is impossible to establish that any kind of action will produce a better total result than its alternative in all cases, it follows that in some cases the neglect of an established rule will probably be the best course of action possible. The question then arises: Can the individual ever be justified in assuming that his is one of these exceptional cases? And it seems that this question may be definitely answered in the negative. For, if it is certain that in a large majority of cases the observance of a certain rule is useful, it follows that there is a large probability that it would be wrong to break the rule in any particular case; and the uncertainty of our knowledge both of effects and of their value, in particular cases, is so great, that it seems doubtful whether the individual’s judgment that the effects will probably be good in his case can ever be set against the general probability that that kind of action is wrong. Added to this general ignorance is the fact that, if the question arises at all, our judgment will generally be biassed by the fact that we strongly desire one of the results which we hope to obtain by breaking the rule. It seems, then, that with regard to any rule which is generally useful, we may assert that it ought always to be observed, not on the ground that in every particular case it will be useful, but on the ground that in any particular case the probability of its being so is greater than that of our being likely to decide rightly that we have before us an instance of its disutility. In short, though we may be sure that there are cases where the rule should be broken, we can never know which those cases are,[p. 163] and ought, therefore, never to break it. It is this fact which seems to justify the stringency with which moral rules are usually enforced and sanctioned, and to give a sense in which we may accept as true the maxims that ‘The end never justifies the means’ and ‘That we should never do evil that good may come.’ The ‘means’ and the ‘evil,’ intended by these maxims, are, in fact, the breaking of moral rules generally recognised and practised, and which, therefore, we may assume to be generally useful. Thus understood, these maxims merely point out that, in any particular case, although we cannot clearly perceive any balance of good produced by keeping the rule and do seem to see one that would follow from breaking it, nevertheless the rule should be observed. It is hardly necessary to point out that this is so only because it is certain that, in general, the end does justify the means in question, and that therefore there is a probability that in this case it will do so also, although we cannot see that it will.
(α) As I've tried to show, it's impossible to prove that any action will always produce a better total result than its alternatives in every situation. This means that in some cases, ignoring an established rule might actually be the best choice. The question then arises: Can an individual ever justifiably think that they are in one of these exceptional cases? It seems the answer is no. If it's clear that in most situations following a certain rule is beneficial, there's a strong chance it would be wrong to break that rule in any specific instance. The uncertainty surrounding our knowledge of the effects and their value in particular situations is so significant that it’s questionable whether an individual’s belief that breaking the rule will likely have positive outcomes can outweigh the general likelihood that such actions are incorrect. On top of this general ignorance, when the question arises, our judgment is often swayed by our strong desire for the outcome we hope to achieve by breaking the rule. Therefore, regarding any rule that is generally useful, we should assert that it ought to always be followed—not because it will be beneficial in every single case, but because the chances of it being beneficial are greater in any given situation compared to the likelihood that we’ll correctly identify a case where breaking it would be justified. In summary, while we can be confident that there are instances where the rule should be broken, we can never know exactly which ones those are, and thus we should never break the rule. This fact seems to justify the strictness with which moral rules are typically enforced and accepted, supporting maxims like ‘The end never justifies the means’ and ‘We should never do evil for good to come from it.’ The ‘means’ and the ‘evil’ referred to by these maxims are essentially the breach of moral rules that are widely recognized and practiced, which we can assume are generally useful. Understood this way, these maxims simply emphasize that even if we can't clearly see the benefits of following the rule and seem to identify potential benefits from breaking it, we should still adhere to the rule. It’s worth noting that this holds true only because it's certain that, generally speaking, the end does justify the means involved, and thus there is a probability that it will do so in this case as well, even if we can’t see that it will.
But moreover the universal observance of a rule which is generally useful has, in many cases, a special utility, which seems deserving of notice. This arises from the fact that, even if we can clearly discern that our case is one where to break the rule is advantageous, yet, so far as our example has any effect at all in encouraging similar action, it will certainly tend to encourage breaches of the rule which are not advantageous. We may confidently assume that what will impress the imagination of others will not be the circumstances in which our case differs from ordinary cases and which justify our exceptional action, but the points in which it resembles other actions that are really criminal. In cases, then, where example has any influence at all, the effect of an exceptional right action will generally be to encourage wrong ones. And this effect will probably be exercised not only on other persons but on the agent himself. For it is impossible for any one to keep his intellect and sentiments so clear, but that, if he has once approved of a generally wrong action, he will be more likely to approve of it also under other circumstances than those which justified it in the first instance. This inability to discriminate exceptional cases offers, of course, a still stronger[p. 164] reason for the universal enforcement, by legal or social sanctions, of actions generally useful. It is undoubtedly well to punish a man, who has done an action, right in his case but generally wrong, even if his example would not be likely to have a dangerous effect. For sanctions have, in general, much more influence upon conduct than example; so that the effect of relaxing them in an exceptional case will almost certainly be an encouragement of similar action in cases which are not exceptional.
But additionally, the widespread following of a rule that is generally helpful has, in many cases, a specific benefit that is worth noting. This comes from the fact that even if we can clearly see that breaking the rule is beneficial in our situation, as far as our example has any effect in promoting similar behavior, it will likely encourage violations of the rule that are not beneficial. We can confidently assume that what will stick in the minds of others will not be the reasons our situation is different from typical cases and justifies our unusual action, but rather the aspects in which it resembles actions that are truly wrong. Therefore, in cases where examples do have any influence, the result of a rare right action will generally be to promote wrong ones. This effect will probably be felt not only by others but also by the person involved. It is impossible for anyone to keep their thoughts and feelings so clear that if they have once accepted a generally wrong action, they will be less likely to accept it again under circumstances other than those that justified it initially. This inability to distinguish exceptional cases provides an even stronger[p. 164] reason for universally enforcing, through legal or social penalties, actions that are generally useful. It is definitely appropriate to punish someone who has done something right in their case but generally wrong, even if their example is unlikely to have a harmful effect. This is because penalties usually have much more influence on behavior than examples; therefore, reducing them in an exceptional situation will almost certainly encourage similar actions in cases that are not exceptional.
The individual can therefore be confidently recommended always to conform to rules which are both generally useful and generally practised. In the case of rules of which the general observance would be useful but does not exist, or of rules which are generally practised but which are not useful, no such universal recommendations can be made. In many cases the sanctions attached may be decisive in favour of conformity to the existing custom. But it seems worth pointing out that, even apart from these, the general utility of an action most commonly depends upon the fact that it is generally practised: in a society where certain kinds of theft are the common rule, the utility of abstinence from such theft on the part of a single individual becomes exceedingly doubtful, even though the common rule is a bad one. There is, therefore, a strong probability in favour of adherence to an existing custom, even if it be a bad one. But we cannot, in this case, assert with any confidence that this probability is always greater than that of the individual’s power to judge that an exception will be useful; since we are here supposing certain one relevant fact—namely, that the rule, which he proposes to follow, would be better than that which he proposes to break, if it were generally observed. Consequently the effect of his example, so far as it tends to break down the existing custom, will here be for the good. The cases, where another rule would certainly be better than that generally observed, are, however, according to what was said above, very rare; and cases of doubt, which are those which arise most frequently, carry us into the next division of our subject.
The individual can therefore be confidently advised always to follow rules that are both generally useful and commonly practiced. In situations where rules would be beneficial but aren't widely observed, or where rules are commonly practiced but not helpful, no such universal recommendations can be made. Often, the consequences tied to these rules may strongly favor sticking to the existing customs. However, it's important to note that, apart from these consequences, the overall usefulness of an action usually depends on how widely it is practiced: in a society where certain types of theft are the norm, the benefit of not stealing as an individual becomes very questionable, even if the common practice is a negative one. Therefore, there's a strong likelihood in favor of adhering to an existing custom, even if it’s a bad one. But we can't confidently say that this likelihood is always greater than the individual's ability to determine that making an exception would be useful; since we are assuming one relevant fact—namely, that the rule they intend to follow would be better than the one they plan to break, if it were generally observed. Thus, the impact of their example, as it aims to challenge the existing custom, will likely be positive. However, according to what was mentioned earlier, cases where another rule is definitely better than the norm are quite rare; and situations of uncertainty, which happen most often, lead us into the next part of our discussion.
100. (β) This next division consists in the discussion of the method by which an individual should decide what to do with regard to possible actions of which the general utility[p. 165] cannot be proved. And it should be observed, that, according to our previous conclusions, this discussion will cover almost all actions, except those which, in our present state of society, are generally practised. For it has been urged that a proof of general utility is so difficult, that it can hardly be conclusive except in a very few cases. It is certainly not possible with regard to all actions which are generally practised; though here, if the sanctions are sufficiently strong, they are sufficient by themselves to prove the general utility of the individual’s conformity to custom. And if it is possible to prove a general utility in the case of some actions, not generally practised, it is certainly not possible to do so by the ordinary method, which tries to shew in them a tendency to that preservation of society, which is itself a mere means, but only by the method, by which in any case, as will be urged, the individual ought to guide his judgment—namely, by shewing their direct tendency to produce what is good in itself or to prevent what is bad.
100. (β) This next section covers how a person should decide what to do concerning potential actions where the overall usefulness cannot be demonstrated. It should be noted that, based on our earlier conclusions, this discussion will address almost all actions, except those commonly practiced in our current society. It has been pointed out that proving general usefulness is so challenging that it is rarely conclusive, except in a few cases. It's definitely not feasible for all actions that are commonly performed; however, if the social pressures are strong enough, they can sufficiently demonstrate the general usefulness of an individual's adherence to societal norms. And while it may be possible to establish general usefulness for some actions that aren't commonly practiced, it certainly can't be done through the usual method that attempts to show their contribution to societal preservation, which is just a means to an end. Instead, it should be done by the method that, as will be argued, the individual should use to shape their judgment—specifically, by demonstrating their direct tendency to promote what is inherently good or to prevent what is bad.
The extreme improbability that any general rule with regard to the utility of an action will be correct seems, in fact, to be the chief principle which should be taken into account in discussing how the individual should guide his choice. If we except those rules which are both generally practised and strongly sanctioned among us, there seem to be hardly any of such a kind that equally good arguments cannot be found both for and against them. The most that can be said for the contradictory principles which are urged by moralists of different schools as universal duties, is, in general, that they point out actions which, for persons of a particular character and in particular circumstances, would and do lead to a balance of good. It is, no doubt, possible that the particular dispositions and circumstances which generally render certain kinds of action advisable, might to some degree be formulated. But it is certain that this has never yet been done; and it is important to notice that, even if it were done, it would not give us, what moral laws are usually supposed to be—rules which it would be desirable for every one, or even for most people, to follow. Moralists commonly assume[p. 166] that, in the matter of actions or habits of action, usually recognised as duties or virtues, it is desirable that every one should be alike. Whereas it is certain that, under actual circumstances, and possible that, even in a much more ideal condition of things, the principle of division of labour, according to special capacity, which is recognised in respect of employments, would also give a better result in respect of virtues.
The extreme unlikelihood that any general rule about the usefulness of an action will be correct seems to be the main principle to consider when discussing how individuals should make their choices. If we exclude those rules that are widely practiced and strongly upheld among us, there seem to be hardly any rules where equally strong arguments can't be found both for and against them. The best that can be said for the conflicting principles put forth by different moralists as universal duties is that they highlight actions which, for people of certain character types and in specific situations, would lead to a good outcome. It's possible that the specific traits and situations that typically make certain actions advisable could be somewhat outlined. However, it's clear that this has never been fully achieved; and it’s important to note that, even if it were achieved, it wouldn't provide us with what moral laws are generally thought to be—rules that everyone, or even most people, should follow. Moralists often assume that when it comes to actions or habits considered duties or virtues, it's desirable for everyone to be the same. Yet, it's clear that, in real circumstances, and potentially in a more ideal situation, the principle of dividing labor based on individual strengths, which is acknowledged in job roles, would also yield better results in terms of virtues.
It seems, therefore, that, in cases of doubt, instead of following rules, of which he is unable to see the good effects in his particular case, the individual should rather guide his choice by a direct consideration of the intrinsic value or vileness of the effects which his action may produce. Judgments of intrinsic value have this superiority over judgments of means that, if once true, they are always true; whereas what is a means to a good effect in one case, will not be so in another. For this reason the department of Ethics, which it would be most useful to elaborate for practical guidance, is that which discusses what things have intrinsic value and in what degrees; and this is precisely that department which has been most uniformly neglected, in favour of attempts to formulate rules of conduct.
It seems, therefore, that in cases of doubt, rather than following rules that he cannot see the positive effects of in his specific situation, a person should guide his choice by directly considering the true value or worthlessness of the outcomes his actions may produce. Judgments of intrinsic value have the advantage over judgments of means because, if they are true once, they are always true; whereas something that is a means to a good effect in one situation may not be in another. For this reason, the area of Ethics that would be most useful for practical guidance is the one that discusses which things have intrinsic value and to what extent; and this is exactly the area that has been most consistently overlooked, in favor of trying to establish rules of conduct.
We have, however, not only to consider the relative goodness of different effects, but also the relative probability of their being attained. A less good, that is more likely to be attained, is to be preferred to a greater, that is less probable, if the difference in probability is great enough to outweigh the difference in goodness. And this fact seems to entitle us to assert the general truth of three principles, which ordinary moral rules are apt to neglect. (1) That a lesser good, for which any individual has a strong preference (if only it be a good, and not an evil), is more likely to be a proper object for him to aim at, than a greater one, which he is unable to appreciate. For natural inclination renders it immensely more easy to attain that for which such inclination is felt. (2) Since almost every one has a much stronger preference for things which closely concern himself, it will in general be right for a man to aim rather at goods affecting himself and those in whom he has a strong personal interest, than to attempt a[p. 167] more extended beneficence. Egoism is undoubtedly superior to Altruism as a doctrine of means: in the immense majority of cases the best thing we can do is to aim at securing some good in which we are concerned, since for that very reason we are far more likely to secure it. (3) Goods, which can be secured in a future so near as to be called ‘the present,’ are in general to be preferred to those which, being in a further future, are, for that reason, far less certain of attainment. If we regard all that we do from the point of view of its rightness, that is to say as a mere means to good, we are apt to neglect one fact, at least, which is certain; namely, that a thing that is really good in itself, if it exist now, has precisely the same value as a thing of the same kind which may be caused to exist in the future. Moreover moral rules, as has been said, are, in general, not directly means to positive goods but to what is necessary for the existence of positive goods; and so much of our labour must in any case be devoted to securing the continuance of what is thus a mere means—the claims of industry and attention to health determine the employment of so large a part of our time, that, in cases where choice is open, the certain attainment of a present good will in general have the strongest claims upon us. If it were not so, the whole of life would be spent in merely assuring its continuance; and, so far as the same rule were continued in the future, that for the sake of which it is worth having, would never exist at all.
We need to consider not only how good different outcomes are but also how likely we are to achieve them. A less desirable outcome that is more likely to happen should be preferred over a better one that is less probable, especially if the difference in likelihood is enough to outweigh the difference in quality. This leads us to recognize the validity of three principles that common moral guidelines often overlook. (1) A smaller good that someone strongly prefers (as long as it is, indeed, a good and not an evil) is generally a better target for that person than a larger good that they cannot appreciate. Natural inclination makes it much easier to achieve what we are drawn to. (2) Since most people prefer things that directly involve them more intensely, it is usually right for someone to focus on goods that affect them and those they care about rather than trying to help a wider range of people. Egoism is undeniably a more effective guiding principle than Altruism: in most cases, the best thing we can do is to pursue a good that matters to us because we are more likely to achieve it. (3) Goods that can be realized in the near future, what we might call 'the present,' are generally more desirable than those farther off, which are less certain to be attained. When we assess our actions solely based on their rightness, viewing them merely as a means to achieve good, we tend to overlook a key fact: something that is genuinely good in itself, if it exists now, holds the same value as the same type of good that could exist in the future. Furthermore, moral rules, as mentioned earlier, are generally not direct means to positive goods but rather to what is necessary for those goods to exist. A significant portion of our efforts must be devoted to ensuring the continuation of these merely necessary means—our commitments to work and health take up a large part of our time, meaning that when we have the option to choose, the reliable achievement of a present good will likely take priority. If this weren't the case, life would be consumed with just maintaining existence, and if this tendency continued into the future, the very goods that make life worth living would never come to be.
101. (4) A fourth conclusion, which follows from the fact that what is ‘right’ or what is our ‘duty’ must in any case be defined as what is a means to good, is, as was pointed out above (§ 89), that the common distinction between these and the ‘expedient’ or ‘useful,’ disappears. Our ‘duty’ is merely that which will be a means to the best possible, and the expedient, if it is really expedient, must be just the same. We cannot distinguish them by saying that the former is something which we ought to do, whereas of the latter we cannot say we ‘ought.’ In short the two concepts are not, as is commonly assumed by all except Utilitarian moralists, simple concepts ultimately distinct. There is no such distinction in[p. 168] Ethics. The only fundamental distinction is between what is good in itself and what is good as a means, the latter of which implies the former. But it has been shewn that the distinction between ‘duty’ and ‘expediency’ does not correspond to this: both must be defined as means to good, though both may also be ends in themselves. The question remains, then: What is the distinction between duty and expediency?
101. (4) A fourth conclusion, which comes from the fact that what is 'right' or what is our 'duty' has to be defined as a means to good, is, as mentioned earlier (§ 89), that the usual difference between these and the 'expedient' or 'useful' disappears. Our 'duty' is simply what will lead to the best possible outcome, and the expedient, if it is truly expedient, must be the same. We can't separate them by saying that the former is something we should do, while we can't say we ' ought ' for the latter. In short, the two ideas are not, as most people think except for Utilitarian moralists, fundamentally different concepts. There is no such distinction in[p. 168] Ethics. The only key difference is between what is good in itself and what is good as a means, with the latter implying the former. However, it has been shown that the difference between 'duty' and 'expediency' doesn't match this: both must be defined as means to good, though both may also be ends in themselves. The question remains: What is the difference between duty and expediency?
One distinction to which these distinct words refer is plain enough. Certain classes of action commonly excite the specifically moral sentiments, whereas other classes do not. And the word ‘duty’ is commonly applied only to the class of actions which excite moral approval, or of which the omission excites moral disapproval—especially to the latter. Why this moral sentiment should have become attached to some kinds of actions and not to others is a question which can certainly not yet be answered; but it may be observed that we have no reason to think that the actions to which it was attached were or are, in all cases, such as aided or aid the survival of a race: it was probably originally attached to many religious rites and ceremonies which had not the smallest utility in this respect. It appears, however, that, among us, the classes of action to which it is attached also have two other characteristics in enough cases to have influenced the meaning of the words ‘duty’ and ‘expediency.’ One of these is that ‘duties’ are, in general, actions which a considerable number of individuals are strongly tempted to omit. The second is that the omission of a ‘duty’ generally entails consequences markedly disagreeable to some one else. The first of these is a more universal characteristic than the second: since the disagreeable effects on other people of the ‘self-regarding duties,’ prudence and temperance, are not so marked as those on the future of the agent himself; whereas the temptations to imprudence and intemperance are very strong. Still, on the whole, the class of actions called duties exhibit both characteristics: they are not only actions, against the performance of which there are strong natural inclinations, but also actions of which the most obvious effects, commonly considered goods, are effects on other people. Expedient actions, on the other hand, are actions to[p. 169] which strong natural inclinations prompt us almost universally, and of which all the most obvious effects, commonly considered good, are effects upon the agent. We may then roughly distinguish ‘duties’ from expedient actions, as actions with regard to which there is a moral sentiment, which we are often tempted to omit, and of which the most obvious effects are effects upon others than the agent.
One clear distinction that these different words refer to is straightforward. Certain types of actions usually trigger specific moral feelings, while others do not. The term ‘duty’ is typically used only for actions that generate moral approval, or whose absence leads to moral disapproval—especially the latter. The reason why some actions have become associated with these moral sentiments and others have not is a question that remains unanswered; however, we have no reason to believe that the actions tied to these sentiments were or are always beneficial for the survival of a group. They were likely originally linked to many religious rites and ceremonies that had no practical utility in this regard. It seems that, among us, the actions classified as duties also tend to share two additional characteristics frequently enough to have shaped the meanings of the words ‘duty’ and ‘expediency.’ One of these is that ‘duties’ generally involve actions that many individuals are strongly tempted to avoid. The second is that neglecting a ‘duty’ usually leads to consequences that are notably unpleasant for someone else. The first characteristic is more universal than the second: since the negative effects of the ‘self-regarding duties,’ such as prudence and temperance, are not as pronounced as those on the agent's future; however, the temptations to be imprudent and intemperate are quite strong. Nonetheless, overall, actions classified as duties display both traits: they are not only actions against which there is strong natural inclination, but also actions whose most obvious impacts, commonly seen as positive, are on other people. On the flip side, expedient actions are those to[p. 169] which strong natural inclinations almost universally drive us, and whose most obvious effects, generally viewed as good, concern the agent themselves. We can then roughly differentiate ‘duties’ from expedient actions, viewing duties as actions associated with a moral sentiment, which we are often tempted to avoid, and whose most evident effects are on others rather than the agent.
But it is to be noticed that none of these characteristics, by which a ‘duty’ is distinguished from an expedient action, gives us any reason to infer that the former class of actions are more useful than the latter—that they tend to produce a greater balance of good. Nor, when we ask the question, ‘Is this my duty?’ do we mean to ask whether the action in question has these characteristics: we are asking simply whether it will produce the best possible result on the whole. And if we asked this question with regard to expedient actions, we should quite as often have to answer it in the affirmative as when we ask it with regard to actions which have the three characteristics of ‘duties.’ It is true that when we ask the question, ‘Is this expedient?’ we are asking a different question—namely, whether it will have certain kinds of effect, with regard to which we do not enquire whether they are good or not. Nevertheless, if it should be doubted in any particular case whether these effects were good, this doubt is understood as throwing doubt upon the action’s expediency: if we are required to prove an action’s expediency, we can only do so by asking precisely the same question by which we should prove it a duty—namely, ‘Has it the best possible effects on the whole?’
But it's important to note that none of the characteristics that differentiate a 'duty' from an expedient action give us any reason to believe that the first group of actions is more useful than the second—that they result in a greater overall good. When we ask the question, 'Is this my duty?' we are not inquiring whether the action has these characteristics; we are simply asking if it will lead to the best possible outcome overall. If we asked this question regarding expedient actions, we would often end up answering it positively just as frequently as when we ask it about actions that have the three characteristics of 'duties.' It’s true that when we ask, 'Is this expedient?' we are asking a different question—specifically, whether it will have certain types of effects, without considering if those effects are good or bad. However, if there is any uncertainty in a specific case about whether those effects are good, that doubt is seen as questioning the action's expediency. If we need to prove an action's expediency, we can only do so by posing the same question that would determine if it is a duty—namely, 'Does it have the best possible effects overall?'
Accordingly the question whether an action is a duty or merely expedient, is one which has no bearing on the ethical question whether we ought to do it. In the sense in which either duty or expediency are taken as ultimate reasons for doing an action, they are taken in exactly the same sense: if I ask whether an action is really my duty or really expedient, the predicate of which I question the applicability to the action in question is precisely the same. In both cases I am asking, ‘Is this event the best on the whole that I can effect?’; and[p. 170] whether the event in question be some effect upon what is mine (as it usually is, where we talk of expediency) or some other event (as is usual, where we talk of duty), this distinction has no more relevance to my answer than the distinction between two different effects on me or two different effects on others. The true distinction between duties and expedient actions is not that the former are actions which it is in any sense more useful or obligatory or better to perform, but that they are actions which it is more useful to praise and to enforce by sanctions, since they are actions which there is a temptation to omit.
So, the question of whether an action is a duty or just practical doesn’t really affect the ethical question of whether we should do it. In the context where duty and practicality are seen as ultimate reasons for taking an action, they are considered in exactly the same way: if I ask whether an action is really my duty or really practical, I'm questioning the same concept's relevance to the action at hand. In both cases, I’m asking, ‘Is this the best overall outcome I can achieve?’; and[p. 170] whether that outcome is something that affects what is mine (as is often the case when we discuss practicality) or some other outcome (as is typical when we talk about duty), this distinction doesn’t impact my answer any more than the difference between two distinct outcomes for myself or for others. The real difference between duties and practical actions isn’t that the former are inherently more useful, obligatory, or better to carry out, but that they are actions that it’s more beneficial to commend and enforce with consequences because they are actions people are tempted to skip.
102. With regard to ‘interested’ actions, the case is somewhat different. When we ask the question, ‘Is this really to my interest?’ we appear to be asking exclusively whether its effects upon me are the best possible; and it may well happen that what will effect me in the manner, which is really the best possible, will not produce the best possible results on the whole. Accordingly my true interest may be different from the course which is really expedient and dutiful. To assert that an action is ‘to my interest,’ is, indeed, as was pointed out in Chap. III. (§§ 59-61), to assert that its effects are really good. ‘My own good’ only denotes some event affecting me, which is good absolutely and objectively; it is the thing, and not its goodness, which is mine; everything must be either ‘a part of universal good’ or else not good at all; there is no third alternative conception ‘good for me.’ But ‘my interest,’ though it must be something truly good, is only one among possible good effects; and hence, by effecting it, though we shall be doing some good, we may be doing less good on the whole, than if we had acted otherwise. Self-sacrifice may be a real duty; just as the sacrifice of any single good, whether affecting ourselves or others, may be necessary in order to obtain a better total result. Hence the fact that an action is really to my interest, can never be a sufficient reason for doing it: by shewing that it is not a means to the best possible, we do not shew that it is not to my interest, as we do shew that it is not expedient. Nevertheless there is no necessary conflict between duty and interest: what is to my interest may also be a means to the best possible.[p. 171] And the chief distinction conveyed by the distinct words ‘duty’ and ‘interest’ seems to be not this source of possible conflict, but the same which is conveyed by the contrast between ‘duty’ and ‘expediency.’ By ‘interested’ actions are mainly meant those which, whether a means to the best possible or not, are such as have their most obvious effects on the agent; which he generally has no temptation to omit; and with regard to which we feel no moral sentiment. That is to say, the distinction is not primarily ethical. Here too ‘duties’ are not, in general, more useful or obligatory than interested actions; they are only actions which it is more useful to praise.
102. When it comes to ‘interested’ actions, the situation is a bit different. When we ask, ‘Is this really in my best interest?’ it seems like we’re only considering whether its impact on me is the best it can be. It's possible that what impacts me in the best way might not lead to the best overall outcome. Therefore, my true interest could differ from what is actually the right and sensible choice. To say that an action is ‘in my interest’ really means that its effects are genuinely positive. ‘My own good’ simply refers to something happening to me that is good in an absolute and objective sense; it's the thing itself, not its goodness, that is mine; everything must either be ‘part of the universal good’ or not good at all; there is no third option of ‘good for me.’ However, ‘my interest,’ while it must be something genuinely good, is just one of many potential good outcomes; thus, by pursuing it, we might be doing some good, but we may be doing less overall good compared to other choices. Self-sacrifice can be a real duty; similar to how sacrificing any single good, whether it affects us or others, may be essential for achieving a better total outcome. So, the fact that an action is genuinely in my interest can never be a sufficient reason to do it: showing that it is not a pathway to the best possible outcome doesn’t prove it isn’t in my interest, unlike showing that it's not practical. Still, there doesn't have to be a conflict between duty and interest: what’s in my interest can also be a way to achieve the best possible outcome.[p. 171] The main distinction between the terms ‘duty’ and ‘interest’ seems to reflect not this potential conflict but rather the same contrast between ‘duty’ and ‘expediency.’ ‘Interested’ actions mainly refer to those that, regardless of whether they are a means to the best possible outcome, have effects that are most apparent to the person taking the action; they usually don’t have any temptation to skip these actions; and in relation to them, we don’t feel any moral obligation. In other words, this distinction isn’t primarily ethical. In this context, ‘duties’ are generally not more beneficial or obligatory than interested actions; they are just actions that are more often praised.
103. (5) A fifth conclusion, of some importance, in relation to Practical Ethics concerns the manner in which ‘virtues’ are to be judged. What is meant by calling a thing a ‘virtue’?
103. (5) A fifth conclusion, which is somewhat significant, regarding Practical Ethics focuses on how ‘virtues’ are evaluated. What does it mean to label something as a ‘virtue’?
There can be no doubt that Aristotle’s definition is right, in the main, so far as he says that it is an ‘habitual disposition’ to perform certain actions: this is one of the marks by which we should distinguish a virtue from other things. But ‘virtue’ and ‘vice’ are also ethical terms: that is to say, when we use them seriously, we mean to convey praise by the one and dispraise by the other. And to praise a thing is to assert either that it is good in itself or else that it is a means to good. Are we then to include in our definition of virtue that it must be a thing good in itself?
There’s no doubt that Aristotle’s definition is mostly correct when he says that virtue is a ‘habitual disposition’ to perform certain actions; this is one of the key ways we should differentiate virtue from other qualities. However, ‘virtue’ and ‘vice’ are also ethical terms. This means that when we use them seriously, we intend to express approval with one and disapproval with the other. To praise something is to assert that it is either good in itself or a means to something good. Should we then include in our definition of virtue that it must be inherently good?
Now it is certain that virtues are commonly regarded as good in themselves. The feeling of moral approbation with which we generally regard them partly consists in an attribution to them of intrinsic value. Even a Hedonist, when he feels a moral sentiment towards them, is regarding them as good-in-themselves; and Virtue has been the chief competitor with Pleasure for the position of sole good. Nevertheless I do not think we can regard it as part of the definition of virtue that it should be good in itself. For the name has so far an independent meaning, that if in any particular case a disposition commonly considered virtuous were proved not to be good in itself, we should not think that a sufficient reason for saying that it was not a virtue but was only thought to be so. The test for the ethical connotation of virtue is the same as that for duty:[p. 172] What should we require to be proved about a particular instance, in order to say that the name was wrongly applied to it? And the test which is thus applied both to virtues and duties, and considered to be final, is the question: Is it a means to good? If it could be shewn of any particular disposition, commonly considered virtuous, that it was generally harmful, we should at once say: Then it is not really virtuous. Accordingly a virtue may be defined as an habitual disposition to perform certain actions, which generally produce the best possible results. Nor is there any doubt as to the kind of actions which it is ‘virtuous’ habitually to perform. They are, in general, those which are duties, with this modification that we also include those which would be duties, if only it were possible for people in general to perform them. Accordingly with regard to virtues, the same conclusion holds as with regard to duties. If they are really virtues they must be generally good as means; nor do I wish to dispute that most virtues, commonly considered as such, as well as most duties, really are means to good. But it does not follow that they are a bit more useful than those dispositions and inclinations which lead us to perform interested actions. As duties from expedient actions, so virtues are distinguished from other useful dispositions, not by any superior utility, but by the fact that they are dispositions, which it is particularly useful to praise and to sanction, because there are strong and common temptations to neglect the actions to which they lead.
Now it’s clear that virtues are generally seen as good in their own right. The moral approval we feel towards them partly comes from the belief that they have intrinsic value. Even a Hedonist, when experiencing a moral sentiment about them, views them as good in themselves; and Virtue has been the main rival to Pleasure for the title of sole good. Still, I don’t think we can define virtue as needing to be good in itself. The term has an independent meaning so that if a particular trait commonly seen as virtuous were shown not to be good in itself, we wouldn’t say it wasn’t a virtue but just thought to be one. The test for the ethical meaning of virtue is the same as for duty: [p. 172] What do we need to prove about a specific situation to say the name was applied incorrectly? The test applied to both virtues and duties, and which is seen as conclusive, is the question: Is it a means to good? If it could be shown that any trait, typically considered virtuous, was generally harmful, we would immediately say: Then it’s not truly virtuous. Thus, a virtue can be defined as a habitual tendency to perform certain actions that usually lead to the best outcomes. There’s no doubt about the types of actions that are ‘virtuous’ to habitually perform. They are generally those that are duties, with the addition that we also include actions that would be duties if it were possible for most people to carry them out. Therefore, the same conclusion applies to virtues as it does to duties. If they are truly virtues, they must generally be good means; and I don’t want to argue that most virtues, usually considered as such, along with most duties, genuinely are means to good. But that doesn’t mean they’re any more useful than the traits and inclinations that lead us to act out of self-interest. Just as duties differ from expedient actions, virtues are distinguished from other useful dispositions, not by any greater usefulness, but by the fact that they are traits particularly worth praising and supporting, because there are strong and common temptations to overlook the actions they encourage.
Virtues, therefore, are habitual dispositions to perform actions which are duties, or which would be duties if a volition were sufficient on the part of most men to ensure their performance. And duties are a particular class of those actions, of which the performance has, at least generally, better total results than the omission. They are, that is to say, actions generally good as means: but not all such actions are duties; the name is confined to that particular class which it is often difficult to perform, because there are strong temptations to the contrary. It follows that in order to decide whether any particular disposition or action is a virtue or a duty, we must face all the difficulties enumerated in section (3) of this chapter.[p. 173] We shall not be entitled to assert that any disposition or action is a virtue or duty except as a result of an investigation, such as was there described. We must be able to prove that the disposition or action in question is generally better as a means than any alternatives possible and likely to occur; and this we shall only be able to prove for particular states of society: what is a virtue or a duty in one state of society may not be so in another.
Virtues are therefore habitual tendencies to take actions that are considered duties, or that would be duties if most people were motivated enough to carry them out. Duties are a specific category of actions that generally lead to better overall outcomes than choosing not to do them. These actions are typically good means to an end, but not all good actions qualify as duties; the term is reserved for those specific actions that are often difficult to do because there are strong temptations to do the opposite. Thus, to determine if a specific disposition or action is a virtue or a duty, we need to address all the challenges outlined in section (3) of this chapter.[p. 173] We can't claim that any disposition or action is a virtue or duty without conducting an investigation like the one described earlier. We must be able to demonstrate that the disposition or action is generally a better option than any likely alternatives, and we can only prove this under certain social conditions: what qualifies as a virtue or duty in one society may not apply in another.
104. But there is another question with regard to virtues and duties which must be settled by intuition alone—by the properly guarded method which was explained in discussing Hedonism. This is the question whether the dispositions and actions, commonly regarded (rightly or not) as virtues or duties, are good in themselves; whether they have intrinsic value. Virtue or the exercise of virtue has very commonly been asserted by moralists to be either the sole good, or, at least, the best of goods. Indeed, so far as moralists have discussed the question what is good in itself at all, they have generally assumed that it must be either virtue or pleasure. It would hardly have been possible that such a gross difference of opinion should exist, or that it should have been assumed the discussion must be limited to two such alternatives, if the meaning of the question had been clearly apprehended. And we have already seen that the meaning of the question has hardly ever been clearly apprehended. Almost all ethical writers have committed the naturalistic fallacy—they have failed to perceive that the notion of intrinsic value is simple and unique; and almost all have failed, in consequence, to distinguish clearly between means and end—they have discussed, as if it were simple and unambiguous, the question, ‘What ought we to do?’ or ‘What ought to exist now?’ without distinguishing whether the reason why a thing ought to be done or to exist now, is that it is itself possessed of intrinsic value, or that it is a means to what has intrinsic value. We shall, therefore, be prepared to find that virtue has as little claim to be considered the sole or chief good as pleasure; more especially after seeing that, so far as definition goes, to call a thing a virtue is merely to declare that it is a means to good. The advocates of virtue have, we shall see, this superiority over the Hedonists, that[p. 174] inasmuch as virtues are very complex mental facts, there are included in them many things which are good in themselves and good in a much higher degree than pleasure. The advocates of Hedonism, on the other hand, have the superiority that their method emphasizes the distinction between means and ends; although they have not apprehended the distinction clearly enough to perceive that the special ethical predicate, which they assign to pleasure as not being a mere means, must also apply to many other things.
104. But there's another question about virtues and duties that can only be answered through intuition—the careful approach we discussed when looking at Hedonism. This question is whether the traits and actions typically seen (whether correctly or not) as virtues or duties are inherently good; whether they have intrinsic value. Many moralists have claimed that virtue or the practice of virtue is either the only good or at least the highest good. In fact, whenever moralists have tackled the question of what is good in itself, they’ve generally assumed it must be either virtue or pleasure. It’s hard to believe that such a stark difference of opinion could exist or that people would think the discussion had to be restricted to just these two options, if the question’s meaning had been clearly understood. And we've already seen that the meaning of the question is rarely clear. Almost all ethical writers have fallen into the naturalistic fallacy—they haven’t recognized that the idea of intrinsic value is straightforward and unique; and almost all have failed to distinguish clearly between means and ends—they've debated, as if it were simple and clear-cut, the question, ‘What should we do?’ or ‘What should exist now?’ without clarifying whether the reason something should be done or exist now is that it has intrinsic value itself or because it’s a means to something that has intrinsic value. Thus, we should expect to find that virtue is just as unlikely to be considered the sole or main good as pleasure is; especially after realizing that, in terms of definition, calling something a virtue just means saying that it’s a means to what’s good. We will see that supporters of virtue have this advantage over the Hedonists: because virtues are very complex mental constructs, they include many elements that are good in themselves and even better than pleasure. On the other hand, Hedonists have the advantage that their method highlights the difference between means and ends; although they haven’t quite grasped that the specific ethical quality they attribute to pleasure as not being merely a means must also apply to many other things.
105. With regard, then, to the intrinsic value of virtue, it may be stated broadly: (1) that the majority of dispositions, which we call by that name, and which really do conform to the definition, so far as that they are dispositions generally valuable as means, at least in our society, have no intrinsic value whatever; and (2) that no one element which is contained in the minority, nor even all the different elements put together, can without gross absurdity be regarded as the sole good. As to the second point it may be observed that even those who hold the view that the sole good is to be found in virtue, almost invariably hold other views contradictory of this, owing chiefly to a failure to analyse the meaning of ethical concepts. The most marked instance of this inconsistency is to be found in the common Christian conception that virtue, though the sole good, can yet be rewarded by something other than virtue. Heaven is commonly considered as the reward of virtue; and yet it is also commonly considered, that, in order to be such a reward, it must contain some element, called happiness, which is certainly not completely identical with the mere exercise of those virtues which it rewards. But if so, then something which is not virtue must be either good in itself or an element in what has most intrinsic value. It is not commonly observed that if a thing is really to be a reward, it must be something good in itself: it is absurd to talk of rewarding a person by giving him something, which is less valuable than what he already has or which has no value at all. Thus Kant’s view that virtue renders us worthy of happiness is in flagrant contradiction with the view, which he implies and which is associated with his name, that a Good Will is the only thing having intrinsic value. It[p. 175] does not, indeed, entitle us to make the charge sometimes made, that Kant is, inconsistently, an Eudaemonist or Hedonist: for it does not imply that happiness is the sole good. But it does imply that the Good Will is not the sole good: that a state of things in which we are both virtuous and happy is better in itself than one in which the happiness is absent.
105. Regarding the inherent value of virtue, it can be broadly stated: (1) that most traits we refer to as virtues, which fit the definition, typically serve as valuable means in our society but have no intrinsic value; and (2) that no single element within the few that do can, without extreme absurdity, be viewed as the sole good. Concerning the second point, it's noted that even those who believe that virtue is the only good often hold contradictory views, primarily due to a failure to analyze ethical concepts. A prominent example of this inconsistency is found in the common Christian belief that virtue is the sole good, yet it can still be rewarded with something other than virtue. Heaven is often seen as the reward for virtue; however, it is also typically thought that to serve as a reward, it must include an element called happiness, which is not entirely the same as simply practicing the virtues it acknowledges. If that’s the case, then what is not virtue must be either good in itself or part of what holds the most intrinsic value. It is rarely noted that if something is truly to be a reward, it must be good in itself: it's absurd to say we're rewarding someone by giving them something less valuable than what they already have or that has no value at all. Thus, Kant's idea that virtue makes us worthy of happiness contradicts his implication, associated with his name, that a Good Will is the only thing with intrinsic value. This doesn’t unjustly support the claim that Kant is inconsistently a Eudaemonist or Hedonist, as it doesn’t suggest that happiness is the sole good. However, it does imply that the Good Will is not the only good: that a situation where we are both virtuous and happy is objectively better than one where happiness is absent.
106. In order, however, justly to consider the claims of virtue to intrinsic value, it is necessary to distinguish several very different mental states, all of which fall under the general definition that they are habitual dispositions to perform duties. We may thus distinguish three very different states, all of which are liable to be confused with one another, upon each of which different moral systems have laid great stress, and for each of which the claim has been made that it alone constitutes virtue, and, by implication, that it is the sole good. We may first of all distinguish between (a) that permanent characteristic of mind, which consists in the fact that the performance of duty has become in the strict sense a habit, like many of the operations performed in the putting on of clothes, and (b) that permanent characteristic, which consists in the fact that what may be called good motives habitually help to cause the performance of duties. And in the second division we may distinguish between the habitual tendency to be actuated by one motive, namely, the desire to do duty for duty’s sake, and all other motives, such as love, benevolence, etc. We thus get the three kinds of virtue, of which we are now to consider the intrinsic value.
106. To fairly evaluate the claims of virtue as having intrinsic value, it's important to identify several distinct mental states, all of which can be generally defined as habitual tendencies to fulfill responsibilities. We can differentiate three very distinct states that are often confused with one another, each of which different moral systems have emphasized, and for each of which the argument has been made that it alone represents virtue, implying that it is the only good. First, we can distinguish between (a) a lasting mental characteristic where fulfilling duty has become a true habit, similar to how we automatically put on clothes, and (b) a lasting characteristic where good motives consistently drive the fulfillment of duties. In the second category, we can identify the habitual inclination to be motivated by one specific reason, namely, the desire to fulfill duty for its own sake, as opposed to other motives like love or kindness. This gives us the three types of virtue that we will now examine for their intrinsic value.
(a) There is no doubt that a man’s character may be such that he habitually performs certain duties, without the thought ever occurring to him, when he wills them, either that they are duties or that any good will result from them. Of such a man we cannot and do not refuse to say that he possesses the virtue consisting in the disposition to perform those duties. I, for instance, am honest in the sense that I habitually abstain from any of the actions legally qualified as thieving, even where some other persons would be strongly tempted to commit them. It would be grossly contrary to common usage to deny that, for this reason, I really have the virtue of honesty: it is quite certain that I have an habitual disposition to perform a duty.[p. 176] And that as many people as possible should have a like disposition is, no doubt, of great utility: it is good as a means. Yet I may safely assert that neither my various performances of this duty, nor my disposition to perform them, have the smallest intrinsic value. It is because the majority of instances of virtue seem to be of this nature, that we may venture to assert that virtues have, in general, no intrinsic value whatsoever. And there seems good reason to think that the more generally they are of this nature the more useful they are; since a great economy of labour is effected when a useful action becomes habitual or instinctive. But to maintain that a virtue, which includes no more than this, is good in itself is a gross absurdity. And of this gross absurdity, it may be observed, the Ethics of Aristotle is guilty. For his definition of virtue does not exclude a disposition to perform actions in this way, whereas his descriptions of the particular virtues plainly include such actions: that an action, in order to exhibit virtue, must be done τοῦ καλοῦ ἕνεκα is a qualification which he allows often to drop out of sight. And, on the other hand, he seems certainly to regard the exercise of all virtues as an end in itself. His treatment of Ethics is indeed, in the most important points, highly unsystematic and confused, owing to his attempt to base it on the naturalistic fallacy; for strictly we should be obliged by his words to regard θεωρία as the only thing good in itself, in which case the goodness which he attributes to the practical virtues cannot be intrinsic value; while on the other hand he does not seem to regard it merely as utility, since he makes no attempt to shew that they are means to θεωρία. But there seems no doubt that on the whole he regards the exercise of the practical virtues as a good of the same kind as (i.e. having intrinsic value), only in a less degree than, θεωρία; so that he cannot avoid the charge that he recommends as having intrinsic value, such instances of the exercise of virtue as we are at present discussing—instances of a disposition to perform actions which, in the modern phrase, have merely an ‘external rightness.’ That he is right in applying the word ‘virtue’ to such a disposition cannot be doubted. But the protest against the view that ‘external rightness’ is sufficient to constitute either ‘duty’ or ‘virtue’—a protest which is[p. 177] commonly, and with some justice, attributed as a merit to Christian morals—seems, in the main, to be a mistaken way of pointing out an important truth: namely, that where there is only ‘external rightness’ there is certainly no intrinsic value. It is commonly assumed (though wrongly) that to call a thing a virtue means that it has intrinsic value: and on this assumption the view that virtue does not consist in a mere disposition to do externally right actions does really constitute an advance in ethical truth beyond the Ethics of Aristotle. The inference that, if virtue includes in its meaning ‘good in itself,’ then Aristotle’s definition of virtue is not adequate and expresses a false ethical judgment, is perfectly correct: only the premiss that virtue does include this in its meaning is mistaken.
(a) There's no doubt that a person's character can be such that they routinely carry out certain duties without ever thinking about whether they are, in fact, duties or if any good might come from them. We can't deny that this person has the virtue of being inclined to do those duties. For example, I'm honest in that I always refrain from actions that are legally considered theft, even when others might feel a strong temptation to commit those acts. It would be totally absurd to deny that, for this reason, I genuinely possess the virtue of honesty; it's clear that I have a habitual tendency to fulfill a duty.[p. 176] And it's certainly very beneficial for as many people as possible to share a similar tendency: it's good as a means to an end. However, I can confidently say that neither my actions in fulfilling this duty nor my inclination to do so have any intrinsic value. Because many examples of virtue seem to fit this description, we might reasonably conclude that virtues, in general, lack any intrinsic value. Furthermore, it seems logical to believe that the more common these types of virtues are, the more useful they are; since a significant efficiency in effort occurs when a useful action becomes habitual or instinctive. But to argue that a virtue, which consists solely of this, is inherently good is an outright absurdity. And this gross absurdity can be found in Aristotle's Ethics. His definition of virtue doesn’t eliminate a tendency to perform actions in this manner, while his descriptions of particular virtues clearly include such actions: he often neglects the requirement that an action must be done for the sake of the good (τοῦ καλοῦ ἕνεκα) to truly exhibit virtue. On the flip side, he seems to definitely view the exercise of all virtues as an end in itself. His approach to Ethics is, in many key aspects, highly disorganized and unclear, stemming from his effort to ground it in the naturalistic fallacy; because strictly speaking, his words would imply that θεωρία is the only thing that is good in itself, making any goodness he attributes to the practical virtues not of intrinsic value. Yet, he doesn’t seem to consider it merely utility, since he makes no attempt to show that they serve as means to θεωρία. However, it's clear that overall, he considers the practice of practical virtues to be a good of a similar nature to θεωρία (i.e., having intrinsic value), just to a lesser extent; thereby inviting the charge that he endorses as intrinsically valuable such examples of virtue as we are currently discussing—examples of a tendency to perform actions which, in modern terms, only have an ‘external rightness.’ There’s no doubt that he is correct to label such a tendency as ‘virtue.’ However, the challenge to the idea that ‘external rightness’ is sufficient to establish either ‘duty’ or ‘virtue’—a challenge often, and somewhat justifiably, credited to Christian morals—appears largely to miss the mark in highlighting an important truth: namely, that where there is only ‘external rightness,’ there is certainly no intrinsic value. It is commonly assumed (though incorrectly) that calling something a virtue implies it has intrinsic value: on this assumption, the belief that virtue does not consist solely in a tendency to perform externally right actions indeed represents a progression in ethical truth compared to the Ethics of Aristotle. The conclusion that, if virtue implies ‘good in itself,’ then Aristotle’s definition of virtue is inadequate and reflects a flawed ethical judgment, is entirely valid; only the premise that virtue does include this in its meaning is mistaken.
107. (b) A man’s character may be such that, when he habitually performs a particular duty, there is, in each case of his performance, present in his mind, a love of some intrinsically good consequence which he expects to produce by his action or a hatred of some intrinsically evil consequence which he hopes to prevent by it. In such a case this love or hatred will generally be part cause of his action, and we may then call it one of his motives. Where such a feeling as this is present habitually in the performance of duties, it cannot be denied that the state of the man’s mind, in performing it, contains something intrinsically good. Nor can it be denied that, where a disposition to perform duties consists in the disposition to be moved to them by such feelings, we call that disposition a virtue. Here, therefore, we have instances of virtue, the exercise of which really contains something that is good in itself. And, in general, we may say that wherever a virtue does consist in a disposition to have certain motives, the exercise of that virtue may be intrinsically good; although the degree of its goodness may vary indefinitely according to the precise nature of the motives and their objects. In so far, then, as Christianity tends to emphasize the importance of motives, of the ‘inward’ disposition with which a right action is done, we may say that it has done a service to Ethics. But it should be noticed that, when Christian Ethics, as represented by the New Testament, are praised for[p. 178] this, two distinctions of the utmost importance, which they entirely neglect, are very commonly overlooked. In the first place the New Testament is largely occupied with continuing the tradition of the Hebrew prophets, by recommending such virtues as ‘justice’ and ‘mercy’ as against mere ritual observances; and, in so far as it does this, it is recommending virtues which may be merely good as means, exactly like the Aristotelian virtues. This characteristic of its teaching must therefore be rigorously distinguished from that which consists in its enforcement of such a view as that to be angry without a cause is as bad as actually to commit murder. And, in the second place, though the New Testament does praise some things which are only good as means, and others which are good in themselves, it entirely fails to recognise this distinction. Though the state of the man who is angry may be really as bad in itself as that of the murderer, and so far Christ may be right, His language would lead us to suppose that it is also as bad in every way, that it also causes as much evil: and this is utterly false. In short, when Christian Ethics approves, it does not distinguish whether its approval asserts ‘This is a means to good’ or ‘This is good in itself’; and hence it both praises things merely good as means, as if they were good in themselves, and things merely good in themselves as if they were also good as means. Moreover it should be noticed, that if Christian Ethics does draw attention to those elements in virtues which are good in themselves, it is by no means alone in this. The Ethics of Plato are distinguished by upholding, far more clearly and consistently than any other system, the view that intrinsic value belongs exclusively to those states of mind which consist in love of what is good or hatred of what is evil.
107. (b) A person's character can be such that, when they regularly perform a specific duty, there is in their mind, each time they act, a love for some good outcome they expect to achieve or a dislike for some bad outcome they hope to avoid. In this case, this love or dislike typically acts as a reason for their action, and we can call it one of their motives. When such feelings are consistently present while performing duties, it cannot be denied that the person's mindset during the action contains something inherently good. It is also true that when a person's tendency to fulfill duties is driven by these feelings, we refer to that tendency as a virtue. Therefore, we see examples of virtue that genuinely involve something good in itself. Generally, we can say that wherever a virtue involves a tendency to have specific motives, practicing that virtue may be inherently good; although the extent of its goodness can vary greatly based on the specific motives and their targets. Thus, as Christianity emphasizes the significance of motives and the ‘inner’ disposition behind right actions, we can say it contributes positively to Ethics. However, it should be noted that when Christian Ethics, as presented in the New Testament, is praised for this, two crucial distinctions that it completely overlooks are often missed. First, the New Testament mainly continues the teachings of the Hebrew prophets by promoting virtues like ‘justice’ and ‘mercy’ over mere ritual practices; and in doing so, it advocates for virtues that may be merely good as means, similar to Aristotelian virtues. This aspect of its teaching must be clearly distinguished from its assertion that being angry without cause is as wrong as committing murder. Secondly, while the New Testament does commend some things that are only good as means and others that are good in themselves, it fails to recognize this distinction entirely. Although the state of someone who is angry may indeed be just as bad in itself as that of a murderer, and in that sense Christ may be correct, His words suggest that it is also as harmful in every way and also causes as much evil, which is completely untrue. In short, when Christian Ethics gives approval, it does not clarify whether its approval means ‘This is a means to good’ or ‘This is good in itself’; and as a result, it both commends things that are merely good as means as if they were good in themselves, and things that are simply good in themselves as if they were also good as means. Moreover, it should be noted that if Christian Ethics highlights the components of virtues that are good in themselves, it is by no means unique in this regard. Plato’s Ethics stand out because they clearly and consistently uphold the idea that intrinsic value is exclusive to those mental states that involve love for what is good or hatred for what is evil.
108. But (c) the Ethics of Christianity are distinguished from those of Plato by emphasizing the value of one particular motive—that which consists in the emotion excited by the idea, not of any intrinsically good consequences of the action in question, nor even of the action itself, but by that of its rightness. This idea of abstract ‘rightness’ and the various degrees of the specific emotion excited by it are what constitute the specifically ‘moral sentiment’ or ‘conscience.’ An action seems[p. 179] to be most properly termed ‘internally right[23],’ solely in virtue of the fact that the agent has previously regarded it as right: the idea of ‘rightness’ must have been present to his mind, but need not necessarily have been among his motives. And we mean by a ‘conscientious’ man, one who, when he deliberates, always has this idea in his mind, and does not act until he believes that his action is right.
108. But (c) the ethics of Christianity differ from those of Plato by highlighting the importance of one particular motive—that which arises from the emotion triggered by the idea of rightness, not from any inherently good outcomes of the action itself, nor even the action itself, but from its rightness. This concept of abstract ‘rightness’ and the various levels of specific emotion it triggers are what form the specific ‘moral sentiment’ or ‘conscience.’ An action seems[p. 179] to be most accurately described as ‘internally right[23],’ simply because the person has previously considered it to be right: the idea of ‘rightness’ must have been present in their mind, but it doesn’t necessarily have to have been part of their motives. When we refer to a ‘conscientious’ person, we mean someone who always considers this idea when making decisions, and doesn’t act until they believe their action is right.
The presence of this idea and its action as a motive certainly seem to have become more common objects of notice and commendation owing to the influence of Christianity; but it is important to observe that there is no ground for the view, which Kant implies, that it is the only motive which the New Testament regards as intrinsically valuable. There seems little doubt that when Christ tells us to ‘Love our neighbours as ourselves,’ He did not mean merely what Kant calls ‘practical love‘—beneficence of which the sole motive is the idea of its rightness, or the emotion caused by that idea. Among the ‘inward dispositions’ of which the New Testament inculcates the value, there are certainly included what Kant terms mere ‘natural inclinations,’ such as pity, etc.
The presence of this idea and its role as a motive definitely seem to have become more commonly recognized and appreciated due to the influence of Christianity; however, it's important to note that there's no basis for the view that Kant suggests, which is that it is the only motive that the New Testament considers intrinsically valuable. It’s quite clear that when Christ tells us to ‘Love our neighbors as ourselves,’ He did not mean just what Kant refers to as ‘practical love’—goodness driven solely by the idea of its rightness or the feeling that comes from that idea. Among the ‘inward dispositions’ that the New Testament emphasizes as valuable, there are certainly what Kant calls mere ‘natural inclinations,’ like pity, etc.
But what are we to say of virtue, when it consists in a disposition to be moved to the performance of duties by this idea? It seems difficult to deny that the emotion excited by rightness as such has some intrinsic value; and still more difficult to deny that its presence may heighten the value of some wholes into which it enters. But, on the other hand, it certainly has not more value than many of the motives treated in our last section—emotions of love towards things really good in themselves. And as for Kant’s implication that it is the sole good[24], this is inconsistent with other of his own views. For he certainly regards it as better to perform the actions, to which he maintains that it prompts us—namely, ‘material’ duties—than to omit them. But, if better at all, then, these actions must be[p. 180] better either in themselves or as a means. The former hypothesis would directly contradict the statement that this motive was sole good, and the latter is excluded by Kant himself since he maintains that no actions can cause the existence of this motive. And it may also be observed that the other claim which he makes for it, namely, that it is always good as a means, can also not be maintained. It is as certain as anything can be that very harmful actions may be done from conscientious motives; and that Conscience does not always tell us the truth about what actions are right. Nor can it be maintained even that it is more useful than many other motives. All that can be admitted is that it is one of the things which are generally useful.
But what can we say about virtue when it’s driven by the idea of performing our duties? It’s hard to deny that the emotion inspired by doing what’s right has some inherent value, and even harder to deny that it can enhance the value of certain actions or outcomes. However, it definitely doesn’t hold more value than many of the motivations we discussed earlier—like feelings of love toward truly good things. As for Kant’s suggestion that this is the only good [24], it doesn’t align with some of his other ideas. He clearly thinks it’s better to carry out the actions that he claims it encourages—specifically, ‘material’ duties—than to ignore them. But if these actions are better in any way, then they must be[p. 180] better either in themselves or as a means. The first option would go against the idea that this motive is the sole good, and the second option is ruled out by Kant himself since he argues that no actions can cause this motive to exist. Additionally, it’s worth noting that his other claim—that it is always good as a means—can’t hold up either. It’s as certain as anything can be that harmful actions can be taken based on conscientious motives, and our conscience doesn’t always guide us correctly on what actions are right. Nor can we claim that it is more useful than many other motivations. The only thing we can agree on is that it is one of the generally useful aspects.
What more I have to say with regard to those elements in some virtues which are good in themselves, and with regard to their relative degrees of excellence, as well as the proof that all of them together cannot be the sole good, may be deferred to the next chapter.
What else I need to say about certain virtues that are good in themselves, their relative levels of excellence, and the evidence that none of them alone can be the ultimate good will be covered in the next chapter.
109. The main points in this chapter, to which I desire to direct attention, may be summarised as follows:—(1) I first pointed out how the subject-matter with which it deals, namely, ethical judgments on conduct, involves a question, utterly different in kind from the two previously discussed, namely: (a) What is the nature of the predicate peculiar to Ethics? and (b) What kinds of things themselves possess this predicate? Practical Ethics asks, not ‘What ought to be?’ but ‘What ought we to do?’; it asks what actions are duties, what actions are right, and what wrong: and all these questions can only be answered by shewing the relation of the actions in question, as causes or necessary conditions, to what is good in itself. The enquiries of Practical Ethics thus fall entirely under the third division of ethical questions—questions which ask, ‘What is good as a means?’ which is equivalent to ‘What is a means to good—what is cause or necessary condition of things good in themselves?’ (86-88). But (2) it asks this question, almost exclusively, with regard to actions which it is possible for most men to perform, if only they will them; and with regard to these, it does not ask merely, which among them will have some[p. 181] good or bad result, but which, among all the actions possible to volition at any moment, will produce the best total result. To assert that an action is a duty, is to assert that it is such a possible action, which will always, in certain known circumstances, produce better results than any other. It follows that universal propositions of which duty is predicate, so far from being self-evident, always require a proof, which it is beyond our present means of knowledge ever to give (89-92). But (3) all that Ethics has attempted or can attempt, is to shew that certain actions, possible by volition, generally produce better or worse total results than any probable alternative: and it must obviously be very difficult to shew this with regard to the total results even in a comparatively near future; whereas that what has the best results in such a near future, also has the best on the whole, is a point requiring an investigation which it has not received. If it is true, and if, accordingly, we give the name of ‘duty’ to actions which generally produce better total results in the near future than any possible alternative, it may be possible to prove that a few of the commonest rules of duty are true, but only in certain conditions of society, which may be more or less universally presented in history; and such a proof is only possible in some cases without a correct judgment of what things are good or bad in themselves—a judgment which has never yet been offered by ethical writers. With regard to actions of which the general utility is thus proved, the individual should always perform them; but in other cases, where rules are commonly offered, he should rather judge of the probable results in his particular case, guided by a correct conception of what things are intrinsically good or bad (93-100). (4) In order that any action may be shewn to be a duty, it must be shewn to fulfil the above conditions; but the actions commonly called ‘duties’ do not fulfil them to any greater extent than ‘expedient’ or ‘interested’ actions: by calling them ‘duties’ we only mean that they have, in addition, certain non-ethical predicates. Similarly by ‘virtue’ is mainly meant a permanent disposition to perform ‘duties’ in this restricted[p. 182] sense: and accordingly a virtue, if it is really a virtue, must be good as a means, in the sense that it fulfils the above conditions; but it is not better as a means than non-virtuous dispositions; it generally has no value in itself; and, where it has, it is far from being the sole good or the best of goods. Accordingly ‘virtue’ is not, as is commonly implied, an unique ethical predicate (101-109).
109. The key points in this chapter that I want to highlight can be summarized as follows:—(1) I first pointed out that the subject matter it addresses, namely, ethical judgments on conduct, raises a question that is completely different from the two previously discussed: (a) What is the nature of the concept unique to Ethics? and (b) What types of things possess this concept? Practical Ethics asks not ‘What should be?’ but ‘What should we do?’; it inquires what actions are duties, which are right, and which are wrong: and all these questions can only be answered by showing the relationship of the actions in question as causes or necessary conditions to what is good in itself. The inquiries of Practical Ethics thus fall entirely under the third category of ethical questions—questions that ask, ‘What is good as a means?’ which is the same as asking ‘What is a means to good—what is the cause or necessary condition of things that are good in themselves?’ (86-88). But (2) it almost exclusively asks this question about actions that most people can perform, if only they will them; and regarding these, it does not merely ask which among them will yield some[p. 181] good or bad outcome, but which among all possible actions at any moment will produce the best total outcome. To say that an action is a duty means that it is one that can always, in certain known circumstances, lead to better results than any other. It follows that universal statements about duty are not self-evident; they always require evidence, which our current knowledge cannot provide (89-92). But (3) all that Ethics has tried or can try to do is show that certain actions, possible by will, generally produce better or worse total outcomes than any likely alternative: and it is obviously very challenging to demonstrate this regarding total outcomes, even in the relatively near future; while the idea that what has the best results in the near future also has the best overall outcomes is something that requires investigation, which has not happened. If it is true that we consider actions which generally produce better total outcomes in the near future than any possible alternatives as ‘duty,’ it might be possible to prove that a few common rules of duty are true, but only under certain social conditions that may be more or less commonly found throughout history; and such proof is only achievable in some cases without an accurate judgment of what things are intrinsically good or bad—which has not yet been provided by ethical theorists. For actions whose general utility is thus demonstrated, individuals should always perform them; but in other situations, where rules are commonly suggested, they should instead assess the likely outcomes in their specific case, guided by a correct understanding of what things are inherently good or bad (93-100). (4) For any action to be shown as a duty, it must meet the aforementioned conditions; however, the actions typically labeled as ‘duties’ do not fulfill them any more than ‘expedient’ or ‘self-interested’ actions do: by calling them ‘duties,’ we simply mean that they have, in addition, certain non-ethical characteristics. Similarly, ‘virtue’ mainly refers to a consistent tendency to perform ‘duties’ in this limited[p. 182] sense: therefore, a virtue, if it is genuinely a virtue, must be good as a means, in the sense that it meets these conditions; but it is not better as a means than non-virtuous dispositions; it typically holds no value in itself; and when it does, it is far from being the only good or the best good. Thus, ‘virtue’ is not, as is commonly suggested, a unique ethical concept (101-109).
[p. 183]
[p. 183]
CHAPTER VI.
THE IDEAL.
THE IDEAL.
110. The title of this chapter is ambiguous. When we call a state of things ‘ideal’ we may mean three distinct things, which have only this in common: that we always do mean to assert, of the state of things in question, not only that it is good in itself, but that it is good in itself in a much higher degree than many other things. The first of these meanings of ‘ideal’ is (1) that to which the phrase ‘The Ideal’ is most properly confined. By this is meant the best state of things conceivable, the Summum Bonum or Absolute Good. It is in this sense that a right conception of Heaven would be a right conception of the Ideal: we mean by the Ideal a state of things which would be absolutely perfect. But this conception may be quite clearly distinguished from a second, namely, (2) that of the best possible state of things in this world. This second conception may be identified with that which has frequently figured in philosophy as the ‘Human Good,’ or the ultimate end towards which our action should be directed. It is in this sense that Utopias are said to be Ideals. The constructor of an Utopia may suppose many things to be possible, which are in fact impossible; but he always assumes that some things, at least, are rendered impossible by natural laws, and hence his construction differs essentially from one which may disregard all natural laws, however certainly established. At all events the question ‘What is the best state of things which we could possibly bring about?’ is quite distinct from the question ‘What would be the best state of things conceivable?’ But, thirdly, we may mean[p. 184] by calling a state of things ‘ideal’ merely (3) that it is good in itself in a high degree. And it is obvious that the question what things are ‘ideal’ in this sense is one which must be answered before we can pretend to settle what is the Absolute or the Human Good. It is with the Ideal, in this third sense, that this chapter will be principally concerned. Its main object is to arrive at some positive answer to the fundamental question of Ethics—the question: ‘What things are goods or ends in themselves?’ To this question we have hitherto obtained only a negative answer: the answer that pleasure is certainly not the sole good.
110. The title of this chapter is unclear. When we refer to a situation as ‘ideal,’ we might mean three different things, which all share one common belief: that we assert the situation is not only good on its own, but that it is significantly better than many other situations. The first meaning of ‘ideal’ is (1) the one most closely associated with the phrase ‘The Ideal.’ This refers to the best conceivable state of affairs, the Summum Bonum or Absolute Good. In this sense, a correct understanding of Heaven would be a correct understanding of the Ideal: we refer to the Ideal as a situation that would be absolutely perfect. However, this idea can be clearly separated from the second meaning, which is (2) the best possible situation in this world. This second meaning aligns with what has often been described in philosophy as the ‘Human Good,’ or the ultimate goal toward which our actions should be aimed. It is in this context that Utopias are considered Ideals. The creator of a Utopia might assume many things are feasible that are, in reality, impossible; but they always acknowledge that, at the very least, some things are made impossible by natural laws, making their design fundamentally different from one that disregards all established natural laws. In any case, the question ‘What is the best situation we could possibly create?’ is quite different from the question ‘What would be the best situation that could be imagined?’ Lastly, we may refer to a situation as ‘ideal’ merely (3) to imply that it is highly good in itself. It’s clear that determining what things are ‘ideal’ in this sense is essential before we can claim to discern what constitutes the Absolute or the Human Good. This chapter will primarily focus on the Ideal in this third sense. Its main goal is to provide a definitive answer to the fundamental question of Ethics—the question: ‘What things are goods or ends in themselves?’ So far, we have only received a negative answer to this question: that pleasure is definitely not the sole good.
111. I have just said that it is upon a correct answer to this question that correct answers to the two other questions, What is the Absolute Good? and What is the Human Good? must depend; and, before proceeding to discuss it, it may be well to point out the relation which it has to these two questions.
111. I just mentioned that finding the right answer to this question relies on the correct answers to the other two questions: What is the Absolute Good? and What is the Human Good? Before we dive into this, it might be helpful to highlight how this question is connected to those two.
(1) It is just possible that the Absolute Good may be entirely composed of qualities which we cannot even imagine. This is possible, because, though we certainly do know a great many things that are good-in-themselves, and good in a high degree, yet what is best does not necessarily contain all the good things there are. That this is so follows from the principle explained in Chap. I. (§§ 18-22), to which it was there proposed that the name ‘principle of organic unities’ should be confined. This principle is that the intrinsic value of a whole is neither identical with nor proportional to the sum of the values of its parts. It follows from this that, though in order to obtain the greatest possible sum of values in its parts, the Ideal would necessarily contain all the things which have intrinsic value in any degree, yet the whole which contained all these parts might not be so valuable as some other whole, from which certain positive goods were omitted. But if a whole, which does not contain all positive goods, may yet be better than a whole which does, it follows that the best whole may be one, which contains none of the positive goods with which we are acquainted.
(1) It's possible that the Absolute Good could be entirely made up of qualities we can't even imagine. This is likely because, while we definitely know many things that are good in themselves and very good, what is best doesn’t have to include all the good things that exist. This idea comes from the principle explained in Chap. I. (§§ 18-22), where it was suggested that the term ‘principle of organic unities’ should be specifically defined. This principle states that the intrinsic value of a whole is neither the same as nor proportional to the sum of the values of its parts. This means that, although to achieve the greatest possible sum of values among its parts, the Ideal would need to include everything that has any degree of intrinsic value, the whole that includes all these parts might not be as valuable as another whole that leaves out some positive goods. So, if a whole that doesn’t include all positive goods can still be better than one that does, it follows that the best whole may be one that contains none of the positive goods we know of.
It is, therefore, possible that we cannot discover what[p. 185] the Ideal is. But it is plain that, though this possibility cannot be denied, no one can have any right to assert that it is realised—that the Ideal is something unimaginable. We cannot judge of the comparative values of things, unless the things we judge are before our minds. We cannot, therefore, be entitled to assert that anything, which we cannot imagine, would be better than some of the things which we can; although we are also not entitled to deny the possibility that this may be the case. Consequently our search for the Ideal must be limited to a search for that one, among all the wholes composed of elements known to us, which seems to be better than all the rest. We shall never be entitled to assert that this whole is Perfection, but we shall be entitled to assert that it is better than any other which may be presented as a rival.
It is, therefore, possible that we may not be able to figure out what[p. 185] the Ideal actually is. However, it’s clear that, while we can’t deny this possibility, no one has the right to claim that it exists—that the Ideal is something we can't even imagine. We can’t assess the relative merits of things unless those things are present in our minds. So, we can’t claim that anything we can’t imagine is necessarily better than some things we can; although we also can’t deny the chance that it might be. As a result, our quest for the Ideal should focus on finding the one whole, made up of elements we know, that seems better than all the others. We will never be able to say that this whole is Perfection, but we can say it is better than any other that might be considered a rival.
But, since anything which we can have any reason to think ideal must be composed of things that are known to us, it is plain that a comparative valuation of these must be our chief instrument for deciding what is ideal. The best ideal we can construct will be that state of things which contains the greatest number of things having positive value, and which contains nothing evil or indifferent—provided that the presence of none of these goods, or the absence of things evil or indifferent, seems to diminish the value of the whole. And, in fact, the chief defect of such attempts as have been made by philosophers to construct an Ideal—to describe the Kingdom of Heaven—seems to consist in the fact that they omit many things of very great positive value, although it is plain that this omission does not enhance the value of the whole. Where this is the case, it may be confidently asserted that the ideal proposed is not ideal. And the review of positive goods, which I am about to undertake, will, I hope, shew that no ideals yet proposed are satisfactory. Great positive goods, it will appear, are so numerous, that any whole, which shall contain them all, must be of vast complexity. And though this fact renders it difficult, or, humanly speaking, impossible, to decide what is The Ideal, what is the absolutely best state of things imaginable, it is sufficient to condemn those Ideals, which[p. 186] are formed by omission, without any visible gain in consequence of such omission. Philosophers seem usually to have sought only for the best of single things; neglecting the fact that a whole composed of two great goods, even though one of these be obviously inferior to the other, may yet be often seen to be decidedly superior to either by itself.
But since anything we can reasonably think of as ideal must be made up of things we know, it's clear that comparing these things should be our main tool for determining what is ideal. The best ideal we can come up with will be the situation that includes the most things with positive value and has nothing evil or indifferent, as long as having these goods or not having things that are evil or indifferent doesn't lower the overall value. In fact, the main flaw in attempts by philosophers to create an Ideal—like describing the Kingdom of Heaven—seems to be that they leave out many things of great positive value, even though this omission doesn’t actually increase the value of the whole. When this happens, we can confidently say that the proposed ideal is not truly ideal. The review of positive goods that I’m about to undertake will, I hope, show that no ideals proposed so far are satisfactory. It will become clear that there are so many great positive goods that any whole containing them all must be extremely complex. And while this complexity makes it difficult, if not impossible, to determine what The Ideal is—the absolutely best imaginable state of things—it is enough to reject those Ideals formed by exclusion without any real benefit from that exclusion. Philosophers usually seem to have only looked for the best of individual things, ignoring the fact that a whole made up of two great goods, even if one is clearly inferior to the other, can often be seen as distinctly better than either one alone.
(2) On the other hand, Utopias—attempted descriptions of a Heaven upon Earth—commonly suffer not only from this, but also from the opposite defect. They are commonly constructed on the principle of merely omitting the great positive evils, which exist at present, with utterly inadequate regard to the goodness of what they retain: the so-called goods, to which they have regard, are, for the most part, things which are, at best, mere means to good—things, such as freedom, without which, possibly, nothing very good can exist in this world, but which are of no value in themselves and are by no means certain even to produce anything of value. It is, of course, necessary to the purpose of their authors, whose object is merely to construct the best that may be possible in this world, that they should include, in the state of things which they describe, many things, which are themselves indifferent, but which, according to natural laws, seem to be absolutely necessary for the existence of anything which is good. But, in fact, they are apt to include many things, of which the necessity is by no means apparent, under the mistaken idea that these things are goods-in-themselves, and not merely, here and now, a means to good: while, on the other hand, they also omit from their description great positive goods, of which the attainment seems to be quite as possible as many of the changes which they recommend. That is to say, conceptions of the Human Good commonly err, not only, like those of the Absolute Good, in omitting some great goods, but also by including things indifferent; and they both omit and include in cases where the limitations of natural necessity, by the consideration of which they are legitimately differentiated from conceptions of the Absolute Good, will not justify the omission and inclusion. It is, in fact, obvious that in order to decide correctly at what state of things we ought to aim, we must not[p. 187] only consider what results it is possible for us to obtain, but also which, among equally possible results, will have the greatest value. And upon this second enquiry the comparative valuation of known goods has a no less important bearing than upon the investigation of the Absolute Good.
(2) On the other hand, Utopias—attempts to describe a perfect world—often struggle not just with one issue, but also with the opposite problem. They are typically built on the idea of simply ignoring the major evils that exist today, while not giving proper attention to the positives they feature. The so-called goods they focus on are mostly just tools for achieving good—like freedom, which is essential for any goodness to exist in this world, but has no inherent value and doesn’t guarantee any real value on its own. Their authors find it necessary to include many indifferent things in their envisioned world, as these seem to be absolutely required for any goodness to exist according to natural laws. However, they often include many elements whose necessity is far from obvious, mistakenly thinking these elements are goods in themselves, rather than just being means to an end right now. At the same time, they also leave out significant positive goods that could be just as attainable as many of the changes they suggest. In other words, ideas of the Human Good often make mistakes by not only omitting important goods like those concerning the Absolute Good, but also by including indifferent things; they both leave out and add in instances where the natural necessities that differentiate them from ideas of the Absolute Good do not justify those omissions and inclusions. It's clear that to accurately determine what state of affairs we should strive for, we must not only think about what outcomes are achievable, but also consider which of those possible outcomes will provide the greatest value. This second inquiry is just as crucial as evaluating known goods in relation to the Absolute Good.
112. The method which must be employed in order to decide the question ‘What things have intrinsic value, and in what degrees?’ has already been explained in Chap. III. (§§ 55, 57). In order to arrive at a correct decision on the first part of this question, it is necessary to consider what things are such that, if they existed by themselves, in absolute isolation, we should yet judge their existence to be good; and, in order to decide upon the relative degrees of value of different things, we must similarly consider what comparative value seems to attach to the isolated existence of each. By employing this method, we shall guard against two errors, which seem to have been the chief causes which have vitiated previous conclusions on the subject. The first of these is (1) that which consists in supposing that what seems absolutely necessary here and now, for the existence of anything good—what we cannot do without—is therefore good in itself. If we isolate such things, which are mere means to good, and suppose a world in which they alone, and nothing but they, existed, their intrinsic worthlessness becomes apparent. And, secondly, there is the more subtle error (2) which consists in neglecting the principle of organic unities. This error is committed, when it is supposed, that, if one part of a whole has no intrinsic value, the value of the whole must reside entirely in the other parts. It has, in this way, been commonly supposed, that, if all valuable wholes could be seen to have one and only one common property, the wholes must be valuable solely because they possess this property; and the illusion is greatly strengthened, if the common property in question seems, considered by itself, to have more value than the other parts of such wholes, considered by themselves. But, if we consider the property in question, in isolation, and then compare it with the whole, of which it forms a part, it may become easily apparent that, existing by itself, the property in question has not nearly[p. 188] so much value, as has the whole to which it belongs. Thus, if we compare the value of a certain amount of pleasure, existing absolutely by itself, with the value of certain ‘enjoyments,’ containing an equal amount of pleasure, it may become apparent that the ‘enjoyment’ is much better than the pleasure, and also, in some cases, much worse. In such a case it is plain that the ‘enjoyment’ does not owe its value solely to the pleasure it contains, although it might easily have appeared to do so, when we only considered the other constituents of the enjoyment, and seemed to see that, without the pleasure, they would have had no value. It is now apparent, on the contrary, that the whole ‘enjoyment’ owes its value quite equally to the presence of the other constituents, even though it may be true that the pleasure is the only constituent having any value by itself. And similarly, if we are told that all things owe their value solely to the fact that they are ‘realisations of the true self,’ we may easily refute this statement, by asking whether the predicate that is meant by ‘realising the true self,’ supposing that it could exist alone, would have any value whatsoever. Either the thing, which does ‘realise the true self,’ has intrinsic value or it has not; and if it has, then it certainly does not owe its value solely to the fact that it realises the true self.
112. The method we need to use to answer the question ‘What things have intrinsic value, and to what extent?’ has already been explained in Chap. III. (§§ 55, 57). To properly address the first part of this question, we need to think about what things, if they existed on their own, in complete isolation, we would still consider to be good; and to determine the relative degrees of value for different things, we should also consider the comparative value attached to the isolated existence of each. By using this method, we can avoid two errors that seem to have significantly distorted previous conclusions on the topic. The first error is (1) the assumption that what seems absolutely necessary right now for the existence of anything good—what we cannot do without—is therefore good in itself. If we isolate such items, which are merely means to an end, and imagine a world where only they exist, their intrinsic worthlessness becomes clear. The second, more subtle error (2) occurs when the principle of organic unities is overlooked. This error arises when it’s assumed that if one part of a whole has no intrinsic value, the value of the entire entity must lie completely in the other parts. It has been commonly thought that if all valuable wholes share one and only one common trait, those wholes must be valuable solely because they have that trait; this illusion is further strengthened if that shared property appears, on its own, to hold more value than the other components of such wholes, considered individually. However, if we examine the property in question in isolation and then compare it to the whole it belongs to, it may quickly become clear that, by itself, the property doesn’t hold nearly as much value as the entire entity. For example, if we compare the value of a certain amount of pleasure existing absolutely by itself to certain ‘enjoyments’ that contain an equal amount of pleasure, it may become obvious that ‘enjoyment’ is often more valuable than the pleasure itself, and in some cases, it could be much less valuable. In such scenarios, it’s clear that the ‘enjoyment’ does not derive its value solely from the pleasure it includes, even though it might appear that way when we only look at the other parts of the enjoyment, thinking they would have no value without the pleasure. In fact, it’s clear that the whole ‘enjoyment’ owes its value equally to the presence of the other components, even if it’s true that pleasure is the only part that holds any value on its own. Similarly, if we are told that all things have value solely because they are ‘realizations of the true self,’ we can easily challenge this claim by asking whether the quality referred to as ‘realizing the true self,’ assuming it could exist independently, would have any value at all. Either the thing that ‘realizes the true self’ has intrinsic value, or it does not; and if it does, then it certainly doesn’t owe its value merely to the fact that it realizes the true self.
113. If, now, we use this method of absolute isolation, and guard against these errors, it appears that the question we have to answer is far less difficult than the controversies of Ethics might have led us to expect. Indeed, once the meaning of the question is clearly understood, the answer to it, in its main outlines, appears to be so obvious, that it runs the risk of seeming to be a platitude. By far the most valuable things, which we know or can imagine, are certain states of consciousness, which may be roughly described as the pleasures of human intercourse and the enjoyment of beautiful objects. No one, probably, who has asked himself the question, has ever doubted that personal affection and the appreciation of what is beautiful in Art or Nature, are good in themselves; nor, if we consider strictly what things are worth having purely for their own sakes, does it appear probable that any one will think that[p. 189] anything else has nearly so great a value as the things which are included under these two heads. I have myself urged in Chap. III. (§ 50) that the mere existence of what is beautiful does appear to have some intrinsic value; but I regard it as indubitable that Prof. Sidgwick was so far right, in the view there discussed, that such mere existence of what is beautiful has value, so small as to be negligible, in comparison with that which attaches to the consciousness of beauty. This simple truth may, indeed, be said to be universally recognised. What has not been recognised is that it is the ultimate and fundamental truth of Moral Philosophy. That it is only for the sake of these things—in order that as much of them as possible may at some time exist—that any one can be justified in performing any public or private duty; that they are the raison d’être of virtue; that it is they—these complex wholes themselves, and not any constituent or characteristic of them—that form the rational ultimate end of human action and the sole criterion of social progress: these appear to be truths which have been generally overlooked.
113. If we apply this method of complete isolation and guard against these mistakes, it seems that the question we need to answer is much less complicated than the debates in Ethics might suggest. In fact, once we fully understand what the question means, the answer, in its main aspects, seems so obvious that it risks coming off as a cliché. The most valuable things we know or can imagine are certain states of consciousness, which can be generally described as the pleasures of human connection and the enjoyment of beautiful things. Almost everyone who has considered this question probably agrees that personal affection and appreciating beauty in Art or Nature are good in themselves. Moreover, when we strictly think about what things are worth having just for their own sake, it seems unlikely that anyone would believe anything else holds nearly the same value as those two categories. I have previously argued in Chap. III. (§ 50) that simply having beauty does appear to hold some intrinsic value; however, I believe it's undeniable that Prof. Sidgwick was correct in the discussion there, suggesting that the mere existence of beauty has a value so small that it can be ignored when compared to the value attached to the consciousness of beauty. This straightforward fact may indeed be considered universally acknowledged. What has not been recognized is that this is the ultimate and fundamental truth of Moral Philosophy. It is only for the sake of these things—so that as much of them as possible may exist at some point—that anyone can justify performing any public or private duty; they are the raison d’être of virtue; it is they—these complex wholes themselves, not any part or characteristic of them—that serve as the rational ultimate goal of human action and the sole measure of social progress: these seem to be truths that have generally been overlooked.
That they are truths—that personal affections and aesthetic enjoyments include all the greatest, and by far the greatest, goods we can imagine, will, I hope, appear more plainly in the course of that analysis of them, to which I shall now proceed. All the things, which I have meant to include under the above descriptions, are highly complex organic unities; and in discussing the consequences, which follow from this fact, and the elements of which they are composed, I may hope at the same time both to confirm and to define my position.
That they are truths—that personal connections and aesthetic experiences encompass all the greatest, and by far the greatest, goods we can imagine, will, I hope, become clearer as I analyze them further. Everything I intend to include under these descriptions is highly complex organic unities; and by discussing the implications of this fact and the elements that make them up, I hope to both affirm and clarify my stance.
114. I. I propose to begin by examining what I have called aesthetic enjoyments, since the case of personal affections presents some additional complications. It is, I think, universally admitted that the proper appreciation of a beautiful object is a good thing in itself; and my question is: What are the main elements included in such an appreciation?
114. I. I want to start by looking at what I call aesthetic pleasures, since personal feelings involve some extra complexities. I think it's widely accepted that genuinely appreciating a beautiful object is valuable in itself; my question is: What are the key components involved in that appreciation?
(1) It is plain that in those instances of aesthetic appreciation, which we think most valuable, there is included, not merely a bare cognition of what is beautiful in the object, but also some kind of feeling or emotion. It is not sufficient that[p. 190] a man should merely see the beautiful qualities in a picture and know that they are beautiful, in order that we may give his state of mind the highest praise. We require that he should also appreciate the beauty of that which he sees and which he knows to be beautiful—that he should feel and see its beauty. And by these expressions we certainly mean that he should have an appropriate emotion towards the beautiful qualities which he cognises. It is perhaps the case that all aesthetic emotions have some common quality; but it is certain that differences in the emotion seem to be appropriate to differences in the kind of beauty perceived: and by saying that different emotions are appropriate to different kinds of beauty, we mean that the whole which is formed by the consciousness of that kind of beauty together with the emotion appropriate to it, is better than if any other emotion had been felt in contemplating that particular beautiful object. Accordingly we have a large variety of different emotions, each of which is a necessary constituent in some state of consciousness which we judge to be good. All of these emotions are essential elements in great positive goods; they are parts of organic wholes, which have great intrinsic value. But it is important to observe that these wholes are organic, and that, hence, it does not follow that the emotion, by itself, would have any value whatsoever, nor yet that, if it were directed to a different object, the whole thus formed might not be positively bad. And, in fact, it seems to be the case that if we distinguish the emotional element, in any aesthetic appreciation, from the cognitive element, which accompanies it and is, in fact, commonly thought of as a part of the emotion; and if we consider what value this emotional element would have, existing by itself, we can hardly think that it has any great value, even if it has any at all. Whereas, if the same emotion be directed to a different object, if, for instance, it is felt towards an object that is positively ugly, the whole state of consciousness is certainly often positively bad in a high degree.
(1) It’s clear that in those moments when we appreciate art, especially the ones we value the most, it's not just about recognizing what's beautiful in the object; there’s also some kind of feeling or emotion involved. It’s not enough for someone to just see the beautiful aspects of a painting and know they're beautiful for us to really praise their mindset. We need them to truly appreciate the beauty of what they see and understand that it’s beautiful—that they should feel and perceive its beauty. By this, we mean they should have an appropriate emotional response to the beautiful qualities they recognize. All aesthetic emotions likely share some common traits; however, it’s clear that the feelings vary in relation to the different types of beauty we identify. When we say that different emotions are appropriate for different kinds of beauty, we mean that the combination of recognizing that type of beauty along with the fitting emotion makes for a better experience than if any other emotion were felt while appreciating that specific beautiful object. As a result, there’s a wide range of emotions, each of which is a crucial part of a state of awareness that we consider positive. All these emotions are essential components of significant positive experiences; they are parts of interconnected wholes that hold significant intrinsic value. However, it’s important to note that these wholes are organic, meaning that it doesn’t necessarily mean the emotion, by itself, has any value at all, nor that, if directed at a different object, the resulting whole couldn’t be negative. In fact, if we separate the emotional aspect of any aesthetic appreciation from the cognitive aspect that typically accompanies it and is often viewed as part of the emotion, and if we evaluate the value of this emotional element on its own, it’s difficult to believe it has much value, if any. Conversely, if the same emotion is directed toward another object, say one that is clearly ugly, then the entire conscious experience is often quite negative.
115. (2) In the last paragraph I have pointed out the two facts, that the presence of some emotion is necessary to give any very high value to a state of aesthetic appreciation, and[p. 191] that, on the other hand, this same emotion, in itself, may have little or no value: it follows that these emotions give to the wholes of which they form a part a value far greater than that which they themselves possess. The same is obviously true of the cognitive element which must be combined with these emotions in order to form these highly valuable wholes; and the present paragraph will attempt to define what is meant by this cognitive element, so far as to guard against a possible misunderstanding. When we talk of seeing a beautiful object, or, more generally, of the cognition or consciousness of a beautiful object, we may mean by these expressions something which forms no part of any valuable whole. There is an ambiguity in the use of the term ‘object,’ which has probably been responsible for as many enormous errors in philosophy and psychology as any other single cause. This ambiguity may easily be detected by considering the proposition, which, though a contradiction in terms, is obviously true: That when a man sees a beautiful picture, he may see nothing beautiful whatever. The ambiguity consists in the fact that, by the ‘object’ of vision (or cognition), may be meant either the qualities actually seen or all the qualities possessed by the thing seen. Thus in our case: when it is said that the picture is beautiful, it is meant that it contains qualities which are beautiful; when it is said that the man sees the picture, it is meant that he sees a great number of the qualities contained in the picture; and when it is said that, nevertheless, he sees nothing beautiful, it is meant that he does not see those qualities of the picture which are beautiful. When, therefore, I speak of the cognition of a beautiful object, as an essential element in a valuable aesthetic appreciation, I must be understood to mean only the cognition of the beautiful qualities possessed by that object, and not the cognition of other qualities of the object possessing them. And this distinction must itself be carefully distinguished from the other distinction expressed above by the distinct terms ‘seeing the beauty of a thing’ and ‘seeing its beautiful qualities.’ By ‘seeing the beauty of a thing’ we commonly mean the having an emotion towards its beautiful qualities; whereas in the ‘seeing of its beautiful qualities’ we do not include any emotion.[p. 192] By the cognitive element, which is equally necessary with emotion to the existence of a valuable appreciation, I mean merely the actual cognition or consciousness of any or all of an object’s beautiful qualities—that is to say any or all of those elements in the object which possess any positive beauty. That such a cognitive element is essential to a valuable whole may be easily seen, by asking: What value should we attribute to the proper emotion excited by hearing Beethoven’s Fifth Symphony, if that emotion were entirely unaccompanied by any consciousness, either of the notes, or of the melodic and harmonic relations between them? And that the mere hearing of the Symphony, even accompanied by the appropriate emotion, is not sufficient, may be easily seen, if we consider what would be the state of a man, who should hear all the notes, but should not be aware of any of those melodic and harmonic relations, which are necessary to constitute the smallest beautiful elements in the Symphony.
115. (2) In the last paragraph, I highlighted two key points: first, that some form of emotion is necessary to give any significant value to a state of aesthetic appreciation, and[p. 191] second, that this same emotion, on its own, may have little or no value. This means that these emotions contribute to the overall value of the experiences they are part of, surpassing the value they hold individually. The same is clearly true for the cognitive element that must combine with these emotions to create those highly valuable experiences. This paragraph will clarify what is meant by the cognitive element to prevent misunderstandings. When we say we see a beautiful object, or refer more generally to the cognition or awareness of a beautiful object, we might be talking about something that is not part of a valuable experience at all. There’s an ambiguity in the term ‘object’ that has likely caused as many significant errors in philosophy and psychology as any other single factor. This ambiguity can be recognized by considering the statement, which, though contradictory by nature, is clearly true: a person looking at a beautiful painting might not actually see anything beautiful. The ambiguity lies in the fact that the ‘object’ of vision (or cognition) can refer to either the qualities that are actually seen or all the qualities that the thing has. So, in this case: when we say the painting is beautiful, we mean it has qualities that are beautiful; when we say the person sees the painting, we mean they see many of the qualities in it; and when we say that, nonetheless, they see nothing beautiful, we mean they do not see the qualities of the painting that are beautiful. Therefore, when I talk about the cognition of a beautiful object as an essential part of valuable aesthetic appreciation, I specifically mean the cognition of the beautiful qualities that the object has, and not the cognition of other qualities of the object that don’t contribute to its beauty. This distinction needs to be carefully separated from the earlier distinction made using the specific terms ‘seeing the beauty of a thing’ and ‘seeing its beautiful qualities.’ By ‘seeing the beauty of a thing,’ we usually mean having an emotional response to its beautiful qualities; whereas when we talk about ‘seeing its beautiful qualities,’ we don’t include any emotional response.[p. 192] The cognitive element, which is just as necessary as emotion for valuable appreciation, refers to the actual cognition or awareness of any or all of an object’s beautiful qualities—that is, any or all aspects of the object that have a positive beauty. It’s easy to see that such a cognitive element is essential for a valuable experience by asking: What value would we assign to the appropriate emotion triggered by hearing Beethoven’s Fifth Symphony if that emotion were entirely unaccompanied by any awareness of the notes or the melodic and harmonic relationships between them? It’s also clear that merely hearing the Symphony, despite having the right emotion, isn’t enough. This can be understood by imagining a person who hears all the notes but is not aware of any of the melodic and harmonic relationships necessary to constitute even the smallest beautiful elements in the Symphony.
116. (3) Connected with the distinction just made between ‘object’ in the sense of the qualities actually before the mind, and ‘object’ in the sense of the whole thing which possesses the qualities actually before the mind, is another distinction of the utmost importance for a correct analysis of the constituents necessary to a valuable whole. It is commonly and rightly thought that to see beauty in a thing which has no beauty is in some way inferior to seeing beauty in that which really has it. But under this single description of ‘seeing beauty in that which has no beauty,’ two very different facts, and facts of very different value, may be included. We may mean either the attribution to an object of really beautiful qualities which it does not possess or the feeling towards qualities, which the object does possess but which are in reality not beautiful, an emotion which is appropriate only to qualities really beautiful. Both these facts are of very frequent occurrence; and in most instances of emotion both no doubt occur together: but they are obviously quite distinct, and the distinction is of the utmost importance for a correct estimate of values. The former may be called an error of judgment, and the latter an error of taste; but it is[p. 193] important to observe that the ‘error of taste’ commonly involves a false judgment of value; whereas the ‘error of judgment’ is merely a false judgment of fact.
116. (3) Related to the distinction just made between ‘object’ as the qualities currently in our minds and ‘object’ as the entire thing that has those qualities is another crucial distinction for accurately analyzing what makes a valuable whole. It’s commonly and rightly believed that finding beauty in something that isn’t beautiful is somewhat inferior to recognizing beauty in something that truly is. However, this single phrase ‘seeing beauty in something that has no beauty’ can describe two very different situations, each with different implications. We could mean either the attribution of genuinely beautiful qualities to an object that lacks them, or the feeling towards qualities that the object actually has but aren’t beautiful—an emotion that only fits qualities that are truly beautiful. Both situations happen quite often, and in most emotional encounters, they probably occur together; but they are clearly distinct, and this distinction is crucial for properly assessing values. The former can be called an error of judgment, while the latter can be labeled an error of taste; yet it's important to note that the ‘error of taste’ usually involves a false judgment of value, while the ‘error of judgment’ is simply a false judgment of fact.
Now the case which I have called an error of taste, namely, where the actual qualities we admire (whether possessed by the ‘object’ or not) are ugly, can in any case have no value, except such as may belong to the emotion by itself; and in most, if not in all, cases it is a considerable positive evil. In this sense, then, it is undoubtedly right to think that seeing beauty in a thing which has no beauty is inferior in value to seeing beauty where beauty really is. But the other case is much more difficult. In this case there is present all that I have hitherto mentioned as necessary to constitute a great positive good: there is a cognition of qualities really beautiful, together with an appropriate emotion towards these qualities. There can, therefore, be no doubt that we have here a great positive good. But there is present also something else; namely, a belief that these beautiful qualities exist, and that they exist in a certain relation to other things—namely, to some properties of the object to which we attribute these qualities: and further the object of this belief is false. And we may ask, with regard to the whole thus constituted, whether the presence of the belief, and the fact that what is believed is false, make any difference to its value? We thus get three different cases of which it is very important to determine the relative values. Where both the cognition of beautiful qualities and the appropriate emotion are present we may also have either, (1) a belief in the existence of these qualities, of which the object, i.e. that they exist, is true: or (2) a mere cognition, without belief, when it is (a) true, (b) false, that the object of the cognition, i.e. the beautiful qualities, exists: or (3) a belief in the existence of the beautiful qualities, when they do not exist. The importance of these cases arises from the fact that the second defines the pleasures of imagination, including a great part of the appreciation of those works of art which are representative; whereas the first contrasts with these the appreciation of what is beautiful in Nature, and the human affections. The third, on the other hand, is contrasted with[p. 194] both, in that it is chiefly exemplified in what is called misdirected affection; and it is possible also that the love of God, in the case of a believer, should fall under this head.
Now, the situation I’ve referred to as an error of taste, where the qualities we admire (whether they actually belong to the ‘object’ or not) are unattractive, holds no real value except for the emotion itself; and in most cases, it’s actually a significant drawback. In this sense, it's definitely reasonable to say that finding beauty in something that has none is less valuable than recognizing beauty where it truly exists. However, the other situation is much more complex. In this case, we have all that I've previously mentioned as necessary to create a great positive good: we have awareness of genuinely beautiful qualities, along with a fitting emotional response to these qualities. Therefore, there's no doubt that this constitutes a significant positive good. But there’s also something else involved; specifically, a belief that these beautiful qualities are real, and that they exist in relation to other things—namely, some traits of the object we attribute these qualities to. Moreover, the belief we hold is incorrect. We might wonder, regarding the whole situation, whether the presence of the belief and the fact that it’s false affects its value. This leads us to three different scenarios where determining their relative values is very important. When both the understanding of beautiful qualities and the matching emotion are present, we might also have either, (1) a belief in the existence of these qualities that is actually true: or (2) a mere awareness, without belief, when it is (a) true, (b) false, that the object of awareness, i.e., the beautiful qualities, exist: or (3) a belief in the existence of beautiful qualities when they do not actually exist. The significance of these cases comes from the fact that the second one defines the pleasures of imagination, which includes a large part of our appreciation for those works of art that are representative; while the first contrasts with this, highlighting the appreciation of what is beautiful in Nature and human emotions. The third, on the other hand, is contrasted with both, as it is mainly shown in what we call misdirected affection; and it’s also possible that a believer’s love for God could fall into this category.
117. Now all these three cases, as I have said, have something in common, namely, that, in them all, we have a cognition of really beautiful qualities together with an appropriate emotion towards those qualities. I think, therefore, it cannot be doubted (nor is it commonly doubted) that all three include great positive goods; they are all things of which we feel convinced that they are worth having for their own sakes. And I think that the value of the second, in either of its two subdivisions, is precisely the same as the value of the element common to all three. In other words, in the case of purely imaginative appreciations we have merely the cognition of really beautiful qualities together with the appropriate emotion; and the question, whether the object cognised exists or not, seems here, where there is no belief either in its existence or in its non-existence, to make absolutely no difference to the value of the total state. But it seems to me that the two other cases do differ in intrinsic value both from this one and from one another, even though the object cognised and the appropriate emotion should be identical in all three cases. I think that the additional presence of a belief in the reality of the object makes the total state much better, if the belief is true; and worse, if the belief is false. In short, where there is belief, in the sense in which we do believe in the existence of Nature and horses, and do not believe in the existence of an ideal landscape and unicorns, the truth of what is believed does make a great difference to the value of the organic whole. If this be the case, we shall have vindicated the belief that knowledge, in the ordinary sense, as distinguished on the one hand from belief in what is false and on the other from the mere awareness of what is true, does contribute towards intrinsic value—that, at least in some cases, its presence as a part makes a whole more valuable than it could have been without.
117. Now, all three of these cases, as I’ve mentioned, have something in common: in each case, we recognize truly beautiful qualities along with a fitting emotion toward those qualities. I believe, therefore, it can’t be denied (and it's not usually questioned) that all three involve significant positive benefits; they are all things we feel are worth having for their own sake. I think the value of the second case, in either of its two subdivisions, is exactly the same as the value of the element shared by all three. In other words, in purely imaginative appreciation, we simply recognize beautiful qualities along with the relevant emotion, and whether the object recognized actually exists or not seems irrelevant here, where there’s no belief in either its existence or non-existence, to the overall value of the experience. However, it seems to me that the other two cases differ in intrinsic value both from this one and from each other, even if the recognized object and the appropriate emotion are the same in all three situations. I think that the presence of a belief in the reality of the object enhances the overall experience significantly if the belief is true, and diminishes it if the belief is false. In short, where we do believe in the existence of nature and horses, and do not believe in the existence of an ideal landscape and unicorns, the truth of what is believed greatly impacts the value of the entire experience. If this is the case, we will have confirmed the belief that knowledge, in the common understanding, set apart from belief in what is false and from mere awareness of what is true, does contribute to intrinsic value—that, at least in some situations, its inclusion as a component makes a whole more valuable than it could have been without it.
Now I think there can be no doubt that we do judge that[p. 195] there is a difference of value, such as I have indicated, between the three cases in question. We do think that the emotional contemplation of a natural scene, supposing its qualities equally beautiful, is in some way a better state of things than that of a painted landscape: we think that the world would be improved if we could substitute for the best works of representative art real objects equally beautiful. And similarly we regard a misdirected affection or admiration, even where the error involved is a mere error of judgment and not an error of taste, as in some way unfortunate. And further, those, at least, who have a strong respect for truth, are inclined to think that a merely poetical contemplation of the Kingdom of Heaven would be superior to that of the religious believer, if it were the case that the Kingdom of Heaven does not and will not really exist. Most persons, on a sober, reflective judgment, would feel some hesitation even in preferring the felicity of a madman, convinced that the world was ideal, to the condition either of a poet imagining an ideal world, or of themselves enjoying and appreciating the lesser goods which do and will exist: But, in order to assure ourselves that these judgments are really judgments of intrinsic value upon the question before us, and to satisfy ourselves that they are correct, it is necessary clearly to distinguish our question from two others which have a very important bearing upon our total judgment of the cases in question.
Now I believe there’s no doubt that we do recognize a difference in value, as I’ve pointed out, between the three scenarios we've discussed. We feel that emotionally experiencing a natural scene, assuming its qualities are equally beautiful, is somehow a better situation than that of looking at a painted landscape: we believe the world would be better off if we could replace the best works of representational art with real objects of equal beauty. Similarly, we view a misguided affection or admiration, even if the mistake is just a misjudgment rather than an issue of taste, as somewhat unfortunate. Furthermore, those who strongly value the truth tend to believe that a purely poetic contemplation of the Kingdom of Heaven would be better than that of a religious believer, if it turns out that the Kingdom of Heaven does not and will not truly exist. Most people, when thinking carefully, would hesitate to prefer the happiness of a madman who is convinced that the world is ideal over either a poet envisioning an ideal world or themselves enjoying and appreciating the real joys that do and will exist. However, to ensure that these judgments genuinely reflect intrinsic value regarding the matter at hand, and to confirm that they are correct, we need to clearly differentiate our question from two others that significantly impact our overall judgment of the cases in question.
118. In the first place (a) it is plain that, where we believe, the question whether what we believe is true or false, will generally have a most important bearing upon the value of our belief as a means. Where we believe, we are apt to act upon our belief, in a way in which we do not act upon our cognition of the events in a novel. The truth of what we believe is, therefore, very important as preventing the pains of disappointment and still more serious consequences. And it might be thought that a misdirected attachment was unfortunate solely for this reason: that it leads us to count upon results, which the real nature of its object is not of a kind to ensure. So too the Love of God, where, as usual, it includes the belief that he will annex to certain actions consequences, either in this life or[p. 196] the next, which the course of nature gives no reason to expect, may lead the believer to perform actions of which the actual consequences, supposing no such God to exist, may be much worse than he might otherwise have effected: and it might be thought that this was the sole reason (as it is a sufficient one) why we should hesitate to encourage the Love of God, in the absence of any proof that he exists. And similarly it may be thought that the only reason why beauty in Nature should be held superior to an equally beautiful landscape or imagination, is that its existence would ensure greater permanence and frequency in our emotional contemplation of that beauty. It is, indeed, certain that the chief importance of most knowledge—of the truth of most of the things which we believe—does, in this world, consist in its extrinsic advantages: it is immensely valuable as a means.
118. First of all, it’s clear that where we have beliefs, the question of whether those beliefs are true or false plays a significant role in determining their value as a means. When we believe something, we tend to act on that belief in ways we wouldn't act based solely on our understanding of events in a story. Therefore, the truth of our beliefs is crucial because it helps prevent the pain of disappointment and even more serious outcomes. It might be thought that misguided attachments are unfortunate mainly for this reason: they lead us to expect results that the true nature of their objects cannot guarantee. Similarly, the Love of God, which typically includes the belief that certain actions will bring consequences, either in this life or[p. 196] the next, that nature doesn't provide any reason to expect, can lead believers to take actions that could have much worse outcomes if we assume no such God exists. This could be seen as the only reason (and a sufficient one) to hesitate in encouraging the Love of God when there's no proof of His existence. Likewise, one could argue that the only reason beauty in Nature should be valued more than an equally beautiful landscape or imagination is that its existence would offer greater permanence and more frequent emotional engagement with that beauty. It’s clear that the main importance of most knowledge—the truth behind most of what we believe—lies in its external benefits: it is incredibly valuable as a means.
And secondly, (b) it may be the case that the existence of that which we contemplate is itself a great positive good, so that, for this reason alone, the state of things described by saying, that the object of our emotion really exists, would be intrinsically superior to that in which it did not. This reason for superiority is undoubtedly of great importance in the case of human affections, where the object of our admiration is the mental qualities of an admirable person; for that two such admirable persons should exist is greatly better than that there should be only one: and it would also discriminate the admiration of inanimate nature from that of its representations in art, in so far as we may allow a small intrinsic value to the existence of a beautiful object, apart from any contemplation of it. But it is to be noticed that this reason would not account for any difference in value between the cases where the truth was believed and that in which it was merely cognised, without either belief or disbelief. In other words, so far as this reason goes, the difference between the two subdivisions of our second class (that of imaginative contemplation) would be as great as between our first class and the second subdivision of our second. The superiority of the mere cognition of a beautiful object, when that object also happened to exist, over the same cognition when the object did not exist, would,[p. 197] on this count, be as great as that of the knowledge of a beautiful object over the mere imagination of it.
And secondly, (b) it might be true that the existence of what we contemplate is itself a significant positive good, so that, for this reason alone, the situation described by saying that the object of our emotion actually exists would be inherently better than one in which it does not. This reason for being better is certainly very important when it comes to human feelings, where the object of our admiration is the mental qualities of a worthy person; because having two such admirable people is much better than having just one. It also differentiates our admiration of inanimate nature from that of its representations in art, as we may grant a small intrinsic value to the existence of a beautiful object, regardless of whether we are contemplating it. However, it's important to note that this reason wouldn’t explain any difference in value between situations where the truth is believed and those where it’s simply acknowledged, without either belief or disbelief. In other words, as far as this reason goes, the difference between the two subcategories of our second class (that of imaginative contemplation) would be as significant as the difference between our first class and the second subcategory of our second class. The superiority of the mere cognition of a beautiful object, when that object also happens to exist, compared to the same cognition when the object did not exist, would, [p. 197] on this basis, be as considerable as that of the knowledge of a beautiful object over just imagining it.
119. These two reasons for discriminating between the value of the three cases we are considering, must, I say, be carefully distinguished from that, of which I am now questioning the validity, if we are to obtain a correct answer concerning this latter. The question I am putting is this: Whether the whole constituted by the fact that there is an emotional contemplation of a beautiful object, which both is believed to be and is real, does not derive some of its value from the fact that the object is real? I am asking whether the value of this whole, as a whole, is not greater than that of those which differ from it, either by the absence of belief, with or without truth, or, belief being present, by the mere absence of truth? I am not asking either whether it is not superior to them as a means (which it certainly is), nor whether it may not contain a more valuable part, namely, the existence of the object in question. My question is solely whether the existence of its object does not constitute an addition to the value of the whole, quite distinct from the addition constituted by the fact that this whole does contain a valuable part.
119. These two reasons for distinguishing the value of the three cases we are looking at must be carefully separated from the one I am currently questioning, if we want to get the right answer about the latter. The question I’m asking is this: Does the entire experience of emotionally contemplating a beautiful object, which is both believed to be and is real, derive some of its value from the fact that the object is real? I’m wondering if the value of this entire experience, as a whole, is greater than that of those which differ from it, either due to the lack of belief, regardless of whether there is truth, or, if belief is present, simply by the absence of truth? I’m not asking either whether it isn’t superior to them as a means (which it definitely is), nor whether it might not contain a more valuable part, namely, the existence of the object itself. My question is only whether the existence of its object adds to the value of the whole in a way that’s distinct from the increase in value coming from the fact that this whole includes a valuable part.
If, now, we put this question, I cannot avoid thinking that it should receive an affirmative answer. We can put it clearly by the method of isolation; and the sole decision must rest with our reflective judgment upon it, as thus clearly put. We can guard against the bias produced by a consideration of value as a means by supposing the case of an illusion as complete and permanent as illusions in this world never can be. We can imagine the case of a single person, enjoying throughout eternity the contemplation of scenery as beautiful, and intercourse with persons as admirable, as can be imagined; while yet the whole of the objects of his cognition are absolutely unreal. I think we should definitely pronounce the existence of a universe, which consisted solely of such a person, to be greatly inferior in value to one in which the objects, in the existence of which he believes, did really exist just as he believes them to do; and that it would be thus inferior not only because it would lack the goods which consist in the existence of the objects in question, but also[p. 198] merely because his belief would be false. That it would be inferior for this reason alone follows if we admit, what also appears to me certain, that the case of a person, merely imagining, without believing, the beautiful objects in question, would, although these objects really existed, be yet inferior to that of the person who also believed in their existence. For here all the additional good, which consists in the existence of the objects, is present, and yet there still seems to be a great difference in value between this case and that in which their existence is believed. But I think that my conclusion may perhaps be exhibited in a more convincing light by the following considerations. (1) It does not seem to me that the small degree of value which we may allow to the existence of beautiful inanimate objects is nearly equal in amount to the difference which I feel that there is between the appreciation (accompanied by belief) of such objects, when they really exist, and the purely imaginative appreciation of them when they do not exist. This inequality is more difficult to verify where the object is an admirable person, since a great value must be allowed to his existence. But yet I think it is not paradoxical to maintain that the superiority of reciprocal affection, where both objects are worthy and both exist, over an unreciprocated affection, where both are worthy but one does not exist, does not lie solely in the fact that, in the former case, we have two good things instead of one, but also in the fact that each is such as the other believes him to be. (2) It seems to me that the important contribution to value made by true belief may be very plainly seen in the following case. Suppose that a worthy object of affection does really exist and is believed to do so, but that there enters into the case this error of fact, that the qualities loved, though exactly like, are yet not the same which really do exist. This state of things is easily imagined, and I think we cannot avoid pronouncing that, although both persons here exist, it is yet not so satisfactory as where the very person loved and believed to exist is also the one which actually does exist.
If we ask this question now, I can't help but think it deserves a yes answer. We can clarify it by isolating the issue; the final judgment must be based on our reflective thinking about it, as it has been clearly stated. We can avoid the bias from considering value as a means by imagining a scenario where an illusion is complete and permanent, something that illusions in our world can never be. We can picture a single person, enjoying for all eternity the beauty of a landscape and the company of admirable people, even though everything he perceives is completely unreal. I believe we should definitely say that a universe consisting solely of such a person is greatly inferior in value to one where the objects he believes in truly exist just as he thinks they do; and it would be inferior not only because it lacks the reality of those objects, but also [p. 198] simply because his belief is false. It would be inferior for this reason alone if we accept, which I also see as likely, that a person merely imagining, without actually believing in, those beautiful objects would, even though those objects did exist, still be in a lesser situation than the person who actually believes in their existence. Because in that scenario, all the additional goodness from the existence of the objects is present, yet there's still a significant difference in value compared to someone who believes in that existence. But I think I can present my conclusion in a more convincing way through the following points. (1) To me, the small value we might assign to the existence of beautiful inanimate objects is nowhere near equal to the difference I feel between appreciating (with belief) such objects when they actually exist versus appreciating them purely in imagination when they don’t exist. This difference is harder to prove when the object is an admirable person, as we must acknowledge a great value in their existence. However, I think it's not unreasonable to argue that the superiority of mutual affection, where both parties are worthy and exist, over unreciprocated affection, where both are worthy but one does not exist, lies not just in having two good things instead of one, but also in the fact that each person is perceived as the other believes them to be. (2) I think the significant value added by genuine belief can be clearly illustrated with the following scenario. Imagine a worthy object of affection that truly exists and is believed to exist, but there's an error in that the loved qualities, while similar, are not the same as those that actually exist. We can easily imagine this situation, and I believe we cannot avoid saying that, although both people are present, it’s still not as satisfying as when the very person loved and believed to exist is also the one who actually exists.
120. If all this be so, we have, in this third section, added to our two former results the third result that a true belief in the reality of an object greatly increases the value of many[p. 199] valuable wholes. Just as in sections (1) and (2) it was maintained that aesthetic and affectionate emotions had little or no value apart from the cognition of appropriate objects, and that the cognition of these objects had little or no value apart from the appropriate emotion, so that the whole, in which both were combined, had a value greatly in excess of the sum of the values of its parts; so, according to this section, if there be added to these wholes a true belief in the reality of the object, the new whole thus formed has a value greatly in excess of the sum obtained by adding the value of the true belief, considered in itself, to that of our original wholes. This new case only differs from the former in this, that, whereas the true belief, by itself, has quite as little value as either of the two other constituents taken singly, yet they, taken together, seem to form a whole of very great value, whereas this is not the case with the two wholes which might be formed by adding the true belief to either of the others.
120. If all this is true, in this third section, we have added to our previous two results a third one: that genuinely believing in the reality of an object significantly boosts the value of many[p. 199] valuable wholes. Just as in sections (1) and (2) it was argued that aesthetic and affectionate emotions have little or no value without understanding the right objects, and that understanding these objects has little or no value without the appropriate emotion, creating a whole where both are combined results in a value much greater than the sum of its parts; this section suggests that if a true belief in the reality of the object is added to these wholes, the new whole formed has a value significantly greater than simply adding the value of the true belief, considered on its own, to that of our original wholes. The only difference here is that, while the true belief has as little value by itself as either of the two other components alone, when combined, they seem to create a whole of very high value, which isn’t the case with the two wholes formed by adding the true belief to either of the others.
The importance of the result of this section seems to lie mainly in two of its consequences. (1) That it affords some justification for the immense intrinsic value, which seems to be commonly attributed to the mere knowledge of some truths, and which was expressly attributed to some kinds of knowledge by Plato and Aristotle. Perfect knowledge has indeed competed with perfect love for the position of Ideal. If the results of this section are correct, it appears that knowledge, though having little or no value by itself, is an absolutely essential constituent in the highest goods, and contributes immensely to their value. And it appears that this function may be performed not only by that case of knowledge, which we have chiefly considered, namely, knowledge of the reality of the beautiful object cognised, but also by knowledge of the numerical identity of this object with that which really exists, and by the knowledge that the existence of that object is truly good. Indeed all knowledge, which is directly concerned with the nature of the constituents of a beautiful object, would seem capable of adding greatly to the value of the contemplation of that object, although, by itself, such knowledge would have no value at all.—And (2) The second important consequence, which follows from this section,[p. 200] is that the presence of true belief may, in spite of a great inferiority in the value of the emotion and the beauty of its object, constitute with them a whole equal or superior in value to wholes, in which the emotion and beauty are superior, but in which a true belief is wanting or a false belief present. In this way we may justify the attribution of equal or superior value to an appreciation of an inferior real object, as compared with the appreciation of a greatly superior object which is a mere creature of the imagination. Thus a just appreciation of nature and of real persons may maintain its equality with an equally just appreciation of the products of artistic imagination, in spite of much greater beauty in the latter. And similarly though God may be admitted to be a more perfect object than any actual human being, the love of God may yet be inferior to human love, if God does not exist.
The significance of the results in this section mainly lies in two of its implications. (1) It provides some justification for the immense intrinsic value that is often attributed to simply having knowledge of certain truths, a value specifically acknowledged by Plato and Aristotle regarding some types of knowledge. Perfect knowledge has indeed rivaled perfect love for the title of Ideal. If the findings here are accurate, it seems that knowledge, despite having little or no value on its own, is an absolutely essential part of the highest goods and greatly enhances their value. This role seems to be fulfilled not only by the type of knowledge we primarily focused on, which is knowledge of the reality of the beautiful object recognized, but also by knowledge of the numerical identity of this object with what truly exists, and by the understanding that the existence of that object is genuinely good. In fact, all knowledge that directly relates to the nature of the components of a beautiful object seems capable of significantly enhancing the value of contemplating that object, even though such knowledge alone would be of no value at all. — And (2) The second important consequence of this section,[p. 200] is that the presence of true belief may, despite a much lower value of the emotion and the beauty of its object, create a whole that is equal to or greater in value than wholes where the emotion and beauty are superior but lack true belief or contain false belief. This allows us to justify considering an appreciation of a less significant real object as having equal or greater value compared to the appreciation of an immensely superior object that is merely a figment of the imagination. Thus, a fair appreciation of nature and real people can maintain its worth alongside a similarly fair appreciation of the products of artistic imagination, even though the latter may be much more beautiful. Similarly, while God might be seen as a more perfect object than any actual human being, love for God may still be lesser than human love, if God does not exist.
121. (4) In order to complete the discussion of this first class of goods—goods which have an essential reference to beautiful objects—it would be necessary to attempt a classification and comparative valuation of all the different forms of beauty, a task which properly belongs to the study called Aesthetics. I do not, however, propose to attempt any part of this task. It must only be understood that I intend to include among the essential constituents of the goods I have been discussing, every form and variety of beautiful object, if only it be truly beautiful; and, if this be understood, I think it may be seen that the consensus of opinion with regard to what is positively beautiful and what is positively ugly, and even with regard to great differences in degree of beauty, is quite sufficient to allow us a hope that we need not greatly err in our judgments of good and evil. In anything which is thought beautiful by any considerable number of persons, there is probably some beautiful quality; and differences of opinion seem to be far more often due to exclusive attention, on the part of different persons, to different qualities in the same object, than to the positive error of supposing a quality that is ugly to be really beautiful. When an object, which some think beautiful, is denied to be so by others, the truth is usually that it lacks some beautiful quality or is deformed by[p. 201] some ugly one, which engage the exclusive attention of the critics.
121. (4) To wrap up the discussion about this first category of goods—those that relate to beautiful objects—it would be essential to try to classify and compare the value of all the different types of beauty, a task that rightly falls under the study of Aesthetics. However, I do not plan to embark on that task. It should just be understood that I intend to include in the essential elements of the goods I've been talking about every form and variety of beautiful object, as long as it is genuinely beautiful; and if this is clear, I believe we can see that the general agreement on what is definitely beautiful and what is definitely ugly, even regarding significant variations in beauty, is enough to give us confidence that we won't be too far off in our judgments of good and evil. In anything considered beautiful by a considerable number of people, there is likely some beautiful quality; and differences in opinion seem to stem more from people focusing exclusively on different qualities within the same object than from the mistaken belief that an ugly quality is actually beautiful. When an object that some find beautiful is declared otherwise by others, the reality is that it usually lacks some beautiful quality or is marred by[p. 201] some ugly aspect that draws the sole focus of the critics.
I may, however, state two general principles, closely connected with the results of this chapter, the recognition of which would seem to be of great importance for the investigation of what things are truly beautiful. The first of these is (1) a definition of beauty, of what is meant by saying that a thing is truly beautiful. The naturalistic fallacy has been quite as commonly committed with regard to beauty as with regard to good: its use has introduced as many errors into Aesthetics as into Ethics. It has been even more commonly supposed that the beautiful may be defined as that which produces certain effects upon our feelings; and the conclusion which follows from this—namely, that judgments of taste are merely subjective—that precisely the same thing may, according to circumstances, be both beautiful and not beautiful—has very frequently been drawn. The conclusions of this chapter suggest a definition of beauty, which may partially explain and entirely remove the difficulties which have led to this error. It appears probable that the beautiful should be defined as that of which the admiring contemplation is good in itself. That is to say: To assert that a thing is beautiful is to assert that the cognition of it is an essential element in one of the intrinsically valuable wholes we have been discussing; so that the question, whether it is truly beautiful or not, depends upon the objective question whether the whole in question is or is not truly good, and does not depend upon the question whether it would or would not excite particular feelings in particular persons. This definition has the double recommendation that it accounts both for the apparent connection between goodness and beauty and for the no less apparent difference between these two conceptions. It appears, at first sight, to be a strange coincidence, that there should be two different objective predicates of value, ‘good’ and ‘beautiful,’ which are nevertheless so related to one another that whatever is beautiful is also good. But, if our definition be correct, the strangeness disappears; since it leaves only one unanalysable predicate of value, namely ‘good,’ while ‘beautiful,’ though not identical with, is to be defined by reference to this,[p. 202] being thus, at the same time, different from and necessarily connected with it. In short, on this view, to say that a thing is beautiful is to say, not indeed that it is itself good, but that it is a necessary element in something which is: to prove that a thing is truly beautiful is to prove that a whole, to which it bears a particular relation as a part, is truly good. And in this way we should explain the immense predominance, among objects commonly considered beautiful, of material objects—objects of the external senses; since these objects, though themselves having, as has been said, little or no intrinsic value, are yet essential constituents in the largest group of wholes which have intrinsic value. These wholes themselves may be, and are, also beautiful; but the comparative rarity, with which we regard them as themselves objects of contemplation, seems sufficient to explain the association of beauty with external objects.
I can, however, mention two general principles closely tied to the findings of this chapter, which seem crucial for examining what things are truly beautiful. The first of these is (1) a definition of beauty—what it means to say that something is truly beautiful. The naturalistic fallacy has been just as frequently committed regarding beauty as it has been regarding goodness; its use has introduced as many errors into Aesthetics as it has into Ethics. It has often been assumed that beauty can be defined as something that produces certain feelings in us; and the conclusion drawn from this—namely, that judgments of taste are merely subjective—suggests that the same thing can, depending on the circumstances, be both beautiful and not beautiful. The conclusions of this chapter propose a definition of beauty that may help explain and fully resolve the difficulties that have led to this mistake. It seems likely that beauty should be defined as that which is good in itself when admired. In other words, to claim that something is beautiful means asserting that understanding it is a key part of one of the inherently valuable whole discussions we've had; thus, the question of whether it is truly beautiful or not is based on the objective question of whether that whole is genuinely good, and not on whether it would or would not provoke specific feelings in particular people. This definition has the advantage of explaining both the apparent connection between goodness and beauty and the clear distinction between these two concepts. It initially seems odd that there are two different objective values—‘good’ and ‘beautiful’—which are related such that anything beautiful is also good. However, if our definition is correct, this oddity fades; it shows that there is only one unanalysable value, which is ‘good,’ while ‘beautiful,’ though not the same, is defined in relation to this, [p. 202] being thus both different and necessarily connected. In short, from this perspective, saying that something is beautiful doesn't mean it is itself good, but that it is a necessary part of something that is: to prove that something is truly beautiful is to prove that a larger whole, of which it is a part, is truly good. This also helps explain the overwhelming predominance of material objects—external sensory objects—in what we generally consider beautiful; even though these objects themselves have, as mentioned, little or no intrinsic value, they are essential parts of the largest groups of wholes that do have intrinsic value. These wholes can also be beautiful, but the relative rarity with which we view them as objects of contemplation seems to adequately clarify why beauty is associated with external objects.
And secondly (2) it is to be observed that beautiful objects are themselves, for the most part, organic unities, in this sense, that they are wholes of great complexity, such that the contemplation of any part, by itself, may have no value, and yet that, unless the contemplation of the whole includes the contemplation of that part, it will lose in value. From this it follows that there can be no single criterion of beauty. It will never be true to say: This object owes its beauty solely to the presence of this characteristic; nor yet that: Wherever this characteristic is present, the object must be beautiful. All that can be true is that certain objects are beautiful, because they have certain characteristics, in the sense that they would not be beautiful unless they had them. And it may be possible to find that certain characteristics are more or less universally present in all beautiful objects, and are, in this sense, more or less important conditions of beauty. But it is important to observe that the very qualities, which differentiate one beautiful object from all others, are, if the object be truly beautiful, as essential to its beauty, as those which it has in common with ever so many others. The object would no more have the beauty it has, without its specific qualities, than without those that are generic; and the generic qualities, by themselves, would fail, as completely, to give beauty, as those which are specific.
And secondly, it should be noted that beautiful objects are mostly organic wholes, meaning they are complex entities where considering any single part alone might not hold much value. However, if appreciating the whole doesn't include considering that part, its value diminishes. This leads to the conclusion that there can't be a single standard for beauty. It’s inaccurate to say: This object’s beauty comes exclusively from this characteristic; or conversely: Any object with this characteristic must be beautiful. What can be accurate is that certain objects are beautiful because they possess specific characteristics, meaning they wouldn’t be beautiful if they lacked them. It might be possible to identify certain characteristics that appear more or less universally in all beautiful objects and that are, in this way, more or less crucial for beauty. But it’s essential to recognize that the unique qualities that set one beautiful object apart from others are, if the object is truly beautiful, just as vital to its beauty as the qualities it shares with many others. The object wouldn’t have its specific beauty without its unique qualities any more than it would without its common ones; and the common qualities, on their own, would completely fail to convey beauty, just like those that are unique.
[p. 203]122. II. It will be remembered that I began this survey of great unmixed goods, by dividing all the greatest goods we know into the two classes of aesthetic enjoyments, on the one hand, and the pleasures of human intercourse or of personal affection, on the other. I postponed the consideration of the latter on the ground that they presented additional complications. In what this additional complication consists, will now be evident; and I have already been obliged to take account of it, in discussing the contribution to value made by true belief. It consists in the fact that in the case of personal affection, the object itself is not merely beautiful, while possessed of little or no intrinsic value, but is itself, in part at least, of great intrinsic value. All the constituents which we have found to be necessary to the most valuable aesthetic enjoyments, namely, appropriate emotion, cognition of truly beautiful qualities, and true belief, are equally necessary here; but here we have the additional fact that the object must be not only truly beautiful, but also truly good in a high degree.
[p. 203]122. II. It will be remembered that I started this exploration of significant pure goods by categorizing all the greatest goods we know into two groups: aesthetic pleasures, on one side, and the joys of human connection or personal affection, on the other. I delayed discussing the latter because it involves more complexities. The nature of these extra complications will now be clear; I have already had to address it when considering the value added by true belief. This complexity lies in the fact that, with personal affection, the object is not just beautiful with little or no intrinsic worth, but is also, at least in part, of considerable intrinsic value. All the elements we've identified as essential for the most valuable aesthetic experiences—namely, suitable emotion, understanding of genuinely beautiful qualities, and true belief—are equally crucial here, but we also have the additional requirement that the object must be not only genuinely beautiful but also truly good to a high extent.
It is evident that this additional complication only occurs in so far as there is included in the object of personal affection some of the mental qualities of the person towards whom the affection is felt. And I think it may be admitted that, wherever the affection is most valuable, the appreciation of mental qualities must form a large part of it, and that the presence of this part makes the whole far more valuable than it could have been without it. But it seems very doubtful whether this appreciation, by itself, can possess as much value as the whole in which it is combined with an appreciation of the appropriate corporeal expression of the mental qualities in question. It is certain that in all actual cases of valuable affection, the bodily expressions of character, whether by looks, by words, or by actions, do form a part of the object towards which the affection is felt, and that the fact of their inclusion appears to heighten the value of the whole state. It is, indeed, very difficult to imagine what the cognition of mental qualities alone, unaccompanied by any corporeal expression, would be like; and, in so far as we succeed in making this abstraction, the whole considered certainly appears to have less value. I[p. 204] therefore conclude that the importance of an admiration of admirable mental qualities lies chiefly in the immense superiority of a whole, in which it forms a part, to one in which it is absent, and not in any high degree of intrinsic value which it possesses by itself. It even appears to be doubtful, whether, in itself, it possesses so much value as the appreciation of mere corporeal beauty undoubtedly does possess; that is to say, whether the appreciation of what has great intrinsic value is so valuable as the appreciation of what is merely beautiful.
It’s clear that this extra complication only happens when the object of personal affection includes some of the mental qualities of the person we feel affection for. I think it’s safe to say that wherever affection is most meaningful, recognizing mental qualities plays a big role in it, and having this aspect makes the whole experience much more valuable than it would be without it. However, it’s really questionable whether this appreciation, by itself, can have as much value as the complete experience that combines it with recognition of the appropriate physical expression of those mental qualities. It’s certain that in all real instances of meaningful affection, the physical expressions of character—whether through looks, words, or actions—are part of what we feel affection for, and the inclusion of these expressions seems to enhance the overall value of the experience. It’s actually quite hard to imagine what understanding mental qualities alone, without any physical expression, would be like; and to the extent that we manage to make this separation, the whole experience certainly seems less valuable. I[p. 204] therefore conclude that the importance of admiring admirable mental qualities lies mainly in how much more valuable an experience is when it includes them compared to when it does not, rather than in any significant intrinsic value that it has on its own. It even seems uncertain whether, by itself, it holds as much value as the appreciation of mere physical beauty undoubtedly does; in other words, whether valuing something with great intrinsic worth is as valuable as valuing something that is simply beautiful.
But further if we consider the nature of admirable mental qualities, by themselves, it appears that a proper appreciation of them involves a reference to purely material beauty in yet another way. Admirable mental qualities do, if our previous conclusions are correct, consist very largely in an emotional contemplation of beautiful objects; and hence the appreciation of them will consist essentially in the contemplation of such contemplation. It is true that the most valuable appreciation of persons appears to be that which consists in the appreciation of their appreciation of other persons: but even here a reference to material beauty appears to be involved, both in respect of the fact that what is appreciated in the last instance may be the contemplation of what is merely beautiful, and in respect of the fact that the most valuable appreciation of a person appears to include an appreciation of his corporeal expression. Though, therefore, we may admit that the appreciation of a person’s attitude towards other persons, or, to take one instance, the love of love, is far the most valuable good we know, and far more valuable than the mere love of beauty, yet we can only admit this if the first be understood to include the latter, in various degrees of directness.
But if we think about what makes mental qualities admirable, it seems that truly appreciating them also involves a reference to physical beauty in another way. Admirable mental qualities, if our earlier conclusions are right, largely stem from an emotional appreciation of beautiful objects; therefore, understanding them fundamentally involves reflecting on that appreciation. It’s true that the best way to appreciate someone is to value how they appreciate others: but even in this case, we see that reference to physical beauty is involved, both because what’s ultimately appreciated may simply be the contemplation of beauty, and because the best appreciation of a person seems to include an awareness of their physical presence. So, while we might agree that valuing someone's attitude towards others, or the love of love, is the highest good we know, and much more valuable than just loving beauty, we can only accept this if we understand that the former includes the latter, albeit in different ways.
With regard to the question what are the mental qualities of which the cognition is essential to the value of human intercourse, it is plain that they include, in the first place, all those varieties of aesthetic appreciation, which formed our first class of goods. They include, therefore, a great variety of different emotions, each of which is appropriate to some different kind of beauty. But we must now add to these the whole range of emotions, which are appropriate to persons, and which are[p. 205] different from those which are appropriate to mere corporeal beauty. It must also be remembered that just as these emotions have little value in themselves, and as the state of mind in which they exist may have its value greatly heightened, or may entirely lose it and become positively evil in a great degree, according as the cognitions accompanying the emotions are appropriate or inappropriate; so too the appreciation of these emotions, though it may have some value in itself, may yet form part of a whole which has far greater value or no value at all, according as it is or is not accompanied by a perception of the appropriateness of the emotions to their objects. It is obvious, therefore, that the study of what is valuable in human intercourse is a study of immense complexity; and that there may be much human intercourse which has little or no value, or is positively bad. Yet here too, as with the question what is beautiful, there seems no reason to doubt that a reflective judgment will in the main decide correctly both as to what are positive goods and even as to any great differences in value between these goods. In particular, it may be remarked that the emotions, of which the contemplation is essential to the greatest values, and which are also themselves appropriately excited by such contemplation, appear to be those which are commonly most highly prized under the name of affection.
Regarding the question of what mental qualities are essential for the value of human interaction, it's clear that they include, first and foremost, all the different forms of aesthetic appreciation, which made up our first category of goods. They encompass a wide range of emotions, each suited to a different kind of beauty. However, we must also consider the full spectrum of emotions appropriate to individuals, which differ from those related to physical beauty alone. It should be noted that just as these emotions have little intrinsic value on their own, and their significance can be greatly increased or completely diminish—potentially becoming harmful—based on whether the accompanying thoughts are fitting or not; the appreciation of these emotions, while it may have some value in itself, can also be part of a bigger picture that is much more valuable or of no value at all, depending on whether it is paired with an understanding of the appropriateness of the emotions toward their objects. Therefore, it’s clear that studying what is valuable in human interactions is incredibly complex; there may be much human interaction that holds little to no value, or is actively harmful. Yet here too, similar to the discussion of beauty, it seems reasonable to expect that thoughtful judgment will generally determine correctly what constitutes positive goods and even identify significant differences in value among those goods. Notably, it can be observed that the emotions that are crucial for experiencing the highest values, and which are themselves stirred by such contemplation, tend to be those that are commonly prized as affection.
123. I have now completed my examination into the nature of those great positive goods, which do not appear to include among their constituents anything positively evil or ugly, though they include much which is in itself indifferent. And I wish to point out certain conclusions which appear to follow, with regard to the nature of the Summum Bonum, or that state of things which would be the most perfect we can conceive. Those idealistic philosophers, whose views agree most closely with those here advocated, in that they deny pleasure to be the sole good and regard what is completely good as having some complexity, have usually represented a purely spiritual state of existence as the Ideal. Regarding matter as essentially imperfect, if not positively evil, they have concluded that the total absence of all material properties is necessary to a state of perfection. Now, according to what has been said, this view[p. 206] would be correct so far as it asserts that any great good must be mental, and so far as it asserts that a purely material existence, by itself, can have little or no value. The superiority of the spiritual over the material has, in a sense, been amply vindicated. But it does not follow, from this superiority, that a perfect state of things must be one, from which all material properties are rigidly excluded: on the contrary, if our conclusions are correct, it would seem to be the case that a state of things, in which they are included, must be vastly better than any conceivable state in which they were absent. In order to see that this is so, the chief thing necessary to be considered is exactly what it is which we declare to be good when we declare that the appreciation of beauty in Art and Nature is so. That this appreciation is good, the philosophers in question do not for the most part deny. But, if we admit it, then we should remember Butler’s maxim that: Everything is what it is, and not another thing. I have tried to shew, and I think it is too evident to be disputed, that such appreciation is an organic unity, a complex whole; and that, in its most undoubted instances, part of what is included in this whole is a cognition of material qualities, and particularly of a vast variety of what are called secondary qualities. If, then, it is this whole, which we know to be good, and not another thing, then we know that material qualities, even though they be perfectly worthless in themselves, are yet essential constituents of what is far from worthless. What we know to be valuable is the apprehension of just these qualities, and not of any others; and, if we propose to subtract them from it, then what we have left is not that which we know to have value, but something else. And it must be noticed that this conclusion holds, even if my contention, that a true belief in the existence of these qualities adds to the value of the whole in which it is included, be disputed. We should then, indeed, be entitled to assert that the existence of a material world was wholly immaterial to perfection; but the fact that what we knew to be good was a cognition of material qualities (though purely imaginary), would still remain. It must, then, be admitted on pain of self-contradiction—on pain of holding that things are not what they are, but something else[p. 207]—that a world, from which material qualities were wholly banished, would be a world which lacked many, if not all, of those things, which we know most certainly to be great goods. That it might nevertheless be a far better world than one which retained these goods, I have already admitted (§ 111 (1)). But in order to shew that any such world would be thus better, it would be necessary to shew that the retention of these things, though good in themselves, impaired, in a more than equal degree, the value of some whole, to which they might belong; and the task of shewing this has certainly never been attempted. Until it be performed, we are entitled to assert that material qualities are a necessary constituent of the Ideal; that, though something utterly unknown might be better than any world containing either them or any other good we know, yet we have no reason to suppose that anything whatever would be better than a state of things in which they were included. To deny and exclude matter, is to deny and exclude the best we know. That a thing may retain its value, while losing some of its qualities, is utterly untrue. All that is true is that the changed thing may have more value than, or as much value as, that of which the qualities have been lost. What I contend is that nothing, which we know to be good and which contains no material qualities, has such great value that we can declare it, by itself, to be superior to the whole which would be formed by the addition to it of an appreciation of material qualities. That a purely spiritual good may be the best of single things, I am not much concerned to dispute, although, in what has been said with regard to the nature of personal affection, I have given reasons for doubting it. But that by adding to it some appreciation of material qualities, which, though perhaps inferior by itself, is certainly a great positive good, we should obtain a greater sum of value, which no corresponding decrease in the value of the whole, as a whole, could counterbalance—this, I maintain, we have certainly no reason to doubt.
123. I have now finished my exploration of the nature of those great positive goods, which seem to lack any elements that are truly evil or unattractive, even though they include many things that are indifferent. I want to highlight certain conclusions that seem to stem from this regarding the nature of the Summum Bonum, or that state of affairs which would be the most perfect we can imagine. Those idealistic philosophers, whose ideas align most closely with the ones I've presented here, deny that pleasure is the only good and believe that complete goodness has some complexity. They often depict a purely spiritual existence as the Ideal. Seeing matter as fundamentally flawed, if not outright evil, they conclude that a complete absence of all material properties is necessary for perfection. However, based on what I’ve discussed, this view[p. 206] is correct only in stating that any significant good must be mental, and in claiming that a purely material existence, by itself, has little or no value. The superiority of the spiritual over the material has, in a sense, been thoroughly justified. However, it does not follow from this superiority that a perfect state must eliminate all material properties; on the contrary, if our conclusions are accurate, it seems that a state of affairs that includes them must be far better than any conceivable state without them. To grasp this, the key aspect to consider is exactly what it is that we call good when we say that appreciating beauty in Art and Nature is good. Most philosophers do not deny that this appreciation is good. But if we accept it, we should remember Butler’s principle that: Everything is what it is, and not something else. I have attempted to show, and I believe it's too clear to dispute, that such an appreciation is an organic unity, a complex whole; and that, in its clearest examples, what is included in this whole is an awareness of material qualities, especially a wide range of what are known as secondary qualities. If it is this whole that we recognize as good, and not something else, then we understand that material qualities, even if they are worthless on their own, are still essential parts of what is far from worthless. What we perceive as valuable is the recognition of these qualities, and not of any other qualities; and if we attempt to remove them, what’s left is not what we acknowledge as valuable, but something different. Furthermore, it must be noted that this conclusion remains valid, even if someone disputes my claim that a true belief in the existence of these qualities enhances the value of the whole they belong to. We could then assert that the existence of a material world was completely irrelevant to perfection; however, the fact that what we recognize as good is a perception of material qualities (even if purely imaginary) would still hold true. Therefore, we must admit, under penalty of self-contradiction—under penalty of claiming that things are not as they are, but as something else[p. 207]—that a world devoid of material qualities would lack many, if not all, of those things we know for certain to be great goods. That it could still be a far better world than one that included these goods, I have already acknowledged (§ 111 (1)). However, to demonstrate that such a world would be better, we would need to show that keeping these qualities, though good on their own, diminishes the value of some whole they might belong to; and this task has certainly never been undertaken. Until it is done, we are justified in asserting that material qualities are a necessary part of the Ideal; that, although something completely unknown might be better than any world with either them or any other good we understand, we have no grounds to believe that anything at all would surpass a state of affairs that includes them. To deny and exclude matter is to deny and exclude what we know to be the best. The idea that a thing may retain its value while losing some of its qualities is entirely false. What is true is that the altered thing may be more valuable than, or just as valuable as, the original thing from which the qualities have been lost. My argument is that nothing we know to be good, which contains no material qualities, holds such significant value that we can claim it, by itself, to be superior to the entirety formed by adding an appreciation of material qualities. Whether a purely spiritual good might be the best of single things, I am not particularly eager to dispute, although I have presented reasons to doubt this in previous discussions about personal affection. But by adding some appreciation of material qualities, which, though possibly lesser on their own, is undoubtedly a significant positive good, we should achieve a greater overall value that no corresponding decrease in the total value of the whole could outweigh—this, I assert, we certainly have no reason to doubt.
124. In order to complete this discussion of the main principles involved in the determination of intrinsic values, the chief remaining topics, necessary to be treated, appear to be two. The first of these is the nature of great intrinsic evils,[p. 208] including what I may call mixed evils; that is to say, those evil wholes, which nevertheless contain, as essential elements, something positively good or beautiful. And the second is the nature of what I may similarly call mixed goods; that is to say, those wholes, which, though intrinsically good as wholes, nevertheless contain, as essential elements, something positively evil or ugly. It will greatly facilitate this discussion, if I may be understood throughout to use the terms ‘beautiful’ and ‘ugly,’ not necessarily with reference to things of the kind which most naturally occur to us as instances of what is beautiful and ugly, but in accordance with my own proposed definition of beauty. Thus I shall use the word ‘beautiful’ to denote that of which the admiring contemplation is good in itself; and ‘ugly’ to denote that of which the admiring contemplation is evil in itself.
124. To wrap up this discussion on the main principles involved in figuring out intrinsic values, the key topics left to cover seem to be two. The first is the nature of significant intrinsic evils,[p. 208] which includes what I call mixed evils; these are evil entities that still contain something genuinely good or beautiful as essential elements. The second topic is the nature of what I refer to as mixed goods; these are entities that are intrinsically good as a whole, yet they also include something inherently evil or ugly as essential elements. This discussion will be much smoother if I can clarify that, when I use the terms 'beautiful' and 'ugly,' I’m not just referencing the things that first come to mind as beautiful or ugly. Instead, I’ll follow my own definition of beauty. So, I’ll use 'beautiful' to describe something that is good to admire, and 'ugly' to describe something that is bad to admire.
I. With regard, then, to great positive evils, I think it is evident that, if we take all due precautions to discover precisely what those things are, of which, if they existed absolutely by themselves, we should judge the existence to be a great evil, we shall find most of them to be organic unities of exactly the same nature as those which are the greatest positive goods. That is to say, they are cognitions of some object, accompanied by some emotion. Just as neither a cognition nor an emotion, by itself, appeared capable of being greatly good, so (with one exception), neither a cognition nor an emotion, by itself, appears capable of being greatly evil. And just as a whole formed of both, even without the addition of any other element, appeared undoubtedly capable of being a great good, so such a whole, by itself, appears capable of being a great evil. With regard to the third element, which was discussed as capable of adding greatly to the value of a good, namely, true belief, it will appear that it has different relations towards different kinds of evils. In some cases the addition of true belief to a positive evil seems to constitute a far worse evil; but in other cases it is not apparent that it makes any difference.
I. When it comes to significant positive evils, I think it's clear that if we take all necessary steps to identify exactly what those things are that, if they existed completely on their own, we would consider their existence a great evil, we will find that most of them are organic unities exactly like those that represent the greatest positive goods. In other words, they are perceptions of some object, combined with some emotion. Just as neither a perception nor an emotion, by itself, seems capable of being greatly good, neither a perception nor an emotion, by itself, seems capable of being greatly evil (with one exception). Just as a whole made up of both, even without adding anything else, seems undoubtedly capable of being a great good, so such a whole, by itself, seems capable of being a great evil. Regarding the third element, which we discussed as having the potential to greatly enhance the value of a good, namely, true belief, it seems to have different effects on different types of evils. In some cases, adding true belief to a positive evil seems to create a far worse evil; in other cases, it’s not clear that it makes any difference.
The greatest positive evils may be divided into the following three classes.
The biggest positive evils can be categorized into these three groups.
125. (1) The first class consists of those evils, which seem always to include an enjoyment or admiring contemplation of[p. 209] things which are themselves either evil or ugly. That is to say these evils are characterised by the fact that they include precisely the same emotion, which is also essential to the greatest unmixed goods, from which they are differentiated by the fact that this emotion is directed towards an inappropriate object. In so far as this emotion is either a slight good in itself or a slightly beautiful object, these evils would therefore be cases of what I have called ‘mixed’ evils; but, as I have already said, it seems very doubtful whether an emotion, completely isolated from its object, has either value or beauty: it certainly has not much of either. It is, however, important to observe that the very same emotions, which are often loosely talked of as the greatest or the only goods, may be essential constituents of the very worst wholes: that, according to the nature of the cognition which accompanies them, they may be conditions either of the greatest good, or of the greatest evil.
125. (1) The first category includes those harms that seem to always involve some enjoyment or appreciative contemplation of things that are either evil or unattractive. In other words, these harms are characterized by the presence of the same emotion that is crucial to the highest pure goods, but they differ because this emotion is directed toward an inappropriate object. To the extent that this emotion involves a minor good in itself or a somewhat beautiful object, these harms would then be examples of what I’ve referred to as ‘mixed’ harms. However, as I’ve mentioned before, it’s quite questionable whether an emotion, completely detached from its object, holds any real value or beauty: it certainly doesn’t have much of either. It’s important to note that the very same emotions, which are often casually described as the greatest or only goods, can also be key components of the worst situations: depending on the nature of the understanding that accompanies them, they can lead to either the greatest good or the greatest evil.
In order to illustrate the nature of evils of this class, I may take two instances—cruelty and lasciviousness. That these are great intrinsic evils, we may, I think, easily assure ourselves, by imagining the state of a man, whose mind is solely occupied by either of these passions, in their worst form. If we then consider what judgment we should pass upon a universe which consisted solely of minds thus occupied, without the smallest hope that there would ever exist in it the smallest consciousness of any object other than those proper to these passions, or any feeling directed to any such object, I think we cannot avoid the conclusion that the existence of such a universe would be a far worse evil than the existence of none at all. But, if this be so, it follows that these two vicious states are not only, as is commonly admitted, bad as means, but also bad in themselves.—And that they involve in their nature that complication of elements, which I have called a love of what is evil or ugly, is, I think, no less plain. With regard to the pleasures of lust, the nature of the cognition, by the presence of which they are to be defined, is somewhat difficult to analyse. But it appears to include both cognitions of organic sensations and perceptions of states of the body, of which the enjoyment is certainly an evil in itself. So far as these are concerned, lasciviousness would,[p. 210] then, include in its essence an admiring contemplation of what is ugly. But certainly one of its commonest ingredients, in its worst forms, is an enjoyment of the same state of mind in other people: and in this case it would therefore also include a love of what is evil. With regard to cruelty, it is easy to see that an enjoyment of pain in other people is essential to it; and, as we shall see, when we come to consider pain, this is certainly a love of evil: while, in so far as it also includes a delight in the bodily signs of agony, it would also comprehend a love of what is ugly. In both cases, it should be observed, the evil of the state is heightened not only by an increase in the evil or ugliness of the object, but also by an increase in the enjoyment.
To illustrate the nature of this type of evil, I can take two examples—cruelty and lust. It's easy to convince ourselves that these are significant intrinsic evils by imagining a person whose mind is completely consumed by either of these passions in their most extreme form. If we then think about what we would conclude about a universe made up entirely of minds like that, with no hope of any awareness of anything beyond those passions or any feelings directed at anything else, I believe we can't escape the conclusion that such a universe would be a much worse evil than having no universe at all. If that's true, it follows that these two vicious states are not just bad as means, but also bad in themselves. It also seems clear that they involve a blend of elements that I’ve referred to as a love of what is evil or ugly. Concerning the pleasures of lust, the nature of the understanding that defines them is somewhat difficult to analyze. However, it seems to include both awareness of physical sensations and perceptions of bodily states, which is certainly an evil by itself. In this sense, lust would, then, involve an admiration of what is ugly. But certainly, one of its most common elements, in its worst forms, includes enjoying the same state of mind in other people, which means it would also involve a love of what is evil. As for cruelty, it's easy to see that taking pleasure in the suffering of others is essential to it; and, as we will discuss when we address pain, this certainly represents a love of evil. Additionally, since it also involves delighting in the physical signs of agony, it would also encompass a love of what is ugly. In both cases, it's important to note that the evil of the state becomes more intense not only with an increase in the evil or ugliness of the object, but also with a rise in the enjoyment.
It might be objected, in the case of cruelty, that our disapproval of it, even in the isolated case supposed, where no considerations of its badness as a means could influence us, may yet be really directed to the pain of the persons, which it takes delight in contemplating. This objection may be met, in the first place, by the remark that it entirely fails to explain the judgment, which yet, I think, no one, on reflection, will be able to avoid making, that even though the amount of pain contemplated be the same, yet the greater the delight in its contemplation, the worse the state of things. But it may also, I think, be met by notice of a fact, which we were unable to urge in considering the similar possibility with regard to goods—namely the possibility that the reason why we attribute greater value to a worthy affection for a real person, is that we take into account the additional good consisting in the existence of that person. We may I think urge, in the case of cruelty, that its intrinsic odiousness is equally great, whether the pain contemplated really exists or is purely imaginary. I, at least, am unable to distinguish that, in this case, the presence of true belief makes any difference to the intrinsic value of the whole considered, although it undoubtedly may make a great difference to its value as a means. And so also with regard to other evils of this class: I am unable to see that a true belief in the existence of their objects makes any difference in the degree of their positive demerits. On the other hand, the presence of another class of beliefs seems to make a considerable difference.[p. 211] When we enjoy what is evil or ugly, in spite of our knowledge that it is so, the state of things seems considerably worse than if we made no judgment at all as to the object’s value. And the same seems also, strangely enough, to be the case when we make a false judgment of value. When we admire what is ugly or evil, believing that it is beautiful and good, this belief seems also to enhance the intrinsic vileness of our condition. It must, of course, be understood that, in both these cases, the judgment in question is merely what I have called a judgment of taste; that is to say, it is concerned with the worth of the qualities actually cognised and not with the worth of the object, to which those qualities may be rightly or wrongly attributed.
It could be argued, in the case of cruelty, that our disapproval of it, even in the hypothetical situation where we aren't influenced by its negative effects as a means, might actually stem from the pain it inflicts on individuals, which we take pleasure in observing. This argument can be countered by noting that it completely fails to explain the judgment, which I believe no one can avoid making upon reflection, that even if the level of pain considered is the same, the more enjoyment taken in observing it, the worse the situation is. Additionally, I think we can address this by pointing out a fact that we couldn’t bring up when discussing a similar possibility regarding good things—namely, the possibility that the reason we assign more value to genuine affection for a real person is because we recognize the extra goodness that comes from that person's existence. In the case of cruelty, we can argue that its inherent disgusting nature remains just as significant, whether the pain we consider is real or purely imagined. At least for me, I can’t see how, in this instance, the presence of true belief makes any difference to the intrinsic value of the entire situation, even though it may significantly affect its value as a means. The same goes for other evils within this category: I can't see that having true belief in the existence of their subjects changes the extent of their inherent wrongness. On the other hand, the existence of another type of belief appears to make a significant impact. When we take pleasure in what is wrong or unpleasant, despite knowing it is, the situation seems much worse than if we didn’t judge the object’s value at all. Strangely enough, the same seems to apply when we make a false judgment of value. When we admire what is ugly or wrong, thinking it’s beautiful and good, this belief also seems to increase the intrinsic wrongness of our condition. It’s important to clarify, in both cases, that the judgment in question is merely what I’ve referred to as a judgment of taste; that is, it concerns the worth of the qualities we actually perceive, not the worth of the object to which those qualities may be accurately or inaccurately assigned.[p. 211]
Finally it should be mentioned that evils of this class, beside that emotional element (namely enjoyment and admiration) which they share with great unmixed goods, appear always also to include some specific emotion, which does not enter in the same way into the constitution of any good. The presence of this specific emotion seems certainly to enhance the badness of the whole, though it is not plain that, by itself, it would be either evil or ugly.
Finally, it should be noted that evils of this kind, besides the emotional element (specifically enjoyment and admiration) that they share with truly good things, always seem to include some specific emotion that isn't part of any good in the same way. The presence of this specific emotion definitely seems to increase the negativity of the whole, although it's not clear that, on its own, it would be considered evil or ugly.
126. (2) The second class of great evils are undoubtedly mixed evils; but I treat them next, because, in a certain respect, they appear to be the converse of the class last considered. Just as it is essential to this last class that they should include an emotion, appropriate to the cognition of what is good or beautiful, but directed to an inappropriate object; so to this second class it is essential that they should include a cognition of what is good or beautiful, but accompanied by an inappropriate emotion. In short, just as the last class may be described as cases of the love of what is evil or ugly, so this class may be described as cases of the hatred of what is good or beautiful.
126. (2) The second group of significant problems is definitely mixed issues; I’ll address them next because, in a way, they seem to be the opposite of the previous group. Just like the last group requires an emotion that’s suitable for recognizing what is good or beautiful but aimed at the wrong object, this second group requires an understanding of what is good or beautiful but is accompanied by an inappropriate emotion. In short, while the last group can be described as instances of loving what is evil or ugly, this group can be described as instances of hating what is good or beautiful.
With regard to these evils it should be remarked: First, that the vices of hatred, envy and contempt, where these vices are evil in themselves, appear to be instances of them; and that they are frequently accompanied by evils of the first class, for example, where a delight is felt in the pain of a good person.[p. 212] Where they are thus accompanied, the whole thus formed is undoubtedly worse than if either existed singly.
Regarding these problems, it should be noted: First, that the vices of hatred, envy, and contempt, which are bad in themselves, serve as examples of these issues; and that they are often accompanied by the worst kinds of evils, such as feeling pleasure in the suffering of a good person.[p. 212] When they occur together, the overall situation is undoubtedly worse than if either existed on its own.
And secondly: That in their case a true belief in the existence of the good or beautiful object, which is hated, does appear to enhance the badness of the whole, in which it is present. Undoubtedly also, as in our first class, the presence of a true belief as to the value of the objects contemplated, increases the evil. But, contrary to what was the case in our first class, a false judgment of value appears to lessen it.
And secondly: In their situation, genuinely believing in the existence of the good or beautiful object that is hated seems to amplify the negativity of the whole scenario where it exists. Certainly, just like in our first category, having a true belief about the value of the objects being considered heightens the negativity. However, unlike in our first category, a false judgment of value seems to reduce it.
127. (3) The third class of great positive evils appears to be the class of pains.
127. (3) The third category of significant positive evils seems to be the category of pains.
With regard to these it should first be remarked that, as in the case of pleasure, it is not pain itself, but only the consciousness of pain, towards which our judgments of value are directed. Just as in Chap. III., it was said that pleasure, however intense, which no one felt, would be no good at all; so it appears that pain, however intense, of which there was no consciousness, would be no evil at all.
Concerning these points, it should first be noted that, similar to pleasure, it's not the pain itself, but our awareness of it that shapes our judgments of value. Just as mentioned in Chap. III., intense pleasure that no one experiences wouldn't be considered good at all; similarly, intense pain that goes unnoticed wouldn't be considered evil at all.
It is, therefore, only the consciousness of intense pain, which can be maintained to be a great evil. But that this, by itself, may be a great evil, I cannot avoid thinking. The case of pain thus seems to differ from that of pleasure: for the mere consciousness of pleasure, however intense, does not, by itself, appear to be a great good, even if it has some slight intrinsic value. In short, pain (if we understand by this expression, the consciousness of pain) appears to be a far worse evil than pleasure is a good. But, if this be so, then pain must be admitted to be an exception from the rule which seems to hold both of all other great evils and of all great goods: namely that they are all organic unities to which both a cognition of an object and an emotion directed towards that object are essential. In the case of pain and of pain alone, it seems to be true that a mere cognition, by itself, may be a great evil. It is, indeed, an organic unity, since it involves both the cognition and the object, neither of which, by themselves, has either merit or demerit. But it is a less complex organic unity than any other great evil and than any great good, both in respect of the fact that it does not involve, beside the cognition, an emotion directed[p. 213] towards its object, and also in respect of the fact that the object may here be absolutely simple, whereas in most, if not all, other cases, the object itself is highly complex.
It is, therefore, only the awareness of intense pain that can be considered a significant evil. However, I firmly believe that this, by itself, can indeed be a major evil. The situation with pain seems to differ from that of pleasure: the mere awareness of pleasure, no matter how intense, does not, by itself, seem to be a great good, even if it holds some slight intrinsic value. In short, pain (if we understand this term as the awareness of pain) appears to be a far worse evil than pleasure is a good. If this is true, then pain must be recognized as an exception to the rule that seems to apply to all other major evils and all major goods: namely, that they are all organic unities that require both a cognition of an object and an emotion directed towards that object. In the case of pain and pain alone, it seems accurate that mere cognition, on its own, can be a significant evil. It is, indeed, an organic unity, since it involves both cognition and the object, neither of which holds any merit or demerit by themselves. However, it is a less complex organic unity than any other major evil and any major good, both in that it does not involve, besides the cognition, an emotion directed[p. 213] at its object, and also in that the object can be completely simple here, while in most, if not all, other cases, the object itself is quite complex.
This want of analogy between the relation of pain to intrinsic evil and of pleasure to intrinsic good, seems also to be exhibited in a second respect. Not only is it the case that consciousness of intense pain is, by itself, a great evil, whereas consciousness of intense pleasure is, by itself, no great good; but also the converse difference appears to hold of the contribution which they make to the value of the whole, when they are combined respectively with another great evil or with a great good. That is to say, the presence of pleasure (though not in proportion to its intensity) does appear to enhance the value of a whole, in which it is combined with any of the great unmixed goods which we have considered: it might even be maintained that it is only wholes, in which some pleasure is included, that possess any great value: it is certain, at all events, that the presence of pleasure makes a contribution to the value of good wholes greatly in excess of its own intrinsic value. On the contrary, if a feeling of pain be combined with any of the evil states of mind which we have been considering, the difference which its presence makes to the value of the whole, as a whole, seems to be rather for the better than the worse: in any case, the only additional evil which it introduces, is that which it, by itself, intrinsically constitutes. Thus, whereas pain is in itself a great evil, but makes no addition to the badness of a whole, in which it is combined with some other bad thing, except that which consists in its own intrinsic badness; pleasure, conversely, is not in itself a great good, but does make a great addition to the goodness of a whole in which it is combined with a good thing, quite apart from its own intrinsic value.
The lack of similarity between the relationship of pain to intrinsic evil and pleasure to intrinsic good also shows up in another way. Not only is intense pain, on its own, a significant evil, but intense pleasure, on its own, is not a significant good. Additionally, the opposite seems to be true regarding how they affect the overall value when combined with another significant evil or good. In other words, the presence of pleasure (even if not in proportion to its intensity) seems to enhance the value of a whole when it’s combined with any of the major pure goods we've examined. One could argue that only wholes that include some pleasure have any significant value. It's certain, in any case, that pleasure adds greatly to the value of good wholes, far beyond its own intrinsic value. On the other hand, if pain is mixed with any of the negative states of mind we've considered, its presence seems to improve the overall value, not diminish it. In any case, the only added evil it contributes is what it intrinsically represents. Thus, while pain is a significant evil by itself, it doesn’t increase the badness of a whole when combined with another bad thing; it simply adds its own intrinsic badness. In contrast, pleasure is not a significant good by itself but does greatly enhance the goodness of a whole when combined with a good thing, regardless of its own intrinsic value.
128. But finally, it must be insisted that pleasure and pain are completely analogous in this: that we cannot assume either that the presence of pleasure always makes a state of things better on the whole, or that the presence of pain always makes it worse. This is the truth which is most liable to be overlooked with regard to them; and it is because this is true, that the common theory, that pleasure is the only good and pain the[p. 214] only evil, has its grossest consequences in misjudgments of value. Not only is the pleasantness of a state not in proportion to its intrinsic worth; it may even add positively to its vileness. We do not think the successful hatred of a villain the less vile and odious, because he takes the keenest delight in it; nor is there the least need, in logic, why we should think so, apart from an unintelligent prejudice in favour of pleasure. In fact it seems to be the case that wherever pleasure is added to an evil state of either of our first two classes, the whole thus formed is always worse than if no pleasure had been there. And similarly with regard to pain. If pain be added to an evil state of either of our first two classes, the whole thus formed is always better, as a whole, than if no pain had been there; though here, if the pain be too intense, since that is a great evil, the state may not be better on the whole. It is in this way that the theory of vindictive punishment may be vindicated. The infliction of pain on a person whose state of mind is bad may, if the pain be not too intense, create a state of things that is better on the whole than if the evil state of mind had existed unpunished. Whether such a state of things can ever constitute a positive good, is another question.
128. But ultimately, it's important to emphasize that pleasure and pain are completely similar in this way: we can't assume that the presence of pleasure always improves a situation overall, or that pain always makes it worse. This is a truth that is often overlooked when it comes to them; and this is why the common belief that pleasure is the only good and pain is the only evil leads to serious misjudgments about value. Not only is the pleasantness of a situation not proportional to its true worth, but it can even make its ugliness worse. We don't consider the successful hatred of a villain any less vile and detestable just because he takes great pleasure in it; nor is there any logical reason for us to think so, aside from a misguided bias in favor of pleasure. In fact, it appears that whenever pleasure is added to a bad situation from either of our first two categories, the overall result is always worse than if there had been no pleasure at all. The same goes for pain. If pain is added to a bad situation from either of our first two categories, the overall outcome is always better than if there had been no pain; although, if the pain is too severe, since that is a major evil, the situation might not be better overall. This is how the theory of vindictive punishment can be justified. Inflicting pain on someone who is already in a bad state of mind might, if the pain isn't too extreme, create a situation that is better overall than if the bad state of mind had gone unpunished. Whether such a situation can ever count as a positive good is a different question.
129. II. The consideration of this other question belongs properly to the second topic, which was reserved above for discussion namely the topic of ‘mixed’ goods. ‘Mixed’ goods were defined above as things, which, though positively good as wholes, nevertheless contain, as essential elements, something intrinsically evil or ugly. And there certainly seem to be such goods. But for the proper consideration of them, it is necessary to take into account a new distinction the distinction just expressed as being between the value which a thing possesses ‘as a whole,’ and that which it possesses ‘on the whole.’
129. II. The discussion of this other question fits into the second topic, which we set aside earlier to discuss, namely the topic of ‘mixed’ goods. ‘Mixed’ goods were defined earlier as things that, while definitely good as a whole, still contain, as essential components, something inherently evil or unattractive. And there certainly seem to be such goods. However, to properly evaluate them, we need to recognize a new distinction—the distinction between the value a thing has ‘as a whole’ and the value it has ‘on the whole.’
When ‘mixed’ goods were defined as things positively good as wholes, the expression was ambiguous. It was meant that they were positively good on the whole; but it must now be observed that the value which a thing possesses on the whole may be said to be equivalent to the sum of the value which it possesses as a whole, together with the intrinsic values which may belong to any of its parts. In fact, by the ‘value which[p. 215] a thing possesses as a whole,’ there may be meant two quite distinct things. There may be meant either (1) That value which arises solely from the combination of two or more things; or else (2) The total value formed by the addition to (1) of any intrinsic values which may belong to the things combined. The meaning of the distinction may perhaps be most easily seen by considering the supposed case of vindictive punishment. If it is true that the combined existence of two evils may yet constitute a less evil than would be constituted by the existence of either singly, it is plain that this can only be because there arises from the combination a positive good which is greater than the difference between the sum of the two evils and the demerit of either singly: this positive good would then be the value of the whole, as a whole, in sense (1). Yet if this value be not so great a good as the sum of the two evils is an evil, it is plain that the value of the whole state of things will be a positive evil; and this value is the value of the whole, as a whole, in sense (2). Whatever view may be taken with regard to the particular case of vindictive punishment, it is plain that we have here two distinct things, with regard to either of which a separate question may be asked in the case of every organic unity. The first of these two things may be expressed as the difference between the value of the whole thing and the sum of the value of its parts. And it is plain that where the parts have little or no intrinsic value (as in our first class of goods, §§ 114, 115), this difference will be nearly or absolutely identical with the value of the whole thing. The distinction, therefore, only becomes important in the case of wholes, of which one or more parts have a great intrinsic value, positive or negative. The first of these cases, that of a whole, in which one part has a great positive value, is exemplified in our 2nd and 3rd classes of great unmixed goods (§§ 120, 122); and similarly the Summum Bonum is a whole of which many parts have a great positive value. Such cases, it may be observed, are also very frequent and very important objects of Aesthetic judgment; since the essential distinction between the ‘classical’ and the ‘romantic’ styles consists in the fact that the former aims at obtaining the greatest possible value[p. 216] for the whole, as a whole, in sense (1), whereas the latter sacrifices this in order to obtain the greatest possible value for some part, which is itself an organic unity. It follows that we cannot declare either style to be necessarily superior, since an equally good result on the whole, or ‘as a whole’ in sense (2), may be obtained by either method; but the distinctively aesthetic temperament seems to be characterised by a tendency to prefer a good result obtained by the classical, to an equally good result obtained by the romantic method.
When ‘mixed’ goods were defined as things clearly good as wholes, the term was vague. It intended to mean that they were clearly good on the whole; however, it should now be noted that the value a thing possesses on the whole can be considered the same as the sum of its value as a whole, along with the intrinsic values that may belong to any of its parts. In fact, by the ‘value which [p. 215] a thing possesses as a whole,’ two distinct ideas might be intended. It could refer to either (1) the value that comes solely from the combination of two or more things, or (2) the total value created by adding to (1) any intrinsic values belonging to the combined things. This distinction can perhaps be most easily understood by considering the hypothetical scenario of vindictive punishment. If it’s true that the combination of two wrongs can result in a less serious wrong than either one on its own, it’s clear that this is only because the combination brings about a positive good that surpasses the difference between the total of the two wrongs and the demerit of either one alone: this positive good would then represent the value of the whole, as a whole, in sense (1). Yet if this value isn’t as significant a good as the sum of the two wrongs represents a wrong, it’s evident that the total condition will be a positive wrong; and this value is the value of the whole, as a whole, in sense (2). Regardless of the viewpoint concerning the specific case of vindictive punishment, it’s evident that we have here two distinct things, regarding either of which a separate question could be raised for every organic unity. The first of these two aspects can be expressed as the difference between the value of the entire entity and the sum of the value of its components. It’s clear that where the components have little or no intrinsic value (as in our first class of goods, §§ 114, 115), this difference will be nearly or completely identical to the value of the entire entity. The distinction, therefore, only becomes significant in the case of wholes, where one or more parts have a substantial intrinsic value, whether positive or negative. The first scenario, where a whole has one part with a significant positive value, is illustrated in our 2nd and 3rd classes of significant unmixed goods (§§ 120, 122); similarly, the Summum Bonum is a whole where many parts have a considerable positive value. It should be noted that such instances are also quite common and significant subjects of Aesthetic judgment; since the fundamental difference between ‘classical’ and ‘romantic’ styles lies in the fact that the former seeks to achieve the highest possible value[p. 216] for the whole, as a whole, in sense (1), while the latter sacrifices this to achieve the highest possible value for some part, which functions as an organic unity. Therefore, we cannot claim that either style is necessarily superior, as an equally good outcome on the whole, or ‘as a whole’ in sense (2), can be achieved by either approach; however, the distinctively aesthetic temperament seems to be characterized by a tendency to favor a good outcome achieved through the classical method over an equally good outcome obtained through the romantic approach.
130. But what we have now to consider are cases of wholes, in which one or more parts have a great negative value—are great positive evils. And first of all, we may take the strongest cases, like that of retributive punishment, in which we have a whole, exclusively composed of two great positive evils—wickedness and pain. Can such a whole ever be positively good on the whole?
130. What we need to think about now are situations where the whole thing includes one or more parts that have a significant negative value—representing serious positive evils. To start, let's consider the strongest examples, like retributive punishment, where we have a whole made up solely of two major positive evils—wickedness and suffering. Can such a whole ever be positively good overall?
(1) I can see no reason to think that such wholes ever are positively good on the whole. But from the fact that they may, nevertheless, be less evils, than either of their parts taken singly, it follows that they have a characteristic which is most important for the correct decision of practical questions. It follows that, quite apart from consequences or any value which an evil may have as a mere means, it may, supposing one evil already exists, be worth while to create another, since, by the mere creation of this second, there may be constituted a whole less bad than if the original evil had been left to exist by itself. And similarly, with regard to all the wholes which I am about to consider, it must be remembered, that, even if they are not goods on the whole, yet, where an evil already exists, as in this world evils do exist, the existence of the other part of these wholes will constitute a thing desirable for its own sake—that is to say, not merely a means to future goods, but one of the ends which must be taken into account in estimating what that best possible state of things is, to which every right action must be a means.
(1) I can't see any reason to believe that such combinations are ever truly good overall. However, since they might be less harmful than either of their individual parts on their own, it suggests they have an important feature for making practical decisions. This means that aside from the consequences or any value an evil might have just as a means, if one evil already exists, it might be worth creating another. By creating this second one, there might be a whole that is less bad than if we just left the first evil alone. Similarly, regarding all the combinations I’ll discuss, it should be noted that even if they aren't good overall, when an evil already exists—as evils do in this world—the existence of the other part of these combinations will be something desirable for its own sake. In other words, it's not just a means to achieve future goods, but one of the ends that must be taken into account when evaluating what the best possible situation is, which every right action aims to achieve.
131. (2) But, as a matter of fact, I cannot avoid thinking that there are wholes, containing something positively evil and ugly, which are, nevertheless, great positive goods on the whole.[p. 217] Indeed, it appears to be to this class that those instances of virtue, which contain anything intrinsically good, chiefly belong. It need not, of course, be denied that there is sometimes included in a virtuous disposition more or less of those unmixed goods which were first discussed—that is to say, a real love of what is good or beautiful. But the typical and characteristic virtuous dispositions, so far as they are not mere means, seem rather to be examples of mixed goods. We may take as instances (a) Courage and Compassion, which seem to belong to the second of the three classes of virtues distinguished in our last chapter (§ 107); and (b) the specifically ‘moral’ sentiment, by reference to which the third of those three classes was defined (§ 108).
131. (2) However, I can't help but think that there are whole situations that contain elements that are definitely evil and ugly, but still result in overall positive outcomes. [p. 217] In fact, it seems that the examples of virtue that include anything inherently good mostly belong to this category. It's true that a virtuous mindset can include varied amounts of those pure goods we talked about earlier—that is, a genuine love for what is good or beautiful. But typical virtuous dispositions, especially those that aren't just means to an end, appear to be more about mixed goods. For example, we can consider (a) Courage and Compassion, which seem to fit into the second of the three categories of virtues we identified in our last chapter (§ 107); and (b) the specifically ‘moral’ sentiment that helped define the third category (§ 108).
Courage and compassion, in so far as they contain an intrinsically desirable state of mind, seem to involve essentially a cognition of something evil or ugly. In the case of courage the object of the cognition may be an evil of any of our three classes; in the case of compassion, the proper object is pain. Both these virtues, accordingly, must contain precisely the same cognitive element, which is also essential to evils of class (1); and they are differentiated from these by the fact that the emotion directed to these objects is, in their case, an emotion of the same kind which was essential to evils of class (2). In short, just as evils of class (2) seemed to consist in a hatred of what was good or beautiful, and evils of class (1) in a love of what was evil or ugly; so these virtues involve a hatred of what is evil or ugly. Both these virtues do, no doubt, also contain other elements, and, among these, each contains its specific emotion; but that their value does not depend solely upon these other elements, we may easily assure ourselves, by considering what we should think of an attitude of endurance or of defiant contempt toward an object intrinsically good or beautiful, or of the state of a man whose mind was filled with pity for the happiness of a worthy admiration. Yet pity for the undeserved sufferings of others, endurance of pain to ourselves, and a defiant hatred of evil dispositions in ourselves or in others, seem to be undoubtedly admirable in themselves; and if so, there are admirable things, which must be lost, if there were no cognition of evil.
Courage and compassion, as they represent a desirable state of mind, seem to fundamentally involve recognizing something evil or unpleasant. For courage, the focus can be any type of evil; for compassion, it specifically relates to pain. Therefore, both virtues share the same cognitive aspect, which is also crucial to the first category of evils; they differ in that the emotions directed towards these subjects are of a type that relates to the second category of evils. In summary, just as the second category of evils seemed to arise from a hatred of what is good or beautiful, and the first category from a love of what is evil or ugly, these virtues reflect a hatred of what is evil or ugly. These virtues undoubtedly encompass other elements, and each includes its specific emotion; however, we can easily confirm that their value isn't solely based on these other components by considering how we would view an attitude of enduring or defiantly disregarding something intrinsically good or beautiful, or thinking about someone who feels pity for a happiness that is rightly admired. Nonetheless, feeling pity for the unjust suffering of others, enduring pain ourselves, and having a defiant hatred for evil traits in ourselves or others are surely admirable qualities in themselves; if that’s the case, there are admirable aspects that would be lost without the recognition of evil.
[p. 218]Similarly the specifically ‘moral’ sentiment, in all cases where it has any considerable intrinsic value, appears to include a hatred of evils of the first and second classes. It is true that the emotion is here excited by the idea that an action is right or wrong; and hence the object of the idea which excites it is generally not an intrinsic evil. But, as far as I can discover, the emotion with which a conscientious man views a real or imaginary right action, contains, as an essential element, the same emotion with which he views a wrong one: it seems, indeed, that this element is necessary to make his emotion specifically moral. And the specifically moral emotion excited by the idea of a wrong action, seems to me to contain essentially a more or less vague cognition of the kind of intrinsic evils, which are usually caused by wrong actions, whether they would or would not be caused by the particular action in question. I am, in fact, unable to distinguish, in its main features, the moral sentiment excited by the idea of rightness and wrongness, wherever it is intense, from the total state constituted by a cognition of something intrinsically evil together with the emotion of hatred directed towards it. Nor need we be surprised that this mental state should be the one chiefly associated with the idea of rightness, if we reflect on the nature of those actions which are most commonly recognised as duties. For by far the greater part of the actions, of which we commonly think as duties, are negative: what we feel to be our duty is to abstain from some action to which a strong natural impulse tempts us. And these wrong actions, in the avoidance of which duty consists, are usually such as produce, very immediately, some bad consequence in pain to others; while, in many prominent instances, the inclination, which prompts us to them, is itself an intrinsic evil, containing, as where the impulse is lust or cruelty, an anticipatory enjoyment of something evil or ugly. That right action does thus so frequently entail the suppression of some evil impulse, is necessary to explain the plausibility of the view that virtue consists in the control of passion by reason. Accordingly, the truth seems to be that, whenever a strong moral emotion is excited by the idea of rightness, this emotion is accompanied by a vague cognition of the kind of[p. 219] evils usually suppressed or avoided by the actions which most frequently occur to us as instances of duty; and that the emotion is directed towards this evil quality. We may, then, conclude that the specific moral emotion owes almost all its intrinsic value to the fact that it includes a cognition of evils accompanied by a hatred of them: mere rightness, whether truly or untruly attributed to an action, seems incapable of forming the object of an emotional contemplation, which shall be any great good.
[p. 218]Similarly, the specifically ‘moral’ feeling, whenever it holds significant intrinsic value, seems to comprise a disdain for first and second-class evils. It's true that this emotion is triggered by the notion of whether an action is right or wrong; thus, the idea that provokes it is usually not an intrinsic evil. However, as far as I can tell, the emotion a conscientious person experiences towards a real or imagined right action includes, as a fundamental component, the same feeling they have towards a wrong one: it appears that this component is essential for their emotion to be considered specifically moral. The specific moral emotion triggered by the idea of a wrong action seems to fundamentally contain a somewhat vague understanding of the types of intrinsic evils typically caused by wrong actions, regardless of whether the specific action in question would actually cause them. In fact, I find it hard to distinguish, in its main aspects, the moral feeling evoked by the perception of rightness and wrongness, whenever it's intense, from the overall state consisting of an awareness of something intrinsically evil along with the emotion of hatred directed at it. We shouldn't be surprised that this mental state is primarily tied to the idea of rightness, especially when considering the nature of actions most commonly identified as duties. The majority of the actions we usually view as duties are negative: what we feel is our duty is to abstain from some action that strongly tempts us. These wrong actions, which duty requires us to avoid, typically lead to immediate negative consequences for others; often, the urge that leads us to them is itself an intrinsic evil, offering, as in cases of lust or cruelty, an anticipatory enjoyment of something evil or unpleasant. The fact that right action often involves suppressing some evil impulse is essential to understanding why the idea that virtue consists of controlling passion through reason seems reasonable. Thus, it appears that, whenever a strong moral emotion is stirred by the notion of rightness, this emotion is accompanied by a general awareness of the types of[p. 219] evils that are typically suppressed or avoided by the actions most often viewed as duties, and that this emotion is directed towards this negative quality. We can, therefore, conclude that the specific moral emotion derives nearly all its intrinsic value from the fact that it includes a recognition of evils paired with a hatred of them: mere rightness, whether rightly or wrongly assigned to an action, seems incapable of being the focus of an emotional contemplation that holds any substantial good.
132. If this be so, then we have, in many prominent instances of virtue, cases of a whole, greatly good in itself, which yet contains the cognition of something, whereof the existence would be a great evil: a great good is absolutely dependent for its value, upon its inclusion of something evil or ugly, although it does not owe its value solely to this element in it. And, in the case of virtues, this evil object does, in general, actually exist. But there seems no reason to think that, when it does exist, the whole state of things thus constituted is therefore the better on the whole. What seems indubitable, is only that the feeling contemplation of an object, whose existence would be a great evil, or which is ugly, may be essential to a valuable whole. We have another undoubted instance of this in the appreciation of tragedy. But, in tragedy, the sufferings of Lear, and the vice of Iago may be purely imaginary. And it seems certain that, if they really existed, the evil thus existing, while it must detract from the good consisting in a proper feeling towards them, will add no positive value to that good great enough to counterbalance such a loss. It does, indeed, seem that the existence of a true belief in the object of these mixed goods does add some value to the whole in which it is combined with them: a conscious compassion for real suffering seems to be better, as a whole, than a compassion for sufferings merely imaginary; and this may well be the case, even though the evil involved in the actual suffering makes the total state of things bad on the whole. And it certainly seems to be true that a false belief in the actual existence of its object makes a worse mixed good than if our state of mind were that with which we normally regard pure fiction. Accordingly we may[p. 220] conclude that the only mixed goods, which are positively good on the whole, are those in which the object is something which would be a great evil, if it existed, or which is ugly.
132. If this is the case, then we have, in many clear examples of virtue, situations where something as a whole is greatly good on its own, yet also includes an awareness of something that would be a significant evil if it existed: great good is completely reliant on its association with something evil or ugly for its value, even though it doesn't owe its worth entirely to this element. In the cases of virtues, this negative element generally does actually exist. However, there's no reason to believe that, when it does exist, the overall situation is therefore better. What seems undeniable is that the emotional consideration of an object, whose existence would be a great evil, or that is ugly, may be essential to creating something valuable. We see another clear example of this in the appreciation of tragedy. Yet, in tragedy, the sufferings of Lear and the wickedness of Iago may be completely fictional. It seems certain that if they truly existed, the existing evil would lessen the good resulting from a proper feeling towards them, without adding enough positive value to outweigh that loss. Indeed, it appears that a true belief in the object of these mixed goods adds some value to the overall experience in which it is combined: a conscious compassion for real suffering seems better as a whole than compassion for merely imaginary sufferings; and this may be true even though the evil involved in actual suffering makes the overall situation bad. It also certainly seems true that a false belief in the actual existence of its object results in a worse mixed good than if we had the perspective with which we typically regard pure fiction. Therefore, we can conclude that the only mixed goods that are positively good overall are those in which the object is something that would be a great evil if it existed or that is ugly.
133. With regard, then, to those mixed goods, which consist in an appropriate attitude of the mind towards things evil or ugly, and which include among their number the greater part of such virtues as have any intrinsic value whatever, the following three conclusions seem to be those chiefly requiring to be emphasized:—
133. Regarding those mixed goods, which involve having the right mindset about things that are bad or unattractive, and which include most of the virtues that have any real value, the following three conclusions seem to be the most important to highlight:—
(1) There seems no reason to think that where the object is a thing evil in itself, which actually exists, the total state of things is ever positively good on the whole. The appropriate mental attitude towards a really existing evil contains, of course, an element which is absolutely identical with the same attitude towards the same evil, where it is purely imaginary. And this element, which is common to the two cases, may be a great positive good, on the whole. But there seems no reason to doubt that, where the evil is real, the amount of this real evil is always sufficient to reduce the total sum of value to a negative quantity. Accordingly we have no reason to maintain the paradox that an ideal world would be one in which vice and suffering must exist in order that it may contain the goods consisting in the appropriate emotion towards them. It is not a positive good that suffering should exist, in order that we may compassionate it; or wickedness, that we may hate it. There is no reason to think that any actual evil whatsoever would be contained in the Ideal. It follows that we cannot admit the actual validity of any of the arguments commonly used in Theodicies; no such argument succeeds in justifying the fact that there does exist even the smallest of the many evils which this world contains. The most that can be said for such arguments is that, when they make appeal to the principle of organic unity, their appeal is valid in principle. It might be the case that the existence of evil was necessary, not merely as a means, but analytically, to the existence of the greatest good. But we have no reason to think that this is the case in any instance whatsoever.
(1) There doesn’t seem to be any reason to believe that when the object is something evil in itself, which actually exists, the overall situation is ever truly good overall. The correct mental attitude towards a real evil obviously includes an element that is exactly the same as that attitude towards the same evil when it’s purely imaginary. This element, shared by both cases, can be a significant positive good in general. However, there isn’t any reason to doubt that when the evil is real, the extent of this real evil is always enough to lower the total sum of value to a negative amount. Thus, we have no reason to hold the paradox that an ideal world would have to include vice and suffering so that it can contain the goods that arise from the appropriate emotions towards them. It’s not a positive good for suffering to exist just so we can feel compassion for it; nor for wickedness to exist so that we can hate it. There’s no reason to think that any real evil would occur in the Ideal. This leads us to conclude that we cannot accept the actual validity of any arguments typically made in Theodicies; none of these arguments succeed in justifying the existence of even the smallest of the many evils present in this world. The most that can be said for such arguments is that, when they appeal to the principle of organic unity, their appeal is valid in principle. It might be possible that the existence of evil is necessary, not just as a means, but analytically, for the existence of the greatest good. But we have no reason to believe that this is the case in any particular instance.
But (2) there is reason to think that the cognition of things[p. 221] evil or ugly, which are purely imaginary, is essential to the Ideal. In this case the burden of proof lies the other way. It cannot be doubted that the appreciation of tragedy is a great positive good; and it seems almost equally certain that the virtues of compassion, courage, and self-control contain such goods. And to all these the cognition of things which would be evil, if they existed, is analytically necessary. Here then we have things of which the existence must add value to any whole in which they are contained; nor is it possible to assure ourselves that any whole, from which they were omitted, would thereby gain more in its value as a whole, than it would lose by their omission. We have no reason to think that any whole, which did not contain them, would be so good on the whole as some whole in which they were obtained. The case for their inclusion in the Ideal is as strong as that for the inclusion of material qualities (§ 123, above). Against the inclusion of these goods nothing can be urged except a bare possibility.
But (2) there is reason to believe that understanding things[p. 221] evil or ugly, which are purely imaginary, is essential to the Ideal. In this case, the burden of proof lies the other way. It’s undeniable that appreciating tragedy is a significant positive good; and it seems almost equally certain that the virtues of compassion, courage, and self-control encompass such goods. Additionally, understanding things that would be evil, if they existed, is analytically necessary. Here, we have elements whose existence must add value to any whole in which they are included; nor is it possible to confirm that any whole, from which they are excluded, would gain more in its value as a whole than it would lose by their omission. We have no reason to believe that any whole lacking them would be as good on the whole as some whole that includes them. The case for their inclusion in the Ideal is as strong as that for the inclusion of material qualities (§ 123, above). Against the inclusion of these goods, nothing can be argued except a mere possibility.
Finally (3) it is important to insist that, as was said above, these mixed virtues have a great practical value, in addition to that which they possess either in themselves or as mere means. Where evils do exist, as in this world they do, the fact that they are known and properly appreciated, constitutes a state of things having greater value as a whole even than the same appreciation of purely imaginary evils. This state of things, it has been said, is never positively good on the whole; but where the evil, which reduces its total value to a negative quantity, already unavoidably exists, to obtain the intrinsic value which belongs to it as a whole will obviously produce a better state of things than if the evil had existed by itself, quite apart from the good element in it which is identical with the appreciation of imaginary evils, and from any ulterior consequences which its existence may bring about. The case is here the same as with retributive punishment. Where an evil already exists, it is well that it should be pitied or hated or endured, according to its nature; just as it may be well that some evils should be punished. Of course, as in all practical cases, it often happens that the attainment of this good is incompatible with the attainment of another and a greater one. But it is important[p. 222] to insist that we have here a real intrinsic value, which must be taken into account in calculating that greatest possible balance of intrinsic value, which it is always our duty to produce.
Finally (3) it’s important to emphasize that, as mentioned earlier, these mixed virtues have significant practical value, beyond what they have on their own or just as means. Where evils exist, which they do in this world, the fact that they are recognized and properly understood creates a situation that has greater value as a whole than merely acknowledging imaginary evils. This situation, as has been pointed out, is never entirely good on the whole; however, where evils that diminish the total value to a negative level already exist, recognizing the intrinsic value that belongs to it as a whole will clearly lead to a better situation than if the evil existed alone, separate from the good element that aligns with the appreciation of imaginary evils and from any further consequences that its existence may bring. The situation is similar to retributive punishment. When an evil already exists, it’s appropriate to feel pity, hatred, or endurance towards it, depending on its nature; just as it may also be appropriate for some evils to be punished. Of course, as in all practical situations, it often happens that achieving this good conflicts with attaining another, greater good. But it’s essential[p. 222] to stress that we have a genuine intrinsic value here, which must be considered when calculating the greatest possible balance of intrinsic value, which is always our responsibility to create.
134. I have now completed such remarks as seemed most necessary to be made concerning intrinsic values. It is obvious that for the proper answering of this, the fundamental question of Ethics, there remains a field of investigation as wide and as difficult, as was assigned to Practical Ethics in my last chapter. There is as much to be said concerning what results are intrinsically good, and in what degrees, as concerning what results it is possible for us to bring about: both questions demand, and will repay, an equally patient enquiry. Many of the judgments, which I have made in this chapter, will, no doubt, seem unduly arbitrary: it must be confessed that some of the attributions of intrinsic value, which have seemed to me to be true, do not display that symmetry and system which is wont to be required of philosophers. But if this be urged as an objection, I may respectfully point out that it is none. We have no title whatever to assume that the truth on any subject-matter will display such symmetry as we desire to see—or (to use the common vague phrase) that it will possess any particular form of ‘unity.’ To search for ‘unity’ and ‘system,’ at the expense of truth, is not, I take it, the proper business of philosophy, however universally it may have been the practice of philosophers. And that all truths about the Universe possess to one another all the various relations, which may be meant by ‘unity,’ can only be legitimately asserted, when we have carefully distinguished those various relations and discovered what those truths are. In particular, we can have no title to assert that ethical truths are ‘unified’ in any particular manner, except in virtue of an enquiry conducted by the method which I have endeavoured to follow and to illustrate. The study of Ethics would, no doubt, be far more simple, and its results far more ‘systematic,’ if, for instance, pain were an evil of exactly the same magnitude as pleasure is a good; but we have no reason whatever to assume that the Universe is such that ethical truths must display this kind of symmetry: no argument[p. 223] against my conclusion, that pleasure and pain do not thus correspond, can have any weight whatever, failing a careful examination of the instances which have led me to form it. Nevertheless I am content that the results of this chapter should be taken rather as illustrating the method which must be pursued in answering the fundamental question of Ethics, and the principles which must be observed, than as giving the correct answer to that question. That things intrinsically good or bad are many and various; that most of them are ‘organic unities,’ in the peculiar and definite sense to which I have confined the term; and that our only means of deciding upon their intrinsic value and its degree, is by carefully distinguishing exactly what the thing is, about which we ask the question, and then looking to see whether it has or has not the unique predicate ‘good’ in any of its various degrees: these are the conclusions, upon the truth of which I desire to insist. Similarly, in my last chapter, with regard to the question ‘What ought we to do?’ I have endeavoured rather to shew exactly what is the meaning of the question, and what difficulties must consequently be faced in answering it, than to prove that any particular answers are true. And that these two questions, having precisely the nature which I have assigned to them, are the questions which it is the object of Ethics to answer, may be regarded as the main result of the preceding chapters. These are the questions which ethical philosophers have always been mainly concerned to answer, although they have not recognised what their question was—what predicate they were asserting to attach to things. The practice of asking what things are virtues or duties, without distinguishing what these terms mean; the practice of asking what ought to be here and now, without distinguishing whether as means or end—for its own sake or for that of its results; the search for one single criterion of right or wrong, without the recognition that in order to discover a criterion we must first know what things are right or wrong; and the neglect of the principle of ‘organic unities’—these sources of error have hitherto been almost universally prevalent in Ethics. The conscious endeavour to avoid them all, and to apply to all the ordinary objects of ethical[p. 224] judgment these two questions and these only: Has it intrinsic value? and Is it a means to the best possible?—this attempt, so far as I know, is entirely new; and its results, when compared with those habitual to moral philosophers, are certainly sufficiently surprising: that to Common Sense they will not appear so strange, I venture to hope and believe. It is, I think, much to be desired that the labour commonly devoted to answering such questions as whether certain ‘ends’ are more or less ‘comprehensive’ or more or less ‘consistent’ with one another—questions, which, even if a precise meaning were given to them, are wholly irrelevant to the proof of any ethical conclusion—should be diverted to the separate investigation of these two clear problems.
134. I have now finished the comments that seemed most necessary regarding intrinsic values. It's clear that to properly address this fundamental question of Ethics, there remains a field of investigation as broad and complex as what was assigned to Practical Ethics in my last chapter. There is just as much to discuss about what results are intrinsically good, and to what extent, as there is about what results we can actually achieve: both questions require, and will repay, equally thorough inquiry. Many of the judgments I've made in this chapter may seem overly arbitrary: it must be acknowledged that some of the intrinsic value attributions I believe to be true do not show the symmetry and system typically expected by philosophers. But if this is raised as an objection, I would respectfully argue that it is not one. We have no grounds to assume that the truth about any subject will exhibit the symmetry we wish to see—or (to use the common vague phrase) that it will have any specific form of ‘unity.’ Seeking ‘unity’ and ‘system’ at the cost of truth is, in my opinion, not the true purpose of philosophy, regardless of how commonly it has been the practice of philosophers. Furthermore, asserting that all truths about the Universe have various relations that can be interpreted as ‘unity’ can only be properly claimed once we have carefully distinguished these various relations and identified what those truths are. Specifically, we have no right to claim that ethical truths are ‘unified’ in any particular way, except through an inquiry conducted by the method I have sought to follow and demonstrate. The study of Ethics would undoubtedly be much simpler, and its outcomes much more ‘systematic,’ if, for instance, pain were an evil of exactly the same magnitude as pleasure is a good; but we have no reason to assume that the Universe operates in such a way that ethical truths exhibit this type of symmetry: no argument[p. 223] against my conclusion that pleasure and pain do not correspond in this way can hold any weight without a careful examination of the instances that led me to that conclusion. Nevertheless, I am content for the conclusions of this chapter to be seen more as a demonstration of the method that must be employed in answering the fundamental question of Ethics and the principles that must be upheld, rather than providing the definitive answer to that question. The fact that things intrinsically good or bad are numerous and diverse; that most of them are ‘organic unities’ in the specific sense I have defined; and that our only way to determine their intrinsic value and its degree is by carefully clarifying exactly what the thing is that we're questioning, and then checking if it has or does not have the unique label ‘good’ in any of its various degrees: these are the points I wish to emphasize. Similarly, in my previous chapter concerning the question ‘What ought we to do?’ I aimed more to clarify the meaning of the question and the difficulties that must consequently be faced in answering it, rather than proving that any specific answers are correct. That these two questions, having precisely the nature I've ascribed to them, are the questions that Ethics aims to answer may be seen as the main outcome of the earlier chapters. These are the questions that ethical philosophers have always focused on, even if they have not recognized what their question truly was—or what predicate they were claiming to apply to things. The practice of asking what things are virtues or duties without clarifying what these terms mean; the practice of inquiring what ought to be done here and now without distinguishing whether it is means or ends—for its own sake or for the sake of its outcomes; the pursuit of a single criterion of right or wrong without acknowledging that to discover a criterion we must first understand what things are right or wrong; and the neglect of the principle of ‘organic unities’—these sources of error have been nearly universally prevalent in Ethics. The conscious effort to avoid all these pitfalls and to apply to all the ordinary objects of ethical[p. 224] judgment these two questions and these only: Does it have intrinsic value? and Is it a means to the best possible outcome?—this effort, as far as I know, is entirely new; and its outcomes, when compared to those typically seen in moral philosophy, are certainly quite surprising: I hope and believe that to Common Sense they will not seem so strange. I think it would be very beneficial if the effort usually spent on answering questions like whether certain ‘ends’ are more or less ‘comprehensive’ or more or less ‘consistent’ with one another—questions that, even if given a precise meaning, are entirely unrelated to proving any ethical conclusion—were redirected to the independent investigation of these two clear problems.
135. The main object of this chapter has been to define roughly the class of things, among which we may expect to find either great intrinsic goods or great intrinsic evils; and particularly to point out that there is a vast variety of such things, and that the simplest of them are, with one exception, highly complex wholes, composed of parts which have little or no value in themselves. All of them involve consciousness of an object, which is itself usually highly complex, and almost all involve also an emotional attitude towards this object; but, though they thus have certain characteristics in common, the vast variety of qualities in respect of which they differ from one another are equally essential to their value: neither the generic character of all, nor the specific character of each, is either greatly good or greatly evil by itself; they owe their value or demerit, in each case, to the presence of both. My discussion falls into three main divisions, dealing respectively (1) with unmixed goods, (2) with evils, and (3) with mixed goods. (1) Unmixed goods may all be said to consist in the love of beautiful things or of good persons: but the number of different goods of this kind is as great as that of beautiful objects, and they are also differentiated from one another by the different emotions appropriate to different objects. These goods are undoubtedly good, even where the things or persons loved are imaginary; but it was urged that, where the thing or person is real and is believed to be so, these two facts together, when combined with the mere[p. 225] love of the qualities in question, constitute a whole which is greatly better than that mere love, having an additional value quite distinct from that which belongs to the existence of the object, where that object is a good person. Finally it was pointed out that the love of mental qualities, by themselves, does not seem to be so great a good as that of mental and material qualities together; and that, in any case, an immense number of the best things are, or include, a love of material qualities (113-123). (2) Great evils may be said to consist either (a) in the love of what is evil or ugly, or (b) in the hatred of what is good or beautiful, or (c) in the consciousness of pain. Thus the consciousness of pain, if it be a great evil, is the only exception to the rule that all great goods and great evils involve both a cognition and an emotion directed towards its object (124-128). (3) Mixed goods are those which include some element which is evil or ugly. They may be said to consist either in hatred of what is ugly or of evils of classes (a) and (b), or in compassion for pain. But where they include an evil, which actually exists, its demerit seems to be always great enough to outweigh the positive value which they possess (129-133).
135. The main goal of this chapter has been to broadly define the types of things where we might find significant intrinsic goods or significant intrinsic evils; specifically, to highlight that there's a wide variety of these things, and that the simplest among them, with one exception, are very complex entities made up of parts that have little or no value on their own. All of them involve awareness of an object, which is generally also quite complex, and almost all also involve an emotional response towards this object; however, while they share certain common traits, the wide range of qualities by which they differ from one another is equally essential to their value: neither the general nature of all, nor the specific nature of each, is inherently highly good or highly evil on its own; their value or drawbacks come, in each case, from both being present. My discussion is divided into three main sections: (1) unmixed goods, (2) evils, and (3) mixed goods. (1) Unmixed goods can be said to consist of the love for beautiful things or good people: however, the variety of these types of goods is as vast as the variety of beautiful objects, and they are also distinguished by the different emotions connected to different objects. These goods are undoubtedly good, even when the things or people loved are imaginary; but it has been argued that when the object is real and believed to be so, these two facts, in combination with mere[p. 225] affection for the qualities in question, create a whole that is significantly better than just that mere love, adding a distinct value that comes from the existence of the object, especially when that object is a good person. Finally, it has been noted that love for mental qualities alone does not seem to be as significant a good as love for both mental and material qualities together; and that, in any case, many of the best things involve or include an appreciation of material qualities (113-123). (2) Major evils can be described as either (a) the love of what is evil or ugly, (b) the hatred of what is good or beautiful, or (c) the awareness of pain. Thus, the awareness of pain, if it’s a significant evil, is the only exception to the notion that all major goods and evils involve both an awareness and an emotion directed toward its object (124-128). (3) Mixed goods are those that contain some element that is evil or ugly. They can be described as either stemming from hatred of what is ugly or from evils of types (a) and (b), or from compassion for pain. However, when they include a real evil, its drawbacks seem to always outweigh the positive value they have (129-133).
[p. 227]
[p. 227]
INDEX.
- Aesthetic
- Aesthetics 200
- Affection
- Altruism 96-7, 167
- Analytic judgments 7, 29, 33-4, 35, 220-1
- Appreciation 189-90, 200, 204-5, 221
- Approval 131
- Approve 60
- Approbation 171
- Appropriate, inappropriate 192, 199, 204-5, 209, 211, 220
- defined 190
- Aristotle 4
- Art
- Autonomy 127
- Bad 5, 27, 28, 95, 140, 143, 157, 178, 181, 188, 209, 210, 213, 214, 216, 218
- ‘Based on’ 38, 49, 54, 114, 115, 118, 120, 122, 144
- Beauty
- Being, dist. from existence 110-11
- Belief, value of 193-200, 208, 210-11, 212, 219, 224-5
- Benevolence, Sidgwick’s ‘principle of Rational’ 102-3
- Bentham 145
- Bradley, F. H.
- Butler, Bishop 86, 206
- Casuistry 4-5
- Causal judgments
- Causal relations 31-3, 34-6
- Chastity 158
- Classical style 215-16
- Christ
- Christian Ethics 178
- Clifford, W. K. 40
- Cognition
- [p. 228]Commands, confused with moral laws 128-9, 141
- Common sense 224
- Compassion 217, 219, 220, 225
- Conduct, relation of to Ethics 2-3, 146, 180
- Conscience
- Conscientiousness 218
- Contempt 211, 217
- Corporeal beauty 203-4
- Courage 217
- Crimes 161
- Criterion
- Cruelty 209-11, 218
- Darwin 47
- Definition, nature of 6-9, 18-20
- Desirable, meaning of 65-7, 73
- Desire, cause and object of 68-70, 73-4
- Duty
- Egoistic Hedonism 18
- Egoism, as doctrine of end 18, 96-105, 109
- Egoism, as doctrine of means 96-7, 105, 167
- Emotion
- Empirical 39, 111, 123
- Empiricism 103, 124-5, 130
- End = effect 32
- End = good in itself 18, 24, 64-6, 72, 73, 79-81, 83, 85, 94-5, 184, 216
- End = object of desire 68, 70, 71, 72
- Enjoyment 77, 96, 188, 208
- Envy 211
- Epistemology 133, 140-1
- Ethics
- Eudaemonist 175
- Evil 153, 156, 158, 160, 186, 193, 205, 207-14, 224, 225
- Evolution 46-8, 54-8
- Evolutionistic 46, 50, 52, 54, 58
- Existence
- Expediency 167-70, 181
- Habit 171, 175-6, 177
- Hatred 211, 214
- Health 42-3, 65, 157, 167
- Heaven 115, 174, 183, 185, 195
- upon Earth 186
- Hedonism 39, 52, 59-63, 90-1, 96, 108-9, 174
- Hegel 30, 34, 110
- Heteronomous 127
- Higher 48-9, 78
- Hobbes 97
- Honesty 175-6
- Hypothetical laws 22, 155
- Ideal
- Idealistic 130, 205
- Imagination, value of 193, 194, 196, 197, 210, 219, 220, 221, 224
- Imperative 128
- Industry 157, 167
- Intention 179 n. 1
- Interest 102
- Intrinsic
- Intuition
- Intuitionism
- [p. 230]Lasciviousness 209-10
- Law
- Legal 126, 128
- Leibniz 125
- Life 15, 46, 50, 52, 156
- Logical
- Love
- Lucian 45
- Lust 209-10, 218
- Lying 154
- Mackenzie, Prof. J. S. 114, 120
- Material qualities, value of 204, 205-7, 221, 225
- Matter, value of 205-7
- Meaning, ‘to have no’ 31, 34-5
- Means = cause or necessary condition 18, 21-3, 89, 180
- Mental
- Mercy 178
- Metaphysical 39, 58, 110-15, 139-40
- Method
- Mill, J. S. 145
- Moral
- Motive 67, 70, 177, 178-80
- Murder 148, 151, 154, 156-7, 178
- Natural
- Natural = normal 42-4, 58
- Natural = necessary 44-5, 58
- Naturalism 20, 40, 58, 144
- Naturalistic
- Nature 40-1, 110, 111, 112
- Nature, life according to 41-2, 113
- Nature, value of 188, 193, 195, 200, 206
- Necessity
- New Testament 177, 178, 179
- Object
- Objective 82, 201
- Obligation
- Obligatory 25, 148, 170
- [p. 231]Organic relation, unity, whole
- Ought
- Pain 64, 65, 210, 212-4, 217, 222-3, 225
- Particular 3-4
- Perception 111, 112, 134, 136
- Pessimism 51, 53, 156
- Plato
- Pleasure 12-13, 16
- Pity 217, 221
- Positive science 39
- Possible action 150-1
- Practical 216, 221
- Practice 2, 20
- Praise 171
- Preference 77-9, 131
- Promises 157
- Property, respect of 157
- Propositions, types of 123-6
- Prove 11, 65, 66, 74, 75-7, 99, 112, 137, 141, 143, 145, 169, 181
- Prudence 168
- Psychological 11, 130, 140, 148
- Punishment 164
- Reason 143-4
- Representative art 193
- Reward 174
- Right 18, 24-5, 105, 146, 180, 216, 218, 223
- Romantic style 215-16
- Rousseau 42
- Sanctions 159, 164
- Secondary qualities 206
- Self-evidence 143, 144, 148, 181
- Self-realisation 113, 114, 120, 188
- Self-sacrifice 170
- Sensation 134
- Sensationalist 130
- Sidgwick, Henry 145
- value of beauty 81-4, 85-7
- on Bentham 17-19
- rationality of Egoism 99-103
- ‘good’ unanalysable 17
- Hedonism 59, 63, 64, 81-7, 91-6, 108-9
- ‘method’ of Intuitionism 59, 92-4
- value of knowledge 82, 86
- neglects principle of organic wholes 93
- pleasure as criterion 91-2, 94-5
- quality of pleasure 77, 81
- value of unconscious 81-4
- Sins 161
- Spencer, Herbert 46, 48-58
- Spinoza 110, 113
- Spiritual, value of 205-6
- Summum Bonum 183, 205
- Stoics 41, 110
- Synthetic 7, 58, 143
- Taste, error of 192-3, 211
- Taylor, A. E. 60
- Temperance 157, 168
- Theodicies 220
- Tragedy 219, 221
- [p. 232]Truth
- Tyndall 40
- Ugly 208, 209-11, 214, 216-19, 221
- Ultimate end 51, 83, 85, 96-7, 99-102, 183, 189
- Unity 222
- organic, see ‘Organic’
- Universal
- Universalistic Hedonism 103
- Useful 106, 146, 167
- Utilitarianism 63, 96, 99, 104-7, 109
- Utopias 183, 186
PRINTED IN ENGLAND BY J. B. PEACE, M.A.
AT THE CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
PRINTED IN ENGLAND BY J. B. PEACE, M.A.
AT CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
FOOTNOTES
Footnotes
[1] ‘The Origin of the Knowledge of Right and Wrong.’ By Franz Brentano. English Translation by Cecil Hague. Constable, 1902.—I have written a review of this book, which will, I hope, appear in the International Journal of Ethics for October, 1903. I may refer to this review for a fuller account of my reasons for disagreeing with Brentano.
[1] ‘The Origin of the Knowledge of Right and Wrong.’ By Franz Brentano. English Translation by Cecil Hague. Constable, 1902.—I’ve written a review of this book, which I hope will be published in the International Journal of Ethics for October 1903. I can refer to this review for a more detailed explanation of why I disagree with Brentano.
[23] This sense of the term must be carefully distinguished from that in which the agent’s intention may be said to be ‘right,’ if only the results he intended would have been the best possible.
[23] This interpretation of the term needs to be clearly separated from the situation where the agent's intention can be considered 'right' simply because the outcomes they aimed for would have been the best possible.
Transcriber’s note
Transcription note
- Obvious printer errors have been silently corrected.
- Original spelling was kept, but variant spellings were made consistent when a predominant usage was found.
- Blank pages have been skipped.
- Footnotes have been renumbered and moved to the end of the book.
Download ePUB
If you like this ebook, consider a donation!