This is a modern-English version of Vision and Design, originally written by Fry, Roger.
It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling,
and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If
you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.
Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.
Contents. Contents. (etext transcriber's note) (etext transcriber's note) |
Vision and Design | ||
BY ROGER FRY LONDON CHATTO & WINDUS 1920 |
All rights reserved
PRINTED IN ENGLAND BY WILLIAM CLOWES AND SONS, LIMITED
LONDON AND BECCLES
All rights reserved
PRINTED IN ENGLAND BY WILLIAM CLOWES AND SONS, LIMITED
LONDON AND BECCLES
PREFACE
This book contains a selection from my writings on Art extending over a period of twenty years. Some essays have never before been published in England; and I have also added a good deal of new matter and made slight corrections throughout. In the laborious work of hunting up lost and forgotten publications, and in the work of selection, revision, and arrangement I owe everything to Mr. R. R. Tatlock’s devoted and patient labour.
This book includes a collection of my writings on Art spanning two decades. Some essays have never been published in England before; I've also included a lot of new content and made minor corrections throughout. In the painstaking process of locating lost and forgotten publications, as well as in the tasks of selection, revision, and organization, I owe everything to Mr. R. R. Tatlock’s dedicated and patient efforts.
DEDICATED
TO
MY SISTER MARGERY
WITHOUT WHOSE GENTLE BUT PERSISTENT PRESSURE
THIS BOOK WOULD NEVER HAVE BEEN MADE
DEDICATED
TO
MY SISTER MARGERY
WITHOUT WHOSE GENTLE BUT PERSISTENT PRESSURE
THIS BOOK WOULD NEVER HAVE BEEN MADE
CONTENTS
LIST OF ILLUSTRATIONS
VISION AND DESIGN
ART AND LIFE[1]
WHEN we look at ancient works of art we habitually treat them not merely as objects of æsthetic enjoyment but also as successive deposits of the human imagination. It is indeed this view of works of art as crystallised history that accounts for much of the interest felt in ancient art by those who have but little æsthetic feeling and who find nothing to interest them in the work of their contemporaries where the historical motive is lacking and they are left face to face with bare æsthetic values.
WHEN we look at ancient artworks, we often see them not just as sources of beauty but also as layers of human creativity through time. It's this perspective of art as captured history that explains a lot of the fascination some people have with ancient art, especially those who may not have a strong appreciation for aesthetics and find little to engage them in contemporary work that lacks a historical context, leaving them confronted only with pure aesthetic qualities.
I once knew an old gentleman who had retired from his city office to a country house—a fussy, feeble little being who had cut no great figure in life. He had built himself a house which was preternaturally hideous; his taste was deplorable and his manners indifferent; but he had a dream, the dream of himself as an exquisite and refined intellectual dandy living in a society of elegant frivolity. To realise this dream he had spent large sums in buying up every scrap of eighteenth-century French furniture which he could lay hands on. These he stored in an immense upper floor in his house which was always locked except when he went up to indulge in his dream and to become for a time a courtier at Versailles doing homage to the du Barry, whose toilet-tables and what-nots were strewn pell-mell about the room without order or effect of any kind. Such is an extreme instance of the historical way of looking at works of art. For this old gentleman, as for how many an American millionaire, art was merely a help to an imagined dream life.
I once knew an old gentleman who had retired from his city job to a country house—a fussy, frail little guy who hadn’t made much of an impact in life. He built himself a house that was ridiculously ugly; his taste was terrible and his manners were average; but he had a dream, the dream of being an exquisite and refined intellectual dandy living in a society of elegant frivolity. To achieve this dream, he spent a lot of money collecting every piece of eighteenth-century French furniture he could find. He stored these in a huge upper floor of his house that was always locked, except when he went up to indulge in his fantasy and temporarily be a courtier at Versailles, paying tribute to the du Barry, whose dressing tables and knick-knacks were scattered around the room without any organization or aesthetic appeal. This is an extreme example of the historical way of viewing art. For this old gentleman, as for many American millionaires, art was just a means to support a fantasized lifestyle.
To many people then it seems an easy thing to pass thus directly from the work of art to the life of the time which produced it. We all in fact weave an imagined Middle Ages around the parish church{2} and an imagined Renaissance haunts us in the college courts of Oxford and Cambridge. We don’t, I fancy, stop to consider very closely how true the imagined life is: we are satisfied with the prospect of another sort of life which we might have lived, which we often think we might have preferred to our actual life. We don’t stop to consider much how far the pictured past corresponds to any reality, certainly not to consider what proportion of the whole reality of the past life gets itself embalmed in this way in works of art. Thus we picture our Middle Ages as almost entirely occupied with religion and war, our Renaissance as occupied in learning, and our eighteenth century as occupied in gallantry and wit. Whereas, as a matter of fact, all of these things were going on all the time while the art of each period has for some reason been mainly taken up with the expression of one or another activity. There is indeed a certain danger in accepting too naïvely the general atmosphere—the ethos, which the works of art of a period exhale. Thus when we look at the thirteenth-century sculpture of Chartres or Beauvais we feel at once the expression of a peculiar gracious piety, a smiling and gay devoutness which we are tempted to take for the prevailing mood of the time—and which we perhaps associate with the revelation of just such a type of character in S. Francis of Assisi. A study of Salimbeni’s chronicle with its interminable record of squalid avarice and meanness, or of the fierce brutalities of Dante’s Inferno are necessary correctives of such a pleasant dream.
For many people, it seems easy to jump directly from a work of art to the life of the time that created it. We all, in fact, create an imagined Middle Ages around the parish church{2} and an imagined Renaissance lingers in the college courtyards of Oxford and Cambridge. I think we don’t take the time to think about how accurate our imagined lives are: we’re satisfied with the idea of another kind of life we might have lived, which we often think we might have preferred to our actual lives. We don’t usually consider how much the pictured past reflects any reality, definitely not the proportion of the entire reality of past life that gets captured in works of art. Thus, we think of our Middle Ages as being mostly about religion and war, our Renaissance as focused on learning, and our eighteenth century as centered on charm and wit. However, the truth is that all of these aspects were happening all the time, while the art from each period seems to focus mainly on one activity or another. There’s definitely a risk in naively accepting the overall atmosphere—the ethos that the works of art of a period convey. So, when we look at the thirteenth-century sculptures of Chartres or Beauvais, we immediately feel the expression of a distinctive gracious piety, a cheerful and devout spirit that we might mistakenly take as the dominant mood of the time—and which we might associate with a similar type of character in S. Francis of Assisi. A study of Salimbeni’s chronicle, with its endless accounts of sordid greed and pettiness, or the harsh brutalities of Dante’s Inferno, serves as necessary corrections to such a pleasant illusion.
It would seem then that the correspondence between art and life which we so habitually assume is not at all constant and requires much correction before it can be trusted. Let us approach the same question from another point and see what result we obtain. Let us consider the great revolutions in art and the revolutions in life and see if they coincide. And here let me try to say what I mean by life as contrasted with art. I mean the general intellectual and instinctive reaction to their surroundings of those men of any period whose lives rise to complete self-consciousness. Their view of the universe as a whole and their conception of their relations to their kind. Of course their conception of the nature and function of art will itself be one of the most varying aspects of life and may in any particular period profoundly modify the correspondence of art to life.
It seems that the link between art and life, which we often take for granted, is actually not consistent and needs a lot of adjustments before we can rely on it. Let's look at the same question from a different angle and see what we find. Let’s examine the major revolutions in art alongside the revolutions in life and see if they align. Here, I want to clarify what I mean by life in contrast to art. I’m talking about the overall intellectual and instinctual reactions of people from any period who have achieved a full awareness of themselves. Their perspective of the universe as a whole and their understanding of their relationships with others. Naturally, their views on the nature and purpose of art will vary greatly across different periods and can significantly alter the connection between art and life at any given time.
Perhaps the greatest revolution in life that we know of at all{3} intimately was that which effected the change from Paganism to Christianity. That this was no mere accident is evident from the fact that Christianity was only one of many competing religions, all of which represented a closely similar direction of thought and feeling. Any one of these would have produced practically the same effect, that of focussing men’s minds on the spiritual life as opposed to the material life which had pre-occupied them for so long. One cannot doubt then that here was a change which denoted a long prepared and inevitable readjustment of men’s attitude to their universe. Now the art of the Roman Empire showed no trace whatever of this influence; it went on with precisely the same motives and principles which had satisfied Paganism. The subjects changed and became mainly Christian, but the treatment was so exactly similar that it requires more than a cursory glance to say if the figure on a sarcophagus is Christ or Orpheus, Moses or Æsculapius.
Perhaps the biggest change in life that we know of so well{3} was the shift from Paganism to Christianity. It's clear that this was no accident, considering that Christianity was just one of many competing religions, all of which shared a similar approach to thought and feeling. Any one of these religions would have produced almost the same result: shifting people's focus from the material life that had occupied them for so long to the spiritual life. It's hard to deny that this was a change that signified a long-prepared and inevitable adjustment in how people viewed their universe. Meanwhile, the art of the Roman Empire showed no sign of this influence; it continued with the same motives and principles that had satisfied Paganism. The subjects became mainly Christian, but the style was so similar that it takes more than a quick look to tell if the figure on a sarcophagus is Christ or Orpheus, Moses or Æsculapius.
The next great turning-point in history is that which marks the triumph of the forces of reaction towards the close of the twelfth century—a reaction which destroyed the promising hopes of freedom of thought and manners which make the twelfth century appear as a foretaste of modern enlightenment. Here undoubtedly the change in life corresponds very closely with a great change in art—the change from the Romanesque to the Gothic, and at first sight we might suppose a causal connection between the two. But when we consider the nature of the changes in the two sequences, this becomes very doubtful. For whereas in the life of the Middle Ages the change was one of reaction—the sharp repression by the reactionary forces of a gradual growth of freedom—the change in art is merely the efflorescence of certain long prepared and anticipated effects. The forms of Gothic architecture were merely the answer to certain engineering problems which had long occupied the inventive ingenuity of twelfth-century architects, while in the figurative arts the change merely showed a new self-confidence in the rendering of the human figure, a newly developed mastery in the handling of material. In short, the change in art was in the opposite direction to that in life. Whereas in life the direction of movement was sharply bent backwards, in art the direction followed on in a continuous straight line.
The next major turning point in history is marked by the victory of reactionary forces toward the end of the twelfth century—a reaction that crushed the hopeful prospects for freedom of thought and behavior that made the twelfth century seem like a preview of modern enlightenment. Here, the shift in life closely aligns with a significant change in art—the transition from Romanesque to Gothic. At first glance, we might think there’s a direct link between the two. However, upon examining the nature of the changes in each, that connection becomes questionable. In the context of the Middle Ages, the shift was a reaction—a strong suppression by reactionary forces of a gradual increase in freedom—while the change in art was simply a blossoming of certain long-awaited and anticipated outcomes. The forms of Gothic architecture were just responses to engineering challenges that had long engaged the inventive minds of twelfth-century architects. Meanwhile, in the figurative arts, the change reflected newfound self-confidence in depicting the human figure and an advanced control over materials. In short, the shift in art was in the opposite direction from that in life. While life was moving sharply backward, art progressed along a steady, straight path.
It is true that in one small particular the reaction did have a{4} direct effect on art. The preaching of S. Bernard of Clairvaux did impose on the architects who worked for the Cistercian order a peculiar architectural hypocrisy. They were bound by his traditional influence to make their churches have an appearance of extreme simplicity and austerity, but they wanted nevertheless to make them as magnificent and imposing as possible. The result was a peculiar style of ostentatious simplicity. Paray le Monial is the only church left standing in which this curious and, in point of fact, depressing evidence of the direct influence of the religious reaction on art is to be seen, and, as a curiosity in psychological expression, it is well worth a visit. For the rest the movement of art went on entirely unaffected by the new orientation of thought.
It's true that in one small way, the reaction had a{4} direct impact on art. The preaching of S. Bernard of Clairvaux forced the architects working for the Cistercian order into a kind of architectural hypocrisy. They were influenced by his traditional ideas to make their churches look very simple and austere, but they still wanted to make them as grand and impressive as possible. The result was a unique style of flashy simplicity. Paray le Monial is the only church still standing that showcases this strange and, honestly, kind of depressing evidence of the religious reaction's direct influence on art. And as a curious example of psychological expression, it’s definitely worth a visit. Aside from that, the movement of art continued unaffected by the new way of thinking.
We come now to the Renaissance, and here for the first time in our survey we may, I think, safely admit a true correspondence between the change in life and the change in art. The change in life, if one may generalise on such a vast subject, was towards the recognition of the rights of the individual to complete self-realisation and the recognition of the objective reality of the material universe which implied the whole scientific attitude—and in both these things the exemplar which men put before themselves was the civilisation of Greece and Rome. In art the change went pari passu with the change in life, each assisting and directing the other—the first men of science were artists like Brunelleschi, Ucello, Piero della Francesca and Leonardo da Vinci. The study of classical literature was followed in strict connection with the study of classical canons of art, and the greater sense of individual importance found its expression in the new naturalism which made portraiture in the modern sense possible.
We now turn to the Renaissance, and for the first time in our review, I think we can confidently acknowledge a true connection between changes in life and changes in art. The shift in life, if we can generalize about such a broad topic, was towards recognizing the rights of individuals for complete self-realization and acknowledging the objective reality of the material universe, which is the foundation of the scientific approach. In both these aspects, people looked up to the civilizations of Greece and Rome as examples. In art, the change occurred simultaneously with the change in life, with each influencing and guiding the other. The first scientists were artists like Brunelleschi, Ucello, Piero della Francesca, and Leonardo da Vinci. The study of classical literature was closely linked to the study of classical art principles, and the growing sense of individual significance was expressed through the new naturalism that allowed for modern-style portraiture.
For once then art and the other functions of the human spirit found themselves in perfect harmony and direct alliance, and to that harmony we may attribute much of the intensity and self-assurance of the work of the great Renaissance artists. It is one of the rarest of good fortunes for an artist to find himself actually understood and appreciated by the mass of his educated contemporaries, and not only that, but moving alongside of and in step with them towards a similar goal.
For once, art and the other aspects of the human spirit were in perfect harmony and direct alignment, and we can credit that harmony for much of the intensity and confidence in the work of the great Renaissance artists. It's one of the rarest blessings for an artist to be truly understood and appreciated by the educated masses of their time, and even more so to be moving alongside them toward a shared goal.
The Catholic reaction retarded and impeded the main movement of Renaissance thought, but it did not really succeed either in{5} suppressing it or changing the main direction of its current. In art it undoubtedly had some direct effect, it created a new kind of insincerity of expression, a florid and sentimental religiosity—a new variety of bad taste, the rhetorical and over-emphatic. And I suspect that art was already prepared for this step by a certain exhaustion of the impulsive energy of the Renaissance—so that here too we may admit a correspondence.
The Catholic response slowed down and hindered the main movement of Renaissance thought, but it didn’t really manage to {5} suppress it or change its main direction. In art, it definitely had some direct influence; it created a new kind of insincerity in expression, a flowery and sentimental religiosity—a new form of bad taste, characterized by being rhetorical and overly dramatic. I suspect that art was already set up for this shift due to a certain fatigue in the spontaneous energy of the Renaissance—so we can acknowledge a connection here as well.
The seventeenth century shows us no violent change in life, but rather the gradual working out of the principles implicit in the Renaissance and the Catholic reaction. But here we come to another curious want of correspondence between art and life, for in art we have a violent revolution, followed by a bitter internecine struggle among artists. This revolution was inaugurated by Caravaggio, who first discovered the surprising emotional possibilities of chiaroscuro and who combined with this a new idea of realism—realism in the modern sense, viz., the literal acceptance of what is coarse, common, squalid or undistinguished in life—realism in the sense of the novelists of Zola’s time. To Caravaggio’s influence we might trace not only a great deal of Rembrandt’s art but the whole of that movement in favour of the extravagantly impressive and picturesque, which culminated in the romantic movement of the nineteenth century. Here, then, is another surprising want of correspondence between art and life.
The seventeenth century doesn't show any drastic changes in life, but rather the gradual development of the ideas that were inherent in the Renaissance and the Catholic response. However, we encounter another interesting mismatch between art and life, as in art we see a drastic revolution followed by a fierce internal conflict among artists. This revolution began with Caravaggio, who was the first to explore the surprising emotional potential of chiaroscuro and combined it with a new idea of realism—realism in the modern sense, meaning the straightforward acceptance of what is rough, ordinary, grimy, or unremarkable in life—realism in the style of the novelists from Zola’s era. Caravaggio’s influence can be traced not only in much of Rembrandt’s work but also throughout the movement that favored the extravagantly striking and picturesque, which peaked in the romantic movement of the nineteenth century. So, we see another surprising disconnect between art and life.
In the eighteenth century we get a curious phenomenon. Art goes to court, identifies itself closely with a small aristocratic clique, becomes the exponent of their manners and their tastes. It becomes a luxury. It is no longer in the main stream of spiritual and intellectual effort, and this seclusion of art may account for the fact that the next great change in life—the French Revolution and all its accompanying intellectual ferment—finds no serious correspondence in art. We get a change, it is true; the French Republicans believed they were the counterpart of the Romans, and so David had to invent for them that peculiarly distressing type of the ancient Roman—always in heroic attitudes, always immaculate, spotless and with a highly polished ‘Mme. Tussaud’ surface. By-the-by, I was almost forgetting that we do owe Mme. Tussaud to the French Revolution. But the real movement of art lay in quite other directions to David—lay in the gradual unfolding of the Romanticist conception of the world{6}—a world of violent emotional effects, of picturesque accidents, of wild nature, and this was a long prepared reaction from the complacent sophistication of eighteenth-century life. It is possible that one may associate this with the general state of mind that produced the Revolution, since both were a revolt against the established order of the eighteenth century; but curiously enough it found its chief ally in the reaction which followed the Revolution, in the neo-Christianism of Chateaubriand and the new sentimental respect for the age of faith—which, incidentally, appeared so much more picturesque than the age of reason.
In the eighteenth century, we see a curious shift. Art aligns itself closely with a small aristocratic group, becoming a representation of their manners and tastes. It turns into a luxury. It's no longer part of the main flow of spiritual and intellectual progress, and this detachment of art might explain why the next significant change in society—the French Revolution and its surrounding intellectual upheaval—doesn’t have much of a reflection in art. There is a change, to be sure; the French Republicans thought they were the modern-day Romans, so David had to create that uniquely distressing image of the ancient Roman—always in heroic poses, always pristine and polished, like a highly finished Madame Tussaud figure. By the way, I almost forgot to mention that we actually owe Madame Tussaud to the French Revolution. But the real development in art was happening in entirely different directions from David—specifically, in the gradual emergence of the Romantic view of the world—a world of intense emotions, striking accidents, and wild nature, which was a long-prepared reaction against the smug sophistication of eighteenth-century life. This can potentially be linked to the general mindset that led to the Revolution, as both were rebellions against the established order of the eighteenth century; yet, interestingly, it found its main support in the reaction that followed the Revolution, in the neo-Christianism of Chateaubriand and the new sentimental appreciation for the age of faith—which, incidentally, seemed much more picturesque than the age of reason.
It would be interesting at this point to consider how far during the nineteenth century reactionary political and religious thought was inspired primarily by æsthetic considerations—a curious instance of the counter-influence of art on life might perhaps be discovered in the devotees of the Oxford movement. But this would take us too far afield.
It would be interesting now to consider how much reactionary political and religious thought in the nineteenth century was mainly inspired by aesthetic considerations—a strange example of how art can influence life might be found among the followers of the Oxford movement. However, this would lead us off track.
The foregoing violently foreshortened view of history and art will show, I hope, that the usual assumption of a direct and decisive connection between life and art is by no means correct. It may, I hope, give pause to those numerous people who have already promised themselves a great new art as a result of the present war, though perhaps it is as well to let them enjoy it in anticipation, since it is, I fancy, the only way in which they are likely to enjoy a great art of any kind. What this survey suggests to me is that if we consider this special spiritual activity of art we find it no doubt open at times to influences from life, but in the main self-contained—we find the rhythmic sequences of change determined much more by its own internal forces—and by the readjustment within it, of its own elements—than by external forces. I admit, of course, that it is always conditioned more or less by economic changes, but these are rather conditions of its existence at all than directive influences. I also admit that under certain conditions the rhythms of life and of art may coincide with great effect on both; but in the main the two rhythms are distinct, and as often as not play against each other.
The previous, overly simplified view of history and art will hopefully show that the common belief in a direct and significant link between life and art is not accurate. I hope this gives pause to the many people who are eagerly expecting a groundbreaking new art as a result of the current war. However, it might be better to let them enjoy that anticipation, as it seems to be the only way they’re likely to appreciate great art of any kind. What this overview suggests to me is that when we consider this unique spiritual activity of art, we find it sometimes influenced by life, but mainly self-sufficient. The rhythmic changes in art are influenced much more by its own internal forces and the adjustments of its own elements than by external factors. I acknowledge, of course, that it is always somewhat shaped by economic changes, but these serve more as conditions for its existence than as guiding influences. I also recognize that under certain circumstances, the rhythms of life and art can align in ways that significantly impact both; however, generally, the two rhythms are separate and often contrast with each other.
We have, I hope, gained some experience with which to handle the real subject of my inquiry, the relation of the modern movement in art to life. To understand it we must go back to the impressionist{7} movement, which dates from about 1870. The artists who called themselves impressionists combined two distinct ideas. On the one hand they upheld, more categorically than ever before, the complete detachment of the artistic vision from the values imposed on vision by everyday life—they claimed, as Whistler did in his “10 o’clock,” to be pure artists. On the other hand a group of them used this freedom for the quasi-scientific description of new effects of atmospheric colour and atmospheric perspective, thereby endowing painting with a quite new series of colour harmonies, or at least of harmonies which had not been cultivated by European painters for many hundreds of years. They did more than this—the effects thus explored were completely unfamiliar to the ordinary man, whose vision is limited to the mere recognition of objects with a view to the uses of everyday life. He was forced, in looking at their pictures, to accept as artistic representation something very remote from all his previous expectations, and thereby he also acquired in time a new tolerance in his judgments on works of art, a tolerance which was destined to bear a still further strain in succeeding developments.
I hope we've gained some experience to tackle the main topic of my inquiry: the connection between the modern art movement and life. To understand this, we need to look back at the Impressionist movement, which started around 1870. The artists who identified as Impressionists combined two distinct ideas. First, they firmly advocated for the complete separation of artistic vision from the values imposed by everyday life; they claimed, as Whistler did in his “10 o’clock,” to be pure artists. Second, a group among them took this freedom to create quasi-scientific descriptions of new effects of atmospheric color and perspective, introducing painting to a whole new range of color harmonies—harmonies that hadn't been explored by European painters for hundreds of years. They did more than that—the effects they explored were entirely foreign to the average person, whose perception is limited to simply recognizing objects for daily use. When looking at their paintings, people had to accept as artistic representation something very different from what they had previously expected, which led them to develop a new tolerance in their judgments of art, a tolerance that would be further tested in later artistic movements.
As against these great advantages which art owes to impressionism we must set the fact that the pseudo-scientific and analytic method of these painters forced artists to accept pictures which lacked design and formal co-ordination to a degree which had never before been permitted. They, or rather some of them, reduced the artistic vision to a continuous patchwork or mosaic of coloured patches without architectural framework or structural coherence. In this, impressionism marked the climax of a movement which had been going on more or less steadily from the thirteenth century—the tendency to approximate the forms of art more and more exactly to the representation of the totality of appearance. When once representation had been pushed to this point where further development was impossible, it was inevitable that artists should turn round and question the validity of the fundamental assumption that art aimed at representation; and the moment the question was fairly posed it became clear that the pseudo-scientific assumption that fidelity to appearance was the measure of art had no logical foundation. From that moment on it became evident that art had arrived at a critical moment, and that the greatest revolution in art that had taken place since Græco-Roman{8} impressionism became converted into Byzantine formalism was inevitable. It was this revolution that Cézanne inaugurated and that Gauguin and van Goch continued. There is no need here to give in detail the characteristics of this new movement: they are sufficiently familiar. But we may summarise them as the re-establishment of purely æsthetic criteria in place of the criterion of conformity to appearance—the rediscovery of the principles of structural design and harmony.
Compared to the great advantages that art gained from impressionism, we must acknowledge that the pseudo-scientific and analytical methods of these painters forced artists to create works that lacked design and formal coordination in a way that had never been allowed before. They, or at least some of them, reduced artistic vision to a continuous patchwork or mosaic of colored patches without any architectural framework or structural coherence. In this way, impressionism represented the peak of a movement that had been steadily evolving since the thirteenth century—the tendency to align art forms more closely with the totality of visual appearance. Once representation reached this point where further development was impossible, it was only natural for artists to question the validity of the fundamental assumption that art aimed at representation. When this question was raised, it became clear that the pseudo-scientific belief that fidelity to appearance was the measure of art lacked logical support. From that moment on, it was evident that art had reached a critical juncture, and the greatest revolution in art since Greco-Roman times—when impressionism evolved into Byzantine formalism—became unavoidable. This revolution was initiated by Cézanne and continued by Gauguin and van Gogh. There’s no need to detail the characteristics of this new movement; they are quite familiar. But we can summarize them as the re-establishment of purely aesthetic criteria instead of the criterion of conformity to appearance—the rediscovery of principles of structural design and harmony.
The new movement has, also, led to a new canon of criticism, and this has changed our attitude to the arts of other times and countries. So long as representation was regarded as the end of art, the skill of the artist and his proficiency in this particular feat of representation were regarded with an admiration which was in fact mainly non-æsthetic. With the new indifference to representation we have become much less interested in skill and not at all interested in knowledge. We are thus no longer cut off from a great deal of barbaric and primitive art the very meaning of which escaped the understanding of those who demanded a certain standard of skill in representation before they could give serious consideration to a work of art. In general the effect of the movement has been to render the artist intensely conscious of the æsthetic unity of the work of art, but singularly naïve and simple as regards other considerations.
The new movement has also created a fresh approach to criticism, which has transformed how we view the arts from different times and places. As long as representation was seen as the ultimate goal of art, people admired the artist's skills and ability in that specific area of representation, but this admiration was mostly non-aesthetic. With our growing indifference to representation, we have become much less interested in skill and entirely uninterested in knowledge. Consequently, we are no longer disconnected from a lot of primitive and tribal art, the true meaning of which was overlooked by those who required a certain level of skill in representation before they could truly appreciate a work of art. Overall, the impact of this movement has made artists highly aware of the aesthetic unity of their work, yet somewhat naïve and simplistic regarding other aspects.
It remains to be considered whether the life of the past fifty years has shown any such violent reorientation as we have found in the history of modern art. If we look back to the days of Herbert Spencer and Huxley, what changes are there in the general tendencies of life? The main ideas of rationalism seem to me to have steadily made way—there have been minor counter revolutions, it is true, but the main current of active thought has surely moved steadily along the lines already laid down. I mean that the scientific attitude is more and more widely accepted. The protests of organised religion and of various mysticisms seem to grow gradually weaker and to carry less weight. Hardly any writers or thinkers of first-rate calibre now appear in the reactionary camp. I see, in short, no big change in direction, no evident revulsion of feeling.
It’s worth considering whether the past fifty years have shown any drastic shifts like we've seen in the history of modern art. If we look back to the times of Herbert Spencer and Huxley, what changes can we identify in the overall trends of life? The key ideas of rationalism seem to have steadily gained ground—there have been minor counter-revolutions, it's true, but the main flow of active thought has certainly continued along the established paths. By this, I mean that the scientific perspective is increasingly accepted. The opposition from organized religion and various spiritual beliefs seems to be weakening and losing influence. Hardly any prominent writers or thinkers now belong to the reactionary side. In short, I see no significant change in direction, no clear shift in sentiment.

13th Cent. Sculpture in the Cloister of S. John Lateran |
Auguste Rodin. Group from “The Burghers of Calais” |
Henri Matisse. Sculpture in Plaster |
Property of the Artist | ||
Plate I. |
self-confident. It would admit far greater difficulties in presenting its picture of the universe than would have occurred to Spencer. The fact is that scepticism has turned on itself and has gone behind a great many of the axioms that seemed self-evident to the earlier rationalists. I do not see that it has at any point threatened the superstructure of the rationalist position, but it has led us to recognise the necessity of a continual revision and reconstruction of these data. Rationalism has become less arrogant and less narrow in its vision. And this is partly due also to the adventure of the scientific spirit into new regions. I refer to all that immense body of study and speculation which starts from Robertson Smith’s “Religion of the Israelites.” The discovery of natural law in what seemed to earlier rationalists the chaotic fancies and caprices of the human imagination. The assumption that man is a mainly rational animal has given place to the discovery that he is, like other animals, mainly instinctive. This modifies immensely the attitude of the rationalist—it gives him a new charity and a new tolerance. What seemed like the wilful follies of mad or wicked men to the earlier rationalists are now seen to be inevitable responses to fundamental instinctive needs. By observing mankind the man of science has lost his contempt for him. Now this I think has had an important bearing on the new movement in art. In the first place I find something analogous in the new orientation of scientific and artistic endeavour. Science has turned its instruments in on human nature and begun to investigate its fundamental needs, and art has also turned its vision inwards, has begun to work upon the fundamental necessities of man’s æsthetic functions.
self-confident. It recognizes far greater challenges in depicting its view of the universe than would have occurred to Spencer. The reality is that skepticism has turned inwards and examined many of the principles that seemed obvious to earlier rationalists. I don’t believe it has ever really threatened the foundation of the rationalist position, but it has made us realize the need for constant review and restructuring of this information. Rationalism has become less arrogant and less narrow-minded. This shift is partly due to the exploration of the scientific spirit into new areas. I’m referring to the extensive body of study and speculation that starts with Robertson Smith’s “Religion of the Israelites.” The identification of natural laws in what earlier rationalists viewed as the chaotic whims and fancies of the human mind. The belief that humans are primarily rational beings has shifted to the understanding that we are, like other animals, largely driven by instinct. This greatly changes the rationalist’s perspective—it brings about a new sense of empathy and tolerance. What previously seemed like the reckless actions of insane or immoral individuals to the earlier rationalists are now understood as natural reactions to basic instinctual needs. By studying humanity, the scientist has lost his disdain for it. I believe this has significantly influenced the new movement in art. First, I see a parallel in the new direction of scientific and artistic pursuits. Science has focused its tools on human nature and started to explore its basic needs, and art has also begun to look inward, working on the fundamental requirements of human aesthetic functions.
But besides this analogy, which may be merely accidental and not causal, I think there can be little doubt that the new scientific development (for it is in no sense a revolution) has modified men’s attitude to art. To Herbert Spencer religion was primitive fear of the unknown and art was sexual attraction—he must have contemplated with perfect equanimity, almost with satisfaction, a world in which both these functions would disappear. I suppose that the scientific man of to-day would be much more ready to admit not only the necessity but the great importance of æsthetic feeling for the spiritual existence of man. The general conception of life in the mid-nineteenth century ruled out art as noxious, or at best, a useless{10} frivolity, and above all as a mere survival of more primitive stages of evolution.
But aside from this analogy, which might just be coincidental and not causational, I believe there’s little doubt that the recent scientific advancement (since it’s not a revolution in any way) has changed people’s views on art. To Herbert Spencer, religion was just a primitive fear of the unknown, and art was simply sexual attraction—he must have looked at a world where these two functions vanished with complete calmness, even satisfaction. I think today’s scientists would be much more willing to acknowledge not only the necessity but also the significant importance of aesthetic feeling for the spiritual well-being of humanity. The general perception of life in the mid-nineteenth century dismissed art as harmful or, at best, a pointless frivolity, and, above all, as just a remnant of earlier stages of evolution.{10}
On the other hand, the artist of the new movement is moving into a sphere more and more remote from that of the ordinary man. In proportion as art becomes purer the number of people to whom it appeals gets less. It cuts out all the romantic overtones of life which are the usual bait by which men are induced to accept a work of art. It appeals only to the æsthetic sensibility, and that in most men is comparatively weak.
On the other hand, the artist of the new movement is entering a space that’s increasingly distant from the everyday person. As art becomes more refined, the number of people it resonates with decreases. It eliminates all the romantic elements of life that typically attract people to a piece of art. It appeals only to aesthetic sensibility, which is relatively weak in most people.
In the modern movement in art, then, as in so many cases in past history, the revolution in art seems to be out of all proportion to any corresponding change in life as a whole. It seems to find its sources, if at all, in what at present seem like minor movements. Whether the difference between the nineteenth and twentieth centuries will in retrospect seem as great in life as they already do in art I cannot guess—at least it is curious to note how much more conscious we are of the change in art then we are in the general change in thought and feeling.
In the modern art movement, just like in many moments in history, the changes in art appear to be much greater than any similar changes in life overall. It seems to draw its inspiration, if anywhere, from what currently seem like minor movements. Whether the differences between the nineteenth and twentieth centuries will seem as significant in life as they already do in art, I can't say—it's interesting to observe how much more aware we are of the changes in art than we are of the broader shifts in thought and emotion.
Note.—The original lecture was not illustrated, but the opportunity of publishing this summary of it has suggested the possibility of introducing a few examples to illustrate one point, viz., the extent to which the works of the new movement correspond in aim with the works of early art while being sharply contrasted with those of the penultimate period. This will be, perhaps, most evident in Plate I, where I have placed a figure from the cloisters of S. John Lateran, carved by a thirteenth-century sculptor—then one of Rodin’s Burghers of Calais, and then Matisse’s unfinished alto-rilievo figure. Here there is no need to underline the startling difference shown by Rodin’s descriptive method from the more purely plastic feeling of the two other artists. Matisse and the thirteenth-century artist are much closer together than Matisse and Rodin.
Note.—The original lecture didn't include illustrations, but the chance to publish this summary has inspired me to add a few examples to clarify one point: the extent to which the works of the new movement align with the goals of early art while sharply contrasting with those of the last period. This will be most obvious in Plate I, where I've included a figure from the cloisters of S. John Lateran, carved by a thirteenth-century sculptor—followed by one of Rodin’s Burghers of Calais, and then Matisse’s unfinished alto-rilievo figure. There’s no need to emphasize the striking difference between Rodin’s descriptive method and the more purely plastic approach of the other two artists. Matisse and the thirteenth-century artist are much closer together than Matisse and Rodin.
In Plate II I have placed Picasso beside Raphael. Here the obvious fact is the common preoccupation of both artists with certain problems of plastic design and the similarity of their solutions. Had I had space to put a Sargent beside these the same violent contrast would have been produced.{11}
In Plate II, I positioned Picasso next to Raphael. The clear point is that both artists shared a common focus on specific issues of visual design and their similar approaches to solving them. If I had room to include a Sargent alongside them, it would have created an equally striking contrast.{11}

Raphael. “La Donna Gravida” | Pitti Palace, Florence | Pablo Picasso. Portrait of Miss Gertrude Stein | Miss Gertrude Stein | |
Plate II. |
AN ESSAY IN ÆSTHETICS[2]
A CERTAIN painter, not without some reputation at the present day, once wrote a little book on the art he practises, in which he gave a definition of that art so succinct that I take it as a point of departure for this essay.
A CERTAIN painter, who's somewhat known today, once wrote a short book about the art he practices, in which he provided such a concise definition of that art that I use it as a starting point for this essay.
“The art of painting,” says that eminent authority, “is the art of imitating solid objects upon a flat surface by means of pigments.” It is delightfully simple, but prompts the question—Is that all? And, if so, what a deal of unnecessary fuss has been made about it. Now, it is useless to deny that our modern writer has some very respectable authorities behind him. Plato, indeed, gave a very similar account of the affair, and himself put the question—is it then worth while? And, being scrupulously and relentlessly logical, he decided that it was not worth while, and proceeded to turn the artists out of his ideal republic. For all that, the world has continued obstinately to consider that painting was worth while, and though, indeed, it has never quite made up its mind as to what, exactly, the graphic arts did for it, it has persisted in honouring and admiring its painters.
“The art of painting,” says that well-respected authority, “is the art of imitating solid objects on a flat surface using pigments.” It sounds pretty straightforward, but it raises the question—Is that really all there is to it? And if it is, what a lot of unnecessary fuss has been made about it. Now, it's pointless to deny that our modern writer has some very credible figures supporting him. Plato, in fact, offered a similar perspective on the matter and asked himself—is it really worth it? And, being thoroughly logical, he concluded that it wasn’t worth it and went on to banish artists from his ideal republic. Despite that, the world has stubbornly continued to believe that painting is worthwhile, and while it has never quite figured out what, exactly, the graphic arts contribute, it has consistently honored and admired its painters.
Can we arrive at any conclusions as to the nature of the graphic arts, which will at all explain our feelings about them, which will at least put them into some kind of relation with the other arts, and not leave us in the extreme perplexity, engendered by any theory of mere imitation? For, I suppose, it must be admitted that if imitation is the sole purpose of the graphic arts, it is surprising that the works of such arts are ever looked upon as more than curiosities, or ingenious toys, are ever taken seriously by grown-up people. Moreover, it will be surprising that they have no recognisable affinity with other arts, such as music or architecture, in which the imitation of actual objects is a negligible quantity.
Can we come to any conclusions about the graphic arts that will explain our feelings toward them? Can we at least connect them to other art forms, rather than leaving us confused by any theory that sees them as just imitation? It seems that if imitation is the only goal of the graphic arts, it's odd that people ever view these works as more than curiosities or clever toys, or that adults take them seriously at all. Additionally, it's surprising that they don't have any clear relationship with other arts, like music or architecture, where imitating real objects is hardly a focus.
I must begin with some elementary psychology, with a consideration of the nature of instincts. A great many objects in the world, when presented to our senses, put in motion a complex nervous machinery, which ends in some instinctive appropriate action. We see a wild bull in a field; quite without our conscious interference a nervous process goes on, which, unless we interfere forcibly, ends in the appropriate reaction of flight. The nervous mechanism which results in flight causes a certain state of consciousness, which we call the emotion of fear. The whole of animal life, and a great part of human life, is made up of these instinctive reactions to sensible objects, and their accompanying emotions. But man has the peculiar faculty of calling up again in his mind the echo of past experiences of this kind, of going over it again, “in imagination” as we say. He has, therefore, the possibility of a double life; one the actual life, the other the imaginative life. Between these two lives there is this great distinction, that in the actual life the processes of natural selection have brought it about that the instinctive reaction, such, for instance, as flight from danger, shall be the important part of the whole process, and it is towards this that the man bends his whole conscious endeavour. But in the imaginative life no such action is necessary, and, therefore, the whole consciousness may be focussed upon the perceptive and the emotional aspects of the experience. In this way we get, in the imaginative life, a different set of values, and a different kind of perception.
I need to start with some basic psychology, looking at the nature of instincts. A lot of things in the world, when we sense them, trigger a complex nervous response that leads to some instinctive action. For example, we see a wild bull in a field; without any conscious effort, a nervous process happens that, unless we forcefully step in, ends with the instinctive reaction of running away. The nervous system that causes us to flee creates a certain state of awareness that we call the emotion of fear. All animal life, and a significant part of human life, consists of these instinctive responses to sensory objects and their related emotions. However, humans have the unique ability to recall and reflect on these past experiences in our minds, going over them again “in imagination,” as we say. This gives us the potential for a double life: one that is real and one that is imaginative. The key difference between these two lives is that in real life, natural selection has made the instinctive reaction, like fleeing from danger, a crucial part of the process, and this is where a person directs their full conscious effort. In imaginative life, no such reaction is needed, so the entire consciousness can focus on the perception and emotional sides of the experience. This way, we get a different set of values and a different type of perception in our imaginative life.
We can get a curious side glimpse of the nature of this imaginative life from the cinematograph. This resembles actual life in almost every respect, except that what the psychologists call the conative part of our reaction to sensations, that is to say, the appropriate resultant action is cut off. If, in a cinematograph, we see a runaway horse and cart, we do not have to think either of getting out of the way or heroically interposing ourselves. The result is that in the first place we see the event much more clearly; see a number of quite interesting but irrelevant things, which in real life could not struggle into our consciousness, bent, as it would be, entirely upon the problem of our appropriate reaction. I remember seeing in a cinematograph the arrival of a train at a foreign station and the people descending from the carriages; there was no platform, and to my{13} intense surprise I saw several people turn right round after reaching the ground, as though to orientate themselves; an almost ridiculous performance, which I had never noticed in all the many hundred occasions on which such a scene had passed before my eyes in real life. The fact being that at a station one is never really a spectator of events, but an actor engaged in the drama of luggage or prospective seats, and one actually sees only so much as may help to the appropriate action.
We can get an interesting glimpse into the nature of this imaginative experience through film. It resembles real life in almost every way, except that what psychologists refer to as the conative part of our reaction to sensations—the appropriate resulting action—is missing. For example, when we see a runaway horse and cart in a movie, we don’t have to think about dodging it or stepping in heroically. As a result, we first see the event much more clearly; we notice several intriguing but irrelevant things that would not enter our minds in real life, where we are focused entirely on how to react appropriately. I remember watching a film of a train arriving at a foreign station and people getting off the carriages; there was no platform, and to my intense surprise, I saw several people turn around right after stepping off, as if to orient themselves—an almost silly action that I had never noticed during the hundreds of times I had witnessed such a scene in real life. The truth is, at a station, you’re never just a spectator; you’re an actor caught up in the drama of managing luggage or finding seats, and you truly see only as much as is necessary for the appropriate action.
In the second place, with regard to the visions of the cinematograph, one notices that whatever emotions are aroused by them, though they are likely to be weaker than those of ordinary life, are presented more clearly to the consciousness. If the scene presented be one of an accident, our pity and horror, though weak, since we know that no one is really hurt, are felt quite purely, since they cannot, as they would in life, pass at once into actions of assistance.
In the second place, when it comes to the images shown by the cinema, we see that any emotions they evoke—although they might be less intense than those in real life—are presented more clearly to our minds. If the scene is one of an accident, our feelings of sympathy and horror, although mild because we know no one is actually hurt, are experienced more purely since they can't immediately turn into actions of help, as they would in real life.
A somewhat similar effect to that of the cinematograph can be obtained by watching a mirror in which a street scene is reflected. If we look at the street itself we are almost sure to adjust ourselves in some way to its actual existence. We recognise an acquaintance, and wonder why he looks so dejected this morning, or become interested in a new fashion in hats—the moment we do that the spell is broken, we are reacting to life itself in however slight a degree, but, in the mirror, it is easier to abstract ourselves completely, and look upon the changing scene as a whole. It then, at once, takes on the visionary quality, and we become true spectators, not selecting what we will see, but seeing everything equally, and thereby we come to notice a number of appearances and relations of appearances, which would have escaped our vision before, owing to that perpetual economising by selection of what impressions we will assimilate, which in life we perform by unconscious processes. The frame of the mirror then, does, to some extent, turn the reflected scene from one that belongs to our actual life into one that belongs rather to the imaginative life. The frame of the mirror makes its surface into a very rudimentary work of art, since it helps us to attain to the artistic vision. For that is what, as you will already have guessed, I have been coming to all this time, namely that the work of art is intimately connected{14} with the secondary imaginative life, which all men live to a greater or lesser extent.
A similar effect to that of the cinematograph can be achieved by watching a mirror that reflects a street scene. If we look at the street itself, we're likely to adjust ourselves to its reality. We might recognize someone we know and wonder why they seem so down today or become intrigued by a new hat trend—once we do that, the spell is broken, and we're responding to life itself, even if just a little. But in the mirror, it's easier to completely disconnect and view the changing scene as a whole. It then takes on a dreamy quality, and we become true spectators, not choosing what to see but noticing everything equally, allowing us to notice various details and connections that we might have missed before. This is because we constantly filter our impressions in real life, often without realizing it. The frame of the mirror, then, somewhat transforms the reflected scene from something that’s part of our actual life into something that belongs to our imaginative life. The mirror's frame turns its surface into a basic form of art since it helps us achieve an artistic perspective. For, as you might have guessed by now, I've been leading up to the idea that a work of art is closely linked to the secondary imaginative life, which everyone experiences to varying degrees.{14}
That the graphic arts are the expression of the imaginative life rather than a copy of actual life might be guessed from observing children. Children, if left to themselves, never, I believe, copy what they see, never, as we say, “draw from nature,” but express, with a delightful freedom and sincerity, the mental images which make up their own imaginative lives.
The graphic arts reflect our creative spirit rather than just replicating real life, which you can see by watching children. If kids are allowed to be themselves, they don't really copy what they see; they don't, as we might say, "draw from nature." Instead, they express, in a charmingly free and honest way, the mental images that shape their own imaginative worlds.
Art, then, is an expression and a stimulus of this imaginative life, which is separated from actual life by the absence of responsive action. Now this responsive action implies in actual life moral responsibility. In art we have no such moral responsibility—it presents a life freed from the binding necessities of our actual existence.
Art, then, is a way to express and inspire our imaginative life, which is distinct from real life due to the lack of responsive action. This responsive action in real life suggests moral responsibility. In art, there’s no such moral obligation—it offers a life unbound by the demands of our everyday existence.
What then is the justification for this life of the imagination which all human beings live more or less fully? To the pure moralist, who accepts nothing but ethical values, in order to be justified, it must be shown not only not to hinder but actually to forward right action, otherwise it is not only useless but, since it absorbs our energies, positively harmful. To such a one two views are possible, one the Puritanical view at its narrowest, which regards the life of the imagination as no better or worse than a life of sensual pleasure, and therefore entirely reprehensible. The other view is to argue that the imaginative life does subserve morality. And this is inevitably the view taken by moralists like Ruskin, to whom the imaginative life is yet an absolute necessity. It is a view which leads to some very hard special pleading, even to a self-deception which is in itself morally undesirable.
What, then, justifies this life of imagination that all human beings experience to varying degrees? For the strict moralist, who values only ethical principles, it must be shown not only to not interfere but actually to support right actions; otherwise, it’s not just useless but also, since it drains our energy, potentially harmful. For such individuals, there are two possible perspectives: one is the narrow Puritanical view that sees the life of imagination as nothing better or worse than a life of physical pleasure, making it completely unacceptable. The other perspective argues that the imaginative life does, in fact, support morality. This is the position taken by moralists like Ruskin, who believe that the imaginative life is an absolute necessity. This view can lead to some intense arguments and even self-deception, which is morally undesirable in itself.
But here comes in the question of religion, for religion is also an affair of the imaginative life, and, though it claims to have a direct effect upon conduct, I do not suppose that the religious person if he were wise would justify religion entirely by its effect on morality, since that, historically speaking, has not been by any means uniformly advantageous. He would probably say that the religious experience was one which corresponded to certain spiritual capacities of human nature, the exercise of which is in itself good and desirable apart from their effect upon actual life. And so, too, I think the artist might if he chose take a mystical attitude, and declare that the fullness and completeness of the imaginative life he leads may correspond to{15} an existence more real and more important than any that we know of in mortal life.
But this brings up the question of religion, since religion is also part of our imaginative lives, and while it claims to have a direct impact on our behavior, I don’t think a wise religious person would fully justify religion solely based on its influence on morality, as historically, that hasn't always been beneficial. They might argue that the religious experience aligns with certain spiritual aspects of human nature, and that engaging with these aspects is valuable and positive, regardless of how they impact real life. Similarly, I believe an artist could adopt a mystical perspective, claiming that the richness and fullness of the imaginative life they lead may connect to an existence that is more real and significant than any we experience in our mortal lives.
And in saying that, his appeal would find a sympathetic echo in most minds, for most people would, I think, say that the pleasures derived from art were of an altogether different character and more fundamental than merely sensual pleasures, that they did exercise some faculties which are felt to belong to whatever part of us there may be which is not entirely ephemeral and material.
And by saying that, his argument would resonate with many people, because most folks would likely agree that the joys we get from art are of a different nature and more essential than just physical pleasures. They engage certain abilities that are connected to the deeper part of us that isn't just temporary and material.
It might even be that from this point of view we should rather justify actual life by its relation to the imaginative, justify nature by its likeness to art. I mean this, that since the imaginative life comes in the course of time to represent more or less what mankind feels to be the completest expression of its own nature, the freest use of its innate capacities, the actual life may be explained and justified in its approximation here and there, however partially and inadequately, to that freer and fuller life.
It might even be that from this perspective we should justify real life by how it relates to the imaginative, and justify nature by how it resembles art. What I mean is that since the imaginative life eventually comes to represent what people feel is the fullest expression of their own nature and the most complete use of their inherent abilities, real life can be explained and justified by how it, in some ways and to some extent, comes close to that freer and fuller life.
Before leaving this question of the justification of art, let me put it in another way. The imaginative life of a people has very different levels at different times, and these levels do not always correspond with the general level of the morality of actual life. Thus in the thirteenth century we read of barbarity and cruelty which would shock even us; we may I think admit that our moral level, our general humanity is decidedly higher to-day, but the level of our imaginative life is incomparably lower; we are satisfied there with a grossness, a sheer barbarity and squalor which would have shocked the thirteenth century profoundly. Let us admit the moral gain gladly, but do we not also feel a loss; do we not feel that the average business man would be in every way a more admirable, more respectable being if his imaginative life were not so squalid and incoherent? And, if we admit any loss then, there is some function in human nature other than a purely ethical one, which is worthy of exercise.
Before leaving this question about the justification of art, let me rephrase it. The creative life of a society has different levels at different times, and these levels don’t always align with the general standard of morality in real life. For example, in the thirteenth century, there were acts of barbarity and cruelty that would still shock us today; we can agree that our moral standards and general humanity are significantly higher now. However, the level of our creative expression is incredibly lower; we’re often okay with a coarseness, a sheer barbarity and filth that would have deeply shocked people in the thirteenth century. We should gladly acknowledge the moral progress, but don’t we also feel a loss? Don’t we think that the average businessperson would be a more admirable, more respectable person if their creative life weren’t so sordid and disjointed? If we acknowledge any loss, then there must be some aspect of human nature that goes beyond just ethical considerations and deserves to be nurtured.
Now the imaginative life has its own history both in the race and in the individual. In the individual life one of the first effects of freeing experience from the necessities of appropriate responsive action is to indulge recklessly the emotion of self-aggrandisement. The day-dreams of a child are filled with extravagant romances in which he is always the invincible hero. Music—which of all the arts{16} supplies the strongest stimulus to the imaginative life, and at the same time has the least power of controlling its direction—music, at certain stages of people’s lives, has the effect merely of arousing in an almost absurd degree this egoistic elation, and Tolstoy appears to believe that this is its only possible effect. But with the teaching of experience and the growth of character the imaginative life comes to respond to other instincts and to satisfy other desires, until, indeed, it reflects the highest aspirations and the deepest aversions of which human nature is capable.
Now, the imaginative life has its own history both in humanity and in individuals. In a person's life, one of the first results of freeing experiences from the need for appropriate responses is to recklessly indulge in the emotion of self-importance. A child's daydreams are filled with extravagant fantasies where they are always the unbeatable hero. Music—which of all the arts{16} provides the strongest boost to the imaginative life, yet has the least power to direct it—at certain stages in people's lives, often only serves to provoke an almost ridiculous level of this self-centered excitement, and Tolstoy seems to believe that this is its only possible effect. But with life experiences and personal growth, the imaginative life starts to respond to other instincts and satisfy different desires, eventually reflecting the highest aspirations and deepest aversions that human nature can experience.
In dreams and when under the influence of drugs the imaginative life passes out of our own control, and in such cases its experiences may be highly undesirable, but whenever it remains under our own control it must always be on the whole a desirable life. That is not to say that it is always pleasant, for it is pretty clear that mankind is so constituted as to desire much besides pleasure, and we shall meet among the great artists, the great exponents, that is, of the imaginative life, many to whom the merely pleasant is very rarely a part of what is desirable. But this desirability of the imaginative life does distinguish it very sharply from actual life, and is the direct result of that first fundamental difference, its freedom from necessary external conditions. Art, then, is, if I am right, the chief organ of the imaginative life, it is by art that it is stimulated and controlled within us, and, as we have seen, the imaginative life is distinguished by the greater clearness of its perception, and the greater purity and freedom of its emotion.
In dreams and when under the influence of drugs, our imaginative life goes beyond our control, and in those instances, the experiences can be quite undesirable. However, when it stays under our control, it is generally a positive experience. That doesn't mean it's always enjoyable, because humans naturally seek more than just pleasure. Among great artists—those who truly embody the imaginative life—many find that simple pleasure is seldom what they desire. This appeal of the imaginative life sets it apart from real life and comes directly from its fundamental freedom from external constraints. Thus, art is, if I'm correct, the primary avenue for the imaginative life; it stimulates and regulates it within us. As we've noted, the imaginative life is characterized by sharper perception and more pure, unrestrained emotions.
First with regard to the greater clearness of perception. The needs of our actual life are so imperative, that the sense of vision becomes highly specialised in their service. With an admirable economy we learn to see only so much as is needful for our purposes; but this is in fact very little, just enough to recognise and identify each object or person; that done, they go into an entry in our mental catalogue and are no more really seen. In actual life the normal person really only reads the labels as it were on the objects around him and troubles no further. Almost all the things which are useful in any way put on more or less this cap of invisibility. It is only when an object exists in our lives for no other purpose than to be seen that we really look at it, as for instance at a China ornament or a precious{17} stone, and towards such even the most normal person adopts to some extent the artistic attitude of pure vision abstracted from necessity.
First, regarding the increased clarity of perception. The demands of our everyday life are so crucial that our sense of sight becomes highly specialized to meet them. With impressive efficiency, we learn to see only what’s necessary for our purposes; however, this is actually very little—just enough to recognize and identify each object or person. Once that’s done, they get filed away in our mental catalog and are no longer truly seen. In everyday life, the average person mostly just reads the labels on the objects around them and doesn’t pay much more attention. Almost everything that serves a purpose wears this cloak of invisibility. We only truly look at something when it exists in our lives solely to be seen, like a china ornament or a precious{17} stone, and even then, the most typical person adopts a bit of an artistic mindset, viewing it as something to appreciate rather than just a necessity.
Now this specialisation of vision goes so far that ordinary people have almost no idea of what things really look like, so that oddly enough the one standard that popular criticism applies to painting, namely, whether it is like nature or not, is one which most people are, by the whole tenour of their lives, prevented from applying properly. The only things they have ever really looked at being other pictures; the moment an artist who has looked at nature brings to them a clear report of something definitely seen by him, they are wildly indignant at its untruth to nature. This has happened so constantly in our own time that there is no need to prove it. One instance will suffice. Monet is an artist whose chief claim to recognition lies in the fact of his astonishing power of faithfully reproducing certain aspects of nature, but his really naïve innocence and sincerity was taken by the public to be the most audacious humbug, and it required the teaching of men like Bastien-Lepage, who cleverly compromised between the truth and an accepted convention of what things looked like, to bring the world gradually round to admitting truths which a single walk in the country with purely unbiassed vision would have established beyond doubt.
Now this specialization of vision has reached a point where ordinary people have almost no idea what things actually look like. Strangely enough, the one standard that popular criticism uses to evaluate painting—whether it resembles nature or not—is something most people are, throughout their lives, unable to apply correctly. The only things they’ve really looked at are other pictures; the moment an artist who has observed nature presents them with a clear depiction of something he has seen, they become outrageously upset at its perceived inaccuracy to nature. This has happened so frequently in our time that no proof is needed. One example will suffice. Monet is an artist whose main credit lies in his incredible ability to faithfully reproduce certain aspects of nature, but his genuine innocence and honesty were seen by the public as the most outrageous deception. It took the influence of people like Bastien-Lepage, who cleverly navigated between truth and accepted conventions of appearance, to gradually lead the world to acknowledge truths that a simple walk in the countryside with an unbiased perspective would have confirmed beyond doubt.
But though this clarified sense perception which we discover in the imaginative life is of great interest, and although it plays a larger part in the graphic arts than in any other, it might perhaps be doubted whether, interesting, curious, fascinating as it is, this aspect of the imaginative life would ever by itself make art of profound importance to mankind. But it is different, I think, with the emotional aspect. We have admitted that the emotions of the imaginative are generally weaker than those of actual life. The picture of a saint being slowly flayed alive, revolting as it is, will not produce the actual physical sensations of sickening disgust that a modern man would feel if he could assist at the actual event; but they have a compensating clearness of presentment to the consciousness. The more poignant emotions of actual life have, I think, a kind of numbing effect analogous to the paralysing influence of fear in some animals; but even if this experience be not generally admitted, all will admit that the need for responsive action hurries us along and prevents us from ever realising{18} fully what the emotion is that we feel, from co-ordinating it perfectly with other states. In short, the motives we actually experience are too close to us to enable us to feel them clearly. They are in a sense unintelligible. In the imaginative life, on the contrary, we can both feel the emotion and watch it. When we are really moved at the theatre we are always both on the stage and in the auditorium.
But even though this clear sense perception that we find in the imaginative life is really interesting, and while it plays a bigger role in visual arts than in any other area, one might wonder if, no matter how intriguing and captivating it is, this aspect of the imaginative life alone could ever make art truly important to humanity. However, I believe the emotional aspect is different. We’ve acknowledged that the emotions in imaginative works are generally less intense than those in real life. The image of a saint being slowly flayed alive, disturbing as it is, won’t evoke the actual physical sensations of deep disgust that a modern person would feel if they witnessed the real event; but it does have a clear presence in our awareness. The more intense emotions of real life can have a numbing effect, similar to how fear can paralyze some animals; but even if not everyone agrees with this experience, it’s clear that the need for immediate response rushes us along and keeps us from ever fully understanding what the emotion we feel is, and from perfectly connecting it with other feelings. In short, the motivations we actually experience are too immediate for us to grasp them clearly. They’re somewhat unintelligible. In contrast, in the imaginative life, we can both feel the emotion and observe it. When we are genuinely moved in the theater, we are always both on stage and in the audience.
Yet another point about the emotions of the imaginative life—since they require no responsive action we can give them a new valuation. In real life we must to some extent cultivate those emotions which lead to useful action, and we are bound to appraise emotions according to the resultant action. So that, for instance, the feelings of rivalry and emulation do get an encouragement which perhaps they scarcely deserve, whereas certain feelings which appear to have a high intrinsic value get almost no stimulus in actual life. For instance, those feelings to which the name of the cosmic emotion has been somewhat unhappily given find almost no place in life, but, since they seem to belong to certain very deep springs of our nature, do become of great importance in the arts.
Another aspect of the emotions tied to imaginative life is that, since they don't require a specific action in response, we can reevaluate their value. In our everyday lives, we tend to nurture emotions that lead to practical outcomes, and we judge emotions based on the actions they produce. For example, emotions like rivalry and competition receive more encouragement than they might actually warrant, while certain feelings that seem to hold significant intrinsic value often get very little recognition in real life. Take the emotions referred to as cosmic emotion; they find little place in daily life, but because they tap into some of our deepest instincts, they become extremely important in the arts.
Morality, then, appreciates emotion by the standard of resultant action. Art appreciates emotion in and for itself.
Morality values emotion based on the actions that result from it. Art values emotion for its own sake.
This view of the essential importance in art of the expression of the emotions is the basis of Tolstoy’s marvellously original and yet perverse and even exasperating book, “What is Art,” and I willingly confess, while disagreeing with almost all his results, how much I owe to him.
This perspective on the crucial role of expressing emotions in art forms the foundation of Tolstoy’s incredibly original, yet contradictory and often frustrating book, “What is Art.” I admit, despite disagreeing with most of his conclusions, I owe him a lot.
He gives an example of what he means by calling art the means of communicating emotions. He says, let us suppose a boy to have been pursued in the forest by a bear. If he returns to the village and merely states that he was pursued by a bear and escaped, that is ordinary language, the means of communicating facts or ideas; but if he describes his state first of heedlessness, then of sudden alarm and terror as the bear appears, and finally of relief when he gets away, and describes this so that his hearers share his emotions, then his description is a work of art.
He gives an example of what he means by calling art the way to communicate emotions. He says, let's imagine a boy being chased by a bear in the forest. If he comes back to the village and just says that he was chased by a bear and managed to escape, that's plain language, just conveying facts or ideas; but if he shares how he felt first carefree, then suddenly scared and terrified when the bear showed up, and finally relieved when he got away, and conveys this in a way that lets his listeners feel his emotions, then his story is a work of art.
Now in so far as the boy does this in order to urge the villagers to go out and kill the bear, though he may be using artistic methods, his speech is not a pure work of art; but if of a winter evening the boy{19} relates his experience for the sake of the enjoyment of his adventure in retrospect, or better still, if he makes up the whole story for the sake of the imagined emotions, then his speech becomes a pure work of art. But Tolstoy takes the other view, and values the emotions aroused by art entirely for their reaction upon actual life, a view which he courageously maintains even when it leads him to condemn the whole of Michelangelo, Raphael and Titian, and most of Beethoven, not to mention nearly everything he himself has written, as bad or false art.
Now, when the boy does this to encourage the villagers to go out and kill the bear, even if he’s using artistic methods, his speech isn’t a pure work of art. However, if on a winter evening the boy{19} shares his experience just to enjoy looking back on his adventure, or even better, if he creates the whole story to evoke imagined emotions, then his speech becomes a pure work of art. But Tolstoy sees it differently; he values the emotions stirred by art solely for their impact on real life, a perspective he boldly upholds even when it leads him to criticize the works of Michelangelo, Raphael, Titian, and most of Beethoven, not to mention much of his own writing, as bad or misguided art.
Such a view would, I think, give pause to any less heroic spirit. He would wonder whether mankind could have always been so radically wrong about a function that, whatever its value be, is almost universal. And in point of fact he will have to find some other word to denote what we now call art. Nor does Tolstoy’s theory even carry him safely through his own book, since, in his examples of morally desirable and therefore good art, he has to admit that these are to be found, for the most part, among works of inferior quality. Here, then, is at once the tacit admission that another standard than morality is applicable. We must therefore give up the attempt to judge the work of art by its reaction on life, and consider it as an expression of emotions regarded as ends in themselves. And this brings us back to the idea we had already arrived at, of art as the expression of the imaginative life.
Such a viewpoint would likely make any less heroic person hesitate. They would question whether humanity has always been so fundamentally mistaken about a purpose that, regardless of its worth, is almost universal. In fact, they would need to find a different term to describe what we now refer to as art. Additionally, Tolstoy’s theory doesn’t hold up in his own work, since in his examples of morally desirable and therefore good art, he has to admit that most of these are found among works of lower quality. This is, in itself, a silent acknowledgment that a standard other than morality applies. Therefore, we must abandon the attempt to evaluate art by its impact on life and instead regard it as an expression of emotions that are seen as valuable in their own right. This brings us back to the idea we have already reached, of art as the expression of the imaginative life.
If, then, an object of any kind is created by man not for use, for its fitness to actual life, but as an object of art, an object subserving the imaginative life, what will its qualities be? It must in the first place be adapted to that disinterested intensity of contemplation, which we have found to be the result of cutting off the responsive action. It must be suited to that heightened power of perception which we found to result therefrom.
If an object is created by humans not for practical use or its utility in real life, but as a work of art meant to serve the imaginative experience, what qualities will it have? First, it needs to be designed for that intense, uninterested contemplation that we’ve identified as a result of removing reactive engagement. It must also support the increased ability to perceive that comes from that.
And the first quality that we demand in our sensations will be order, without which our sensations will be troubled and perplexed, and the other quality will be variety, without which they will not be fully stimulated.
And the first quality we expect from our sensations is order, without which our sensations will be confused and frustrating, and the other quality is variety, without which they won't be completely engaged.
It may be objected that many things in nature, such as flowers, possess these two qualities of order and variety in a high degree, and these objects do undoubtedly stimulate and satisfy that clear{20} disinterested contemplation which is characteristic of the æsthetic attitude. But in our reaction to a work of art there is something more—there is the consciousness of purpose, the consciousness of a peculiar relation of sympathy with the man who made this thing in order to arouse precisely the sensations we experience. And when we come to the higher works of art, where sensations are so arranged that they arouse in us deep emotions, this feeling of a special tie with the man who expressed them becomes very strong. We feel that he has expressed something which was latent in us all the time, but which we never realised, that he has revealed us to ourselves in revealing himself. And this recognition of purpose is, I believe, an essential part of the æsthetic judgment proper.
It might be argued that many things in nature, like flowers, have a strong sense of order and variety, and these things do indeed inspire and satisfy that clear, disinterested contemplation that is typical of the aesthetic attitude. However, in our response to a work of art, there’s something more—there’s an awareness of intention, a sense of a unique connection with the person who created this work to evoke exactly the feelings we experience. And when we look at the more profound works of art, where sensations are arranged to provoke deep emotions in us, this sense of a special bond with the creator becomes very powerful. We feel that the artist has expressed something that was always within us, but that we never recognized, that he has helped us discover ourselves by revealing himself. This awareness of purpose is, in my view, a crucial aspect of the aesthetic judgment itself.
The perception of purposeful order and variety in an object gives us the feeling which we express by saying that it is beautiful, but when by means of sensations our emotions are aroused we demand purposeful order and variety in them also, and if this can only be brought about by the sacrifice of sensual beauty we willingly overlook its absence.
The way we recognize intentional order and diversity in something makes us feel that it's beautiful. However, when our emotions are stirred through our senses, we also expect that same sense of order and diversity from those feelings. If achieving this requires giving up some of that sensual beauty, we're often okay with ignoring its lack.
Thus, there is no excuse for a china pot being ugly, there is every reason why Rembrandt’s and Degas’ pictures should be, from the purely sensual point of view, supremely and magnificently ugly.
Thus, there’s no excuse for a china pot to be unattractive; there are plenty of reasons why Rembrandt’s and Degas’ paintings should, from a purely sensual perspective, be utterly and strikingly ugly.
This, I think, will explain the apparent contradiction between two distinct uses of the word beauty, one for that which has sensuous charm, and one for the æsthetic approval of works of imaginative art where the objects presented to us are often of extreme ugliness. Beauty in the former sense belongs to works of art where only the perceptual aspect of the imaginative life is exercised, beauty in the second sense becomes as it were supersensual, and is concerned with the appropriateness and intensity of the emotions aroused. When these emotions are aroused in a way that satisfies fully the needs of the imaginative life we approve and delight in the sensations through which we enjoy that heightened experience, because they possess purposeful order and variety in relation to those emotions.
I believe this will clarify the seeming contradiction between two different uses of the word "beauty." One refers to things that have a sensuous appeal, while the other relates to the aesthetic appreciation of imaginative art, where the subjects presented can often be very ugly. In the first sense, beauty applies to artworks that engage only the perceptual aspects of the imaginative experience. In the second sense, beauty becomes almost beyond the senses and focuses on the relevance and intensity of the emotions stirred up. When these emotions are triggered in a way that fully meets the needs of our imaginative experience, we appreciate and enjoy the sensations that come from that heightened experience, since they have a purposeful structure and variety connected to those emotions.
In a picture this unity is due to a balancing of the attractions to the eye about the central line of the picture. The result of this balance of attractions is that the eye rests willingly within the bounds of the picture. Dr. Denman Ross of Harvard University has made a most valuable study of the elementary considerations upon which this balance is based in his “Theory of Pure Design.” He sums up his results in the formula that a composition is of value in proportion to the number of orderly connections which it displays.
In a picture, this unity comes from balancing the visual attractions around the central line of the image. This balance allows the eye to comfortably settle within the edges of the picture. Dr. Denman Ross from Harvard University has conducted an important study on the basic elements that support this balance in his “Theory of Pure Design.” He summarizes his findings with the idea that a composition is valuable in relation to the number of organized connections it shows.
Dr. Ross wisely restricts himself to the study of abstract and meaningless forms. The moment representation is introduced forms have an entirely new set of values. Thus a line which indicated the sudden bend of a head in a certain direction would have far more than its mere value as line in the composition because of the attraction which a marked gesture has for the eye. In almost all paintings this disturbance of the purely decorative values by reason of the representative effect takes place, and the problem becomes too complex for geometrical proof.
Dr. Ross smartly sticks to studying abstract and meaningless shapes. The moment you introduce representation, these shapes gain a completely new set of values. For example, a line that shows the quick tilt of a head in one direction carries much more significance than just being a line in the composition, thanks to the way a noticeable gesture catches the eye. In nearly all paintings, this disruption of purely decorative values due to the representational effect happens, making the problem too complicated for geometric proof.
This merely decorative unity is, moreover, of very different degrees of intensity in different artists and in different periods. The necessity for a closely woven geometrical texture in the composition is much greater in heroic and monumental design than in genre pieces on a small scale.
This decorative unity varies significantly in intensity among different artists and across different time periods. The need for a tightly woven geometric structure in the composition is much more important in heroic and monumental designs than in smaller genre pieces.
It seems also probable that our appreciation of unity in pictorial design is of two kinds. We are so accustomed to consider only the unity which results from the balance of a number of attractions presented to the eye simultaneously in a framed picture that we forget the possibility of other pictorial forms.
It also seems likely that our understanding of unity in visual design comes in two forms. We’re so used to thinking about the unity created by balancing several visual elements presented at the same time in a framed image that we overlook the possibility of other visual styles.
In certain Chinese paintings the length is so great that we cannot take in the whole picture at once, nor are we intended to do so. Sometimes a landscape is painted upon a roll of silk so long that we can only look at it in successive segments. As we unroll it at one end and roll it up at the other we traverse wide stretches of country, tracing, perhaps, all the vicissitudes of a river from its source to the sea, and yet, when this is well done, we have received a very keen impression of pictorial unity.
In some Chinese paintings, the length is so extensive that we can't see the entire picture at once, and that's intentional. Sometimes, a landscape is painted on a roll of silk that's so long that we can only view it in sections. As we unroll it from one end and roll it up at the other, we move through vast areas, following the journey of a river from its source to the sea, and if done well, we still get a strong sense of artistic unity.
Such a successive unity is of course familiar to us in literature and music, and it plays its part in the graphic arts. It depends upon{22} the forms being presented to us in such a sequence that each successive element is felt to have a fundamental and harmonious relation with that which preceded it. I suggest that in looking at drawings our sense of pictorial unity is largely of this nature; we feel, if the drawing be a good one, that each modulation of the line as our eye passes along it gives order and variety to our sensations. Such a drawing may be almost entirely lacking in the geometrical balance which we are accustomed to demand in paintings, and yet have, in a remarkable degree, unity.
Such a continuous unity is definitely something we're used to seeing in literature and music, and it also plays a role in visual arts. It relies on the forms being presented to us in a way that makes each element feel fundamentally and harmoniously related to what came before it. I propose that when we look at drawings, our sense of pictorial unity is mostly shaped by this idea; we sense, if the drawing is well done, that each change in the line as our eye moves along it brings order and variety to our feelings. A drawing like this might lack the geometric balance we typically expect in paintings, yet it can still have a remarkable sense of unity.
Let us now see how the artist passes from the stage of merely gratifying our demand for sensuous order and variety to that where he arouses our emotions. I will call the various methods by which this is effected, the emotional elements of design.
Let’s now explore how the artist moves from simply satisfying our need for visual harmony and diversity to a point where they evoke our emotions. I will refer to the different ways this is achieved as the emotional elements of design.
The first element is that of the rhythm of the line with which the forms are delineated.
The first element is the rhythm of the line used to outline the shapes.
The drawn line is the record of a gesture, and that gesture is modified by the artist’s feeling which is thus communicated to us directly.
The drawn line captures a gesture, and that gesture is influenced by the artist's emotions, which are communicated to us directly.
The second element is mass. When an object is so represented that we recognise it as having inertia we feel its power of resisting movement, or communicating its own movement to other bodies, and our imaginative reaction to such an image is governed by our experience of mass in actual life.
The second element is mass. When we see an object and recognize it as having inertia, we sense its ability to resist movement or to transfer its movement to other objects. Our mental response to this image is shaped by our real-life experiences with mass.
The third element is space. The same sized square on two pieces of paper can be made by very simple means to appear to represent either a cube two or three inches high, or a cube of hundreds of feet, and our reaction to it is proportionately changed.
The third element is space. The same-sized square on two pieces of paper can be easily made to seem like either a cube that's two or three inches tall, or a cube that’s hundreds of feet in size, and our reaction to it changes accordingly.
The fourth element is that of light and shade. Our feelings towards the same object become totally different according as we see it strongly illuminated against a black background or dark against light.
The fourth element is light and shadow. Our feelings about the same object can change completely depending on whether we see it brightly lit against a dark background or dark against bright light.
A fifth element is that of colour. That this has a direct emotional effect is evident from such words as gay, dull, melancholy in relation to colour.
A fifth element is color. It's clear that color has a direct emotional impact, as seen in words like bright, dull, and sad when referring to color.
Now it will be noticed that nearly all these emotional elements of design are connected with essential conditions of our physical existence: rhythm appeals to all the sensations which accompany muscular activity; mass to all the infinite adaptations to the force of gravity which we are forced to make; the spatial judgment is equally profound and universal in its application to life; our feeling about inclined planes is connected with our necessary judgments about the conformation of the earth itself; light, again, is so necessary a condition of our existence that we become intensely sensitive to changes in its intensity. Colour is the only one of our elements which is not of critical or universal importance to life, and its emotional effect is neither so deep nor so clearly determined as the others. It will be seen, then, that the graphic arts arouse emotions in us by playing upon what one may call the overtones of some of our primary physical needs. They have, indeed, this great advantage over poetry, that they can appeal more directly and immediately to the emotional accompaniments of our bare physical existence.
Now you'll notice that almost all these emotional aspects of design are tied to the basic conditions of our physical lives: rhythm resonates with all the sensations that come with muscle activity; mass relates to the countless adjustments we have to make to the force of gravity; our sense of space is deeply rooted and universally relevant to our experiences; our feelings about slopes are linked to our essential judgments about the shape of the earth itself; light is such a vital part of our existence that we become highly sensitive to changes in its intensity. Color is the only element that isn’t crucial or universally significant to life, and its emotional impact isn’t as profound or clearly defined as the others. So, it’s clear that the graphic arts evoke emotions in us by tapping into what can be called the overtones of some of our primary physical needs. They have, in fact, a significant advantage over poetry, as they can appeal more directly and immediately to the emotional aspects of our basic physical existence.
If we represent these various elements in simple diagrammatic terms, this effect upon the emotions is, it must be confessed, very weak. Rhythm of line, for instance, is incomparably weaker in its stimulus of the muscular sense than is rhythm addressed to the ear in music, and such diagrams can at best arouse only faint ghost-like echoes of emotions of differing qualities; but when these emotional elements are combined with the presentation of natural appearances, above all with the appearance of the human body, we find that this effect is indefinitely heightened.
If we represent these different elements in simple diagrams, it's clear that their effect on emotions is, to be honest, quite weak. For example, the rhythm of lines is far less stimulating to our body's muscles compared to the rhythm we experience through music. These diagrams can at best evoke only faint, ghost-like echoes of various emotions; however, when these emotional elements are combined with natural appearances, especially the human body, we see that this effect is significantly amplified.
When, for instance, we look at Michelangelo’s “Jeremiah,” and realise the irresistible momentum his movements would have, we experience powerful sentiments of reverence and awe. Or when we look at Michelangelo’s “Tondo” in the Uffizi, and find a group of figures so arranged that the planes have a sequence comparable in breadth and dignity to the mouldings of the earth mounting by clearly-felt gradations to an overtopping summit, innumerable instinctive reactions are brought into play.[3]
When we look at Michelangelo’s “Jeremiah,” we can feel the strong energy behind his movements, which fills us with deep respect and awe. Or when we examine Michelangelo’s “Tondo” in the Uffizi and notice the way the figures are positioned, creating a flow that’s as broad and dignified as the layers of the earth rising in clear stages to a towering peak, we have a multitude of instinctive reactions. [3]
At this point the adversary (as Leonardi da Vinci calls him) is likely enough to retort, “You have abstracted from natural forms a number of so-called emotional elements which you yourself admit are very weak when stated with diagrammatic purity; you then put them back, with the help of Michelangelo, into the natural forms whence they were derived, and at once they have value, so that after all it appears that the natural forms contain these emotional elements ready made up for us, and all that art need do is to imitate Nature.”
At this point, the opponent (as Leonardo da Vinci refers to him) is likely to respond, “You’ve taken some emotional elements from natural forms, which you admit are pretty weak when presented in a purely diagrammatic way; then you reinsert them, with Michelangelo’s help, into the natural forms they came from, and suddenly they have value. So it seems like the natural forms already have these emotional elements built-in for us, and all art really needs to do is imitate Nature.”
But, alas! Nature is heartlessly indifferent to the needs of the imaginative life; God causes His rain to fall upon the just and upon the unjust. The sun neglects to provide the appropriate limelight effect even upon a triumphant Napoleon or a dying Cæsar.[4] Assuredly we have no guarantee that in nature the emotional elements will be combined appropriately with the demands of the imaginative life, and it is, I think, the great occupation of the graphic arts to give us first of all order and variety in the sensuous plane, and then so to arrange the sensuous presentment of objects that the emotional elements are elicited with an order and appropriateness altogether beyond what Nature herself provides.
But, unfortunately! Nature is completely indifferent to the needs of creative life; God makes His rain fall on both the just and the unjust. The sun doesn’t provide the right spotlight effect even for a victorious Napoleon or a dying Caesar.[4] We definitely have no guarantee that in nature the emotional elements will be properly combined with the needs of creative life, and I believe it is the main purpose of the graphic arts to first give us order and variety in the sensory realm, and then to organize the sensory presentation of objects in a way that brings out the emotional elements with a level of order and appropriateness that goes far beyond what nature offers.
Let me sum up for a moment what I have said about the relation of art to Nature, which is, perhaps, the greatest stumbling-block to the understanding of the graphic arts.
Let me quickly recap what I’ve mentioned about the connection between art and Nature, which is probably the biggest hurdle to comprehending the graphic arts.
I have admitted that there is beauty in Nature, that is to say, that certain objects constantly do, and perhaps any object may, compel us to regard it with that intense disinterested contemplation that belongs to the imaginative life, and which is impossible to the actual life of necessity and action; but that in objects created to arouse the æsthetic feeling we have an added consciousness of purpose on the part of the creator, that he made it on purpose not to be used but to be regarded and enjoyed; and that this feeling is characteristic of the æsthetic judgment proper.
I’ve acknowledged that there’s beauty in Nature, meaning that certain things consistently can, and maybe anything can, draw us into that deep, selfless contemplation that’s part of the imaginative experience, which isn’t possible in the practical, necessity-driven life. However, with objects designed to evoke aesthetic appreciation, we have an extra awareness of the creator’s intention—that they were made not for use but for observation and enjoyment; and this appreciation is a key aspect of true aesthetic judgment.
When the artist passes from pure sensations to emotions aroused by means of sensations, he uses natural forms which, in themselves,{25} are calculated to move our emotions, and he presents these in such a manner that the forms themselves generate in us emotional states, based upon the fundamental necessities of our physical and physiological nature. The artist’s attitude to natural form is, therefore, infinitely various according to the emotions he wishes to arouse. He may require for his purpose the most complete representation of a figure, he may be intensely realistic, provided that his presentment, in spite of its closeness to natural appearance, disengages clearly for us the appropriate emotional elements. Or he may give us the merest suggestion of natural forms, and rely almost entirely upon the force and intensity of the emotional elements involved in his presentment.
When an artist moves from pure sensations to emotions triggered by those sensations, they use natural forms that are designed to evoke our feelings. The artist presents these forms in a way that creates emotional responses in us, based on our basic physical and physiological needs. Consequently, the artist's relationship with natural forms varies greatly depending on the emotions they want to provoke. They might aim for a detailed representation of a figure and be highly realistic, as long as this representation clearly communicates the intended emotional aspects. Alternatively, they might only hint at natural forms and depend largely on the strength and intensity of the emotional elements present in their work.
We may, then, dispense once for all with the idea of likeness to Nature, of correctness or incorrectness as a test, and consider only whether the emotional elements inherent in natural form are adequately discovered, unless, indeed, the emotional idea depends at any point upon likeness, or completeness of representation.{26}
We can, then, completely set aside the idea of resembling Nature, of judging correctness or incorrectness as a measure, and focus solely on whether the emotional aspects inherent in natural form are sufficiently expressed, unless, of course, the emotional idea relies at any point on resemblance or completeness of representation.{26}
THE OTTOMAN AND THE WHATNOT[5]
SUCH were the outlandish names of the two great clans that marched under the flag of the Antimacassar to the resounding periods of Mr. Podsnap’s rhetoric. For all the appearance of leisure, for all the absence of hustle, those were strenuous days. Respectability and “the young person” were perpetually menaced by inveterate human nature, and were always or nearly always just being saved as by a miracle. But in the end it was the boast of the Victorians that they had established a system of taboos almost as complicated and as all-pervading as that of the Ojibbeways or the Waramunga. The Ottoman, which seated two so conveniently, was liable to prove a traitor, but what the Ottoman risked could be saved by the Whatnot, with Tennyson and John Greenleaf Whittier to counsel and assuage. One of the things they used to say in those days, quite loudly and distinctly, was: “Distance lends enchantment to the view.” It seemed so appropriate at the frequent and admirably organised picnics that at last it was repeated too often, and the time came when, under pain of social degradation, it was forbidden to utter the hated words. But now that we are busy bringing back the Ottoman and the Whatnot from the garret and the servants’ hall to the drawing-room, we may once more repeat the phrase with impunity, and indeed this article has no other purpose than to repeat once more (and with how new a relish!): “Distance lends enchantment to the view.”
SUCH were the bizarre names of the two major clans that marched under the flag of the Antimacassar to the booming speeches of Mr. Podsnap. Despite the appearance of leisure and the lack of hurry, those were intense times. Respectability and “the young person” were constantly threatened by unchangeable human nature, always or almost always being saved by a miracle. Ultimately, the Victorians took pride in having created a system of taboos that was nearly as intricate and pervasive as that of the Ojibbeways or the Waramunga. The Ottoman, which conveniently seated two, could prove to be treacherous, but whatever risk the Ottoman posed could be mitigated by the Whatnot, with Tennyson and John Greenleaf Whittier to advise and calm. One of the things people used to say back then, quite loudly and clearly, was: “Distance lends enchantment to the view.” It felt so fitting at the frequent and well-organized picnics that it eventually got repeated too much, leading to a point where it became socially unacceptable to say those despised words. But now that we are busy bringing back the Ottoman and the Whatnot from the attic and the servants’ area to the living room, we can once again say the phrase without worry, and indeed this article exists just to repeat once more (and with delightful newness!): “Distance lends enchantment to the view.”
Also, with our passion for science and exact measurement, we shall wish to discover the exact distance at which enchantment begins. And this is easier than might be supposed; for any one who has lived long enough will have noticed that a certain distance lends a violent disgust to the view—that as we recede there comes a period of oblivion and total unconsciousness, to be succeeded when consciousness returns by the ecstasy, the nature of which we are considering.
Also, with our love for science and precise measurement, we want to find out the exact distance at which enchantment starts. This is easier than it seems; anyone who has lived long enough will have noticed that a certain distance brings a strong dislike to the view—that as we move farther away, there comes a time of forgetfulness and complete unawareness, followed by a return to consciousness marked by the ecstasy we are examining.
I, alas! can remember the time when the Ottoman and Whatnot{27} still lingered in the drawing-rooms of the less fashionable and more conservative bourgeoisie; lingered despised, rejected, and merely awaiting their substitutes. I can remember the sham Chippendale and the sham old oak which replaced them. I can remember a still worse horror—a genuine modern style which as yet has no name, a period of black polished wood with spidery lines of conventional flowers incised in the wood and then gilt. These things must have belonged to the eighties—I think they went with the bustle; but as they are precisely at the distance where unconsciousness has set in, it is more difficult to me to write the history of this period than it would be to tell of the sequence of styles in the Tang dynasty. And now, having watched the Whatnot disappear, I have the privilege of watching its resurrection. I have passed from disgust, through total forgetfulness, into the joys of retrospection.
I can still remember when the Ottoman and Whatnot{27} hung around in the drawing rooms of the less trendy and more traditional middle class; they were there, looked down upon, ignored, and just waiting to be replaced. I recall the fake Chippendale and the fake old oak that took their place. I also remember an even worse nightmare—a true modern style that doesn't even have a name yet, a time of black polished wood with thin lines of standard flowers carved into it and then gilded. These must have come from the eighties—I think they were part of the bustle era; but because it's far enough back that I've become oblivious to it, it's harder for me to write about this period than to describe the series of styles in the Tang dynasty. And now, having seen the Whatnot fade away, I have the chance to witness its comeback. I've gone from disgust, through complete forgetfulness, to the pleasure of looking back.
Now my belief is that none of these feelings have anything to do with our æsthetic reactions to the objects as works of art. The odd thing about either real or would-be works of art, that is to say, about any works made with something beyond a purely utilitarian aim—the odd thing is that they can either affect our æsthetic sensibilities or they can become symbols of a particular way of life. In this aspect they affect our historical imagination through our social emotions. That the historical images they conjure up in us are probably false has very little to do with it; the point is that they exist for us, and exist for most people, far more vividly and poignantly than any possible æsthetic feelings. And somehow the works of each period come to stand for us as symbols of some particular and special aspect of life. A Limoges casket evokes the idea of a life of chivalrous adventure and romantic devotion; an Italian cassone gives one a life of intellectual ferment and Boccaccian freedom; before a Caffieri bronze or a Riesener bureau one imagines oneself an exquisite aristocrat proof against the deeper passions, and gifted with a sensuality so refined and a wit so ready that gallantry would be a sufficient occupation for a lifetime. Whoever handling a Louis XV. tabatière reflected how few of the friends of its original owner ever washed, and how many of them were marked with smallpox? The fun of these historical evocations is precisely in what they leave out.{28}
Now, I believe that none of these feelings relate to our aesthetic reactions to objects as works of art. The strange thing about both real and pretender artworks, meaning any creations made with something beyond a purely practical goal—the strange thing is that they can either influence our aesthetic feelings or become symbols of a particular lifestyle. In this way, they impact our historical imagination through our social emotions. Whether the historical images they evoke in us are likely false doesn’t really matter; what matters is that they exist for us, and they exist for most people in a much more vivid and poignant way than any possible aesthetic feelings. Somehow, the works from each period come to symbolize specific and special aspects of life. A Limoges casket brings to mind a life of chivalrous adventure and romantic devotion; an Italian cassone suggests a life of intellectual excitement and Boccaccian freedom; in front of a Caffieri bronze or a Riesener bureau, one imagines oneself as an exquisite aristocrat, immune to deeper emotions, and endowed with such refined sensuality and quick wit that gallantry would occupy a lifetime. Who, while handling a Louis XV. tabatière, considers how few friends of its original owner ever washed, and how many were scarred by smallpox? The interesting part of these historical evocations is precisely in what they leave out.{28}
And in order that this process of selection and elimination may take place, precise and detailed knowledge must have faded from the collective memory, and the blurred but exquisite outlines of a generalisation must have been established.
And for this process of selecting and removing to happen, clear and detailed knowledge must have faded from collective memory, and the vague but beautiful outlines of a general idea must have taken shape.
We have just got to this point with the Victorian epoch. It has just got its vague and generalised Stimmung. We think as we look at Leech’s drawings, or sit in a bead-work chair, of a life which was the perfect flower of bourgeoisie. The aristocracy with their odd irregular ways, the Meredith heroines and heroes, are away in the background; the Victorian life is of the upper bourgeoisie. It is immensely leisured, untroubled by social problems, unblushingly sentimental, impenitently unintellectual, and devoted to sport. The women are exquisitely trained to their social functions; they respond unfailingly to every sentimental appeal; they are beautifully ill-informed, and yet yearning for instruction; they have adorable tempers and are ever so mildly mischievous. The men can afford, without fear of impish criticism, to flaunt their whiskers in the sea breeze, and to expatiate on their contempt for everything that is not correct.
We've just reached this point with the Victorian era. It has developed a vague and generalized vibe. When we look at Leech’s drawings or sit in a beaded chair, we think of a life that represents the perfect example of the bourgeoisie. The aristocracy, with their peculiar and irregular behaviors, along with the heroines and heroes of Meredith, are in the background; the Victorian life is that of the upper bourgeoisie. It's filled with leisure, unaffected by social issues, unashamedly sentimental, unapologetically unintellectual, and focused on sports. The women are expertly trained for their social roles; they respond perfectly to every sentimental appeal; they are beautifully uninformed yet eager for knowledge; they have charming personalities and are just slightly mischievous. The men can confidently show off their whiskers in the sea breeze and express their disdain for everything that isn’t considered proper.
Here, I suppose, is something like the outline of that generalised historical fancy that by now emanates so fragrantly from the marble inlaid tables and the beadwork screens of the period. How charming and how false it is, one sees at once when one reflects that we imagine the Victorians for ever playing croquet without ever losing their tempers.
Here’s something like the outline of that generalized historical idea that now flows so beautifully from the marble inlaid tables and the beaded screens of the time. It’s both charming and completely misleading when you realize that we picture the Victorians as always playing croquet without ever getting frustrated.
It is evident, then, that we have just arrived at the point where our ignorance of life in the Victorian period is such as to allow the incurable optimism of memory to build a quite peculiar little earthly paradise out of the boredoms, the snobberies, the cruel repressions, the mean calculations and rapacious speculations of the mid-nineteenth century. Go a little later, and the imagination is hopelessly hampered by familiarity with the facts of life which the roseate mist has not yet begun to transmute. But let those of us who are hard at work collecting Victorian paper-weights, stuffed hummingbirds and wax flowers reflect that our successors will be able to create quite as amusing and wonderful interiors out of the black wood cabinets and “æsthetic” crewel-work of the eighties. They will{29} not be able to do this until they have constructed the appropriate social picture, the outlines of which we cannot dimly conceive. We have at this moment no inkling of the kind of lies they will invent about the eighties to amuse themselves; we only know that when the time comes the legend will have taken shape, and that, from that moment on, the objects of the time will have the property of emanation.
It’s clear that we’ve reached a point where our lack of understanding of life during the Victorian era allows the unshakeable optimism of memory to create a unique little earthly paradise from the boredom, snobbery, harsh repressions, petty calculations, and greedy speculations of the mid-nineteenth century. If we go a bit further, our imagination will be heavily restricted by our knowledge of the realities of life that the rosy haze hasn’t begun to change yet. But for those of us who are busy collecting Victorian paperweights, stuffed hummingbirds, and wax flowers, let’s remember that future generations will be able to create equally entertaining and impressive settings from the dark wood cabinets and “aesthetic” crewel work of the 1880s. They won’t be able to do this until they’ve formed the right social picture, which we can hardly imagine. Right now, we have no idea what kind of stories they will fabricate about the 1880s to entertain themselves; we only know that when the time comes, a legend will emerge, and from that point on, the objects from that era will possess a mystical quality.
So far it has been unnecessary even to consider whether the objects of the Victorian period are works of art or not; all that is necessary is that they should have some margin of freedom from utility, some scope for the fancy of their creators. And the Victorian epoch is, I think, unusually rich in its capacity for emanation, for it was the great period of fancy work. As the age-long traditions of craftsmanship and structural design, which had lingered on from the Middle Ages, finally faded out under the impact of the new industrialism, the amateur stepped in, his brain teeming with fancies. Craftsmanship was dead, the craftsman replaced either by the machine or by a purely servile and mechanical human being, a man without tradition, without ideas of his own, who was ready to accomplish whatever caprices the amateur or the artist might set him to. It was an age of invention and experiment, an age of wildly irresponsible frivolity, curiosity and sentimentality. To gratify sentiment, nature was opposed to the hampering conventions of art; to gratify fatuous curiosity, the most improbable and ill-suited materials conceivable were used. What they call in France le style coco is exactly expressive of this. A drawing of a pheasant is coloured by cutting up little pieces of real pheasant’s feathers and sticking them on in the appropriate places. Realistic flowers are made out of shells glued together, or, with less of the pleasant shock of the unexpected, out of wax or spun glass. They experiment in colour, using the new results of chemistry boldly, greens from arsenic, magenta and maroons from coal-tar, with results sometimes happy, sometimes disastrous; but always we feel behind everything the capricious fancy of the amateur with his desire to contribute by some joke or conjuring trick to the social amenities. The general groundwork of design, so far as any tradition remains at all, is a kind of bastard baroque passing at times into a flimsy caricature of rococo, but almost always so overlaid and{30} transfigured by the fancies of the amateur as to be hardly recognisable, and yet all, by now, so richly redolent of its social legend as to have become a genuine style.
So far, it hasn't even been necessary to think about whether the objects from the Victorian era are true works of art; all that really matters is that they have some degree of freedom from utility, offering some room for the imagination of their creators. I believe the Victorian period is particularly rich in this creativity because it was a peak time for fancy work. As the long-standing traditions of craftsmanship and structural design that had persisted since the Middle Ages began to fade away with the rise of industrialization, amateurs emerged, their minds overflowing with ideas. True craftsmanship had died, with the craftsman replaced either by machines or by purely mechanical workers—people without tradition or personal ideas, ready to carry out whatever whims the amateur or artist wanted. It was a time of invention and experimentation, marked by wildly irresponsible frivolity, curiosity, and sentimentality. To satisfy sentiment, nature was liberated from the restrictive conventions of art; to indulge foolish curiosity, the most unlikely and poorly suited materials were utilized. What they call in France le style coco perfectly captures this. A depiction of a pheasant is made by cutting up tiny pieces of real pheasant feathers and gluing them in the right spots. Realistic flowers are crafted from shells glued together, or, without the delightful shock of the unexpected, from wax or spun glass. They boldly experiment with color, using the latest chemistry discoveries—greens from arsenic, magenta and maroons from coal-tar—with outcomes that are sometimes pleasing and sometimes disastrous; yet, there's always a sense of the whimsical imagination of the amateur wanting to add some humor or magic to social interactions. The overall design structure, as long as any tradition still exists, resembles a kind of mixed-up baroque style that occasionally turns into a flimsy caricature of rococo, but is almost always so covered and{30} transformed by the amateur's fancies that it's barely recognizable. Yet, it is all so richly infused with its social history that it has become a genuine style.
There is reason enough, then, why we should amuse ourselves by collecting Victorian objects of art, or at least those of us who have the special social-historical sensibility highly developed. But so curiously intertwisted are our emotions that we are always apt to put a wrong label on them, and the label “beauty” comes curiously handy for almost any of the more spiritual and disinterested feelings. So our collector is likely enough to ask us to admire his objects, not for their social emanations, but for their intrinsic æsthetic merit, which, to tell the truth, is far more problematical. Certain it is that the use of material at this period seems to be less discriminating, and the sense of quality feebler, than at any previous period of the world’s history, at all events since Roman times—Pompeii, by-the-by, was a thoroughly Victorian city. The sense of design was also chaotically free from all the limitations of purpose and material, and I doubt if it attained to that perfect abstract sense of harmony which might justify any disregard of those conditions. No, on the whole it will be better to recognise fully how endearing, how fancy-free, how richly evocative are the objects of the Victorian period than to trouble our heads about their æsthetic value.
There are plenty of reasons for us to enjoy collecting Victorian art, especially for those of us who have a keen awareness of social history. However, our emotions can be so intertwined that we often mislabel them, and the label “beauty” conveniently fits a lot of our more spiritual and unbiased feelings. So, our collector might ask us to admire their pieces, not for their social significance, but for their intrinsic aesthetic value, which, to be honest, is much more questionable. It's clear that the use of materials during this time seems less discerning, and the sense of quality is weaker than in any previous period of history, at least since Roman times—by the way, Pompeii was a very Victorian city. The sense of design was also wildly free from any constraints of purpose and material, and I doubt it achieved that perfect abstract sense of harmony that could justify ignoring those conditions. No, overall it’s better to fully recognize how charming, whimsical, and richly evocative the objects from the Victorian era are rather than stressing over their aesthetic value.
The discovery of Victorian art is due to a few enterprising and original artists. In a future article I hope to show why it is to the artist rather than to the collector that we always owe such discoveries, and also why artists are of all people the most indifferent to the æsthetic value of the objects they recommend to our admiration.{31}
The discovery of Victorian art can be credited to a handful of innovative and creative artists. In a future article, I plan to explain why we should always appreciate the artist more than the collector for these discoveries, as well as why artists tend to be the least concerned about the aesthetic value of the objects they suggest we admire.{31}
THE ARTIST’S VISION[6]
IN the preceding article I stated that artists always lead the way in awakening a new admiration for forgotten and despised styles, and that in doing so they anticipate both the archæologist and the collector. I also suggested that they were of all people the least fitted to report upon the æsthetic value of the objects they pressed upon us.
IN the previous article, I mentioned that artists are always at the forefront of reviving a new appreciation for overlooked and undervalued styles, and by doing so, they get ahead of both archaeologists and collectors. I also pointed out that they are, above all, the least qualified to assess the aesthetic value of the works they present to us.
Biologically speaking, art is a blasphemy. We were given our eyes to see things, not to look at them. Life takes care that we all learn the lesson thoroughly, so that at a very early age we have acquired a very considerable ignorance of visual appearances. We have learned the meaning for life of appearances so well that we understand them, as it were, in shorthand. The subtlest differences of appearance that have a utility value still continue to be appreciated, while large and important visual characters, provided they are useless for life, will pass unnoticed. With all the ingenuity and resource which manufacturers put into their business, they can scarcely prevent the ordinary eye from seizing on the minute visual characteristics that distinguish margarine from butter. Some of us can tell Canadian cheddar at a glance, and no one was ever taken in by sham suède gloves.
Biologically speaking, art is a mistake. We have our eyes to see things, not just to look at them. Life makes sure we learn this lesson well, so by a young age, we've picked up a significant ignorance of appearances. We've grasped the importance of appearances in life so effectively that we understand them, in a way, in shorthand. The tiniest differences in appearance that are useful are still recognized, while big and significant visual features, as long as they're not useful for life, often go unnoticed. No matter how clever and resourceful manufacturers are, they can hardly stop the average person from noticing the small visual details that differentiate margarine from butter. Some of us can identify Canadian cheddar at a glance, and no one has ever been fooled by fake suede gloves.
The sense of sight supplies prophetic knowledge of what may affect the inner fortifications, the more intimate senses of taste and touch, where it may already be too late to avert disaster. So we learn to read the prophetic message, and, for the sake of economy, to neglect all else. Children have not learned it fully, and so they look at things with some passion. Even the grown man keeps something of his unbiological, disinterested vision with regard to a few things. He still looks at flowers, and does not merely see them. He also keeps objects which have some marked peculiarity of appearance that catches his eye. These may be natural, like precious stones,{32} fossils, incrustations and such like; or they may be manufactured entirely with a view to pleasing by peculiarities of colour or shape, and these are called ornaments. Such articles, whether natural or artificial, are called by those who sell them ‘curios,’ and the name is not an unhappy one to denote the kind of interest which they arouse. As I showed in a previous article, such objects get attached to them a secondary interest, arising from the kind of social milieu that they were made for, so that they become not merely curious for the eye, but stimulating to our social-historical imagination.
The sense of sight gives us a prophetic understanding of what could impact our inner defenses, the deeper senses of taste and touch, where it might already be too late to prevent disaster. So, we learn to interpret this prophetic message and, to save effort, we ignore everything else. Children haven't fully grasped this lesson yet, so they view things with some passion. Even as adults, we retain a bit of that childlike, unbiased perspective regarding a few things. We still appreciate flowers and don’t just see them. We also collect items that have a distinct appearance that catches our attention. These can be natural, like precious stones,{32} fossils, and similar objects, or they can be entirely man-made to appeal with unique colors or shapes, known as ornaments. Such items, whether natural or artificial, are referred to as ‘curios’ by those who sell them, a fitting term that reflects the kind of interest they spark. As I mentioned in a previous article, these objects also accumulate a secondary interest linked to the social context in which they were created, making them not just eye-catching, but also engaging for our social-historical imagination.
The vision with which we regard such objects is quite distinct from the practical vision of our instinctive life. In the practical vision we have no more concern after we have read the label on the object; vision ceases the moment it has served its biological function. But the curiosity vision does contemplate the object disinterestedly; the object ex hypothesi has no significance for actual life; it is a play or fancy object, and our vision dwells much more consciously and deliberately upon it. We notice to some extent its forms and colours, especially when it is new to us.
The way we look at such objects is very different from the practical way we see things in our everyday life. In practical vision, we stop paying attention once we’ve read the label; our focus ends as soon as it fulfills its biological purpose. But with curiosity, we look at the object without any personal interest; the object, by definition, has no real relevance to our lives; it’s just something for fun or imagination, and we pay much more conscious and deliberate attention to it. We start to notice its shapes and colors, especially when it's something we haven't seen before.
But human perversity goes further even than this in its misapplication of the gift of sight. We may look at objects not even for their curiosity or oddity, but for their harmony of form and colour. To arouse such a vision the object must be more than a ‘curio’: it has to be a work of art. I suspect that such an object must be made by some one in whom the impulse was not to please others, but to express a feeling of his own. It is probably this fundamental difference of origin between the ‘curio’ or ornament and the work of art that makes it impossible for any commercial system, with its eye necessarily on the customer, ever to produce works of art, whatever the ingenuity with which it is attempted.
But human stubbornness goes even further in misusing the gift of sight. We might look at things not just for their curiosity or strangeness, but for their harmony of shape and color. To inspire that kind of view, the object needs to be more than just a "curio"; it has to be a piece of art. I suspect that such an object must be created by someone whose goal wasn’t to please others, but to express their own feelings. It’s likely this fundamental difference in origin between the "curio" or decoration and the work of art that makes it impossible for any commercial system, which necessarily focuses on the customer, to ever produce true works of art, regardless of how cleverly they try.
But we are concerned here not with the origin, but with the vision. This is at once more intense and more detached from the passions of the instinctive life than either of the kinds of vision hitherto discussed. Those who indulge in this vision are entirely absorbed in apprehending the relation of forms and colour to one another, as they cohere within the object. Suppose, for example, that we are looking at a Sung bowl; we apprehend gradually the shape of the outside contour, the perfect sequence of the curves,{33} and the subtle modifications of a certain type of curve which it shows; we also feel the relation of the concave curves to the outside contour; we realise that the precise thickness of the walls is consistent with the particular kind of matter of which it is made, its appearance of density and resistance; and finally we recognise, perhaps, how satisfactory for the display of all these plastic qualities are the colour and the dull lustre of the glaze. Now while we are thus occupied there comes to us, I think, a feeling of purpose; we feel that all these sensually logical conformities are the outcome of a particular feeling, or of what, for want of a better word, we call an idea; and we may even say that the pot is the expression of an idea in the artist’s mind. Whether we are right or not in making this deduction, I believe it nearly always occurs in such æsthetic apprehension of an object of art. But in all this no element of curiosity, no reference to actual life, comes in; our apprehension is unconditioned by considerations of space or time; it is irrelevant to us to know whether the bowl was made seven hundred years ago in China, or in New York yesterday. We may, of course, at any moment switch off from the æsthetic vision, and become interested in all sorts of quasi-biological feelings; we may inquire whether it is genuine or not, whether it is worth the sum given for it, and so forth; but in proportion as we do this we change the focus of our vision; we are more likely to examine the bottom of the bowl for traces of marks than to look at the bowl itself.
But here we’re not focused on the origin, but on the vision. This is both more intense and more detached from the emotions of instinctive life than the types of vision we’ve discussed before. Those who engage in this vision are completely absorbed in understanding how forms and colors relate to each other as they come together within the object. For example, if we look at a Sung bowl, we gradually perceive the shape of the outer edge, the perfect flow of the curves, and the subtle variations of a specific type of curve it displays; we also sense how the concave curves relate to the outer contour; we realize that the exact thickness of the walls aligns with the particular material it’s made from, along with its appearance of density and resistance; and finally, we might recognize how satisfying the color and soft shine of the glaze are for showcasing all these physical qualities. While we’re engaged in this, I believe we experience a sense of purpose; we sense that all these logically appealing aspects are the result of a specific feeling, or what we might describe as an idea; we could even say that the pot expresses an idea in the artist’s mind. Whether we’re correct in this assumption or not, I think it almost always happens in this aesthetic engagement with an artwork. However, in all this, there’s no sense of curiosity, no connection to real life; our understanding isn’t affected by thoughts of space or time; it doesn’t matter to us whether the bowl was made seven hundred years ago in China or in New York yesterday. Of course, at any moment, we can switch from this aesthetic vision and become interested in various quasi-biological feelings; we might question whether it’s authentic, whether it’s worth the price paid for it, and so on; but as we do this, we shift our focus; we are more likely to scrutinize the bottom of the bowl for marks than to appreciate the bowl itself.
Such, then, is the nature of the æsthetic vision, the vision with which we contemplate works of art. It is to such a vision, if to anything outside himself, that the artist appeals, and the artist in his spare hours may himself indulge in the æsthetic vision; and if one can get him to do so, his verdict is likely to be as good as any one’s.
Such is the nature of the aesthetic vision, the way we look at works of art. It is this vision, beyond himself, that the artist appeals to, and in his free time, he may also enjoy the aesthetic vision. If you can get him to engage with it, his opinion is likely to be just as valid as anyone else's.
The artist’s main business in life, however, is carried on by means of yet a fourth kind of vision, which I will call the creative vision. This, I think, is the furthest perversion of the gifts of nature of which man is guilty. It demands the most complete detachment from any of the meanings and implications of appearances. Almost any turn of the kaleidoscope of nature may set up in the artist this detached and impassioned vision, and, as he contemplates the particular field of vision, the (æsthetically) chaotic and accidental{34} conjunction of forms and colours begins to crystallise into a harmony; and as this harmony becomes clear to the artist, his actual vision becomes distorted by the emphasis of the rhythm which has been set up within him. Certain relations of directions of line become for him full of meaning; he apprehends them no longer casually or merely curiously, but passionately, and these lines begin to be so stressed and stand out so clearly from the rest that he sees them far more distinctly than he did at first. Similarly colours, which in nature have almost always a certain vagueness and elusiveness, become so definite and clear to him, owing to their now necessary relation to other colours, that if he chooses to paint his vision he can state them positively and definitely. In such a creative vision the objects as such tend to disappear, to lose their separate unities, and to take their places as so many bits in the whole mosaic of vision. The texture of the whole field of vision becomes so close that the coherence of the separate patches of tone and colour within each object is no stronger than the coherence with every other tone and colour throughout the field.
The artist's main focus in life, however, is conducted through yet another type of vision, which I’ll refer to as creative vision. I believe this is the most significant distortion of nature’s gifts that humans are capable of. It requires complete detachment from any meanings and implications of appearances. Almost any shift in nature can trigger this detached and passionate vision in the artist, and as they observe this particular vision, the (aesthetic) chaos and randomness of forms and colors start to form a harmony. As this harmony becomes clearer to the artist, their actual perception is distorted by the rhythm that develops within them. Certain line directions take on deep significance; they perceive them not just casually or out of curiosity, but with passion, and these lines become so emphasized that they stand out much more clearly than they initially did. Similarly, colors, which in nature often have a certain ambiguity and elusiveness, become so distinct and vivid to the artist due to their necessary relationship with other colors that if they decide to paint their vision, they can express them clearly and definitively. In this creative vision, the objects themselves tend to fade away, losing their individual identities, and instead become parts of a complete mosaic of vision. The texture of the entire visual field becomes so dense that the connection of the separate patches of tone and color within each object is no stronger than the connection with every other tone and color throughout the entire field.
In such circumstances the greatest object of art becomes of no more significance than any casual piece of matter; a man’s head is no more and no less important than a pumpkin, or, rather, these things may be so or not according to the rhythm that obsesses the artist and crystallises his vision. Since it is the habitual practice of the artist to be on the look out for these peculiar arrangements of objects that arouse the creative vision, and become material for creative contemplation, he is liable to look at all objects from this point of view. In so far as the artist looks at objects only as part of a whole field of vision which is his own potential picture, he can give no account of their æsthetic value. Every solid object is subject to the play of light and shade, and becomes a mosaic of visual patches, each of which for the artist is related to other visual patches in the surroundings. It is irrelevant to ask him, while he is looking with this generalised and all-embracing vision, about the nature of the objects which compose it. He is likely even to turn away from works of art in which he may be tempted to relapse into an æsthetic vision, and so see them as unities apart from their surroundings. By preference he turns to objects which make no strong æsthetic{35} appeal in themselves. But he may like objects which attract by some oddity or peculiarity of form or colour, and thereby suggest to him new and intriguing rhythms. In his continual and restless preoccupation with appearance he is capable of looking at objects from which both æsthetic and even curious vision may turn instinctively, or which they may never notice, so little prospect of satisfaction do they hold out. But the artist may always find his satisfaction, the material for his picture, in the most unexpected quarters. Objects of the most despised periods, or objects saturated for the ordinary man with the most vulgar and repulsive associations, may be grist to his mill. And so it happened that while the man of culture and the connoisseur firmly believed that art ended with the brothers Adam, Mr. Walter Sickert was already busy getting hold of stuffed birds and wax flowers just for his own queer game of tones and colours. And now the collector and the art-dealer will be knocking at Mr. Sickert’s door to buy the treasures at twenty times the price the artist paid for them. Perhaps there are already younger artists who are getting excited about the tiles in the refreshment room at South Kensington, and, when the social legend has gathered round the names of Sir Arthur Sullivan and Connie Gilchrist, will inspire in the cultured a deep admiration for the “æsthetic” period.
In such situations, the most important artwork loses its significance and becomes just as relevant as any random object; a person's head is just as significant as a pumpkin, or rather, these things might be important or not depending on the rhythm that consumes the artist and shapes their vision. Since artists tend to look for those unique arrangements of objects that ignite their creativity and serve as material for artistic reflection, they are likely to view everything from this perspective. As long as the artist perceives objects solely as part of their own potential composition, they can't properly assess their aesthetic value. Every solid object interacts with light and shadow, forming a mosaic of visual fragments, each of which relates to other fragments in the environment. It’s pointless to ask them about the nature of the objects within this broad and all-encompassing vision. They might even avoid artworks that tempt them to revert to a purely aesthetic perspective and see them as independent from their surroundings. Instead, they prefer objects that don't have a strong aesthetic appeal on their own. However, they might be drawn to items that have some unusual characteristics in shape or color, which can inspire new and fascinating rhythms. In their constant and restless focus on appearance, they can observe objects that both aesthetic and even curious views might instinctively overlook, or those that don’t seem to promise any satisfaction. But the artist can always find joy and inspiration for their work in the most unexpected places. Objects that society may regard as lowly or that carry the most vulgar and repulsive connotations for the average person can provide material for their creativity. And so it was that while cultured individuals and art connoisseurs believed that art reached its peak with the Adam brothers, Mr. Walter Sickert was already busy collecting stuffed birds and wax flowers for his own unique play with tones and colors. Now, art collectors and dealers are eager to approach Mr. Sickert to purchase these treasures for twenty times what he paid for them. Perhaps there are already younger artists excited by the tiles in the refreshment room at South Kensington, who, when stories begin to circulate about Sir Arthur Sullivan and Connie Gilchrist, will spark a deep appreciation for the “aesthetic” period among the cultured class.
The artist is of all men the most constantly observant of his surroundings, and the least affected by their intrinsic æsthetic value. He is more likely on the whole to paint a slum in Soho than St. Paul’s, and more likely to do a lodging-house interior than a room at Hampton Court. He may, of course, do either, but his necessary detachment comes more easily in one case than the other. The artist is, I believe, a very good critic if you can make him drop his own job for a minute, and really attend to some one else’s work of art; but do not go to him when he is on duty as an artist if you want a sound judgment about objects of art. The different visions I have discussed are like the different gears of a motor-car, only that we sometimes step from one gear into another without knowing it, and the artist may be on the wrong gear for answering us truly. Mr. Walter Sickert is likely to have a Sickert in his eye when he gives us a panegyric on a bedroom candlestick.{36}
The artist is the most observant of all people regarding his surroundings and the least influenced by their artistic value. He’s more likely to paint a slum in Soho than St. Paul’s Cathedral, and more inclined to depict a room in a boarding house than one at Hampton Court. He can certainly do either, but his necessary detachment is easier to achieve in one situation than the other. I believe the artist is a really good critic if you can get him to put aside his own work for a moment and truly focus on someone else’s artwork; but don’t ask him for a solid judgment about art objects when he’s busy being an artist. The different perspectives I’ve talked about are similar to the different gears of a car, except that we sometimes shift from one gear to another without realizing it, which means the artist might be in the wrong gear when we ask for his honest opinion. Mr. Walter Sickert is probably seeing his own style when he gives praise to a bedside candlestick.{36}
ART AND SOCIALISM[7]
I AM not a Socialist, as I understand that word, nor can I pretend to have worked out those complex estimates of economic possibility which are needed before one can endorse the hopeful forecasts of Lady Warwick, Mr. Money, and Mr. Wells. What I propose to do here is first to discuss what effect plutocracy, such as it is to-day, has had of late, and is likely to have in the near future, upon one of the things which I should like to imagine continuing upon our planet—namely, art. And then briefly to prognosticate its chances under such a regime as my colleagues have sketched.
I am not a Socialist, at least not in the way that term is commonly understood, nor can I claim to have figured out the complex economic analyses required to support the optimistic predictions of Lady Warwick, Mr. Money, and Mr. Wells. What I intend to do here is first discuss the impact that plutocracy, as it exists today, has had recently and is likely to have in the near future on something I hope will continue to thrive on our planet—art. Then I'll briefly speculate on its prospects under the type of regime that my colleagues have described.
As I understand it, art is one of the chief organs of what, for want of a better word, I must call the spiritual life. It both stimulates and controls those indefinable overtones of the material life of man which all of us at moments feel to have a quality of permanence and reality that does not belong to the rest of our experience. Nature demands with no uncertain voice that the physical needs of the body shall be satisfied first; but we feel that our real human life only begins at the point where that is accomplished, that the man who works at some uncreative and uncongenial toil merely to earn enough food to enable him to continue to work has not, properly speaking, a human life at all.
As I see it, art is one of the main aspects of what I can only call the spiritual life. It both inspires and shapes those subtle feelings within our material existence that many of us sometimes sense have a level of permanence and reality that our everyday experiences lack. Nature clearly demands that our physical needs be met first; however, we feel that our true human life really starts only after that is taken care of. The person who engages in monotonous and unpleasant work just to make enough money to keep going doesn’t, in a true sense, have a human life at all.
It is the argument of commercialism, as it once was of aristocracy, that the accumulation of surplus wealth in a few hands enables this spiritual life to maintain its existence, that no really valuable or useless work (for from this point of view only useless work has value) could exist in the community without such accumulations of wealth. The argument has been employed for the disinterested work of scientific research. A doctor of naturally liberal and generous impulses told me that he was becoming a reactionary simply because he feared that public bodies would never{37} give the money necessary for research with anything like the same generosity as is now shown by the great plutocrats. But Sir Ray Lankester does not find that generosity sufficient, and is prepared at least to consider a State more ample-spirited.
It’s the argument of commercialism, just like it used to be for aristocracy, that having a lot of surplus wealth concentrated in a few hands allows this spiritual life to keep going. Without these wealth accumulations, no truly valuable or pointless work (because from this perspective, only pointless work holds value) could survive in society. This argument has been used to justify the unselfish work of scientific research. A doctor with naturally liberal and generous impulses told me he was becoming conservative simply because he worries that public organizations will never provide the funding needed for research with the same generosity that the wealthy do today. However, Sir Ray Lankester does not see that generosity as enough and is at least willing to consider a more generous approach from the State.
The situation as regards art and as regards the disinterested love of truth is so similar that we might expect this argument in favour of a plutocratic social order to hold equally well for both art and science, and that the artist would be a fervent upholder of the present system. As a matter of fact, the more representative artists have rarely been such, and not a few, though working their life long for the plutocracy, have been vehement Socialists.
The situation regarding art and the unbiased love of truth is so similar that we might expect this argument supporting a wealthy social order to apply equally to both art and science, and that artists would strongly support the current system. In reality, the more prominent artists have rarely been like that, and many, despite spending their lives working for the wealthy elite, have been passionate Socialists.
Despairing of the conditions due to modern commercialism, it is not unnatural that lovers of beauty should look back with nostalgia to the age when society was controlled by a landed aristocracy. I believe, however, that from the point of view of the encouragement of great creative art there is not much difference between an aristocracy and a plutocracy. The aristocrat usually had taste, the plutocrat frequently has not. Now taste is of two kinds, the first consisting in the negative avoidance of all that is ill-considered and discordant, the other positive and a by-product; it is that harmony which always results from the expression of intense and disinterested emotion. The aristocrat, by means of his good taste of the negative kind, was able to come to terms with the artist; the plutocrat has not. But both alike desire to buy something which is incommensurate with money. Both want art to be a background to their radiant self-consciousness. They want to buy beauty as they want to buy love; and the painter, picture-dealer, and the pander try perennially to persuade them that it is possible. But living beauty cannot be bought; it must be won. I have said that the aristocrat, by his taste, by his feeling for the accidentals of beauty, did manage to get on to some kind of terms with the artist. Hence the art of the eighteenth century, an art that is prone before the distinguished patron, subtly and deliciously flattering and yet always fine. In contrast to that the art of the nineteenth century is coarse, turbulent, clumsy. It marks the beginning of a revolt. The artist just managed to let himself be coaxed and cajoled by the aristocrat, but when the aristocratic was succeeded by the plutocratic patron with less{38} conciliatory manners and no taste, the artist rebelled; and the history of art in the nineteenth century is the history of a band of heroic Ishmaelites, with no secure place in the social system, with nothing to support them in the unequal struggle but a dim sense of a new idea, the idea of the freedom of art from all trammels and tyrannies.
Feeling frustrated with the state of things because of modern commercialism, it’s understandable that those who appreciate beauty look back longingly to a time when society was ruled by a landed aristocracy. However, I believe that when it comes to supporting great creative art, there isn’t much difference between an aristocracy and a plutocracy. The aristocrat usually has taste, while the plutocrat often does not. Taste comes in two forms: the first is simply not liking anything that is poorly thought out or jarring, while the second is a more positive by-product; it’s the harmony that arises from expressing deep and selfless emotion. The aristocrat, with his refined negative taste, could connect with the artist; the plutocrat cannot. Yet both want to purchase something that money cannot quantify. They seek art to enhance their own self-awareness, wanting to buy beauty just as they want to buy love. The painter, art dealer, and those who cater to their desires constantly try to convince them that it’s possible. But real beauty cannot be bought; it must be earned. I’ve mentioned that the aristocrat, through his taste and appreciation for the nuances of beauty, managed to find a way to engage with the artist. This led to the art of the eighteenth century, which catered to the esteemed patron, delicately flattering yet always refined. In contrast, the art of the nineteenth century is rough, chaotic, and awkward. It signals the start of a rebellion. The artist, who could be sweet-talked by the aristocrat, found himself at odds with the plutocratic patron who lacked charm and taste. The nineteenth-century art narrative is the story of a group of heroic outcasts, without a secure place in society, supported only by a vague sense of a new idea: the freedom of art from all constraints and oppressions.
The place that the artists left vacant at the plutocrat’s table had to be filled, and it was filled by a race new in the history of the world, a race for whom no name has yet been found, a race of pseudo-artists. As the prostitute professes to sell love, so these gentlemen professed to sell beauty, and they and their patrons rollicked good-humouredly through the Victorian era. They adopted the name and something of the manner of artists; they intercepted not only the money, but the titles and fame and glory which were intended for those whom they had supplanted. But, while they were yet feasting, there came an event which seemed at the time of no importance, but which was destined to change ultimately the face of things, the exhibition of ancient art at Manchester in 1857. And with this came Ruskin’s address on the Political Economy of Art, a work which surprises by its prophetic foresight when we read it half a century later. These two things were the Mene Tekel of the orgy of Victorian Philistinism. The plutocrat saw through the deception; it was not beauty the pseudo-artist sold him, any more than it was love which the prostitute gave. He turned from it in disgust and decided that the only beauty he could buy was the dead beauty of the past. Thereupon set in the worship of patine and the age of forgery and the detection of forgery. I once remarked to a rich man that a statue by Rodin might be worthy even of his collection. He replied, “Show me a Rodin with the patine of the fifteenth century, and I will buy it.”
The spot that the artists left empty at the rich person's table had to be filled, and it was filled by a new group in the history of the world, a group for whom no name has been found yet, a group of fake artists. Just as a prostitute claims to sell love, these men claimed to sell beauty, and they and their patrons happily enjoyed themselves through the Victorian era. They took on the name and some of the style of artists; they intercepted not just the money, but also the titles, fame, and glory that were meant for those they had replaced. But while they were still celebrating, an event occurred that seemed insignificant at the time but was destined to change everything—the exhibition of ancient art in Manchester in 1857. Along with that came Ruskin’s address on the Political Economy of Art, a work that surprises with its foresight when we read it half a century later. These two events were the warning signs of the excesses of Victorian Philistinism. The wealthy man saw through the trick; it wasn’t beauty the fake artist was selling him, any more than it was love that the prostitute provided. He turned away in disgust and decided that the only beauty he could buy was the dead beauty of the past. This led to the admiration of patine and the era of forgery and forgery detection. I once mentioned to a rich man that a statue by Rodin might be worthy of his collection. He responded, “Show me a Rodin with the patine of the fifteenth century, and I will buy it.”
Patine, then, the adventitious material beauty which age alone can give, has come to be the object of a reverence greater than that devoted to the idea which is enshrined within the work of art. People are right to admire patine. Nothing is more beautiful than gilded bronze of which time has taken toll until it is nothing but a faded shimmering splendour over depths of inscrutable gloom; nothing finer than the dull glow which Pentelic marble has gathered from past centuries of sunlight and warm Mediterranean breezes. Patine{39} is good, but it is a surface charm added to the essential beauty of expression; its beauty is literally skin-deep. It can never come into being or exist in or for itself; no patine can make a bad work good, or the forgers would be justified. It is an adjectival and ancillary beauty scarcely worthy of our prolonged contemplation.
Patina, then, the surface beauty that only age can provide, has become something we revere even more than the idea captured in the artwork itself. People are right to appreciate patina. Nothing is more stunning than gilded bronze that time has worn down to a faded shimmering elegance over layers of deep mystery; nothing more exquisite than the soft glow that Pentelic marble has absorbed from centuries of sunlight and warm Mediterranean breezes. Patina{39} is nice, but it’s just a surface charm added to the true beauty of expression; its beauty is literally skin-deep. It can never come into being or exist for its own sake; no patina can turn a bad piece into a good one, or else the forgers would be vindicated. It’s a secondary and superficial beauty hardly deserving of our extended attention.
There is to the philosopher something pathetic in the Plutocrat’s worship of patine. It is, as it were, a compensation for his own want of it. On himself all the rough thumb and chisel marks of his maker—and he is self-made—stand as yet unpolished and raw; but his furniture, at least, shall have the distinction of age-long acquaintance with good manners.
There’s something tragic about how the wealthy person admires patine. It’s almost like a way to make up for their own lack of it. On themselves, all the rough edges and marks from their creator—since they’ve made themselves—remain unrefined and raw; but at least their furniture will have the elegance that comes from a long history of good taste.
But the net result of all this is that the artist has nothing to hope from the plutocrat. To him we must be grateful indeed for that brusque disillusionment of the real artist, the real artist who might have rubbed along uneasily for yet another century with his predecessor, the aristocrat. Let us be grateful to him for this; but we need not look to him for further benefits, and if we decide to keep him the artist must be content to be paid after he is dead and vicariously in the person of an art-dealer. The artist must be content to look on while sums are given for dead beauty, the tenth part of which, properly directed, would irrigate whole nations and stimulate once more the production of vital artistic expression.
But the end result of all this is that the artist has no reason to expect anything from the wealthy. We should be truly thankful for that abrupt wake-up call regarding the real artist, the one who might have struggled along for another century with his predecessor, the aristocrat. Let’s appreciate him for this; however, we shouldn't expect any more from him, and if we choose to keep him around, the artist has to settle for getting paid only after he's gone, and indirectly through an art dealer. The artist has to watch as huge sums are spent on long-gone beauty, amounts that, if used wisely, could support entire nations and reignite the creation of meaningful artistic expression.
I would not wish to appear to blame the plutocrat. He has often honestly done his best for art; the trouble is not of his making more than of the artist’s, and the misunderstanding between art and commerce is bound to be complete. The artist, however mean and avaricious he may appear, knows that he cannot really sell himself for money any more than the philosopher or the scientific investigator can sell himself for money. He takes money in the hope that he may secure the opportunity for the free functioning of his creative power. If the patron could give him that instead of money he would bless him; but he cannot, and so he tries to get him to work not quite freely for money; and in revenge the artist indulges in all manner of insolences, even perhaps in sharp practices, which make the patron feel, with some justification, that he is the victim of ingratitude and wanton caprice. It is impossible that the artist should work for the plutocrat; he must work for himself, because{40} it is only by so doing that he can perform the function for which he exists; it is only by working for himself that he can work for mankind.
I wouldn’t want to seem like I’m blaming the wealthy. He has often genuinely tried his best for art; the issues aren’t solely his fault, just as they aren’t solely the artist's either, and the disconnect between art and business is bound to be complete. The artist, no matter how petty or greedy he might seem, understands that he can’t truly sell himself for money any more than a philosopher or a scientist can. He accepts money hoping to create the freedom to truly express his creative abilities. If the patron could provide that instead of cash, he would be grateful; but he can’t, so he attempts to get him to work somewhat freely for money. In retaliation, the artist may engage in all sorts of disrespectful behavior, even potentially shady tactics, which can make the patron feel, with some reason, that he’s dealing with ingratitude and random whim. It’s impossible for the artist to work for the wealthy; he must work for himself because{40} that’s the only way he can fulfill the purpose he exists for; it’s only by working for himself that he can contribute to humanity.
If, then, the particular kind of accumulation of surplus wealth which we call plutocracy has failed, as surely it has signally failed, to stimulate the creative power of the imagination, what disposition of wealth might be conceived that would succeed better? First of all, a greater distribution of wealth, with a lower standard of ostentation, would, I think, do a great deal to improve things without any great change in other conditions. It is not enough known that the patronage which really counts to-day is exercised by quite small and humble people. These people with a few hundreds a year exercise a genuine patronage by buying pictures at ten, twenty, or occasionally thirty pounds, with real insight and understanding, thereby enabling the young Ishmaelite to live and function from the age of twenty to thirty or so, when perhaps he becomes known to richer buyers, those experienced spenders of money who are always more cautious, more anxious to buy an investment than a picture. These poor, intelligent first patrons to whom I allude belong mainly to the professional classes; they have none of the pretensions of the plutocrat and none of his ambitions. The work of art is not for them, as for him, a decorative backcloth to his stage, but an idol and an inspiration. Merely to increase the number and potency of these people would already accomplish much; and this is to be noticed, that if wealth were more evenly distributed, if no one had a great deal of wealth, those who really cared for art would become the sole patrons, since for all it would be an appreciable sacrifice, and for none an impossibility. The man who only buys pictures when he has as many motor-cars as he can conceivably want would drop out as a patron altogether.
If the specific type of wealth accumulation we refer to as plutocracy has clearly failed to inspire creative imagination, what different approach to wealth distribution could work better? First, I believe a wider distribution of wealth, along with a more modest lifestyle, could significantly improve the situation without needing major changes elsewhere. It's not widely recognized that the real patrons of today are often ordinary people with modest incomes. These individuals, earning just a few hundred a year, genuinely support artists by purchasing pieces for ten, twenty, or sometimes thirty pounds, showing true appreciation and understanding. This support allows young artists to thrive from their twenties to about thirty, until they attract wealthier buyers, who tend to be more cautious and focused on investments rather than art. The first patrons I’m talking about mainly come from professional backgrounds; they don’t share the plutocrat’s pretensions or ambitions. For them, art isn’t just a backdrop for their lives, as it is for the wealthy, but rather an object of worship and inspiration. Simply increasing the number and influence of these individuals would make a big difference. Notably, if wealth were distributed more evenly, and no one had excessive wealth, the genuine art enthusiasts would become the primary patrons, since supporting art would be a meaningful sacrifice for everyone but not an impossible one. The person who buys art only when they have more cars than they need would no longer be a patron at all.
But even this would only foster the minor and private arts; and what the history of art definitely elucidates is that the greatest art has always been communal, the expression—in highly individualised ways, no doubt—of common aspirations and ideals.
But even this would only promote the smaller, private arts; and what the history of art clearly shows is that the greatest art has always been communal, reflecting common aspirations and ideals, though in very individualized ways, of course.
Let us suppose, then, that society were so arranged that considerable surplus wealth lay in the hands of public bodies, both national and local; can we have any reasonable hope that they would{41} show more skill in carrying out the delicate task of stimulating and using the creative power of the artist?
The immediate prospect is certainly not encouraging. Nothing, for instance, is more deplorable than to watch the patronage of our provincial museums. The gentlemen who administer these public funds naturally have not realised so acutely as private buyers the lesson so admirably taught at Christie’s, that pseudo or Royal-Academic art is a bad investment. Nor is it better if we turn to national patronage. In Great Britain, at least, we cannot get a postage stamp or a penny even respectably designed, much less a public monument. Indeed, the tradition that all public British art shall be crassly mediocre and inexpressive is so firmly rooted that it seems to have almost the prestige of constitutional precedent. Nor will any one who has watched a committee commissioning a presentation portrait, or even buying an old master, be in danger of taking too optimistic a view. With rare and shining exceptions, committees seem to be at the mercy of the lowest common denominator of their individual natures, which is dominated by fear of criticism; and fear and its attendant, compromise, are bad masters of the arts.
The immediate outlook is definitely not promising. For example, there's nothing more disappointing than seeing how our provincial museums are funded. The individuals who manage these public funds haven't grasped as clearly as private buyers have the lesson that was brilliantly demonstrated at Christie’s: that pseudo or Royal-Academic art is a poor investment. It doesn’t get any better if we look at national funding. At least in Great Britain, we can't even get a postage stamp or a penny that's decently designed, let alone a public monument. In fact, the tradition that all public British art should be blatantly mediocre and uninspired is so deeply ingrained that it has almost the weight of constitutional precedent. Anyone who has observed a committee commissioning a portrait or buying an old master will be unlikely to have an overly optimistic outlook. With rare and impressive exceptions, committees seem to be influenced by the lowest common denominator of their members' traits, which is driven by a fear of criticism; and fear, along with compromise, are poor guides in the arts.
Speaking recently at Liverpool, Mr. Bernard Shaw placed the present situation as regards public art in its true light. He declared that the corruption of taste and the emotional insincerity of the mass of the people had gone so far that any picture which pleased more than ten per cent. of the population should be immediately burned....
Speaking recently in Liverpool, Mr. Bernard Shaw highlighted the current state of public art accurately. He stated that the decline in taste and the lack of genuine emotion among most people had reached a point where any artwork that appealed to more than ten percent of the population should be immediately destroyed....
This, then, is the fundamental fact we have to face. And it is this that gives us pause when we try to construct any conceivable system of public patronage.
This is the basic fact we need to confront. And it's this that makes us hesitate when we attempt to create any possible system of public support.
For the modern artist puts the question of any socialistic—or, indeed, of any completely ordered—state in its acutest form. He demands as an essential to the proper use of his powers a freedom from restraint such as no other workman expects. He must work when he feels inclined; he cannot work to order. Hence his frequent quarrels with the burgher who knows he has to work when he is disinclined, and cannot conceive why the artist should not do likewise. The burgher watches the artist’s wayward and apparently quite unmethodical activity, and envies his job. Now, in any Socialistic{42} State, if certain men are licensed to pursue the artistic calling, they are likely to be regarded by the other workers with some envy. There may be a competition for such soft jobs among those who are naturally work-shy, since it will be evident that the artist is not called to account in the same way as other workers.
For the modern artist raises the issue of any socialist—or really, any fully organized—state in the sharpest way possible. He insists on having a freedom from restrictions that no other worker expects. He needs to create when he feels inspired; he can’t just work on command. This often leads to conflicts with the regular worker who understands he has to put in effort even when he doesn’t want to, and can’t see why the artist shouldn’t have to do the same. The worker sees the artist’s unpredictable and seemingly unstructured process and envies his job. In any Socialist{42} State, if certain people are allowed to pursue artistic careers, they are likely to be viewed with envy by other workers. There might be competition for such easy gigs among those who naturally avoid hard work, as it will be clear that the artist isn’t held to the same expectations as other workers.
If we suppose, as seems not unlikely, in view of the immense numbers who become artists in our present social state, that there would be this competition for the artistic work of the community, what methods would be devised to select those required to fill the coveted posts? Frankly, the history of art in the nineteenth century makes us shudder at the results that would follow. One scarcely knows whether they would be worse if Bumble or the Academy were judge. We only know that under any such conditions none of the artists whose work has ultimately counted in the spiritual development of the race would have been allowed to practise the coveted profession.
If we assume, which seems likely given the huge number of people becoming artists in today's society, that there would be competition for artistic roles in the community, what methods would be created to choose those needed for the desired positions? Honestly, the history of art in the nineteenth century makes us cringe at the possible outcomes. It’s hard to say if things would be worse with Bumble or the Academy as judges. We only know that under any such circumstances, none of the artists whose work has truly contributed to the spiritual growth of humanity would have been permitted to practice the sought-after profession.
There is in truth, as Ruskin pointed out in his “Political Economy of Art,” a gross and wanton waste under the present system. We have thousands of artists who are only so by accident and by name, on the one hand, and certainly many—one cannot tell how many—who have the special gift but have never had the peculiar opportunities which are to-day necessary to allow it to expand and function. But there is, what in an odd way consoles us, a blind chance that the gift and the opportunity may coincide; that Shelley and Browning may have a competence, and Cézanne a farm-house he could retire to. Bureaucratic Socialism would, it seems, take away even this blind chance that mankind may benefit by its least appreciable, most elusive treasures, and would carefully organise the complete suppression of original creative power; would organise into a universal and all-embracing tyranny the already overweening and disastrous power of endowed official art. For we must face the fact that the average man has two qualities which would make the proper selection of the artist almost impossible. He has, first of all, a touching proclivity to awe-struck admiration of whatever is presented to him as noble by a constituted authority; and, secondly, a complete absence of any immediate reaction to a work of art until his judgment has thus been hypnotised by the voice of authority. Then, and not{43} till then, he sees, or swears he sees, those adorable Emperor’s clothes that he is always agape for.
There is, as Ruskin pointed out in his “Political Economy of Art,” a significant and unnecessary waste in the current system. We have thousands of artists who are only artists by chance and by name, and certainly many—too many to count—who have real talent but haven’t had the unique opportunities necessary today for that talent to grow and thrive. Yet, oddly enough, there’s a blind chance that the talent and opportunity might come together; that Shelley and Browning might find financial stability, and Cézanne might have a farmhouse to retreat to. Bureaucratic Socialism would seem to eliminate even this blind chance for humanity to benefit from its most subtle and elusive treasures and would methodically suppress original creative power; it would enforce a universal, all-encompassing tyranny over the already excessive and harmful influence of official art. We must acknowledge that the average person has two traits that make it almost impossible to select the right artist. First, they have a touching tendency to be awestruck by whatever is presented to them as noble by a governing authority; and second, they completely lack any immediate reaction to art until their judgment has been mesmerized by the voice of authority. Only then do they see, or claim to see, the enchanting Emperor’s clothes they are always eager for.
I am speaking, of course, of present conditions, of a populace whose emotional life has been drugged by the sugared poison of pseudo-art, a populace saturated with snobbishness, and regarding art chiefly for its value as a symbol of social distinctions. There have been times when such a system of public patronage as we are discussing might not have been altogether disastrous. Times when the guilds represented more or less adequately the genuine artistic intelligence of the time; but the creation, first of all, of aristocratic art, and finally of pseudo-art, have brought it about that almost any officially organised system would at the present moment stereotype all the worst features of modern art.
I’m talking about the current situation, about a population whose emotional lives have been numbed by the sugary poison of fake art, a population drenched in snobbishness, viewing art mainly as a marker of social status. There have been moments when a public patronage system like the one we're discussing might not have been completely disastrous. Times when the guilds somewhat accurately represented the true artistic talent of the era; however, the rise of aristocratic art, and eventually fake art, has led to a point where any officially organized system would, at this moment, reinforce all the worst aspects of modern art.
Now, in thus putting forward the extreme difficulties of any system of publicly controlled art, we are emphasising perhaps too much the idea of the artist as a creator of purely ideal and abstract works, as the medium of inspiration and the source of revelation. It is the artist as prophet and priest that we have been considering, the artist who is the articulate soul of mankind. Now, in the present commercial State, at a time when such handiwork as is not admirably fitted to some purely utilitarian purpose has become inanely fatuous and grotesque, the artist in this sense has undoubtedly become of supreme importance as a protestant, as one who proclaims that art is a reasonable function, and one that proceeds by a nice adjustment of means to ends. But if we suppose a state in which all the ordinary objects of daily life—our chairs and tables, our carpets and pottery—expressed something of this reasonableness instead of a crazy and vapid fantasy, the artist as a pure creator might become, not indeed of less importance—rather more—but a less acute necessity to our general living than he is to-day. Something of the sanity and purposefulness of his attitude might conceivably become infused into the work of the ordinary craftsman, something, too, of his creative energy and delight in work. We must, therefore, turn for a moment from the abstractly creative artist to the applied arts and those who practise them.
Now, in bringing up the significant challenges of any system of publicly managed art, we might be focusing a bit too much on the notion of the artist as someone who creates purely ideal and abstract works, serving as the medium of inspiration and the source of revelation. We have been considering the artist as a prophet and priest, the one who represents the voice of humanity. In today’s commercial society, when handiwork that doesn’t serve a purely practical purpose has become pointless and absurd, the artist in this way has undeniably become incredibly important as a figure of protest, someone who declares that art is a reasonable function that balances means with ends. However, if we imagine a situation where all the everyday objects in our lives—like our chairs and tables, carpets and pottery—reflected something of this reasonableness instead of a nonsensical and empty fantasy, the artist as a pure creator might not be less significant—perhaps even more so—but would be less of a necessity to our daily lives than he is today. Some of the rationality and intentionality of his approach might naturally find its way into the work of regular craftsmen, along with a bit of his creative energy and enjoyment in the work. Therefore, we must take a moment to shift our focus from the abstractly creative artist to the applied arts and those who practice them.
We are so far obliged to protect ourselves from the implications of modern life that without a special effort it is hard to conceive the{44} enormous quantity of “art” that is annually produced and consumed. For the special purpose of realising it I take the pains to write the succeeding paragraphs in a railway refreshment-room, where I am actually looking at those terribly familiar but fortunately fleeting images which such places afford. And one must remember that public places of this kind merely reflect the average citizen’s soul, as expressed in his home.
We are so caught up in protecting ourselves from the effects of modern life that, without making a special effort, it's hard to grasp the huge amount of “art” that gets produced and consumed each year. To truly understand this, I'm taking the time to write the following paragraphs in a train station café, where I can see those painfully familiar yet thankfully temporary images that these places provide. It's also important to remember that public spaces like this simply mirror the average person’s spirit, as shown in their home.
The space my eye travels over is a small one, but I am appalled at the amount of “art” that it harbours. The window towards which I look is filled in its lower part by stained glass; within a highly elaborate border, designed by some one who knew the conventions of thirteenth-century glass, is a pattern of yellow and purple vine leaves with bunches of grapes, and flitting about among these many small birds. In front is a lace curtain with patterns taken from at least four centuries and as many countries. On the walls, up to a height of four feet, is a covering of lincrusta walton stamped with a complicated pattern in two colours, with sham silver medallions. Above that a moulding but an inch wide, and yet creeping throughout its whole with a degenerate descendant of a Græco-Roman carved guilloche pattern; this has evidently been cut out of the wood by machine or stamped out of some composition—its nature is so perfectly concealed that it is hard to say which. Above this is a wall-paper in which an effect of eighteenth-century satin brocade is imitated by shaded staining of the paper. Each of the little refreshment-tables has two cloths, one arranged symmetrically with the table, the other a highly ornate printed cotton arranged “artistically” in a diagonal position. In the centre of each table is a large pot in which every beautiful quality in the material and making of pots has been carefully obliterated by methods each of which implies profound scientific knowledge and great inventive talent. Within each pot is a plant with large dark-green leaves, apparently made of india-rubber. This painful catalogue makes up only a small part of the inventory of the “art” of the restaurant. If I were to go on to tell of the legs of the tables, of the electric-light fittings, of the chairs into the wooden seats of which some tremendous mechanical force has deeply impressed a large distorted anthemion—if I were to tell of all these things, my reader and I{45} might both begin to realise with painful acuteness something of the horrible toil involved in all this display. Display is indeed the end and explanation of it all. Not one of these things has been made because the maker enjoyed the making; not one has been bought because its contemplation would give any one any pleasure, but solely because each of these things is accepted as a symbol of a particular social status. I say their contemplation can give no one pleasure; they are there because their absence would be resented by the average man who regards a large amount of futile display as in some way inseparable from the conditions of that well-to-do life to which he belongs or aspires to belong. If everything were merely clean and serviceable he would proclaim the place bare and uncomfortable.
The space my gaze scans is small, but I'm shocked by the amount of "art" it contains. The window I’m looking at has stained glass at the bottom; within an elaborate border designed by someone familiar with thirteenth-century glass techniques, there's a pattern of yellow and purple vine leaves with clusters of grapes, along with several small birds flitting about. In front is a lace curtain featuring patterns from at least four different centuries and as many countries. The walls are covered up to a height of four feet with lincrusta walton stamped in a complex two-color pattern, adorned with fake silver medallions. Above that is a molding just an inch wide, but it’s covered entirely with a degenerate version of a Greco-Roman carved guilloche pattern; it’s evidently been cut by machine or stamped from some kind of material—its exact nature is so well concealed that it’s hard to tell which. Above this is wallpaper that mimics the effect of eighteenth-century satin brocade through shaded stains on the paper. Each of the little refreshment tables has two tablecloths, one neatly arranged with the table, the other a colorful printed cotton laid out “artistically” in a diagonal position. In the center of each table is a large pot where every beautiful quality of the material and craftsmanship has been carefully erased through methods requiring significant scientific knowledge and great creative talent. Inside each pot is a plant with large dark-green leaves that look rubbery. This painful list is just a small part of the “art” inventory of the restaurant. If I were to describe the table legs, the electric light fixtures, the chairs with their wooden seats deeply embossed with a grotesque anthemion design—if I were to elaborate on all of these items, my reader and I might both begin to realize with a painful clarity the horrible effort involved in this display. Display is indeed the purpose and explanation of it all. None of these items were made for the joy of crafting; none were purchased for the pleasure they might provide; instead, each one is seen as a symbol of a certain social status. I argue that contemplating them can’t bring anyone joy; they exist because their absence would be frowned upon by the average person, who views a great deal of pointless display as somehow linked to the conditions of the well-off life they belong to or wish to be a part of. If everything were simply clean and functional, they'd call the place bare and uncomfortable.
The doctor who lines his waiting-room with bad photogravures and worse etchings is acting on exactly the same principle; in short, nearly all our “art” is made, bought, and sold merely for its value as an indication of social status.
The doctor who fills his waiting room with poor-quality prints and even worse etchings is doing it for the same reason; basically, almost all of our “art” is created, purchased, and traded just for its value as a sign of social status.
Now consider the case of those men whose life-work it is to stimulate this eczematous eruption of pattern on the surface of modern manufactures. They are by far the most numerous “artists” in the country. Each of them has not only learned to draw but has learned by sheer application to put forms together with a similitude of that coherence which creative impulse gives. Probably each of them has somewhere within him something of that creative impulse which is the inspiration and delight of every savage and primitive craftsman; but in these manufacturer’s designers the pressure of commercial life has crushed and atrophied that creative impulse completely. Their business is to produce, not expressive design, but dead patterns. They are compelled, therefore, to spend their lives behaving in an entirely idiotic and senseless manner, and that with the certainty that no one will ever get positive pleasure from the result; for one may hazard the statement that until I made the effort just now, no one of the thousands who use the refreshment-rooms ever really looked at the designs.
Now think about the people whose job is to create the repetitive designs on modern products. They are by far the most numerous "artists" in the country. Each of them has learned to draw, and through hard work, they can arrange shapes in a way that resembles the creativity of true artistic inspiration. It's likely that each of them has some form of that creative drive within, which brings joy to every traditional craftsman; however, in these designers for manufacturers, the demands of commercial life have completely stifled that creative spark. Their job is to create not expressive designs but lifeless patterns. Consequently, they end up spending their lives acting in a completely pointless and foolish way, knowing that no one will ever genuinely enjoy their work; in fact, it's safe to say that until I pointed it out just now, none of the countless people who use the refreshment rooms ever really noted the designs.
This question of the creation and consumption of art tends to become more and more pressing. I have shown just now what an immense mass of art is consumed, but this is not the same art{46} as that which the genuine artist produces. The work of the truly creative artist is not merely useless to the social man—it appears to be noxious and inassimilable. Before art can be “consumed” the artistic idea must undergo a process of disinfection. It must have extracted and removed from it all, or nearly all, that makes it æsthetically valuable. What occurs when a great artist creates a new idea is somewhat as follows: We know the process well enough, since it has taken place in the last fifty years. An artist attains to a new vision. He grasps this with such conviction that he is able to express it in his work. Those few people in his immediate surroundings who have the faculty of æsthetic perception become very much excited by the new vision. The average man, on the other hand, lacks this faculty and, moreover, instinctively protects the rounded perfection of his universe of thought and feeling from the intrusion of new experience; in consequence he becomes extremely irritated by the sight of works which appear to him completely unintelligible. The misunderstanding between this small minority and the public becomes violent. Then some of the more intelligent writers on art recognise that the new idea is really related to past æsthetic expressions which have become recognised. Then a clever artist, without any individual vision of his own, sees the possibility of using a modification of the new idea, makes an ingenious compromise between it and the old, generally accepted notions of art. The public, which has been irritated by its incomprehension of the new idea, finding the compromise just intelligible, and delighted to find itself cleverer than it thought, acclaims the compromising intermediary as a genius. The process of disinfection thus begun goes on with increasing energy and rapidity, and before long the travesty of the new idea is completely assimilable by the social organism. The public, after swallowing innumerable imitations of the new idea, may even at last reluctantly accept the original creator as a great man, but generally not until he has been dead for some time and has become a vague and mythical figure.
The issue of creating and consuming art is becoming more urgent. I just showed how much art gets consumed, but it's not the same art{46} that a true artist produces. The work of a genuinely creative artist isn't just useless to society—it often seems harmful and hard for people to digest. Before art can be "consumed," the artistic idea must go through a process of sanitization. It needs to shed almost everything that makes it aesthetically valuable. What happens when a great artist comes up with a new idea is something we know well, as it's happened in the last fifty years. An artist gains a new perspective. They grasp it with such certainty that they can express it in their work. Those few around them with an appreciation for aesthetics get really excited about this new vision. Meanwhile, the average person lacks this ability and instinctively shields their well-rounded view of the world from new experiences; as a result, they become frustrated when they encounter works that seem completely nonsensical to them. The gap between this small group and the general public becomes intense. Then some insightful art critics recognize that the new idea actually ties back to established aesthetic expressions. A clever artist, who doesn't have a unique vision of their own, sees a chance to tweak the new idea, creating a clever blend of it with the older, accepted art concepts. The public, frustrated by its inability to understand the new idea, finds the compromise just clear enough and is pleased to think they’re smarter than they realized, so they praise the intermediary artist as a genius. This process of sanitization continues with more energy and speed, and soon the distorted version of the new idea is easily digestible for society. After consuming countless imitations of the new idea, the public might finally, albeit grudgingly, acknowledge the original creator as a significant figure, but usually not until some time has passed since their death, turning them into a vague and legendary character.
The fact is that the average man uses art entirely for its symbolic value. Art is in fact the symbolic currency of the world. The possession of rare and much coveted works of art is regarded as a sign of national greatness. The growth and development of the Kaiser Friedrich museum was due to the active support of the late Emperor, a man whose distaste for genuine art is notorious, but whose sense of the symbolic was highly developed. Large and expensively ornamented buildings become symbols of municipal greatness. The amount of useless ornaments on façades of their offices is a valuable symbol of the financial exuberance of big commercial undertakings; and, finally, the social status of the individual is expressed to the admiring or envious outer world by the streamlines of an aristocratic motor-car, or the superfluity of lace curtains in the front windows of a genteel suburban villa.
The truth is that the average person views art mainly for its symbolic meaning. Art really serves as the symbolic currency of the world. Owning rare and highly sought-after artworks is seen as a sign of national pride. The growth and development of the Kaiser Friedrich Museum happened thanks to the strong support of the late Emperor, a man famously uninterested in true art, but very aware of its symbolic significance. Large, lavishly decorated buildings become emblems of city prestige. The excessive decorations on the facades of their offices symbolize the financial extravagance of big businesses; ultimately, a person's social standing is conveyed to the admiring or envious outside world through the sleek design of an upscale car or the abundance of lace curtains in the front windows of an upscale suburban home.
The social man, then, lives in a world of symbols, and though he presses other things into his service, such, for instance, as kings, footmen, dogs, women, he finds in art his richest reservoir of symbolic currency. But in a world of symbolists the creative artist and the creative man of science appear in strange isolation as the only people who are not symbolists. They alone are up against certain relations which do not stand for something else, but appear to have ultimate value, to be real.
The social person, then, lives in a world of symbols, and while he uses other things for his purposes, like kings, servants, dogs, and women, he finds that art is his greatest source of symbolic value. However, in a world full of symbol makers, the creative artist and the innovative scientist seem strangely isolated as the only ones who aren’t symbol makers. They alone face certain realities that don’t represent something else but seem to have intrinsic worth, that are real.
Art as a symbolic currency is an important means of the instinctive life of man, but art as created by the artist is in violent revolt against the instinctive life, is an expression of the reflective and fully conscious life. It is natural enough, then, that before it can be used by the instinctive life it must be deprived by travesty of its too violent assertion of its own reality. Travesty is necessary at first to make it assimilable, but in the end long familiarity may rob even original works of art of their insistence, so that, finally, even the great masterpieces may become the most cherished symbols of the lords of the instinctive life, may, as in fact they frequently do, become the property of millionaires.
Art as a symbolic currency is a vital part of human instinctive life, but art created by the artist strongly opposes this instinctive life; it reflects a thoughtful and fully aware existence. It's understandable, then, that before it can be embraced by instinctive life, it must be distorted through parody to tone down its intense claim to reality. Initially, parody is essential to make it easier to digest, but over time, prolonged exposure might dull even original works of art, so that ultimately, even the greatest masterpieces can turn into beloved symbols for those driven by instinct. In fact, this often happens, and they end up being owned by the wealthy.
I suspect that a very similar process takes place with regard to truth. In order that truth may not outrage too violently the passions and egoisms of the instinctive life it, too, must undergo a process of deformation.
I think a very similar process happens with truth. To avoid shocking the passions and egos of our instinctive nature too much, truth also has to go through a process of distortion.
Society, for example, accepts as much of the ascertainable truth as it can stand at a given period in the form of the doctrine of its organised religion.
Society, for instance, accepts as much of the verifiable truth as it can handle at any given time through the beliefs of its organized religion.
Now what effect would the development of the Great State which this book anticipates have upon all this? First, I suppose that the fact that every one had to work might produce a new reverence, especially in the governing body, for work, a new sense of disgust and horror at wasteful and purposeless work. Mr. Money has written of waste of work; here in unwanted pseudo-art is another colossal waste. Add to this ideal of economy in work the presumption that the workers in every craft would be more thoroughly organised and would have a more decisive voice in the nature and quality of their productions. Under the present system of commercialism the one object, and the complete justification, of producing any article is, that it can be made either by its intrinsic value, or by the fictitious value put upon it by advertisement, to sell with a sufficient profit to the manufacturer. In any socialistic state, I imagine—and to a large extent the Great State will be socialistic at least—there would not be this same automatic justification for manufacture; people would not be induced artificially to buy what they did not want, and in this way a more genuine scale of values would be developed. Moreover, the workman would be in a better position to say how things should be made. After years of a purely commercial standard, there is left even now, in the average workman, a certain bias in favour of sound and reasonable workmanship as opposed to the ingenious manufacture of fatuous and fraudulent objects; and, if we suppose the immediate pressure of sheer necessity to be removed, it is probable that the craftsman, acting through his guild organisations, would determine to some extent the methods of manufacture. Guilds might, indeed, regain something of the political influence that gave us the Gothic cathedrals of the Middle Ages. It is quite probable that this guild influence would act as a check on some innovations in manufacture which, though bringing in a profit, are really disastrous{49} to the community at large. Of such a nature are all the so-called improvements whereby decoration, the whole value of which consists in its expressive power, is multiplied indefinitely by machinery. When once the question of the desirability of any and every production came to be discussed, as it would be in the Great State, it would inevitably follow that some reasonable and scientific classifications would be undertaken with regard to machinery. That is to say, it would be considered in what processes and to what degree machinery ought to replace handiwork, both from the point of view of the community as a whole and from that of the producer. So far as I know, this has never been undertaken even with regard to mere economy, no one having calculated with precision how far the longer life of certain hand-made articles does not more than compensate for increased cost of production. And I suppose that in the Great State other things besides mere economy would come into the calculation. The Great State will live, not hoard.
What impact would the development of the Great State, as anticipated in this book, have on all of this? First, I think that the necessity for everyone to work might create a new respect—especially among the governing body—for labor, along with a fresh sense of disgust and horror at wasteful and pointless work. Mr. Money has written about wasted effort; here, unwanted pseudo-art represents another tremendous waste. Coupling this ideal of efficiency in work with the assumption that workers in every trade would be more organized and have a stronger voice in the nature and quality of their products is essential. Under the current commercial system, the sole purpose, and complete justification, for producing any item is whether it can be sold at a sufficient profit, based on either its intrinsic value or the artificial value created through advertising. In any socialist state, I imagine—and to a significant extent the Great State will be socialist—there wouldn’t be this automatic justification for manufacturing; people wouldn’t be artificially encouraged to buy what they don’t want, leading to a more authentic scale of values. Furthermore, workers would be in a better position to dictate how things should be made. After years of purely commercial standards, the average worker still holds some preference for solid and sensible craftsmanship over the clever production of pointless and deceptive items; and if we assume the immediate pressure of necessity is lifted, it’s likely that craftsmen, through their guild organizations, would have some say in manufacturing methods. Guilds might even regain some political influence reminiscent of what helped create the Gothic cathedrals of the Middle Ages. It’s quite likely that this guild influence would serve as a check on certain manufacturing innovations that, while profitable, could be detrimental to the wider community. This includes all the so-called improvements where decoration—whose value lies entirely in its expressiveness—is indefinitely reproduced by machines. Once the question of the desirability of any and all production is discussed, as it would be in the Great State, it would inevitably lead to some reasonable and scientific classifications regarding machinery. In other words, it would be addressed how and to what extent machinery should replace manual labor, both from the perspective of the community as a whole and from that of the producer. As far as I know, this has never been thoroughly examined, even in terms of pure economy, with no one precisely calculating how far the longer lifespan of certain handmade items offsets higher production costs. I also believe that in the Great State, other factors beyond just economic considerations would be taken into account. The Great State will thrive, not just hoard.
It is probable that in many directions we should extend mechanical operations immensely, that such things as the actual construction of buildings, the mere laying and placing of the walls might become increasingly mechanical. Such methods, if confined to purely structural elements, are capable of beauty of a special kind, since they can express the ordered ideas of proportion, balance, and interval as conceived by the creative mind of the architect. But in process of time one might hope to see a sharp line of division between work of this kind and such purely expressive and non-utilitarian design as we call ornament; and it would be felt clearly that into this field no mechanical device should intrude, that, while ornament might be dispensed with, it could never be imitated, since its only reason for being is that it conveys the vital expressive power of a human mind acting constantly and directly upon matter.
It’s likely that we would greatly expand mechanical operations in many ways, so that things like actual building construction and the simple laying and placing of walls could become increasingly automated. These methods, if limited to purely structural elements, can possess a certain kind of beauty, as they reflect the ordered concepts of proportion, balance, and spacing envisioned by the architect's creative mind. However, over time, we might hope to see a clear distinction between this type of work and what we call ornament, which is purely expressive and non-functional design. It would be evident that no mechanical device should enter this realm; while ornamentation might be unnecessary, it can never be replicated because its only purpose is to convey the vital expressive power of a human mind directly interacting with material.
Finally, I suppose that in the Great State we might hope to see such a considerable levelling of social conditions that the false values put upon art by its symbolising of social status would be largely destroyed and, the pressure of mere opinion being relieved, people would develop some more immediate reaction to the work of art than they can at present achieve.
Finally, I think that in the Great State we might expect to see such a significant leveling of social conditions that the superficial values placed on art because of its association with social status would be mostly eliminated. With the pressure of public opinion lifted, people would have a more genuine response to art than they currently do.
Supposing, then, that under the Great State it was found{50} impossible, at all events at first, to stimulate and organise the abstract creative power of the pure artist, the balance might after all be in favour of the new order if the whole practice of applied art could once more become rational and purposeful. In a world where the objects of daily use and ornament were made with practical common sense, the æsthetic sense would need far less to seek consolation and repose in works of pure art.
Assuming that under the Great State, it was found{50} impossible, at least initially, to inspire and organize the creative power of the true artist, the new order might ultimately be more beneficial if the entire practice of applied art could become rational and purposeful again. In a world where everyday items and decorations were made with practical common sense, the appreciation for pure art would require much less effort to find comfort and peace.
Nevertheless, in the long run mankind will not allow this function, which is necessary to its spiritual life, to lapse entirely. I imagine, however, that it would be much safer to penalise rather than to stimulate such activity, and that simply in order to sift out those with a genuine passion from those who are merely attracted by the apparent ease of the pursuit. I imagine that the artist would naturally turn to one of the applied arts as his means of livelihood; and we should get the artist coming out of the bottega, as he did in fifteenth-century Florence. There are, moreover, innumerable crafts, even besides those that are definitely artistic, which, if pursued for short hours (Sir Leo Money has shown how short these hours might be), would leave a man free to pursue other callings in his leisure.
However, in the long run, humanity won't let this function, which is essential for spiritual life, fade away completely. I think it would be much better to penalize rather than encourage such activity, simply to distinguish those with a true passion from those who are just drawn to the apparent ease of it. I envision that the artist would naturally turn to one of the applied arts for a living; we would see artists emerging from the bottega, just like in fifteenth-century Florence. Additionally, there are countless crafts, even beyond the clearly artistic ones, which if done for shorter hours (as Sir Leo Money has shown how short these hours could be), would allow a person the freedom to explore other pursuits in their spare time.
The majority of poets to-day are artists in this position. It is comparatively rare for any one to make of poetry his actual means of livelihood. Our poets are, first of all, clerks, critics, civil servants, or postmen. I very much doubt if it would be a serious loss to the community if the pure graphic artist were in the same position. That is to say, that all our pictures would be made by amateurs. It is quite possible to suppose that this would be not a loss, but a great gain. The painter’s means of livelihood would probably be some craft in which his artistic powers would be constantly occupied, though at a lower tension and in a humbler way. The Great State aims at human freedom; essentially, it is an organisation for leisure—out of which art grows; it is only a purely bureaucratic Socialism that would attempt to control the æsthetic lives of men.
Most poets today find themselves in this position. It's relatively rare for anyone to actually earn a living from poetry. Our poets are primarily clerks, critics, civil servants, or postmen. I seriously doubt that the community would suffer if visual artists were in the same situation. In other words, all our artworks could come from amateurs. It's quite possible to think that this wouldn't be a loss, but rather a significant gain. A painter's livelihood would likely come from some craft where their artistic skills are continuously engaged, albeit at a lower intensity and in a more modest way. The Great State aims for human freedom; at its core, it's an organization for leisure—out of which art emerges; only a strictly bureaucratic Socialism would try to control people's aesthetic lives.
In the Great State, moreover, and in any sane Socialism, there would be opportunity for a large amount of purely private buying and selling. Mr. Wells’s Modern Utopia, for example, hypothecates a vast superstructure of private trading. A painter might sell his pictures to those who were engaged in more lucrative employment, though one supposes that with the much more equal distribution of wealth the sums available for this would be incomparably smaller than at present; a picture would not be a speculation, but a pleasure, and no one would become an artist in the hope of making a fortune.
In the Great State, and in any reasonable form of Socialism, there would still be plenty of room for private buying and selling. For instance, Mr. Wells’s Modern Utopia imagines a huge framework of private trade. A painter could sell their artwork to people with better-paying jobs, though one would assume that with a much more equal distribution of wealth, the money available for this would be significantly lower than it is now; a painting would be a source of enjoyment, not a financial gamble, and no one would pursue a career as an artist hoping to get rich.
Ultimately, of course, when art had been purified of its present unreality by a prolonged contact with the crafts, society would gain a new confidence in its collective artistic judgment, and might even boldly assume the responsibility which at present it knows it is unable to face. It might choose its poets and painters and philosophers and deep investigators, and make of such men and women a new kind of kings.{52}
Ultimately, when art has been refined through a long interaction with craftsmanship, society will gain new confidence in its collective artistic judgment and may even boldly take on responsibilities it currently feels unable to handle. It could select its poets, painters, philosophers, and deep thinkers, and elevate these individuals to a new kind of leadership.{52}
ART AND SCIENCE[8]
THE author of an illuminating article, “The Place of Science,” in The Athenæum for April 11th, distinguishes between two aspects of intellectual activity in scientific work. Of these two aspects one derives its motive power from curiosity, and this deals with particular facts. It is only when, through curiosity, man has accumulated a mass of particular observations that the second intellectual activity manifests itself, and in this the motive is the satisfaction which the mind gets from the contemplation of inevitable relations. To secure this end the utmost possible generalisation is necessary.
THE author of an insightful article, “The Place of Science,” in The Athenæum for April 11th, points out two aspects of intellectual activity in scientific work. One of these aspects comes from curiosity and focuses on specific facts. It's only when, through curiosity, we gather a plethora of specific observations that the second intellectual activity appears, driven by the satisfaction the mind gains from understanding inevitable relationships. To achieve this, the greatest possible generalization is needed.
In a later article S. says boldly that this satisfaction is an æsthetic satisfaction: “It is in its æsthetic value that the justification of the scientific theory is to be found, and with it the justification of the scientific method.” I should like to pose to S. at this point the question of whether a theory that disregarded facts would have equal value for science with one which agreed with facts. I suppose he would say No; and yet, so far as I can see, there would be no purely æsthetic reason why it should not. The æsthetic value of a theory would surely depend solely on the perfection and complexity of the unity attained, and I imagine that many systems of scholastic theology, and even some more recent systems of metaphysic, have only this æsthetic value. I suspect that the æsthetic value of a theory is not really adequate to the intellectual effort entailed unless, as in a true scientific theory (by which I mean a theory which embraces all the known relevant facts), the æsthetic value is reinforced by the curiosity value which comes in when we believe it to be true. But now, returning to art, let me try to describe rather more clearly its analogies with science.
In a later article, S. confidently states that this satisfaction is an aesthetic satisfaction: “It is in its aesthetic value that the justification of the scientific theory is to be found, and with it the justification of the scientific method.” At this point, I’d like to ask S. whether a theory that ignores facts would hold the same value for science as one that aligns with facts. I assume he’d say no; yet, from what I can see, there’s no purely aesthetic reason why it shouldn’t. The aesthetic value of a theory would surely depend entirely on the perfection and complexity of the unity achieved, and I imagine that many systems of scholastic theology, and even some more recent systems of metaphysics, possess only this aesthetic value. I suspect that the aesthetic value of a theory isn’t truly sufficient for the intellectual effort required unless, as in a genuine scientific theory (by which I mean one that includes all the known relevant facts), the aesthetic value is enhanced by the curiosity value that comes in when we believe it to be true. But now, returning to art, let me try to describe its similarities with science more clearly.
Both of these aspects—the particularising and the generalising—have their counterparts in art. Curiosity impels the artist to the{53} consideration of every possible form in nature: under its stimulus he tends to accept each form in all its particularity as a given, unalterable fact. The other kind of intellectual activity impels the artist to attempt the reduction of all forms, as it were, to some common denominator which will make them comparable with one another. It impels him to discover some æsthetically intelligible principle in various forms, and even to envisage the possibility of some kind of abstract form in the æsthetic contemplation of which the mind would attain satisfaction—a satisfaction curiously parallel to that which the mind gets from the intellectual recognition of abstract truth.
Both of these aspects—the specific and the general—have their parallels in art. Curiosity drives the artist to explore every possible form in nature: fueled by this, they tend to accept each form in all its uniqueness as a fixed, unchangeable reality. The other type of intellectual activity pushes the artist to try to reduce all forms to a common denominator that makes them comparable with one another. It encourages them to find some aesthetically meaningful principle in different forms, and even to imagine the possibility of some kind of abstract form that the mind could contemplate, attaining a satisfaction that interestingly mirrors the satisfaction derived from understanding abstract truth.
If we consider the effects of these two kinds of intellectual activity, or rather their exact analogues, in art, we have to note that in so far as the artist’s curiosity remains a purely intellectual curiosity it interferes with the perfection and purity of the work of art by introducing an alien and non-æsthetic element and appealing to non-æsthetic desires; in so far as it merely supplies the artist with new motives and a richer material out of which to build his designs, it is useful but subsidiary. Thus the objection to a “subject picture,” in so far as one remains conscious of the subject as something outside of, and apart from, the form, is a valid objection to the intrusion of intellect, of however rudimentary a kind, into an æsthetic whole. The ordinary historical pictures of our annual shows will furnish perfect examples of such an intrusion, since they exhibit innumerable appeals to intellectual recognitions without which the pictures would be meaningless. Without some previous knowledge of Caligula or Mary Queen of Scots we are likely to miss our way in a great deal of what passes for art to-day.
When we think about the effects of these two types of intellectual activity, or their exact equivalents, in art, we need to recognize that as long as the artist’s curiosity remains purely intellectual, it disrupts the perfection and purity of the artwork by introducing a foreign and non-aesthetic element that appeals to non-aesthetic desires. When it simply provides the artist with new motivations and a richer material to create from, it's useful but secondary. Therefore, the criticism of a “subject picture,” as long as one remains aware of the subject as something separate from the form, is a valid concern about the intrusion of intellect, no matter how basic, into an aesthetic whole. The typical historical paintings we see in annual exhibitions offer perfect examples of this intrusion, as they contain countless appeals to intellectual understandings that would make the paintings meaningless otherwise. Without some prior knowledge of Caligula or Mary Queen of Scots, we might easily miss the point of much of what is considered art today.
The case of the generalising intellect, or rather its analogue, in art is more difficult. Here the recognition of relations is immediate and sensational—perhaps we ought to consider it as curiously akin to those cases of mathematical geniuses who have immediate intuition of mathematical relations which it is beyond their powers to prove—so that it is by analogy that we may talk of it at all as intellectual. But the analogy is so close that I hope it may justify the use I here suggest. For in both cases the utmost possible generalisation is aimed at, and in both the mind is held in delighted equilibrium by the contemplation of the inevitable relations of all the parts in the{54} whole, so that no need exists to make reference to what is outside the unity, and this becomes for the time being a universe.
The situation with the generalizing mind, or its equivalent in art, is more complex. Here, recognizing relationships happens instantly and emotionally—maybe we should think of it as strangely similar to those mathematical geniuses who have an immediate understanding of mathematical relationships that they cannot prove. It's only by analogy that we can even refer to it as intellectual. But the analogy is so strong that I hope it supports the idea I'm putting forward. In both scenarios, the goal is to achieve the highest level of generalization, and in both, the mind finds joyful balance by observing the inevitable connections of all the parts in the{54} whole, meaning there's no need to reference anything outside of that unity, creating a temporary universe.
It will be seen how close the analogies are between the methods and aims of art and science, and yet there remains an obstinate doubt in the mind whether at any point they are identical. Probably in order to get much further we must wait for the psychologists to solve a number of problems; meanwhile this at least must be pointed out—that, allowing that the motives of science are emotional, many of its processes are purely intellectual, that is to say, mechanical. They could be performed by a perfectly non-sentient, emotionless brain, whereas at no point in the process of art can we drop feeling. There is something in the common phraseology by which we talk of seeing a point or an argument, whereas we feel the harmony of a work of art; and for some reason we attach a more constant emotional quality to feeling than to seeing, which is so constantly used for coldly practical ends.
It will be clear how similar the methods and goals of art and science are, yet there's still a stubborn doubt about whether they are the same at any point. To make more progress, we might have to wait for psychologists to address several issues; in the meantime, it’s important to note that while the motivations behind science can be emotional, many of its processes are purely intellectual, meaning they’re mechanical. They could be carried out by a completely non-sentient, emotionless brain, while in art, we can never remove emotion from the process. There’s something in the way we commonly express ourselves when we talk about seeing a point or an argument, whereas we feel the harmony of a piece of art; and for some reason, we associate a more consistent emotional quality with feeling than with seeing, which is often used for practical, unemotional purposes.
From the merest rudiments of pure sensation up to the highest efforts of design each point in the process of art is inevitably accompanied by pleasure; it cannot proceed without it. If we describe the process of art as a logic of sensation, we must remember that the premises are sensations, and that the conclusion can only be drawn from them by one who is in an emotional state with regard to them. Thus a harmony in music cannot be perceived by a person who merely hears accurately the notes which compose it—it can only be recognised when the relations of those notes to one another are accompanied by emotion. It is quite true that the recognition of inevitability in thought is normally accompanied by a pleasurable emotion, and that the desire for this mental pleasure is the motive force which impels to the making of scientific theory. But the inevitability of the relations remains equally definite and demonstrable whether the emotion accompanies it or not, whereas an æsthetic harmony simply does not exist without the emotional state. The harmony is not true (to use our analogy) unless it is felt with emotion.
From the simplest basics of pure sensation to the most intricate designs, every step in the process of art is unavoidably linked to pleasure; it can't happen without it. If we talk about the process of art as a logic of sensation, we need to keep in mind that the starting points are sensations, and the conclusion can only be reached by someone who has an emotional response to them. For example, a harmony in music can't be truly appreciated by someone who just hears the notes clearly; it can only be recognized when the relationships between those notes are felt emotionally. It's true that realizing the necessity in thought usually comes with a pleasurable emotion, and that the pursuit of this mental enjoyment drives the creation of scientific theories. However, the necessity of those relationships remains clear and can be proven whether there's emotion involved or not, while an aesthetic harmony simply doesn’t exist without an emotional response. The harmony is not true (to use our analogy) unless it’s experienced with emotion.
None the less, perhaps, the highest pleasure in art is identical with the highest pleasure in scientific theory. The emotion which accompanies the clear recognition of unity in a complex seems to be so similar in art and in science that it is difficult not to suppose that{55} they are psychologically the same. It is, as it were, the final stage of both processes. This unity-emotion in science supervenes upon a process of pure mechanical reasoning; in art it supervenes upon a process of which emotion has all along been an essential concomitant.
Nonetheless, perhaps the greatest pleasure in art is the same as the greatest pleasure in scientific theory. The emotion that comes with clearly recognizing unity in something complex seems to be very similar in both art and science, making it hard not to believe that{55} they are psychologically the same. It's like the final stage of both processes. This feeling of unity in science arises after a process of purely mechanical reasoning; in art, it arises from a process where emotion has always been an essential part.
It may be that in the complete apprehension of a work of art there occurs more than one kind of feeling. There is generally a basis of purely physiological pleasure, as in seeing pure colours or hearing pure sounds; then there is the specifically æsthetic emotion by means of which the necessity of relations is apprehended, and which corresponds in science to the purely logical process; and finally there is the unity-emotion, which may not improbably be of an identical kind in both art and science.
It’s possible that understanding a piece of art involves multiple feelings. There’s usually a foundation of pure physiological pleasure, like seeing vibrant colors or hearing clear sounds; then there’s the specific aesthetic emotion that helps us understand the need for connections, which corresponds to the purely logical process in science; and finally, there’s the unity emotion, which likely shares a similar nature in both art and science.
In the art of painting we may distinguish between the unity of texture and the unity of design. I know quite well that these are not really completely separable, and that they are to some extent mutually dependent; but they may be regarded as separate for the purpose of focussing our attention. Certainly we can think of pictures in which the general architecture of the design is in no way striking or remarkable which yet please us by the perfection of the texture, that is to say, the ease with which we apprehend the necessary relationship of one shape, tone or colour with its immediately surrounding shapes, tones or colours; our æsthetic sense is continually aroused and satisfied by the succession of inevitable relationships. On the other hand, we know of works of art in which the unity and complexity of the texture strike us far less than the inevitable and significant relationship of the main divisions of the design—pictures in which we should say that the composition was the most striking beauty. It is when the composition of a picture, adequately supported as it must be by significance of texture, reveals to us the most surprising and yet inevitable relationships that we get most strongly the final unity-emotion of a work of art. It is these pictures that are, as S. would say of certain theories, the most significant for contemplation. Nor before such works can we help implicitly attributing to their authors the same kind of power which in science we should call “great intellect,” though perhaps in both the term “great imaginative organisation” would be better.{56}
In painting, we can differentiate between the unity of texture and the unity of design. I understand that these two aren’t entirely separable and they rely on each other to some degree, but we can look at them separately to better focus our attention. There are definitely artworks where the overall design isn’t particularly striking, yet they appeal to us because of the flawless texture—meaning how easily we grasp the necessary connections between shapes, tones, or colors and their immediate surroundings; our aesthetic sense is constantly engaged and satisfied by the flow of inevitable relationships. Conversely, there are artworks where the unity and intricacy of the texture stand out much less than the obvious and meaningful relationships among the main parts of the design—pieces where we would conclude that the composition is the most impressive beauty. It’s when a painting’s composition, properly supported by meaningful texture, reveals surprising yet necessary relationships that we truly experience the final unity-emotion of the artwork. These paintings are, as S. might say about certain theories, the most significant for contemplation. Before such works, we can’t help but implicitly attribute to their creators the same kind of ability that we would call “great intellect” in science, although perhaps “great imaginative organization” would be a more fitting term in both cases.{56}
THE ART OF THE BUSHMEN[9]
IN the history of mankind drawing has at different times and among different races expressed so many different conceptions, and has used such various means, that it would seem to be not one art, but many. It would seem, indeed, that it has its origins in several quite distinct instincts of the human race, and it may not be altogether unimportant even for the modern draughtsman to investigate these instincts in their simpler manifestations in order to check and control his own methods. The primitive drawing of our own race is singularly like that of children. Its most striking peculiarity is the extent to which it is dominated by the concepts of language. In a child’s drawing we find a number of forms which have scarcely any reference to actual appearances, but which directly symbolise the most significant concepts of the thing represented. For a child, a man is the sum of the concept’s head (which in turn consists of eyes, nose, mouth), arms, hands (five fingers), legs, feet. Torso is not a concept which interests him, and it is, therefore, usually reduced to a single line which serves to link the concept-symbol head with those of the legs. The child does, of course, know that the figure thus drawn is not like a man, but it is a kind of hieroglyphic script for a man, and satisfies his desire for expression. Precisely the same phenomenon occurs in primitive art; the symbols for concepts gradually take on more and more of the likeness to appearances, but the mode of approach remains even in comparatively advanced periods the same. The artist does not seek to transfer a visual sensation to paper, but to express a mental image which is coloured by his conceptual habits.
IN the history of humanity, drawing has at various times and across different cultures represented a wide range of ideas and used many different techniques, suggesting that it is not just one art form but many. It seems to have its roots in several distinct human instincts, and it might be useful for today’s artists to explore these instincts in their simpler forms to refine and guide their own methods. The primitive drawings of our own species are remarkably similar to those of children. One of their most noticeable features is how much they are influenced by language. In children’s drawings, we often find shapes that barely resemble what they depict, yet they directly symbolize the most important ideas of the subject. For a child, a man is represented by the sum of the head (made up of eyes, nose, mouth), arms, hands (five fingers), legs, and feet. The torso isn’t a concept that interests them, so it’s usually reduced to a single line connecting the head to the legs. Children know that their drawing doesn't look like a real man, but it acts as a kind of shorthand for a man, fulfilling their need for expression. The same thing happens in primitive art; the symbols for concepts gradually become more similar to actual appearances, but the overall approach remains consistent even in more advanced times. The artist isn’t trying to recreate a visual sensation on paper; instead, they are expressing a mental image shaped by their conceptual understanding.
Prof. Loewy[10] has investigated the laws which govern representation in early art, and has shown that the influence of the early{57} artist’s ideas of representation persist in Greek sculpture down to the time of Lysippus. He enumerates seven peculiarities of early drawing, of which the most important are that the figures are shown with each of their parts in its broadest aspect, and that the forms are stylised—i.e. present linear formations that are regular or tend to regularity.
Prof. Loewy[10] has examined the rules governing representation in early art and has demonstrated that the early{57} artist’s concepts of representation continue to influence Greek sculpture up until the era of Lysippus. He lists seven characteristics of early drawing, with the most significant being that the figures are depicted with each part shown in its most pronounced form, and that the shapes are stylized—i.e. they present linear patterns that are consistent or tend towards consistency.
Of the first of these peculiarities Egyptian and Assyrian sculpture, even of the latest and most developed periods, afford constant examples. We see there the head in profile, the eye full face, the shoulders and breast full face, and by a sudden twist in the body the legs and feet again in profile. In this way each part is presented in that aspect which most clearly expresses its corresponding visual concepts. Thus a foot is much more clearly denoted by its profile view than by the rendering of its frontal appearance—while no one who was asked to think of an eye would visualise it to himself in any other than a full-face view. In such art, then, the body is twisted about so that each part may be represented by that aspect which the mental image aroused by the name of the part would have, and the figure becomes an ingenious compound of typical conceptual images. In the case of the head two aspects are accepted as symbolic of the concept “head,” the profile and the full-face; but it is very late in the development of art before men are willing to accept any intermediate position as intelligible or satisfactory. It is generally supposed that early art avoids foreshortening because of its difficulty. One may suppose rather that it is because the foreshortened view of a member corresponds so ill with the normal conceptual image, and is therefore not accepted as sufficiently expressive of the idea. Yet another of the peculiarities named by Prof. Loewy must be mentioned, namely, that the “conformation and movement of the figures and their parts are limited to a few typical shapes.” And these movements are always of the simplest kinds, since they are governed by the necessity of displaying each member in its broadest and most explicit aspect. In particular the crossing of one limb over another is avoided as confusing.
Of the first of these unique traits, Egyptian and Assyrian sculpture, even in the latest and most advanced periods, provides constant examples. We see the head in profile, the eye from the front, the shoulders and chest from the front, and with a sudden twist of the body, the legs and feet again in profile. This way, each part is shown in the perspective that best represents its corresponding visual concept. For instance, a foot is much more clearly depicted from the side than from the front, while no one asked to think of an eye would visualize it any way other than from the front. In this art, the body is twisted so that each part can be shown from the angle that matches the mental image conjured by the name of that part, resulting in a clever mix of typical conceptual images. For the head, two views are accepted as symbols of the concept “head”: profile and full-face; however, it takes a long time in the progression of art before people are willing to accept any middle ground as understandable or satisfying. It’s often thought that early art avoids foreshortening because it’s challenging. One could argue instead that it’s because the foreshortened view of a body part doesn’t align well with the usual mental image, making it less expressive of the idea. Another of the peculiarities noted by Prof. Loewy is that “the shape and movement of the figures and their parts are limited to a few typical forms.” These movements are always the simplest, as they are driven by the need to present each member in its most straightforward and explicit form. Specifically, crossing one limb over another is avoided as it can be confusing.
Such in brief outline are some of the main principles of drawing both among primitive peoples and among our own children. It is not a little surprising then to find, when we turn to Miss Tongue’s{58} careful copies of the drawings executed by the Bushmen of South Africa[11] that the principles are more often contradicted than exemplified. We find, it is true, a certain barbaric crudity and simplicity which give these drawings a superficial resemblance to children’s drawings or those of primitive times, but a careful examination will show how different they are. The drawings are of different periods, though none of them probably are of any considerable antiquity, since the habit of painting over an artist’s work when once he was forgotten obtained among the bushmen no less than with more civilised people. These drawings are also of very different degrees of skill. They represent for the most part scenes of the chase and war, dances and festivals, and in one case there is an illustration to a bushman story and one figure is supposed to represent a ghost. There is no evidence of deliberate decorative purpose in these paintings. The figures are cast upon the walls of the cave in such a way as to represent, roughly, the actual scenes.[12] Nothing could be more unlike primitive art than some of these scenes. For instance, the battle fought between two tribes over the possession of some cattle, is entirely unlike battle scenes such as we find in early Assyrian reliefs. There the battle is schematic, all the soldiers of one side are in profile to right, all the soldiers of the opposing side are in profile to left. The whole scene is perfectly clear to the intelligence, it follows the mental image of what a battle ought to be, but is entirely unlike what a battle ever is. Now, in the Bushman drawing, there is nothing truly schematic; it is difficult to find out the soldiers of the two sides; they are all mixed up in a confused hurly-burly, some charging, others flying, and here and there single combats going on at a distance from the main battle. But more than this, the men are in every conceivable attitude, running, standing, kneeling, crouching, or turning sharply round in the middle of flight to face the enemy once more.{59}
Such is a brief overview of some of the main principles of drawing among both primitive peoples and our own children. It’s rather surprising then, when we look at Miss Tongue’s{58} detailed copies of the drawings made by the Bushmen of South Africa[11], that the principles are often contradicted rather than demonstrated. True, there’s a certain roughness and simplicity that gives these drawings a superficial similarity to children’s art or those from primitive times, but a closer look reveals how different they really are. The drawings come from various periods, though none are likely very old, since the practice of painting over an artist’s work once he was forgotten existed among the Bushmen just as it did among more civilized people. Additionally, these drawings display a wide range of skill levels. Most depict scenes of hunting and warfare, dances, and celebrations, and in one case, there’s an illustration of a Bushman story with one figure representing a ghost. There’s no sign of a deliberate decorative intention in these paintings. The figures are portrayed on the cave walls in a way that roughly represents the actual events.[12] Nothing could be further from primitive art than some of these scenes. For example, the battle between two tribes over cattle looks nothing like battle scenes we see in early Assyrian reliefs. In those, the battle is laid out schematically, with all the soldiers from one side in profile to the right and all the opposing soldiers in profile to the left. The whole scene is easy to understand, following the mental image of what a battle should look like, but it bears no resemblance to how battles actually occur. Conversely, in the Bushman drawing, there’s nothing schematic; it’s hard to distinguish the soldiers from the two sides; they are all jumbled together in a chaotic mix, some charging, others fleeing, with distant single combats happening away from the main fight. Moreover, the men are depicted in every imaginable position—running, standing, kneeling, crouching, or suddenly turning around during flight to face the enemy again.{59}
In fact we have, in all its confusion, all its indeterminate variety and accident, a rough silhouette of the actual appearance of such a scene as viewed from above, for the Bushman makes this sacrifice of actual appearance to lucidity of statement—that he represents the figures as spread out over the ground, and not as seen one behind another.
In reality, we have, despite all its confusion and unpredictable differences, a rough outline of what such a scene would look like from above. The Bushman sacrifices the true appearance for clarity in presentation—he shows the figures spread out across the ground instead of one behind the other.
Or take again Plate XI of Miss Tongue’s album; the scene is the Veldt with elands and rheboks scattered over its surface. The animals are arranged in the most natural and casual manner; sometimes in this case part of one animal is hidden by the animal in front; but what strikes one most is the fact that extremely complicated poses are rendered with the same ease as the more frequent profile view, and that momentary actions are treated with photographic verisimilitude. See Figs. 1 and 2.
Or take again Plate XI of Miss Tongue’s album; the scene is the Veldt with elands and rheboks scattered across it. The animals are arranged in a natural and casual way; sometimes part of one animal is hidden by the one in front. But what stands out the most is how very complex poses are depicted with the same ease as the more common profile views, and that fleeting actions are shown with photographic accuracy. See Figs. 1 and 2.
Another surprising instance of this is shown in Fig. 3, taken from Plate XIX of Miss Tongue’s book, and giving a rhebok seen from behind in a most difficult and complicated attitude. Or again, the man running in Fig. 5. Here is the silhouette of a most{60} complicated gesture with foreshortening of one thigh and crossing of the arm holding the bow over the torso, rendered with apparent certainty and striking verisimilitude. Most curious of all are the cases of which Fig. 4 is an example, of animals trotting, in which the gesture is seen by us to be true only because our slow and imperfect vision has been helped out by the instantaneous photograph. Fifty years ago we should have rejected such a rendering as absurd; we now know it to be a correct statement of one movement in the action of trotting.
Another surprising example of this is shown in Fig. 3, taken from Plate XIX of Miss Tongue’s book, which depicts a rhebok seen from behind in a very challenging and intricate pose. Or consider the man running in Fig. 5. Here is the silhouette of a very complicated gesture with one thigh foreshortened and the arm holding the bow crossing over the torso, depicted with clear confidence and striking realism. Most interesting of all are the examples in Fig. 4, showing animals trotting, where the gesture appears accurate to us only because our slow and imperfect vision has been aided by the instantaneous photograph. Fifty years ago, we would have dismissed such a representation as ridiculous; now we understand it to accurately capture one movement in the action of trotting.
Another point to be noticed is that in primitive and in children’s art such features as eyes, ears, horns, tails, since they correspond to well-marked concepts, always tend to be drawn disproportionately large and prominent. Now, in the Bushman drawings, the eye, the most significant of all, is frequently omitted, and when represented bears its true proportion to the head. Similarly, horns, ears, and tails are never exaggerated. Indeed, however faulty these drawings may be, they have one great quality, namely, that each figure is seen as a single entity, and the general character of the silhouette is aimed at rather than a sum of the parts. Those who have taught drawing to children will know with what infinite pains civilised man arrives at this power.
Another point to note is that in primitive and children's art, features like eyes, ears, horns, and tails, since they represent well-defined concepts, are typically drawn disproportionately large and noticeable. However, in Bushman drawings, the eye, the most important feature of all, is often left out, and when it is shown, it reflects its actual size relative to the head. Likewise, horns, ears, and tails are never exaggerated. Indeed, despite any flaws these drawings may have, they possess a significant quality: each figure is perceived as a whole, with the overall shape being prioritized over the individual parts. Those who have taught drawing to children will understand the immense effort that civilized people put into achieving this ability.
By way of contrast to these extraordinary performances of the Bushman draughtsman, I give in outline, Fig. 6, the two horses of a chariot on an early (Dipylon) Greek vase. The man who drew it was incomparably more of an artist; but how entirely his intellectual and conceptual way of handling phenomena has obscured his vision! His two horses are a sum of concept-symbols, arranged with great orderliness and with a decorative feeling, but without any sort of likeness to appearance. Mr. Balfour, in his preface to Miss Tongue’s book, notices briefly some of these striking characteristics of the Bushman drawings. He says:—
In contrast to the remarkable works of the Bushman artist, I present in outline, Fig. 6, the two horses of a chariot from an early (Dipylon) Greek vase. The person who drew it was infinitely more skilled as an artist; however, his intellectual and conceptual approach to depicting reality has completely clouded his perception! His two horses are a collection of concept-symbols, organized neatly and with a sense of decoration, but lacking any resemblance to what they actually look like. Mr. Balfour, in his preface to Miss Tongue’s book, briefly remarks on some of these striking features of the Bushman drawings. He states:—
“The paintings are remarkable not only for the realism exhibited by so many, but also for a freedom from the limitation to delineation in profile which characterises for the most part the drawings of primitive peoples, especially where animals are concerned. Attitudes of a kind difficult to render were ventured upon without hesitation,{61} and an appreciation even of the rudiments of perspective is occasionally to be noted, though only in a crude and uncertain form. The practice of endeavouring to represent more than could be seen at one time, a habit so characteristic of the art of primitive peoples as also of civilised children, is far less noticeable in Bushman art than might have been expected from the rudimentary general culture of these people, and one does not see instances of both eyes being indicated upon a profile face, or a mouth in profile on a full face, such as are so familiar in the undeveloped art of children and of most backward races.”
The paintings are impressive not just because of the realism displayed by many, but also for their freedom from the limitations of profile drawing that mostly defines the artwork of primitive cultures, especially when it comes to animals. They confidently explored poses that are hard to capture,{61} and you can occasionally see a basic understanding of perspective, although it's still pretty rough and not quite accurate. The tendency to show more than what could be seen at once, a common trait in the art of primitive people as well as in young kids, is much less evident in Bushman art than you might expect given these people's simple overall culture, and you don't see examples of both eyes being shown on a profile face, or a mouth in profile on a full face, which are common in the naive art of children and many less developed cultures.
Since, then, Bushman drawing has little analogy to the primitive art of our own races, to what can we relate it? The Bushmen of Australia have apparently something of the same power of transcribing pure visual images, but the most striking case is that of Palæolithic man. In the caves of the Dordogne and of Altamira in Spain, Palæolithic man has left paintings which date from about 10,000 B.C., in which, as far as mere naturalism of representation of animals goes, he has surpassed anything that not only our own primitive peoples, but even the most accomplished animal draughtsmen have ever achieved. Fig. 7 shows in outline a bison from Altamira. The certainty and completeness of the pose, the perfect rhythm and the astonishing verisimilitude of the movement are evident even in this. The Altamira drawings show a much higher level of accomplishment than those of the Bushmen, but the general likeness is so great as to have suggested the idea that the Bushmen are descendants of Palæolithic man who have remained at the same rudimentary stage as regards the other arts of life, and have retained something of their unique power of visual transcription.
Since Bushman drawing has little in common with the primitive art of our own cultures, what can we compare it to? The Bushmen of Australia seem to have a similar ability to capture pure visual images, but the most notable example is that of Paleolithic man. In the caves of the Dordogne and Altamira in Spain, Paleolithic man created paintings dating back to around 10,000 B.C.. In terms of naturalistic representation of animals, he has surpassed not only our own primitive peoples but even the most skilled animal artists of today. Fig. 7 shows an outline of a bison from Altamira. The certainty and completeness of the pose, the perfect rhythm, and the remarkable realism of the movement are all clear, even in this. The Altamira drawings demonstrate a much higher level of skill than those of the Bushmen, yet the overall resemblance is so strong that it raises the idea that the Bushmen might be descendants of Paleolithic man who have stayed at a similar basic stage in other aspects of life but have maintained some of their unique talent for visual depiction.
Whether this be so or not, it is to be noted that all the peoples whose drawing shows this peculiar power of visualisation belong to what we call the lowest of savages; they are certainly the least civilisable, and the South African Bushmen are regarded by other native{62} races in much the same way that we look upon negroes. It would seem not impossible that the very perfection of vision, and presumably of the other senses[13] with which the Bushmen and Palæolithic man were endowed, fitted them so perfectly to their surroundings that there was no necessity to develop the mechanical arts beyond the elementary instruments of the chase. We must suppose that Neolithic man, on the other hand, was less perfectly adapted to his surroundings, but that his sensual defects were more than compensated for by increased intellectual power. This greater intellectual power manifested itself in his desire to classify phenomena, and the conceptual view of nature began to predominate. And it was this habit of thinking of things in terms of concepts which deprived him for ages of the power to see what they looked like. With Neolithic man drawing came to express man’s thought about things rather than his sensations of them, or rather, when he tried to reproduce his sensations, his habits of thought intervened, and dictated to his hand orderly, lucid, but entirely non-naturalistic forms.
Whether this is true or not, it’s important to note that all the people whose drawings show this unique ability to visualize belong to what we call the lowest level of savages; they are definitely the least civilizable, and the South African Bushmen are viewed by other native races much like how we view black people. It seems possible that the very excellence of their vision, and likely their other senses, with which the Bushmen and Paleolithic man were gifted, allowed them to adapt so well to their environment that there was no need to develop mechanical skills beyond basic tools for hunting. We can assume that Neolithic man, on the other hand, was less perfectly suited to his surroundings, but his sensory shortcomings were more than offset by greater intellectual capabilities. This increased intellectual ability was evident in his desire to categorize phenomena, and a conceptual understanding of nature started to dominate. It was this tendency to think about things in terms of concepts that deprived him for ages of the ability to see how things truly appeared. With Neolithic man, drawing began to represent his thoughts about things rather than his sensations of them, or rather, when he attempted to depict his sensations, his thought processes intervened, guiding his hand to create orderly, clear, but completely non-naturalistic forms.
How deeply these visual-conceptual habits of Neolithic man have sunk into our natures may be seen by their effects upon hysterical patients, a statement which I owe to the kindness of Dr. Henry Head, F.R.S. If the word “chest” is mentioned most people see a vague image of a flat surface on which are marked the sternum and the pectoral muscles; when the word “back” is given, they see another flat or almost flat surface with markings of the spine and the shoulder-blades; but scarcely any one, having these two mental images called up, thinks of them as parts of a continuous cylindrical body. Now, in the case of some hysterical patients anæsthesia is found just over some part of the body which has been isolated from the rest in thought by means of the conceptual image. It will occur, for instance, in the chest, but will not go beyond the limits which the conceptualised visual image of a chest defines. Or it will be associated with the concept hand, and will stop short at the wrists. It is not surprising, then, that a mode of handling the continuum of natural appearance, which dictates even the behaviour of disease, should have profoundly modified all artistic representations{63} of nature since the conceptual habit first became strongly marked in Neolithic man. An actual definition of drawing given by a child may be quoted in this connection, “First I think and then I draw a line round my think.”
How deeply these visual-conceptual habits of Neolithic people have become part of our nature can be seen in their effects on hysterical patients, a point I owe to the kindness of Dr. Henry Head, F.R.S. When the term “chest” is mentioned, most people picture a vague image of a flat surface marked with the sternum and pectoral muscles; when “back” is mentioned, they envision another flat or nearly flat surface with markings of the spine and shoulder blades. However, hardly anyone, when these two mental images are evoked, thinks of them as parts of a continuous cylindrical body. In some hysterical patients, numbness is found just over a part of the body that has been mentally separated from the rest through the conceptual image. For example, it may occur in the chest but won't extend beyond the boundaries defined by the conceptualized visual image of the chest. Or it may be linked to the concept of the hand and will stop at the wrists. It’s not surprising, then, that a way of perceiving the continuum of the natural world, which even influences the behavior of disease, has significantly altered all artistic representations of nature since the conceptual habit first became pronounced in Neolithic people. A child’s definition of drawing fits here: “First I think and then I draw a line around my thought.”{63}
It would be an exaggeration to suppose that Palæolithic and Bushman drawings are entirely uninfluenced by the concepts which even the most primitive people must form. Indeed, the preference for the profile view of animals—though as we have seen other aspects are frequent—would alone indicate this, but they appear to have been at a stage of intellectual development where the concepts were not so clearly grasped as to have begun to interfere with perception, and where therefore the retinal image passed into a clear memory picture with scarcely any intervening mental process. In the art of even civilised man we may, I think, find great variations in the extent to which the conceptualising of visual images has proceeded. Egyptian and Assyrian art remained intensely conceptual throughout, no serious attempt was made to give greater verisimilitude to the symbols employed. The Mycenæan artists, on the other hand, seem to have been appreciably more perceptual, but the Greeks returned to an intensely conceptualised symbolism in which some of their greatest works of art were expressed, and only very gradually did they modify their formulæ so as to admit of some approach to verisimilitude, and even so the appeal to vision was rather by way of correcting and revising accepted conceptual images than as the foundation of a work of art. The art of China, and still more of Japan, has been distinctly more perceptual. Indeed, the Japanese drawings of birds and animals approach more nearly than those of any other civilised people to the immediacy and rapidity of transcription of Bushman and Palæolithic art. The Bushman silhouettes of cranes (Fig. 8) might almost have come from a Japanese screen{64} Like Japanese drawings, they show an alertness to accept the silhouette as a single whole instead of reconstructing it from separately apprehended parts. It is partly due to Japanese influence that our own Impressionists have made an attempt to get back to that ultra-primitive directness of vision. Indeed they deliberately sought to deconceptualise art. The artist of to-day has therefore to some extent a choice before him of whether he will think form like the early artists of European races or merely see it like the Bushmen. Whichever his choice, the study of these drawings can hardly fail to be of profound interest. The Bushmen paintings on the walls of caves and sheltered rocks are fast disappearing; the race itself, of which Miss Bleek gives a fascinating account, is now nothing but a remnant. The treatment that they have received at the hands of the white settlers does not seem to have been conspicuously more sympathetic or intelligent than that meted out to them by negro conquerors, and thus the opportunity of solving some of the most interesting problems of human development has been for ever lost. The gratitude of all students of art is due to Miss Tongue and Miss Bleek, by whose zeal and industry these remains of a most curious phase of primitive art have been adequately recorded.{65}
It would be an exaggeration to think that Paleolithic and Bushman drawings are completely unaffected by the ideas that even the most primitive people must create. In fact, the preference for side views of animals—although, as we’ve seen, other angles are common—suggests this. However, they seem to have reached an intellectual stage where their concepts weren’t clearly defined enough to interfere with perception, allowing the visual image to become a clear memory with almost no mental process in between. In art, even among civilized people, there are considerable differences in how much visual images have been conceptualized. Egyptian and Assyrian art maintained a strong conceptual nature throughout, with no serious attempts made to give more realism to the symbols used. Mycenaean artists, on the other hand, appear to have been more perceptually focused, but the Greeks reverted to a highly conceptual symbolism in some of their greatest artworks, gradually modifying their formulas to allow for a degree of realism. Even then, their appeal to vision was more about correcting and refining established concepts than about forming a work of art from direct observation. The art of China, and especially Japan, has been notably more perceptual. Indeed, Japanese drawings of birds and animals come closest to the immediacy and speed of the Bushman and Paleolithic art. The Bushman silhouettes of cranes (Fig. 8) could almost belong to a Japanese screen. Like Japanese drawings, they show a readiness to accept the silhouette as a complete image rather than reconstructing it from separately understood parts. It’s partly due to Japanese influence that our own Impressionists have tried to reclaim that ultra-primitive straightforwardness of vision. They intentionally sought to strip art of conceptualization. Today’s artists, therefore, have some choice: they can either think about form like the early European artists or just see it like the Bushmen. Regardless of their choice, studying these drawings is sure to be deeply interesting. The Bushmen's paintings on cave walls and sheltered rocks are quickly disappearing; the race itself, as Miss Bleek fascinatingly describes, is now just a remnant. The treatment they’ve received from white settlers hasn't been notably more compassionate or intelligent than that from Black conquerors, leading to the permanent loss of opportunities to explore some of the most intriguing questions of human development. All art students owe gratitude to Miss Tongue and Miss Bleek, whose dedication and hard work have ensured these remnants of a curious phase of primitive art are well-documented.
NEGRO SCULPTURE[14]
WHAT a comfortable mental furniture the generalisations of a century ago must have afforded! What a right little, tight little, round little world it was when Greece was the only source of culture, when Greek art, even in Roman copies, was the only indisputable art, except for some Renaissance repetitions! Philosophy, the love of truth, liberty, architecture, poetry, drama, and for all we knew music—all these were the fruits of a special kind of life, each assisted the development of the other, each was really dependent on all the rest. Consequently if we could only learn the Greek lessons of political freedom and intellectual self-consciousness all the rest would be added unto us.
WHAT a comfortable way of thinking the generalizations from a century ago must have provided! What a neat, compact, little world it was when Greece was the sole source of culture, when Greek art, even in Roman replicas, was the only undeniable art, aside from some Renaissance copies! Philosophy, the pursuit of truth, freedom, architecture, poetry, drama, and for all we knew music—all these were results of a unique way of life, each supporting the growth of the others, each truly dependent on everything else. So, if we could just grasp the Greek lessons of political freedom and self-awareness, everything else would follow.
And now, in the last sixty years, knowledge and perception have poured upon us so fast that the whole well-ordered system has been blown away, and we stand bare to the blast, scarcely able to snatch a hasty generalisation or two to cover our nakedness for a moment.
And now, in the last sixty years, knowledge and perception have come at us so quickly that the entire well-organized system has been destroyed, and we stand exposed to the chaos, barely able to grab a quick generalization or two to cover our vulnerability for even a moment.
Our desperate plight comes home to one at the Chelsea Book Club, where are some thirty chosen specimens of negro sculpture. If to our ancestors the poor Indian had “an untutored mind,” the Congolese’s ignorance and savagery must have seemed too abject for discussion. One would like to know what Dr. Johnson would have said to any one who had offered him a negro idol for several hundred pounds. It would have seemed then sheer lunacy to listen to what a negro savage had to tell us of his emotions about the human form. And now one has to go all the way to Chelsea in a chastened spirit and prostrate oneself before his “stocks and stones.”
Our desperate situation really hits home at the Chelsea Book Club, where there are around thirty selected pieces of Black sculpture. If our ancestors considered the poor Native American to have “an untutored mind,” the ignorance and so-called savagery of the Congolese must have seemed too pitiful for discussion. It would be interesting to know what Dr. Johnson would have thought if someone offered him a Black idol for several hundred pounds. At that time, it would have seemed completely crazy to consider what a so-called savage had to share about his feelings regarding the human form. And now, we have to travel all the way to Chelsea with a humbler attitude and bow down before his “stocks and stones.”
We have the habit of thinking that the power to create expressive plastic form is one of the greatest of human achievements, and the names of great sculptors are handed down from generation to generation, so that it seems unfair to be forced to admit that certain nameless{66} savages have possessed this power not only in a higher degree than we at this moment, but than we as a nation have ever possessed it. And yet that is where I find myself. I have to admit that some of these things are great sculpture—greater, I think, than anything we produced even in the Middle Ages. Certainly they have the special qualities of sculpture in a higher degree. They have indeed complete plastic freedom; that is to say, these African artists really conceive form in three dimensions. Now this is rare in sculpture. All archaic European sculpture—Greek and Romanesque, for instance—approaches plasticity from the point of view of bas-relief. The statue bears traces of having been conceived as the combination of front, back, and side bas-reliefs. And this continues to make itself felt almost until the final development of the tradition. Complete plastic freedom with us seems only to come at the end of a long period, when the art has attained a high degree of representational skill and when it is generally already decadent from the point of view of imaginative significance.
We often think that the ability to create expressive three-dimensional forms is one of humanity's greatest achievements, and the names of renowned sculptors are passed down through generations. It feels unfair to acknowledge that certain unknown{66} artists from the past could create these forms not only with greater skill than we do now, but with more mastery than we as a nation have ever achieved. Yet, that’s how I feel. I have to acknowledge that some of these works are truly great sculptures—greater, I believe, than anything we made even during the Middle Ages. They obviously possess the essential qualities of sculpture to a higher degree. These African artists fully grasp form in three dimensions, which is quite rare in sculpture. Most ancient European sculpture—like Greek and Romanesque—approaches three-dimensionality primarily from the perspective of bas-relief. Statues show signs of having been thought of as a mix of front, back, and side bas-reliefs. This influence persists nearly until the art form's final evolution. Complete three-dimensional freedom in our sculptures seems to emerge only after a long period, typically when the art has developed a high level of representational skill and is, by then, often considered to be declining in imaginative significance.
Now, the strange thing about these African sculptures is that they bear, as far as I can see, no trace of this process. Without ever attaining anything like representational accuracy they have complete freedom. The sculptors seem to have no difficulty in getting away from the two-dimensional plane. The neck and the torso are conceived as cylinders, not as masses with a square section. The head is conceived as a pear-shaped mass. It is conceived as a single whole, not arrived at by approach from the mask, as with almost all primitive European art. The mask itself is conceived as a concave plane cut out of this otherwise perfectly unified mass.
Now, the interesting thing about these African sculptures is that they show, as far as I can tell, no evidence of this process. Without ever achieving anything like realistic detail, they have complete freedom. The sculptors seem to have no trouble moving away from the two-dimensional surface. The neck and torso are designed as cylinders, not as blocks with flat sides. The head is shaped like a pear. It's seen as a single unit, not formed by starting from the mask, as is the case with nearly all primitive European art. The mask itself is viewed as a concave surface cut out of this otherwise perfectly unified form.
And here we come upon another curious difference between negro sculpture and our own, namely, that the emphasis is utterly different. Our emphasis has always been affected by our preferences for certain forms which appeared to us to mark the nobility of man. Thus we shrink from giving the head its full development; we like to lengthen the legs and generally to force the form into a particular type. These preferences seem to be dictated not by a plastic bias, but by our reading of the physical symbols of certain qualities which we admire in our kind, such, for instance, as agility, a commanding presence, or a pensive brow. The negro, it seems, either has no such{67}
And here we encounter another interesting difference between African sculpture and our own: the emphasis is completely different. Our emphasis has always been shaped by our preferences for certain forms that we believe signify the nobility of humanity. As a result, we tend to avoid developing the head fully; we prefer to elongate the legs and generally push the form into a specific type. These preferences seem to stem not from a sculptural inclination, but from our interpretation of the physical symbols of certain qualities we admire in people, such as agility, a strong presence, or a thoughtful expression. It appears that African artists, on the other hand, either do not share these preferences {67}
preferences, or his preferences happen to coincide more nearly with what his feeling for pure plastic design would dictate. For instance, the length, thinness, and isolation of our limbs render them extremely refractory to fine plastic treatment, and the negro scores heavily by his willingness to reduce the limbs to a succession of ovoid masses sometimes scarcely longer than they are broad. Generally speaking, one may say that his plastic sense leads him to give its utmost amplitude and relief to all the protuberant parts of the body, and to get thereby an extraordinarily emphatic and impressive sequence of planes. So far from clinging to two dimensions, as we tend to do, he actually underlines, as it were, the three-dimensionalness of his forms. It is in some such way, I suspect, that he manages to give to his forms their disconcerting vitality, the suggestion that they make of being not mere echoes of actual figures, but of possessing an inner life of their own. If the negro artist wanted to make people believe in the potency of his idols he certainly set about it in the right way.
preferences, or his preferences happen to align more closely with what his appreciation for pure plastic design would suggest. For example, the length, thinness, and separation of our limbs make them quite resistant to fine plastic treatment, while the Black artist benefits significantly from his ability to simplify the limbs into a series of oval shapes that are often barely longer than they are wide. Generally speaking, one could say that his plastic sense encourages him to emphasize the fullness and relief of all the protruding parts of the body, resulting in an extraordinarily striking and impactful arrangement of planes. Rather than sticking to two dimensions, as we tend to do, he actually highlights, in a sense, the three-dimensional quality of his forms. I suspect it is in this way that he manages to imbue his forms with a captivating vitality, suggesting that they are not just reflections of real figures but have an inner life of their own. If the Black artist aimed to make people believe in the power of his idols, he certainly went about it in the right way.
Besides the logical comprehension of plastic form which the negro shows, he has also an exquisite taste in his handling of material. No doubt in this matter his endless leisure has something to do with the marvellous finish of these works. An instance of this is seen in the treatment of the tattoo cicatrices. These are always rendered in relief, which means that the artist has cut away the whole surface around them. I fancy most sculptors would have found some less laborious method of interpreting these markings. But this patient elaboration of the surface is characteristic of most of these works. It is seen to perfection in a wooden cup covered all over with a design of faces and objects that look like clubs in very low relief. The galbe of this cup shows a subtlety and refinement of taste comparable to that of the finest Oriental craftsmen.
Besides the clear understanding of form that the Black artist demonstrates, he also has an exceptional taste in his use of materials. It's likely that his abundance of free time plays a role in the remarkable quality of these works. One example of this is how he treats the tattoo scars. These are always depicted in relief, meaning the artist has carved away the entire surface around them. I think most sculptors would have found a less tedious way to portray these marks. However, this patient detailing of the surface is typical of many of these works. It is showcased beautifully in a wooden cup that is entirely covered with a design of faces and shapes that resemble clubs in very low relief. The shape of this cup displays a subtlety and refinement of taste comparable to that of the finest Oriental craftsmen.
It is curious that a people who produced such great artists did not produce also a culture in our sense of the word. This shows that two factors are necessary to produce the cultures which distinguish civilised peoples. There must be, of course, the creative artist, but there must also be the power of conscious critical appreciation and comparison. If we imagined such an apparatus of critical appreciation as the Chinese have possessed from the earliest times{68} applied to this negro art, we should have no difficulty in recognising its singular beauty. We should never have been tempted to regard it as savage or unrefined. It is for want of a conscious critical sense and the intellectual powers of comparison and classification that the negro has failed to create one of the great cultures of the world, and not from any lack of the creative æsthetic impulse, nor from lack of the most exquisite sensibility and the finest taste. No doubt also the lack of such a critical standard to support him leaves the artist much more at the mercy of any outside influence. It is likely enough that the negro artist, although capable of such profound imaginative understanding of form, would accept our cheapest illusionist art with humble enthusiasm.{69}
It’s interesting that a group of people who created such amazing artists didn’t also create a culture as we understand it today. This suggests that two factors are essential to develop the cultures that define civilized societies. There must be, of course, the creative artist, but there also needs to be the ability for conscious critical appreciation and comparison. If we could apply the same level of critical appreciation that the Chinese have had from early times{68} to this Black art, we would easily recognize its unique beauty. We wouldn’t be tempted to view it as primitive or uncultured. The reason the Black community hasn’t created one of the world’s great cultures is not due to a lack of creative aesthetic impulse, nor a lack of exquisite sensitivity and refined taste, but rather a lack of conscious critical awareness and the intellectual capacity for comparison and classification. Additionally, without such a critical standard to support them, artists are much more vulnerable to outside influences. It’s very likely that a Black artist, despite having a profound imaginative understanding of form, would accept our most simplistic illusionist art with eager admiration.{69}
ANCIENT AMERICAN ART[15]
NOTHING in the history of our Western civilisation is more romantic nor for us more tantalising than the story of the discovery and the wanton destruction of the ancient civilisations of America. Here were two complex civilisations which had developed in complete independence of the rest of the world; even so completely independent of each other that, for all their general racial likeness, they took on almost opposite characters. If only we could know these alternative efforts of the human animal to come to terms with nature and himself with something like the same fulness with which we know the civilisations of Greece and Rome, what might we not learn about the fundamental necessities of mankind? They would have been for us the opposite point of our orbit; they would have given us a parallax from which we might have estimated the movements of that dimmest and most distant phenomenon, the social nature of man. And as it is, what scraps of ill-digested and ill-arranged information and what fragments of ruined towns have to suffice us! Still, so fascinating is the subject that we owe Mr. Joyce[16] a debt of gratitude for the careful and thorough accumulation of all the material which the archæological remains afford. These by themselves would be only curious or beautiful as the case may be; their full value and significance can only come out when they are illustrated by whatever is known of their place in the historical sequence of the civilisations. Mr. Joyce gives us what is known of the outlines of Mexican and Peruvian history as far as it can be deciphered from the early accounts of Spanish invaders and from the original documents, and he brings the facts thus established to bear on the antiquities. Unfortunately for the reader of these books, the story is terribly involved and complicated{70} even when it is not dubious. Thus in Mexico we have to deal with an almost inextricable confusion of tribes and languages having much in common, but each interpreting their common mythology and religion in a special manner. Even Greek mythology, which we once seemed to know fairly well, takes on under the pressure of modern research an unfamiliar formlessness—becomes indistinct and shifting in its outlines; and the various civilisations of Mexico, each with its innumerable gods and goddesses with varying names and varying attributes, produce on the mind a sense of bewildering and helpless wonder, and still more a sense of pervading horror at the underlying nature of the human imagination. For one quality emerges in all the different aspects of their religions, its hideous inhumanity and cruelty, its direct inspiration of all the most ingenious tortures both in peace and war—above all, the close alliance between religion and war, and going with both of these the worship of suffering as an end in itself. Only at one point in this nightmare of inhumanity do we get a momentary sense of pleasure—itself a savage one—that is in the knowledge that at certain sacred periods the priests, whose main business was the torturing of others, were themselves subjected to the purificatory treatment. A bas-relief in the British Museum shows with grim realism the figure of a kneeling priest with pierced tongue, pulling a rope through the hole. Under such circumstances one would at least hesitate to accuse the priesthood of hypocrisy.
NOTHING in the history of our Western civilization is more romantic or more tantalizing for us than the story of the discovery and reckless destruction of the ancient civilizations of America. Here were two complex societies that developed completely independently from the rest of the world; so independent, in fact, that despite their general racial similarities, they took on almost opposing characteristics. If only we could understand these alternative human efforts to connect with nature and themselves as fully as we understand the civilizations of Greece and Rome, how much could we learn about the fundamental necessities of humankind? They would have served as the opposite point of reference for our understanding; they could have provided a perspective from which we could gauge the elusive and distant phenomenon of human social nature. Unfortunately, we are left with meager scraps of poorly organized information and fragments of ruined towns. Still, the subject is so fascinating that we owe Mr. Joyce[16] a debt of gratitude for his careful and thorough compilation of all the archaeological evidence. By themselves, these remnants would only be curious or beautiful; their true value and significance emerge only when seen in the context of their historical timeline. Mr. Joyce presents what we know about the outlines of Mexican and Peruvian history, as interpreted from the early accounts of Spanish invaders and original documents, and he connects these established facts to the antiquities. Unfortunately for readers of these books, the story is incredibly convoluted and complicated{70}, even when not questionable. In Mexico, we encounter an almost impossible mix of tribes and languages that share many similarities but each interprets their common mythology and religion in unique ways. Even Greek mythology, which we once thought we understood well, transforms under modern research into something unfamiliar—becoming vague and shifting in its outlines; and the various civilizations of Mexico, each with its countless gods and goddesses with different names and attributes, evoke a sense of overwhelming and helpless wonder, and even more so, a pervasive horror at the nature of human imagination. One disturbing quality is evident in all these different aspects of their religions: their brutal inhumanity and cruelty, their direct inspiration for numerous tortures in times of peace and war—especially the close connection between religion and war, along with a worship of suffering as an end in itself. The only moment of grim pleasure we find in this nightmare of inhumanity is knowing that at certain sacred times, the priests, whose primary role was torturing others, underwent their own purifying rituals. A bas-relief in the British Museum depicts with stark realism a kneeling priest with a pierced tongue, pulling a rope through the hole. Under such circumstances, one would hesitate to accuse the priesthood of hypocrisy.
When we turn to Peru the picture is less grim. The Incas do not seem to have been so abjectly religious as the Aztecs; they had at least abolished human sacrifice, which the Aztecs practised on a colossal scale, and though the tyranny of the governing classes was more highly organised, it was inspired by a fairly humane conception.
When we look at Peru, the situation seems less bleak. The Incas didn't appear to be as desperately religious as the Aztecs; they had at least eliminated human sacrifice, which was practiced on a massive scale by the Aztecs. Although the ruling classes were more systematically oppressive, their approach was based on a relatively humane understanding.
But we must leave the speculations on such general questions, which are as regards these books incidental to the main object, and turn to the consideration of the archæological remains and the investigation of their probable sequence and dating.
But we should set aside the speculations on these broad questions, which are incidental to the main purpose of these books, and focus on examining the archaeological remains and investigating their likely sequence and dating.
Our attitude to the artistic remains of these civilisations has a curious history. The wonder of the Spanish invaders at the sight of vast and highly organised civilisations where only savagery was expected has never indeed ceased, but the interest in their remains{71} has changed from time to time. The first emotion they excited besides wonder was the greed of the conquerors for the accumulated treasure. Then among the more cultivated Spaniards supervened a purely scientific curiosity to which we owe most of our knowledge of the indigenous legend and history. Then came the question of origins, which is still as fascinating and unsettled as ever, and to the belief that the Mexicans were the lost ten tribes of Israel we owe Lord Kingsborough’s monumental work in nine volumes on Mexican antiquities. To such odd impulses perhaps, rather than to any serious appreciation of their artistic merits, we owe the magnificent collection of Mexican antiquities in the British Museum. Indeed, it is only in this century that, after contemplating them from every other point of view, we have begun to look at them seriously as works of art. Probably the first works to be admitted to this kind of consideration were the Peruvian pots in the form of highly realistic human heads and figures.[17]
Our perspective on the artistic remains of these civilizations has a fascinating history. The amazement of the Spanish invaders at the sight of large, advanced civilizations where they expected only savagery has never truly faded, but the interest in their remains{71} has shifted over time. Initially, besides wonder, they sparked the conquerors' greed for the riches that had been amassed. Then, among the more educated Spaniards, a purely scientific curiosity emerged, leading to much of what we know today about indigenous legends and histories. This was followed by questions about origins, which remain as intriguing and unresolved as ever, and the belief that the Mexicans were the lost ten tribes of Israel inspired Lord Kingsborough’s monumental nine-volume work on Mexican antiquities. Perhaps it was these unusual impulses, rather than any genuine appreciation of their artistic value, that led to the impressive collection of Mexican antiquities in the British Museum. In fact, it is only in this century that, after examining them from every other angle, we have started to regard them seriously as art. Likely the first pieces to receive this kind of attention were the Peruvian pots shaped like incredibly realistic human heads and figures.[17]
Still more recently we have come to recognise the beauty of Aztec and Maya sculpture, and some of our modern artists have even gone to them for inspiration. This is, of course, one result of the general æsthetic awakening which has followed on the revolt against the tyranny of the Græco-Roman tradition.
Even more recently, we have started to appreciate the beauty of Aztec and Maya sculpture, and some of our contemporary artists have drawn inspiration from them. This is, of course, a result of the overall aesthetic awakening that has come after the rebellion against the dominance of the Greco-Roman tradition.
Both in Mexico and Peru we have to deal with at least two, possibly four, great cultures, each overthrown in turn by the invasion of less civilised, more warlike tribes, who gradually adopt the general scheme of the older civilisation. In Mexico there is no doubt about the superiority, from an artistic point of view, of the earlier culture—the Aztecs had everything to learn from the Maya, and they never rose to the level of their predecessors. The relation is, in fact, curiously like that of Rome to Greece. Unfortunately we have to learn almost all we know of Maya culture through their Aztec conquerors, but the ruins of Yucatan and Guatemala are by far the finest and most complete vestiges left to us.
Both in Mexico and Peru, we have to consider at least two, possibly four, major cultures, each displaced in turn by the invasion of less advanced, more aggressive tribes, who gradually adopt the overall structure of the earlier civilization. In Mexico, there is no doubt about the artistic superiority of the earlier culture—the Aztecs had a lot to learn from the Maya, and they never reached the level of their predecessors. The relationship is actually quite similar to that of Rome to Greece. Unfortunately, we have to learn almost everything we know about Maya culture through their Aztec conquerors, but the ruins of Yucatan and Guatemala are by far the finest and most complete remains we have.
In Peru also we find in the Tihuanaco gateway a monument of some pre-Inca civilisation, and one that in regard to the art of sculpture far surpasses anything that the later culture reveals. It is of special interest, moreover, for its strong stylistic likeness to the Maya{72} sculpture of Yucatan. This similarity prompts the interesting speculation that the earlier civilisations of the two continents had either a common origin or points of contact, whereas the Inca and Aztec cultures seem to drift entirely apart. The Aztecs carry on at a lower level the Maya art of sculpture, whereas the Incas seem to drop sculpture almost entirely, a curious fact in view of the ambitious nature of their architectural and engineering works. One seems to guess that the comparatively humane socialistic tyranny of the Incas developed more and more along purely practical lines, whilst the hideous religiosity of the Aztecs left a certain freedom to the imaginative artist.
In Peru, we also find a monument at the Tihuanaco gateway from a pre-Inca civilization that, in terms of sculpture, is far superior to anything seen in later cultures. It's especially interesting because it shares a strong stylistic resemblance with the Maya sculpture of Yucatan. This similarity raises the intriguing possibility that the earlier civilizations of the two continents might have had a common origin or contact points, while the Inca and Aztec cultures seem to have developed entirely separately. The Aztecs maintain a lower level of Maya sculpture, whereas the Incas appear to have almost abandoned sculpture altogether, which is surprising given the ambitious nature of their architectural and engineering achievements. One might surmise that the relatively humane, socialistic rule of the Incas evolved more along practical lines, while the grim religiosity of the Aztecs allowed for a degree of freedom for imaginative artists.{72}
In looking at the artistic remains of so remote and strange a civilisation one sometimes wonders how far one can trust one’s æsthetic appreciation to interpret truly the feelings which inspired it. In certain works one cannot doubt that the artist felt just as we feel in appreciating his work. This must, I think, hold on the one hand of the rich ornamental arabesques of Maya buildings or the marvellous inlaid feather and jewel work of either culture; and on the other hand, when we look at the caricatural realistic figures of Truxillo pottery we need scarcely doubt that the artist’s intention agrees with our appreciation, for such a use of the figure is more or less common to all civilisations. But when we look at the stylistic sculpture of Maya and Aztec art, are we, one wonders, reading in an intention which was not really present? One wonders, for instance, how far external and accidental factors may not have entered in to help produce what seems to us the perfect and delicate balance between representational and purely formal considerations. Whether the artist was not held back both by ritualistic tradition and the difficulty of his medium from pushing further the actuality of his presentation—whether, in fact, the artist deplored or himself approved just that reticence which causes our admiration. At times Maya sculpture has a certain similarity to Indian religious sculptural reliefs, particularly in the use of flat surfaces entirely incrusted with ornaments in low relief; but on the whole the comparison is all in favour of the higher æsthetic sensibility of the Maya artists, whose co-ordination of even the most complicated forms compares favourably with the incoherent luxuriance of most Indian work.{73}
When examining the artistic remnants of such a distant and unusual civilization, one often wonders how much we can rely on our aesthetic sense to accurately interpret the emotions that inspired it. In some works, it's clear that the artist felt just as we do when appreciating their creations. This holds true, for example, for the intricate ornamental designs of Maya buildings or the stunning inlaid feather and jewel work from both cultures. On the other hand, when we consider the caricature-like realistic figures of Truxillo pottery, we can be pretty sure that the artist's intentions align with our appreciation since this kind of representation is fairly common across civilizations. However, when looking at the stylistic sculptures of Maya and Aztec art, we might wonder if we're interpreting an intention that wasn't actually there. One might wonder how much external and accidental factors influenced what appears to us as the perfect and delicate balance between representational and purely formal elements. Was the artist constrained by ritualistic traditions and the challenges of their medium, preventing them from enhancing the realism of their work? Did the artist lament or embrace that restraint which leads to our admiration? At times, Maya sculpture resembles Indian religious sculptural reliefs, especially in the use of flat surfaces completely covered with low relief ornaments. However, overall, the comparison favors the greater aesthetic sensibility of Maya artists, whose ability to coordinate even the most complex forms stands in contrast to the chaotic richness of much Indian work.{73}
In this, as in so many of its characteristics, Maya art comes much nearer to early Chinese sculpture; and again one wonders that such a civilisation should have produced such sensitive and reasoned designs—designs which seem to imply a highly developed self-conscious æsthetic sensibility. Nor do the Maya for all their hieratic ritualism seem to fall into the dead, mechanical repetition which the endless multiplication of religious symbols usually entails, as, for instance, most markedly in Egyptian art. But this strange difference between what we know of Mexican civilisation and what we might have interpreted from the art alone is only one more instance of the isolation of the æsthetic from all other human activities. The Frontispiece to this book gives an example of Maya sculpture from Piedras Negras. Mr. Joyce, in his learned and plausible theory of the dating of Mexican monuments, ascribes these remains to a date of about 50-200 A.D.
In this way, like many other features, Maya art is much closer to early Chinese sculpture; it makes one wonder how such a civilization could produce such sensitive and well-thought-out designs—designs that suggest a highly developed sense of aesthetic awareness. Despite their formal rituals, the Maya don’t fall into the lifeless, mechanical repetition that often comes with the endless proliferation of religious symbols, as seen most clearly in Egyptian art. This curious contrast between what we know about Mexican civilization and what we might interpret from the art alone is yet another example of the separation of aesthetics from all other human activities. The Frontispiece of this book shows an example of Maya sculpture from Piedras Negras. Mr. Joyce, in his learned and convincing theory about the dating of Mexican monuments, attributes these remains to around 50-200 A.D.
They are certainly among the finest remains of Maya sculpture, and this example shows at once the extreme richness of the decorative effect and the admirable taste with which this is co-ordinated in a plastic whole in which the figure has its due predominance. Though the relief of the ornamental part is kept flat and generally square in section, it has nothing of the dryness and tightness that such a treatment often implies.
They are definitely some of the best examples of Maya sculpture, and this piece highlights both the incredible richness of the decorative effect and the impressive taste with which it is coordinated into a cohesive whole where the figure stands out prominently. Although the relief of the ornamental part is kept flat and mostly square in shape, it lacks the dryness and rigidity that such a style usually suggests.
Mr. Joyce’s books are compiled with amazing industry, and contain a vast accumulation of information. If we have a complaint, it is that for those who are not specialists this information is poured out in almost too uniform a flood, with too little by way of general ideas to enable the mind to grasp or relate them properly. If some of the minor details of obscure proper names had been relegated to the notes, it would have been possible to seize the general outlines more readily. The books are rather for reference than adapted to consecutive reading. In his judgments on the various speculations to which these civilisations have given rise Mr. Joyce is, as one would expect from so careful a scholar, cautious and negative. He does not, as far as I remember, even allude to the theory of the Lost Ten Tribes, but he does condescend to discuss the theory of cultural influence from Eastern Asia which has more than once been put forward by respectable ethnologists. He decides against this fascinating hypothesis more definitely than one would expect—more{74}
Mr. Joyce’s books are put together with incredible effort and include a wealth of information. If we have a criticism, it's that for those who aren't experts, this information comes at them in an almost overwhelming stream, with too few overarching ideas to help them understand or connect the details properly. If some of the lesser-known proper names had been shifted to the notes, it would have been easier to grasp the main points. The books are more suited for reference than for continuous reading. In his evaluations of the different theories that these civilizations have sparked, Mr. Joyce is, as you would expect from such a diligent scholar, careful and reserved. He doesn't, as far as I can remember, even mention the theory of the Lost Ten Tribes, but he does take the time to discuss the idea of cultural influence from Eastern Asia, which has been proposed by respected ethnologists more than once. He dismisses this intriguing hypothesis more decisively than one might expect—more{74}
definitely, I should say, than the facts before us allow. He declares, for instance, that the calendrical system of Mexico shows no similarity with those of Eastern Asia, whereas Dr. Lehmann gives a circumstantial account of a very curious likeness, the almost exact correspondence of two quite peculiar systems of reckoning. My own bias in favour of the theory of Eastern Asiatic influence is, I confess, based on what may seem very insufficient grounds, namely, the curious likeness of the general treatment of naturalistic forms and the peculiar character of the stylisation of natural forms in early Chinese and American art. It is of course impossible to define a likeness of general character which depends so largely on feeling, but it consists to some extent in the predilection for straight lines and rectangles—a spiral in nature becoming in both early Chinese and American art a sequence of rectangular forms with rounded corners. What is more remarkable is that the further back we go in Chinese art the greater the resemblance becomes, so that a Chou bronze, or still more the carved horns which have survived from the Shang dynasty, are extraordinarily like Maya or Tihuanaco sculpture. Again, it is curious to note how near to early Chinese bronzes are the tripod vases of the Guetar Indians. All these may of course be of quite independent origin, but their similarity cannot be dismissed lightly in view of the long persistence in any civilisation of such general habits of design. Thus the general habits of design of the Cretan civilisation persisted into Greek and even Roman and Christian art; the habits of design of Chinese artists have persisted, though through great modifications, for more than three thousand years. One other fact which may seem almost too isolated and insignificant may perhaps be put forward here. In a history of the Mormons, published in 1851, there is given a figure of an inscribed bronze (see Figure) which was dug up by the Mormons in Utah in 1843. Since Brigham Young pretended to have dug up the original book of Mormon his followers had a superstitious reverence for all such treasure trove, and probably the bronze{75} still exists and might be worth investigation. Now this drawing, here reproduced, looks to me like an extremely bad and unintelligent reproduction of an early Chinese object, in general appearance not unlike certain early pieces of jade. It is fairly certain that at the time the Mormons discovered this, no such objects had found their way out of China, since the interest in and knowledge of this period of Chinese art is of much later growth. So it appears conceivable that the object, whatever its nature, is a relic of some early cultural invasion from Eastern Asia. The physical possibilities of such invasions from the Far East certainly seem to be under-estimated by Mr. Joyce.{76}
definitely, I should say, than the facts before us allow. He states, for example, that the calendar system of Mexico shows no similarity to those of Eastern Asia, while Dr. Lehmann provides a detailed account of a very interesting resemblance—the almost exact correspondence of two quite unique systems of measuring time. I admit that my own preference for the theory of Eastern Asian influence is based on what may seem to be rather weak evidence, specifically the intriguing similarities in the overall treatment of naturalistic forms and the unique stylization of natural forms in early Chinese and American art. It's obviously challenging to define a general likeness that relies so heavily on feeling, but it partly consists of a tendency towards straight lines and rectangles—a spiral in nature transforms into a series of rectangular forms with rounded corners in both early Chinese and American art. What’s more striking is that as we go further back in Chinese art, the similarities increase, so much so that a Chou bronze, or even more so, the carved horns from the Shang dynasty, bear a remarkable resemblance to Maya or Tihuanaco sculpture. Furthermore, it's interesting to note how closely related the tripod vases of the Guetar Indians are to early Chinese bronzes. All these could certainly be of completely independent origin, but their similarities shouldn't be taken lightly considering the long-lasting attributes of design in any civilization. For instance, the general design characteristics of Cretan civilization continued into Greek and even Roman and Christian art; the design habits of Chinese artists have persevered, albeit through significant changes, for over three thousand years. Another fact that might seem somewhat isolated and trivial can be mentioned here. In a history of the Mormons published in 1851, there’s an illustration of an inscribed bronze (see Figure) discovered by the Mormons in Utah in 1843. Since Brigham Young claimed to have unearthed the original Book of Mormon, his followers held a superstitious reverence for all such discoveries, and likely this bronze{75} still exists and might be worth looking into. This drawing, reproduced here, appears to me as a very poor and unskilled imitation of an early Chinese object, not unlike certain early jade pieces in general appearance. It's quite certain that at the time the Mormons found this, no such items had been brought out of China, as the interest in and knowledge of this period of Chinese art developed much later. Thus, it seems possible that this object, whatever its actual nature, is a remnant of some early cultural influence from Eastern Asia. The physical possibilities of such influences from the Far East do indeed seem to be underestimated by Mr. Joyce.{76}
THE
MUNICH EXHIBITION OF MOHAMMEDAN ART[18]
IT would be hard to exaggerate the importance of this exhibition for those who are interested in the history not alone of Oriental but of European art. Perhaps the most fascinating problem that presents itself to the art historian is that of the origins of mediæval art. Until we understand more or less completely how in the dim centuries of the later Empire and early middle age the great transformation of Græco-Roman into mediæval art was accomplished, we cannot quite understand the Renaissance itself, nor even the form which the whole modern art of Europe has come in the course of centuries to assume. And on this problem the Munich exhibition throws many illuminating sidelights. Early Mohammedan art is seen here to be a meeting point of many influences. There are still traces of the once widespread Hellenistic tradition, though this is seen to be retreating before the refluent wave of aboriginal ideas. Sassanid art had already been the outcome of these contending forces, and the pre-eminence of Sassanid art in forming early Mohammedan styles is clearly brought out in this exhibition. Then there is a constant exchange with Byzantium, and finally continual waves of influence, sometimes fertilising, sometimes destructive, from that great reservoir of Central Asian civilisation, the importance of which is now at last being gradually revealed to us by the discoveries of Dr. Stein, Drs. Lecoq and Grunwedel, and M. Pelliot.
It's hard to overstate how important this exhibition is for anyone interested in the history of both Oriental and European art. One of the most intriguing challenges for art historians is understanding the origins of medieval art. Until we grasp how the significant transformation from Greco-Roman to medieval art occurred during the later Roman Empire and early Middle Ages, we can't fully comprehend the Renaissance or the way modern European art has evolved over the centuries. This exhibition in Munich sheds a lot of light on that issue. Early Islamic art serves as a convergence of various influences. You can still see remnants of the once widespread Hellenistic tradition, although it's fading in the face of returning native ideas. Sassanid art arose from these conflicting forces, and the exhibition clearly highlights how influential Sassanid art was in shaping early Islamic styles. Additionally, there was a constant exchange with Byzantine art, and we can see ongoing waves of influence—sometimes beneficial, sometimes harmful—emanating from the vast reservoir of Central Asian civilization. The significance of this region has finally begun to emerge through the discoveries of Dr. Stein, Drs. Lecoq and Grunwedel, and M. Pelliot.
And through this great clearing-house of early Mohammedan art there are signs of influences passing from West to East. The most striking example is that of the plate in cloisonnée enamel from the Landes Museum at Innsbruck. Here we have the one certain example of Mohammedan cloisonnée enamel established by its dedication{77} to a prince of the Orthokid dynasty of the twelfth century. It is extraordinary that this solitary example should alone have survived from what must, judging from the technical excellence of this specimen, have once been a flourishing craft. The general effect of the intricate pattern of animal forms upon a whiteish ground suggests, on the one hand, the earliest examples of Limoges enamels, and on the other the early Chinese, and there can be little doubt that the Chinese did in fact derive their knowledge of cloisonnée, which they themselves called “Western ware,” from these early Mohammedan craftsmen, who had themselves learned the technique from Byzantium.
And through this major hub of early Islamic art, you can see influences flowing from West to East. The most noticeable example is a plate made of cloisonné enamel at the Landes Museum in Innsbruck. This plate represents the only confirmed instance of Islamic cloisonné enamel, marked by its dedication{77} to a prince of the Orthokid dynasty from the twelfth century. It's remarkable that this single example is the only one that has survived from what must have been a thriving craft, given the technical skill shown in this piece. The overall effect of the complex design of animal shapes on a whitish background resembles, on one side, the earliest examples of Limoges enamels, and on the other, early Chinese works. There’s little doubt that the Chinese actually learned about cloisonné, which they referred to as “Western ware,” from these early Islamic artisans, who had themselves adopted the technique from Byzantium.
But on the whole the stream of influence is in the opposite direction, from East to West, and one realises at Munich that in the great period of artistic discovery and formation of styles the near East and the West were developing in closest contact and harmony. Indeed the most fertile, if not actually the most resplendent, period of both arts, was attained whilst they were still almost indistinguishable. If it were not for the habit of these early Mohammedan craftsmen of interweaving inscriptions into their designs, a habit which endears them quite especially to art-historians, how many works of Oriental manufacture would have been ascribed to Europe? In spite of these inscriptions, indeed, such an authority as M. Babelon has sought to place to the account of Western artists the superb cut crystal vessels, of which the noblest example is the inscribed ewer of the tenth century in the treasury of S. Mark’s. Or take again the textiles. In the exhibition there are a number of fragments of textiles of the tenth to the twelfth centuries, in which the general principle of design is the same; for the most part the surface is covered by circular reserves in which severely conventionalised figures of hunters, lions, or monsters are placed in pairs symmetrically confronted. Only minute study has enabled specialists to say that some were made in Sassanid, Persia, some in Byzantium, some in Sicily, and some in Western Europe. The dominant style in all these is again derived from Sassanid art. And here once more one must note the strange recrudescence after so long of Assyrian types and motives, and its invasion of Western Europe, through Byzantium, Sicily, and Spain.
But overall, the flow of influence goes the other way, from East to West, and you realize in Munich that during the great period of artistic discovery and style formation, the Near East and the West were developing in close contact and harmony. In fact, the most productive, if not the most brilliant, period for both arts occurred when they were still nearly indistinguishable. If it weren’t for the early Muslim craftsmen's habit of incorporating inscriptions into their designs—a trait that makes them especially appealing to art historians—how many works of Oriental craftsmanship would have been credited to Europe? Despite these inscriptions, authorities like M. Babelon have tried to attribute the stunning cut crystal vessels, of which the finest example is the inscribed ewer from the tenth century in the treasury of S. Mark’s, to Western artists. And consider the textiles again. The exhibition features several fragments from the tenth to the twelfth centuries, where the overall design principle is the same; mostly, the surface is filled with circular areas that feature severely stylized figures of hunters, lions, or monsters arranged symmetrically in pairs. Only through careful study have experts been able to determine that some were made in Sassanid Persia, some in Byzantium, some in Sicily, and some in Western Europe. The dominant style across all of these again comes from Sassanid art. Once again, it's worth noting the surprising resurgence of Assyrian themes and motifs and their spread into Western Europe through Byzantium, Sicily, and Spain.
What strikes us most in comparing Græco-Roman art with the{78} new art which gradually emerges in the middle ages is that, on the one hand, we have a series of decorative designs never so remarkable for vitality as for their elegance, and become by the time of the Roman Empire only less perfunctory and mechanical than the patterns of modern times; and on the other hand an art in which the smallest piece of pattern-making shows a tense vitality even in its most purely geometrical manifestations, and the figure is used with a new dramatic expressiveness unhindered by the artist’s ignorance of actual form. Now in the splendid photographs of the Sassanid rock carvings which Dr. Sarre has taken and which are exposed at Munich, we can see something of this process of the creation of the new vital system of design. In the earlier reliefs, those of the time of Sapor, we have, it is true, a certain theatrical splendour of pose and setting, but in the actual forms some flaccidity and inflation. The artists who wrought them show still the predominance of the worn-out Hellenistic tradition which spread in Alexander’s wake over Asia. In the stupendous relief of Chosroes at Tak-i-Bostan, on the other hand, we have all the dramatic energy, the heraldic splendour of the finest mediæval art, and the source of this new inspiration is seen to be the welling up once more of the old indigenous Mesopotamian art. We have once more that singular feeling for stress, for muscular tension, and for dramatic oppositions, which distinguish the bas-reliefs of Babylon and Nineveh from all other artistic expressions of the antique world. It would be possible by the help of exhibits at Munich to trace certain Assyrian forms right through to Mediæval European art. Take, for instance, the lion heads on the pre-Babylonian mace from Goudea in the Louvre; one finds a precisely similar convention for the lion head on the Sassanid repoussé metalwork found in Russia. Once again it occurs in the superb carved rock crystal waterspout lent by the Karlsruhe Museum (Room 54), and one finds it again on the font of Lincoln Cathedral and in the lions that support the doorway columns of Italian cathedrals. In all these there is a certain community of style, a certain way of symbolising the leonine nature which one may look for in vain in Greek and Græco-Roman art.
What stands out to us when we compare Græco-Roman art with the new art that gradually emerges in the Middle Ages is that, on one hand, we have a series of decorative designs that are more notable for their elegance than for their vitality and have become, by the time of the Roman Empire, only slightly less mechanical than the patterns we see today; on the other hand, there's an art form where even the smallest piece of pattern-making reveals a tense vitality, even in its most purely geometric forms, and the figure is used with a new dramatic expressiveness, unhindered by the artist’s lack of understanding of actual form. Now, in the stunning photographs of the Sassanid rock carvings taken by Dr. Sarre and displayed in Munich, we can see some of this process in creating the new vital design system. In the earlier reliefs from the time of Sapor, there's indeed a certain theatrical splendor in pose and setting, but in the actual forms, some flaccidity and inflation is evident. The artists who made them still show the lingering influence of the tired Hellenistic tradition that spread across Asia in Alexander’s wake. In the breathtaking relief of Chosroes at Tak-i-Bostan, however, we see all the dramatic energy and heraldic splendor characteristic of the finest medieval art, and the source of this new inspiration appears to be a resurgence of the old native Mesopotamian art. We find once again that unique sense of stress, muscular tension, and dramatic contrasts that distinguish the bas-reliefs of Babylon and Nineveh from all other artistic expressions of the ancient world. It’s possible, with the help of the exhibits in Munich, to trace certain Assyrian forms all the way into medieval European art. For example, the lion heads on the pre-Babylonian mace from Goudea in the Louvre have a strikingly similar style to the lion head found in the Sassanid repoussé metalwork discovered in Russia. This style also appears in the exquisite carved rock crystal waterspout loaned by the Karlsruhe Museum (Room 54), and again on the font of Lincoln Cathedral and in the lions supporting the doorway columns of Italian cathedrals. In all these examples, there is a shared style and a distinctive way of symbolizing the lion-like nature that one would search for in vain in Greek and Græco-Roman art.
Even if this seem too forced an interpretation of facts, it is none the less clear that everywhere in early Mohammedan art this{79} recrudescence of Assyrian forms may be traced, and that their influence was scarcely less upon Europe than upon the near East. Dr. Sarre has taken a tracing of the pattern which is represented in low relief upon the robes of Chosroes in the Tak-i-Bostan relief. In South Kensington Museum there is an almost identical piece of silk brocade which actually comes from the ruins of Khorsabad, and in the same museum one may find more than one Byzantine imitation of this design and closely similar ones made in Sicily; and the conventional winged monster which forms the basis of these designs has a purely Assyrian air.
Even if this seems like a forced interpretation of the facts, it’s still clear that in early Islamic art, the revival of Assyrian forms can be seen everywhere, and their influence was hardly less on Europe than on the Near East. Dr. Sarre has made a tracing of the pattern depicted in low relief on the robes of Chosroes in the Tak-i-Bostan relief. At the South Kensington Museum, there is an almost identical piece of silk brocade that actually comes from the ruins of Khorsabad. In the same museum, you can find several Byzantine imitations of this design and closely similar ones made in Sicily; the conventional winged monster that forms the basis of these designs has a distinctly Assyrian look.
In Egypt, too, it would seem that there was before the Arab invasion a marked recrudescence of indigenous native design which enabled the Coptic craftsmen gradually to transform the motives given to them by Roman conquerors into something entirely non-Hellenistic. And the incredible beauty of the Fatimite textiles of the tenth, eleventh, and twelfth centuries, of which a few precious relics are shown in Room 17, preserve something, especially in the bird forms, of this antique derivation.
In Egypt, it also seems that before the Arab invasion, there was a noticeable revival of native design that allowed Coptic craftsmen to gradually change the influences from their Roman conquerors into something completely non-Hellenistic. The stunning beauty of the Fatimite textiles from the tenth, eleventh, and twelfth centuries, with a few precious examples displayed in Room 17, retains something, especially in the bird designs, from this ancient tradition.
But to return once more to Sassanid art. The specimens from the Hermitage and Prince Bobrinsky’s collections form an object lesson of extraordinary interest in the development of early Mohammedan art. They have inherited and still retain that extreme realisation of massive splendour, that fierce assertion of form and positive statement of relief which belongs to the art of the great primitive Empires, and most of all to the art of Mesopotamia, and yet they already adumbrate the forms of Mohammedan art into which they pass by insensible degrees. Here, too, we find vestiges of the dying Hellenistic tradition. One of Prince Bobrinsky’s bronzes, a great plate, has, for instance, a design composed of classic vases, from which spring stems which bend round into a series of circles, a design which might almost be matched as regards form, though not as regards spirit, in the wall decorations of Pompeii. Or take again the superb repoussé silver plate representing a Sassanid king spearing a lion. Here the floating drapery of the king and the edge of his tunic show a deliberately schematised rendering of the traditional folds of the Greek peplos. But how much more Assyrian than Greek is the whole effect—the dramatic tension of the figures{80} expressed by an emphasis on all the lines of muscular effort, as in the legs of the horse and the lions. How Assyrian, too, is the feeling for relief, and the predilection for imbricated or closely set parallel lines as in the lions’ manes. In the conventional rock under one of the lions one seems to see also a hint of Chinese forms.
But let's go back to Sassanid art. The pieces from the Hermitage and Prince Bobrinsky’s collections are incredibly interesting examples of how early Islamic art developed. They have inherited and still showcase a remarkable sense of grandeur, a bold assertion of form, and a clear emphasis on relief that belongs to the art of the great ancient empires, especially Mesopotamia. Yet, they also hint at the forms of Islamic art that they gradually evolve into. Here, we can also see traces of the fading Hellenistic tradition. One of Prince Bobrinsky’s bronzes, a large plate, features a design made up of classic vases, from which stems twist into a series of circles—a design that could almost be compared in form, though not in essence, to the wall decorations of Pompeii. Another example is the stunning repoussé silver plate depicting a Sassanid king spearing a lion. The flowing drapery of the king and the edge of his tunic display a purposely schematic interpretation of the traditional folds of the Greek peplos. However, the overall effect is much more Assyrian than Greek—the dramatic tension of the figures is expressed through a focus on all the lines of muscular effort, like in the legs of the horse and the lions. The sense of relief and the preference for interwoven or closely set parallel lines, as seen in the lions’ manes, are also distinctly Assyrian. Beneath one of the lions, the conventional rock seems to suggest a hint of Chinese forms.
Still more Assyrian is another plate, the arrangement of which recalls the reliefs of Assurbanipal or Sennacherib, and yet already there are forms which anticipate Mohammedan art; the gate of the city, its crenelations, and the forms of the helmets of the soldiers, all have an air of similarity with far later Mohammedan types. Another plate, not reproduced here, shows a Sassanid king regaling himself with wine and music, and gives already more than a hint of the favourite designs of the Rhages potters or the bronze workers of Mossoul.
Another plate has a distinctly Assyrian style, reminiscent of the reliefs of Assurbanipal or Sennacherib. However, it also features forms that hint at future Islamic art; the city gate, its battlements, and the shape of the soldiers' helmets all bear a resemblance to much later Islamic designs. Another plate, which isn't shown here, depicts a Sassanid king enjoying wine and music, and suggests the popular designs of the Rhages potters or the bronze workers of Mossoul.
Among Prince Bobrinsky’s bronzes which were found in the Caucasus is a late Sassanid aquamanile in the form of a bird. It is already almost Mohammedan, though retaining something of the extreme solidity and weight of earlier art. Once more, in the aggressive schematisation of the form of the tail and the suggestion of feathers by a series of deeply marked parallel lines, we get a reminiscence of Assyrian art, while in the treatment of the crest there is the more florid interweaving of curves which adumbrate not only Mohammedan but Indian forms.
Among Prince Bobrinsky’s bronzes discovered in the Caucasus is a late Sassanid water jug shaped like a bird. It is nearly Islamic, yet still holds onto some of the heavy solidity of earlier art. Once again, in the bold design of the tail and the representation of feathers created by a series of deeply etched parallel lines, we see a reminder of Assyrian art. Meanwhile, the way the crest is designed features more intricate curves that hint at not just Islamic but also Indian styles.
In the aquamanile in the form of a horse (see Plate) the Sassanid influence is still predominant, but there can be no doubt that this is already Mohammedan, probably of the eighth or ninth century. We have already here the characteristics of Fatimite bronzes, of which a few specimens are shown at Munich. The great griffin of Pisa could not, of course, be moved from the Campo Santo, nor are the two specimens in the Louvre shown, but the stag from the Bavarian National Museum is there and affords a most interesting comparison with Prince Bobrinsky’s horse. Both have the same large generalisation of form, and in both we have the curious effect of solidity and mass produced by the shortened hind legs, with the half-squatting movement to which that gives rise.
In the horse-shaped aquamanile (see Plate), the Sassanid influence is still strong, but it's clear this piece is already Islamic, probably from the eighth or ninth century. We can already see the features of Fatimid bronzes, some of which are displayed in Munich. The great griffin from Pisa, of course, can’t be moved from the Campo Santo, and the two pieces in the Louvre aren't on display, but the stag from the Bavarian National Museum is there and provides a fascinating comparison with Prince Bobrinsky’s horse. Both pieces share a similar broad form, and in both, the shortened hind legs create an interesting effect of solidity and mass, resulting in a half-squatting posture.
nearly parallel to that of Egypt. This school, however, never developed as fully along sculptural lines, and at a comparatively early date abandoned sculpture for the art of bronze inlay, of which Mossoul was the great centre in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries. In the incised designs on the horse we have an example of the early forms of the palmette ornament and of the interlacing curves which form the basis of most subsequent Mohammedan patterns. Within the reserves formed by the intreccie are small figures, of which one—that of a man seated and playing the lute—can just be made out in the reproduction. It is already typical of the figure design which the Mohammedan artists developed in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries.
nearly parallel to that of Egypt. This school, however, never fully developed along sculptural lines and at a relatively early stage abandoned sculpture for the art of bronze inlay, with Mossoul being the major center in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries. The incised designs on the horse showcase the early forms of the palmette ornament and the interlacing curves that form the foundation of most later Mohammedan patterns. Inside the reserves created by the intreccie are small figures, one of which—a man sitting and playing the lute—can just be identified in the reproduction. It is already representative of the figure design that Mohammedan artists advanced in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries.
By way of comparison with this Mesopotamian example, Plate, Fig. 2, shows a supreme example of Fatimite sculpture of the twelfth century. It is, indeed, a matter for regret that Mohammedan artists so soon abandoned an art for which they showed such extraordinary aptitude. The lion which comes from the Kassel Museum has already been published by M. Migeon,[19] but is of such rare beauty and interest in relation to the Sassanid works here described that it seemed desirable to reproduce it again. It shows the peculiar characteristics of all the art produced for the Fatimite court, its exquisite perfection and refinement of taste, its minuteness of detail and finish together with a large co-ordination of parts, a rhythmic feeling for contour and the sequence of planes, which have scarcely ever been equalled. And all these qualities of refinement, almost of sophistication, which Fatimite art possesses, do not, as we see here, destroy the elementary imaginative feeling for the vitality of animal forms. In the case in which this masterpiece of Mohammedan sculpture is shown there is also seen the celebrated lion which once belonged to the painter Fortuny. Noble though this is in general conception, the coarseness of its workmanship and the want of subtlety in its proportions, in comparison with the Kassel lion, makes it evident that it is not from the same school of Egyptian craftsmen, but probably of Spanish origin.
By comparing this Mesopotamian example, Plate, Fig. 2, showcases an outstanding piece of Fatimid sculpture from the twelfth century. It's unfortunate that Muslim artists quickly moved away from an art form for which they had such remarkable skill. The lion from the Kassel Museum has already been featured by M. Migeon,[19] but it's so beautiful and intriguing in relation to the Sassanid works described here that it seemed worthwhile to show it again. It highlights the unique traits of all art created for the Fatimid court, showcasing exquisite perfection and refined taste, intricate details and finish, as well as a strong coordination of parts, a rhythmic sense of contour, and a sequence of planes that are rarely matched. Despite the refinement and almost sophisticated quality of Fatimid art, as seen here, it doesn't diminish the basic imaginative sense of the vitality of animal forms. In the display of this masterpiece of Muslim sculpture, one can also admire the famous lion that once belonged to the painter Fortuny. Although noble in its overall design, the roughness of its craftsmanship and lack of subtlety in its proportions, especially when compared to the Kassel lion, clearly indicate it doesn't come from the same school of Egyptian artisans, but is likely of Spanish origin.
Yet another of the Bobrinsky bronzes of about the same date as the horse is already typically Mohammedan as may be seen{82} by the leaf forms and the intreccie of the crest, but how much of the antique Sassanid proportions and sense of relief is still retained! It is believed to be from Western Turkestan and of the eighth or ninth century. One must suppose that Sassanid forms travelled North and East as well as South and West, and helped in the formation of that Central Asian art which becomes the dominant factor in the later centuries of Mohammedan, more especially of Persian, art.
Another Bobrinsky bronze, roughly the same age as the horse, already shows typical Islamic features, evident in the leaf designs and the intricate crest. However, it still retains much of the antique Sassanid proportions and sense of relief. This piece is believed to be from Western Turkestan and dates back to the eighth or ninth century. One can assume that Sassanid forms spread North and East as well as South and West, significantly influencing the development of Central Asian art, which became a major force in later centuries of Islamic, particularly Persian, art.
Before leaving the question of Sassanid influences I must mention the series of bronze jugs in the Bobrinsky and Sarre collections. The general form is obviously derived from classic originals, but they have a peculiar spout of a rectangular shape placed at right angles on the top of the main opening. The effect of this is to give two openings, one for pouring the water in, the other for pouring it out at right angles. Now in the early Mossoul water jugs we see numerous examples of what are clearly derivations of this form passing by gradual degrees into the familiar neck with spout attached but not separated, which is typical of later Mohammedan water jugs. This evolution can be traced step by step in the Munich Exhibition, and leaves no doubt of the perfect continuity of Sassanid and Mohammedan forms.[20]
Before we move on from discussing Sassanid influences, I need to mention the collection of bronze jugs in the Bobrinsky and Sarre collections. The overall shape clearly comes from classic originals, but they feature a unique rectangular spout positioned at right angles to the main opening. This design creates two openings: one for pouring the water in and the other for pouring it out at right angles. In the early Mossoul water jugs, we see many examples that are clearly variations of this design, gradually transforming into the familiar neck with an attached spout, which is characteristic of later Mohammedan water jugs. This evolution can be followed step by step at the Munich Exhibition, confirming the seamless transition between Sassanid and Mohammedan designs.[20]
One of the features of early Mohammedan art is the vitality of its floral and geometrical ornament, the system of which is uniformly spread throughout the Mohammedan world. The question of where and how this system of ornament arose is not easily solved, but there are indications that Egypt was the place of its earliest development. Its characteristic forms seem certainly derived from the universal palmette of Græco-Roman decoration. The palmette, so rigid, unvarying and frequently so lifeless in the hands of Græco-Roman artists, became the source of the flexible and infinitely varied systems of Mohammedan design, so skilfully interwoven, so subtly adapted to their purpose, that the supremacy of Mohammedan art in this particular has been recognised and perpetuated in the word Arabesque.{83} It is curious to note that the history of this development is almost a repetition of what occurred many centuries before in the formation of the system of Celtic ornament. There, too, the Greek palmette was the point of departure. The Celtic bronze-workers adopted a cursive abbreviation of it which allowed of an almost too unrestrained flexibility in their patterns, but one peculiarly adapted to their bronze technique. In the case of Mohammedan art it would seem that the change from the palmette was effected by Coptic wood-carvers and by the artists who decorated in plaster the earliest Egyptian mosques. Indeed, one may suspect that the transformation of Græco-Roman ornament had already been initiated by Coptic workers in pre-Mohammedan times. One or two exhibits of Coptic reliefs in woodwork in Room 48 show how far this process had already gone. The Coptic wood-carvers arrived at an extremely simple and economical method of decoration by incisions with a gouge, each ending in a spiral curve, and so set as to leave in relief a sequence of forms resembling a half-palmette, and at times approaching very closely to the characteristic interlacing “trumpet” forms of Celtic ornament. A similar method was employed with even greater freedom and with a surprising richness and variety of effect in the plaster decorations of the earliest mosques, such as that of Ibn Tulun. In this way there was developed a singularly easy and rhythmic manner of filling any given space with interlaced and confluent forms suited to the caligraphic character of Mohammedan design. It cannot be denied that in course of time it pandered to the besetting sin of the oriental craftsman, his intolerable patience and thoughtless industry, and became in consequence as dead in its mere intricacy and complexity as the Græco-Roman original in its frigid correctness. The periods of creation in ornamental design seem indeed to be even rarer than those of creation in the figurative arts, and if the greater part of Mohammedan art shows, along with increasing technical facility, a constant degradation in ornamental design it is no exception to a universal rule. At any rate, up to the end of the thirteenth century its vitality was as strong and its adaptability even greater than the ornamental design of Christian Europe.
One of the key features of early Islamic art is the vibrant floral and geometric patterns, which are uniformly spread across the Islamic world. The origins of this decorative style are not easily determined, but it seems that Egypt was where it first developed. The distinctive forms appear to be based on the universal palmette found in Greco-Roman decoration. Unlike the rigid and often lifeless palmettes crafted by Greco-Roman artists, the palmette became the source of the flexible and incredibly varied designs in Islamic art, masterfully interwoven and subtly tailored to their purposes, establishing the dominance of Islamic art in this area, which is still recognized today in the term "Arabesque."{83} It’s interesting to note that the history of this development closely mirrors what happened centuries earlier with the Celtic ornament system. There too, the Greek palmette served as the starting point. Celtic bronze workers adopted a cursive shorthand of it that allowed for a flexibility in their designs, particularly suited for their bronze techniques. In Islamic art, it seems that the transition from the palmette was influenced by Coptic woodworkers and artists who created plaster decorations in the earliest Egyptian mosques. Indeed, one might suggest that the transformation of Greco-Roman ornament was already being initiated by Coptic artisans prior to the rise of Islam. One or two examples of Coptic wooden reliefs displayed in Room 48 showcase how advanced this evolution had already become. The Coptic woodworkers developed a straightforward and efficient method of decoration using gouge incisions, each ending in a spiral, which created a sequence of forms resembling a half-palmette and occasionally closely resembling the distinctive interlaced “trumpet” shapes of Celtic art. A similar technique was applied with even more freedom, leading to a surprising richness and variety in the plaster decorations of the earliest mosques, like Ibn Tulun. This resulted in a uniquely fluid and rhythmic way of filling spaces with interlaced and converging forms, suitable for the calligraphic nature of Islamic design. Over time, however, it fell victim to the common flaw of the Oriental craftsman: his excessive patience and unthinking labor, ultimately becoming as lifeless in its complexity as its Greco-Roman predecessor was in its cold precision. The periods of innovation in decorative design appear to be even rarer than those in the figurative arts, and while much of Islamic art reflects increasing technical skill alongside a consistent decline in ornamental design, this is not an exception to a broader trend. Nonetheless, up until the end of the thirteenth century, its vitality remained strong, and its adaptability surpassed that of the ornamental design seen in Christian Europe.
The design based on the half-palmette adapted itself easily to other materials than wood and plaster. In an even more cursive{84} form it was used alike by miniaturists and the closely allied painters on pottery. Of the former a good instance is that of a manuscript of Dioscorides, written and painted by Abdullah ben el-Fadhl in the year 1223 A.D. It is of Mesopotamian origin and shows in the decorative treatment of the figures a close affinity with the painting on contemporary pottery from Rakka. It is surprising how much character and even humour the artist gives to figures which are conceived in a purely calligraphic and abstract manner, and what richness and nobility of style there is in the singularly economical and rapid indications of brocaded patterns in the robes. Here we see how, in the hands of the miniaturists, the half-palmette ornament becomes even more cursive and flexible, more readily adapted to any required space than in the hands of the wood-carver and plasterer.
The design based on the half-palmette easily adapted to materials other than wood and plaster. In a more flowing form, it was used by both miniaturists and painters on pottery. A good example from the miniaturists is a manuscript of Dioscorides, created and illustrated by Abdullah ben el-Fadhl in 1223 A.D. It comes from Mesopotamia and shows a close connection in decorative style with contemporary pottery from Rakka. It's surprising how much character and even humor the artist imparts to figures that are designed in a purely calligraphic and abstract style, and there is a richness and elegance in the simple and quick representations of brocaded patterns on the robes. Here we see how, in the hands of miniaturists, the half-palmette ornament becomes more flowing and adaptable, fitting into any space more easily than it does in the hands of wood-carvers and plasterers.
The whole of the figure-design of this period, as seen in the pottery of Rakka, Rhages, and Sultanabad, shows the same characteristics. It is all calligraphic rather than naturalistic, but it is notable how much expression is attained within the flexible formula which these Mohammedan artists had evolved. The requirements of the potter’s craft stimulated the best elements of such a school of draughtsmanship, and for their power of creating an illusion of real existence by the sheer swiftness and assurance of their rhythm, few draughtsmen have surpassed the unknown masters who threw their indications of scenes from contemporary life upon the fragile bowls and lustred cups of early Syrian and Persian pottery.
The entire design style of this period, as seen in the pottery from Rakka, Rhages, and Sultanabad, shares the same traits. It's more calligraphic than realistic, but it's impressive how much expression is achieved within the flexible style developed by these Muslim artists. The demands of pottery craftsmanship pushed the best aspects of this drawing style, and when it comes to creating an illusion of real life through the speed and confidence of their rhythm, few artists have outdone the unknown masters who depicted scenes from contemporary life on the delicate bowls and shiny cups of early Syrian and Persian pottery.
It is generally believed now that not only in ceramics and metal work, but even in glass, Fatimite culture was pre-eminent. Probably no such collection of enamelled oriental glass has ever been brought together as that at Munich.
It is widely accepted today that Fatimite culture was exceptional not just in ceramics and metalwork, but also in glass. Likely, no other collection of enameled Oriental glass has ever been assembled like the one in Munich.
An example of glass of Egyptian origin bearing the date 737 A.D., belonging to Dr. Fouquet, shows how early the manufacture of glass was already established in Egypt. To Egypt, too, must be ascribed the splendid crystals and carved glass-work in which the Munich Exhibition is particularly rich. One of these is the so-called Hedwig glass from the Rijksmuseum, at Amsterdam. It has two finely conventionalised lions and eagles which resemble the types of Fatimite sculpture. It is described by Migeon (“Manuel,” p. 378){85} as being of moulded glass, but the design is probably cut on the wheel in the manner employed for rock-crystal. Among the examples of carved crystal one of the finest is the less well-known example of a waterspout in the shape of a lion’s head, lent by the Karlsruhe Museum. In all these figures the distinctive quality of Fatimite art, its combination of massive grandeur of design with extreme refinement, are apparent.
An example of Egyptian glass dated 737 A.D., owned by Dr. Fouquet, illustrates how early glass manufacturing was established in Egypt. Egypt is also credited with the stunning crystals and carved glassworks that the Munich Exhibition showcases so richly. One of these is the so-called Hedwig glass from the Rijksmuseum in Amsterdam. It features two beautifully styled lions and eagles that resemble Fatimite sculpture styles. Migeon describes it in his "Manuel" (p. 378){85} as being made of molded glass, but the design was likely cut using a wheel like in rock-crystal techniques. Among the carved crystal examples, one of the finest is a lesser-known waterspout shaped like a lion's head, lent by the Karlsruhe Museum. In all these pieces, the unique qualities of Fatimite art — its blend of impressive design and extreme refinement — are evident.
None the less, the evidence in favour of Syrian and Mesopotamian centres of glass-industry is very strong, and if many of the pieces, especially the earliest ones, are still relegated to Egypt, some of the finest are still ascribed, though on no very conclusive grounds, to the Syrian workshops. The finest of these belong to the late twelfth and early thirteenth centuries, and, generally speaking, the work of the fourteenth century shows a decline. Perhaps the most splendid specimen known is the large bottle from the treasury of S. Stephen’s, Vienna. The glass in this and the kindred piece from the same place shows a peculiar brownish yellow tone almost of the colour of honey, which gives the most perfect background to the enamelled figure-decoration. In the choice of subjects with a predominance of scenes from the chase there is undoubtedly a considerable resemblance to the scenes on the encrusted bronze work of Mossoul, and this, so far as it goes, makes in favour of a Syrian origin. But whatever their origin, the finest of these pieces show a decorative splendour and a perfection of taste which has assured their appreciation from the days of the Crusaders. Already in the inventory of Charles V. of France such pieces, frequently mounted on silver stands, figure among the King’s choicest treasures. Nor was the appreciation of this beautiful craft confined to Europe. One of the many proofs of a continual interchange between the Mohammedan and Chinese civilisations is seen in the number of examples of this glass which have come from China. In Munich there is a magnificent bowl lent by Dr. Sarre which is of Chinese provenance, and numerous other pieces have been recorded.
Nonetheless, the evidence supporting the existence of glass-making centers in Syria and Mesopotamia is quite strong. While many pieces, particularly the earliest ones, are still attributed to Egypt, some of the finest are credited, albeit without solid proof, to Syrian workshops. The best of these date back to the late twelfth and early thirteenth centuries, and generally speaking, the work from the fourteenth century shows a decline. Perhaps the most stunning example known is a large bottle from the treasury of S. Stephen’s in Vienna. The glass in this bottle, as well as in a similar piece from the same location, has a unique brownish-yellow hue, reminiscent of honey, which provides a perfect backdrop for the enamelled figures. The choice of subjects, particularly the scenes depicting hunting, bears a strong resemblance to the encrusted bronze work from Mossoul, suggesting a Syrian origin. Regardless of where they come from, the finest pieces exhibit a decorative richness and a level of taste that have ensured their admiration since the days of the Crusaders. In fact, in the inventory of Charles V of France, such pieces, often mounted on silver stands, are listed among the King’s most prized possessions. Furthermore, the appreciation for this exquisite craft extended beyond Europe. One of many indicators of ongoing exchanges between the Islamic and Chinese civilizations can be seen in the abundance of this glass found in China. In Munich, there is a remarkable bowl on loan from Dr. Sarre that originates from China, along with numerous other recorded pieces.
The collection of incrusted bronzes at Munich is extremely rich, ranging from the twelfth-century work, in which plastic relief is still used, accompanied by sparse incrustations of red copper upon the almost strawy yellow bronze, to the fourteenth and fifteenth-century{86} work, in which plastic relief has altogether disappeared, and elaborate incrustations of silver and even gold give to the surface an extreme profusion of delicate interwoven traceries. Here, too, the earliest work shows the finest sense of design. The specimen from the Piet Latauderie collection, still retains in its relief of stylistic animals a feeling for mass and grandeur inherited from Sassanid metal-workers, and the incrustations, though exquisitely wrought, are kept in due subordination to the general design. Some of the thirteenth-century pieces, though already tending to too great intricacy, still attain to a finely co-ordinated effect by the use of reserves filled with boldly designed figures. Some of the best of these contain scenes borrowed from Christian mythology, among which I may mention, as a superb example, the great bowl belonging to the Duc d’Arenberg.
The collection of inlaid bronzes in Munich is incredibly rich, spanning from 12th-century pieces that still feature plastic relief and minimal inlays of red copper on the nearly straw-colored yellow bronze, to 14th and 15th-century works where plastic relief is completely absent, showcasing intricate inlays of silver and even gold that create an abundance of delicate interwoven patterns on the surface. Additionally, the earliest works demonstrate an exceptional sense of design. The piece from the Piet Latauderie collection still possesses a sense of mass and grandeur in its relief featuring stylistic animals, inherited from Sassanid metalworkers, and the inlays, while exquisitely crafted, are harmoniously subordinate to the overall design. Some 13th-century pieces, though leaning towards excessive complexity, still achieve a well-coordinated look through the use of reserves filled with boldly designed figures. Some of the finest examples include scenes drawn from Christian mythology, and I would highlight the magnificent bowl owned by the Duc d’Arenberg as a superb illustration.
I have alluded at various points to the influence of Chinese art upon Mohammedan. Among the most decisive and curious instances of this is a bronze mirror with the signs of the Zodiac in relief. Round the edge is an inscription of dedication to one of the Orthokid princes. It is of Mesopotamian workmanship. Here the derivation from Chinese mirrors, which date back to Han times, is unmistakable, and is seen in every detail, even to the griffin-head in the centre, pierced to allow of the string by which it was carried.{87}
I have mentioned several times the influence of Chinese art on Islamic art. One of the most significant and interesting examples of this is a bronze mirror featuring the Zodiac signs in relief. Around the edge is an inscription dedicated to one of the Orthokid princes. It was made in Mesopotamia. Here, the connection to Chinese mirrors, which go back to Han times, is clear and is evident in every detail, including the griffin head in the center, which is pierced to allow for the string used to carry it.{87}
GIOTTO[21]
The Church of St. Francis in Assisi
WE find abundant evidences in studying early Christian art that Christianity at its origin exercised no new stimulating influence upon its development, but if it were claimed for the Franciscan movement that it brought about the great outburst of Italian art the position would be harder to refute: and indeed what S. Francis accomplished, the literal acceptance by official Christendom of Christ’s teaching, was tantamount to the foundation of a new religion, and the heresy of some of his followers, who regarded his as a final dispensation superseding that of the New Testament, can scarcely have seemed unreasonable to those who witnessed the change in the temper of society which his example brought about. S. Francis was the great orthodox heretic. What he effected within the bounds of the Church, for a time at all events, was only accomplished for later times by a rupture with the Papal power. He established the idea of the equality of all men before God and the immediate relationship of the individual soul to the Deity. He enabled every man to be his own priest. To the fervour with which these ideas were grasped by his countrymen we may ascribe to some extent the extreme individualism of the Italian Renaissance, the absence of the barriers of social caste to the{88} aspirations of the individual and the passionate assertion on his part of the right to the free use of all his activities. No doubt the individualism of, say, a Sigismondo Malatesta in the fifteenth century was very different to anything which S. Francis would have approved; none the less such a view of life was rendered possible by the solvent action of his teaching on the fixed forms of society.
WE discover plenty of evidence in studying early Christian art that Christianity, at its beginning, didn't really influence its development in a new way. However, it would be harder to dispute that the Franciscan movement sparked a major surge in Italian art. What St. Francis achieved—the actual acceptance by mainstream Christianity of Christ’s teachings—essentially laid the groundwork for a new religion. The heresy of some of his followers, who saw his teachings as a final revelation that replaced the New Testament, might not have seemed unreasonable to those who witnessed the shift in society that his example brought about. St. Francis was the great orthodox heretic. What he achieved within the Church, even if only for a time, would later require a break from Papal authority. He introduced the idea of equality among all people before God and emphasized the direct connection between the individual soul and the Divine. He allowed each person to be their own priest. The passion with which his countrymen embraced these ideas can partly explain the extreme individualism of the Italian Renaissance, the absence of social caste barriers to individual aspirations, and the passionate assertion of the right to freely pursue all their activities. Although the individualism of someone like Sigismondo Malatesta in the fifteenth century was very different from what St. Francis would have endorsed, such a perspective on life was made possible by the transformative effect of his teachings on the established social order.
But of more immediate importance to our purpose is the æsthetic element in S. Francis’ teaching. To say that in his actions S. Francis aimed at artistic effect would perhaps give a wrong impression of his character, but it is true that his conception of holiness was almost as much an æsthetic as a moral one. To those who know S. Bonaventura’s life a number of stories will suggest themselves, which indicate a perfectly harmonious attitude to life rather than a purely moral one: stories such as that of the sheep which was given to him, and which he received joyfully because of its simplicity and innocence, “and holding it in his hands he admonished it to be intent to praise God and to keep itself from offending the brethren; and the sheep observed fully the commandment of the Blessed Francis, and when it heard the brethren singing in the choir ran thither quickly, and without any teaching bent before the altar of the Blessed Virgin and bleated, as though it had human reason.”
But what's more important for our purpose is the aesthetic aspect of St. Francis’ teachings. Saying that St. Francis sought artistic effect in his actions might give the wrong impression of his character, but it’s true that his idea of holiness was as much about aesthetics as it was about morals. To those familiar with St. Bonaventure’s life, many stories come to mind that reflect a perfectly harmonious approach to life rather than just a moral one: stories like the one about the sheep given to him, which he happily accepted for its simplicity and innocence. “Holding it in his hands, he urged it to focus on praising God and to avoid upsetting his brothers; and the sheep completely adhered to St. Francis’ command, running quickly to the choir when it heard the brothers singing, and without any training, kneeling before the altar of the Blessed Virgin and bleating, as if it had human understanding.”
S. Francis, the “Jongleur de Dieu,” was actually a poet before his conversion, and his whole life had the pervading unity and rhythm of a perfect work of art. Not that he was a conscious artist. The whole keynote of the Franciscan teaching was its spontaneity, but his feelings for moral and æsthetic beauty were intimately united. Indeed, his life, like the Italian art which in a sense arose from it, like the Gothic French art which was a simultaneous expression of the same spirit, implies an attitude, as rare in life as in art, in which spiritual and sensuous beauty are so inextricably interwoven that instead of conflicting they mutually intensify their effects.
S. Francis, the “Jongleur de Dieu,” was actually a poet before he converted, and his entire life had the unity and rhythm of a perfect work of art. Not that he was a deliberate artist. The main theme of Franciscan teaching was its spontaneity, but his feelings for moral and aesthetic beauty were deeply connected. In fact, his life, much like the Italian art that, in a way, grew from it, and like the Gothic French art that simultaneously expressed the same spirit, reflects a mindset, as rare in life as in art, where spiritual and sensory beauty are so intertwined that instead of clashing, they enhance each other's effects.
Not only was the legend of S. Francis’ life full of suggestions of poetical and artistic material, but his followers rewrote the New Testament from the Franciscan point of view, emphasising the poetical and dramatic elements of the story. In particular they shifted the focus of interest by making the relationship of the Virgin to her son the central motive of the whole. It will be seen that{89} Italian artists down to Raphael turned rather to the Franciscan than the Vulgate version.[22] In fact, S. Bonaventura and the great poet of the movement, the cultivated and ecstatic Jacopone di Todi, did for the Christian legend very much what Pindar did for classical mythology; without altering the doctrine they brought into full relief its human and poetical significance.
Not only was the story of St. Francis’ life filled with ideas for poetry and art, but his followers also reimagined the New Testament from a Franciscan perspective, highlighting the poetic and dramatic aspects of the narrative. They particularly shifted the focus to make the relationship between the Virgin and her son the central theme. It’s evident that{89} Italian artists, all the way up to Raphael, leaned more towards the Franciscan interpretation rather than the Vulgate version.[22] In fact, St. Bonaventura and the movement’s prominent poet, the refined and passionate Jacopone di Todi, did for the Christian story what Pindar did for classical mythology; they didn’t change the doctrine but highlighted its human and poetic significance.
It is not surprising, then, to find that the great church at Assisi, built with all the magnificence that the whole of Italy could contribute to honour the spouse of Divine Poverty, should be the cradle of the new art of Italy—the neo-Christian or Franciscan art, as we might almost call it.
It’s not surprising, then, that the magnificent church in Assisi, built with all the resources Italy could offer to honor the partner of Divine Poverty, serves as the birthplace of the new art of Italy—the neo-Christian or Franciscan art, as we might almost call it.
The lower church of S. Francesco was probably decorated almost immediately after the building was finished, between 1240 and 1250, but these early works are almost obliterated by a second decoration undertaken after 1300. We must therefore turn to the upper church, the paintings of which were probably completed before 1300, as the chief source of our knowledge of the emergence of the new Italian style. It was there that the Italian genius first attained to self-expression in the language of monumental painting—a language which no other nation of modern Europe has ever been able to command except in rare and isolated instances.
The lower church of S. Francesco was likely decorated soon after the building was completed, between 1240 and 1250, but these early works are almost completely covered up by a second round of decoration done after 1300. So, we should focus on the upper church, where the paintings were probably finished before 1300, as the main source for understanding the rise of the new Italian style. It was there that Italian creativity first expressed itself in the language of monumental painting—a language that no other modern European nation has been able to master, except in a few rare cases.
And here we plunge at once into a very difficult, perhaps an insoluble problem: who were the painters who carried out this immense scheme of decoration? The archives of the church have been searched in vain, and we are left with a sentence of Ghiberti’s commentary, and Vasari, who here proves an uncertain guide, so that we are thrown chiefly on the resources of internal evidence.
And here we dive right into a really tough, maybe even an impossible problem: who were the artists behind this enormous decoration project? The church's archives have been searched without success, and we're left with just a line from Ghiberti’s commentary and Vasari, who isn’t a very reliable source here. This means we mainly have to rely on the clues within the artwork itself.
The paintings of the upper church may be briefly enumerated thus: In the choir are faint remains of frescoes of the life of the Virgin; in the right transept a Crucifixion and other subjects almost obliterated; in the left transept another Crucifixion, better preserved, and archangels in the triforium. The nave is divided into an upper and lower series; the upper series contains scenes of the Old and New Testaments, the lower is devoted to the legend of S. Francis, and in alternate vaults of the roof are paintings of single figures.
The paintings in the upper church can be summarized like this: In the choir, you can see faint remnants of frescoes depicting the life of the Virgin; in the right transept, there's a Crucifixion and other subjects that are nearly worn away; in the left transept, there's another Crucifixion that is better preserved, along with archangels in the triforium. The nave is divided into an upper and lower series; the upper series features scenes from the Old and New Testaments, while the lower series focuses on the legend of St. Francis, with individual figures painted in alternate vaults of the ceiling.
We will begin with the Crucifixion of the left transept, which is clearly by an artist of decided and marked personality. It is certainly less pleasing and less accomplished than the works of the later Byzantine school, and in spite of certain motives, such as the floating drapery of the Christ, which show Byzantine reminiscences, it is derived in the main from the native Italian tradition. This is shown in the stumpy proportions of the figures and the crude, not to say hideous, realism of the faces of the crowd. The classical origin of the tradition is still traceable in the sandalled feet and the reminiscence of the toga in some of the draperies. But the chief interest lies in the serious attempt made by the artist to give dramatic reality to the scene in a way never attempted by the less human Byzantines. The action of the Magdalen throwing up both arms in despair is really impressive, and this is a more vivacious rendering of a gesture traditional in Western early Christian art; an instance occurs in the fifth century MS. of Genesis at Vienna. But the artist shows his originality more in the expressive and sometimes beautiful poses of the weeping angels and the natural movements of the Virgin and S. John.
We will start with the Crucifixion in the left transept, created by an artist with a distinctive personality. It's definitely less attractive and polished than works from the later Byzantine school. Despite some elements, like Christ's floating drapery, that hint at Byzantine influences, the piece mainly comes from the Italian tradition. This is evident in the awkward proportions of the figures and the rough, even ugly, realism of the crowd's faces. You can still see classical origins in the sandaled feet and some drapery reminiscent of togas. However, what’s most interesting is the artist's serious effort to bring dramatic reality to the scene, a feat not attempted by the less relatable Byzantines. The gesture of Mary Magdalene throwing her arms up in despair is genuinely striking, and it’s a more lively interpretation of a gesture that’s traditional in early Western Christian art; a similar instance can be found in a fifth-century manuscript of Genesis in Vienna. The artist showcases his originality through the expressive and sometimes beautiful poses of the weeping angels and the natural movements of the Virgin and St. John.
Very nearly allied to this are the archangels of the triforium, and some of the frescoes of the upper scenes in the nave, such as the Nativity and the Betrayal. These belong to the same group, though they are not necessarily by the master of the Crucifixion himself.
Very closely related to this are the archangels in the triforium and some of the frescoes in the upper scenes of the nave, like the Nativity and the Betrayal. They are part of the same group, though they may not have been created by the master of the Crucifixion himself.
As we proceed along the nave, still keeping to the upper series, we come upon another distinct personality, whose work is typified in the Deception of Isaac. In certain qualities this master is not altogether unlike the master of the Crucifixion. Like him, he replaces the purely schematic linear rendering of drapery by long streaks of light and dark paint, so arranged as to give the idea of actual modelling in relief. But he does this not only with greater naturalism, but with a greatly increased sense of pure beauty. The painting is not hieratic and formal, as the Byzantine would have made it, nor has it that overstrained attempt at dramatic vehemence which we saw in the Crucifixion. The faces have remarkable beauty, and throughout{91} there is a sense of placid and dignified repose which is rare in mediæval work. It is, in fact, decidedly classical, and classical, too, in a sense different from the vague reminiscences of classic origin which permeate early Christian art, and were faintly echoed in the Crucifixion. Rachel especially, with her full, well-rounded eyes, wide apart and set deep in their sockets, her straight nose and small mouth, might almost have come straight from a Pompeian picture.
As we move along the central aisle, still focusing on the upper series, we come across another distinct personality, whose work is exemplified in the Deception of Isaac. In some ways, this artist is somewhat similar to the master of the Crucifixion. Like him, he replaces the purely schematic linear depiction of drapery with long streaks of light and dark paint, arranged to create the illusion of actual three-dimensional modeling. However, he does this not only with greater realism but also with a significantly enhanced sense of pure beauty. The painting is neither hierarchical and formal, like the Byzantine style, nor does it exhibit the overemphasized dramatic intensity we saw in the Crucifixion. The faces possess remarkable beauty, and throughout{91} there is a feeling of calm and dignified repose that is rare in medieval art. It is, in fact, decidedly classical, and classical in a way that differs from the vague hints of classical roots that permeate early Christian art, which were faintly reflected in the Crucifixion. Rachel, in particular, with her full, well-rounded eyes, wide apart and set deep in their sockets, her straight nose and small mouth, could almost have come straight from a Pompeian painting.
The hair, too, instead of being in tangled masses, as in the Crucifixion, or rendered by parallel lines, as in the Sacrifice of Isaac, is drawn into elegantly disposed curls, which yet have something of the quality of hair, and which remind us of the treatment in classic bronzes.
The hair, instead of being in tangled clumps like in the Crucifixion or shown with straight lines like in the Sacrifice of Isaac, is styled into elegant curls that still have the texture of real hair, reminiscent of the way hair is depicted in classic bronze sculptures.
The last vault of the nave, with the Doctors of the Church, is by an artist who is extremely similar to the last, and clearly belongs to the same group. The level brows nearly meeting over the bridge of the nose, the straight profile and the curled hair show the similarity, as does also the drapery. The classic tendencies of this artist may be seen in the amorini caryatides in the extreme corners of the spandril, while the decoration of one of the arches of the church by the same hand has, arising from an urn of pure classic design, a foliated scrollwork, in which centaurs disport themselves.
The last vault of the nave, featuring the Doctors of the Church, is by an artist who looks very much like the previous one and clearly belongs to the same group. The level brows that nearly meet over the bridge of the nose, the straight profile, and the curled hair all show the similarity, as does the drapery. The classic style of this artist can be seen in the amorini caryatides in the far corners of the spandril, while the decoration of one of the arches of the church by the same artist features a foliated scrollwork arising from an urn with a pure classic design, where centaurs are having fun.
In the lower series representing the Life of S. Francis we are at once struck by the resemblances to the last two paintings. The Pope, who is approving the rule of S. Francis, is almost a repetition of one of the Doctors of the Church. We have the same peculiar drapery with shiny, slippery, high lights, broadly washed on in well-disposed folds. The faces, too, though they are more individual and far more expressive, are, nevertheless, built on the same lines. They have similar straight profiles, the same deeply-cut level brows, which tend to meet in a line across the nose. The general impression it makes is that it is by a younger artist than the master of the Esau fresco, but one who has a keener feeling for reality and a far deeper sense of the dramatic situation.
In the lower section depicting the Life of St. Francis, we immediately notice the similarities to the last two paintings. The Pope, who is endorsing the rule of St. Francis, closely resembles one of the Doctors of the Church. The same distinctive drapery with shiny, slippery highlights is broadly applied in well-structured folds. The faces, while more individual and expressive, are still constructed along similar lines. They feature comparable straight profiles and the same pronounced, level brows that tend to meet in a line across the nose. Overall, it gives the impression of being created by a younger artist than the one behind the Esau fresco, but one with a sharper sense of reality and a much deeper grasp of the dramatic situation.
We will now turn to the historical evidence. The earliest and best is that of Ghiberti (early fifteenth century), who tells us simply that Giotto painted the S. Francis legend. Vasari says that Cimabue worked first in the lower church with Greek artists, and then did the{92} whole of the upper church, except the S. Francis legend, which he ascribes to Giotto. In addition to these we have a sixteenth-century MS. and an account of the church by Petrus Rudolphus of the same period, which agree that both Giotto and Cimabue painted in the upper church.
We will now look at the historical evidence. The earliest and most reliable comes from Ghiberti (early fifteenth century), who tells us that Giotto painted the S. Francis legend. Vasari mentions that Cimabue first worked in the lower church with Greek artists and then painted the{92} entire upper church, except for the S. Francis legend, which he credits to Giotto. Additionally, there's a sixteenth-century manuscript and an account of the church by Petrus Rudolphus from the same era, both of which confirm that Giotto and Cimabue painted in the upper church.
We may take it, then, that we have fairly good evidence for ascribing the S. Francis series in the main to Giotto, and a consensus of traditional opinion that somewhere in the other frescoes we ought to discover Cimabue.
We can confidently say that there's solid evidence linking the S. Francis series mainly to Giotto, and there's a general agreement that we should find Cimabue in some of the other frescoes.
The name of Cimabue is fraught with tender associations. To the last generation, happy in its innocence, it was familiar as a household word. Browning could sing without a qualm: “My painter—who, but Cimabue?” The cult of Cimabue became fashionable; it offended Philistine nostrils and received its due castigation from Mr. Punch. And now, alas, he would be a bold man who dared to say that he admired Cimabue, who dared to do more than profess a pious belief in his existence. Only recently a distinguished critic[23] has endeavoured to hand over to Duccio di Buoninsegna the very stronghold of the Cimabue faith, the altar-piece of the Rucellai Chapel in Sta. Maria Novella. But the myth dies hard, and Florentine guides will still point out the portraits of all Cimabue’s relations in the little figures round the frame. Ever since the time of Rumohr, however, who considered him to be little more than an emanation of Vasari’s brain heated by patriotic fervour, it has been established that we have no documentary evidence for any single picture by him. We do know, however, that at the very end of his life he executed the mosaic of the apse in the cathedral at Pisa. But this is a much restored work, and originally can have been little but an adaptation of a Byzantine design, and it throws no light on his work as a painter. In any case, all criticisms of his reputation in his own day, whether deserved or not, must fall to the ground before Dante’s celebrated lines, “Credette Cimabue nella pittura Tener lo campo, ed ora ha Giotto il grido,” for on this point Dante is first-rate evidence. And that being the case, there is a probability, almost amounting to certainty, that the man who “held the field” in painting would be requisitioned for the greatest national undertaking of his day, the decoration of{93} S. Francesco at Assisi, even though, as we have seen, it would be impossible to accept Vasari’s statement that he did the whole.
The name Cimabue carries a lot of emotional weight. For the last generation, blissfully unaware, it was a common name in households. Browning could sing without hesitation: “My painter—who else but Cimabue?” The Cimabue trend became popular; it turned off some critics and was rightly mocked by Mr. Punch. And now, unfortunately, it would take a courageous person to admit they liked Cimabue, to do more than just express a respectful belief in his existence. Recently, a prominent critic[23] has attempted to attribute the stronghold of the Cimabue legacy, the altar-piece of the Rucellai Chapel in Sta. Maria Novella, to Duccio di Buoninsegna. But the myth is hard to shake, and Florentine guides will still point out the portraits of all Cimabue’s relatives in the small figures around the frame. However, since Rumohr's time, who thought of him as merely a product of Vasari's imagination fueled by national pride, it has been established that we have no documentary proof of any single painting by him. We do know, however, that at the end of his life, he completed the mosaic in the apse of the cathedral in Pisa. But this is a heavily restored piece that likely started as just an adaptation of a Byzantine design, and it doesn’t really inform us about his painting style. In any case, whatever criticisms there were about his reputation during his lifetime, whether justified or not, must be set aside in light of Dante’s famous lines, “Cimabue thought he would dominate painting, but now it’s Giotto who has the glory,” for Dante is reliable evidence on this matter. Given that, it’s likely that the man who “held the field” in painting would be called upon for the greatest national project of his time, the decoration of{93} S. Francesco at Assisi, even though, as we’ve seen, it would be impossible to accept Vasari’s claim that he did it all.
In looking for Cimabue among the groups of the upper church which we have selected, it will be worth while to take as an experimental guide other works ascribed traditionally to our artist. If these should agree in their artistic qualities with one another and with any one group at Assisi, we shall have some probability in favour of our view. And the result of such a process is to find in the master of the Crucifixion our elusive and celebrated painter.
In searching for Cimabue among the groups in the upper church that we've chosen, it will be helpful to use other works traditionally attributed to our artist as a reference. If these works match in artistic quality with each other and with any group at Assisi, it will support our perspective. The outcome of this process is to identify our elusive and famous painter in the master of the Crucifixion.
It would be wearisome to go in detail through all these works; it will suffice to say that in certain marked peculiarities they all agree with one another and with the Crucifixion. The most striking likeness will be found between the heads which appear under the Virgin’s throne in the picture in the Academy at Florence, which Vasari attributes to Cimabue, and the grotesque heads to the right of the Crucifixion. There is the same crude attempt at realism, the same peculiar matted hair, the same curious drawing of the eye-socket which gives the appearance of spectacles. The characteristics of this picture will again be found in the Cimabue of the Louvre which comes from Pisa, where he is known to have worked. Very similar, too, in innumerable details of architectural setting, of movement of hands and heads, and of drapery is the fresco of the Madonna Enthroned and S. Francis, in the lower church at Assisi. Finally, the Rucellai Madonna, in spite of its very superior qualities, which must be due to its being a later work, answers in many detailed tests to the characteristics of this group of paintings.[24]
It would be exhausting to go into detail about all these works; it’s enough to say that they all share certain distinct features that are consistent with each other and with the Crucifixion. The most notable similarity can be seen between the heads that appear under the Virgin's throne in the painting at the Academy in Florence, which Vasari attributes to Cimabue, and the grotesque heads to the right of the Crucifixion. There’s the same awkward attempt at realism, the same peculiar matted hair, and the same unusual shape of the eye socket that looks like glasses. The characteristics of this piece can also be found in the Cimabue at the Louvre, which comes from Pisa, where he is known to have worked. The fresco of the Madonna Enthroned and St. Francis in the lower church at Assisi is very similar as well, in countless details of architectural setting, movement of hands and heads, and drapery. Lastly, the Rucellai Madonna, despite its clearly superior qualities, likely because it’s a later work, matches many specific characteristics of this group of paintings.[24]
And now, having found our Cimabue in the master of the Crucifixion, what must our verdict be on his character as an artist? Frankly we must admit that he is not to be thought of in the same category with the master of the Esau fresco, much less with Duccio or Giotto.[25] There is, however, in his work that spark of vitality which the Italians rightly prized above Byzantine accomplishment. He gave to his historical compositions a rude dramatic vigour, and to his Madonnas and Angels a suggestion of sentimental charm which borders on affectation; he was, in fact, a sentimental realist whose relation to the Byzantine masters must have been something like that of Caravaggio to the academic school of the Caracci.
And now that we’ve identified our Cimabue in the master of the Crucifixion, what should we conclude about his character as an artist? Honestly, we have to accept that he doesn’t belong in the same league as the master of the Esau fresco, let alone Duccio or Giotto.[25] However, there is a spark of vitality in his work that the Italians valued more than Byzantine achievements. He infused his historical pieces with a rough, dramatic energy, and his Madonnas and Angels have a hint of sentimental charm that verges on being overdone; he was, in fact, a sentimental realist whose relationship to the Byzantine masters was likely similar to Caravaggio's with the academic school of the Caracci.
We come next to the master of the Deception of Isaac, and the closely allied, if not identical, painter who did the Four Doctors of the vault. We have already noticed the likeness of these works to the legend of S. Francis, which we may take provisionally to be Giotto’s; but, in spite of the similarity of technique, they are inspired by a very diverse sentiment. They are not dramatic and intense as Giotto’s; they show a more conscious aspiration after style; the artist will not allow the requirements of formal beauty to be disturbed by the desire for expressive and life-like gestures. Where, then, could an artist of this period acquire such a sense of pure classic beauty in painting? In sculpture it might be possible to find classic models throughout Italy as Niccolo did at Pisa, but Rome was the only place which could fulfil the requirements for a painter. There must at this time have been many more remains of classical painting among the ruins of the Palatine than are now to be seen, and it is a natural conclusion that the artist who painted the figure of Rachel was directly{95} inspired by them. Nor is there anything difficult in the assumption that this unknown precursor of Giotto was a Roman artist, for the Roman school of painting was by far the most precocious of any in Italy. At Subiaco there are frescoes, some of which must date from the lifetime of S. Francis, which already, as in the portrait of S. Francis himself, show a certain freedom from Byzantine formalism. But it is in the works of the Cosmati, Jacopo Torriti, Rusutti, and Cavallini in the latter half of the thirteenth century that we see how vigorous and progressive an art was springing up in Rome.[26] Had not the removal of the Popes to Avignon in the fourteenth century left the city a prey to internal discord, we can hardly doubt that the Roman would have been one of the greatest and earliest developed schools of Italian painting. As it is, we find in the mosaics under the apse of Sta. Maria in Trastevere, executed about the year 1290, compositions in every way comparable to Giotto’s frescoes. These mosaics, too, have architectural accessories which are very similar to the architecture of the “Doctors of the Church” at Assisi. The architecture based on a study of classic forms is of the kind always associated with the Cosmati family. It will be seen that it is quite distinct from the architecture of Cimabue’s and Duccio’s Madonnas, but that it becomes the normal treatment in Giotto’s frescoes.
Next, we look at the master of the Deception of Isaac and the closely related, if not the same, painter who created the Four Doctors of the vault. We have already pointed out the similarity of these works to the story of S. Francis, which we can tentatively attribute to Giotto; however, despite the similarity in technique, they express a very different sentiment. They lack the dramatic intensity of Giotto’s work; instead, they demonstrate a more deliberate pursuit of style. The artist prioritizes formal beauty over the desire for expressive and lifelike gestures. Where, then, could an artist from this period gain such a sense of pure classical beauty in painting? While it might be possible to find classical models in sculpture throughout Italy, as Niccolo did in Pisa, Rome was the only place that could meet the needs of a painter. During this time, there must have been many more remnants of classical painting among the ruins of the Palatine than can be seen now, leading us to reasonably conclude that the artist who painted Rachel was directly inspired by them. It is also reasonable to assume that this unknown predecessor of Giotto was a Roman artist, as the Roman painting school was by far the most advanced in Italy. At Subiaco, there are frescoes, some of which must have been created during S. Francis's lifetime, displaying a certain freedom from Byzantine formalism, as seen in the portrait of S. Francis himself. However, it is in the works of the Cosmati, Jacopo Torriti, Rusutti, and Cavallini in the latter half of the thirteenth century that we see the emergence of a vigorous and progressive art in Rome. Had the Popes not moved to Avignon in the fourteenth century, leaving the city vulnerable to internal conflict, it’s hard to doubt that Rome would have become one of the greatest and earliest developed schools of Italian painting. As it is, we find in the mosaics under the apse of Sta. Maria in Trastevere, completed around 1290, compositions that can be compared to Giotto’s frescoes in every way. These mosaics also feature architectural elements that closely resemble the architecture of the “Doctors of the Church” at Assisi. The architecture, rooted in a study of classical forms, is typically associated with the Cosmati family. It is evident that this architecture is quite different from that of Cimabue’s and Duccio’s Madonnas, but it becomes the standard approach in Giotto’s frescoes.
There is, then, a curiously close analogy between the origins of neo-Christian painting and neo-Christian sculpture in Italy; just as Giovanni Pisano’s work was preceded by the purely classic revival which culminated in Niccolo’s Baptistery pulpit, so in painting Giotto’s work emerges from a similar classic revival based on the study of Roman wall-paintings. The perfect similarity between Niccolo Pisano’s sentiment and that of the master of the Esau fresco may be realised by comparing the action of Rachel’s hand in the fresco with that of the Virgin in the Annunciation of the Baptistery pulpit. In both we have the same autarchic conception of character conveyed by the same measured ease of gesture, which contrasts vividly with the more expansive ideals of neo-Christian art, of which Giotto appears from the first as the most perfect representative.
There is a surprisingly close similarity between the beginnings of neo-Christian painting and neo-Christian sculpture in Italy. Just as Giovanni Pisano’s work was preceded by a revival of classical styles that peaked with Niccolo’s Baptistery pulpit, Giotto’s painting also comes from a similar revival rooted in the study of Roman wall paintings. The striking resemblance between Niccolo Pisano’s sentiment and that of the master of the Esau fresco can be seen when comparing Rachel’s hand in the fresco with the Virgin’s hand in the Annunciation of the Baptistery pulpit. In both cases, we see the same self-sufficient portrayal of character expressed through a similar controlled gesture, which contrasts sharply with the broader ideals of neo-Christian art, where Giotto stands out as the most complete representative from the beginning.
In examining the series of frescoes describing the life of S.{96} Francis we find varieties in the proportions of the figures and in the types of features which suggest the co-operation of more than one artist, but the spirit that inspires the compositions throughout is one. And this afflatus which suddenly quickens so much that was either tentative or narrowly accomplished into a new fulness of life, a new richness of expression, is, we may feel certain, due to the genius of Giotto.
In looking at the series of frescoes that depict the life of S.{96} Francis, we notice differences in the proportions of the figures and in the styles of facial features, which suggest that more than one artist contributed to the work. However, the overall inspiration behind the compositions remains consistent. This burst of creativity that transforms what was once tentative or limited into a vibrant new life and rich expression is definitely the result of Giotto's genius.
If we look at one of these frescoes, such, for example, as the Presepio at Greccio, and at the same time endeavour to transport ourselves into the position of a contemporary spectator, what will strike us most immediately and make the most startling general impression is its actuality. Here at last, after so many centuries of copying the traditional forms handed down from a moribund Pagan art—centuries during which these abstractions had become entirely divorced from the life of the time—here at last was an artist who gave a scene as it must have happened, with every circumstance evidently and literally rendered. The scene of the institution of the Presepio takes place in a little chapel divided from the body of the church by a marble wall. The pulpit and crucifix are therefore seen from behind, the latter leaning forward into the church and showing from the chapel only the wooden battens and fastenings of the back. The singing-desk in the centre is drawn with every detail of screws and adjustments, while the costume of the bystanders is merely the ordinary fashionable dress of the day. The research for actuality could not be carried farther than this. When some years ago a French painter painted the scene of Christ at the house of the Pharisee with the figures in evening dress it aroused the most vehement protests, and produced for a time a shock of bewilderment and surprise. This is not to suggest any real analogy between the works of the two artists, but merely that the innovation made by Giotto must have been in every way as surprising to his contemporaries. Nor was Giotto’s, like M. Béraud’s, a succès de scandale; on the contrary, it was immediately recognised as satisfying a want which had been felt ever since the legend of S. Francis, the setting of which belonged to their own time and country, had been incorporated by the Italians in their mythology. The earliest artists had tried to treat the subject according to the formulas of Byzantine biblical scenes, but with such unsatisfactory results as may be seen in the altar-piece of the Bardi{97} Chapel of Sta. Croce at Florence. In Giotto’s frescoes at Assisi it acquired for the first time a treatment in which the desire for actuality was fully recognised. But actuality alone would not have satisfied Giotto’s patrons; it was necessary that the events should be presented as scenes of everyday life, but it was also necessary that they should possess that quality of universal and eternal significance which distinguishes a myth from a mere historical event. It was even more necessary that they should be heroic than that they should be actual. And it was in his power to satisfy such apparently self-contradictory conditions that Giotto’s unique genius manifested itself. It was this that made him the greatest story-teller in line, the supreme epic-painter of the world. The reconciliation of these two aims, actuality and universality, is indeed the severest strain on the power of expression. To what a temperature must the imagination be raised before it can fuse in its crucible those refractory squalid trivialities unconsecrated by time and untinged by romance with which the artist must deal if he is to be at once “topical” and heroic, to be at one and the same time in “Ercles’ vein” and Mrs. Gamp’s. Even in literature it is a rare feat. Homer could accomplish it, and Dante, but most poets must find a way round. In Dante the power is constantly felt. He could not only introduce the politics and personalities of his own time, but he could use such similes as that of old tailors peering for their needles’ eyes, a half-burnt piece of paper, dogs nozzling for fleas, and still more unsavoury trivialities, without for a moment lowering the high key in which his comedy was pitched. The poet deals, however, with the vague and blurred mental images which words call up, but the painter must actually present the semblance of the thing in all its drab familiarity. And yet Giotto succeeded. He could make the local and particular stand for a universal idea.
If we look at one of these frescoes, like the Presepio at Greccio, and try to imagine ourselves as a contemporary viewer, what hits us immediately and leaves the biggest impression is its realness. Finally, after centuries of copying traditional forms from a dying Pagan art—centuries during which these abstractions had completely lost touch with contemporary life—here was an artist who depicted a scene as it must have really occurred, with every detail clearly and literally represented. The scene of the creation of the Presepio takes place in a small chapel separated from the main church by a marble wall. The pulpit and crucifix are seen from behind, the latter leaning forward into the church, showing only the wooden supports and fastenings from the back. The singing desk in the center is depicted with detailed screws and adjustments, while the attire of the onlookers is simply the regular fashionable clothing of the day. The pursuit of reality could not have gone further than this. A few years ago, when a French painter depicted the scene of Christ at the Pharisee’s house with figures in evening dress, it sparked intense protests and caused a momentary shock of confusion and surprise. This isn't to suggest any real comparison between the works of the two artists, but merely to point out that Giotto’s innovation must have been just as striking to his contemporaries. Unlike M. Béraud’s work, Giotto’s was not a sensational scandal; rather, it was immediately acknowledged as fulfilling a need that had been felt since the legend of St. Francis, whose setting belonged to their own time and place, became part of Italian mythology. The earliest artists had attempted to portray the subject following the formulas of Byzantine biblical scenes, but with disappointing results, as seen in the altar piece of the Bardi Chapel of Sta. Croce in Florence. In Giotto’s frescoes at Assisi, it was treated for the first time in a way that fully recognized the desire for realism. However, reality alone wouldn't have satisfied Giotto’s patrons; it was essential that the events were shown as everyday scenes, but they also needed to possess that quality of universal and timeless significance that sets a myth apart from a mere historical event. It was even more crucial that they should appear heroic than just realistic. Giotto’s unique genius was reflected in his ability to meet these seemingly contradictory requirements. This is what made him the greatest storyteller in line and the supreme epic painter of the world. Balancing these two aims, reality and universality, certainly puts a severe strain on expressive power. Just think of the level of imagination required to blend the raw, mundane details unadorned by time and romance that the artist must work with to be both “topical” and heroic, to be simultaneously in “Ercles’ vein” and Mrs. Gamp’s. Even in literature, this is a rare accomplishment. Homer could pull it off, and so could Dante, but most poets need to find an alternative route. Dante’s power is always evident. He could not only bring in the politics and personalities of his own time but could also use similes like old tailors searching for their needle’s eyes, a half-burnt piece of paper, or dogs scratching for fleas, along with even more unsavory details, without lowering the elevated tone of his comedy. The poet works with vague and blurred mental images that words evoke, but the painter must present a tangible resemblance of the subject in all its ordinary familiarity. Yet Giotto succeeded. He could make the local and specific represent a universal idea.
But, without detracting in any way from what was due to Giotto’s superlative genius, it may be admitted that something was given by the propitious moment of his advent. For the optics of the imagination are variable: in an age like the present, men and events grow larger as they recede into the mist of the past; it is rarely that we think of a man as truly great till he has for long received the consecration of death. But there must be periods when men have a surer{98} confidence in their own judgments—periods of such creative activity that men can dare to measure the reputations of their contemporaries, which are of their own creation, against the reputations of antiquity—and in such periods the magnifying, mythopoetical effect, which for us comes only with time, takes place at once, and swells their contemporaries to heroic proportions. It was thus that Dante saw those of his own time—could even see himself—in the proportions they must always bear. The fact that S. Francis was canonised two years after death, and within twenty years was commemorated by the grandest monument in Italy, is a striking proof of that superb self-confidence.
But, without taking away from Giotto’s outstanding genius, it’s fair to say that the timing of his arrival played a role too. Our perspective on history is fluid: in times like today, people and events seem larger as they fade into the past; we rarely recognize someone as truly great until long after they’ve passed away. Yet, there are times when people have a stronger confidence in their own judgments—periods of such creativity that they feel bold enough to compare the reputations of their peers, which they have shaped themselves, against those of the past—and during these times, the magnifying, myth-making effect, which for us usually takes time, happens immediately, elevating their contemporaries to heroic status. This is how Dante perceived those around him—he could even see himself in the way they would always be remembered. The fact that St. Francis was canonized two years after his death and honored with the grandest monument in Italy within twenty years is a striking testament to that remarkable self-confidence.
We will return to the frescoes: the evidence for their being in the main by Giotto himself rests not only on the general consensus of tradition, but upon the technical characteristics and, most of all, upon the imaginative conception of the subjects. None the less, in so big a work it is probable that assistants were employed to carry out Giotto’s designs, and this will account for many slight discrepancies of style. Certain frescoes, however—notably the last three of the series—show such marked differences that we must suppose that one of these assistants rose to the level of an original creative artist.
We will go back to the frescoes: the evidence that most of them were created by Giotto himself is based not only on a general agreement of tradition but also on the technical details and, most importantly, on the imaginative way the subjects are portrayed. However, because this is such a large project, it’s likely that some assistants were hired to execute Giotto’s designs, which could explain various minor style differences. Certain frescoes, particularly the last three in the series, display such distinct differences that we must consider that one of these assistants developed into a truly original creative artist.
In the fresco of S. Francis kneeling before the Pope, we have already noticed Giotto’s close connection with the artists of the Roman school. Their influence is not confined to the figures and drapery; the architecture—in which it may be noted, by the way, that Giotto has already arrived instinctively at the main ideas of linear perspective—with its minute geometrical inlays, its brackets and mouldings, derived from classic forms, is entirely in the manner of the Cosmati. But the composition illustrates, none the less, the differences which separate him from the master of the Esau fresco. Giotto is at this stage of his career not only less accomplished, but he has nothing of that painter’s elegant classical grace. He has, instead, the greatest and rarest gift of dramatic expressiveness. For though the poses, especially of the bishop seated on the Pope’s left, lack grace, and the faces show but little research for positive beauty or regularity of feature, the actual scene, the dramatic situation, is given in an entirely new and surprising way. Of what overwhelming importance for{99} the history of the world this situation was, perhaps Giotto himself could scarcely realise. For this probably represents, not the approbation of the order of minor brethren by Honorius III., which was a foregone conclusion, but the permission to preach given by Innocent III., a far more critical moment in the history of the movement. For Innocent III., in whom the Papacy reached the zenith of its power, had already begun the iniquitous Albigensian crusade, and was likely to be suspicious of any unofficial religious teaching. It cannot have been with unmixed pleasure that he saw before him this poverty-stricken group of Francis and his eleven followers, whose appearance declared in the plainest terms their belief in that primitive communistic Christianity which, in the case of Petrus Waldus, had been branded by excommunication. In fact, the man who now asked for the Papal blessing on his mission was in most respects a Waldensian. Francis (the name Francesco is itself significant) was probably by birth, certainly by predilection[27] and temperament, half a Frenchman; his mother came from Provence, and his father had business connections at Lyons; so that it is not impossible that Francis was influenced by what he knew, through them, of the Waldensian movement. In any case, his teaching was nearly identical with that of Petrus Waldus; both taught religious individualism and, by precept at all events, communism. It was, therefore, not unnatural that Innocent should not respond at once to S. Francis’ application. According to one legend, the Pope’s first advice to him was to consort with swine, as befitted one of his miserable appearance. But, whatever his spontaneous impulses may have been, he had the good sense to accept the one man through whom the Church could again become popular and democratic.
In the fresco of St. Francis kneeling before the Pope, we’ve already seen Giotto’s close ties with artists from the Roman school. Their influence goes beyond just the figures and drapery; the architecture shows that Giotto instinctively grasps the main concepts of linear perspective, featuring intricate geometric inlays, brackets, and moldings drawn from classical forms, all styled after the Cosmati. However, the composition also highlights the differences between him and the master of the Esau fresco. At this point in his career, Giotto is not only less skilled but also lacks the elegant classical grace of that painter. Instead, he possesses the remarkable and rare gift of dramatic expressiveness. Although the poses, particularly that of the bishop seated on the Pope’s left, lack elegance and the faces show little pursuit of ideal beauty or symmetry, the scene and dramatic situation are presented in a completely new and surprising way. Giotto might not have fully understood how significant this moment was for the history of the world. This likely doesn’t represent the approval of the order of minor brothers by Honorius III., which was already expected, but rather the permission to preach granted by Innocent III., a much more critical moment in the movement's history. Innocent III., when the Papacy was at its peak power, had already initiated the unjust Albigensian crusade and would likely be wary of any unofficial religious teachings. He probably didn’t view with unqualified pleasure this impoverished group of Francis and his eleven followers, whose appearance plainly reflected their belief in a primitive communistic Christianity, which had led to excommunication for Petrus Waldus. In reality, the man who sought the Papal blessing for his mission was, in many ways, a Waldensian. Francis (the name Francesco is telling) was likely half French by birth and certainly by inclination and temperament; his mother was from Provence and his father had business ties in Lyons, so it’s possible Francis was influenced by what he learned about the Waldensian movement through them. In any case, his teachings closely matched those of Petrus Waldus; both advocated for religious individualism and, at least in theory, communism. Thus, it wasn't surprising that Innocent didn’t immediately respond favorably to St. Francis’ request. According to one legend, the Pope’s initial advice to him was to associate with pigs, fitting for someone of his sorry appearance. Yet, regardless of his initial feelings, he wisely recognized the importance of accepting the one man through whom the Church could become popular and democratic again.
Of all that this acceptance involved, no one who lived before the Reformation could understand the full significance, but Giotto has here expressed something of the dramatic contrasts involved in this meeting of the greatest of saints and the most dominating of{100} popes—something of the importance of the moment when the great heretic was recognised by the Church.
Of all that this acceptance meant, no one who lived before the Reformation could grasp the full significance, but Giotto has captured some of the dramatic contrasts in this meeting of the greatest of saints and the most powerful of{100} popes—something of the importance of the moment when the great heretic was acknowledged by the Church.
In the fresco of S. Francis before the Sultan we have a means of comparing Giotto at this period with the later Giotto of the Bardi Chapel, in Florence where the same scene is treated with more intimate psychological imagination; but here already the story is told with a vividness and simplicity which none but Giotto could command. The weak and sinuous curves of the discomfited sages, the ponderous and massive contour of the indignant Sultan, show that Giotto’s command of the direct symbolism of line is at least as great as Duccio’s in the Three Maries, while his sense of the roundness and solid relief of the form is, as Mr. Berenson[28] has ably pointed out, far greater. We find in the Sultan, indeed, the type for which Giotto showed a constant predilection—a well-formed, massive body, with high rounded shoulders and short neck, but with small and shapely hands. As is natural in the work of an artist who set himself so definitely to externalise the tension of a critical moment, his hands are always eloquent; it is impossible to find in his work a case where the gestures of the hands are not explicit indications of a particular emotion. The architecture in this fresco is a remarkable evidence of the classical tendencies which he inherited from the Cosmati school. The Sultan’s throne has, it is true, a quasi-Gothic gable, but the coffered soffit, and the whole of the canopy opposite to it, with its winged genii, pilasters, and garlands are derived from classic sources.
In the fresco of S. Francis before the Sultan, we can compare Giotto's work from this period with his later piece in the Bardi Chapel in Florence, where he approached the same scene with a deeper psychological insight. However, even here, the story is conveyed with a vividness and simplicity that only Giotto could achieve. The delicate and flowing shapes of the defeated sages and the heavy, imposing figure of the angry Sultan show that Giotto's mastery of direct symbolic line is at least as strong as Duccio's in the Three Maries, while his ability to depict the roundness and solid relief of form, as Mr. Berenson[28] has expertly noted, is significantly greater. In the Sultan, we see the type that Giotto consistently favored—a well-built, strong figure with high, rounded shoulders and a short neck, but small and elegant hands. As is typical of an artist who aimed to express the tension of a critical moment, his hands are always expressive; you can never find a case in his work where the gestures of the hands do not clearly represent a specific emotion. The architecture in this fresco is a remarkable testament to the classical influences he inherited from the Cosmati school. While the Sultan’s throne does have a sort of Gothic gable, the coffered soffit and the entire canopy opposite, adorned with winged genies, pilasters, and garlands, are derived from classical sources.
We have already considered the Presepio as an example of Giotto’s power of giving the actual setting of a scene without losing its heroic quality. It is also an example of his power of visualising the psychological situation; here, the sudden thrill which permeates an assembly at a moment of unwonted exaltation. It depicts the first representation of the Nativity instituted at Greccio by S. Francis; it is the moment at which he takes the image of the Infant Christ in his arms, when, to the ecstatic imaginations of the bystanders, it appeared for an instant transformed into a living child of transcendent beauty. The monks at the back are still singing the Lauds (one can almost tell what note each is singing, so perfect is Giotto’s command{101} of facial expression), but the immediate bystanders and the priest are lost in wrapt contemplation of S. Francis and the Child.[29]
We have already looked at the Presepio as an example of Giotto's ability to depict the actual setting of a scene while keeping its heroic feel. It's also a demonstration of his skill in visualizing the psychological moment; here, the sudden thrill that fills a gathering during an unexpected moment of joy. It shows the first Nativity scene created at Greccio by St. Francis; it captures the moment when he holds the image of the Infant Christ, when, for the excited imaginations of the spectators, it seemed for an instant to transform into a living child of extraordinary beauty. The monks in the back are still singing the Lauds (you can almost pinpoint the note each one is singing, thanks to Giotto's mastery{101} of facial expression), but the people closest to him and the priest are engrossed in deep contemplation of St. Francis and the Child.[29]
One of the most beautiful of the whole series is the fresco which represents the nuns of S. Clare meeting the Saint’s body as it is borne to burial. Throughout the series Giotto took Bonaventura’s life as his text, and it is interesting to see how near akin the two renderings are, both alike inspired by that new humanity of feeling which S. Francis’ life had aroused. Having described the beauty of the Saint’s dead body, “of which the limbs were so soft and delicate to the touch that they seemed to have returned to the tenderness of a child’s, and appeared by many manifest signs to be innocent as never having done wrong, so like a child’s were they,” he adds,
One of the most beautiful pieces in the entire series is the fresco depicting the nuns of St. Clare meeting the Saint’s body as it is taken for burial. Throughout the series, Giotto used Bonaventura’s life as his inspiration, and it’s fascinating to see how closely related the two interpretations are, both influenced by the newfound humanity that St. Francis’ life sparked. After describing the beauty of the Saint’s lifeless body, “with limbs so soft and delicate to the touch that they seemed to have returned to a child's tenderness, and appeared in many obvious ways to be innocent, as if they had never done wrong, so much like a child’s were they,” he adds,
Therefore it is not to be marvelled at if seeing a body so white and seeing therein those black nails and that wound in the side which seemed to be a fresh red rose of spring, if those that saw it felt therefor great wonder and joy. And in the morning when it was day the companies and people of the city and all the country round came together, and being instructed to translate that most holy body from that place to the city of Assisi, moved with great solemnity of hymns and songs and divine offices, and with a multitude of torches and of candles lighted and with branches of trees in their hands; and with such solemnity going towards the city of Assisi and passing by the church of S. Damiano, in which stayed Clara the noble virgin who is to-day a saint on earth and in heaven, they rested there a little. She and her holy virgins were comforted to see and kiss that most holy body of their father the blessed Francis adorned with those holy stigmata and white and shining as has been said.
So, it's no surprise that when people saw a body so white, along with those black nails and the wound in the side that looked like a fresh red rose of spring, they felt great wonder and joy. In the morning, when the sun was up, the townspeople and everyone from the surrounding countryside gathered together. They were directed to move that most holy body from its place to the city of Assisi, doing so with great solemnity—hymns, songs, and religious services, a multitude of lit torches and candles, and branches of trees in their hands. As they made their way to Assisi, passing by the church of S. Damiano, where the noble virgin Clara, now a saint on earth and in heaven, stayed, they paused for a moment. She and her holy virgins were filled with joy to see and kiss the most holy body of their father, the blessed Francis, adorned with those holy stigmata, shining white as described.
Bonaventura, we see, had already conceived the scene with such consummate artistic skill that it was, as it were, ready made for Giotto. He had only to translate that description into line and colour; and in doing so he has lost nothing of its beauty. Giotto, like Bonaventura, is apparently perfectly simple, perfectly direct and literal, and yet the result is in both cases a work of the rarest imaginative power. Nor is it easy to analyse its mysterious charm. Giotto was a great painter in the strictest and most technical sense of the word, but his technical perfection is not easily appreciated in these damaged works, and one cannot explain the effect this produces by any actual beauty of the surface quality of the painting; it depends rather on our perception, through the general disposition and action of the figures, of Giotto’s attitude to life, of the instinctive rightness{102} of feeling through which he was enabled to visualise the scene in its simplest and most inevitable form.
Bonaventura, as we can see, had already imagined the scene with such remarkable artistic skill that it was practically ready for Giotto to bring to life. He only had to translate that vision into lines and colors; and in doing so, he maintained all of its beauty. Giotto, much like Bonaventura, appears to be perfectly straightforward and direct, yet the outcome in both cases is a work with extraordinary imaginative power. It's also not easy to pinpoint its mysterious allure. Giotto was a master painter in the strictest and most technical sense of the term, but his technical excellence is hard to appreciate in these damaged pieces, and you can't explain the effect they create by any actual beauty of the paint's surface; it relies more on our understanding of Giotto’s perspective on life, reflected through the overall arrangement and actions of the figures, the instinctive rightness of feeling that allowed him to visualize the scene in its simplest and most inevitable form.
We come now to the three last frescoes of the series which show such marked differences from the rest, though some of the peculiarities, the minute hands and elegant features, appear in parts of some of the preceding frescoes, notably in our last: we may imagine that an assistant working under Giotto was, as the work progressed, given a larger and larger share in the execution, and finally carried out the three last frescoes alone. But this is pure hypothesis; all we can do at present is to note the difference not only of types, but even to some extent in the manner of conception, that they evince. One of them recounts the story of a woman of Benevento devoted to S. Francis, who died after forgetting one of her sins in her last confession. At the intercession of the dead Saint she was allowed to come to life again, finish her confession, and so defeat of his prey the black devil who had already come for her soul. Here the whole spacing out of the composition indicates a peculiar feeling, very different from Giotto’s. The artist crowds his figures into narrow, closely-packed groups, and leaves vast spaces of bare wall between. In this particular instance the result is very impressive; it intensifies the supreme importance of the confession and emphasises the loneliness and isolation of the soul that has already once passed away. When we look at the individual figures the differences are even more striking; the long thin figures, the repetition of perpendicular lines, the want of variety in the poses of the heads, a certain timidity in the movements, the long masks, too big in proportion for the heads, the tiny elegant features, elongated necks, and minute hands—all these characteristics contrast with Giotto’s tendency to massive proportions and easy expansive movements. Not that these figures have not great beauty; only it is of a recondite and exquisite kind. The artist that created these types must have loved what was sought out and precious; though living so long before Raphael, he must have been something of a “pre-Raphaelite.”
We now come to the last three frescoes of the series, which show significant differences from the others. Although some unique features, like delicate hands and graceful faces, can be found in earlier frescoes, especially the last one, we can imagine that an assistant working under Giotto progressively took on more responsibility in executing these final three frescoes, eventually completing them on his own. But that's just speculation; all we can do now is observe the differences in style and approach. One of them tells the story of a woman from Benevento who was devoted to St. Francis. She died after forgetting one of her sins during her last confession. Thanks to the intercession of the deceased Saint, she was allowed to come back to life, finish her confession, and thwart the devil who had come for her soul. In this example, the overall arrangement of the composition conveys a distinct emotion that differs from Giotto’s. The artist groups his figures tightly together in narrow clusters while leaving large areas of bare wall between them. This choice makes the scene even more powerful; it highlights the critical nature of the confession and accentuates the solitude of the soul that has already departed. When we examine the individual figures, the differences become even more pronounced: the elongated, slender figures, the repeated vertical lines, the lack of variety in the poses of the heads, a certain hesitance in their movements, the long faces that are disproportionately large for the heads, the tiny, elegant features, the elongated necks, and the delicate hands—all these traits contrast with Giotto’s preference for robust proportions and flowing movements. It's not that these figures lack beauty; rather, their beauty is subtle and refined. The artist who created these forms must have appreciated the rare and precious; even if he lived long before Raphael, he was likely something of a "pre-Raphaelite."
We have no clue to the identity of this pseudo-Giotto; he is quite distinct from Giotto’s known pupils, and indeed may rather have been a contemporary artist who came under Giotto’s influence than one trained by him. Besides the frescoes at Assisi, we are{103} fortunate enough to possess one other picture by this interesting artist. It is a small altar-piece dedicated to S. Cecilia, which hangs in the corridor of the Uffizi, and has been attributed both to Cimabue and to Giotto. The long Rosetti-like necks and heads, the poses, in which elegance is preferred to expressiveness, and the concentration of the figures so as to leave large empty spaces even in these small compositions, are sufficient grounds for attributing it to Giotto’s fellow-worker at Assisi.[30]
We have no idea who this pseudo-Giotto is; he’s quite different from Giotto’s known students, and he may have actually been a contemporary artist influenced by Giotto rather than someone who was trained by him. In addition to the frescoes at Assisi, we are{103} lucky enough to have one other piece by this intriguing artist. It’s a small altar piece dedicated to S. Cecilia, located in the corridor of the Uffizi, and it has been attributed to both Cimabue and Giotto. The long necks and heads reminiscent of Rosetti, the poses that favor elegance over expressiveness, and the way the figures are arranged to leave large empty spaces even in these small pieces are enough reasons to attribute it to Giotto’s collaborator at Assisi.[30]
In the year 1298 Giotto entered into a contract with Cardinal Stefaneschi to execute for him the mosaic of the “Navicella,” now in the porch of S. Peter’s. We have in this the first ascertainable date of Giotto’s life. It is one which, however, fits very well with the internal evidences of his style, as it would give the greater part of the last decade of the thirteenth century as the period of Giotto’s activity in the Upper Church at Assisi. One other work on the evidence of style we may attribute to the master’s pre-Roman period, and that is the Madonna of the Academy at Florence. Here Giotto followed the lines of Cimabue’s enthroned Madonnas, though with his own greatly increased sense of solidity in the modelling and vivacity in the poses. It cannot, however, be considered as a prepossessing work. It may be due to restoration that the picture shows no signs of Giotto’s peculiar feeling for tonality; but even the design is scarcely satisfactory, the relation of the Madonna to the throne is such that her massive proportions leave an impression of ungainliness rather than of grandeur. In the throne itself he has made an experiment in the new Gothic architecture, but he has hardly managed to harmonise it with the earlier classic forms of the Cosmati, which still govern the main design. We shall see that in his work at Rome he overcame all these difficulties.
In 1298, Giotto signed a contract with Cardinal Stefaneschi to create the mosaic of the “Navicella,” which is now located in the porch of St. Peter’s. This date is the first confirmed date in Giotto’s life. It aligns well with the stylistic evidence we have, suggesting that most of the last decade of the thirteenth century was when Giotto was active in the Upper Church at Assisi. Based on stylistic evidence, we can also attribute another work to Giotto's pre-Roman period: the Madonna of the Academy in Florence. In this piece, Giotto emulated Cimabue’s enthroned Madonnas but infused it with his own stronger sense of solidity in modeling and liveliness in the poses. However, it can’t be considered a particularly appealing work. It might be due to restoration, but the painting shows no signs of Giotto’s unique sensitivity to tonality; even the design is only moderately successful, with the relationship between the Madonna and the throne resulting in her bulky proportions creating an impression of clumsiness rather than grandeur. In the throne itself, Giotto attempted to experiment with the new Gothic architecture, but he struggled to unify it with the earlier classical forms of the Cosmati, which still dominate the overall design. We will see that in his work in Rome, he addressed all these challenges.
In Rome Giotto worked chiefly for Cardinal Stefaneschi. This is significant of Giotto’s close relations with the Roman school, for it was Bartolo, another member of the same family, who commissioned the remarkable mosaics of Sta. Maria in Trastevere, executed in 1290,{104} mosaics which show how far the Roman school had already advanced towards the new art, of which Giotto’s work was the consummation.
In Rome, Giotto mainly worked for Cardinal Stefaneschi. This highlights Giotto’s close ties with the Roman school, as it was Bartolo, another member of the same family, who commissioned the impressive mosaics of Sta. Maria in Trastevere, created in 1290,{104} mosaics that demonstrate how much the Roman school had already progressed toward the new art that Giotto's work represented.
The mosaic of the “Navicella,” which was the greatest undertaking of Giotto’s activity in Rome, is unfortunately terribly restored. We can, however, still recognise the astonishing dramatic force of the conception and the unique power which Giotto possessed of giving a vivid presentation of a particular event, accompanied by the most circumstantial details, and at the same time suggesting to the imagination a symbolical interpretation of universal and abstract significance. Even the surprising intrusion of a genre motive in the fisherman peacefully angling on the shore does not disturb our recognition of this universal interpretation, which puts so clearly the relation of the ship of the Church, drifting helplessly with its distraught crew, to the despairing Peter, who has here the character of an emissary and intermediary, and the impassive and unapproachable figure of Christ himself.
The mosaic of the “Navicella,” which was the most significant project of Giotto’s work in Rome, is unfortunately poorly restored. We can, however, still appreciate the incredible dramatic intensity of the concept and the unique ability Giotto had to vividly depict a specific event, complete with intricate details, while also suggesting a symbolic interpretation of universal and abstract significance. Even the unexpected inclusion of a genre scene with the fisherman calmly fishing on the shore doesn’t disrupt our understanding of this universal interpretation, which clearly illustrates the relationship between the ship of the Church, drifting helplessly with its panicked crew, and the despairing Peter, who acts as a messenger and intermediary, alongside the calm and distant figure of Christ himself.
The daring originality which Giotto shows in placing the predominant figure at the extreme edge of the composition, the feeling for perspective which enabled him to give verisimilitude to the scene by throwing back the ship into the middle distance, the new freedom and variety in the movements of the Apostles in the boat, by which the monotony of the eleven figures crowded into so limited a space is evaded, are proofs of Giotto’s rare power of invention, a power which enabled him to treat even the most difficult abstractions with the same vivid sense of reality as the dramatic incidents of contemporary life. It is not to be wondered at that this should be the work most frequently mentioned by the Italian writers of the Renaissance. The storm-gods blowing their Triton’s horns are a striking instance of how much Giotto assimilated at this time from Pagan art.
The bold originality that Giotto displays by placing the main figure at the far edge of the composition, his understanding of perspective that allows him to create a realistic scene by setting the ship in the background, and the new freedom and variety in the movements of the Apostles in the boat, which avoids the monotony of cramming eleven figures into such a tight space, are all evidence of Giotto’s exceptional creative power. This power allowed him to handle even the most challenging abstractions with the same vivid sense of reality as the dramatic events of contemporary life. It's not surprising that this is the work most often referenced by Italian writers of the Renaissance. The storm gods blowing their Triton’s horns are a striking example of how much Giotto absorbed from Pagan art at this time.
But of far greater beauty are the panels for the high altar of S. Peter’s, also painted for Cardinal Stefaneschi, and now to be seen in the sacristy, where the more obvious beauties of Melozzo da Forli’s music-making angels too often lead to their being overlooked. And yet, unnoticed in the dark corners of the room, they have escaped the attentions of restorers and glow with all the rare translucency of Giotto’s tempera.
But the panels for the high altar of St. Peter’s, also painted for Cardinal Stefaneschi, are even more beautiful, and you can now see them in the sacristy, where the more striking beauty of Melozzo da Forli’s music-making angels often means they get overlooked. Yet, tucked away in the dark corners of the room, they have avoided the attention of restorers and shine with all the unique translucency of Giotto’s tempera.
These are the first pictures we have examined by Giotto in which{105} we are able to appreciate at all the beauty and subtlety of his tone contrasts, for not only have the frescoes of the upper church at Assisi and the “Madonna” of the Academy suffered severely from restoration, but it is probable that in his youthful works he had not freed himself altogether from the harsher tonality of earlier art. Here, however, Giotto shows that power which is distinctive of the greatest masters of paint, of developing a form within a strictly limited scale of tone, drawing out of the slightest contrasts their fullest expressiveness for the rendering of form; a method which, though adopted from an intuitive feeling for pure beauty, gives a result which can only be described as that of an enveloping atmosphere surrounding the forms.[31]
These are the first works by Giotto we've looked at where{105} we can really appreciate the beauty and subtlety of his tonal contrasts. The frescoes in the upper church at Assisi and the “Madonna” in the Academy have both been heavily restored, and it's likely that in his earlier works, he hadn’t completely moved past the harsher tones of older art. Here, though, Giotto demonstrates the unique power found in the greatest painters, skillfully developing forms within a narrow range of tones and drawing out the deepest expressiveness from even the smallest contrasts to depict form. This approach, while rooted in an instinctive appreciation for pure beauty, results in a surrounding atmosphere that envelops the forms.[31]
The kneeling figure, presumably Cardinal Stefaneschi himself, in the “Christ enthroned” is an admirable instance of this quality. With what tender, scarcely perceptible gradations, with what a limited range from dark to light is the figure expressed; and yet it is not flat, the form is perfectly realised between the two sweeping curves whose simplicity would seem, but for the masterly modelling, to prevent the possibility of their containing a human figure. The portrait is as remarkable in sentiment as in execution. The very conception of introducing a donor into such a composition was new.[32] It was a sign of the new individualism which marked the whole of the great period of Italian art, and finally developed into extravagance. The donor having once found his way into pictures of sacred ceremonial remained, but he not infrequently found it difficult to comport himself becomingly amid celestial surroundings; as he became more important, and heaven itself became less so, he asserted himself with unseemly self-assurance, until at last his matter-of-fact countenance, rendered with prosaic fidelity, stares out at the spectator in contemptuous indifference to the main action of the composition, the illusion of which it effectually destroys.
The kneeling figure, likely Cardinal Stefaneschi himself, in the “Christ enthroned” is a great example of this quality. The figure is expressed with such delicate, almost imperceptible gradations and a limited range from dark to light; yet, it’s not flat. The form is perfectly realized between the two smooth curves that, due to the masterful modeling, wouldn’t seem capable of containing a human figure. The portrait is notable for its sentiment as much as its execution. The idea of including a donor in such a composition was innovative. It signaled the new individualism characterizing the entire great period of Italian art, which ultimately led to extravagance. Once the donor made his way into images of sacred ceremonies, he remained, but he often struggled to fit into the divine surroundings appropriately. As he gained more importance and heaven itself became less significant, he asserted himself with inappropriate confidence, until eventually, his matter-of-fact expression, depicted with practical accuracy, gazes at the viewer with disdainful indifference to the main action of the composition, effectively ruining its illusion.
But here, where the idea is new, it has no such jarring effect; it is not yet a stereotyped formula, an excuse for self-advertisement{106} or social display, but the direct outcome of a poetical and pious thought; and Giotto, with his unique rightness of feeling, has expressed, by the hand clinging to the throne and the slightly bent head, just the appropriate attitude of humble adoration, which he contrasts with the almost nonchalant ease and confidence of the angels. Even in so purely ceremonial a composition as this Giotto contrives to create a human situation.
But here, where the idea is fresh, it doesn't have that jarring effect; it isn't yet a tired formula, a cover for self-promotion or social showing off, but the direct result of a heartfelt and spiritual thought. Giotto, with his unique sensitivity, captures the appropriate attitude of humble worship through the hand gripping the throne and the slightly bowed head, contrasting it with the casual ease and confidence of the angels. Even in such a purely ceremonial composition as this, Giotto manages to create a human situation.{106}
In the planning of this picture Giotto has surpassed not only Duccio’s and Cimabue’s versions of the Enthronement motive but his own earlier work at Florence. The throne, similar in construction to that in the Academy picture, no longer shows the inconsistencies of two conflicting styles, but is of pure and exquisitely proportioned Gothic; the difficult perspective of the arches at the side is rendered with extraordinary skill though without mathematical accuracy. The relation of the figure of Christ to the throne is here entirely satisfactory, with the result that the great size of the figure no longer appears unnatural, but as an easily accepted symbol of divinity. In the drawing of the face of the Christ he has retained the hieratic solemnity given by the rigid delineation of Byzantine art.
In planning this painting, Giotto has outdone not only Duccio’s and Cimabue’s versions of the Enthronement theme but also his earlier work in Florence. The throne, which is constructed similarly to the one in the Academy painting, no longer displays the inconsistencies of two conflicting styles; instead, it is purely and beautifully proportioned in Gothic style. The challenging perspective of the arches on the sides is rendered with remarkable skill, even if it lacks mathematical precision. The relationship between Christ and the throne is completely satisfying, so the size of Christ’s figure doesn’t seem unnatural anymore; it’s easily accepted as a symbol of divinity. In the depiction of Christ’s face, he has kept the formal seriousness inherent in the rigid lines of Byzantine art.
But if the “Christ enthroned” is a triumph of well-calculated proportions, the “Crucifixion of S. Peter” which formed one side of the triptych, is even more remarkable for the beauty of its spacing and the ingenuity of its arrangement.
But if the “Christ enthroned” is a triumph of well-planned proportions, the “Crucifixion of S. Peter,” which made up one side of the triptych, is even more impressive for the beauty of its spacing and the cleverness of its layout.
In designing such a panel with its narrow cusped arch and gold background, the artist’s first consideration must be its effect as mere pattern when seen on the altar at the end of a church. In his frescoes, Giotto’s first preoccupation was with the drama to be presented; here it was with the effect of sumptuous pattern.
In creating a panel with its narrow pointed arch and gold background, the artist's main focus had to be how it looked as a simple pattern when viewed from the altar at the back of a church. In his frescoes, Giotto primarily concentrated on the drama to be conveyed; here, however, it was about the impact of a rich pattern.
And the given data out of which the pattern was to be made were by no means tractable. The subject of the Crucifixion of S. Peter was naturally not a favourite one with artists, and scarcely any succeeded in it entirely, even in the small dimensions of a predella piece, to which it was generally relegated. For it is almost impossible to do away with the unpleasant effect of a figure seen thus upside down. The outstretched arms, which in the crucifixion of Christ give a counterbalancing line to the long horizontal of the spectators, here only increases the difficulty of the single upright. But Giotto,{107} by a brilliant inspiration,[33] found his solution in the other fact given by his subject—namely, that the martyrdom took place between the goals of the Circus of Nero. By making these huge pyramids adapted from two well-known Roman monuments (the Septizonium and the pyramid of Cestius), he has obtained from the gold background just that dignified effect of spreading out above and contracting below which is so effective in renderings of the crucifixion of Christ, an effect which he still further emphasises by the two angels, whose spreading wings and floating draperies increase the brocade-like richness of the symmetrical pattern.
And the data used to create the pattern were definitely not easy to work with. The topic of Saint Peter's Crucifixion was not particularly popular among artists, and very few managed to depict it successfully, even in the small format of a predella piece, where it was usually placed. It's almost impossible to avoid the awkward impression of a figure shown upside down. The outstretched arms that provide balance in Christ's crucifixion only add to the challenge of the single upright here. However, Giotto, by a stroke of genius, found his solution in another aspect of his subject—specifically, that the martyrdom occurred between the goals of Nero’s Circus. By incorporating these massive pyramids inspired by two famous Roman monuments (the Septizonium and the Pyramid of Cestius), he created a gold background that provides just the right dignified effect of expanding above and contracting below, which is so striking in portrayals of Christ’s crucifixion. He further highlights this effect with two angels, whose outspread wings and flowing draperies enhance the luxurious, brocade-like richness of the symmetrical design.
Nor, the pattern once assured, has Giotto failed of vivid dramatic presentation. It is surprising to find crowded into so small a space so many new poses all beautifully expressive of the individual shades of a common feeling: the woman to the left of the cross leaning her head on her hand as though sorrow had become a physical pain; the beautiful figure of the youth, with long waving hair, who throws back both arms with a despairing gesture; the woman lifting her robe to wipe her tears; and, most exquisite of all, and most surprising, in its novelty and truth to life, the figure of the girl to the left, drawn towards the terrible scene by a motion of sympathy and yet shrinking back with instinctive shyness and terror. In the child alone Giotto has, as was usually the case, failed of a rhythmical and expressive pose. And what an entirely new study of life is seen here in the variety of the types! In one—the man whose profile cuts the sky to the left—he seems to have been indebted to some Roman portrait-bust; another, on horseback to the left, is clearly a Mongolian type, with slant eyes and pigtail, a curious proof of the intercourse with the extreme East which the Franciscan missionaries had already established. In the drawing of the nude figure of S. Peter, in spite of the unfortunate proportion of the head, the same direct study of nature has enabled Giotto to realise the structure of the figure more adequately than any artist since Roman times. One can well understand the astonishment and delight of Giotto’s contemporaries at this unfolding of the new possibilities of art, which could now interpret all the variety and richness of human life and could so intensify its appeal to the emotions. One other peculiarity of this picture is{108} interesting and characteristic of Giotto’s attitude. In painting the frame of his panel he did not merely add figures as decorative and symbolic accessories, he brought them into relation with the central action, for each of them gazes at S. Peter with a different expression of pity and grief. Giotto had to be dramatic even in his frames.[34]
Nor, once the pattern was established, did Giotto fail to present vivid drama. It's surprising to see so many new poses packed into such a small space, all beautifully expressing different shades of a shared emotion: the woman to the left of the cross leaning her head on her hand as if sorrow had become a physical pain; the striking figure of the young man with long flowing hair, throwing back both arms in a gesture of despair; the woman lifting her robe to wipe her tears; and, most exquisite of all, and most surprising in its novelty and lifelike quality, is the figure of the girl to the left, drawn toward the horrifying scene by a sense of sympathy but instinctively retreating in shyness and fear. In the child, however, Giotto has, as was often the case, failed to capture a rhythmic and expressive pose. The variety of types presents an entirely new perspective on life! In one—the man whose profile cuts the sky to the left—it seems he was inspired by some Roman portrait bust; another, on horseback to the left, clearly represents a Mongolian type, with slanted eyes and a pigtail, showcasing the interactions with the far East that the Franciscan missionaries had already established. In the drawing of the nude figure of St. Peter, despite the unfortunate proportion of the head, Giotto's direct study of nature has allowed him to depict the structure of the figure more accurately than any artist since Roman times. One can easily understand the astonishment and delight of Giotto’s contemporaries at this revealing of new possibilities in art, which could now interpret all the variety and richness of human life and could amplify its emotional appeal. One other interesting aspect of this picture, characteristic of Giotto's approach, is that in painting the frame of his panel, he didn’t just add figures as decorative and symbolic elements; he connected them to the central action, as each gazes at St. Peter with a different expression of pity and grief. Giotto had to be dramatic even in his frames.{108}
That Giotto remained in Rome till after the great Jubilee of 1300 is shown by the fragment of his fresco of the Papal Benediction which still remains on a pillar of S. John Lateran. There is every probability that at this time he met Dante, who was collecting the materials for the terrible portrait of Boniface VIII. which he drew in the “Inferno.”
That Giotto stayed in Rome until after the great Jubilee of 1300 is evidenced by the fragment of his fresco of the Papal Benediction that still exists on a pillar of S. John Lateran. It's highly likely that during this time, he met Dante, who was gathering information for the harsh portrayal of Boniface VIII that he created in the “Inferno.”
The next ascertainable date in Giotto’s life is that of the decoration of the Arena chapel at Padua, begun in 1305. Here at last we are on indisputable ground. The decoration of this chapel was conceived by Giotto as a single whole, and was entirely carried out by him, though doubtless with the help of assistants, and although it has suffered from restoration it remains the completest monument to his genius. The general effect of these ample silhouettes of golden yellow and red on a ground of clear ultramarine is extraordinarily harmonious, and almost gay. But essentially the design is made up of the sum of a number of separate compositions. The time had not come for co-ordinating these into a single scheme, as Michelangelo did in the ceiling of the Sistine. In the composition of the separate scenes Giotto here shows for the first time his full powers. Nearly every one of these is an entirely original discovery of new possibilities in the relation of forms to one another. The contours of the figures evoke to the utmost the ideal comprehension of volume and mass. The space in which the figures move is treated almost as in a bas-relief, of which they occupy a preponderant part. As compared with the designs at Assisi the space is restricted, and the figures amplified so that the plastic unity of the whole design is more immediately apprehended. I doubt whether in any single building one can see so many astonishing discoveries of formal relations as Giotto has here made. Almost every composition gives one the shock of a discovery at{109}
The next notable date in Giotto’s life is the decoration of the Arena Chapel in Padua, which began in 1305. Here, we finally have solid evidence. Giotto conceived the decoration of this chapel as a unified work and completed it himself, although he likely had assistants. Despite some restoration, it remains the most complete monument to his genius. The overall effect of the bold golden yellow and red figures against a bright ultramarine background is strikingly harmonious and almost cheerful. However, the design consists of several separate compositions. The time had not yet arrived for integrating these into a single scheme, like Michelangelo did in the Sistine Chapel ceiling. In the arrangement of the individual scenes, Giotto demonstrates his full capabilities for the first time. Nearly every one of these is an entirely original exploration of new ways to relate forms to each other. The outlines of the figures beautifully convey the ideal understanding of volume and mass. The space in which the figures are set is handled almost like a bas-relief, of which they occupy a predominant portion. Compared to the designs at Assisi, the space here is more confined, and the figures are more pronounced, making the overall plastic unity of the design clearer. I doubt there’s another single building where you can find as many astonishing discoveries of formal relationships as Giotto has created here. Almost every composition provides a thrilling sense of discovery at{109}
once simple, inevitable, and instantly apprehended, and yet utterly unforeseeable. In most compositions one can guess at some of the steps by which the formal relations were established. Here one is at a loss to conceive by what flight of imagination the synthesis has been attained. We will consider a few in greater detail.
once simple, unavoidable, and immediately understood, and yet completely unpredictable. In most pieces, you can figure out some of the ways the formal relationships were created. Here, it's hard to imagine how the combination was achieved. We'll look at a few in more detail.
Giotto was, I believe, the first artist to represent the Resurrection by the Noli me tangere. The Byzantines almost invariably introduced the Descent into Hades or the Three Maries at the Tomb. In any case it is characteristic of Giotto to choose a subject where the human situation is so intimate and the emotions expressed are so poignant. Here, as in the “Navicella,” where he was free to invent a new composition, he discards the bilateral arrangement, which was almost invariable in Byzantine art, and concentrates all the interest in one corner of the composition. The angels on the tomb are damaged and distorted, but in the head and hands of the Magdalene we can realise Giotto’s greatly increased power and delicacy of modelling as compared with the frescoes at Assisi. It is impossible for art to convey more intensely than this the beauty of such a movement of impetuous yearning. The action of the Christ is as vividly realised; almost too obviously, indeed, does he seem to be edging out of the composition in order to escape the Magdalene’s outstretched hands. This is a striking instance of that power which Giotto possessed more than any other Italian, more indeed than any other artist except Rembrandt, the power of making perceptible the flash of mutual recognition which passes between two souls at a moment of sudden illumination.
Giotto was, I believe, the first artist to depict the Resurrection with the Noli me tangere. The Byzantines almost always featured the Descent into Hades or the Three Marys at the Tomb. It's typical of Giotto to select a subject where the human experience is so personal and the emotions expressed are so intense. Here, as in the “Navicella,” where he had the freedom to create a new composition, he moves away from the symmetrical arrangement that was common in Byzantine art and focuses all the attention in one corner of the scene. The angels on the tomb are damaged and distorted, but in the face and hands of the Magdalene, we can see Giotto’s significantly enhanced skill and sensitivity in modeling compared to the frescoes at Assisi. It’s impossible for art to express more powerfully than this the beauty of such an intense yearning. The action of Christ is equally vividly portrayed; almost too obviously, he seems to be moving out of the scene to escape the Magdalene’s outstretched hands. This is a striking example of the ability Giotto had, more than any other Italian artist, and indeed more than any artist except Rembrandt, to capture the moment of mutual recognition that occurs between two souls during a moment of sudden realization.
In the “Pietà” (Plate) a more epic conception is realised, for the impression conveyed is of a universal and cosmic disaster: the air is rent with the shrieks of desperate angels whose bodies are contorted in a raging frenzy of compassion. And the effect is due in part to the increased command, which the Paduan frescoes show, of simplicity and logical directness of design. These massive boulder-like forms, these draperies cut by only a few large sweeping folds, which suffice to give the general movement of the figure with unerring precision, all show this new tendency in Giotto’s art as compared with the more varied detail, the more individual characterisation, of his early works. It is by this consciously acquired and masterly{110} simplicity that Giotto keeps here, in spite of the unrestrained extravagance of passion, the consoling dignity of style. If one compares it, for example, with the works of Flemish painters, who explored the depths of human emotion with a similar penetrating and sympathetic curiosity, one realises the importance of what all the great Italians inherited from Græco-Roman civilisation—the urbanity of a great style. And nowhere is it felt more than here, where Giotto is dealing with emotions which classical art scarcely touched.
In the “Pietà” (Plate), a more epic idea comes to life, conveying a sense of universal and cosmic disaster: the air is filled with the screams of desperate angels, their bodies twisted in a frenzied display of compassion. This effect is partly due to the increased mastery shown in the Paduan frescoes, characterized by their simplicity and clear design. These massive, boulder-like forms and the drapes marked by only a few large, sweeping folds effectively capture the overall movement of the figures with perfect precision, reflecting a new direction in Giotto’s art compared to the more detailed and individualized characteristics of his earlier works. It is through this deliberately acquired and skillful{110} simplicity that Giotto maintains, despite the wild intensity of emotion, a comforting dignity of style. When compared to the works of Flemish painters, who similarly explored the depths of human emotion with a keen and empathetic eye, one recognizes the significance of what all the great Italians learned from Greco-Roman civilization—the sophistication of a grand style. This is felt nowhere more than here, where Giotto engages with emotions that classical art rarely addressed.
It is interesting that Giotto should first have attained to this perfect understanding of style at Padua, where he was, as we know, in constant intercourse with Dante. Dante must have often watched him, perhaps helped him by suggestions, in decorating the chapel built with the ill-gotten wealth of that Scrovegni whom he afterwards seated amid the usurers on the burning sands of Hell.
It's fascinating that Giotto first achieved this perfect understanding of style in Padua, where he was, as we know, in constant contact with Dante. Dante must have often observed him, maybe even assisted him with suggestions, while decorating the chapel funded by the ill-gotten riches of that Scrovegni, whom he later placed among the usurers on the burning sands of Hell.
It is mainly by means of the composition and the general conception of pose and movement that Giotto expresses the dramatic idea. And regarded from that point of view, these frescoes are an astounding proof of Giotto’s infallible intuitions. The characters he has created here are as convincing, as ineffaceable, as any that have been created by poets. The sad figure of Joachim is one never to be forgotten. In every incident of his sojourn in the wilderness, after the rejection of his offering in the temple, his appearance indicates exactly his mental condition. When he first comes to the sheepfold, he gazes with such set melancholy on the ground that the greeting of his dog and his shepherds cannot arouse his attention; when he makes a sacrifice he crawls on hands and knees in the suspense of expectation, watching for a sign from heaven; even in his sleep we guess at his melancholy dreams; and in the scene where he meets his wife at the Golden Gate on his return, Giotto has touched a chord of feeling at least as profound as can be reached by the most consummate master of the art of words.
Giotto mainly uses the arrangement of figures and the overall design of poses and movements to convey dramatic ideas. From this perspective, these frescoes are incredible evidence of Giotto’s keen insights. The characters he created are as believable and unforgettable as any crafted by poets. The sorrowful figure of Joachim leaves a lasting impression. Throughout his time in the wilderness, after his offering was rejected at the temple, his demeanor perfectly reflects his mental state. When he arrives at the sheepfold, he looks down with deep sadness, so much so that he doesn’t even notice his dog and shepherds greeting him. While making a sacrifice, he crawls on his hands and knees in anxious anticipation, waiting for a sign from heaven; even in his sleep, we sense his sorrowful dreams; and in the moment where he reconnects with his wife at the Golden Gate upon his return, Giotto evokes emotions as deep as those stirred by the greatest masters of the written word.
It is true that in speaking of these one is led inevitably to talk of elements in the work which modern criticism is apt to regard as lying outside the domain of pictorial art. It is customary to dismiss all that concerns the dramatic presentation of the subject as literature or illustration, which is to be sharply distinguished from the qualities of design. But can this clear distinction be drawn in fact? The{111} imaginings of a playwright, a dramatic poet, and a dramatic painter have much in common, but they are never at any point identical. Let us suppose a story to be treated by all three: to each, as he dwells on the legend, the imagination will present a succession of images, but those images, even at their first formation, will be quite different in each case, they will be conditioned and coloured by the art which the creator practises, by his past observation of nature with a view to presentment in that particular art. The painter, like Giotto, therefore, actually imagines in terms of figures capable of pictorial presentment, he does not merely translate a poetically dramatic vision into pictorial terms. And to be able to do this implies a constant observation of natural forms with a bias towards the discovery of pictorial beauty. To be able, then, to conceive just the appropriate pose of a hand to express the right idea of character and emotion in a picture, is surely as much a matter of a painter’s vision as to appreciate the relative “values” of a tree and cloud so as to convey the mood proper to a particular landscape.
It's true that when discussing these topics, one inevitably ends up talking about aspects of the work that modern critics tend to see as outside the realm of visual art. It’s common to dismiss everything related to the dramatic presentation of the subject as literature or illustration, which is clearly different from the qualities of design. But can we really draw such a clear line? The ideas of a playwright, a dramatic poet, and a dramatic painter share a lot in common, but they are never identical. Let's imagine a story that all three are tackling: for each, as they focus on the legend, their imagination will create a sequence of images, but those images, even from the very beginning, will vary significantly for each one. They will be shaped and influenced by the art that the creator practices and by their previous observations of nature aimed at presentation in that specific art form. The painter, like Giotto, actually imagines in terms of figures that can be depicted visually; he doesn’t just translate a poetically dramatic vision into pictorial format. To do this requires a continuous observation of natural forms with an eye for discovering pictorial beauty. Therefore, being able to conceive just the right pose of a hand to express the appropriate character and emotion in a picture is just as much a part of a painter's vision as understanding the relative “values” of a tree and cloud to convey the right mood for a particular landscape.
Before leaving the Paduan frescoes, I must allude to those allegorical figures of the virtues and vices in which Giotto has, as it were, distilled the essence of his understanding of human nature. These personified virtues and vices were the rhetorical commonplaces of the day, but Giotto’s intuitive understanding of the expression of emotion enabled him to give them a profound significance. He has in some succeeded in giving not merely a person under the influence of a given passion, but the abstract passion itself, not merely an angry woman, but anger. To conceive thus a figure possessed absolutely by a single passion implied, an excursion beyond the regions of experience; no merely scientific observation of the effects of emotion would have enabled him to conceive the figure of Anger. It required an imagination that could range the remotest spaces thus to condense in visible form the bestial madness of the passion, to depict what Blake would have called the “diabolical abstract” of anger.
Before leaving the Paduan frescoes, I need to mention those allegorical figures representing virtues and vices in which Giotto has, in a sense, captured the essence of his understanding of human nature. These personified virtues and vices were common rhetorical themes of the time, but Giotto’s intuitive grasp of emotional expression allowed him to give them deep significance. He has, in some cases, created not just a person affected by a specific passion, but the passion itself—not just an angry woman, but anger itself. To envision a figure completely consumed by a single passion required a leap beyond ordinary experience; simple scientific observation of emotional effects wouldn’t have allowed him to conceive the figure of Anger. It took an imagination capable of reaching far and wide to distill into visible form the raw madness of that passion, to illustrate what Blake would have called the “diabolical abstract” of anger.
We come now to the last great series of frescoes by Giotto which we possess, those of the Bardi and Peruzzi chapels of Sta. Croce, his maturest and most consummate works. From the very first Giotto had to the full the power of seizing upon whatever in the forms of{112} nature expressed life and emotion, but the perfect understanding of the conditions of a suave and gracious style was only slowly acquired. In the Florentine frescoes it is the geniality, the persuasiveness of the style which first strikes us. They have, indeed, an almost academic perfection of design.
We now turn to the last great series of frescoes by Giotto that we have, those in the Bardi and Peruzzi chapels of Sta. Croce, which are his most mature and accomplished works. From the beginning, Giotto had a remarkable ability to capture whatever in the forms of{112} nature expressed life and emotion, but he gradually developed a deep understanding of the elements that create a smooth and elegant style. In the Florentine frescoes, what strikes us first is the warmth and appeal of the style. They indeed exhibit an almost academic perfection in design.
The comparison of the “Death of S. Francis” here with the early fresco of the subject at Assisi shows how far Giotto has moved from the literal realism of his first works. At Assisi crowds of people push round the bier, soldiers and citizens come in to see, there is all the shifting variety of the actual event. Here the composition is sublimated and refined, reduced to its purest elements. The scene is still vividly, intensely real, but it is apprehended in a more pensive and meditative vein. There is in the composition a feeling for space which imposes a new mood of placidity and repose. This composition became the typical formula for such subjects throughout the Renaissance, but it was never again equalled. In spite of its apparent ease and simplicity, it is really by the subtlest art that all these figures are grouped in such readily apprehended masses without any sense of crowding and with such variety of gesture in the figures. The fresco, which had remained for more than a century under a coat of whitewash, was discovered in 1841 and immediately disfigured by utter restoration. The artist,[35] with a vague idea that Giotto was a decorative artist, and that decoration meant something ugly and unnatural, surrounded the figures with hard inexpressive lines. We can, therefore, only guess, by our knowledge of Giotto elsewhere, and by the general idea of pose, how perfect was the characterisation of the actors in the scene, how each responded according to his temperament to the general sorrow, some in humble prostration, one with a more intimate and personal affection, and one, to whom the vision of the ascending soul is apparent, wrapt in mystic ecstasy.
The comparison of the “Death of S. Francis” here with the early fresco of the same subject at Assisi shows how far Giotto has evolved from the straightforward realism of his earlier works. At Assisi, crowds of people gather around the bier, soldiers and townsfolk come to watch, capturing the dynamic variety of the actual event. Here, the composition is elevated and refined, stripped down to its essential elements. The scene remains vividly, intensely real, but it is experienced in a more thoughtful and reflective way. There is a sense of space in the composition that creates a new mood of calm and serenity. This composition became the standard formula for similar subjects throughout the Renaissance, but it was never again matched. Despite its apparent simplicity and ease, it is through subtle artistry that all these figures are arranged into easily understood groups without feeling overcrowded and with such varied gestures. The fresco, which had been covered by a layer of whitewash for over a century, was rediscovered in 1841 and then unfortunately damaged through misguided restoration efforts. The artist,[35] with only a vague idea that Giotto was a decorative artist—and that decoration meant something ugly and unnatural—surrounded the figures with harsh, lifeless lines. Therefore, we can only speculate, based on our knowledge of Giotto from other works and by the general idea of pose, how beautifully each character in the scene was depicted, how each responded to the collective grief—some in humble submission, one with a deeper, more personal affection, and another, for whom the vision of the ascending soul is clear, lost in mystic ecstasy.
An interesting characteristic of these late frescoes is the revival which they declare of Giotto’s early love for classical architecture. He may well have recognised the pictorial value of the large {113}untroubled rectangular spaces which it allowed. In the “Salome” he has approached even more nearly to purely classic forms than in his earliest frescoes at Assisi. The building has an almost Palladian effect with its square parapets surmounted by statues, some of which are clearly derived from the antique. In the soldier who brings in the Baptist’s head he has reverted to the costume of the Roman soldier, whereas, in the allegory of Chastity, the soldiers wear mediæval winged helmets.
An interesting feature of these later frescoes is the revival of Giotto’s early passion for classical architecture. He likely appreciated the visual appeal of the large {113}untroubled rectangular spaces it provided. In the “Salome,” he has gotten even closer to purely classical forms than he did in his earliest frescoes at Assisi. The structure has an almost Palladian look with its square parapets topped with statues, some of which are clearly inspired by ancient designs. In the soldier who brings in the Baptist’s head, he has reverted to the attire of a Roman soldier, while in the allegory of Chastity, the soldiers wear medieval winged helmets.
The fact that there is a free copy of this fresco by the Lorenzetti at Siena made in 1331 gives us the period before which this must have been finished. Here again the mood is singularly placid, but the intensity with which Giotto realised a particularly dramatic moment is shown by a curious detail in which this differs from the usual rendering of the scene. Most artists, wishing to express the essentials of the story, make Salome continue her dance while the head is brought in. But Giotto was too deep a psychologist to make such an error. At the tragic moment she stops dancing and makes sad music on her lyre, to show that she, too, is not wanting in proper sensibility.
The fact that there’s a free copy of this fresco by the Lorenzetti in Siena from 1331 tells us that this must have been finished before that time. Again, the mood is notably calm, but the intensity with which Giotto captured a particularly dramatic moment is highlighted by a curious detail that sets it apart from the usual depiction of the scene. Most artists, wanting to convey the essentials of the story, show Salome continuing her dance while the head is brought in. But Giotto understood psychology too well to make that mistake. At the tragic moment, she stops dancing and plays sad music on her lyre, to illustrate that she, too, possesses genuine sensitivity.
There is evidence in these frescoes of an artistic quality which we could scarcely have believed possible, and yet, as it is most evident in those parts which are least damaged, it is impossible not to believe that Giotto possessed it; and that is the real feeling for chiaroscuro which these paintings show. It is not merely that the light falls in one direction, though even that was a conception which was scarcely grasped before Masaccio, but that Giotto actually composes by light and shade, subordinates figures or groups of figures by letting them recede into gloom and brings others into prominent light. This is particularly well seen in the “Ascension of S. John” where the shadow of the building is made use of to unify the composition and give depth and relief to the imagined space. It is also an example of that beautiful atmospheric tonality of which I have already spoken. In the figure of S. John himself, Giotto seems to have the freedom and ease which we associate with art of a much later date. There is scarcely a hint of archaism in this figure. The head, with its perfect fusion of tones, its atmospheric envelopment, seems already nearly as modern as a head by Titian. Even the colour scheme, the rich{114} earthy reds, the intense sweet blues of the figures relieved against a broken green-grey, is a strange anticipation of Cinquecento art. It seems as though Giotto in these works had himself explored the whole of the promised land to which he led Italian painting.
These frescoes show an artistic quality that we might not have believed possible. However, it’s clear, especially in the parts that are least damaged, that Giotto had this talent; the real sense of light and shadow evident in these paintings confirms it. It's not just that the light comes from one direction—though even that idea was barely understood before Masaccio—but that Giotto actually arranges composition with light and shadow. He emphasizes figures or groups by letting some fade into darkness while bringing others into bright light. This is especially noticeable in the “Ascension of S. John,” where the shadow of the building helps to unify the composition and adds depth to the imagined space. It also exemplifies the lovely atmospheric quality I mentioned earlier. In the figure of S. John, Giotto seems to embody a freedom and ease we usually connect with much later art. There’s hardly any sign of outdated style in this figure. The head, with its perfect blend of tones and atmospheric surround, looks almost as modern as a head by Titian. Even the color scheme—the rich earthy reds and the vibrant blues of the figures set against a muted green-grey—strangely anticipates Cinquecento art. It feels like Giotto, in these works, had already explored the entire promised land that he would later lead Italian painting into.
It is true that we are conscious of a certain archaism here in the relations of the figures and the architecture. A certain violence is done to that demand for verisimilitude which, perhaps wrongly, we now invariably make. But in the “Raising of Drusiana,” even this demand is met. Here the figures all have their just proportions to one another, and to the buildings, and to the town wall which stretches behind them. The scene is imagined, not merely according to the conditions of the dramatic idea, but according to the possibilities and limitations of actual figures moving in a three dimensional space; even the perspective of the ground is understood. Such an imaginative construction of three dimensional space had its disadvantages as well as its advantages for art, but in any case it is an astonishing indication of Giotto’s genius that he thus foresaw the conditions which in the end would be accepted universally in European art. There is scarcely anything here that Raphael would have had to alter to adapt the composition to one of his tapestry cartoons.
It's true that there's a certain outdated quality in the relationships between the figures and the architecture. A bit of a strain is placed on our demand for realism, which we maybe unfairly insist on now. But in the “Raising of Drusiana,” even this demand is fulfilled. Here, the figures are all in proportion to each other, to the buildings, and to the town wall that stretches behind them. The scene is created not just based on the dramatic idea, but also on the actual possibilities and limitations of figures moving in a three-dimensional space; even the perspective of the ground is well understood. This imaginative construction of three-dimensional space had both its pros and cons for art, but it's truly remarkable that Giotto anticipated the conditions that would eventually become standard in European art. There’s almost nothing here that Raphael would need to change to fit the composition into one of his tapestry designs.
Of the dramatic power of this I need add nothing to what has already been said, but as this is the last of his works which we shall examine it may afford an example of some of the characteristics of Giotto’s draughtsmanship. For Giotto was one of the greatest masters of line that the world has seen, and the fact that his knowledge of the forms of the figure was comparatively elementary in no way interferes with his greatness. It is not how many facts about an object an artist can record, but how incisive and how harmonious with itself the record is, that constitutes the essence of draughtsmanship.
I don’t need to add anything about the dramatic power of this that hasn’t already been mentioned, but since this is the last of his works we’ll look at, it can serve as an example of some features of Giotto’s drawing style. Giotto was one of the greatest masters of line in history, and the fact that his understanding of the human form was relatively basic doesn’t diminish his greatness. What truly matters in drawing isn’t how many details an artist can capture about an object, but rather how sharp and cohesive the representation is—it’s this quality that defines the essence of drawing.
In considering the qualities of line, three main elements are to be regarded: First, the decorative rhythm, our sense of sight being constructed like our sense of sound, so that certain relations, probably those which are capable of mathematical analysis, are pleasing, and others discordant. Secondly, the significance of line as enabling us imaginatively to reconstruct a real, not necessarily an actual, object from it. The greatest excellence of this quality will be the condensation of the greatest possible suggestion of real form into the simplest,{115} most easily apprehended line; the absence of confusing superfluity on the one hand, and mechanical, and therefore meaningless simplicity, on the other. Finally, we may regard line as a gesture, which impresses us as a direct revelation of the artist’s personality in the same way that handwriting does.
When looking at the qualities of line, there are three main elements to consider: First, the decorative rhythm. Our sense of sight is structured similarly to our sense of sound, making certain relationships—likely those that can be broken down mathematically—pleasing, while others feel dissonant. Second, the importance of line lies in its ability to help us imagine reconstructing a real, though not necessarily actual, object from it. The highest achievement of this quality is distilling the greatest suggestion of real form into the simplest, {115} most easily understood line, avoiding both confusing excess and mechanical, therefore meaningless, simplicity. Finally, we can think of line as a gesture that serves as a direct expression of the artist’s personality, much like handwriting.
Now, with Giotto, beautiful as his line undoubtedly is, it is not the first quality, the decorative rhythm, that most immediately impresses us. That is not the object of such deliberate and conscious research as with some artists. It is in its significance for the expression of form with the utmost lucidity, the most logical interrelation of parts that his line is so impressive. Here, for instance, in the figure of the kneeling woman, the form is expressed with perfect clearness; we feel at once the relation of the shoulders to one another, the relation of the torso to the pelvis, the main position of the thighs, and all this is conveyed by a curve of incredible simplicity capable of instant apprehension. To record so much with such economy requires not only a rare imaginative grasp of structure, but a manual dexterity which makes the story of Giotto’s O perfectly credible should one care to believe it.
Now, with Giotto, as beautiful as his lines undoubtedly are, it's not the decorative rhythm that impresses us most right away. That's not the focus of his deliberate and thoughtful approach like it is for some artists. What stands out is the clarity in how he expresses form and the logical connection of all the parts. Take, for example, the figure of the kneeling woman; the form is shown with perfect clarity. We immediately understand how the shoulders relate to each other, how the torso connects to the pelvis, and the primary position of the thighs. All of this is conveyed through a remarkably simple curve that can be grasped instantly. Capturing so much with such efficiency requires not only a rare imaginative understanding of structure but also a manual skill that makes the story of Giotto’s O completely believable if one chooses to accept it.
Giotto’s line, regarded as an habitual gesture, is chiefly striking for its breadth and dignity. It has the directness, the absence of preciosity, which belongs to a generous and manly nature. The large sweeping curves of his loose and full draperies are in part the direct outcome of this attitude.
Giotto’s line, seen as a natural expression, is especially impressive for its boldness and grace. It has a straightforwardness and simplicity that reflects a generous and strong character. The broad, flowing curves of his loose and full draperies are partly a result of this approach.
It is difficult to avoid the temptation to say of Giotto that he was the greatest artist that ever lived, a phrase which has been used of too many masters to retain its full emphasis. But at least he was the most prodigious phenomenon in the known history of art. Starting with little but the crude realism of Cimabue, tempered by the effete accomplishment of the Byzantines,[36] to have created an art capable of expressing the whole range of human emotions; to have found, almost without a guide, how to treat the raw material of life itself in a style so direct, so pliant to the idea, and yet so essentially grandiose and heroic; to have guessed intuitively almost all the principles of representation which it required nearly two centuries of enthusiastic research{116} to establish scientifically—to have accomplished all this is surely a more astounding performance than any other one artist has ever achieved.
It's hard not to call Giotto the greatest artist who ever lived, a title that’s been given to too many masters to carry much weight now. But he was definitely the most extraordinary figure in the history of art that we know. Starting with little more than the basic realism of Cimabue and influenced by the declining skill of the Byzantines, he created an art form that could express the full range of human emotions. He figured out, almost on his own, how to handle the raw material of life in a style that was so direct, so adaptable to ideas, and yet distinctly grand and heroic. He instinctively grasped nearly all the principles of representation that would take almost two centuries of dedicated research to define scientifically—accomplishing all of this is undoubtedly a more amazing feat than any other artist has ever pulled off.
But the fascination Giotto’s art exercises is due in part to his position in the development of modern culture. Coming at the same time as Dante, he shares with him the privilege of seeing life as a single, self-consistent, and systematic whole. It was a moment of equilibrium between the conflicting tendencies of human activity, a moment when such men as Dante and Giotto could exercise to the full their critical and analytical powers without destroying the unity of a cosmic theory based on theology. Such a moment was in its nature transitory: the free use of all the faculties which the awakening to a new self-consciousness had aroused, was bound to bring about antitheses which became more and more irreconcilable as time went on. Only one other artist in later times was able again to rise, by means of the conception of natural law, to a point whence life could be viewed as a whole. Even so, it was by a more purely intellectual effort, and Leonardo da Vinci could not keep the same genial but shrewd sympathy for common humanity which makes Giotto’s work so eternally refreshing.{117}
But the fascination with Giotto’s art comes partly from his role in the development of modern culture. Living at the same time as Dante, he shares with him the unique ability to see life as a cohesive, systematic whole. It was a moment of balance between the conflicting aspects of human activity, a time when figures like Dante and Giotto could fully harness their critical and analytical skills without losing sight of the unity in a cosmic theory based on theology. This moment was, by nature, temporary: the unrestricted use of all the abilities awakened by a new self-awareness was bound to create conflicts that became increasingly irreconcilable over time. Only one other artist later on managed to rise again, through the idea of natural law, to a perspective that allowed life to be viewed as a whole. Even then, it was through a more intellectual effort, and Leonardo da Vinci could not maintain the same warm but perceptive connection to everyday humanity that makes Giotto’s work so timelessly refreshing.{117}
THE ART OF FLORENCE[37]
THE “artistic temperament”—as used in the press and the police court, these words betray a general misunderstanding of the nature of art, and of the artist whenever he becomes fully conscious of its purpose. The idea of the artist as the plaything of whim and caprice, a hypersensitive and incoherent emotionalist, is, no doubt, true of a certain class of men, many of whom practise the arts; nothing could be further from a true account of those artists whose work has had the deepest influence on the tradition of art; nothing could be less true of the great artists of the Florentine School.
THE “artistic temperament”—as it's referred to in the media and the courtroom, these terms show a widespread misunderstanding of what art is and what it means for an artist when they truly grasp its purpose. The notion of the artist as someone driven solely by impulse and emotion, a highly sensitive and disorganized person, may accurately describe a certain group of individuals who engage in the arts; however, this fails to accurately represent the true nature of those artists whose work has profoundly shaped the art tradition; it couldn't be further from the reality of the great artists of the Florentine School.
From the rise of modern art in the thirteenth century till now Florence and France have been the decisive factors in the art of Europe. Without them our art might have reflected innumerable pathetic or dramatic moods, it might have illustrated various curious or moving situations, it would not have attained to the conception of generalised truth of form.
From the rise of modern art in the 13th century until now, Florence and France have been the key influences in European art. Without them, our art might have shown countless sad or dramatic emotions, it might have depicted various intriguing or touching scenarios, but it wouldn’t have reached the understanding of a generalized truth in form.
To Florence of the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries and to France of the seventeenth and succeeding centuries we owe the creation of generalised or what, for want of a better word, we may call “intellectual” art.
To Florence in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries and to France in the seventeenth and later centuries, we owe the development of what we might refer to as "intellectual" art.
In speaking of intellect it is necessary to discriminate between two distinct modes of its operation. The intellect may seek to satisfy curiosity by observation of the distinctions between one object and another by means of analysis; but it may concern itself with the discovery of fundamental relations between these objects, by the construction of a synthetic system which satisfies the mind, both for its truth to facts and its logical coherence. The artist may employ both these modes. His curiosity about the phenomena of nature may lead him to accurate observation and recognition of the variety and distinctness of characters, but he also seeks to construe these distinct forms{118} into such a coherent whole as will satisfy the æsthetic desire for unity. Perhaps the processes employed by the artist may not be identical with the intellectual processes of science, but it is evident that they present a very close analogy to them.
When talking about intellect, it's important to distinguish between two different ways it operates. The intellect might aim to satisfy curiosity by observing the differences between various objects through analysis; however, it can also focus on discovering fundamental relationships between these objects by creating a synthetic system that fulfills the mind’s need for both factual accuracy and logical coherence. An artist can use both of these approaches. Their curiosity about natural phenomena might drive them to keen observation and an understanding of the variety and uniqueness of characters, but they also aim to combine these distinct forms{118} into a coherent whole that fulfills the aesthetic desire for unity. The methods used by the artist may not be exactly the same as the intellectual methods in science, but it’s clear that they are very similar.
It is a curious fact that at the beginning of the fifteenth century in Italy, art was deeply affected by both kinds of intellectual activity. Curiosity about natural forms in all their variety and complexity—naturalism in the modern sense—first manifested itself in European art in Flanders, France, and North Italy about the second decade of the fifteenth century. It appears that Italy actually led the way in this movement, and that Lombardy was the point of origin. Pisanello and Jacopo Bellini are the great exemplars in Italy of this idea of exploring indefatigably and somewhat recklessly all those detailed aspects of nature which their predecessors, occupied in the grand Giottesque style, had scorned to notice.
It’s interesting that at the start of the fifteenth century in Italy, art was strongly influenced by both types of intellectual activity. Interest in natural forms in all their variety and complexity—what we now call naturalism—first appeared in European art in Flanders, France, and Northern Italy around the second decade of the fifteenth century. Italy seemed to actually lead this movement, with Lombardy being the starting point. Pisanello and Jacopo Bellini are the key figures in Italy exemplifying the idea of tirelessly and somewhat boldly exploring all those detailed aspects of nature that their predecessors, focused on the grand Giottesque style, had ignored.
In Florence, too, this impulse was undoubtedly felt, but it is the great distinction of the Florentine artists that, however much their curiosity about particular forms may have been excited, their high intellectual passion for abstract ideas impelled them more to the study of some general principles underlying all appearance. They refused to admit the given facts of nature except in so far as they could become amenable to the generalising power of their art. Facts had to be digested into form before they were allowed into the system.
In Florence, this impulse was definitely felt as well, but what set Florentine artists apart is that, no matter how curious they were about specific forms, their strong intellectual drive for abstract ideas pushed them more towards studying the fundamental principles behind all appearances. They didn't accept the realities of nature unless they could be shaped by the broader creative power of their art. Facts needed to be transformed into a form before they could be incorporated into the system.
We can get an idea of what Florence of the fifteenth century meant for the subsequent tradition of European art if we consider that if it had not been for Florence the art of Italy might have been not altogether unlike the art of Flanders and the Rhine—a little more rhythmical, a little more gracious, perhaps, but fundamentally hardly more significant.
We can understand what Florence in the fifteenth century contributed to the future of European art by considering that without Florence, Italian art might not have been very different from the art of Flanders and the Rhine—maybe a bit more rhythmic, a bit more graceful, but fundamentally not much more meaningful.
Although this typically Florentine attitude defined itself most clearly under the stress of naturalism it was, of course, already characteristic of earlier Florentine art. Giotto, indeed, had left the tradition of formal completeness so firmly fixed in Florence that whatever new material had to be introduced it could only be introduced into a clearly recognised system of design.
Although this typical Florentine attitude became most evident under the pressure of naturalism, it was already a hallmark of earlier Florentine art. Giotto had established the tradition of formal completeness so strongly in Florence that any new material could only be incorporated into a clearly defined system of design.
Of Giotto’s own work we rarely get a sight in England, the National Gallery having missed the one great chance of getting him{119} represented some twenty years ago. But though Lady Jekyll’s single figure of Christ can by its nature give no idea of his amazing and almost unequalled power of discovering unexpected inevitabilities of formal relations, it gives none the less something of Giotto’s peculiar beauty of drawing, wherein the completest reality is attained without any attempted verisimilitude. In Mr. Harris’s Bernardo Daddi we get nearer perhaps to Giotto as a composer, and even in his Giovanni da Milano, in spite of some Lombard grossness and sentimentality, the great tradition still lives.
We rarely get to see Giotto’s work in England, as the National Gallery missed a major opportunity to acquire one of his pieces around twenty years ago. While Lady Jekyll’s single figure of Christ doesn’t fully capture his incredible and almost unmatched ability to uncover unexpected formal relationships, it still conveys some of Giotto’s unique beauty in drawing, achieving complete reality without trying for literal accuracy. In Mr. Harris’s Bernardo Daddi, we get a bit closer to Giotto’s style as a composer, and even in his Giovanni da Milano, despite some clumsy Lombard elements and sentimentality, the great tradition still shines through.
Masaccio, represented here by Mr. Rickett’s single figure, is one of the most mysterious personalities in art, and typically Florentine. His mystery lies partly in our ignorance about him, partly in the difficulty of grasping the rapidity of action, the precocity, of genius such as his. Coming at the very beginning of the naturalistic movement he seized with a strange complacency and ease upon the new material it offered, but (and this is what astounds one) he instantly discovered how to assimilate it perfectly to the formal requirements of design. So that not only the discovery of the new material, but its digestion was with him a simultaneous and almost instantaneous process. He was helped perhaps by the fact that the new naturalism was as yet only a general perception of new aspects of natural form. It was left for his younger contemporaries to map out the new country methodically—to the group of adventurous spirits—Brunelleschi, Donatello, Castagno, and Uccello—who founded modern science, and gave to the understanding of classic art a methodical basis. It is in this group that the fierce intellectual passion of the Florentine genius manifests itself most clearly. Perspective and anatomy were the two studies which promised to reveal to them the secrets of natural form. The study of anatomy exemplifies mainly the aspect of curiosity, though even in this the desire to find the underlying principles of appearance is evident—on the other hand perspective, to its first discoverers, appeared to promise far more than an aid to verisimilitude, it may have seemed a visual revelation of the structure of space and through that a key to the construction of pictorial space.
Masaccio, represented here by Mr. Rickett’s single figure, is one of the most enigmatic figures in art and is typically Florentine. His mystery comes from both our lack of knowledge about him and the challenge of understanding the quickness of his actions and the brilliance of his genius. At the start of the naturalistic movement, he embraced the new opportunities it presented with surprising confidence and ease, but what is truly astonishing is how quickly he figured out how to integrate it seamlessly into the formal rules of design. For him, not only was the discovery of this new material simultaneous with its assimilation, but it almost happened all at once. It’s possible he was aided by the fact that this new naturalism was still just a general awareness of fresh aspects of natural form. It was left to his younger contemporaries—an adventurous group including Brunelleschi, Donatello, Castagno, and Uccello—to systematically map out this new territory, laying the groundwork for modern science and providing a methodical basis for understanding classical art. It is within this group that the intense intellectual passion of the Florentine genius is most clearly expressed. Perspective and anatomy were the two areas of study that they believed would uncover the secrets of natural form. The study of anatomy mainly reflects curiosity, though it also reveals the desire to find the fundamental principles of appearance. On the other hand, perspective, to its first discoverers, seemed to offer much more than just a tool for realistic representation; it may have appeared as a visual revelation of spatial structure and, through that, a key to the creation of pictorial space.
To our more penetrating study of æsthetic (for of all sciences, æsthetic has been the greatest laggard) it is evident that neither{120} perspective nor anatomy have any very immediate bearing upon art—both of them are means of ascertaining facts, and the question of art begins where the question of fact ends. But artists have always had to excite themselves with some kind of subsidiary intoxicant, and perspective and anatomy, while they were still in their infancy, acted admirably as stimulants. That they have by now become, for most artists, the dreariest of sedatives may make it difficult to conceive this. But at all events in that first generation they excited their devotees to an ardent search for abstract unity of design. And this excitement went on to the next generation as exemplified by the works of the Umbro-Florentines—Piero della Francesca and Signorelli—and in Florence itself of Pollajuolo.
In our deeper examination of aesthetics (since aesthetics has been the slowest to progress among all sciences), it's clear that neither perspective nor anatomy are directly relevant to art—both are tools for gathering facts, and the discussion of art starts where the discussion of fact ends. However, artists have always needed some sort of additional inspiration, and during their early development, perspective and anatomy served excellently as stimulants. Although they may now feel like the most tiresome sedatives to many artists, making it hard to imagine this, it was different for that initial generation. They motivated their followers to passionately pursue abstract unity in design. This enthusiasm continued into the next generation, as seen in the works of the Umbro-Florentines—Piero della Francesca and Signorelli—and in Florence itself, Pollajuolo.
But the scientific spirit once aroused was destined not to remain for long so stimulating and helpful an assistant to the creation of design. It was bound in the end to start trains of thought too complex and too absorbing to occupy a subordinate place. Already in the rank and file of Florentine artists, the Ghirlandajos, Filippino Lippis, and their kindred, mere curiosity—naïve literalism—had undermined the tradition, so that towards the last quarter of the century hardly any artist knew how to design intelligibly on the scale of a fresco, whereas the merest duffer of the fourteenth century could be certain of the volumes and quantities of his divisions.
But once the scientific spirit was awakened, it wasn't going to stay just a helpful assistant for creating designs for long. It inevitably led to lines of thought that were too complex and engaging to stay in the background. By the final quarter of the century, among Florentine artists like the Ghirlandajos, Filippino Lippis, and others, mere curiosity and naive literalism had weakened the tradition. As a result, hardly any artist knew how to design clearly on the scale of a fresco, while even the most inexperienced artist of the fourteenth century could confidently manage the volumes and proportions of their work.
But it is with Leonardo da Vinci that the higher aspects of the scientific spirit first came into conflict with art. Doubtless this conflict is not fundamental nor final, but only an apparent result of human limitations; but to one who, like Leonardo, first had a Pisgah prospect of that immense territory, to the exploration of which four centuries of the intensest human effort have been devoted without yet getting in sight of its boundaries—to such a man it was almost inevitable that the scientific content of art should assume an undue significance. Up till Leonardo one can say that the process of digesting the new found material into æsthetic form had kept pace with observation, though already in Verrocchio there is a sign of yielding to the crude phenomenon. But with Leonardo himself the organising faculty begins to break down under the stress of new matter. Leonardo himself shared to the full the Florentine passion for abstraction, but it was inevitable that he should be dazzled and fascinated{121} by the vast prospects that opened before his intellectual gaze. It was inevitable that where such vast masses of new particulars revealed themselves to his curiosity their claim for investigation should be the most insistent. Not but what Leonardo did recognise the necessity for his art of some restriction and choice. His keen observation had revealed to him the whole gamut of atmospheric colour which first became a material for design under Monet and his followers. But having described a picture which would exactly correspond to a French painting of 1870, he rejects the whole of this new material as unsuitable for art. But even his rejection was not really a recognition of the claims of form, but only, alas! of another scientific trend with which his mind had become possessed. It was his almost prophetic vision of the possibilities of psychology which determined more than anything else the lines of his work. In the end almost everything was subordinated to the idea of a kind of psychological illustration of dramatic themes—an illustration which was not to be arrived at by an instinctive reconstruction from within, but by deliberate analytic observation. Now in so far as the movements of the soul could be interpreted by movements of the body as a whole, the new material might lend itself readily to plastic construction, but the minuter and even more psychologically significant movements of facial expression demanded a treatment which hardly worked for æsthetic unity. It involved a new use of light and shade, which in itself tended to break down the fundamental divisions of design, though later on Caravaggio and Rembrandt managed, not very successfully, to pull it round so as to become the material for the basic rhythm. And in any case the analytic trend of Leonardo’s mind became too much accentuated to allow of a successful synthesis. Michelangelo, to some extent, and Raphael still more, did, of course, do much to re-establish a system of design on an enlarged basis which would admit of some of Leonardo’s new content, but one might hazard the speculation that European art has hardly yet recovered from the shock which Leonardo’s passion for psychological illustration delivered. Certainly literalism and illustration have through all these centuries been pressing dangers to art—dangers which it has been the harder to resist in that they allow of an appeal to that vast public to whom the language of form is meaningless.{122}
But it’s with Leonardo da Vinci that the deeper aspects of the scientific spirit first clashed with art. This conflict isn’t fundamental or final; it’s just a result of human limitations. For someone like Leonardo, who had a glimpse of that vast territory that has taken four centuries of intense human effort to explore without yet reaching its boundaries, it was almost inevitable that the scientific elements of art would take on an exaggerated importance. Before Leonardo, the process of incorporating newly discovered material into aesthetic forms kept pace with observation, though even in Verrocchio, there’s a hint of yielding to the raw phenomenon. But with Leonardo, the organizing ability starts to break down under the pressure of new material. He fully shared the Florentine passion for abstraction, but it was inevitable that he would be dazzled and fascinated by the broad perspectives that opened up before his intellect. When so many new details presented themselves to his curiosity, their demand for investigation became overwhelming. However, Leonardo did recognize that his art needed some limitations and choices. His sharp observation revealed the entire range of atmospheric color, which only became a design material under Monet and his followers. Yet, after describing a picture that would perfectly match a French painting from 1870, he dismissed this new material as unsuitable for art. Even his rejection wasn’t really about acknowledging the importance of form, but rather, sadly, about another scientific trend that captivated his mind. His almost prophetic insight into the possibilities of psychology greatly influenced his work. Eventually, nearly everything was subordinated to the idea of a kind of psychological representation of dramatic themes—one that wasn’t achieved through instinctive reconstruction from within but through deliberate analytical observation. As movements of the soul could be interpreted through movements of the whole body, the new material could easily lend itself to physical construction, but the more subtle and psychologically significant movements of facial expressions required an approach that didn’t generate aesthetic unity. It called for a new use of light and shadow, which in itself started to break down the fundamental divisions of design, although later Caravaggio and Rembrandt attempted, not very successfully, to reshape it into a fundamental rhythm. In any case, Leonardo’s analytical mindset became overly pronounced to allow for a successful synthesis. Michelangelo, to some extent, and Raphael even more, certainly did much to re-establish a design system on a larger basis that could incorporate some of Leonardo’s new content, but one might speculate that European art has hardly yet recovered from the shock of Leonardo’s passion for psychological illustration. Certainly, literalism and illustration have been pressing dangers to art throughout these centuries—dangers that have been harder to resist since they appeal to the large audience for whom the language of form is meaningless.
In Florentine art, then, one may see at happy moments of equilibrium the supreme advantages of intellectual art and at other and less fortunate moments the dangers which beset so difficult an endeavour. It was after all a Florentine who made the best prophecy of the results of modern æsthetic when he said: “Finally good painting is a music and a melody which intellect only can appreciate and that with difficulty.”{123}
In Florentine art, we can see at joyful moments of balance the great benefits of intellectual art, and at other, less fortunate times, the challenges that come with such a complex pursuit. After all, it was a Florentine who made the best prediction about the outcomes of modern aesthetics when he said: “Ultimately, good painting is like music and a melody that only the intellect can truly appreciate, and even then, it's not easy.”{123}
THE JACQUEMART-ANDRÉ COLLECTION[38]
THE Jacquemart-André collection is not merely one of those accumulations of the art of the past by which it has become the fashion for rich people to impose themselves on the wonder of an ignorant public. It shows that the lady who created it did so partly, at all events, because of a quite personal and intimate love of beautiful things, a love which did not have to seek for its justification and support in the opinion of the world.
THE Jacquemart-André collection isn't just another show of past art where wealthy individuals try to impress an uninformed audience. It demonstrates that the woman behind it was motivated, at least in part, by her genuine and personal passion for beautiful things, a passion that didn’t need public approval or validation.
The three pictures reproduced here are proof of the sincerity and courage of Mdme. André’s artistic convictions. They offer scarcely any foothold for the sentimental and associative understanding of pictures. The “S. George” of Paolo Uccello (see Plate) might, it is true, be taken as a “naïve,” “quaint,” or “primitive” rendering of an “old world” legend—indeed, whilst I was admiring it I gathered from the comments of those who lingered before it for a few seconds that this was the general attitude—but to do so would be to misunderstand the picture completely. Uccello, in fact, lends himself to misunderstanding, and Vasari, with his eye to literary picturesqueness, has done his best to put us off the scent. He made him an “original,” a harmless, ingenious, slightly ridiculous crank, gifted, no doubt, but one whose gifts were wasted by reason of his crankiness. And the legend created by Vasari has stuck. Uccello has always seemed to be a little aside from the main road of art, an agreeable, amusing diversion, one that we can enjoy with a certain humorous and patronising detachment, as we enjoy the innocence of some mediæval chronicler. Uccello, I admit, has lent himself to this misunderstanding because from every other point of view but that of pure design he comes up to the character Vasari has made current. No artist was ever so helpless as he at the dramatic presentment of his theme. Nothing can well be imagined less like a battle than his battle pieces, nor if we think of the Deluge would our wildest fancies{124} have ever conceived anything remotely resembling the scene which he painted with such literal precision, with such a mass of inconclusive and improbable invention, in the Chiostro Verde of Sta. Maria Novella.
The three images shown here prove the sincerity and bravery of Mdme. André’s artistic beliefs. They barely allow for a sentimental or associative interpretation of the artwork. The “S. George” by Paolo Uccello (see Plate) could indeed be seen as a “naïve,” “charming,” or “primitive” take on an “old world” legend—while I admired it, I noticed that the general consensus among those who stopped to look for a few moments was just that—but to view it this way would completely miss the point of the painting. Uccello has been prone to misunderstanding, and Vasari, with his focus on literary flair, has done his best to lead us astray. He portrayed him as an “original”—a harmless, clever, slightly ridiculous eccentric, talented for sure, but whose talents were wasted due to his quirkiness. And the story crafted by Vasari has endured. Uccello has always felt a bit off the main path of art, an enjoyable and entertaining diversion that we can appreciate with a certain humorous and patronizing detachment, much like we might appreciate the naïveté of some medieval chronicler. I admit that Uccello has contributed to this misunderstanding because from every perspective except pure design, he aligns with the persona Vasari promoted. No artist has ever been as ineffective as he is at dramatically presenting his themes. It’s hard to imagine anything less reminiscent of a battle than his battle scenes, nor would our wildest imaginations have ever conjured a scene resembling the Deluge that he painted with such literal accuracy, filled with inconclusive and improbable details, in the Chiostro Verde of Sta. Maria Novella.
The idea of verisimilitude is entirely foreign to him. And here comes in the oddity and irony of his situation. He was the first or almost the first great master of linear perspective. The study of perspective became so engrossing to him that according to Vasari it wasted his talent as an artist.
The concept of realism is completely unfamiliar to him. And this is where the strangeness and irony of his situation arise. He was one of the first great masters of linear perspective. He became so obsessed with the study of perspective that, according to Vasari, it squandered his talent as an artist.
Now perspective is the scientific statement of the nature of visual appearance. To the modern artist it becomes an occasional assistance in giving to his images an air of verisimilitude. Wherever a strict adherence to the laws of perspective would give to his objects a strange or unlikely look he frankly neglects it. But to Uccello perspective seemed, perhaps wrongly, to have an altogether different value. To him it appears to have been a method of recreating a visual world. That is to say, he took certain data of appearance from observation, and by handling them according to the laws of perspective he created a world, which, owing to the simplicity of his data and the rigid application of his laws, has far less resemblance to what we see than his contemporaries and predecessors had contrived by rule of thumb. Had he taken the whole of the data of observed form the application of the laws of perspective would have become impossible, and he would have been thrown back upon imitative realism and the literal acceptance of appearance. Such was indeed what happened to the painters of Flanders and the north, and such has become the usual method of modern realistic art. But nothing was more abhorrent to the spirit of fifteenth-century Florence than such an acceptance of the merely casual, and nothing is more fundamentally opposed to the empirical realism of a Van Eyck or a Frith than the scientific and abstract realism of Paolo Uccello.
Now, perspective is the scientific explanation of how things look visually. For the modern artist, it occasionally helps make their images look more lifelike. Whenever following the rules of perspective would make their objects look strange or unlikely, they simply ignore it. However, to Uccello, perspective seemed—perhaps wrongly—to have a completely different importance. For him, it was a way of recreating a visual world. In other words, he took certain visual information from observation and, by applying the rules of perspective, created a new world that looks much less like reality than what his contemporaries and predecessors achieved through trial and error. If he had used all the information from observed forms, then applying the rules of perspective would have been impossible, and he would have had to rely on imitative realism and a literal interpretation of appearance. That’s exactly what happened with the painters of Flanders and the North, which has become the standard approach in modern realistic art. But nothing was more against the spirit of fifteenth-century Florence than simply accepting the random and casual, and nothing contrasts more sharply with the empirical realism of a Van Eyck or a Frith than the scientific and abstract realism of Paolo Uccello.
This passion, then, for an abstract and theoretical completeness of rendering led Uccello to simplify the data of observed form to an extraordinary extent, and his simplification anticipates in a curious way that of the modern cubists, as one may see from the treatment of his horses in the National Gallery battle-piece.
This passion for achieving an abstract and theoretical completeness in his work led Uccello to simplify the details of observed form to an exceptional degree, and his simplification oddly anticipates that of modern cubists, as can be seen in how he portrays his horses in the National Gallery battle-piece.
do with what he actually accomplishes; that the fundamental quality of his work seems to come out unconsciously as a by-product of his conscious activity. And so it was in Uccello’s case. If one had asked him what his perspective was for, he would probably have said that when once it was completely mastered it would enable the artist to create at will any kind of visual whole, and that this would have the same completeness, the same authenticity as an actual scene. As a matter of fact such a conception is unrealisable; the problem is too complex for solution in this way, and what happened to Uccello was that the simplifications and abstractions imposed upon his observation of nature by the desire to construct his whole scene perspectively, really set free in him his power of a purely æsthetic organisation of form. And it is this, in fact, that makes his pictures so remarkable. In the Jacquemart-André picture, for instance, we see how the complex whole which such a scene as the legend of S. George suggests is reduced to terms of astounding simplicity; saint, horse, dragon, princess are all seen in profile because the problems of representation had to be approached from their simplest aspect. The landscape is reduced to a system of rectilinear forms seen at right angles to the picture plane for the same reason.
do with what he actually accomplishes; that the fundamental quality of his work seems to come out unconsciously as a by-product of his conscious activity. And so it was in Uccello’s case. If someone had asked him what his perspective was for, he probably would have said that once it was completely mastered, it would allow the artist to create any kind of visual whole at will, making it as complete and authentic as an actual scene. In reality, such a concept is unachievable; the problem is too complex to be solved this way. What happened to Uccello was that the simplifications and abstractions he imposed on his observation of nature, driven by the desire to construct his entire scene perspectively, actually unleashed his ability to organize form in a purely aesthetic way. And that’s what makes his pictures so remarkable. In the Jacquemart-André picture, for instance, we see how the complex whole suggested by the scene of S. George is distilled into astounding simplicity; the saint, horse, dragon, and princess are all shown in profile because the challenges of representation had to be approached from their simplest angle. The landscape is simplified into a system of straight forms viewed at right angles to the picture plane for the same reason.
And out of the play of these almost abstract forms mainly rectangular, with a few elementary curves repeated again and again, Uccello has constructed the most perfect, the most amazingly subtle harmony. In Uccello’s hands painting becomes almost as abstract, almost as pure an art as architecture. And as his feeling for the interplay of forms, the rhythmic disposition of planes, was of the rarest and finest, the most removed from anything trivial or merely decorative (in the vulgar sense), he passes by means of this power of formal organisation into a region of feeling entirely remote from that which is suggested if we regard his work as mere illustration. Judged as illustration the “S. George” is quaint, innocent and slightly childish; as design it must rank among the great masterpieces.
And from the play of these nearly abstract shapes, mostly rectangular, with a few basic curves repeated over and over, Uccello has created the most perfect and incredibly subtle harmony. In Uccello’s hands, painting becomes nearly as abstract and pure as architecture. And since his sense of the interaction of forms and the rhythmic arrangement of planes was extremely rare and refined, far from anything trivial or merely decorative, he moves through this power of formal organization into a realm of feeling completely separate from what we might think if we consider his work as just illustration. Viewed as illustration, the “St. George” seems quaint, innocent, and slightly childish; but as a design, it must be considered one of the great masterpieces.
Two other pictures in the Jacquemart-André collection illustrate the same spirit of uncompromising æsthetic adventure which distinguishes one branch of the Florentine school of the fifteenth century, and lifts it above almost all that was being attempted elsewhere in Italy even at this period of creative exuberance.{126}
Two other paintings in the Jacquemart-André collection showcase the same spirit of bold artistic exploration that characterizes one aspect of the Florentine school of the fifteenth century, setting it apart from almost everything else being produced in Italy during this time of creative vitality.{126}
Baldovinetti was at one time in close contact with Uccello, and of all his works the “Madonna and Child” in the Jacquemart-André collection is the most heroically uncompromising (Plate IX). No doubt he accepted more material directly from nature than Uccello did. He was beginning to explore the principles of atmospheric perspective which were destined ultimately to break up the unity of pictorial design, but everything that he takes is used with the same spirit of obedience to the laws of architectonic harmony. The spacing of this design, the relations of volume of the upright mass of the Virgin’s figure to the spaces of sky and landscape have the unmistakable interdependence of great design. Only a great creative artist could have discovered so definite a relationship. The great mass of the rocky hill in the landscape and the horizontal lines of the Child’s figure play into the central idea with splendid effect. Only in the somewhat rounded and insensitive modelling of the Virgin’s face does the weakness of Baldovinetti’s genius betray itself. The contours are everywhere magnificently plastic; only when he tries to create the illusion of plastic relief by modelling, Baldovinetti becomes literal and uninspired. In his profile portrait in the National Gallery he relies fortunately almost entirely on the plasticity of the contour—in his late “Trinità” at the Accademia in Florence the increasing desire for imitative realism has already gone far to destroy this quality.
Baldovinetti was once closely connected with Uccello, and among all his works, the “Madonna and Child” in the Jacquemart-André collection stands out as the most strikingly uncompromising (Plate IX). It’s clear that he took in more from nature directly than Uccello did. He was starting to explore the principles of atmospheric perspective, which would ultimately disrupt the unity of pictorial design, but everything he incorporates is done with a strong commitment to the laws of architectural harmony. The spacing in this design and the relationship between the volume of the Virgin’s figure and the surrounding sky and landscape have the clear interdependence of great design. Only a true creative artist could have recognized such a distinct relationship. The large mass of the rocky hill in the landscape and the horizontal lines of the Child’s figure beautifully enhance the central idea. The only area where Baldovinetti’s talent falters is in the somewhat rounded and lacking modeling of the Virgin’s face. The contours are magnificently shaped everywhere; it’s only when he attempts to create the illusion of plastic relief through modeling that Baldovinetti becomes literal and uninspired. In his profile portrait at the National Gallery, he fortunately relies almost entirely on the plasticity of the contour—in his later “Trinità” at the Accademia in Florence, the growing inclination towards imitative realism has largely undermined this quality.
The third picture (see Plate) which I have taken as illustrating my theme is not, it is true, Florentine, but its author, Signorelli, kept so constantly in touch with the scientific realists of Florence that he may be counted almost as one of them, nor indeed did any of them surpass him in uncompromising fidelity to the necessities of pure design. Certainly there is nothing of the flattering or seductive qualities of the common run of Umbrian art in this robust and audacious composition, in which everything is arranged as it were concentrically around the imposing mass of the Virgin’s figure. The gestures interpreted psychologically are not on the same imaginative plane as the design itself. Signorelli was ill at ease in interpreting any states but those of great tension, and here the gestures are meant to be playful and intimate. As in the Uccello, the illustrative pretext is at variance with the design which it serves; and as in the Uccello, the design itself, the scaffolding of the architectonic structure, is really what counts.{127}
The third picture (see Plate) that I’ve chosen to illustrate my theme isn’t, admittedly, Florentine, but its creator, Signorelli, was in constant touch with the scientific realists of Florence, making him almost one of them. In fact, none of them surpassed him in his unwavering commitment to the essentials of pure design. There’s definitely none of the flattering or seductive qualities typical of most Umbrian art in this strong and bold composition, where everything is arranged almost concentrically around the impressive figure of the Virgin. The gestures, when interpreted psychologically, don’t match the imaginative level of the design itself. Signorelli struggled to portray any states other than those of intense emotion, and in this case, the gestures are meant to be playful and intimate. As seen in Uccello, the illustrative intent clashes with the design it supports; and, like in Uccello, it’s the design itself, the framework of the architectural structure, that truly matters.{127}
DÜRER AND HIS CONTEMPORARIES[39]
IT is a habit of the human mind to make to itself symbols in order to abbreviate its admiration for a class. So Dürer has come to stand for German art somewhat as Raphael once stood for Italian. Such symbols attract to themselves much of the adoration which more careful worshippers would distribute over the Pantheon, and it becomes difficult to appreciate them justly without incurring the charge of iconoclasm. But this, in Dürer’s case, is the more difficult because, whatever one’s final estimate of his art, his personality is at once so imposing and so attractive, and has been so endeared to us by familiarity, that something of this personal attachment has transferred itself to our æsthetic judgment.
It's a natural tendency for people to create symbols that represent their admiration for a particular group. So, Dürer has come to symbolize German art much like Raphael once symbolized Italian art. These symbols draw in a lot of admiration that more discerning fans would spread out across the greats, making it hard to appreciate them fairly without being accused of rejecting them. This is especially tricky in Dürer’s case, because no matter how one ultimately evaluates his work, his personality is both striking and appealing, having become so familiar to us that some of that personal affection has influenced our aesthetic judgment.
The letters from Venice and the Diary of his journey in the Netherlands, which form the matter of this volume, are indeed the singularly fortunate means for this pleasant discourse with the man himself. They reveal Dürer as one of the distinctively modern men of the Renaissance: intensely, but not arrogantly, conscious of his own personality; accepting with a pleasant ease the universal admiration of his genius—a personal admiration, too, of an altogether modern kind; careful of his fame as one who foresaw its immortality. They show him as having, though in a far less degree, something of Leonardo da Vinci’s scientific interest, certainly as having a quick, though naïve curiosity about the world and a quite modern freedom from superstition. It is clear that his dominating and yet kindly personality, no less than his physical beauty and distinction, made him the centre of interest wherever he went. His easy and humorous good-fellowship, of which the letters to Pirkheimer are eloquent, won for him the admiring friendship of the best men of his time. To all these characteristics we must add a deep and sincere religious feeling, which led him to side with the leaders of the Reformation, a feeling that comes out in his passionate sense of loss when he thinks{128} that Luther is about to be put to death, and that prompted him to write a stirring letter to Erasmus, in which he urged him to continue the work of reform. For all that, there is no trace in him of either Protestantism or Puritanism. He was perhaps fortunate—certainly as an artist he was fortunate—in living at a time when the line of cleavage between the Reformers and the Church was not yet so marked as to compel a decisive choice. The symbolism of the Church still had for him its old significance, as yet quickened and not discredited by the reformer’s energy. But intense as Dürer’s devotion was, his religious feeling found its way to effective artistic expression only upon one side, namely, the brooding sense which accompanied it, of the imminence and terror of death. How much more definite is the inspiration in the drawing of “Death on a Horse” (in the British Museum), in the “Knight, Death and the Devil,” and in the allied “Melancholia,” than it is in his renderings of the Virgin or indeed of any of the scenes of Christian legend! It is this feeling, too, which gives to his description of his mother’s death its almost terrible literary beauty and power. Nor in the estimate of Dürer’s character must one leave out the touching affection and piety which the family history written by him in 1524 reveals.
The letters from Venice and the Diary of his trip to the Netherlands, which make up this volume, provide a unique opportunity for engaging with Dürer himself. They show him as one of the truly modern figures of the Renaissance: intensely aware of his own identity, yet not boastful; comfortably accepting the universal admiration of his talent—also a personal admiration of a distinctly modern nature; mindful of his reputation as someone who anticipated his own lasting legacy. They demonstrate that he possessed, though to a lesser extent, some of Leonardo da Vinci’s scientific curiosity and showed a youthful, though innocent, curiosity about the world, alongside a modern skepticism of superstition. It's evident that his commanding yet warm personality, along with his physical attractiveness and grace, drew interest wherever he went. His easygoing and humorous camaraderie, notably reflected in his letters to Pirkheimer, earned him the respect and friendship of the leading figures of his era. To all these traits, we must add a deep and genuine religious sentiment, which aligned him with the Reformation's leaders, a feeling that emerges in his profound sense of loss when he fears Luther might be executed, prompting him to write a powerful letter to Erasmus, urging him to carry on the reform. Despite this, there is no sign of either Protestantism or Puritanism in him. He was perhaps fortunate—certainly as an artist he was fortunate—to live at a time when the divide between the Reformers and the Church wasn’t yet so clear-cut as to require a definite decision. The symbols of the Church still held their previous significance for him, invigorated rather than discredited by the reformers' vigor. However intense Dürer's devotion was, his religious sentiment found effective artistic expression primarily through the looming and terrifying awareness of death. The inspiration is much more vivid in works like “Death on a Horse” (in the British Museum), “Knight, Death and the Devil,” and the related “Melancholia,” compared to his depictions of the Virgin or any scenes from Christian legend. This sentiment also gives his account of his mother's death its almost haunting literary beauty and impact. Additionally, we must not overlook the touching love and devotion revealed in the family history he wrote in 1524 when assessing Dürer’s character.
So much that is attractive and endearing in the man cannot but react upon our attitude to his work—has done so, perhaps, ever since his own day; and it is difficult to get far enough away from Dürer the man to be perfectly just to Dürer the artist. But if we make the attempt, it becomes clear, I think, that Dürer cannot take rank in the highest class of creative geniuses. His position is none the less of great importance and interest for his relation on the one hand to the Gothic tradition of his country, and on the other to the newly perceived splendours of the Italian Renaissance.
So much about the man is attractive and charming that it inevitably affects how we view his work—perhaps it always has, even since his own time; and it’s hard to separate Dürer the man from Dürer the artist to be completely fair. However, if we try, it becomes clear that Dürer doesn’t quite belong in the top tier of creative geniuses. Nonetheless, his place is still significant and interesting due to his connection to the Gothic tradition of his homeland and the newly recognized brilliance of the Italian Renaissance.
Much must depend on our estimate of his last work, the “Four Apostles,” at Munich. In that he summed up all that the patient and enthusiastic labour of a lifetime had taught him. If we regard that as a work of the highest beauty, if we can conscientiously put it beside the figures of the Sistine Chapel, beside the Saints of Mantegna, or Signorelli, or Piero della Francesca, then indeed Dürer’s labour was crowned with success; but if we find in it rather a careful exposition of certain theoretical principles, if we find that the matter is not entirely{129} transfused with the style, if we find a conflict between a certain naïve crudity of vision and a straining after the grand manner, then we have to say that Dürer’s art was the outcome of a magnificent and heroic but miscalculated endeavour.
Much depends on how we view his final work, the “Four Apostles,” in Munich. It captures everything that his patient and passionate work over a lifetime has taught him. If we see it as a piece of the highest beauty, if we can genuinely place it alongside the figures in the Sistine Chapel or the Saints by Mantegna, Signorelli, or Piero della Francesca, then Dürer’s efforts were truly successful. However, if we see it more as a careful explanation of certain theoretical ideas, and if we feel that the content isn't fully infused with style, if we notice a clash between a simple, raw vision and a struggle for grandeur, then we must conclude that Dürer’s art was the result of a magnificent yet misguided endeavor.
It is one of the ironies of history that the Romans, the only Philistine people among Mediterranean races, should have been the great means of transmitting to the modern world that culture which they themselves despised, and that the Germans should have laboured so long and hard to atone for the heroism of their ancestors in resisting that beneficent loss of liberty. Nuremberg of the fifteenth century was certainly given over to the practice of fine art with a pathetic enthusiasm, and it remains as a sad but instructive proof of how little good-will and industry avail by themselves in such matters. The worship of mere professional skill and undirected craftsmanship is there seen pushed to its last conclusions, and the tourist’s wonder is prompted by the sight of stone carved into the shapes of twisted metal, and wood simulating the intricacies of confectionery, his admiration is canvassed by every possible perversion of technical dexterity. Not “What a thing is done!” but, “How difficult it must have been to do it!” is the exclamation demanded.
It’s ironic that the Romans, the only truly uncultured people among the Mediterranean civilizations, ended up being the main force behind passing on a culture they themselves looked down upon. Likewise, the Germans worked so hard to make up for the bravery of their ancestors who fought against that positive loss of freedom. Nuremberg in the fifteenth century was definitely focused on fine art with a sad kind of enthusiasm, and it stands as a stark reminder of how little goodwill and hard work can accomplish in the arts. The admiration for mere technical skill and unrefined craftsmanship reaches its peak here, as tourists marvel at stone carved to mimic twisted metal and wood designed to look like intricate sweets. Instead of asking, “What a remarkable piece!” they ask, “How hard must it have been to create this?”
Of all that perverted technical ingenuity which flaunts itself in the wavering stonework of a Kraft or the crackling woodwork of a Storr, Dürer was inevitably the heir. He grew up in an atmosphere where the acrobatic feats of technique were looked on with admiration rather than contempt. Something of this clung to him through life, and he is always recognised as the prince of craftsmen, the consummate technician. In all this side of Dürer’s art we recognise the last over-blown efflorescence of the mediæval craftsmanship of Germany, of the apprentice system and the “master” piece; but that Gothic tradition had still left in it much that was sound and sincere. Drawing still retained something of the blunt, almost brutal frankness of statement, together with the sense of the characteristic which marked its earlier period. And it is perhaps this inheritance of Gothic directness of statement, this Gothic realism, that accounts for what is ultimately of most value in Dürer’s work. There exists in the Kunsthistorisches Akademie at Vienna a painting of a man, dated 1394, which shows how much of Dürer’s portraiture was already{130} implicit in the Nuremberg school. In this remarkable work, executed, if we may trust the date, nearly a century before Dürer, there is almost everything that interests us in Dürer’s portraits. Indeed, it has to an even greater extent that half-humorous statement of the characteristic, that outrageous realism that makes the vivid appeal of the Oswold Krell, and the absence of which in Dürer’s last years makes the Holtschuer such a tiresome piece of brilliant delineation.
Of all the twisted technical skill that shows off in the uneven stonework of a Kraft or the splintering woodwork of a Storr, Dürer was undoubtedly their heir. He grew up in an environment where the impressive tricks of technique were admired instead of scorned. This influence stayed with him throughout his life, and he is always recognized as the master craftsman, the ultimate technician. In this aspect of Dürer's art, we see the last exaggerated flourish of medieval craftsmanship in Germany, with its apprenticeship system and the “master” piece; yet that Gothic tradition still retained much that was solid and genuine. Drawing continued to hold onto a certain directness and almost brutal honesty, along with the sense of character that defined its earlier period. Perhaps it is this Gothic straightforwardness and realism that explains the most valuable aspects of Dürer's work. In the Kunsthistorisches Akademie in Vienna, there is a painting of a man, dated 1394, that shows how much of Dürer’s portrait style was already present in the Nuremberg school. In this remarkable piece, created, if the date is accurate, almost a century before Dürer, we find almost everything that captivates us in Dürer’s portraits. In fact, it features an even stronger blend of humor and characteristic portrayal, that bold realism that gives a vivid appeal to the Oswold Krell, and the lack of which in Dürer’s later years makes the Holtschuer such a tedious example of brilliant representation.
Dürer was perhaps the greatest infant prodigy among painters, and the drawing of himself at the age of twelve shows how early he had mastered that simple and abrupt sincerity of Gothic draughtsmanship. One is inclined to say that in none of his subsequent work did he ever surpass this in all that really matters, in all that concerns the essential vision and its adequate presentment. He increased his skill until it became the wonder of the world and entangled him in its seductions; his intellectual apprehension was indefinitely heightened, and his knowledge of natural appearances became encyclopædic.
Dürer was probably the most remarkable child prodigy among painters, and his self-portrait at twelve shows how early he mastered the straightforward and direct style of Gothic drawing. One might argue that in none of his later works did he exceed this in what truly matters, in everything related to his essential vision and its proper expression. He honed his skills to the point of becoming a global sensation, which also drew him into its allure; his intellectual understanding deepened endlessly, and his knowledge of the natural world became vast.
What, then, lies at the root of Dürer’s art is this Gothic sense of the characteristic, already menaced by the professional bravura of the late Gothic craftsman. The superstructure is what Dürer’s industry and intellectual acquisitiveness, acting in the peculiar conditions of his day, brought forth. It is in short what distinguishes him as the pioneer of the Renaissance in Germany. This new endeavour was in two directions, one due mainly to the trend of native ideas, the other to Italian influence. The former was concerned mainly with a new kind of realism. In place of the older Gothic realism with its naïve and self-confident statement of the salient characteristic of things seen, this new realism strove at complete representation of appearance by means of perspective, at a more searching and complete investigation of form, and a fuller relief in light and shade.
What lies at the heart of Dürer’s art is this Gothic sense of character, which was already threatened by the skilled showmanship of the late Gothic craftsman. The foundation is what Dürer’s hard work and intellectual curiosity produced under the unique circumstances of his era. In short, this is what marks him as the pioneer of the Renaissance in Germany. This new endeavor moved in two directions, one primarily influenced by native ideas and the other by Italian influence. The first focused mainly on a new kind of realism. Instead of the older Gothic realism, which had a straightforward and confident portrayal of the prominent features of things seen, this new realism aimed for a complete representation of appearances through perspective, a deeper and more thorough exploration of form, and a richer use of light and shadow.
To some extent these aims were followed also by the Italians, and with even greater scientific ardour: all the artists of Europe were indeed striving to master the complete power of representation. But in Italy this aim was never followed exclusively; it was constantly modified and controlled by the idea of design, that is to say, of expression by means of the pure disposition of contours and masses, and by the perfection and ordering of linear rhythm. This notion of design as something other than representation was indeed the common inheritance of European art from the mediæval world, but{131}
To some extent, the Italians also pursued these goals, and with even greater scientific passion: all the artists in Europe were indeed trying to master the full power of representation. However, in Italy, this goal was never pursued in isolation; it was constantly shaped and influenced by the idea of design, meaning expression through the pure arrangement of lines and shapes, as well as the perfection and organization of linear rhythm. This concept of design as something distinct from representation was certainly the shared legacy of European art from the medieval period, but{131}
in Italy the principles of design were more profoundly embedded in tradition, its demands were more clearly felt, and each succeeding generation was quite as deeply concerned with the perfection of design as with the mastery of representation. In the full Renaissance, indeed, this idea of design became the object of fully conscious and deliberate study, and the decadence of Italian art came about, not through indifference to the claims of artistic expression, but through a too purely intellectual and conscious study of them. The northern and especially the Teutonic artists, who had not inherited so strongly this architectonic sense, made indeed heroic efforts to acquire it, sometimes by the futile method of direct imitation of a particular style, sometimes—and this is the case with Dürer—by a serious effort of æsthetic intelligence. But on the whole the attempt must be judged to have failed, and northern art has drifted gradually towards the merely photographic vision.
In Italy, design principles were more deeply rooted in tradition, its expectations were more strongly felt, and each new generation cared just as much about perfecting design as about mastering representation. During the height of the Renaissance, the concept of design became the focus of careful and intentional study. The decline of Italian art didn't stem from a lack of interest in artistic expression, but rather from an overly intellectual and conscious approach to it. Northern artists, particularly those from the Teutonic regions, who hadn't inherited this architectural sense as strongly, made significant efforts to acquire it. Sometimes they did this through the ineffective method of directly imitating a specific style, or, as with Dürer, by genuinely engaging in aesthetic understanding. Overall, however, their attempts can be seen as unsuccessful, and northern art gradually shifted towards a more photographic depiction.
Dürer strove strenuously in both these directions. He unquestionably added immensely to the knowledge of actual form and to the power of representation, but his eagerness led him to regard quantity of form rather than its quality. With him drawing became a means of making manifest the greatest possible amount of form, the utmost roundness of relief, and his studies in pure design failed to keep pace with this. In the end he could not use to significant purpose the increased material at his disposal, and from the point of view of pure design his work actually falls short of that of his predecessor, Martin Schongauer, who indeed was benefited by lacking Dürer’s power of representation.
Dürer worked hard in both directions. He definitely contributed a lot to the understanding of actual form and the ability to represent it, but his enthusiasm made him focus more on the amount of form rather than its quality. For him, drawing became a way to showcase as much form as possible and the greatest depth of relief, while his studies in pure design struggled to keep up with this. In the end, he couldn't effectively utilize the increased material at his disposal, and from the perspective of pure design, his work actually falls short compared to that of his predecessor, Martin Schongauer, who was indeed better off without Dürer's level of representation.
From this point of view it may be worth while to examine in some detail Dürer’s relations to Italian art. The earliest definite example of his study of Italian art is in 1494, when he was probably in Venice for the first time. It is a copy in pen and ink of an engraving of the “Death of Orpheus” by some follower of Mantegna. The engraving is not the work of a great artist, and Dürer’s copy shows his superior skill in the rendering of form; but even here he has failed to realise the beauty of spatial arrangement in the original, and his desire to enrich the design with many skilfully drawn and convincing details results in a distinct weakening of the dramatic effect. Again, in the same year we have two drawings from engravings, this time by Mantegna himself. It is easy to understand that of all Italians, Mantegna should have been the most sympathetic to Dürer, and{132} that he should have regretted more than any other ill-fortune of his life,—more even than the similar fate that prevented his meeting Schongauer,—Mantegna’s death just when he was setting out to Mantua to learn from the great master. What Dürer saw in Mantegna was his clear decision of line and his richly patterned effect. In his pen-and-ink copies he tries to surpass the original in both these ways, and indeed the effect is of greater complexity, with more fullness and roundness of form. Where Mantegna is content with a firm statement of the generalised contour of a limb, Dürer will give a curve for each muscle. There is in Dürer’s copies a mass of brilliant detail; each part is in a sense more convincingly real; but in doing this something of the unity of rhythm and the easy relations of planes has been lost, and on the whole the balance is against the copyist. It is curious that when in time Rembrandt came to copy Mantegna he took the other way, and actually heightened the dramatic effect by minute readjustments of planning, and by a wilful simplification of the line.[40]
From this perspective, it makes sense to take a closer look at Dürer’s connections to Italian art. The first clear example of his study of Italian art dates back to 1494, when he was likely in Venice for the first time. It's a pen and ink copy of an engraving titled “Death of Orpheus” by a follower of Mantegna. The original engraving isn't from a great artist, and Dürer’s copy highlights his skill in representing form; however, even in this instance, he didn't capture the beauty of spatial arrangement found in the original. His attempt to enhance the design with numerous well-drawn and convincing details leads to a noticeable weakening of the dramatic impact. Later that same year, he created two drawings based on engravings by Mantegna himself. It’s easy to see why, out of all the Italian artists, Mantegna would be the most appealing to Dürer, and why he would have especially regretted, more than any other misfortune in his life — even more than the similar fate that kept him from meeting Schongauer — Mantegna’s death just when he was about to head to Mantua to learn from the master. What Dürer admired in Mantegna was his clear line work and rich patterns. In his pen-and-ink copies, Dürer attempts to exceed the original in both aspects, resulting in a more complex effect, with fuller and rounder forms. While Mantegna simply outlines the general shape of a limb, Dürer gives each muscle a curve. Dürer’s copies are filled with brilliant details; each part feels more convincingly real; but in the process, something of the unity of rhythm and the smooth relationships of planes was lost, making the overall balance tilt in favor of the original artist. Interestingly, when Rembrandt eventually copied Mantegna, he took a different approach, actually enhancing the dramatic effect through small adjustments in planning and by deliberately simplifying the lines.
Dürer evidently felt a profound reverence for Mantegna’s designs, for he has altered them but little, and one might well imagine that even Dürer could scarcely improve upon such originals. But it is even more instructive to study his work upon the so-called Tarocchi engravings. Here the originals were not executed by an artist of first-rate ability, though the designs have much of Cossa’s splendid style. Dürer seems, therefore, to have felt no particular constraint about altering them. His alterations (see Plate) show us clearly what it was that he saw in the originals and what he missed. In all these figures Dürer gives increased verisimilitude: his feet are like actual feet, not the schematic abstract of a foot that contents the Italian engraver; his poses are more casual, less formal and symmetrical; and his draperies are more ingeniously disposed; but none the less, from the point of view of the expression of imaginative truth, there is not one of Dürer’s figures which equals the original, not one in which some essential part of the idea is not missed or at least less clearly stated. In general the continuity of the contour is lost sight of and the rhythm frittered away. In the Pope, for instance, Dürer loses all the grave sedateness of the original by breaking the symmetry of the pose, its{133}
Dürer clearly had a deep respect for Mantegna’s designs since he changed them very little, and it’s hard to imagine that even Dürer could improve on such originals. However, it’s even more interesting to look at his work on the so-called Tarocchi engravings. The originals weren’t created by a top-tier artist, although the designs carry much of Cossa’s outstanding style. Because of this, Dürer seems to have felt no real pressure to stick to them. His changes (see Plate) clearly show us what he appreciated in the originals and what he found lacking. In all these figures, Dürer adds a greater sense of realism: his feet look like actual feet, as opposed to the abstract representation that satisfies the Italian engraver; his poses are more relaxed, less formal and symmetrical; and his drapery is arranged more creatively. Still, from the perspective of expressing imaginative truth, none of Dürer’s figures match the originals, and each one misses or at least obscures some essential aspect of the idea. Overall, the flow of the outline is lost, and the rhythm is diminished. In the case of the Pope, for example, Dürer loses all the serious dignity of the original by breaking the symmetry of the pose, its{133}
squareness and immovable aplomb. And with this goes, in spite of the increased verisimilitude, the sense of reality. In the “Knight and Page” not only is the movement of the knight missed by correcting a distortion in the original, but the balance of the composition is lost by displacing the page. In the “Primum Mobile” (see Plate) the ecstatic rush of the figure is lost by slight corrections of the pose and by giving to the floating drapery too complicated a design. It would be tedious to go through these copies in detail, but enough has been said to show how hard it was for Dürer, absorbed by his new curiosity in representation, to grasp those primary and elemental principles of design which were inherent in the Italian tradition.
squareness and unshakeable confidence. Along with this comes, despite the greater realism, a loss of the sense of reality. In the “Knight and Page,” the knight's movement is lost by correcting a distortion in the original, and the balance of the composition is disrupted by moving the page. In the “Primum Mobile” (see Plate), the ecstatic rush of the figure is diminished by slight adjustments to the pose and by making the floating drapery too intricately designed. It would be tedious to go through these copies in detail, but enough has been said to demonstrate how challenging it was for Dürer, engrossed in his new fascination with representation, to grasp those foundational and elemental design principles that were integral to the Italian tradition.
About the same time we find Dürer studying both Pollajuolo and Lorenzo di Credi. The copy of Pollajuolo is not a good example of Dürer’s art; it certainly misses the tension and inner life of Pollajuolo’s nudes. The Lorenzo di Credi, as might be expected, is in many ways more than adequate to the original, though as compared even with Credi, Dürer has not a clear sense of the correlation of linear elements in the design.
Around the same time, we see Dürer studying both Pollajuolo and Lorenzo di Credi. The copy of Pollajuolo isn't a strong representation of Dürer’s work; it definitely lacks the emotional depth and intensity of Pollajuolo’s nudes. The Lorenzo di Credi, as expected, is often more than satisfactory compared to the original, but even when looking at Credi, Dürer doesn't have a clear understanding of how the linear elements relate to each other in the design.
The next stage in Dürer’s connection with Italian art is his intimacy with Jacopo de’ Barbari, who was settled in Nuremberg. From 1500 to 1505 this influence manifests itself clearly in Dürer’s work. Unfortunately Barbari was too second-rate an artist to help him much in the principles of design, though he doubtless stimulated him to pursue those scientific investigations into the theory of human proportions which held out the delusive hope of reducing art to a branch of mathematics.
The next phase of Dürer’s connection with Italian art is his close relationship with Jacopo de’ Barbari, who lived in Nuremberg. From 1500 to 1505, this influence is evident in Dürer’s work. Unfortunately, Barbari was too mediocre an artist to contribute significantly to his understanding of design principles, although he certainly encouraged Dürer to delve into the scientific study of human proportions, which falsely suggested that art could be simplified into a mathematical discipline.
It was not, however, until his second visit to Venice that Dürer realised the inferiority, at all events, of Barbari, and it was then that, through his amiable relations with Giovanni Bellini, he came nearer than at any other moment of his life to penetrating the mysteries of Italian design. It is in the letters from Venice, written at this time, that his connection with the Venetian artists is made clear, and a study of those writings will be found to illuminate in a most interesting way Dürer’s artistic consciousness, and help to answer the question of how he regarded his own work when seen in comparison with the Venetians, and in what manner the Venetians regarded this wonder worker from the north.{134}
It wasn't until his second trip to Venice that Dürer realized that Barbari was not as skilled. During this visit, his friendly relationship with Giovanni Bellini brought him closer than ever to understanding the secrets of Italian design. In the letters Dürer wrote from Venice during this time, his connection with the Venetian artists becomes clear. Studying those letters sheds fascinating light on Dürer’s artistic awareness and helps to answer how he viewed his own work in comparison to the Venetians, as well as how the Venetians perceived this remarkable artist from the north.{134}
EL GRECO[41]
MR. HOLMES has risked a good deal in acquiring for the nation the new El Greco. The foresight and understanding necessary to bring off such a coup are not the qualities that we look for from a Director of the National Gallery. Patriotic people may even be inclined to think that the whole proceeding smacks too much of the manner in which Dr. Bode in past ages built up the Kaiser Friedrich Museum, largely at the expense of English collections. Even before the acquisition of the El Greco there were signs that Mr. Holmes did not fully understand the importance of “muddling through.” And now with the El Greco he has given the British public an electric shock. People gather in crowds in front of it, they argue and discuss and lose their tempers. This might be intelligible enough if the price were known to be fabulous, but, so far as I am aware, the price has not been made known, so that it is really about the picture that people get excited. And what is more, they talk about it as they might talk about some contemporary picture, a thing with which they have a right to feel delighted or infuriated as the case may be—it is not like most old pictures, a thing classified and museumified, set altogether apart from life, an object for vague and listless reverence, but an actual living thing, expressing something with which one has got either to agree or disagree. Even if it should not be the superb masterpiece which most of us think it is, almost any sum would have been well spent on a picture capable of provoking such fierce æsthetic interest in the crowd.
MR. HOLMES has taken quite a risk in acquiring the new El Greco for the nation. The foresight and understanding needed to pull off such a deal aren't exactly what we'd expect from a Director of the National Gallery. Patriotic folks might even feel that the whole situation resembles how Dr. Bode built up the Kaiser Friedrich Museum in the past, mostly at the expense of English collections. Even before getting the El Greco, there were hints that Mr. Holmes didn’t fully grasp the importance of “muddling through.” Now, with the El Greco, he has shocked the British public. People are gathering in crowds in front of it; they argue, discuss, and lose their tempers. This might make sense if the price were known to be outrageous, but as far as I know, the price hasn’t been disclosed, so it’s really about the painting that has people so excited. What’s more, they talk about it like they would a contemporary piece, a work they have every right to feel delighted or angry about—unlike most old paintings that are classified and put in museums, distant from life, and treated with vague and listless reverence. This is a living thing, expressing something that people must either agree or disagree with. Even if it isn't the superb masterpiece that many believe it to be, any amount spent on a painting that can provoke such intense interest in the crowd would be worthwhile.
That the artists are excited—never more so—is no wonder, for here is an old master who is not merely modern, but actually appears a good many steps ahead of us, turning back to show us the way. Immortality if you like! But the public—what is it that makes them “sit up” so surprisingly, one wonders. What makes this El Greco “count” with them as surely no Old Master ever did within memory?{135} First, I suspect, the extraordinary completeness of its realisation. Even the most casual spectator, passing among pictures which retire discreetly behind their canvases, must be struck by the violent attack of these forms, by a relief so outstanding that by comparison the actual scene, the gallery and one’s neighbours are reduced to the key of a Whistlerian Nocturne. Partly, for we must face the fact, the melodramatic apparatus; the “horrid” rocks, the veiled moon, the ecstatic gestures. Not even the cinema star can push expression further than this. Partly, no doubt, the clarity and the balanced rhythm of the design, the assurance and grace of the handling; for, however little people may be conscious of it, formal qualities do affect their reaction to a picture, though they may pass from them almost immediately to its other implications. And certainly here, if anywhere, formal considerations must obtrude themselves even on the most unobservant. The extraordinary emphasis and amplitude of the rhythm, which thus gathers up into a few sweeping diagonals the whole complex of the vision, is directly exciting and stimulating. It affects one like an irresistible melody, and makes that organisation of all the parts into a single whole, which is generally so difficult for the uninitiated, an easy matter for once. El Greco, indeed, puts the problem of form and content in a curious way. The artist, whose concern is ultimately and, I believe, exclusively with form, will no doubt be so carried away by the intensity and completeness of the design, that he will never even notice the melodramatic and sentimental content which shocks or delights the ordinary man. It is none the less an interesting question, though it is rather one of artists’ psychology than of æsthetics, to inquire in what way these two things, the melodramatic expression of a high-pitched religiosity and a peculiarly intense feeling for plastic unity and rhythmic amplitude, were combined in El Greco’s work; even to ask whether there can have been any causal connection between them in the workings of El Greco’s spirit.
That the artists are excited—never more so—is no surprise, because here is an old master who is not just modern, but actually seems several steps ahead of us, turning back to show us the way. Immortality if you want! But the public—what is it that makes them “sit up” so unexpectedly, one wonders. What makes this El Greco “count” with them in a way that no Old Master ever did within living memory? First, I suspect, it’s the extraordinary completeness of its realization. Even the most casual observer, passing among paintings that hold back behind their canvases, must be struck by the intense presence of these forms, by a relief so striking that, in comparison, the actual scene, the gallery, and the people nearby are reduced to the mood of a Whistler-like Nocturne. Partly, we have to face the fact, it’s the melodramatic elements; the “horrid” rocks, the veiled moon, the ecstatic gestures. Not even a movie star can convey expression more than this. Partly, no doubt, it’s the clarity and balanced rhythm of the design, the confidence and grace of the execution; for, no matter how little people may be aware of it, formal qualities do influence their reactions to a painting, even if they quickly move on to its other meanings. And certainly here, if anywhere, formal considerations must make themselves evident even to the least observant. The remarkable emphasis and breadth of the rhythm, which gathers up into a few sweeping diagonals the whole complexity of the vision, is directly exciting and stimulating. It affects one like an irresistible melody, making that organization of all the parts into a single whole, which is usually so challenging for the untrained viewer, an easy task for once. El Greco, indeed, presents the issue of form and content in a strange way. The artist, whose focus is ultimately and, I believe, solely on form, will undoubtedly be so captivated by the intensity and completeness of the design that he will hardly even notice the melodramatic and sentimental content that either shocks or delights the average person. It is nonetheless an intriguing question, though it leans more toward artists’ psychology than aesthetics, to explore how these two aspects—the melodramatic expression of elevated religiosity and a particularly intense appreciation for plastic unity and rhythmic breadth—were combined in El Greco’s work; even to ponder whether there could have been any causal link between them in the workings of El Greco’s spirit.{135}
Strange and extravagantly individual as El Greco seems, he was not really an isolated figure, a miraculous and monstrous apparition thrust into the even current of artistic movement. He really takes his place alongside of Bernini as the greatest exponent of the Baroque idea in figurative art. And the Baroque idea goes back to{136} Michelangelo. Formally, its essence both in art and architecture was the utmost possible enlargement of the unit of design. One can see this most easily in architecture. To Bramante the façade of a palace was made up of a series of storeys, each with its pilasters and windows related proportionally to one another, but each a co-ordinate unit of design. To the Baroque architect a façade was a single storey with pilasters going the whole height, and only divided, as it were, by an afterthought into subordinate groups corresponding to the separate storeys. When it came to sculpture and painting the same tendency expressed itself by the discovery of such movements as would make the parts of the body, the head, trunk, limbs, merely so many subordinate divisions of a single unit. Now to do this implied extremely emphatic and marked poses, though not necessarily violent in the sense of displaying great muscular strain. Such poses correspond as expression to marked and excessive mental states, to conditions of ecstacy, or agony or intense contemplation. But even more than to any actual poses resulting from such states, they correspond to a certain accepted and partly conventional language of gesture. They are what we may call rhetorical poses, in that they are not so much the result of the emotions as of the desire to express these emotions to the onlooker.
El Greco may seem strange and incredibly unique, but he wasn’t an isolated artist, a miraculous and bizarre figure just dropped into the mainstream of artistic movements. He actually stands alongside Bernini as one of the greatest representatives of the Baroque concept in figurative art. This Baroque idea traces back to{136} Michelangelo. In both art and architecture, its core principle was to maximize the scale of the design unit. This is most easily seen in architecture. For Bramante, a palace façade was constructed with a series of stories, each featuring pilasters and windows that were proportionately related to each other, but each functioning as a separate design unit. In contrast, to the Baroque architect, a façade was viewed as one single story with pilasters extending the entire height, only divided, so to speak, by an afterthought into subordinate groups reflecting the different stories. In sculpture and painting, the same trend emerged through the creation of movements that made parts of the body—the head, torso, limbs—simply subordinate divisions of one unified unit. Achieving this required very pronounced and distinct poses, though they didn’t have to be extreme in terms of showing great muscular tension. These poses reflected strong and intense mental states, like ecstasy, agony, or deep contemplation. Yet, even more than actual poses stemming from these states, they related to a certain accepted and somewhat conventional language of gesture. We can think of them as rhetorical poses because they stem from the desire to convey emotions to the observer rather than being purely emotional responses themselves.
When the figure is draped the Baroque idea becomes particularly evident. The artists seek voluminous and massive garments which under the stress of an emphatic pose take heavy folds passing in a single diagonal sweep from top to bottom of the whole figure. In the figure of Christ in the National Gallery picture El Greco has established such a diagonal, and has so arranged the light and shade that he gets a statement of the same general direction twice over, in the sleeve and in the drapery of the thigh.
When the figure is covered, the Baroque concept becomes especially clear. The artists aim for voluminous and substantial garments that, under the strain of an expressive pose, create deep folds that move in a single diagonal line from the top to the bottom of the entire figure. In the depiction of Christ in the National Gallery artwork, El Greco has established such a diagonal and has arranged the light and shadow in a way that emphasizes the same general direction twice, in the sleeve and in the drapery of the thigh.
Bernini was a consummate master of this method of amplifying the unit, but having once set up the great wave of rhythm which held the figure in a single sweep, he gratified his florid taste by allowing elaborate embroidery in the subordinate divisions, feeling perfectly secure that no amount of exuberance would destroy the firmly established scaffolding of his design.
Bernini was a true master of this technique for enhancing the main element, but once he established the grand flow of rhythm that unified the figure in one continuous motion, he indulged his ornate style by adding intricate details in the secondary parts, confident that no level of extravagance could undermine the solid framework of his design.
terrible extravagance of El Greco’s melodrama than the radiant effusiveness and amiability of Bernini’s operas.
terrible extravagance of El Greco’s melodrama than the bright expression and friendliness of Bernini’s operas.
But there is another cause which accounts for our profound difference of feeling towards these two artists. Bernini undoubtedly had a great sense of design, but he was also a prodigious artistic acrobat, capable of feats of dizzying audacity, and unfortunately he loved popularity and the success which came to him so inevitably. He was not fine enough in grain to distinguish between his great imaginative gifts and the superficial virtuosity which made the crowd, including his Popes, gape with astonishment. Consequently he expressed great inventions in a horribly impure technical language. El Greco, on the other hand, had the good fortune to be almost entirely out of touch with the public—one picture painted for the king was sufficient to put him out of court for the rest of his life. And in any case he was a singularly pure artist, he expressed his idea with perfect sincerity, with complete indifference to what effect the right expression might have on the public. At no point is there the slightest compromise with the world; the only issue for him is between him and his idea. Nowhere is a violent form softened, nowhere is the expressive quality of brushwork blurred in order to give verisimilitude of texture; no harshness of accent is shirked, no crudity of colour opposition avoided, wherever El Greco felt such things to be necessary to the realisation of his idea. It is this magnificent courage and purity, this total indifference to the expectations of the public, that bring him so near to us to-day, when more than ever the artist regards himself as working for ends unguessed at by the mass of his contemporaries. It is this also which accounts for the fact that while nearly every one shudders involuntarily at Bernini’s sentimental sugariness, very few artists of to-day have ever realised for a moment how unsympathetic to them is the literary content of an El Greco. They simply fail to notice what his pictures are about in the illustrative sense.
But there's another reason for our strong difference in feelings towards these two artists. Bernini definitely had a great sense of design, but he also had a remarkable talent for eye-catching displays, and sadly, he was drawn to popularity and the success that came to him so easily. He couldn’t quite tell the difference between his extraordinary creative abilities and the shallow skill that made people, including his Popes, stare in awe. As a result, he expressed his brilliant ideas in a clumsy and impure technical style. On the other hand, El Greco was fortunate to be largely disconnected from the public—one painting done for the king was enough to keep him out of favor for the rest of his life. Really, he was a remarkably pure artist, expressing his vision with genuine sincerity and complete indifference to how that expression might affect the public. There’s no compromise with the world in his work; it’s all about the relationship between him and his idea. No harsh forms are softened, and the expressive nature of his brushwork isn’t blurred to create a sense of texture; he doesn’t shy away from strong contrasts or bold colors when he feels they’re essential to convey his idea. It’s this incredible courage and purity, this total indifference to public expectations, that brings him so close to us today, when artists more than ever see themselves as working towards goals that are unknown to most people around them. This is also why, while almost everyone instinctively recoils from Bernini’s sentimental sweetness, very few contemporary artists ever realize just how unappealing the literary aspect of El Greco’s work is to them. They simply don’t register what his paintings are about in a literal sense.
But to return to the nature of Baroque art. The old question here turns up. Did the dog wag his tail because he was pleased, or was he pleased because his tail wagged? Did the Baroque artists choose ecstatic subjects because they were excited about a certain kind of rhythm, or did they elaborate the rhythm to express a feeling for extreme emotional states? There is yet another fact which{138} complicates the matter. Baroque art corresponds well enough in time with the Catholic reaction and the rise of Jesuitism, with a religious movement which tended to dwell particularly on these extreme emotional states, and, in fact, the Baroque artists worked in entire harmony with the religious leaders.
But to get back to the nature of Baroque art. The old question comes up again. Did the dog wag his tail because he was happy, or was he happy because his tail was wagging? Did the Baroque artists choose intense subjects because they were inspired by a certain rhythm, or did they develop that rhythm to convey feelings of extreme emotions? There’s another aspect that{138} complicates things. Baroque art aligns closely in time with the Catholic response and the rise of Jesuitism, along with a religious movement that focused especially on these intense emotional states. In fact, the Baroque artists worked in complete harmony with the religious leaders.
This would look as though religion had inspired the artists with a passion for certain themes, and the need to express these had created Baroque art.
This would seem to suggest that religion inspired artists with a strong passion for certain themes, and this need to express those themes resulted in Baroque art.
I doubt if it was as simple as that. Some action and reaction between the religious ideas of the time and the artists’ conception there may have been, but I think the artists would have elaborated the Baroque idea without this external pressure. For one thing, the idea goes back behind Michelangelo to Signorelli, and in his case, at least, one can see no trace of any preoccupation with those psychological states, but rather a pure passion for a particular kind of rhythmic design. Moreover, the general principle of the continued enlargement of the unit of design was bound to occur the moment artists recovered from the debauch of naturalism of the fifteenth century and became conscious again of the demands of abstract design.
I doubt it was that straightforward. There must have been some interaction between the religious ideas of the time and the artists' vision, but I believe the artists would have developed the Baroque concept without this outside influence. For one, the idea traces back beyond Michelangelo to Signorelli, who, at least in his case, shows no signs of being fixated on those psychological states; instead, he demonstrates a pure passion for a specific type of rhythmic design. Additionally, the general principle of continually expanding the design unit was bound to happen once artists moved past the excesses of naturalism of the fifteenth century and became aware again of the needs of abstract design.
In trying thus to place El Greco’s art in perspective, I do not in the least disparage his astonishing individual force. That El Greco had to an extreme degree the quality we call genius is obvious, but he was neither so miraculous nor so isolated as we are often tempted to suppose.
In attempting to put El Greco’s art into perspective, I don't mean to downplay his incredible individual talent. It's clear that El Greco possessed an extraordinary level of what we call genius, but he wasn't as miraculous or as isolated as we often think.
The exuberance and abandonment of Baroque art were natural expressions both of the Italian and Spanish natures, but they were foreign to the intellectual severity of the French genius, and it was from France, and in the person of Poussin, that the counterblast came. He, indeed, could tolerate no such rapid simplification of design. He imposed on himself endless scruples and compunctions, making artistic unity the reward of a long process of selection and discovery. His art became difficult and esoteric. People wonder sometimes at the diversity of modern art, but it is impossible to conceive a sharper opposition than that between Poussin and the Baroque. It is curious, therefore, that modern artists should be able to look back with almost equal reverence to Poussin and to El Greco. In part, this is due to Cézanne’s influence, for, from one point of view, his art may be{139} regarded as a synthesis of these two apparently adverse conceptions of design. For Cézanne consciously studied both, taking from Poussin his discretion and the subtlety of his rhythm, and from El Greco his great discovery of the permeation of every part of the design with a uniform and continuous plastic theme. The likeness is indeed sometimes startling. One of the greatest critics of our time, von Tschudi—of Swiss origin, I hasten to add, and an enemy of the Kaiser—was showing me El Greco’s “Laocoon,” which he had just bought for Munich, when he whispered to me, as being too dangerous a doctrine to be spoken aloud even in his private room, “Do you know why we admire El Greco’s handling so much? Because it reminds us of Cézanne.”
The energy and freedom of Baroque art were natural expressions of both Italian and Spanish cultures, but they felt foreign to the intellectual rigor of the French mindset. From France, and especially through the work of Poussin, came a strong opposition. He rejected the quick simplification of design entirely. Instead, he imposed on himself rigorous standards and a sense of guilt, making artistic unity the result of a long process of selection and discovery. His art became complex and esoteric. People sometimes wonder at the variety in modern art, but it’s hard to imagine a more distinct contrast than that between Poussin and the Baroque. It’s interesting, then, that modern artists can look back with almost equal admiration at both Poussin and El Greco. Part of this is due to Cézanne’s influence, as his art can be seen as a blend of these two seemingly opposing approaches to design. Cézanne studied both consciously, taking from Poussin his carefulness and the subtlety in rhythm, and from El Greco his groundbreaking realization that every element in the design is infused with a consistent and ongoing plastic theme. The similarities can indeed be surprising. One of the greatest critics of our time, von Tschudi—who I should mention is Swiss and not fond of the Kaiser—was showing me El Greco’s “Laocoon,” which he had just acquired for Munich. He leaned in and, considering it too risky to say out loud even in his own space, whispered, “Do you know why we admire El Greco’s technique so much? Because it reminds us of Cézanne.”
No wonder, then, that for the artist of to-day the new El Greco is of capital importance. For it shows us the master at the height of his powers, at last perfectly aware of his personal conception and daring to give it the completest, most uncompromising expression. That the picture is in a marvellous state of preservation and has been admirably cleaned adds greatly to its value. Dirty yellow varnish no longer interposes here its hallowing influence between the spectator and the artist’s original creation. Since the eye can follow every stroke of the brush, the mind can recover the artist’s gesture and almost the movements of his mind. For never was work more perfectly transparent to the idea, never was an artist’s intention more deliberately and precisely recorded.{140}
No wonder that for today’s artist, the new El Greco is extremely important. It shows us the master at the peak of his abilities, fully aware of his personal vision and daring to express it completely and without compromise. The fact that the painting is in amazing condition and has been beautifully cleaned adds greatly to its value. No dirty yellow varnish now gets in the way of the viewer experiencing the artist’s original work. Since the eye can follow every brushstroke, the mind can grasp the artist’s gestures and almost his thoughts. Never has a work been more transparent to its idea, nor has an artist’s intention been recorded more deliberately and precisely.{140}
THREE PICTURES IN TEMPERA BY WILLIAM BLAKE[42]
BLAKE’S finished pictures have never received the same attention nor aroused the same admiration as his wash-drawings, his wood-cuts, or his engravings. It is difficult to account for this comparative neglect, since they not only show command of a technique which admits of the completest realisation of the idea, but they seem actually to express what was personal to Blake in a purer form than many of his other works, with less admixture of those unfortunate caprices which the false romantic taste of his day imposed too often even on so original and independent a genius. The explanation may perhaps lie in the fact that to most people Blake, for all his inimitable gifts, appears as a divinely inspired amateur rather than as a finished master of his art, and they are willing to tolerate what they regard as his imperfect control of form in media which admit only of hints and suggestions of the artist’s vision.
BLAKE'S finished artworks have never received the same level of attention or admiration as his wash drawings, woodcuts, or engravings. It's hard to explain this relative neglect, since these pieces not only showcase his mastery of a technique that allows for a complete realization of his ideas, but they also seem to express what was uniquely personal to Blake in a clearer way than many of his other works, with less influence from the unfortunate whims that the misguided romantic tastes of his time often imposed on such an original and independent genius. The issue might be that to most people, Blake, despite his unmatched talents, comes across more as a divinely inspired amateur than as a polished master of his craft, and they are inclined to overlook what they see as his lack of control over form in mediums that only allow for hints and suggestions of the artist’s vision.
There assuredly never was a more singular, more inexplicable phenomenon than the intrusion, as though by direct intervention of Providence, of this Assyrian spirit into the vapidly polite circles of eighteenth-century London. The fact that, as far as the middle classes of England were concerned, Puritanism had for a century and a half blocked every inlet and outlet of poetical feeling and imaginative conviction save one, may give us a clue to the causes of such a phenomenon. It was the devotion of Puritan England to the Bible, to the Old Testament especially, that fed such a spirit as Blake’s directly from the sources of the most primeval, the vastest and most abstract imagery which we possess. Brooding on the vague and tremendous images of Hebrew and Chaldæan poetry, he arrived at such indifference to the actual material world, at such an intimate perception of the elemental forces which sway the spirit with immortal{141} hopes and infinite terrors when it is most withdrawn from its bodily conditions, that what was given to his internal vision became incomparably more definite, more precisely and more clearly articulated, than anything presented to his senses. His forms are the visible counterparts to those words, like the deep, many waters, firmament, the foundations of the earth, pit and host, whose resonant overtones blur and enrich the sense of the Old Testament. Blake’s art moves us, if at all, by a similar evocation of vast elemental forces. He deals directly with these spiritual sensations, bringing in from external nature the least possible content which will enable him to create visible forms at all. But though he pushed them to their furthest limits, even he could not transcend the bounds which beset pictorial language; even he was forced to take something of external nature with him into his visionary world, and his wildest inventions are but recombinations and distorted memories of the actual objects of sense.
There has never been a more unique or inexplicable occurrence than the sudden appearance, almost as if by divine intervention, of this Assyrian spirit in the blandly polite circles of eighteenth-century London. The fact that, for the middle classes in England, Puritanism had for a century and a half blocked every avenue for poetic feeling and imaginative belief—except one—might help explain this phenomenon. It was Puritan England's dedication to the Bible, particularly the Old Testament, that nourished a spirit like Blake’s directly from the most ancient, vast, and abstract imagery we have. Contemplating the vague and powerful images of Hebrew and Chaldean poetry, he became indifferent to the physical world and developed a deep awareness of the elemental forces that influence the spirit with eternal hopes and infinite fears when it is most detached from its bodily conditions. What he perceived internally became far more vivid and clearly defined than anything his senses could offer. His forms are the visible counterparts to words like the deep, many waters, firmament, the foundations of the earth, pit, and host, whose resonant tones enhance the Old Testament's meaning. Blake’s art resonates, if at all, by similarly invoking vast elemental forces. He engages directly with these spiritual sensations, using the least amount of external nature necessary to create visible forms. But even though he pushed boundaries, he couldn't escape the limitations of pictorial language; he too had to incorporate elements of the physical world into his visionary realm, and his wildest creations are merely reconfigurations and distorted memories of actual sensory objects.
By the strangest irony, too, the forms which came to his hand as the readiest means of expressing his stupendous conceptions were in themselves the least expressive, the least grandiose, that ever art has dealt with. It was with the worn-out rags of an effete classical tradition long ago emptied of all meaning, and given over to turgid rhetorical display, that Blake had to piece together the visible garments of his majestic and profound ideas. The complete obsession of his nature by these ideas in itself compelled him to this: he was entirely without curiosity about such trivial and ephemeral things as the earth contained. His was the most anti-Hellenic temperament; he had no concern, either gay or serious, with phenomena; they were too transparent to arrest his eye, and that patient and scientific quarrying from the infinite possibilities of nature of just the appropriate forms to convey his ideas was beyond the powers with which nature and the poor traditions of his day supplied him. Tintoretto, who had in some respects a similar temperament, who felt a similar need of conveying directly the revelations of his internal vision, was more happily situated. He was, by comparison, a trivial and vulgar seer, but the richness and expressive power of the forms which lay to his hand in Titian’s and Michelangelo’s art enabled him to attain a more unquestionable achievement.
By the strangest irony, the forms that were the easiest for him to use to express his incredible ideas were actually the least expressive and the least grand that art has ever dealt with. Blake had to piece together the visible representation of his majestic and deep thoughts using the worn-out remnants of a classical tradition that had long lost all meaning, reduced to pompous rhetorical display. His complete obsession with these ideas forced him into this situation: he had no interest in the trivial and fleeting things the world offered. He had the most anti-Hellenic temperament; he had no interest, either light-hearted or serious, in phenomena; they were too obvious to catch his attention, and the careful and methodical search for just the right forms in nature to express his ideas was beyond what nature and the poor traditions of his time could provide. Tintoretto, who shared a similar temperament and felt a similar need to convey the revelations of his inner vision, was in a better position. Although he was a more trivial and ordinary visionary, the richness and expressive power of the forms available to him in Titian's and Michelangelo's art allowed him to achieve a more undeniable success.
But, allowing for circumstances, what Blake did was surely more{142} considerable and implied a greater sheer lift of imaginative effort. That it was an attempt which remained almost without consequences, isolated and incomplete—marred, too, by a certain incoherence and want of reasonable co-ordination—must be allowed, and may perhaps explain why Blake is not universally admitted among our greatest.
But, given the circumstances, what Blake did was definitely more{142} significant and required a greater level of imaginative effort. It's worth noting that his attempt had almost no consequences, was isolated and incomplete—also flawed by a certain lack of coherence and reasonable organization—which might explain why Blake isn't universally recognized as one of our greatest.
The Byzantine style, he declares, was directly and divinely revealed to him; and whether this were so, or whether he obtained it by the dim indications of Ottley’s prints, or through illuminated manuscripts, the marvellous fact remains that he did succeed in recovering for a moment that pristine directness and grandeur of expression which puts him beside the great Byzantine designers as the only fit interpreter of Hebrew mythology. His “Flight into Egypt”[43] will at once recall Giotto’s treatment of the subject in the Arena chapel at Padua; but the likeness is, in a sense, deceptive, for Giotto was working away from Byzantinism as fast as Blake was working towards it, and the two pass one another on the road. For there is here but little of Giotto’s tender human feeling, less still of his robust rationalism; what they have in common, what Blake rediscovered and Giotto inherited, is the sentiment of supernatural dignity, the hieratic solemnity and superhuman purposefulness of the gestures. Even more than in Giotto’s version, the Virgin here sits on the ass as though enthroned in monumental state, her limbs fixed in the rigid symmetry which oriental art has used to express complete withdrawal from the world of sense. No less perfect in its expressiveness of the strange and exalted mood is the movement, repeated with such impressive monotony, in the figures of Joseph and the archangel. It is absurd, we think, to deny to the man who discovered the lines of these figures the power of draughtsmanship. Since Giotto’s day scarcely any one has drawn thus—simplification has been possible only as the last effort of consummate science refining away the superfluous; but here the simplification of the forms is the result of an instinctive passionate reaching out for the direct symbol of the idea.
The Byzantine style, he asserts, was directly and divinely revealed to him; and whether that’s true, or whether he got it from the subtle clues in Ottley’s prints or through illuminated manuscripts, the amazing fact is that he managed to briefly capture that original directness and grandeur of expression that places him alongside the great Byzantine designers as the only true interpreter of Hebrew mythology. His “Flight into Egypt”[43] instantly reminds us of Giotto’s take on the subject in the Arena chapel at Padua; but the similarity is somewhat misleading because Giotto was moving away from Byzantinism just as fast as Blake was moving toward it, with the two crossing paths. Here, there’s little of Giotto’s gentle human emotion, and even less of his strong rationalism; what they share—what Blake rediscovered and Giotto inherited—is the feeling of supernatural dignity, the formal solemnity, and the otherworldly purposefulness of the gestures. Even more than in Giotto’s version, the Virgin here sits on the donkey as if she were enthroned in monumental grandeur, her limbs posed in the rigid symmetry that Oriental art employs to show total withdrawal from the sensory world. The movements in the figures of Joseph and the archangel, repeated with impressive monotony, perfectly express the strange and elevated mood. It seems ridiculous to deny the man who sketched these figures the skill of a draftsman. Since Giotto’s time, hardly anyone has drawn in this way—simplification has only been achieved as the last effort of expert science refining away the unnecessary; yet here, the simplification of forms comes from an instinctive, passionate drive towards the direct symbol of the idea.
as a means to this end, owing them no allegiance and accepting from them only the service that they can render for this purpose. “Poetry,” says Blake, “consists in bold, daring, and masterly conceptions; and shall painting be confined to the sordid drudgery of facsimile representations of merely mortal and perishing substances, and not be, as poetry and music are, elevated into its own proper sphere of invention and visionary conception?” The theory that art appeals solely by the associated ideas of the natural objects it imitates is easily refuted when we consider music and architecture; in those at least the appeal to the spirit is made directly in a language which has no other use than that of conveying its own proper ideas and feelings. But in pictorial art the fallacy that nature is the mistress instead of the servant seems almost ineradicable, and it is difficult to convince people that increased scientific investigation of phenomena, increased knowledge of how things present themselves to our sight, changes the mode, but does not necessarily increase the power, of pictorial expression. The Byzantine artists, with a knowledge of appearances infinitely less than that of the average art student of to-day, could compass the expression of imaginative truths which our most accomplished realists dare not attempt. The essential power of pictorial as of all other arts lies in its use of a fundamental and universal symbolism, and whoever has the instinct for this can convey his ideas, though possessed of only the most rudimentary knowledge of the actual forms of nature; while he who has it not can by no accumulation of observed facts add anything to the spiritual treasure of mankind. Of this language of symbolic form in which the spirit communicates its most secret and indefinable impulses Blake was an eloquent and persuasive master. He could use it, too, to the most diverse ends; and though the sublimity which is based upon dread came most readily to his mind, he could express, as we have seen in the “Flight into Egypt,” the sublimity of divine introspection. In the “David and Bathsheba” (see Plate) he touches a different note, and he shows his true power of symbolic expression in this, that it is not by the treatment of the figure itself, not by any ordinary sensual enticements, that he gives the atmosphere of voluptuous abandonment. It is rather in the extravagant tropical flowers, in the architecture which itself blossoms with oriental exuberance, in the fiery orange of the clouds seen behind{144} trees preternaturally virid, that the spirit is bewildered with anticipations of extravagant bliss. The picture might be described in Blake’s own terminology as the mental abstract of voluptuousness.
as a means to this goal, owing them no loyalty and accepting only the service they can provide for this purpose. “Poetry,” Blake says, “is made of bold, daring, and masterly ideas; should painting be limited to the tedious task of copying mere mortal and fleeting things, and not be, like poetry and music, elevated into its own rightful realm of invention and visionary concepts?” The idea that art only appeals through the associated ideas of the natural objects it imitates can be easily disproven when we think about music and architecture; in those arts, the appeal to the spirit is made directly in a language that serves no other purpose than to convey its own ideas and feelings. However, in pictorial art, the misconception that nature is the master instead of the servant seems nearly impossible to shake, and it's hard to convince people that greater scientific investigation of phenomena, along with increased understanding of how things appear to our eyes, changes the method but doesn’t necessarily enhance the power of pictorial expression. The Byzantine artists, with far less knowledge of appearances than today’s average art student, were able to convey imaginative truths that even our most skilled realists would hesitate to try. The essential power of pictorial art, like all other arts, lies in its use of fundamental and universal symbolism. Anyone with an instinct for this can communicate their ideas, even with only the most basic understanding of nature’s forms; while a person lacking this instinct cannot, no matter how much they observe, contribute anything to humanity's spiritual wealth. Blake was a powerful and persuasive master of this language of symbolic form, which allows the spirit to express its most secret and indefinable impulses. He could use it for diverse purposes; and while the greatness that arises from fear often came to him easily, he could also convey, as seen in the “Flight into Egypt,” the greatness of divine introspection. In “David and Bathsheba” (see Plate), he strikes a different chord and demonstrates his true power of symbolic expression—not through the treatment of the figure itself, nor through any ordinary sensual appeals, but rather in the extravagant tropical flowers, in the architecture that blooms with an oriental richness, and in the fiery orange of the clouds behind{144} unnaturally vibrant trees, that the spirit becomes overwhelmed with anticipations of extravagant joy. The picture might be described in Blake’s own terms as the mental abstraction of sensual pleasure.
All art gives us an experience freed from the disturbing conditions of actual life. Blake’s art, more concentrated than most, gives us an experience which is removed more entirely from bodily and physiological accompaniments, and our experience has the purity, the intensity, and the abstraction of a dream.{145}
All art offers us an experience that is separate from the unsettling realities of everyday life. Blake’s art, which is more focused than most, provides an experience that is completely detached from physical and bodily influences, giving our experience the clarity, intensity, and surreal quality of a dream.{145}
CLAUDE[44]
IN spite of all the attacks of critics, in spite of the development of emphasis and high flavour in modern romantic landscape, which might well have spoilt us for his cool simplicity, Claude still lives, not, indeed, as one of the gods of the sale-room, but in the hearts of contemplative and undemonstrative people. This is surely an interesting and encouraging fact. It means that a very purely artistic and poetical appeal still finds its response in the absence of all subsidiary interests and attractions. The appeal is, indeed, a very limited one, touching only certain highly self-conscious and sophisticated moods, but it is, within its limits, so sincere and so poignant that Claude’s very failings become, as it were, an essential part of its expression. These failings are, indeed, so many and so obvious that it is not to be wondered at if, now and again, they blind even a sensitive nature like Ruskin’s to the fundamental beauty and grandeur of Claude’s revelation. But we must be careful not to count as failings qualities which are essential to the particular kind of beauty that Claude envisages, though, to be quite frank, it is sometimes hard to make up one’s mind whether a particular characteristic is a lucky defect or a calculated negation. Take, for instance, the peculiar gaucherie of his articulations. Claude knows less, perhaps, than any considerable landscape painter—less than the most mediocre of modern landscapists—how to lead from one object to another. His foregrounds are covered with clumsily arranged leaves which have no organic growth, and which, as often as not, lie on the ground instead of springing from it. His trees frequently isolate themselves helplessly from their parent soil. In particular, when he wants a repoussoir in the foreground at either end of his composition he has recourse to a clumsily constructed old bare trunk, which has little more meaning{146} than a stage property. Even in his composition there are naïvetés which may or may not be intentional: sometimes they have the happiest effect, at others they seem not childlike but childish. Such, for instance, is his frequent habit of dividing spaces equally, both vertically and horizontally, either placing his horizontal line half-way up the picture, or a principal building on the central vertical line. At times this seems the last word of a highly subtilised simplicity, of an artifice which conceals itself; at others one cannot be sure that it is not due to incapacity. There is, in fact, a real excuse for Ruskin’s exaggerated paradox that Claude’s drawings look like the work of a child of ten. There is a whole world of beauty which one must not look for at all in Claude. All that beauty of the sudden and unexpected revelation of an unsuspected truth which the Gothic and Early Renaissance art provides is absent from Claude. As the eye follows his line it is nowhere arrested by a sense of surprise at its representative power, nor by that peculiar thrill which comes from the communication of some vital creative force in the artist. Compare, for instance, Claude’s drawing of mountains, which he knew and studied constantly, with Rembrandt’s. Rembrandt had probably never seen mountains, but he obtained a more intimate understanding by the light of his inner vision than Claude could ever attain to by familiarity and study. We need not go to Claude’s figures, where he is notoriously feeble and superficially Raphaelesque, in order to find how weak was his hold upon character, whatever the object he set himself to interpret. In the British Museum there is a most careful and elaborate study of the rocky shores of a stream. Claude has even attempted here to render the contorted stratification of the river-bed, but without any of that intimate imaginative grasp of the tension and stress which underlie the appearance which Turner could give in a few hurried scratches. No one, we may surmise, ever loved trees more deeply than Claude, and we know that he prided himself on his careful observation of the difference of their specific characters; and yet he will articulate their branches in the most haphazard, perfunctory manner. There is nothing in all Claude’s innumerable drawings which reveals the inner life of the tree itself, its aspirations towards air and light, its struggle with gravitation and wind, as one little drawing by Leonardo da Vinci does.{147}
In spite of all the criticism and the shift towards more dramatic and vibrant modern romantic landscapes, which might have made us indifferent to his cool simplicity, Claude still endures—not as a superstar in the art market, but in the hearts of thoughtful and reserved people. This is certainly an interesting and uplifting revelation. It shows that a purely artistic and poetic appeal can still resonate, even without any additional interests or distractions. The appeal is quite limited, touching on certain highly self-aware and sophisticated moods, but within its boundaries, it is so genuine and moving that Claude’s flaws become, in a sense, an essential part of its expression. These flaws are so numerous and obvious that it’s not surprising that even a sensitive person like Ruskin sometimes overlooks the fundamental beauty and grandeur of Claude’s vision. However, we need to be careful not to label as flaws qualities that are essential to the specific kind of beauty that Claude envisions. To be honest, it can sometimes be difficult to decide whether a particular trait is a fortunate defect or a deliberate omission. For example, consider the awkwardness in his art. Claude perhaps knows less about transitioning from one object to another than any significant landscape painter—less than even the most average modern landscapist. His foregrounds are filled with clumsily arranged leaves that seem disordered and often lie flat instead of rising from the ground. His trees often seem detached from their roots. Particularly, when he wants a framing element in the foreground at either edge of his composition, he resorts to a poorly constructed, bare trunk that holds little more meaning than a stage prop. Even in his composition, there are naïvetés that may or may not be intentional: sometimes they produce a wonderful effect, while at other times they come off as not childlike but simply childish. For instance, he frequently divides spaces evenly, both vertically and horizontally, either placing his horizontal line halfway up the picture or positioning a main building along the central vertical line. Occasionally, this seems to be the height of cleverly concealed simplicity, while at other times, one might doubt whether it stems from an inability to do better. In fact, there’s a real basis for Ruskin’s extreme statement that Claude’s drawings look like the work of a ten-year-old. There’s a whole realm of beauty that one should not expect to find in Claude. The surprise and unexpected revelation of an unseen truth that Gothic and Early Renaissance art provides are absent from Claude's work. As the eye follows his lines, it is never caught off guard by a sense of surprise in their representational power, nor by that unique thrill that comes from an artist's genuine creative force. For example, compare Claude’s depiction of mountains, which he knew and studied constantly, with Rembrandt’s. Rembrandt probably never saw mountains, yet he achieved a closer understanding through the light of inner vision than Claude could ever reach through familiarity and study. We need not examine Claude’s figures, where he is notoriously weak and superficially Raphael-like, to find how fragile his grasp on character is, regardless of what he aimed to portray. In the British Museum, there is a very careful and intricate study of the rocky shores of a stream. Claude even tried to depict the twisted layers of the riverbed here, but lacked the intimate imaginative insight into the tension and stress beneath the appearance that Turner could convey in just a few quick strokes. No one, we might assume, ever loved trees more deeply than Claude, and we know he took pride in his careful observation of their specific characteristics; yet, he portrays their branches in the most random, routine manner. There is nothing in all of Claude’s countless drawings that reveals the inner life of the tree itself, its aspirations towards air and light, its struggle with gravity and wind, as one small drawing by Leonardo da Vinci does.{147}
All these defects might pass more easily in a turbulent romanticist, hurrying pell mell to get expressed some moving and dramatic scene, careless of details so long as the main movement were ascertained, but there is none of this fire in Claude. It is with slow ponderation and deliberate care that he places before us his perfunctory and generalised statements, finishing and polishing them with relentless assiduity, and not infrequently giving us details that we do not desire and which add nothing but platitude to the too prolix statement.
All these flaws might be overlooked by a passionate romantic, rushing to capture an emotional and dramatic scene, unconcerned with the details as long as the main idea is conveyed. But Claude lacks that spark. He presents his superficial and generalized statements with slow thoughtfulness and careful intention, meticulously refining and perfecting them, often including details we don’t want that only add cliché to the overly lengthy explanation.
All this and much more the admirer of Claude will be wise to concede to the adversary, and if the latter ask wherein the beauty of a Claude lies he may with more justice than in any other case fall back on the reply of one of Du Maurier’s æsthetes, “in the picture.” For there is assuredly a kind of beauty which is not only compatible with these defects but perhaps in some degree depends on them. We know and recognise it well enough in literature. To take a random instance. Racine makes Titus say in “Bérénice”: “De mon aimable erreur je suis désabusé.” This may be a dull, weak, and colourless mode of expression, but if he had said with Shakespeare, “Now old desire doth in his death-bed lie, and young affection gapes to be his heir,” we should feel that it would destroy the particular kind of even and unaccented harmony at which Racine aimed. Robert Bridges, in his essay on Keats, very aptly describes for literature the kind of beauty which we find in Shakespeare: “the power of concentrating all the far-reaching resources of language on one point, so that a single and apparently effortless expression rejoices the æsthetic imagination at the moment when it is most expectant and exacting.” That, ceteris paribus, applies admirably to certain kinds of design. It corresponds to the nervous touch of a Pollajuolo or a Rembrandt. But Claude’s line is almost nerveless and dull. Even when it is most rapid and free it never surprises us by any intimate revelation of character, any summary indications of the central truth. But it has a certain inexpressive beauty of its own. It is never elegant, never florid, and, above all, never has any ostentation of cleverness. The beauty of Claude’s work is not to be sought primarily in his drawing: it is not a beauty of expressive parts but the beauty of a whole. It corresponds in fact to the poetry of his century—to Milton or Racine. It is in the cumulative effect of the perfect co-ordination of{148} parts none of which is by itself capable of absorbing our attention or fascinating our imagination that the power of a picture by Claude lies. It is the unity and not the content that affects us. There is, of course, content, but the content is only adequate to its purpose and never claims our attention on its own account. The objects he presents to us have no claim on him but as parts of a scheme. They have no life and purpose of their own, and for that very reason it is right that they should be stated in vague and general terms. He wishes a tree to convey to the eye only what the word “tree” might suggest at once to the inner vision. We think first of the mass of waving shade held up against the brilliance of the sky, and this, even with all his detailed elaboration, is about where Claude, whether by good fortune or design, leaves us. It is the same with his rocks, his water, his animals. They are all made for the mental imagery of the contemplative wanderer, not of the acute and ardent observer. But where Claude is supreme is in the marvellous invention with which he combines and recombines these abstract symbols so as to arouse in us more purely than nature herself can the mood of pastoral delight. That Claude was deeply influenced by Virgil one would naturally suppose from his antiquarian classicism, and a drawing in the British Museum shows that he had the idea of illustrating the Æneid. In any case his pictures translate into the language of painting much of the sentiment of Virgil’s Eclogues, and that with a purity and grace that rival his original. In his landscapes Melibœus always leaves his goats to repose with Daphnis under the murmuring shade, waiting till his herds come of themselves to drink at the ford, or in sadder moods of passionless regret one hears the last murmurs of the lament for Gallus as the well-pastured goats turn homewards beneath the evening star.
All this and much more, Claude's admirer should certainly acknowledge regarding the opponent. If the opponent asks where the beauty of a Claude painting lies, they might better answer with the response of one of Du Maurier’s aesthetes, “in the picture.” There is indeed a type of beauty that not only coexists with these flaws but may depend on them to some extent. We recognize this in literature. For instance, Racine has Titus say in “Bérénice”: “I am disabused of my delightful error.” This might be a dull and colorless expression, but if he had said, like Shakespeare, “Now old desire doth in his death-bed lie, and young affection gapes to be his heir,” it would ruin the kind of smooth and unaccented harmony Racine aimed for. Robert Bridges, in his essay on Keats, aptly describes this kind of beauty in Shakespeare: “the power of concentrating all the extensive resources of language on one point, so that a single and seemingly effortless expression delights the aesthetic imagination when it is most expectant and demanding.” That principle, ceteris paribus, perfectly applies to certain types of design. It aligns with the delicate touch of a Pollajuolo or a Rembrandt. But Claude’s lines feel almost lifeless and dull. Even when they are most dynamic and free, they never surprise us with deep character insights or direct hints at the core truth. However, they possess a distinct inexpressive beauty. They are never elegant or overly ornate, and, above all, they lack any showiness of cleverness. The beauty in Claude’s work isn’t mainly found in his drawing; it’s not about expressive details but rather the beauty of the whole. It truly resembles the poetry of his time—like Milton or Racine. The power of a Claude painting lies in the cumulative effect of the perfect coordination of parts, none of which can captivate our attention or imagination on its own. It’s the unity that moves us, not the content. Certainly, there is content, but it only serves its purpose and never demands our attention independently. The elements he depicts don’t stand alone but fit into a broader scheme. They lack individual life and intention, which is why it’s fitting they are presented in vague, general terms. He wants a tree to evoke in the viewer only what the word “tree” might instantly suggest to the mind's eye. We initially think of the mass of swaying shade against the bright sky, and even with all his intricate detailing, that’s exactly where Claude, whether by luck or intention, leaves us. The same goes for his rocks, water, and animals. They are all designed for the imaginative wandering of a contemplative observer rather than the sharp and passionate viewer. But Claude excels in his incredible ability to combine and recombine these abstract symbols, evoking in us, more purely than nature can, the feeling of pastoral bliss. One might naturally assume that Claude was deeply influenced by Virgil given his classical style, and a drawing in the British Museum suggests he intended to illustrate the Æneid. In any case, his paintings translate much of the sentiment of Virgil’s Eclogues into the language of art, with a clarity and grace that rivals the original. In his landscapes, Melibœus always leaves his goats to rest with Daphnis under the gentle shade, waiting for his herds to come drink at the ford, or in moments of passionless regret, one can hear the final whispers of the lament for Gallus as the well-fed goats make their way home beneath the evening star.
Claude is the most ardent worshipper that ever was of the genius loci. Of his landscapes one always feels that “some god is in this place.” Never, it is true, one of the greater gods: no mysterious and fearful Pan, no soul-stirring Bacchus or all-embracing Demeter; scarcely, though he tried more than once deliberately to invoke them, Apollo and the Muses, but some mild local deity, the inhabitant of a rustic shrine whose presence only heightens the glamour of the scene.{149}
Claude is the most passionate admirer of the genius loci. With his landscapes, you can always feel that "some god is in this place." It's true that it's never one of the greater gods: no mysterious and fearsome Pan, no soul-stirring Bacchus, or all-encompassing Demeter; hardly ever, even though he tried several times to call on them, Apollo and the Muses. Instead, it's more of a gentle local deity, the spirit of a humble shrine, whose presence only enhances the beauty of the scene.{149}
It is the sincerity of this worship, and the purity and directness of its expression, which makes the lover of landscape turn with such constant affection to Claude, and the chief means by which he communicates it is the unity and perfection of his general design; it is not by form considered in itself, but by the planning of his tone divisions, that he appeals, and here, at least, he is a past master. This splendid architecture of the tone masses is, indeed, the really great quality in his pictures; its perfection and solidity are what enables them to bear the weight of so meticulous and, to our minds, tiresome an elaboration of detail without loss of unity, and enables us even to accept the enamelled hardness and tightness of his surface. But many people of to-day, accustomed to our more elliptical and quick-witted modes of expression, are so impatient of these qualities that they can only appreciate Claude’s greatness through the medium of his drawings, where the general skeleton of the design is seen without its adornments, and in a medium which he used with perfect ease and undeniable beauty. Thus to reject the pictures is, I think, an error, because it was only when a design had been exposed to constant correction and purification that Claude got out of it its utmost expressiveness, and his improvisations steadily grow under his critical revision to their full perfection. But in the drawings, at all events, Claude’s great powers of design are readily seen, and the study of the drawings has this advantage also, that through them we come to know of a Claude whose existence we could never have suspected by examining only his finished pictures.
The sincerity of this worship and the purity and simplicity of its expression are what make landscape lovers feel such a strong connection to Claude. His main way of communicating this is through the unity and perfection of his overall design. He appeals not by focusing on the form itself, but through how he arranges his tones, and in this regard, he is truly a master. This amazing structure of tone groups is, in fact, the most impressive quality of his paintings. Its perfection and strength allow them to support a level of detail that can seem meticulous and tiresome to us today, without losing their unity, and let us accept the polished hardness and tightness of his surfaces. However, many people today, used to our more concise and quick-witted ways of expression, find these qualities frustrating and can only appreciate Claude’s greatness through his drawings, where the overall outline of the design is visible without the embellishments, and in a medium he handled with ease and undeniable beauty. Therefore, dismissing the paintings seems to be a mistake because it was only after Claude exposed a design to continuous correction and refinement that he was able to extract its full expressiveness, with his improvisations evolving through critical revision to their ultimate perfection. In his drawings, at least, Claude’s extraordinary design abilities are clearly visible, and studying these drawings also reveals a side of Claude that we would never have guessed existed by only looking at his finished paintings.
In speaking of the drawings it is well to recognise that they fall into different classes with different purposes and aims. We need not, for instance, here consider the records of finished compositions in the “Liber Veritatis.” There remain designs for paintings in all stages of completeness, from the first suggestive idea to the finished cartoon and the drawings from nature. It is, perhaps, scarcely necessary to remark that it would have been quite foreign to Claude’s conception of his art to have painted a picture from nature. He, himself, clearly distinguished sharply between his studies and his compositions. His studies, therefore, were not incipient pictures, but exercises done for his own pleasure or for the fertility they gave to his subsequent invention, and they have the unchecked spontaneity{150} and freedom of hand that one would expect in such unreflecting work. These studies again fall into two groups: first, studies of detail, generally of foliage or of tree forms, and occasionally of rocks and flowers; and secondly, studies of general effects. Of the studies of detail I have already said something. They have the charm of an easy and distinguished calligraphy, and of a refined selection of the decorative possibilities of the things seen, but without any of that penetrating investigation of their vital nature which gives its chief beauty to the best work of this kind.
When talking about the drawings, it's important to acknowledge that they belong to different categories, each with distinct purposes and goals. For example, we don't need to consider the records of finished artworks in the “Liber Veritatis.” We have designs for paintings at various stages of completion, from initial concepts to finished cartoons and natural sketches. It's worth noting that Claude would never have thought to paint a picture directly from nature. He clearly made a strong distinction between his studies and his final compositions. His studies were not drafts for future paintings but rather exercises done for his own enjoyment or to enhance his creative process, displaying the raw spontaneity and freehand style expected in such unfiltered work. These studies can also be divided into two categories: first, detailed studies, usually focusing on foliage or tree shapes, and sometimes on rocks and flowers; and second, studies capturing general effects. As I mentioned about the detailed studies, they possess the charm of elegant and refined calligraphy, showcasing a careful selection of the decorative possibilities of the observed subjects, although they lack the deep exploration of their essential nature that gives the best work of this sort its true beauty.{150}
It is, indeed, in the second group of studies from nature that we come from time to time upon motives that startle and surprise us. We find in these a susceptibility to natural charms which, in its width of range and freedom from the traditional limitations of the art of landscape, is most remarkable. Here we find not only Claude the prim seventeenth-century classic, but Claude the romanticist, anticipating the chief ideas of Corot’s later development,[45] and Claude the impressionist, anticipating Whistler and the discovery of Chinese landscape, as, for instance, in the marvellous aperçu of a mist effect, in the British Museum.[46] Or, again, in a view which is quite different from any of these, but quite as remote from the Claude of the oil-paintings, in the great view of the Tiber, a masterpiece of hurried, almost unconscious planning of bold contrasts of transparent gloom and dazzling light on water and plain.
It’s really in the second group of studies from nature that we occasionally come across motives that shock and surprise us. We see a sensitivity to natural beauty that, in its wide range and freedom from the traditional constraints of landscape art, is truly impressive. Here, we encounter not just Claude the strict seventeenth-century classicist, but also Claude the romanticist, who foreshadows the main ideas of Corot’s later work,[45] and Claude the impressionist, who anticipates Whistler and the discovery of Chinese landscapes, as exemplified in the stunning aperçu of a mist effect at the British Museum.[46] Alternatively, there’s a view that, while quite different from these, is just as distant from the Claude of the oil paintings, specifically the grand view of the Tiber, which is a masterpiece of quick, almost instinctive design showcasing striking contrasts of transparent shadows and brilliant light on water and land.
The impression one gets from looking through a collection of Claude’s drawings like that at the British Museum is of a man without any keen feeling for objects in themselves, but singularly open to impressions of general effects in nature, watching always for the shifting patterns of foliage and sky to arrange themselves in some beautifully significant pattern and choosing it with fine and critical taste. But at the same time he was a man with vigorous ideas of the laws of design and the necessity of perfectly realised unity, and to this I suppose one must ascribe the curious contrast between the narrow limits of his work in oil as compared with the wide range, the freedom{151}
The impression you get from looking through a collection of Claude’s drawings, like the one at the British Museum, is of a man who didn’t have a strong attachment to objects themselves but was highly receptive to the general effects in nature. He was always watching for the changing patterns of foliage and sky to come together in a beautifully meaningful arrangement, and he selected these with refined and critical taste. At the same time, he had strong ideas about the principles of design and the necessity for a perfectly realized unity, which I suppose explains the interesting contrast between the limited scope of his oil work and the broad range and freedom{151}
and the profound originality of his work as a draughtsman. Among all these innumerable effects which his ready susceptibility led him to record he found but a few which were capable of being reduced to that logical and mathematical formula which he demanded before complete realisation could be tolerated. In his drawings he composes sometimes with strong diagonal lines, sometimes with free and unstable balance. In his pictures he has recourse to a regular system of polarity, balancing his masses carefully on either side of the centre, sometimes even framing it in like a theatrical scene with two repoussoirs pushed in on either side. One must suppose, then, that he approached the composition of his pictures with a certain timidity, that he felt that safety when working on a large scale could only be secured by a certain recognised type of structure, so that out of all the various moods of nature to which his sensitive spirit answered only one lent itself to complete expression. One wishes at times that he had tried more. There is in the British Museum a half-effaced drawing on blue paper, an idea for treating the Noli me tangere which, had he worked it out, would have added to his complete mastery of bucolic landscape a masterpiece of what one may call tragic landscape. It is true that here, as elsewhere, the figures are in themselves totally inadequate, but they suggested an unusual and intense key to the landscape. On the outskirts of a dimly suggested wood, the figures meet and hold converse; to the right the mound of Calvary glimmers pale and ghost-like against the night sky, while over the distant city the first pink flush of dawn begins. It is an intensely poetical conception. Claude has here created a landscape in harmony with deeper, more mystical aspirations than elsewhere, and, had he given free rein to his sensibilities, we should look to him even more than we do now as the greatest inventor of the motives of pure landscape. As it is, the only ideas to which he gave complete though constantly varied expression are those of pastoral repose.
and the deep originality of his work as a draftsman. Among all the countless effects that his spontaneous sensitivity led him to capture, he found only a few that could be simplified into the logical and mathematical framework he required for full realization. In his drawings, he sometimes composes with strong diagonal lines and at other times with a free and unstable balance. In his paintings, he employs a regular system of balance, carefully distributing his elements on either side of the center, sometimes even framing it like a theatrical scene with two repoussoirs pushed in on either side. One must assume that he approached the composition of his paintings with a certain hesitance, feeling that safety when working on a large scale could only be achieved through a recognized structure type, so that out of all the various moods of nature to which his sensitive spirit responded, only one lent itself to complete expression. At times, one wishes he had explored more. There is a faint drawing on blue paper in the British Museum, an idea for portraying the Noli me tangere which, if he had developed it, would have added to his complete mastery of pastoral landscapes a masterpiece of what might be called tragic landscape. It's true that here, as elsewhere, the figures are fundamentally inadequate, but they suggested an unusual and intense tone to the landscape. On the edge of a vaguely depicted wood, the figures meet and converse; to the right, the mound of Calvary glows faintly and ghost-like against the night sky, while over the distant city, the first pink blush of dawn begins. It’s an intensely poetic idea. Claude has created a landscape here that resonates with deeper, more mystical aspirations than in his other works, and had he allowed his sensibilities to flow freely, we would regard him even more than we do now as the greatest innovator of pure landscape motifs. As it stands, the only concepts to which he gave complete, albeit varied, expression are those of pastoral tranquility.
Claude’s view of landscape is false to nature in that it is entirely anthropocentric. His trees exist for pleasant shade; his peasants to give us the illusion of pastoral life, not to toil for a living. His world is not to be lived in, only to be looked at in a mood of pleasing melancholy or suave reverie. It is, therefore, as true to one aspect of human desire as it is false to the facts of life. It{152} may be admitted that this is not the finest kind of art—it is the art of a self-centred and refined luxury which looks on nature as a garden to its own pleasure-house—but few will deny its genial and moderating charm, and few of us live so strenuously as never to feel a sense of nostalgia for that Saturnian reign to which Virgil and Claude can waft us.{153}
Claude’s view of the landscape is untrue to nature because it is completely centered around human experience. His trees are there for shade; his peasants exist to create an illusion of pastoral life, not to work for their survival. His world is not meant to be lived in, only observed with a sense of pleasing melancholy or smooth daydreaming. It reflects one part of human desire while ignoring the realities of life. It may be agreed that this isn’t the highest form of art—it’s the art of self-indulgence and refined luxury that sees nature as a garden for personal enjoyment—but few would deny its friendly and calming charm, and most of us aren’t so busy that we don’t feel a hint of nostalgia for that golden age to which Virgil and Claude can transport us.
AUBREY BEARDSLEY’S DRAWINGS[47]
MESSRS. CARFAX have on view the most complete collection of Beardsley’s drawings that has hitherto been shown. The development of his precocious and eccentric genius can here be studied in typical examples. We have the drawings of his childhood—drawings inspired by Dicky Doyle and Robida, but in which is already apparent his proclivity to the expression of moral depravity. We pass at a leap from these crude and artistically feeble works to the astonishing “Siegfried,” in which he is already a complete and assured master of an entirely personal style.
MESSRS. CARFAX are showcasing the most complete collection of Beardsley’s drawings ever displayed. You can study the growth of his early and unique talent through representative examples. We have childhood drawings—influenced by Dicky Doyle and Robida—but already showing his tendency to express moral corruption. We quickly move from these rough and artistically weak pieces to the impressive “Siegfried,” where he has fully developed an assured and distinctive style.
From this time onwards, for the remaining six years of his life, Beardsley kept on producing with the fertility of those artists whom the presage of an early death stimulates to a desperate activity. His style was constantly changing in accidentals, but always the same in essentials. He was a confirmed eclectic, borrowing from all ages and all countries. And true eclectic and genuine artist as he was, he converted all his borrowings to his own purposes. It mattered nothing what he fed on; the strange and perverse economy of his nature converted the food into a poison. His line is based upon that of Antonio Pollajuolo. Again and again in his drawings of the nude we see how carefully he must have copied that master of structural and nervous line. But he uses it for something quite other than its original purpose; he converts it from a line expressive of muscular tension and virile force into one expressive of corruption and decay. Mantegna, too, was a favourite with Beardsley, who seems to have had a kind of craving for the opposites to his own predominant qualities; and from Mantegna, the most austere of Italians, he derived again and again motives for his illustrations of depravity. The eighteenth century, China, Japan, even the purest Greek art, were all pressed into his service; the only thing he could do nothing with was nature{154} itself. Here he was entirely at a loss, and whenever he yielded to the pressure of contemporary fashions and attempted to record impressions of things seen, as in the topical illustrations of plays which he contributed to the Pall Mall Magazine, he failed to be even mediocre. Everything that was to be in the least expressive had to come entirely from within, from the nightmares of his own imagination.
From this point on, for the last six years of his life, Beardsley continued to create with the energy of those artists who, sensing an early death, are driven to intense activity. His style constantly changed in its details, but the core remained the same. He was a true eclectic, pulling inspiration from all eras and cultures. And as a genuine artist and eclectic, he transformed all his influences for his own purposes. It didn’t matter what he drew from; the unique and twisted nature of his being turned the input into something toxic. His line work is based on that of Antonio Pollajuolo. Time and again in his nude drawings, we can see how closely he must have studied that master of structural and dynamic line. Yet, he repurposes it for something entirely different; he shifts it from a line defined by muscular tension and male strength to one that conveys corruption and decay. Mantegna was also a favorite of Beardsley, who seemed to have a longing for qualities that contrasted sharply with his own; from Mantegna, the most reserved of Italians, he often drew inspiration for his illustrations of debauchery. The eighteenth century, China, Japan, and even the most refined Greek art were all utilized in his work; the only thing he couldn’t seem to relate to was nature itself. In this realm, he was completely at a standstill, and whenever he succumbed to contemporary trends and tried to capture real-world impressions, like in the topical illustrations for plays he contributed to the Pall Mall Magazine, he barely managed to achieve mediocrity. Anything that had to be even slightly expressive had to come entirely from within, from the nightmares of his own imagination.
His amazing gift of hand is perhaps the quality which most obviously attracts attention, the quality which endeared him most to publishers and process-block makers. It was the one indisputable quality he possessed, not to be denied by the most adverse critic, and yet in itself it is no more than thousands of journeymen artists—engravers, die-cutters, and such like—have always possessed. Nor, to be perfectly frank, is the quality of his line of a very high order; its precision is not unfrequently mechanical. Whistler called him the last of the writing-masters, and there was a truth in this, if we may add that the style of writing which he favoured was degenerate. His long, meandering flourishes ending in sharp spikes and dots, however firm and precise the line, are often mean in intention and poor in quality. What is deserving of real admiration is the fertility of his invention, the skill with which he finds the formula which corresponds, in his peculiar language, with what he wants to describe. As an instance, one may take the garden background to the “Platonic Lament” in the Salome series, where the rose trellis and cut yew-tree behind are brilliant examples of this kind of epitomised description. Still more important artistically, and closely connected with this power of invention, is the real beauty of his spacing, the admirable planning of masses of black and white. At times, as in the “Dancer’s Reward,” he rises almost to the height of the great Greek vase-painters in this respect, though, if we look even at this in detail, the line has an intricacy, a mesquinerie, which is the very opposite of the Greek ideal of draughtsmanship.
His incredible talent with his hands is probably the quality that stands out the most, the one that won him the most favor with publishers and printmakers. It was the one undeniable skill he had, one that even the harshest critics couldn't dismiss, yet it's a skill that thousands of other artists—engravers, die-cutters, and so on—have always had. Honestly, his line quality isn't particularly high; its precision is often more mechanical than artistic. Whistler referred to him as the last of the writing-masters, and there's some truth to that, though we can also say the style of writing he preferred was less than great. His long, winding flourishes that end with sharp spikes and dots, despite being firm and precise, often come across as mean-spirited and low quality. What truly deserves admiration is his inventive talent and the skill with which he finds the right formula to express what he wants in his unique style. For instance, the garden background in the “Platonic Lament” from the Salome series, featuring the rose trellis and trimmed yew tree, serves as brilliant examples of this kind of concise description. Even more important artistically, and closely tied to this inventive power, is the real beauty of his spacing and the excellent planning of black and white masses. At times, as seen in the “Dancer’s Reward,” he nearly reaches the level of the great Greek vase painters in this regard, though if we examine this closely, the line displays an intricacy, a mesquinerie, which is the exact opposite of the Greek ideal of drawing.
No less remarkable is his success in the decorative planning of three tones, of black, white, and grey, and he divides these with such subtle skill that for once it is not a mere false analogy to talk of the colour effect of designs in black and white; for he so disposes the three tones, getting the grey by an evenly distributed network of fine black lines, that each tone produces the sensation of something as{155} distinct from the others as do flat washes of different tints. The “Frontispiece to Salome” is an excellent example of this.
No less impressive is his success in the decorative use of three colors: black, white, and grey. He separates these tones with such skill that it’s not just a false analogy to refer to the color effect of designs in black and white. He arranges the three tones in a way that the grey is created by a finely distributed network of black lines, making each tone feel as distinct from the others as flat washes of different shades. The “Frontispiece to Salome” is a great example of this.
Beardsley had, then, in an extraordinary degree the decorative impulse, the motive which made the mediæval scribe flourish his pen all over the margins of his vellum page; and, spurred by this impulse, he had the patience of an Indian craftsman, covering whole sheets with minute dots and scarcely perceptible lines. This instinct in its purest form rarely makes for the finest art; it is only when controlled by a larger, more genial sentiment for architectural mass that it becomes ennobled, and with Beardsley, in spite of the bold oppositions of his blacks and whites, in spite of his occasional wilful simplification, this rarely occurred. One might even argue that to some extent Beardsley’s moral perversity actually prevented him, in spite of his extraordinary specific talent for design, from ever becoming a great designer. It is just that mesquinerie of line, that littleness and intricacy of the mere decorator, that love of elegance rather than beauty, which on purely artistic grounds one finds to be his great failing, that he cherished as a means of expressing his diabolism. But if Beardsley was corrupt, he was certainly sincere in his corruption. There is no suggestion in his work, as in that of some modern artists, like Señor Zuloaga, that corruption is an affectation taken up in order to astonish the bourgeoisie. Beardsley is never funny or amusing or witty; his attempts in this direction are contemptible; still less is he voluptuous or seductive; he is very serious, very much in earnest. There is even a touch of hieratic austerity and pomp in his style, as becomes the arch-priest of a Satanic cultus. He has, indeed, all the stigmata of the religious artist—the love of pure decoration, the patient elaboration and enrichment of surface, the predilection for flat tones and precision of contour, the want of the sense of mass and relief, the extravagant richness of invention. It is as the Fra Angelico of Satanism that his work will always have an interest for those who are curious about this recurrent phase of complex civilisations. But if we are right in our analysis of his work, the finest qualities of design can never be appropriated to the expression of such morbid and perverted ideals; nobility and geniality of design are attained only by those who, whatever their actual temperament, cherish these qualities in their imagination.{156}
Beardsley had an extraordinary decorative impulse, the drive that made the medieval scribe flourish his pen all over the margins of his vellum pages. Driven by this impulse, he exhibited the patience of an Indian craftsman, filling entire sheets with tiny dots and nearly imperceptible lines. This instinct in its purest form rarely leads to the finest art; it only reaches its potential when guided by a broader, more generous sentiment for architectural mass. With Beardsley, despite the bold contrasts in his blacks and whites and occasional deliberate simplifications, this rarely happened. One could even argue that Beardsley’s moral perversion somewhat kept him, despite his exceptional talent for design, from becoming a great designer. It’s that small-mindedness of line, the intricacy of a mere decorator, that preference for elegance over beauty, which, from a purely artistic standpoint, is his major flaw, yet he embraced it as a way to express his diabolism. But if Beardsley was corrupt, he was genuinely sincere in his corruption. Unlike some modern artists, like Señor Zuloaga, there’s no hint in his work that corruption is an act put on to shock the bourgeoisie. Beardsley is never funny, amusing, or witty; his efforts in that direction are pitiful; he’s even less voluptuous or seductive; he is very serious and earnest. There’s even a touch of rigid austerity and grandeur in his style, suiting the arch-priest of a Satanic cult. He truly embodies all the traits of a religious artist—the love of pure decoration, the careful elaboration and enhancement of surface, the preference for flat tones and precise outlines, the lack of sense for mass and relief, and the extravagance of invention. His work will always capture the interest of those curious about this recurring phase of complex civilizations as the Fra Angelico of Satanism. However, if our analysis of his work is correct, the finest qualities of design can never reflect such morbid and twisted ideals; nobility and warmth in design are achieved only by those who, regardless of their actual temperament, hold these qualities in their imagination.{156}
THE FRENCH POST-IMPRESSIONISTS[48]
WHEN the first Post-Impressionist Exhibition was held in these Galleries two years ago the English public became for the first time fully aware of the existence of a new movement in art, a movement which was the more disconcerting in that it was no mere variation upon accepted themes but implied a reconsideration of the very purpose and aim as well as the methods of pictorial and plastic art. It was not surprising, therefore, that a public which had come to admire above everything in a picture the skill with which the artist produced illusion should have resented an art in which such skill was completely subordinated to the direct expression of feeling. Accusations of clumsiness and incapacity were freely made, even against so singularly accomplished an artist as Cézanne. Such darts, however, fall wide of the mark, since it is not the object of these artists to exhibit their skill or proclaim their knowledge, but only to attempt to express by pictorial and plastic form certain spiritual experiences; and in conveying these, ostentation of skill is likely to be even more fatal than downright incapacity.
WHEN the first Post-Impressionist Exhibition was held in these Galleries two years ago, the English public became fully aware of a new art movement for the first time. This movement was particularly disconcerting because it wasn't just a variation of accepted themes; it called for a rethinking of the very purpose and methods of visual and sculptural art. So, it wasn't surprising that a public who had come to admire the skill in creating illusion in artwork reacted negatively to an art form where such skill was entirely secondary to the direct expression of emotion. Accusations of clumsiness and incompetence were hurled, even at a uniquely talented artist like Cézanne. However, those criticisms miss the point, since these artists aren't trying to showcase their skill or flaunt their knowledge; their goal is to express certain spiritual experiences through visual and sculptural forms. In fact, trying to show off their skill could be more detrimental than outright inability.
Indeed, one may fairly admit that the accusation of want of skill and knowledge, while ridiculous in the case of Cézanne is perfectly justified as regards one artist represented (for the first time in England) in the present Exhibition, namely, Rousseau. Rousseau was a customhouse officer who painted without any training in the art. His pretensions to paint made him the butt of a great deal of ironic wit, but scarcely any one now would deny the authentic quality of his inspiration or the certainty of his imaginative conviction. Here then is one case where want of skill and knowledge do not completely obscure, though they may mar, expression. And this is true of all perfectly naïve and primitive art. But most of the art here seen is neither naïve nor primitive. It is the work of highly civilised and modern men trying to find a pictorial language appropriate to the sensibilities of the modern outlook.{157}
Indeed, one can reasonably acknowledge that the claim of lacking skill and knowledge, while absurd in the case of Cézanne, is entirely justified regarding one artist featured (for the first time in England) in this Exhibition, namely, Rousseau. Rousseau was a customs officer who painted without any formal training in the art. His ambitions to be an artist made him the target of a lot of ironic humor, but hardly anyone today would deny the genuine quality of his inspiration or the clarity of his imaginative vision. Here is an example where a lack of skill and knowledge does not completely overshadow, though it may diminish, expression. This applies to all truly naïve and primitive art. However, most of the art presented here is neither naïve nor primitive. It is the work of highly civilized and modern individuals trying to create a visual language that resonates with contemporary sensibilities.{157}
Another charge that is frequently made against these artists is that they allow what is merely capricious, or even what is extravagant and eccentric, in their work—that it is not serious, but an attempt to impose on the good-natured tolerance of the public. This charge of insincerity and extravagance is invariably made against any new manifestation of creative art. It does not of course follow that it is always wrong. The desire to impose by such means certainly occurs, and is sometimes temporarily successful. But the feeling on the part of the public may, and I think in this case does, arise from a simple misunderstanding of what these artists set out to do. The difficulty springs from a deep-rooted conviction, due to long-established custom, that the aim of painting is the descriptive imitation of natural forms. Now, these artists do not seek to give what can, after all, be but a pale reflex of actual appearance, but to arouse the conviction of a new and definite reality. They do not seek to imitate form, but to create form; not to imitate life, but to find an equivalent for life. By that I mean that they wish to make images which by the clearness of their logical structure, and by their closely-knit unity of texture, shall appeal to our disinterested and contemplative imagination with something of the same vividness as the things of actual life appeal to our practical activities. In fact, they aim not at illusion but at reality.
Another criticism that these artists often face is that they let their work become whimsical, extravagant, or eccentric—that it’s not serious but rather an attempt to take advantage of the public's good-natured tolerance. This accusation of insincerity and excess is repeatedly leveled at any new form of creative art. However, that doesn’t mean it’s always unjustified. The desire to impose through such means does happen, and is sometimes temporarily successful. But the public's reaction may, and I believe in this case does, come from a simple misunderstanding of what these artists aim to achieve. The challenge arises from a deep-seated belief, rooted in long-held customs, that the goal of painting is to imitate natural forms descriptively. These artists aren’t trying to present a mere shadow of actual appearances; instead, they want to evoke the sense of a new and definite reality. They don’t aim to mimic form, but to create it; not to imitate life, but to find something that reflects life. By that, I mean they want to produce images which, through their clear logical structure and tightly woven texture, engage our disinterested and contemplative imagination with a vividness similar to how actual things engage our practical activities. In fact, their goal is not illusion, but reality.
The logical extreme of such a method would undoubtedly be the attempt to give up all resemblance to natural form, and to create a purely abstract language of form—a visual music; and the later works of Picasso show this clearly enough. They may or may not be successful in their attempt. It is too early to be dogmatic on the point, which can only be decided when our sensibilities to such abstract forms have been more practised than they are at present. But I would suggest that there is nothing ridiculous in the attempt to do this. Such a picture as Picasso’s “Head of a Man” would undoubtedly be ridiculous if, having set out to make a direct imitation of the actual model, he had been incapable of getting a better likeness. But Picasso did nothing of the sort. He has shown in his “Portrait of Mlle. L. B.” that he could do so at least as well as any one if he wished, but he is here attempting to do something quite different.
The logical extreme of this method would definitely be trying to eliminate any resemblance to natural forms and create a purely abstract language of form—a visual music; and Picasso's later works illustrate this quite clearly. They may or may not succeed in this effort. It’s too early to be definitive on this, which can only be determined once our understanding of such abstract forms has been more developed than it is now. However, I’d argue that there’s nothing absurd about attempting this. A piece like Picasso’s “Head of a Man” would certainly seem ridiculous if he aimed to create a direct imitation of the actual model but failed to produce a decent likeness. But Picasso didn't do that. He demonstrated in his “Portrait of Mlle. L. B.” that he could achieve a likeness as good as anyone if he wanted to, but here he’s trying to do something entirely different.
No such extreme abstraction marks the work of Matisse. The actual objects which stimulated his creative invention are recognisable{158} enough. But here, too, it is an equivalence, not a likeness, of nature that is sought. In opposition to Picasso, who is pre-eminently plastic, Matisse aims at convincing us of the reality of his forms by the continuity and flow of his rhythmic line, by the logic of his space relations, and, above all, by an entirely new use of colour. In this, as in his markedly rhythmic design, he approaches more than any other European to the ideals of Chinese art. His work has to an extraordinary degree that decorative unity of design which distinguishes all the artists of this school.
No extreme abstraction defines Matisse's work. The actual objects that inspired his creativity are easily recognizable{158}. However, here too, he seeks an equivalence, not a direct likeness, to nature. Unlike Picasso, who is primarily focused on form, Matisse aims to convince us of the reality of his shapes through the continuity and flow of his rhythmic lines, the logic of his spatial relationships, and especially through a completely new approach to color. In this respect, as well as in his distinctly rhythmic design, he aligns more closely than any other European artist with the ideals of Chinese art. His work possesses an extraordinary degree of decorative unity in design that characterizes all artists of this school.
Between these two extremes we may find ranged almost all the remaining artists. On the whole the influence of Picasso on the younger men is more evident than that of Matisse. With the exception of Braque none of them push their attempts at abstraction of form so far as Picasso, but simplification along these lines is apparent in the work of Derain, Herbin, Marchand, and L’Hote. Other artists, such as Doucet and Asselin, are content with the ideas of simplification of form as existing in the general tradition of the Post-Impressionist movement, and instead of feeling for new methods of expression devote themselves to expressing what is most poignant and moving in contemporary life. But however various the directions in which different groups are exploring the newly-found regions of expressive form they all alike derive in some measure from the great originator of the whole idea, Cézanne. And since one must always refer to him to understand the origin of these ideas, it has been thought well to include a few examples of his work in the present Exhibition, although this year it is mainly the moderns, and not the old masters, that are represented. To some extent, also, the absence of the earlier masters in the exhibition itself is made up for by the retrospective exhibition of Monsieur Druet’s admirable photographs. Here Cézanne, Gauguin, and Van Gogh can be studied at least in the main phases of their development.
Between these two extremes, we can find almost all the remaining artists. Overall, Picasso's influence on younger artists is more noticeable than Matisse's. With the exception of Braque, none of them push their attempts at abstracting form as far as Picasso does, but there's a clear simplification in the work of Derain, Herbin, Marchand, and L’Hote. Other artists, like Doucet and Asselin, are satisfied with the ideas of form simplification from the broader Post-Impressionist movement, and instead of seeking new methods of expression, they focus on capturing what is most poignant and impactful in contemporary life. However varied the directions in which different groups are exploring these newly discovered areas of expressive form, they all share some influence from the great originator of the whole concept, Cézanne. Since we always need to refer to him to understand where these ideas come from, it has been deemed appropriate to include a few examples of his work in the current Exhibition, even though this year it mainly features modern artists rather than old masters. To a certain extent, the absence of earlier masters in the exhibition is compensated by the retrospective exhibition of Monsieur Druet’s excellent photographs. Here, Cézanne, Gauguin, and Van Gogh can be studied, especially in the main phases of their development.
Finally, I should like to call attention to a distinguishing characteristic of the French artists seen here, namely, the markedly Classic spirit of their work. This will be noted as distinguishing them to some extent from the English, even more perhaps from the Russians, and most of all from the great mass of modern painting in every country. I do not mean by Classic, dull, pedantic, traditional,{159}
Finally, I want to highlight a unique quality of the French artists shown here, specifically the strong Classic influence in their work. This sets them apart to some degree from the English artists, even more so from the Russians, and most of all from the vast majority of modern painting in every country. By Classic, I don't mean boring, overly formal, or strictly traditional,{159}
reserved, or any of those similar things which the word is often made to imply. Still less do I mean by calling them Classic that they paint “Visits to Æsculapius” or “Nero at the Colosseum.” I mean that they do not rely for their effect upon associated ideas, as I believe Romantic and Realistic artists invariably do.
reserved, or any of those similar kinds of things that the word often suggests. Even less do I mean by calling them Classic that they depict “Visits to Æsculapius” or “Nero at the Colosseum.” What I mean is that they don't depend for their impact on associated ideas, as I think Romantic and Realistic artists always do.
All art depends upon cutting off the practical responses to sensations of ordinary life, thereby setting free a pure and as it were disembodied functioning of the spirit; but in so far as the artist relies on the associated ideas of the objects which he represents, his work is not completely free and pure, since romantic associations imply at least an imagined practical activity. The disadvantage of such an art of associated ideas is that its effect really depends on what we bring with us: it adds no entirely new factor to our experience. Consequently, when the first shock of wonder or delight is exhausted the work produces an ever lessening reaction. Classic art, on the other hand, records a positive and disinterestedly passionate state of mind. It communicates a new and otherwise unattainable experience. Its effect, therefore, is likely to increase with familiarity. Such a classic spirit is common to the best French work of all periods from the twelfth century onwards, and though no one could find direct reminiscences of a Nicholas Poussin here, his spirit seems to revive in the work of artists like Derain. It is natural enough that the intensity and singleness of aim with which these artists yield themselves to certain experiences in the face of nature may make their work appear odd to those who have not the habit of contemplative vision, but it would be rash for us, who as a nation are in the habit of treating our emotions, especially our æsthetic emotions, with a certain levity, to accuse them of caprice or insincerity. It is because of this classic concentration of feeling (which by no means implies abandonment) that the French merit our serious attention. It is this that makes their art so difficult on a first approach but gives it its lasting hold on the imagination.
All art relies on shutting out the practical responses to everyday sensations, allowing for a pure and almost disembodied expression of the spirit. However, as long as the artist depends on the associated ideas of the objects they depict, their work isn’t entirely free and pure, since romantic associations suggest at least a imagined practical activity. The drawback of art based on associated ideas is that its impact largely depends on our personal contributions; it doesn’t introduce any completely new elements to our experience. Therefore, once the initial shock of wonder or delight fades, the work elicits a diminishing response. Classic art, on the other hand, captures a positive and selfless passionate state of mind. It conveys a new and otherwise unreachable experience. Its impact is likely to grow with familiarity. This classic spirit is present in the best French works from the twelfth century onward, and although there are no direct similarities to Nicholas Poussin here, his spirit seems to be revived in artists like Derain. It’s understandable that the intensity and singular focus with which these artists engage with certain experiences in nature may come off as unusual to those who aren’t used to contemplative observation. However, it would be unwise for us, as a nation often treating our emotions—especially our aesthetic feelings—with some triviality, to accuse them of whimsy or insincerity. It is due to this classic concentration of feeling (which certainly doesn’t imply neglect) that the French deserve our serious attention. This is what makes their art challenging at first but ultimately offers a lasting impact on the imagination.
Note.—At least one French artist of great merit was un-represented at the Post-Impressionist Exhibitions—Georges Rouault, a fellow pupil with Matisse of Gustave Moreau. He stands alone in the movement as being a visionary, though, unlike most visionaries, his expression is based on a profound knowledge of natural appearances. The profile here reproduced (see Plate) will give an idea of his strangely individual and powerful style. (1920.)
Note.—At least one highly talented French artist was not represented at the Post-Impressionist Exhibitions—Georges Rouault, who was a classmate of Matisse under Gustave Moreau. He is unique in the movement as a visionary, but unlike many visionaries, his expression comes from a deep understanding of the natural world. The profile shown here (see Plate) provides a glimpse of his uniquely striking and powerful style. (1920.)
DRAWINGS AT THE BURLINGTON FINE ARTS CLUB[49]
THE Burlington Fine Arts Club have arranged a most interesting collection of drawings by dead masters. Abandoning the club’s usual method of taking a particular period or country, the committee have this time allowed their choice to range over many periods and countries, excluding only living artists, and admitting one so recently dead as Degas. This variety of material naturally stimulates one to hazard some general speculations on the nature of drawing as an art. “H. T.,” who writes the preface to the catalogue, already points the way in this direction by some obiter dicta. He points out that the essence of drawing is not the line, but its content. He says:
THE Burlington Fine Arts Club has put together a fascinating collection of drawings by long-gone masters. Instead of focusing on a specific period or country as they usually do, the committee has chosen works from various times and places, only excluding living artists, with the exception of the recently deceased Degas. This diverse selection naturally encourages one to make some general observations on what drawing is as an art form. “H. T.,” who writes the preface for the catalog, hints at this idea with some obiter dicta. He emphasizes that the essence of drawing is not the line itself but rather its content. He states:
A single line may mean nothing beyond a line; add another alongside and both disappear, and we are aware only of the contents, and a form is expressed. The beauty of a line is in its result in the form which it helps to bring into being.
A single line might seem insignificant on its own; add another next to it, and both fade away, leaving us focused only on what they represent, and a shape is created. The beauty of a line lies in the form it contributes to creating.
Here the author has undoubtedly pointed out the most essential quality of good drawing. I should dispute, rather by way of excessive caution, his first statement, “A single line may mean nothing beyond a line,” since a line is always at its least the record of a gesture, indicating a good deal about its maker’s personality, his tastes and even probably the period when he lived; but I entirely agree that the main point is always the effect of two lines to evoke the idea of a certain volume having a certain form. When “H. T.” adds that “Draughtsmen know this, but writers on art do not seem to,” he seems to be too sweeping. Even so bad a writer on art as Pliny had picked up the idea from a Greek art critic, for in describing the drawing of Parrhasios he says:[50]
Here, the author has clearly highlighted the most important quality of good drawing. I would challenge, more out of caution, his first claim, “A single line may mean nothing beyond a line,” because a line is at least a record of a gesture, revealing a lot about the personality of its creator, their preferences, and perhaps even the era they lived in; however, I completely agree that the key point is how two lines work together to suggest the idea of a certain volume with a specific shape. When “H. T.” adds that “Draughtsmen know this, but writers on art do not seem to,” he seems to overgeneralize. Even a less capable writer on art like Pliny recognized this idea from a Greek art critic, as he mentions in his description of Parrhasios’s drawing: [50]
By the admission of artists he was supreme in contour. This is the last subtlety of painting; for to paint the main body and centres of objects is indeed something of an achievement, but one in which many have been famous, but to paint the edges of bodies and express the disappearing planes is rare in the history of art. For the contour must go round itself and so end that it promises other things behind and shows that which it hides.
By the acknowledgment of artists, he was unmatched in contour. This is the ultimate nuance of painting; capturing the main shapes and centers of objects is certainly an accomplishment, and many have excelled at it, but painting the edges of forms and conveying the vanishing planes is uncommon in the history of art. The contour must wrap around itself, implying more behind it and revealing what it conceals.
This is an admirable account, since it gives the clue to the distinction between descriptive drawing and drawing in which the contour does not arrest the form, but creates plastic relief of the whole enclosed volume. Now, this plastic drawing can never be attained by a mere description of the edges of objects. Such a description, however exact, can at the utmost do no more than recall vividly the original object; it cannot enable the spectator to realise its plastic volume more clearly than the original object would. Now, when we look at a really good drawing we do get a much more vivid sense of a plastic volume than we get from actual objects.
This is an impressive account, as it highlights the difference between descriptive drawing and drawing that doesn’t just outline the form but creates a three-dimensional representation of the entire enclosed volume. Plastic drawing can never be achieved simply by describing the edges of objects. Even the most accurate description can only vividly remind us of the original object; it can't help the viewer understand its three-dimensional volume any better than the original object itself. When we look at a truly excellent drawing, we actually gain a much clearer sense of its three-dimensionality than we do from real objects.
Unfortunately this is a very severe test to apply, and would, I think, relegate to an inferior class the vast majority of drawings, even of those in the present exhibition. The vast majority of drawings even by the celebrated masters do appeal mainly by other more subsidiary qualities, by the brightness of their descriptive power, and by the elegance and facility of their execution. There is an undoubted pleasure in the contemplation of mere skill, and there are few ways of demonstrating sheer skill of hand more convincingly than the drawing of a complex series of curves with perfect exactitude and great rapidity. And when the curves thus brilliantly drawn describe vividly some object in life towards which we have pleasing associations we get a complex pleasure which is only too likely to be regarded as an æsthetic experience when in fact it is nothing of the kind.
Unfortunately, this is a very tough standard to apply, and I think it would place the vast majority of drawings, even those in this exhibition, in a lower category. Most drawings, even those by famous masters, tend to appeal mainly through other secondary qualities, like the vibrancy of their descriptive power and the elegance and ease of their execution. There’s undeniably a pleasure in simply admiring skill, and few things demonstrate sheer hand skill more convincingly than drawing a complex series of curves with perfect precision and speed. When those beautifully drawn curves vividly represent something in life that we have positive associations with, we experience a complex pleasure that is all too often mistaken for an aesthetic experience when, in reality, it’s not that at all.
The author of the preface has quite clearly seen that this element of brilliance in the execution of the line does frequently come into play, and he considers this calligraphic quality to be always a sign of a lowered æsthetic purpose, citing Tiepolo quite rightly as a great master of such qualities. And he quite rightly points out that with the deliberate pursuit of calligraphy there is always a tendency to{162} substitute type forms for individual forms. On the other hand, all good drawing also tends to create types, since a type results from the synthetic unity of the design. The real question here would seem to be the fulness or emptiness of the type created, and it would be fair to say that the calligraphic draughtsman accepted most readily an empty type. For instance, one would have to admit that Ingres created a type, and repeated it as much as Tiepolo, only Ingres continually generated his type of form upon actual material, whereas Tiepolo tended merely to repeat his without enriching it with fresh material.
The author of the preface has clearly recognized that this aspect of brilliance in the execution of the line often comes into play. He views this calligraphic quality as a consistent indication of a diminished aesthetic purpose, rightly citing Tiepolo as a great master of such traits. He also correctly notes that the intentional focus on calligraphy tends to replace individual forms with type forms. On the other hand, good drawing also tends to create types, as a type arises from the unified design. The real question seems to focus on the richness or emptiness of the created type, and it would be fair to say that the calligraphic drafter often embraced a more empty type. For example, one must acknowledge that Ingres created a type and repeated it just as much as Tiepolo did, but Ingres consistently generated his type of form from actual material, while Tiepolo mainly repeated his without adding any new material.
The exhibition has been to some extent arranged around Ingres, and as many of his drawings as possible have been collected. Ingres has long been accepted in the schools as par excellence the great modern master of drawing. His great saying, “Le dessin c’est la probité de l’art,” has indeed become a watchword of the schools and an excuse for indulgence in a great deal of gratuitous and misplaced moral feeling. It has led to the display of all kinds of pedagogic folly. Art is a passion or it is nothing. It is certainly a very bad moral gymnasium. It is useless to try to make a kind of moral parallel bars out of the art of drawing. You will certainly spoil the drawing, and it is doubtful if you will get the morals. Drawing is a passion to the draughtsman just as much as colour is to the colourist, and the draughtsman has no reason to feel moral superiority because of the nature of his passion. He is fortunate to have it, and there is an end of the matter. Ingres himself had the passion for draughtsmanship very intensely, though perhaps one would scarcely guess it from the specimens shown in this exhibition. These unfortunately are, with few exceptions, taken from that large class of drawings which he did as a young man in Rome. He was already married, and was poor. He was engaged on some of his biggest and most important compositions, on which he was determined to spare no pains or labour; consequently he found himself forced to earn his living by doing these brilliant and minutely accurate portraits of the aristocratic tourists and their families, who happened to pass through Rome. These drawings bear the unmistakable mark of their origins. They are commissions, and they are done to satisfy the sitter. Anything like serious research for form is out of the question; there is little here but Ingres’s extreme facility and a certain negative good taste. Probably the only drawing{163}
The exhibition is somewhat centered around Ingres, and as many of his drawings as possible have been gathered. Ingres is widely recognized in the art world as the ultimate modern master of drawing. His famous quote, “Drawing is the honesty of art,” has become a motto in art schools and has led to a lot of misplaced moral judgment. This has resulted in various forms of misguided teaching methods. Art is a passion or it’s nothing at all. It’s definitely not a suitable place for moral training. Trying to turn drawing into some kind of moral exercise will ruin the art, and you probably won’t achieve the moral lessons either. Drawing is just as much a passion for the draughtsman as color is for the colorist, and the draughtsman has no reason to feel morally superior due to his passion. He is lucky to have that passion, and that’s that. Ingres had an intense passion for drawing, although you might not fully see it in the works displayed here. Unfortunately, most of these pieces come from a large group of drawings he created as a young man in Rome. At that time, he was already married and struggling financially. He was working on some of his most significant compositions and was committed to putting in a lot of effort and hard work. Consequently, he had to make a living by creating these impressive and highly detailed portraits of aristocratic tourists and their families passing through Rome. These drawings clearly show their origins. They are commissioned works, created to please the sitters. Serious exploration of form isn’t really an option here; what we see is mainly Ingres’s incredible skill and a certain level of understated good taste. Probably the only drawing{163}
here which shows Ingres’s more serious powers is the tight, elaborate and rather repellent study for the “Apotheosis of Napoleon,” which is a splendid discovery of composition within a round (see Plate). But the real fact is, I believe, that Ingres’s power as a draughtsman hardly ever comes out fully in his drawings; one must turn to his paintings to see how great and sincere a researcher he was. In his drawings he was too much pre-occupied with the perfect description of facts; when he came to the painting he began that endless process of readjustment and balance of contours which make him so great and original a designer. If one places his drawings and studies from the nude for, say, his “Venus Anadyomene” beside the photograph of the picture one gets some idea of the tireless and passionate research for the exact correspondence of the contours on either side of the figure which Ingres undertook. He throws over one by one all the brilliant notations of natural form in the studies, and arrives bit by bit at an intensely abstract and simplified statement of the general relations. But though the new statement is emptied of its factual content, it has now become far more compact, far more intense in its plasticity. Here and there among Ingres’s innumerable drawings one may find a nude study in which already this process of elimination and balance has taken place, but the examples are rare, and if one would understand why Ingres is one of the great masters of design, one must face the slightly repellent quality of his oil paintings rather than allow oneself to be seduced by the elegance and ease of his drawings.
What showcases Ingres’s more serious skills is the intricate, detailed, and somewhat off-putting study for the “Apotheosis of Napoleon,” which is a fantastic discovery of composition within a round (see Plate). But the truth is, I believe, that Ingres’s talent as a draftsman rarely shines through in his drawings; you need to look at his paintings to see how great and genuine a researcher he was. In his drawings, he was too focused on the perfect representation of reality; when it came to painting, he began that endless process of adjusting and balancing contours that makes him such a great and original designer. If you place his drawings and studies from the nude for, say, his “Venus Anadyomene” next to the photograph of the painting, you get some sense of the tireless and passionate effort Ingres put into ensuring the contours corresponded accurately on both sides of the figure. He gradually discards the brilliant details of natural form in the studies and arrives piece by piece at a highly abstract and simplified expression of the general relationships. Although this new representation lacks factual content, it has become much more compact and intense in its plasticity. Here and there among Ingres’s countless drawings, you might find a nude study where this process of reduction and balance has already occurred, but such examples are rare. To understand why Ingres is one of the great masters of design, one must confront the somewhat off-putting quality of his oil paintings instead of being lured in by the elegance and simplicity of his drawings.
It would, I think, be possible to show that very few great designers have attained to full expression in line. I suspect, indeed, that the whole tradition of art in Europe, since about the end of the fifteenth century, has been against such complete expression. If we compare the great masterpieces of pure drawing such as the drawings of figures on Persian pots of the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, and the few remaining examples of drawings by the Italian primitives of the fourteenth and early fifteenth centuries, with the vast mass of European drawings subsequent to that date, we see, I think, the contrast of aims and purpose of the two groups. Somewhere about the time of Filippino Lippi there was formulated an idea of drawing which has more or less held the field ever since in art schools.
I think it would be possible to show that very few great designers have fully expressed themselves in line. I actually suspect that the entire tradition of art in Europe, since around the end of the fifteenth century, has been against such complete expression. When we compare the great masterpieces of pure drawing, like the figures on Persian pots from the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, and the few remaining examples of drawings by the Italian primitives of the fourteenth and early fifteenth centuries, with the vast number of European drawings that followed, we can see, I believe, the difference in aims and purposes between the two groups. Around the time of Filippino Lippi, an idea of drawing was established that has mostly remained dominant in art schools ever since.
As most drawing has centred in the human figure we may describe{164} it in relation to that, the more so that this view of drawing undoubtedly came in with the study of anatomy. The general principle is that there are certain cardinal facts about the figure, or points of cardinal importance in the rendering of structure—the artist is trained to observe these with special care, since they become the points de repère for his drawing. And since they are thus specially observed they are noted with a special accent. When once the artist has learned to grasp the relations of these points de repère firmly he learns also to pass from one to the other with great ease and rapidity, not to say with a certain indifference as to what happens in the passage. By this method the essentials of structure and movement of a figure are accurately given and the whole statement can be made with that easy facility and rapidity of line which gives a peculiar pleasure. Such drawing has the merit of being at once structurally accurate and more or less calligraphically pleasing. The most admired masters, such as Vandyke, Watteau, even to some extent Rubens, all exhibit the characteristics of such a conception. Now in the earlier kind of drawing there were no recognised points de repère, no particular moments of emphasis; the line was so drawn that at every point its relation to the opposed contour was equally close, the tension so to speak was always across the line and not along its direction. The essential thing was the position of the line, not its quality, so that there was the less inclination to aim at that easy rapidity which marks the later draughtsmanship. Essentially, then, this earlier drawing was less descriptive and more purely evocative of form. It may well be that the demands made upon the artist by the closer study of nature brought in by the Renaissance became an almost insuperable barrier to artists in the attempt to find any such completely synthetic vision of form as lay to hand for their predecessors. We see, for instance, in Albert Dürer’s “Beetle” an example of purely descriptive and analytic drawing with no attempt at inner coherence of form. On the other hand, of course, all the great formalists made deliberate efforts to come through the complex of phenomena to some abstract synthesis. Fra Bartolomeo and Raphael clearly made such abstraction a matter of deliberate study,[51] but as I have pointed out in the case of Ingres, the{165}
As most drawing has focused on the human figure, we can describe it in relation to that aspect, especially since this perspective on drawing definitely emerged with the study of anatomy. The basic principle is that there are key facts about the figure or crucial points in representing its structure—the artist is trained to observe these carefully, as they become the points de repère for the drawing. Because they are observed in this way, they are highlighted more prominently. Once the artist learns to grasp the relationships between these points de repère, they also discover how to transition from one to another with great ease and speed, even with a certain casualness about the process. This method accurately captures the essentials of a figure's structure and movement, allowing for an overall representation made with that effortless flow and speed of line that is particularly satisfying. Such drawing is notable for being both structurally precise and somewhat visually pleasing. The most respected masters, like Vandyke, Watteau, and even to some degree Rubens, all display the traits of this approach. In earlier types of drawing, there were no recognized points de repère or specific moments of emphasis; instead, the line was drawn in such a way that at every point its relationship to the opposing contour was equally tight, with tension consistently running across the line rather than along its direction. The key aspect was the position of the line, not its quality, leading to less of an inclination toward the easy speed that characterizes later drawing styles. Essentially, this earlier form of drawing was less about description and more about pure evocation of form. It is possible that the requirements imposed on artists by the closer study of nature during the Renaissance became nearly insurmountable obstacles for them in finding a completely synthetic vision of form like their predecessors had. For example, in Albert Dürer’s “Beetle,” we see an instance of purely descriptive and analytic drawing without any attempt at internal coherence of form. Conversely, all the prominent formalists intentionally sought to navigate through the complexities of phenomena to achieve some abstract synthesis. Fra Bartolomeo and Raphael clearly made this abstraction a focus of their studies,[51] but as I have mentioned in the case of Ingres, the{165}
obsession of fact has generally forced the artist to such a long series of experiments towards the final synthetic form that it is only in the finished picture that it emerges fully.
The obsession with accuracy has usually pushed the artist to go through a lengthy series of experiments before arriving at the final form, so it is only in the completed work that it fully comes to light.
On the other hand, some modern masters have also found their way through, more or less completely, and from this point of view few drawings in the exhibition are as remarkable as the drawing of a seated woman by Corot (see Plate). Here one supposes it may be a kind of naïveté of vision rather than the exhaustive process of an Ingres, that has led Corot to this vividly realised plasticity of form. I find the essentials of good drawing more completely realised here than in almost any other drawing in the exhibition, and yet how little of a professional draughtsman Corot was. It is hard to speak here of Degas’s works as drawings. With one exception they are pastels and essentially paintings, but they are of great beauty and show him victorious over his own formidable cleverness, his unrivalled but dangerous power of witty notation.
On the other hand, some modern masters have managed to navigate their way through, more or less completely, and from this perspective, few drawings in the exhibition are as striking as the drawing of a seated woman by Corot (see Plate). Here, one might assume it’s a kind of naïveté of vision rather than the thorough process of an Ingres that has led Corot to this vividly realized plasticity of form. I find the essentials of good drawing more fully expressed here than in almost any other piece in the exhibition, and yet how little of a professional draughtsman Corot was. It’s difficult to classify Degas’s works as drawings. With one exception, they are pastels and essentially paintings, but they are incredibly beautiful and demonstrate his triumph over his own formidable cleverness, his unmatched yet risky ability for witty notation.
At the opposite pole to Corot’s drawing with its splendid revelation of plastic significance we must put Menzel with his fussy preoccupation with undigested fact. It is hard indeed to see quite how Menzel’s drawings found their way into this good company, except perhaps as drunken helots, for they are conspicuously devoid of any æsthetic quality whatever. They are without any rhythmic unity, without any glimmering of a sense of style, and style though it be as cheap as Rowlandson’s is still victorious over sheer misinformed literalness. Somewhere between Menzel and Corot we must place Charles Keane, and I fear, in spite of the rather exaggerated claims made for him in the preface, he is nearer to Menzel, though even so, how much better! The early Millais drawing is of course an astounding attempt by a man of prodigious gift and no sensibility to pretend that he had the latter. It is a pity there are no Rossettis here to show the authentic inspiration of which this is the echo.
At the opposite end from Corot’s drawing, which beautifully reveals the significance of form, we have Menzel, who focuses on a clutter of unprocessed details. It’s hard to see how Menzel’s drawings ended up in this esteemed group, except maybe as unwelcome guests, because they completely lack any aesthetic quality. There’s no sense of rhythm or hint of style—although even Rowlandson’s cheap style is an improvement over Menzel’s confusing literalness. We should place Charles Keane somewhere between Menzel and Corot, and despite the somewhat over-the-top praise given to him in the preface, he leans closer to Menzel, though still far better! The early drawing by Millais is an impressive attempt by a remarkably talented man with no sensitivity, trying to fake having it. It’s unfortunate that there are no Rossettis here to showcase the genuine inspiration that this merely echoes.
I come now to the Rembrandts, of which there are several good examples. Rembrandt always intrigues one by the multiplicity and diversity of his gifts and the struggle between his profound imaginative insight and his excessive talents. The fact is, I believe that Rembrandt was never a linealist, that he never had the conception of contour clearly present to him. He was too intensely and too inveterately{166} a painter and a chiaroscurist. The last thing he saw was a contour, and more than anything else it eluded his vision. His vision was in fact so intensely fixed on the interplay of planes, their modulation into one another, and on the balance of directions, that with him the drawn line has a quite peculiar and personal meaning. It is used first to indicate directions of stress and movement, as, for instance, a straight line will be dashed down to indicate, not the contour of a limb, but its direction, the line along which stress of action takes place. He seems almost to dread the contour, to prefer to make strokes either inside or outside of it, and to trust to the imagination to discover its whereabouts, anything rather than a final definite statement which would arrest the interplay of planes. The line is also used to suggest very vaguely and tentatively the division of planes; but almost always when he comes to use wash on top of the line his washes go across the lines, so that here too one can hardly say the line indicates the division so much as the approximate position of a plane.
I now turn to the Rembrandts, of which there are several great examples. Rembrandt always captivates with the variety and richness of his skills and the tension between his deep imaginative insight and his overwhelming talents. I believe Rembrandt was never a strict line artist; he never had a clear concept of contour in his mind. He was too passionately and deeply a painter and a master of light and shadow. The last thing he focused on was a contour, and more than anything else, it evaded his view. His vision was so intensely directed at the interaction of planes, their blending into one another, and the balance of directions that, for him, the drawn line takes on a unique and personal significance. It's used mainly to indicate directions of emphasis and movement; for example, a straight line is often dashed down to show not the outline of a limb, but its direction, the path along which the action occurs. He almost seems to avoid the contour, preferring to make strokes either inside or outside of it, trusting imagination to discern its location—anything rather than a final, definitive outline that would halt the interplay of planes. The line is also used to suggest very vaguely and tentatively the division of planes; but almost always, when he applies wash over the line, the washes go across the lines, making it difficult to say that the line indicates the division as much as it shows the rough position of a plane.
In conclusion I would suggest that, the art of pure contour is comparatively rare in modern art. For what I should cite as great and convincing examples of that art I would ask the reader to turn to the “Morgan Byzantine Enamels” (Burlington Magazine, vol. xxi. pp. 3, 65, 127, 219, 290), the “Manafi-i-Heiwan” (Burlington Magazine, vol. xxiii. pp. 224, 261), and to Vignier, “Persian Pottery” (Burlington Magazine, vol. xxv. p. 211), while other examples might be found among Byzantine and Carolingian miniaturists.
In conclusion, I would suggest that the art of pure contour is relatively rare in modern art. For great and convincing examples of this art, I would ask the reader to look at the “Morgan Byzantine Enamels” (Burlington Magazine, vol. xxi. pp. 3, 65, 127, 219, 290), the “Manafi-i-Heiwan” (Burlington Magazine, vol. xxiii. pp. 224, 261), and Vignier, “Persian Pottery” (Burlington Magazine, vol. xxv. p. 211), while more examples can be found among Byzantine and Carolingian miniaturists.
Now, this art depends upon a peculiarly synthetic vision and a peculiar system of distortion, without which the outline would arrest the movement of planes too definitely. There indeed is the whole crux of the art of line drawing; the line generates a volume, but it also arrests the planes too definitely: that is why in some great modern artists, as we saw in the case of Rembrandt, there is a peculiar kind of dread of the actual contour. It is felt by those who are sensitive to the interplay and movement of planes that the line must in some way, by its quality or its position, or by breaks or repetitions, avoid arresting the imagination by too positive a statement. It was almost a peculiarity of the early art that I have cited that it was able to express a form in a quite complete, evenly drawn contour without this terrible negative effect of the line. I say almost a peculiarity, because I think{167}
Now, this art relies on a unique synthetic vision and a specific way of distorting shapes, without which the outline would stop the movement of planes too clearly. This is the main challenge of line drawing; the line creates volume, but it also pins down the planes too clearly. That's why some great modern artists, like Rembrandt, seem to have a particular fear of the actual contour. Those who are sensitive to the interplay and movement of planes feel that the line must, in some way—through its quality, position, or by using breaks or repetitions—prevent the imagination from being limited by too direct of a statement. It was almost a unique feature of the early art I've mentioned, as it could express a form with a complete, evenly drawn contour without the negative impact of the line. I say almost a unique feature because I think{167}
a few quite modern artists, such as Matisse (see Plate) and perhaps Modigliani, have recovered such a power, but in the great mass of post Renaissance drawing the art of the pure contour in line has broken down, and the essential qualities even of the great linealists are only to be seen fully in their paintings; the drawn line itself has had to take on other functions.{168}
A few modern artists, like Matisse (see Plate) and maybe Modigliani, have regained that kind of power, but in the vast majority of post-Renaissance drawings, the art of pure contour line has fallen apart, and the key qualities of even the great line artists can only be fully appreciated in their paintings; the drawn line itself has had to adopt other roles.{168}
PAUL CÉZANNE[52]
IN a society which is as indifferent to works of art as our modern industrialism it seems paradoxical that artists of all kinds should loom so large in the general consciousness of mankind—that they should be remembered with reverence and boasted of as national assets when statesmen, lawyers, and soldiers are forgotten. The great mass of modern men could rub along happily enough without works of art or at least without new ones, but society would be sensibly more bored if the artist died out altogether. The fact is that every honest bourgeois, however sedate and correct his life, keeps a hidden and scarce-admitted yearning for that other life of complete individualism which hard necessity or the desire for success has denied him. In contemplating the artist he tastes vicariously these forbidden joys. He regards the artist as a strange species, half idiot, half divine, but above all irresponsibly and irredeemably himself. He seems equally strange in his outrageous egoism and his superb devotion to an idea.
IN a society that is as indifferent to art as our modern industrial world, it's paradoxical that artists of all kinds play such a significant role in the collective consciousness of humanity—that they are remembered with respect and celebrated as national treasures while statesmen, lawyers, and soldiers are quickly forgotten. Most people today could get by just fine without art, or at least without new creations, but society would be noticeably more dull if artists were to completely disappear. The truth is that every average person, no matter how composed and proper their life may seem, harbors a hidden and rarely acknowledged desire for a life of pure individuality that necessity or the pursuit of success has kept from them. By observing the artist, they experience, through vicarious means, the joys that are otherwise off-limits. They see the artist as a peculiar creature, part fool, part divine, but mostly just unapologetically themselves. This uniqueness is evident in their extreme egoism and their remarkable dedication to an idea.
Also in a world where the individual is squeezed and moulded and polished by the pressure of his fellow-men the artist remains irreclaimably individual—in a world where every one else is being perpetually educated the artist remains ineducable—where others are shaped he grows. Cézanne realised the type of the artist in its purest most unmitigated form, and M. Vollard has had the wit to write a book about Cézanne and not about Cézanne’s pictures. The time may come when we shall require a complete study of Cézanne’s work, a measured judgment of his achievement and position—it would probably be rash to attempt it as yet. Meanwhile we have M. Vollard’s portrait, at once documented and captivating. Should the book ever become as well known as it deserves there would be, one guesses,{169}
Also, in a world where individuals are shaped and polished by the influence of others, the artist remains undeniably unique—in a world where everyone else is constantly being educated, the artist remains unteachable—where others are formed, he grows. Cézanne epitomized the artist in its purest and most unfiltered form, and M. Vollard had the insight to write a book about Cézanne rather than just about his paintings. There may come a time when we will need a comprehensive study of Cézanne’s work, a careful evaluation of his accomplishments and his status—it might be premature to attempt that now. In the meantime, we have M. Vollard’s portrait, which is both informative and fascinating. If this book ever becomes as recognized as it deserves to be, one might guess,{169}
ten people fascinated by Cézanne for one who would walk down the street to see his pictures.
ten people fascinated by Cézanne for every one who would walk down the street to see his paintings.
The art historian may sometimes regret that Vasari did not give us more of the æsthetics of his time; but Vasari knew his business, knew, perhaps, that the æsthetics of an age are quickly superseded but that the human document remains of perennial interest to mankind. M. Vollard has played Vasari to Cézanne and done so with the same directness and simplicity, the same narrative ease, the same insatiable delight in the oddities and idiosyncrasies of his subject. And what a model he had to paint! Every word and every gesture he records stick out with the rugged relief of a character in which everything is due to the compulsion of inner forces, in which nothing has been planed down or smoothed away by external pressure—not that external pressure was absent but that the inner compulsion—the inevitable bent of Cézanne’s temperament, was irresistible. In one very important detail Cézanne was spared by life—he always had enough to live on. The thought of a Cézanne having to earn his living is altogether too tragic. But if life spared him in this respect his temperament spared him nothing—for this rough Provençal countryman had so exasperated a sensibility that the smallest detail of daily life, the barking of a dog, the noise of a lift in a neighbouring house, the dread of being touched even by his own son might produce at any moment a nervous explosion. At such times his first relief was in cursing and swearing, but if this failed the chances were that his anger vented itself on his pictures—he would cut one to pieces with his palette knife, or failing that roll it up and throw it into the stove. M. Vollard describes with delightful humour the tortures he endured in the innumerable sittings which he gave Cézanne for his portrait—with what care he avoided any subject of conversation which might lead to misunderstanding. But with all his adroitness there were one or two crises in which the portrait was threatened with the dreaded knife—fortunately Cézanne always found some other work on which to vent his indignation, and the portrait survived, though after a hundred and fifteen sittings, in which Cézanne exacted the immobility of an apple, the portrait was left incomplete. “I am not displeased with the shirt front,” was Cézanne’s characteristic appreciation.
The art historian might sometimes wish that Vasari had shared more about the aesthetics of his time, but Vasari understood his craft. He probably realized that the aesthetics of an era can quickly be replaced, while the human story remains endlessly fascinating to people. M. Vollard has taken on the role of Vasari for Cézanne, doing so with the same straightforwardness and simplicity, the same narrative fluency, and the same insatiable joy in the quirks and uniqueness of his subject. And what a subject he had! Every word and gesture he documented stands out with the vividness of a character driven by deep internal forces, with nothing smoothed down or polished by external pressures—though those pressures existed, it was the inner drive—Cézanne's natural temperament—that was overwhelming. In one significant way, life was kind to Cézanne—he always had enough to live on. The idea of a Cézanne struggling to make ends meet is just too tragic. However, while life spared him in this aspect, his temperament offered no such kindness—this rough Provençal had such a delicate sensibility that the slightest details of everyday life, like a dog's bark or the noise from an elevator in a nearby building, or even the fear of being touched by his own son, could trigger a nervous outburst. During those times, he often turned to cursing and swearing for relief, but if that didn’t work, it was likely that his anger would spill over onto his artwork—he might slash a painting with his palette knife or, if that failed, roll it up and toss it in the stove. M. Vollard humorously recounts the struggles he faced during the countless sittings for Cézanne’s portrait, carefully avoiding any topics that might lead to misunderstandings. But despite his skill, there were still a couple of moments when the portrait seemed at risk of the feared knife—luckily, Cézanne always managed to find another piece of work to unleash his frustration on, and the portrait survived, though after one hundred and fifteen sittings, during which Cézanne demanded the stillness of an apple, the portrait was left unfinished. “I’m not unhappy with the shirt front,” was Cézanne's typical comment.
Two phrases continually recur in Cézanne’s conversation which{170} show his curious idiosyncrasies. One the often-quoted one of his dread that any one might “lui jeter le grappin dessus” and the other “moi qui suis faible dans la vie.” They express his constant attitude of distrust of his kind—for him all women were “des veaux et des calculatrices”—his dread of any possible invasion of his personality, and his sense of impotence in face of the forces of life.
Two phrases keep coming up in Cézanne’s conversations that reveal his unique quirks. One is the often-repeated fear that someone might “lui jeter le grappin dessus” and the other is “moi qui suis faible dans la vie.” These phrases show his ongoing distrust of people—he viewed all women as “des veaux et des calculatrices”—his fear of anyone encroaching on his personality, and his feeling of helplessness in the face of life's challenges.
None the less, though he pathetically exaggerated his weakness he never seems to have had the least doubt about his supreme greatness as an artist; what troubled and irritated him was his incapacity to express his “sensation” in such terms as would make its meaning evident to the world. It was for this reason that he struggled so obstinately and hopelessly to get into the “Salon de M. Bougereau.” His attitude to conventional art was a strange mixture of admiration at its skill and of an overwhelming horror of its emptiness—of its so “horrible resemblance.”
Nevertheless, even though he dramatically overstated his weakness, he never seemed to doubt his greatness as an artist; what bothered and frustrated him was his inability to express his “sensation” in a way that would make its meaning clear to others. This is why he fought so stubbornly and seemingly hopelessly to get into the "Salon de M. Bougereau." His feelings about conventional art were a strange mix of admiration for its skill and a deep horror at its emptiness—its so-called “horrible resemblance.”
The fact is that Cézanne had accepted uncritically all the conventions in the pathetic belief that it was the only way of safety for one “so feeble in life.” So he continued to believe in the Catholic Church not from any religious conviction but because “Rome was so strong”—so, too, he believed in the power and importance of the “Salon de Bougereau” which he hated as much as he feared. So, too, with what seems a paradoxical humility he let it be known, when his fame had already been established among the intelligent, that he would be glad to have the Legion of Honour. But here, too, he was destined to fail. The weighty influence and distinguished position of his friends could avail nothing against the undisguised horror with which any official heard the dreaded name of Cézanne. And it appeared that Cézanne was the only artist in France for whom this distinction was inaccessible, even through “influence.” Nothing is stranger in his life than the contrast between the idea the public formed of Cézanne and the reality. He was one of those men destined to give rise to a legend which completely obscured the reality. He was spoken of as the most violent of revolutionaries—Communard and Anarchist were the favourite epithets—and all the time he was a timid little country gentleman of immaculate respectability who subscribed whole-heartedly to any reactionary opinion which could establish his “soundness.” He was a timid man who really believed{171}
The reality is that Cézanne accepted all the conventions without question, holding onto the mistaken belief that it was the only safe way for someone "so weak in life." He continued to believe in the Catholic Church not because of any genuine religious faith, but simply because "Rome was so powerful." Likewise, he believed in the significance of the "Salon de Bougereau," which he both hated and feared. In what seems like a contradictory humility, he made it known, after his fame had already been secured among the educated, that he would be pleased to receive the Legion of Honour. But once again, he faced disappointment. The considerable influence and esteemed status of his friends did nothing to counter the outright dread any official felt at the mere mention of Cézanne's name. It turned out that Cézanne was the only artist in France for whom this honor was unattainable, even with "influence." Nothing is stranger in his life than the gap between the public's perception of Cézanne and the truth. He was someone destined to create a legend that completely overshadowed reality. People described him as the most extreme revolutionary—Communard and Anarchist were favorite labels—and yet, he was actually a timid little country gentleman of perfect respectability who wholeheartedly embraced any conservative view that could prove his "soundness." He was a timid man who truly believed{171}
in only one thing, “his little sensation”; who laboured incessantly to express this peculiar quality and who had not the faintest notion of doing anything that could shock the feelings of any mortal man or woman. No wonder then that when he looked up from his work and surveyed the world with his troubled and imperfect intellectual vision he was amazed and perturbed at the violent antagonism which he had all unconsciously provoked. No wonder that he became a shy, distrustful misanthrope, almost incapable of any association with his kind.
in only one thing, “his little sensation”; who worked tirelessly to express this unique quality and who had no concept of doing anything that could upset the feelings of anyone. It’s no surprise then that when he looked up from his work and took in the world with his troubled and limited understanding, he was surprised and disturbed by the intense hostility he had unknowingly caused. It’s no wonder he became a shy, distrustful recluse, almost unable to connect with others.
I have suggested that Cézanne was the perfect realisation of the type of the artist—I doubt whether in the whole of Vasari’s great picture gallery there is a more complete type of “original.” But in order to accept this we must banish from our mind the conventional idea of the artist as a man of flamboyant habits and calculated pose. Nothing is less possible to the real artist than pose—he is less capable of it than the ordinary man of business because more than any one else his external activities are determined from within by needs and instincts which he himself barely recognises.
I’ve suggested that Cézanne perfectly embodies the ideal artist—I doubt there’s a more complete example of an “original” in all of Vasari’s extensive collection. To accept this, we need to let go of the traditional image of the artist as someone with flashy habits and a carefully crafted persona. Nothing is less suitable for a true artist than posing—he’s even less capable of it than the average businessperson because, more than anyone else, his external actions are driven by internal needs and instincts that he himself only partially understands.
On the other hand the imitation artist is a past master of pose, he poses as the sport of natural inclinations whilst he is really deliberately exploiting his caprices; and as he has a natural instinct for the limelight this variety of the “Cabotin” generally manages to sit for the portrait of the artist. Cézanne, then, though his external life was that of the most irreproachable of country gentlemen, though he went to mass every Sunday and never willingly left the intimacy of family life, was none the less the purest and most unadulterated of artists, the most narrowly confined to his single activity, the most purely disinterested and the most frankly egoistic of men.
On the other hand, the imitation artist is a skilled master of posing; he pretends to act based on natural instincts while actually exploiting his whims. With a natural knack for being in the spotlight, this type of “show-off” often manages to pose for an artist’s portrait. Cézanne, while leading the life of an upstanding country gentleman—attending mass every Sunday and cherishing family life—was nonetheless the most genuine and unfiltered artist. He was completely focused on his craft, utterly selfless in his art, and also the most openly self-centered person.
Cézanne had no intellectual independence. I doubt if he had the faintest conception of intellectual truth, but this is not to deny that he had a powerful mind. On the contrary he had a profound intelligence of whatever came within his narrow outlook on life, and above all he had the gift of expression, so that however fantastic, absurd, or naïve his opinions may have been, they were always expressed in such racy and picturesque language that they become interesting as revelations of a very human and genuine personality.{172}
Cézanne lacked intellectual independence. I'm not sure he had the slightest idea of intellectual truth, but that doesn't mean he didn't have a strong mind. In fact, he displayed a deep intelligence regarding everything that fell within his limited perspective on life, and most importantly, he had a remarkable gift for expression. So, no matter how fantastical, absurd, or naive his opinions might have been, they were always articulated in such colorful and vivid language that they became fascinating insights into a very human and authentic personality.{172}
One of the tragi-comedies of Cézanne’s life was the story of his early friendship with Zola, followed in middle life by a gradual estrangement, and at last a total separation. It is perhaps the only blot in M. Vollard’s book that he has taken too absolutely Cézanne’s point of view, and has hardly done justice to Zola’s goodness of heart. The cause of friction, apart from Cézanne’s habitual testiness and ill-humour, was that Zola’s feeling for art, which had led him in his youth to a heroic championship of the younger men, faded away in middle life. His own practice of literature led him further and further away from any concern with pure art, and he failed to recognise that his own early prophecy of Cézanne’s greatness had come true, simply because he himself had become a popular author, and Cézanne had failed of any kind of success. Unfortunately Zola, who had evidently lost all real æsthetic feeling, continued to talk about art, and worse than that he had made the hero of “L’Œuvre” a more or less recognisable portrait of his old friend. Cézanne could not tolerate Zola’s gradual acquiescence in worldly ideals and ways of life, and when the Dreyfusard question came up not only did his natural reactionary bias make him a vehement anti-Dreyfusard but he had no comprehension whatever of the heroism of Zola’s actions; he found him merely ridiculous, and believed him to be engaged in an ill-conceived scheme of self-advertisement. But for all his contempt of Zola his affection remained deeper than he knew, and when he heard the news of Zola’s death Cézanne shut himself alone up in his studio, and was heard sobbing and groaning throughout the day.
One of the tragic-comedies of Cézanne’s life was his early friendship with Zola, which gradually faded into estrangement and ultimately ended in complete separation. It's possibly the only flaw in M. Vollard’s book that he has taken Cézanne’s perspective too strongly and hasn’t done justice to Zola’s kindness. The source of their conflict, aside from Cézanne’s usual irritability and bad mood, was that Zola’s passion for art, which had driven him to champion younger artists in his youth, diminished as he grew older. His focus on literature took him further away from genuine art, and he failed to see that his early prediction of Cézanne’s greatness had come true, simply because Zola became a popular author while Cézanne struggled to find any success. Unfortunately, Zola, who clearly lost his genuine artistic feeling, continued to discuss art, and even worse, he portrayed his old friend as the protagonist in “L’Œuvre.” Cézanne couldn’t accept Zola’s gradual acceptance of worldly ideals and lifestyles, and when the Dreyfus Affair arose, not only did his natural conservative bias make him a strong anti-Dreyfusard, but he also couldn’t grasp the heroism in Zola’s actions; he found Zola merely ridiculous and thought he was pursuing a misguided plan for self-promotion. Yet, despite his disdain for Zola, his affection ran deeper than he realized, and when he learned about Zola’s death, Cézanne isolated himself in his studio and was heard sobbing and groaning throughout the day.
Cézanne’s is not the only portrait in M. Vollard’s entertaining book—there are sketches of many characters, among them the few strange and sympathetic men who appreciated and encouraged Cézanne in his early days. Of Cabaner the musician M. Vollard has collected some charming notes. Cabaner was a “philosopher,” and singularly indifferent to the chances of life. During the siege of Paris he met Coppée, and noticing the shells which were falling he became curious. “Where do all these bullets come from?” Coppée: “It would seem that it is the besiegers who send them.” Cabaner, after a silence: “Is it always the Prussians?” Coppée, impatiently: “Who on earth could it be?” Cabaner: “I don’t know ... other nations!” But the book is so full of good stories that I must resist the temptation to quote.{173}
Cézanne isn’t the only portrait in M. Vollard’s entertaining book—there are sketches of many figures, including a few unusual and likable men who appreciated and supported Cézanne in his early days. M. Vollard has gathered some delightful notes about Cabaner the musician. Cabaner was a “philosopher” and remarkably uninterested in life’s uncertainties. During the siege of Paris, he encountered Coppée and, noticing the falling shells, he became curious. “Where do all these bullets come from?” Coppée replied, “It seems like it’s the besiegers sending them.” After a pause, Cabaner asked, “Is it always the Prussians?” Coppée, a bit impatient, responded, “Who else could it possibly be?” Cabaner said, “I don’t know...other nations!” But the book is so filled with great stories that I have to resist the urge to quote.{173}
Fortunately M. Vollard has collected also a large number of Cézanne’s obiter dicta on art. These have all Cézanne’s pregnant wisdom and racy style. They often contain a whole system of æsthetics in a single phrase, as, for instance: “What’s wanted is to do Poussin over again from Nature.”
Fortunately, M. Vollard has gathered a significant collection of Cézanne's obiter dicta on art. These reflect all of Cézanne's profound insights and vibrant style. They often encapsulate an entire system of aesthetics in just one phrase, such as: “What’s needed is to reinterpret Poussin from Nature.”
They show, moreover, the natural bias of Cézanne’s feelings and their gradual modification as his understanding became more profound. What comes out clearly, and it must never be forgotten in considering his art, is that his point of departure was from Romanticism. Delacroix was his god and Ingres, in his early days, his devil—a devil he learned increasingly to respect, but never one imagines really to love, “ce Dominique est très fort mais il m’emm——.” That Cézanne became a supreme master of formal design every one would nowadays admit, but there is some excuse for those contemporaries who complained of his want of drawing. He was not a master of line in the sense in which Ingres was. “The contour escapes me,” as he said. That is to say he arrived at the contour by a study of the interior planes; he was always plastic before he was linear. In his early works, such, for instance, as the “Scène de plein air” (see Plate), he is evidently inspired by Delacroix; he is almost a romanticist himself in such work, and his design is built upon the contrasts of large and rather loosely drawn silhouettes of dark and light. In fact it is the method of Tintoretto, Rubens, and Delacroix.
They also reveal Cézanne’s natural feelings and how they changed as his understanding deepened. One thing that stands out, and should always be remembered when looking at his art, is that he started from Romanticism. Delacroix was his idol, and Ingres, in his early years, was like a devil to him—one he learned to respect over time, but never really loved, “ce Dominique est très fort mais il m’emm——.” It’s widely accepted today that Cézanne became a master of formal design, but we can understand why some of his contemporaries complained about his drawing skills. He wasn’t a master of line in the way Ingres was. “The contour escapes me,” he said. This means he approached contour through studying the inner planes; he always focused on form before line. In his early works, like the “Scène de plein air” (see Plate), it’s clear he was inspired by Delacroix; in fact, he was almost a romanticist in such pieces, and his designs are based on contrasts of large, loosely drawn dark and light silhouettes. Essentially, his method mirrors that of Tintoretto, Rubens, and Delacroix.
In the “Bathers resting,” painted in 1877, there is already a great change. It is rather by the exact placing of plastic units than by continuous flowing silhouettes that the design holds. Giorgione, perhaps, is behind this, but no longer Tintoretto, and, above all, Poussin has intervened.
In the “Bathers resting,” painted in 1877, there is already a big change. The design relies more on the precise arrangement of solid forms than on smoothly flowing outlines. Giorgione might be influencing this, but not Tintoretto anymore, and especially, Poussin has made an impact.
In later works, such as the portrait of “Mme. Cézanne in a greenhouse,” the plasticity has become all-important, there is no longer any suggestion of a romantic decor; all is reduced to the purest terms of structural design.
In later works, like the portrait of “Mme. Cézanne in a greenhouse,” the emphasis on form has become crucial; there’s no longer any hint of a romantic decor; everything is simplified to the most basic elements of structural design.
These notes on Cézanne’s development are prompted by the illustrations in M. Vollard’s book. These are numerous and excellent, and afford a better opportunity for a general study of Cézanne’s œuvre than any other book. In fact, when the time comes for the{174} complete appreciation of Cézanne M. Vollard’s book will be the most important document existing. It should, however, have a far wider appeal than that. I hope that after the war M. Vollard will bring out a small cheap edition[53]—it should become a classic biography. To say, as I would, that M. Vollard’s book is a monument worthy of Cézanne himself is to give it the highest praise.{175}
These notes on Cézanne’s development are inspired by the illustrations in M. Vollard’s book. There are many of them, and they are excellent, providing a better chance to study Cézanne’s œuvre than any other book. In fact, when the time comes for a complete appreciation of Cézanne, M. Vollard’s book will be the most important document available. However, it should appeal to a much broader audience than that. I hope that after the war, M. Vollard will release a small, affordable edition[53]—it should become a classic biography. To say, as I would, that M. Vollard’s book is a monument worthy of Cézanne himself is to give it the highest praise.{175}
RENOIR
WHAT a lover of the commonplace Renoir was! It is a rare quality among artists. A theoretically pure artist exists no more than a Euclidean point, but if such a being could exist, every possible actual sight would be equally suitable as a point of departure for his artistic vision. Everything would stir in him the impulse to creation. He would have no predilections, no tastes for this or that kind of thing. In practice every artist is set going by some particular kind of scene in nature, and for the most part artists have to search out some unusual or unexplored aspect of things. Gauguin, for instance, had to go as far as Tahiti. When Renoir heard of this, he said, in a phrase which revealed his own character: “Pourquoi? On peint si bien a Batignolles.” But there are plenty of artists who paint more or less well at Batignolles or Bloomsbury and yet are not lovers of the commonplace. Like Walter Sickert, for instance, they find their Tahiti in Mornington Crescent. Though they paint in commonplace surroundings, they generally contrive to catch them at an unexpected angle. Something odd or exotic in their taste for life seems to be normal to artists. The few artists or writers who have shared the tastes of the average man have, as a rule, been like Dickens—to take an obvious case—very imperfect and very impure artists, however great their genius. Among great artists one thinks at once of Rubens as the most remarkable example of a man of common tastes, a lover of all that was rich, exuberant and even florid. Titian, too, comes nearly up to the same standard, except that in youth his whole trend of feeling was distorted by the overpowering influence of Giorgione, whose tastes were recondite and strange. Renoir, in the frankness of his colour harmonies, in his feeling for design and even in the quality of his pigment, constantly reminds us of these two. Now it is easier to see how an artist of the sixteenth or seventeenth century could develop commonplace tastes{176} than one of our own times. For with the nineteenth century came in a gradual process of differentiation of the artist from the average man. The modern artist finds himself so little understood by the crowd, in his aims and methods, that he tends to become distinct in his whole attitude to life.
WHAT a lover of the everyday Renoir was! It's a rare trait among artists. A theoretically pure artist exists no more than a geometric point, but if such a being could exist, every possible actual sight would be just as good a starting point for his artistic vision. Everything would spark in him the urge to create. He wouldn’t have preferences or tastes for this or that kind of thing. In reality, every artist is driven by a specific kind of scene in nature, and most artists need to seek out some unusual or unexplored aspect of things. Gauguin, for example, traveled all the way to Tahiti. When Renoir heard about this, he said, in a phrase that revealed his own character: “Why? You paint so well in Batignolles.” But there are plenty of artists who paint reasonably well in Batignolles or Bloomsbury, yet they aren’t lovers of the everyday. Like Walter Sickert, for instance, they find their Tahiti in Mornington Crescent. Even though they paint in ordinary settings, they typically manage to capture them from an unexpected angle. Something unusual or exotic in their approach to life seems to be standard for artists. The few artists or writers who have shared the tastes of the average person are usually, like Dickens—an obvious example—very imperfect and mixed artists, no matter how great their talent. Among great artists, one immediately thinks of Rubens as the most notable example of a person with common tastes, a lover of everything rich, exuberant, and even flamboyant. Titian also comes close to the same standard, except that in his youth, his feelings were heavily influenced by Giorgione, whose tastes were obscure and peculiar. Renoir, in the honesty of his color harmonies, his sense of design, and even in the quality of his paint, constantly reminds us of these two. Now it’s easier to see how an artist from the sixteenth or seventeenth century could develop everyday tastes{176} than one from our own time. With the nineteenth century came a gradual process of differentiation between the artist and the average person. The modern artist finds himself so little understood by the crowd, in his goals and methods, that he tends to stand apart in his entire attitude toward life.
What, then, is so peculiar about Renoir is that he has this perfectly ordinary taste in things and yet remains so intensely, so purely, an artist. The fact is perhaps that he was so much an artist that he never had to go round the corner to get his inspiration; the immediate, obvious, front view of everything was more than sufficient to start the creative impulse. He enjoyed instinctively, almost animally, all the common good things of life, and yet he always kept just enough detachment to feel his delight æsthetically—he kept, as it were, just out of reach of appetite.
What’s strange about Renoir is that he has this perfectly ordinary taste in things, yet he remains such an intensely and purely artistic person. The truth is, he was so much of an artist that he never needed to look beyond what was right in front of him for inspiration; the immediate and obvious view of everything was more than enough to spark his creativity. He instinctively enjoyed, almost in a primal way, all the simple pleasures in life, but he always maintained enough distance to appreciate his joy aesthetically—he kept, in a sense, just out of reach of craving.
More than any other great modern artist Renoir trusted implicitly to his own sensibility; he imposed no barrier between his own delight in certain things and the delight which he communicates. He liked passionately the obviously good things of life, the young human animal, sunshine, sky, trees, water, fruit; the things that every one likes; only he liked them at just the right distance with just enough detachment to replace appetite by emotion. He could rely on this detachment so thoroughly that he could dare, what hardly any other genuine modern has dared to say how much he liked even a pretty sight. But what gives his art so immediate, so universal an appeal is that his detachment went no further than was just necessary. His sensibility is kept at the exact point where it is transmuted into emotion. And the emotion, though it has of course the generalised æsthetic feeling, keeps something of the fulness and immediacy of the simpler attitude. Not that Renoir was either naïve or stupid. When he chose he showed that he was capable of logical construction and vigorous design. But for his own pleasure he would, as he himself said, have been satisfied to make little isolated records of his delight in the detail of a flower or a lock of hair. With the exception of “Les Parapluies” at the National Gallery we have rarely seen his more deliberate compositions in England. But in all his work alike Renoir remains the man who could trust recklessly his instinctive reaction to life.
More than any other great modern artist, Renoir completely trusted his own sensibility; he put no barrier between his delight in certain things and the joy he shared with others. He passionately loved the obvious pleasures of life: young people, sunshine, sky, trees, water, and fruit—things that everyone enjoys. He appreciated these at just the right distance, maintaining enough detachment to transform desire into emotion. He relied on this detachment so much that he could openly express how much he enjoyed even a beautiful sight, which few modern artists have dared to do. What makes his art so immediate and universally appealing is that his detachment was just enough to serve its purpose. His sensibility was precisely tuned, allowing it to be transformed into emotion. This emotion, while having a general aesthetic quality, retains the fullness and immediacy of simpler feelings. However, Renoir was neither naïve nor foolish. When he wanted to, he demonstrated his ability for logical construction and strong design. Yet, for his own enjoyment, he would, as he himself said, have been content to create small, standalone captures of his pleasure in the details of a flower or a strand of hair. Aside from “Les Parapluies” at the National Gallery, we have rarely encountered his more intentional compositions in England. But in all his work, Renoir remains the artist who could instinctively trust his reactions to life.
as it were, just out of reach of appetite—makes Renoir to me, personally, a peculiarly difficult artist. My taste for exotic artists such as Cosima Tura and his kin amounts at times to a vice. Consequently, I am sometimes in danger of not doing Renoir justice, because at the first approach to one of his pictures I miss the purely accessory delight of an unexpected attitude. The first approach to one of his pictures may indeed remind one of pictures that would be the delight of the servants’ hall, so unaffectedly simple is his acceptance of the charm of rosy-cheeked girls, of pretty posies and dappled sunlight. And yet one knows well enough that Renoir was as “artful” as one could wish. Though he had not the biting wit of a Degas, he had a peculiar love of mischievous humour; he was anything but a harmless or innocent character. All his simplicity is on the surface only. The longer one looks, the deeper does Renoir retire behind veil after veil of subtlety. And yet, compared with some modern artists, he was, after all, easy and instinctively simple. Even his plastic unity was arrived at by what seems a more natural method than, say, Cézanne’s. Whereas Cézanne undertook his indefatigable research for the perspective of the receding planes, Renoir seems to have accepted a very simple general plastic formula. Whatever Cézanne may have meant by his celebrated saying about cones and cylinders, Renoir seems to have thought the sphere and cylinder sufficient for his purpose. The figure presents itself to his eye as an arrangement of more or less hemispherical bosses and cylinders, and he appears generally to arrange the light so that the most prominent part of each boss receives the highest light. From this the planes recede by insensible gradations towards the contour, which generally remains the vaguest, least ascertained part of the modelling. Whatever lies immediately behind the contour tends to become drawn into its sphere of influence, to form an undefined recession enveloping and receiving the receding planes. As the eye passes away from the contour, new but less marked bosses form themselves and fill the background with repetitions of the general theme. The picture tends thus to take the form of a bas-relief in which the recessions are not into the profound distances of pictorial space, but only back, as it were, to the block out of which the bossed reliefs emerge, though, of course, by means of atmospheric colour the eye may interpret these recessions as distance. This is clearly in marked{178} contrast to Cézanne’s method of suggesting endless recessions of planes with the most complicated interwoven texture.
as it were, just out of reach of appetite—makes Renoir, to me, a particularly challenging artist. My interest in exotic artists like Cosima Tura and his peers sometimes feels like a weakness. Because of this, I occasionally risk not giving Renoir the credit he deserves, as the first encounter with one of his paintings lacks the simple joy of an unexpected pose. Initially, looking at one of his works might remind you of art that would please the servants, given his straightforward appreciation for the charm of rosy-cheeked girls, beautiful flowers, and dappled sunlight. Yet, it's clear that Renoir was as “artful” as anyone could want. While he might not have had Degas's sharp wit, he had a unique sense of playful humor; he certainly wasn't a harmless or naive character. All his simplicity lies solely on the surface. The longer you observe, the more Renoir retreats behind layers of complexity. However, compared to some modern artists, he was, after all, quite approachable and instinctively uncomplicated. His overall unity was achieved through what appears to be a more natural approach than, say, Cézanne’s. While Cézanne tirelessly searched for the perspective of receding planes, Renoir seemed to embrace a straightforward overall plastic formula. Whatever Cézanne meant by his famous remark about cones and cylinders, Renoir apparently thought the sphere and cylinder were enough for his needs. He sees the figure as a combination of more or less hemispherical shapes and cylinders and generally arranges the light so that the most prominent part of each shape gets the brightest light. From there, the planes gradually recede towards the outline, which usually remains the most vague and uncertain aspect of the modeling. Anything directly behind the outline tends to be drawn into its influence, creating an undefined recess that envelops and incorporates the receding planes. As your gaze moves away from the outline, new but less pronounced shapes emerge and fill the background with echoes of the main theme. Consequently, the artwork tends to resemble a bas-relief where the recessions don't plunge into the deep distances of pictorial space, but instead recede back to the block from which the raised shapes arise, even though atmospheric color can lead the eye to interpret these recessions as depth. This stands in stark{178} contrast to Cézanne’s method of suggesting endless layers of planes with an intricate, interwoven texture.
Renoir’s drawing takes on the same fundamental simplicity. An Ingres arrived at the simplified statement necessary for great design by a process of gradual elimination of all the superfluous sinuosities which his hand had recorded in the first drawing from nature. Renoir seems never to have allowed his eye to accept more than the larger elements of mass and direction. His full, rounded curves embrace the form in its most general aspect. With advancing years and continually growing science he was able, at last, to state this essential synthesis with amazing breadth and ease. He continually increased the amplitude of his forms until, in his latest nudes, the whole design is filled with a few perfectly related bosses. Like Titian’s, Renoir’s power of design increased visibly up to the very end of his life. True, he was capable at all periods of conceiving large and finely co-ordinated compositions, such as “Les Parapluies” and the “Charpentier family”; but at the end even the smallest studies have structural completeness.{179}
Renoir's drawing has the same basic simplicity. Ingres achieved a simplified idea necessary for great design by gradually removing all the unnecessary details that his hand had captured in the initial drawing from nature. Renoir seems to have focused only on the larger elements of mass and direction. His full, rounded curves encompass the form in its most general sense. With age and increasing knowledge, he was eventually able to express this essential synthesis with incredible breadth and ease. He consistently expanded the scale of his forms until, in his later nudes, the entire design is filled with a few perfectly related shapes. Like Titian, Renoir's design ability visibly improved right up to the end of his life. It's true that he was always capable of creating large, well-coordinated compositions, like “Les Parapluies” and the “Charpentier family”; however, by the end, even the smallest studies exhibited structural completeness.{179}
A POSSIBLE DOMESTIC ARCHITECTURE[54]
HOUSES are either builders’ houses or architects’ houses. Not that speculative builders do not employ architects, but they generally employ architects who efface themselves behind the deadly conventionality and bewildering fantasy of their façades. Architects’ houses are generally built to the order of a gentleman who wishes his house to have some distinctive character, to stand out from the common herd of houses, either by its greater splendour or its greater discretion. The builder’s house, like the dresses of the lower middle class, is generally an imitation of the gentleman’s, only of a fashion that has just gone out of date and imitated badly in cheaper materials. No one defends it. It is made so because you must make a house somehow, and bought because it is the usual and therefore inevitable thing. No one enjoys it, no one admires it, it is accepted as part of the use and wont of ordinary life. The gentleman’s and architect’s house is different. Here time and thought, and perhaps great ingenuity and taste are employed in giving to the house an individual character. Unfortunately this individual character is generally terribly conscious of its social aspect, of how the house will look, not to those who live in it so much as to those who come to visit. We have no doubt outlived the more vulgar forms of this social consciousness, those which led to the gross display of merely expensive massiveness and profusion. Few modern houses would satisfy Mr. Podsnap. But its subtler forms are still apparent. They generally make themselves felt in the desire to be romantic. As it requires much too much imagination to find romance in the present, one looks for it in the past, and so a dive is made into some period of history, and its monuments studied and copied, and finally “adapted” to the more elaborate exigencies of modern life. But, alas, these divers into the past seem never to have been able to find the pearl of romance, for, ever since the craze began in the eighteenth century, they have been diving now here, now there, now into Romanesque, now into{180} Gothic, now into Jacobean, now into Queen Anne. They have brought up innumerable architectural “features” which have been duly copied by modern machinery, and carefully glued on to the houses, and still the owners and the architects, to do them justice, feel restless, and are in search of some new old style to try. The search has flagged of late, people know it is useless, and here and there architects have set to work merely to build so well and with such a fine sense of the material employed that the result should satisfy the desire for comeliness without the use of any style. I am thinking of some of Mr. Blow’s earlier works where a peculiar charm resulted from the unstinting care with which every piece of material had been chosen and the whole fitted together almost as though the stones had been precious stones instead of flints or bricks.
HOUSES are either built by builders or designed by architects. While speculative builders do hire architects, they usually choose ones who blend into the bland conventionality and confusing fantasy of their façades. Architects’ houses are typically crafted for a client who wants their home to have a unique character that stands apart from the typical houses, whether through added elegance or understated simplicity. The builder’s house, similar to the attire of the lower middle class, usually mimics the gentleman’s style, but in a fashion that is slightly outdated and poorly executed with cheaper materials. No one defends it. It exists because a house must be built, and it’s bought just because it’s what people usually do, making it an unavoidable choice. No one enjoys it or admires it; it’s merely accepted as part of everyday life. The gentleman’s and architect’s house is different. Here, time, thought, and perhaps considerable creativity and taste are invested in giving the house a unique identity. Unfortunately, this uniqueness often becomes overly aware of its social implications, focusing more on how the house appears to visitors rather than to the residents. We have certainly moved past the more crass versions of this social awareness that led to the ostentatious display of merely expensive bulk and abundance. Few modern homes would meet Mr. Podsnap's approval. But the subtler forms of this awareness still linger. They often reveal themselves in the desire to be romantic. Since it takes too much creativity to find romance in the present, people look to the past, diving into different historical periods, studying and copying their monuments, and then “adapting” them to fit the more complex demands of modern life. Unfortunately, these nostalgic searches for romance have yet to yield satisfactory results, as ever since the trend started in the eighteenth century, they’ve been diving from one style to another, one moment into Romanesque, then into {180} Gothic, then into Jacobean, and finally into Queen Anne. They’ve brought back countless architectural “features” that have been mechanically reproduced and carefully attached to houses, yet the owners and architects, to their credit, remain restless and continue seeking a new old style to experiment with. Recent efforts have slowed; people realize it’s futile. Here and there, architects are simply working to build so effectively and with such a keen sense of the materials used that the outcome satisfies the desire for beauty without adhering to any specific style. I’m thinking of some of Mr. Blow’s earlier works, where a unique charm was achieved through the meticulous selection of every material, fitting them together as if the stones were precious gems rather than flints or bricks.
But on the whole the problem appears to be still unsolved, and the architects go on using styles of various kinds with greater or less degrees of correctness. This they no longer do with the old zest and hope of discovery, but rather with a languid indifference and with evident marks of discouragement.
But overall, the problem still seems unsolved, and architects continue to use various styles with different levels of accuracy. They no longer approach this with the same excitement and hope of discovery but rather with a tired indifference and clear signs of discouragement.
Now style is an admirable thing, it is the result of ease and coherence of feeling, but unfortunately a borrowed style is an even stronger proof of muddled and befogged emotions than the total absence of style. The desire for a style at all costs, even a borrowed style, is part of that exaggerated social consciousness which in other respects manifests itself as snobbery. What if people were just to let their houses be the direct outcome of their actual needs, and of their actual way of life, and allow other people to think what they like. What if they behaved in the matter of houses as all people wish to behave in society without any undue or fussy self-consciousness. Wouldn’t such houses have really a great deal more character, and therefore interest for others, than those which are deliberately made to look like something or other. Instead of looking like something, they would then be something.
Style is a great thing; it's the result of feeling relaxed and coherent. But sadly, a borrowed style often shows even more confusion and mixed emotions than having no style at all. The need for a style at any cost, even if it's borrowed, comes from an exaggerated social awareness that also shows up as snobbery. What if people just let their homes be a true reflection of their genuine needs and lifestyle, and allowed others to think what they want? What if they approached their homes the way they want to act in society, without being overly self-conscious? Wouldn’t those homes have a lot more character and, therefore, be more interesting to others than ones that are purposely designed to look like something else? Instead of trying to appear like something, they could simply be something.
The house which I planned and built for myself was the result of certain particular needs and habits. I had originally no idea of building a house: I had so often heard the proverb that “Fools build houses for wise men to live in,” that I had come to believe it, but I required a house of a certain size for my family within{181} easy reach of London. I looked at a great many houses and found that those which had a sufficient number of rooms were all gentlemen’s establishments, with lodge, stabling, and green-houses. Now it was characteristic of my purse that I could not afford to keep up a gentleman’s establishment and of my tastes that I could not endure to. I was a town dweller, and I wanted a town house and a little garden in the country. As I could not find what I wanted, the idea came into my head that I must build it or go without. The means at my disposal were definitely limited; the question was therefore whether I could build a house of the required size with that sum. I made a plan containing the number of rooms of the sizes I required, and got an estimate. It was largely in excess of the sum I possessed for the purpose. I feared I must give up my scheme when I met a friend who had experimented in building cheap cottages on his estate, and learned from him that the secret of economy was concentration of plan. I also discovered in discussing my first estimate that roofs were cheaper than walls. I thereupon started on a quite different plan, in which I arranged the rooms to form as nearly as possible a solid block, and placed a number of the rooms in a hipped or Mansard roof. It will be seen that, so far, the planning of the house was merely the discovery of a possible equation between my needs and the sum at my disposal.
The house I designed and built for myself came from specific needs and habits. Initially, I had no intention of building a house; I had heard the saying "Fools build houses for wise men to live in" so many times that I started to believe it. However, I needed a house of a certain size for my family, easily accessible from London. I looked at many houses and found that those with enough rooms were all grand estates, complete with lodgings, stables, and greenhouses. Unfortunately, my budget couldn't support maintaining a grand estate, and I couldn't stand the thought of it either. I was a city person and wanted a city home with a small garden in the countryside. Since I couldn't find what I was looking for, I realized I'd have to build it myself or go without. My funds were limited, so the challenge was whether I could construct a house of the right size within that budget. I created a plan with the number of rooms I needed and sought an estimate, but it was far beyond what I had available. Just as I was about to abandon my plans, I met a friend who had tried building affordable cottages on his property, and he told me the key to saving money was focusing the design. I also learned that roofs were cheaper than walls while discussing my first estimate. This led me to create a new plan, arranging the rooms to form a solid block and placing several of them under a hipped or Mansard roof. So far, the planning of the house had been about finding a balance between my needs and my budget.
But in trying to establish this equation I had found it necessary to make the rooms rather smaller than I should have liked, and having a great liking for large and particularly high interiors—I hate Elizabethan rooms with their low ceilings in spite of their prettiness, and I love the interiors of the baroque palaces of Italy—I determined to have one room of generous dimensions and particularly of great height. This large room surrounded by small rooms was naturally made into a general living-place, with arrangements by means of a lift to enable it to be used as a dining hall if there were more in the house than could be accommodated in the small breakfast room.
But in trying to establish this equation, I found it necessary to make the rooms smaller than I would have liked. Since I have a strong preference for large, especially high spaces—I really dislike Elizabethan rooms with their low ceilings despite their charm, and I adore the interiors of the baroque palaces in Italy—I decided to create one room that was generous in size and particularly tall. This large room, surrounded by smaller rooms, was naturally turned into a general living area, with arrangements including a lift to allow it to be used as a dining hall if there were more people in the house than could fit in the small breakfast room.
The estimate for this new concentrated plan, in spite of the large dimensions of the living place, came to little more than half the estimate for the former plan, and made my project feasible, provided that I could calculate all details and did not run into extras.
The estimate for this new concentrated plan, despite the large size of the living space, ended up being just over half of the estimate for the previous plan, making my project possible, as long as I could figure out all the details and avoid any additional costs.
So far then there has been no question of architecture; it has{182} been merely solving the problem of personal needs and habits, and of cost, and if architecture there is to be, it should, I think, come directly out of the solution of these problems. The size and disposition of the plan having thus been fixed, the elevations are given in outline, and the only question is how the rectangle of each elevation is to be treated. Doors and windows are the elements of the design, and here again something will already be determined by needs or tastes. There is need of a certain amount of light, and my own taste is to have as much as possible, so that the windows had to be large rectangles. But when all these things are determined by need there is still a wide margin of choice—the size of the panes in the windows, the depth of recess of the windows within the wall, the flatness or relief of each element. All these and many more are still matters of choice, and it is through the artist’s sense of proportion and his feeling for the plastic relief of the whole surface that a work of mere utility may become a work of art. In the case of the main elevation of my house I found that when all the windows, including the long windows of the high living-place, were duly arranged, there was a want of unity owing to the nearly equal balance between the horizontal and vertical members. I therefore underlined the slight projection of the central part (a projection enforced by by-laws) by varying the material, replacing at this point the plaster of the walls by two bands of red brick. In this way the vertical effect of the central part was made to dominate the whole façade. The artistic or architectural part of this house was confined, then, merely to the careful choice of proportions within certain fixed limits defined by needs, and neither time, money, nor thought were expended on giving the house the appearance of any particular style.
So far, there hasn't been any discussion of architecture; it has{182} simply been about addressing personal needs, habits, and costs. If architecture is going to exist, it should emerge directly from solving these issues. Once the size and layout of the plan are set, the outlines of the elevations are established, and the only question left is how to treat each rectangle of the elevation. Doors and windows are key design elements, and again, needs or preferences will influence these choices. We need a certain amount of light, and personally, I prefer as much as possible, so the windows needed to be large rectangles. But even with needs determining many factors, there's still plenty of room for choice—like the size of the window panes, how deep the window recesses are within the wall, and whether each element is flat or raised. All these details and many more are still up for grabs, and it’s through the artist’s sense of proportion and feeling for the overall texture that a purely functional structure can become a piece of art. When I arranged all the windows in the main elevation of my house, including the long windows of the tall living space, I noticed a lack of unity due to the nearly equal balance between the horizontal and vertical elements. To enhance the slight projection of the central part (which was required by zoning laws), I varied the materials by replacing the plaster at that point with two bands of red brick. This made the vertical effect of the central area stand out across the entire façade. Ultimately, the artistic or architectural aspect of this house came down to carefully selecting proportions within certain fixed limits defined by needs, and no time, money, or effort was spent on making the house look like it belonged to any specific style.
I have gone thus at length into the history of my own house merely as an example of the way in which, I think, a genuine architecture, and in the end, no doubt, an architectural style, might arise. It requires a certain courage or indifference to public opinion on the part of the owner. My own house is neighboured by houses of the most gentlemanly picturesqueness, houses from which tiny gables with window slits jut out at any unexpected angle, and naturally it is regarded as a monstrous eyesore by their inhabitants. Indeed, when I first came here it was supposed that the ugliness of my house was{183} so apparent that I myself could not be blind to it, and should not resent its being criticised in my presence. They were quite right, I did not resent it; I was only very much amused.
I went into detail about my own home's history just to show how, in my opinion, true architecture and eventually a distinctive architectural style can develop. It takes a bit of courage or indifference to public opinion from the owner. My house is surrounded by beautifully designed homes, with small gables and window slits sticking out at odd angles, and naturally, it's seen as a total eyesore by the people living there. In fact, when I first moved here, people thought my house was so ugly that I couldn’t possibly be unaware of it and wouldn’t mind them critiquing it in front of me. They were right; I didn’t mind. I was just really entertained.
To arrive at such a genuine domestic architecture as I conceive, requires, then, this social indifference to surrounding snobbishness on the part of the owner, and it requires a nice sense of proportion and a feeling for values of plastic relief on the part of the artist who designs the house, but it does not require genius or even any extraordinary talent to make a genuine and honest piece of domestic architecture which will continue to look distinguished when the last “style” but one having just become démodé already stinks in the nostrils of all cultured people.{184}
To create a truly authentic domestic architecture as I envision, it takes the owner’s indifference to the surrounding pretentiousness, and it requires a good sense of proportion and an appreciation for the aesthetics from the artist designing the house. However, it doesn’t require genius or even extraordinary talent to produce a genuine and honest piece of domestic architecture that will still look impressive even when the last “style” before it has just gone out of fashion and is already seen as tasteless by all cultured individuals.{184}
JEAN MARCHAND[55]
THERE are some thirty pictures by M. Jean Marchand now on view at the Carfax Gallery in Bury Street. This gives one an occasion for reviewing the work of this comparatively young artist. M. Marchand belongs, of course, to the revolutionary movement of this century in that he derives the general principles of his art from Cézanne, but he is the most traditional of revolutionaries. Not by the wildest stretch of the imagination could one conceive of M. Marchand deliberately or consciously doing anything to astonish the public. It is quite true that no genuine artist ever did, but some artists have found an added piquancy in the thought that inventions that occurred to them would in point of fact have this adventitious charm. But with M. Marchand such possibilities seem more remote than with most of his compeers. An extreme simplicity and directness of outlook and a touching sincerity in all he does are the most prominent characteristics of his work. Not that he makes one suppose him to be too naïve to play tricks with his art; on the contrary, one sees that he is highly self-conscious and intellectual, but that he knows the utter futility of any deliberate emphasis on the artist’s part. He knows that any effect of permanent value must flow directly from the matter in hand; that it is useless to make anything appear more interesting or impressive than it is; that, whatever his vision is, it must be accepted literally, and without any attempt to add to its importance or effectiveness.
THERE are about thirty paintings by M. Jean Marchand currently displayed at the Carfax Gallery on Bury Street. This provides an opportunity to reflect on the work of this relatively young artist. M. Marchand, of course, is part of this century's revolutionary art movement, drawing his fundamental principles from Cézanne, but he is the most traditional among revolutionaries. It's hard to imagine M. Marchand trying to deliberately shock the public. While it’s true that no genuine artist does that, some artists enjoy the idea that their unique ideas might also have that unexpected appeal. However, with M. Marchand, such possibilities seem less likely compared to many of his peers. His work is characterized by extreme simplicity, directness, and a touching sincerity in everything he creates. It’s not that one would think he’s too naïve to play with his art; on the contrary, it’s clear he is very self-aware and intellectual, but he understands the complete futility of any deliberate emphasis on the artist's part. He recognizes that any effect of lasting value must come directly from the subject itself; that it's pointless to make something seem more interesting or impressive than it is; and that whatever his vision may be, it should be taken literally, without any efforts to enhance its significance or impact.
In short, M. Marchand is a classic artist—one might almost in these days say a French artist, and count it as synonymous, but that one remembers that the French, too, have had their orgies of romantic emphasis, and have always ready to hand a convention of coldly exaggerated rhetoric. Moreover, if one thinks of a nearly allied painter{185}
In short, M. Marchand is a classic artist—one could almost say a French artist these days and think they mean the same thing, but then you remember that the French have also had their wild moments of romantic excess and always seem to have at their disposal a style filled with overly dramatic rhetoric. Furthermore, if you consider a closely related painter{185}
such as Derain, whose work is so terribly interesting, one sees that to a quite peculiar degree M. Marchand exemplifies the sentimental honesty of the French. I leave the question open whether this is a moral trait, or is not rather the result of a clearer perception than we often attain to of the extreme futility of lying where art is concerned.
such as Derain, whose work is so incredibly interesting, one sees that to a very unique degree M. Marchand embodies the sentimental honesty of the French. I leave the question open whether this is a moral quality, or if it's more a result of a clearer understanding than we often reach regarding the utter futility of lying when it comes to art.
Certainly one can imagine the temptations for a man of M. Marchand’s great technical ability to choose some slightly wilful or fantastic formula of vision and to exploit it for what it might bring out; for M. Marchand was handicapped in any competition for notoriety by the very normality and sanity of his vision. Compared to the descriptions of sketches in “Jane Eyre,” his pictures would be judged to be entirely lacking in imagination. He never tries to invent what he has not actually seen. Almost any of the ordinary things of life suffice for his theme—a loaf of bread or a hat left on the table, a rather vulgar French château restored by Viollet-le-Duc with a prim garden and decorous lake, a pot of aspidistra in a suburban window. These and the like are the subjects of his pictures, and he paints the objects themselves in all their vulgar everydayness. They do not become excuses for abstract designs; they retain in his pictures all their bleak commonplaceness.
Certainly, it's easy to see the temptations for someone like M. Marchand, with his impressive technical skills, to choose a more whimsical or fantastical style and use it to showcase his work. However, M. Marchand faced a challenge in gaining popularity because of the straightforwardness and clarity of his vision. Compared to the descriptions in “Jane Eyre,” his artwork might be considered totally lacking in imagination. He doesn’t try to create things he hasn’t actually seen. Almost any ordinary aspect of life serves as his subject—a loaf of bread or a hat left on the table, a somewhat tacky French château restored by Viollet-le-Duc with a tidy garden and a neat lake, a potted aspidistra in a suburban window. These are the subjects of his paintings, and he shows the objects as they are in all their everyday mundanity. They do not become mere excuses for abstract designs; they maintain their stark normality in his art.
Any one unfamiliar with his pictures who read such an account of his work might think M. Marchand was a dull literalist, whose mere accomplishment it is to render the similitude of objects. But such a conclusion would be entirely wrong. However frankly M. Marchand accepts the forms of objects, however little his normal vision distorts or idealises them, however consciously and deliberately he chooses the arrangement, he does build up by sheer method and artistic science a unity which has a singularly impressive quality. I heard some one say, in front of a still life which represented a white tablecloth, a glass tumbler, an earthenware water-bottle and a loaf of bread, that it was like Buddha. With such a description as I give of the picture the appreciation sounds precious and absurd; before the picture it seems perfectly just. For M. Marchand has attained the reward of his inflexible honesty; his construction is so solid and unfaltering, he builds up his designs with such massive and direct handling, that without the slightest suggestion of emphasis, without{186} any underlining, the effect comes through; the material becomes expressive; he becomes a creator, and not a mere adapter of form.
Anyone unfamiliar with his paintings who reads such a description of his work might assume M. Marchand is a boring literalist, merely capturing the likeness of objects. But that conclusion would be completely misguided. No matter how straightforwardly M. Marchand accepts the forms of objects, how little his usual vision distorts or idealizes them, or how consciously and deliberately he chooses the composition, he creates a unity through sheer method and artistic skill that carries a remarkably impactful quality. I heard someone say, in front of a still life featuring a white tablecloth, a glass tumbler, an earthenware water bottle, and a loaf of bread, that it resembled Buddha. With the description I provide of the painting, that appreciation sounds pretentious and ridiculous; yet, in front of the painting, it feels perfectly reasonable. Because M. Marchand has reaped the rewards of his unwavering honesty; his structure is so solid and steady, he builds his designs with such strong and direct techniques that, without even the slightest hint of exaggeration, without{186} any emphasis, the effect comes through; the material becomes expressive; he becomes a creator, rather than just a simple adapter of form.
For the understanding of his personality it is interesting to consider his Cubist period, since Marchand’s reaction to Cubism is typical of his nature. Cubism, like S. Paul, has been all things to all men—at least to almost all artists of the present generation. To some it has been a doctrine and a revelation; to some it has been a convenient form of artistic journalism; to some it has been a quick road to notoriety, to some an aid to melodramatic effect. To M. Marchand it was just a useful method and a gymnastic. He used it for just what it could give him as an exercise in the organisation of form. It was to him like a system of notation to a mathematician, a means of handling quantities which without it would have been too elusive and too infinite to grasp. By means of Cubism the infinity of a sphere could be reduced to half a dozen planes, each of which he could learn to relate to all the other planes in the picture; and the singular ease and directness of his plastic construction seem to be due to his early practice of Cubist methods. Having once learned by this process of willed and deliberate analysis how to handle complex forms, he has been able to throw away the scaffolding and to construct palpably related and completely unified designs with something approaching the full complexity of natural forms, though the lucid statement and the ease of handling which it actuates testify to the effect of his apprenticeship in Cubism. Such a use of a theory—as a method, not as a doctrine—seems to me typical of M. Marchand’s balanced judgment, of his alert readiness to use any and every means that could conduce to his slow and methodical development, and hold out hopes of a continued growth.
To understand his personality, it’s helpful to look at his Cubist period, as Marchand’s reaction to Cubism reflects his nature. Cubism, like St. Paul, has meant different things to different people—at least to nearly every artist of this generation. For some, it’s been a guiding principle and a revelation; for others, a convenient way to express artistic ideas; for some, a fast track to fame; and for others, a tool for dramatic effect. For M. Marchand, it was simply a practical method and a workout. He used it for what it could offer him as practice in organizing forms. To him, it was like a notation system for a mathematician, a way to manage concepts that would otherwise be too elusive and infinite to understand. Through Cubism, the infinite nature of a sphere could be simplified into six planes, each of which he could learn to relate to the others in the picture. The remarkable ease and clarity of his design work seem to stem from his early practice with Cubist techniques. Once he learned through this intentional and careful analysis how to handle complex shapes, he was able to remove the scaffolding and create designs that were clearly connected and fully unified, capturing something close to the full complexity of natural forms. However, the clear communication and ease of execution he displays show the impact of his Cubist training. This approach to a theory—as a method instead of a doctrine—seems typical of M. Marchand’s balanced judgment and his keen willingness to use any and all tools that could aid in his gradual and methodical growth, keeping the potential for continued development alive.
M. Marchand, so assured, so settled an artist, is still young. In the landscapes which he did in the South of France just before the war he explored a peculiarly persuasive and harmonious scheme of colour, based on warm ochres, earth reds, and dull blues. These pictures have the envelopment and the sonorous harmony of some early Italian masters in spite of the frank oppositions and the vigorous scaffolding of modern design. In the later work done in the last year he shows a new sense of colour, a new sharpness and almost an audacity, if one can imagine so well-balanced a nature capable of{187} audacity. He uses dull neutral colours, the dirty white of a cloudy sky, harsh dull greens and blacks, the obvious and unattractive colours that so frequently occur in nature; but he uses them in such combinations, and with such accents of tone and such subtly prepared accordances and oppositions, that these obvious dull colours strike one as fascinating discoveries. This is the height of artistic science, so to accept the obvious and commonplace that it gives one the pleasant shock of paradox. It seems hardly rash to foretell for him a solid and continually growing fame.{188}
M. Marchand, a confident and accomplished artist, is still young. In the landscapes he created in the South of France just before the war, he explored a particularly appealing and harmonious color scheme, using warm ochres, earthy reds, and muted blues. These paintings have the depth and rich harmony of some early Italian masters, despite the clear contrasts and the robust structure of modern design. In his later work from the past year, he demonstrates a new sense of color, a fresh sharpness, and even a boldness that you wouldn't expect from such a well-balanced personality. He employs muted neutral colors, the dull white of a cloudy sky, harsh muted greens and blacks—the obvious and unattractive hues that often appear in nature. Yet, he combines them in such ways, with such tonal accents and subtly arranged agreements and contrasts, that these seemingly dull colors emerge as fascinating discoveries. This represents the pinnacle of artistic skill—to embrace the obvious and mundane so completely that it offers a delightful shock of paradox. It hardly seems overzealous to predict a solid and steadily growing reputation for him.{188}
RETROSPECT[56]
THE work of re-reading and selecting from the mass of my writings as an art critic has inevitably brought me up against the question of its consistency and coherence. Although I do not think that I have republished here anything with which I entirely disagree, I cannot but recognise that in many of these essays the emphasis lies in a different place from where I should now put it. Fortunately I have never prided myself upon my unchanging constancy of attitude, but unless I flatter myself I think I can trace a certain trend of thought underlying very different expressions of opinion. Now since that trend seems to me to be symptomatic of modern æsthetic, and since it may perhaps explain much that seems paradoxical in the actual situation of art, it may be interesting to discuss its nature even at the cost of being autobiographical.
THE process of re-reading and selecting from the vast amount of my writing as an art critic has inevitably led me to question its consistency and coherence. While I don’t believe I’ve republished anything I completely disagree with, I can’t help but notice that in many of these essays, the emphasis is placed differently than how I would approach it now. Thankfully, I’ve never claimed to have a permanently unchanging viewpoint, but if I’m honest, I think I can identify a certain underlying trend of thought that connects my varied opinions. Since that trend seems to reflect modern aesthetics, and might help clarify much that appears paradoxical in the current state of art, it could be worth discussing its nature, even if it veers into the autobiographical.
In my work as a critic of art I have never been a pure Impressionist, a mere recording instrument of certain sensations. I have always had some kind of æsthetic. A certain scientific curiosity and a desire for comprehension have impelled me at every stage to make generalisations, to attempt some kind of logical co-ordination of my impressions. But, on the other hand, I have never worked out for myself a complete system such as the metaphysicians deduce from a priori principles. I have never believed that I knew what was the ultimate nature of art. My æsthetic has been a purely practical one, a tentative expedient, an attempt to reduce to some kind of order my æsthetic impressions up to date. It has been held merely until such time as fresh experiences might confirm or modify it. Moreover, I have always looked on my system with a certain suspicion. I have recognised that if it ever formed too solid a crust it might stop the inlets of fresh experience, and I can count various occasions when my principles would have led me to condemn, and when my sensibility has played the part of{189} Balaam with the effect of making temporary chaos of my system. That has, of course, always rearranged itself to take in the new experience, but with each such cataclysm it has suffered a loss of prestige. So that even in its latest form I do not put forward my system as more than a provisional induction from my own æsthetic experiences.
In my work as an art critic, I've never been a pure Impressionist, just a tool recording certain feelings. I've always had some kind of aesthetic perspective. A scientific curiosity and a desire to understand have driven me to make generalizations and try to logically organize my impressions at every stage. However, I’ve never developed a complete system like the metaphysicians create based on a priori principles. I’ve never believed I knew the ultimate nature of art. My aesthetic has been purely practical, a tentative approach to organizing my aesthetic impressions so far. It’s been held only until new experiences could confirm or change it. Additionally, I’ve always viewed my system with a degree of skepticism. I recognized that if it ever became too rigid, it might shut out new experiences, and I can recall various times when my principles would have led me to dismiss something, while my sensitivity acted like Balaam, creating temporary chaos in my system. Of course, it has always reorganized itself to incorporate new experiences, but with each upheaval, it has lost some of its credibility. So even in its latest form, I don't present my system as anything more than a temporary conclusion drawn from my own aesthetic experiences.
I have certainly tried to make my judgment as objective as possible, but the critic must work with the only instrument he possesses—namely, his own sensibility with all its personal equations. All that he can consciously endeavour is to perfect that tool to its utmost by studying the traditional verdicts of men of æsthetic sensibility in the past, and by constant comparison of his own reactions with those of his contemporaries who are specially gifted in this way. When he has done all that he can in this direction—and I would allow him a slight bias in favour of agreement with tradition—he is bound to accept the verdict of his own feelings as honestly as he can. Even plain honesty in this matter is more difficult to attain than would be admitted by those who have never tried it. In so delicate a matter as the artistic judgment one is liable to many accidental disturbing influences, one can scarcely avoid temporary hypnotisms and hallucinations. One can only watch for and try to discount these, taking every opportunity to catch one’s sensibility unawares before it can take cover behind prejudices and theories.
I’ve definitely tried to make my judgment as objective as possible, but the critic has to rely on the only tool they have—their own sensitivity with all its personal biases. All they can consciously work on is perfecting that tool by studying the traditional opinions of people with aesthetic sensitivity in the past and constantly comparing their own reactions with those of their contemporaries who are particularly gifted in this area. Once they’ve done everything they can in this respect—and I would allow them a slight bias in favor of tradition—they have to accept the verdict of their own feelings as honestly as they can. Even plain honesty in this area is harder to achieve than those who have never attempted it might realize. In the delicate realm of artistic judgment, one can be influenced by many accidental factors; it’s almost impossible to avoid temporary biases and illusions. One can only be on the lookout for these and try to account for them, seizing every chance to catch their sensitivity off guard before it can hide behind prejudices and theories.
When the critic holds the result of his reaction to a work of art clearly in view he has next to translate it into words. Here, too, distortion is inevitable, and it is here that I have probably failed most of accuracy, for language in the hands of one who lacks the mastery of a poet has its own tricks, its perversities and habits. There are things which it shies at and goes round, there are places where it runs away and, leaving the reality which it professes to carry tumbled out at the tail of the cart, arrives in a great pother, but without the goods.
When a critic clearly sees their reaction to a piece of art, the next step is to put that reaction into words. However, distortion is bound to happen here, and this is likely where I've struggled the most with accuracy. Language, in the hands of someone who isn't a skilled poet, has its quirks, oddities, and habits. There are concepts that it avoids and circumvents, as well as times when it escapes, leaving the reality it claims to convey left behind in a mess, arriving in a flurry but without the substance.
But in spite of all these limitations and the errors they entail it seems to me that the attempt to attain objective judgments has not altogether failed, and that I seem to myself to have been always groping my way towards some kind of a reasoned and practical æsthetic. Many minds have been engaged alongside of mine in the same pursuit. I think we may claim that partly as a result of our common efforts{190} a rather more intelligent attitude exists in the educated public of to-day than obtained in the last century.
But despite all these limitations and the mistakes they bring, I believe that the effort to reach objective judgments hasn't completely failed, and I feel like I've always been trying to find some sort of thoughtful and practical aesthetic. Many other minds have been working alongside mine in this pursuit. I think we can say that, in part due to our collective efforts{190}, there's a more intelligent attitude among today's educated public compared to the last century.
Art in England is sometimes insular, sometimes provincial. The pre-Raphaelite movement was mainly an indigenous product. The dying echoes of this remarkable explosion reverberated through the years of my nonage, but when I first began to study art seriously the vital movement was a provincial one. After the usual twenty years of delay, provincial England had become aware of the Impressionist movement in France, and the younger painters of promise were working under the influence of Monet. Some of them even formulated theories of naturalism in its most literal and extreme form. But at the same time Whistler, whose Impressionism was of a very different stamp, had put forward the purely decorative idea of art, and had tried in his “Ten o’clock,” perhaps too cavalierly, to sweep away the web of ethical questions, distorted by æsthetic prejudices, which Ruskin’s exuberant and ill-regulated mind had spun for the British public.
Art in England can sometimes feel isolated and a bit behind the times. The pre-Raphaelite movement largely came from within the country. The lingering effects of this incredible artistic surge were still felt throughout my childhood, but when I began to take art seriously, the main movement was more of a local one. After a typical twenty-year lag, provincial England finally noticed the Impressionist movement happening in France, and the up-and-coming artists were influenced by Monet. Some of them even developed theories of naturalism in its most literal and extreme sense. At the same time, Whistler, whose Impressionism was quite different, promoted the idea of art as purely decorative. In his “Ten O’Clock,” he perhaps too casually tried to dismiss the complex ethical issues, which had been distorted by aesthetic biases that Ruskin’s overzealous and chaotic mind had woven for the British public.
The Naturalists made no attempt to explain why the exact and literal imitation of nature should satisfy the human spirit, and the “Decorators” failed to distinguish between agreeable sensations and imaginative significance.
The Naturalists didn’t try to explain why a precise and literal imitation of nature should fulfill the human spirit, and the “Decorators” couldn't tell the difference between pleasant feelings and creative meaning.
After a brief period during which I was interested in the new possibilities opened up by the more scientific evaluation of colour which the Impressionists practised, I came to feel more and more the absence in their work of structural design. It was an innate desire for this aspect of art which drove me to the study of the Old Masters and, in particular, those of the Italian Renaissance, in the hope of discovering from them the secret of that architectonic idea which I missed so badly in the work of my contemporaries. I think now that a certain amount of “cussedness” led me to exaggerate what was none the less a genuine personal reaction. Finding myself out of touch with my generation I took a certain pleasure in emphasising my isolation. I always recognised fully that the only vital art of the day was that of the Impressionists whose theories I disbelieved, and I was always able to admit the greatness of Degas and Renoir. But many of my judgments of modern art were too much affected by my attitude. I do not think I ever praised Mr. Wilson Steer or Mr. Walter Sickert as much as they deserved, and I looked with too{191}
After a short time where I was intrigued by the new possibilities introduced by the scientific approach to color that the Impressionists used, I started to realize more and more how their work lacked structural design. This innate desire for that element of art pushed me to study the Old Masters, especially those from the Italian Renaissance, hoping to uncover the architectural ideas that I found so lacking in my contemporaries' work. I now think that my stubbornness made me exaggerate what was still a genuine personal reaction. Feeling disconnected from my generation, I derived some satisfaction from highlighting my isolation. I always fully acknowledged that the only truly vital art of the time was that of the Impressionists, whose theories I didn't believe in, and I could always recognize the greatness of Degas and Renoir. However, many of my opinions on modern art were overly influenced by my stance. I don’t believe I ever praised Mr
great indulgence on some would-be imitators of the Old Masters. But my most serious lapse was the failure to discover the genius of Seurat (see Plate), whose supreme merits as a designer I had every reason to acclaim. I cannot even tell now whether I ever saw his work in the exhibitions of the early nineties, but if I did his qualities were hidden from me by the now transparent veil of pointillism—a pseudo-scientific system of atmospheric colour notation in which I took no interest.
great indulgence on some would-be imitators of the Old Masters. But my most serious mistake was not recognizing the genius of Seurat (see Plate), whose outstanding skills as a designer I had every reason to praise. I can’t even say now whether I ever saw his work in the exhibitions of the early nineties, but if I did, his qualities were obscured from me by the now clear veil of pointillism—a pseudo-scientific method of atmospheric color notation that I had no interest in.
I think I can claim that my study of the Old Masters was never much tainted by archæological curiosity. I tried to study them in the same spirit as I might study contemporary artists, and I always regretted that there was no modern art capable of satisfying my predilections. I say there was no modern art because none such was known to me, but all the time there was one who had already worked out the problem which seemed to me insoluble of how to use the modern vision with the constructive design of the older masters. By some extraordinary ill luck I managed to miss seeing Cézanne’s work till some considerable time after his death. I had heard of him vaguely from time to time as a kind of hidden oracle of ultra-impressionism, and, in consequence, I expected to find myself entirely unreceptive to his art. To my intense surprise I found myself deeply moved. I have discovered the article in which I recorded this encounter, and though the praise I gave would sound grudging and feeble to-day—for I was still obsessed by ideas about the content of a work of art—I am glad to see that I was so ready to scrap a long-cherished hypothesis in face of a new experience.
I believe I can say that my study of the Old Masters was never really influenced by archaeological curiosity. I tried to approach them the same way I would study contemporary artists, and I always wished there was modern art that could meet my tastes. I say there was no modern art because I wasn’t aware of any, but all along, there was someone who had already solved the problem that seemed impossible to me: how to blend modern vision with the constructive design of the older masters. Unfortunately, I ended up missing Cézanne’s work until quite some time after he died. I had heard of him here and there as a kind of hidden authority of ultra-impressionism, and because of that, I thought I wouldn’t be affected by his art at all. To my surprise, I found myself really moved. I found the write-up where I documented this experience, and even though the praise I gave might sound half-hearted and weak today—since I was still caught up in ideas about the content of a work of art—I’m glad to see that I was willing to let go of a long-held belief in light of a new experience.
In the next few years I became increasingly interested in the art of Cézanne and of those like Gauguin and van Goch who at that time represented the first effects of his profound influence on modern art, and I gradually recognised that what I had hoped for as a possible event of some future century had already occurred, that art had begun to recover once more the language of design and to explore its so long neglected possibilities. Thus it happened that when at the end of 1911, by a curious series of chances, I was in a position to organise an exhibition at the Grafton Galleries, I seized the opportunity to bring before the English public a selection of works conforming to the new direction. For purposes of convenience it was necessary to give these artists a name, and I chose, as being the vaguest and most{192} non-committal, the name of Post-Impressionist. This merely stated their position in time relatively to the Impressionist movement. In conformity with my own previous prejudices against Impressionism, I think I underlined too much their divorce from the parent stock. I see now more clearly their affiliation with it, but I was none the less right in recognising their essential difference, a difference which the subsequent development of Cubism has rendered more evident. Of late the thesis of their fundamental opposition has been again enforced in the writings of M. Lhote.
Over the next few years, I became more and more interested in the art of Cézanne and artists like Gauguin and van Gogh, who at that time represented the early impact of his deep influence on modern art. I slowly realized that what I had hoped for as a potential development in some future century had already happened: art had started to reclaim the language of design and to explore its long-neglected possibilities. So, when at the end of 1911, by a strange series of events, I had the chance to organize an exhibition at the Grafton Galleries, I took the opportunity to showcase a selection of works that aligned with this new direction. To make things easier, I needed to give these artists a name, and I chose the term Post-Impressionist, as it was broad and non-specific. This simply indicated their position in relation to the Impressionist movement. Because of my previous biases against Impressionism, I may have emphasized their separation from the original movement too much. I now understand their connection to it more clearly, but I was still correct in acknowledging their essential differences, which the later development of Cubism has made even more apparent. Recently, the argument about their fundamental opposition has been reinforced in the writings of M. Lhote.
If I may judge by the discussions in the press to which this exhibition gave rise, the general public failed to see that my position with regard to this movement was capable of a logical explanation, as the result of a consistent sensibility. I tried in vain to explain what appeared to me so clear, that the modern movement was essentially a return to the ideas of formal design which had been almost lost sight of in the fervid pursuit of naturalistic representation. I found that the cultured public which had welcomed my expositions of the works of the Italian Renaissance now regarded me as either incredibly flippant or, for the more charitable explanation was usually adopted, slightly insane. In fact, I found among the cultured who had hitherto been my most eager listeners the most inveterate and exasperated enemies of the new movement. The accusation of anarchism was constantly made. From an æsthetic point of view this was, of course, the exact opposite of the truth, and I was for long puzzled to find the explanation of so paradoxical an opinion and so violent an enmity. I now see that my crime had been to strike at the vested emotional interests. These people felt instinctively that their special culture was one of their social assets. That to be able to speak glibly of Tang and Ming, of Amico di Sandro and Baldovinetti, gave them a social standing and a distinctive cachet. This showed me that we had all along been labouring under a mutual misunderstanding, i.e. that we had admired the Italian primitives for quite different reasons. It was felt that one could only appreciate Amico di Sandro when one had acquired a certain considerable mass of erudition and given a great deal of time and attention, but to admire a Matisse required only a certain sensibility. One could feel fairly sure that one’s maid could not rival one in the former case, but might by a mere haphazard gift of Providence{193}
If I can judge by the discussions in the media that this exhibition sparked, the general public didn’t realize that my stance on this movement had a logical explanation stemming from a consistent sensibility. I struggled to clarify what seemed so obvious to me: that the modern movement was basically a return to formal design ideas that had nearly been forgotten in the intense pursuit of realistic representation. I found that the educated audience who had once appreciated my presentations on Italian Renaissance art now viewed me as incredibly superficial, or, in a more generous interpretation, slightly unhinged. In fact, I discovered that among the cultured crowd who had previously been my most enthusiastic supporters were now the most bitter and frustrated opponents of the new movement. They frequently accused me of anarchism, which, from an aesthetic perspective, was the complete opposite of the truth. For a long time, I was puzzled trying to understand the reasoning behind such a contradictory opinion and such fierce hostility. I now realize that my mistake was challenging their deeply held emotional interests. These individuals instinctively sensed that their specific cultural knowledge was a social asset. The ability to discuss Tang and Ming, Amico di Sandro, and Baldovinetti elevated their social standing and gave them a unique appeal. This made me aware that we had been operating under a mutual misunderstanding, meaning that we admired the Italian primitives for very different reasons. People believed that you could only appreciate Amico di Sandro after acquiring a significant amount of knowledge and dedicating considerable time and attention, but appreciating a Matisse only required a certain sensitivity. One could be fairly certain that one’s maid wouldn’t be able to compete in the first situation, but might unexpectedly possess that innate gift of Providence{193}
surpass one in the second. So that the accusation of revolutionary anarchism was due to a social rather than an æsthetic prejudice. In any case the cultured public was determined to look upon Cézanne as an incompetent bungler, and upon the whole movement as madly revolutionary. Nothing I could say would induce people to look calmly enough at these pictures to see how closely they followed tradition, or how great a familiarity with the Italian primitives was displayed in their work. Now that Matisse has become a safe investment for persons of taste, and that Picasso and Derain have delighted the miscellaneous audience of the London Music Halls with their designs for the Russian Ballet, it will be difficult for people to believe in the vehemence of the indignation which greeted the first sight of their works in England.
surpass one in the second. So, the accusation of revolutionary anarchism stemmed from a social rather than an aesthetic bias. In any case, the educated public was set on viewing Cézanne as an incompetent fool, and the entire movement as wildly radical. Nothing I said could get people to look at these paintings with enough calm to see how closely they adhered to tradition or how well they showcased a familiarity with the Italian primitives in their work. Now that Matisse has become a safe choice for those with good taste, and Picasso and Derain have entertained the diverse audiences of the London Music Halls with their designs for the Russian Ballet, it will be hard for people to believe in the intensity of the outrage that met the first viewing of their works in England.
In contrast to its effect on the cultured public the Post-Impressionist exhibition aroused a keen interest among a few of the younger English artists and their friends. With them I began to discuss the problems of æsthetic that the contemplation of these works forced upon us.
In contrast to its impact on the cultured audience, the Post-Impressionist exhibition sparked a strong interest among some younger English artists and their friends. I started discussing the aesthetic issues that looking at these works presented to us.
But before explaining the effects of these discussions upon my æsthetic theory I must return to consider the generalisations which I had made from my æsthetic experiences up to this point.
But before I explain how these discussions impact my aesthetic theory, I need to go back and look at the generalizations I made from my aesthetic experiences up to this point.
In my youth all speculations on æsthetic had revolved with wearisome persistence around the question of the nature of beauty. Like our predecessors we sought for the criteria of the beautiful, whether in art or nature. And always this search led to a tangle of contradictions or else to metaphysical ideas so vague as to be inapplicable to concrete cases.
In my younger days, all discussions about aesthetics kept getting stuck on the question of what beauty really is. Like those before us, we looked for ways to define beauty, whether in art or nature. Every time, this quest ended up in a mess of contradictions or led to such vague metaphysical concepts that they couldn’t be used in real situations.
It was Tolstoy’s genius that delivered us from this impasse, and I think that one may date from the appearance of “What is Art?” the beginning of fruitful speculation in æsthetic. It was not indeed Tolstoy’s preposterous valuation of works of art that counted for us, but his luminous criticism of past æsthetic systems, above all, his suggestions that art had no special or necessary concern with what is beautiful in nature, that the fact that Greek sculpture had run prematurely to decay through an extreme and non-æsthetic admiration of beauty in the human figure afforded no reason why we should for ever remain victims of their error.{194}
It was Tolstoy’s brilliance that got us out of this deadlock, and I think we can trace the start of meaningful discussions in aesthetics back to the release of “What is Art?” It wasn’t really Tolstoy’s outrageous valuation of artworks that mattered to us, but his insightful criticism of earlier aesthetic theories. Most importantly, his idea that art doesn’t necessarily have to be about what’s beautiful in nature. The fact that Greek sculpture decayed too soon due to an excessive, non-aesthetic admiration for human beauty doesn’t mean we have to keep making the same mistake.{194}
It became clear that we had confused two distinct uses of the word beautiful, that when we used beauty to describe a favourable æsthetic judgment on a work of art we meant something quite different from our praise of a woman, a sunset or a horse as beautiful. Tolstoy saw that the essence of art was that it was a means of communication between human beings. He conceived it to be par excellence the language of emotion. It was at this point that his moral bias led him to the strange conclusion that the value of a work of art corresponded to the moral value of the emotion expressed. Fortunately he showed by an application of his theory to actual works of art to what absurdities it led. What remained of immense importance was the idea that a work of art was not the record of beauty already existent elsewhere, but the expression of an emotion felt by the artist and conveyed to the spectator.
It became clear that we had mixed up two different uses of the word beautiful: when we used beauty to describe a positive aesthetic judgment on a piece of art, we meant something completely different from complimenting a woman, a sunset, or a horse as beautiful. Tolstoy realized that the essence of art was that it served as a way of communicating between people. He believed it was the ultimate language of emotion. At this point, his moral viewpoint led him to the odd conclusion that the value of a work of art was tied to the moral value of the emotion it expressed. Fortunately, he demonstrated through his applications of this theory to real works of art how absurd this could be. What remained extremely important was the idea that a work of art is not just a record of beauty that already exists elsewhere, but rather an expression of an emotion felt by the artist and communicated to the viewer.
The next question was, Of what kind of emotions is art the expression? Is love poetry the expression of the emotion of love, tragedy the expression of pity and fear, and so forth? Clearly the expression in art has some similarity to the expression of these emotions in actual life, but it is never identical. It is evident that the artist feels these emotions in a special manner, that he is not entirely under their influence, but sufficiently withdrawn to contemplate and comprehend them. My “Essay in Æsthetic” here reprinted, elaborates this point of view, and in a course of unpublished lectures I endeavoured to divide works of visual art according to the emotional point of view, adopting the classification already existing in poetry into Epic, Dramatic, Lyric, and Comedic.
The next question was, What kind of emotions does art express? Is love poetry simply the expression of love, while tragedy conveys feelings of pity and fear, and so on? It's clear that the expression in art has some similarities to how these emotions are expressed in real life, but it’s never exactly the same. It’s evident that the artist experiences these emotions in a unique way, not entirely controlled by them, but distant enough to reflect on and understand them. My “Essay in Æsthetic” reprinted here explores this perspective, and in a series of unpublished lectures, I tried to categorize visual art based on emotional perspectives, using the existing classifications from poetry: Epic, Dramatic, Lyric, and Comedic.
I conceived the form of the work of art to be its most essential quality, but I believed this form to be the direct outcome of an apprehension of some emotion of actual life by the artist, although, no doubt, that apprehension was of a special and peculiar kind and implied a certain detachment. I also conceived that the spectator in contemplating the form must inevitably travel in an opposite direction along the same road which the artist had taken, and himself feel the original emotion. I conceived the form and the emotion which it conveyed as being inextricably bound together in the æsthetic whole.
I believed that the shape of a piece of art was its most important quality, but I thought this shape resulted directly from the artist's understanding of some real-life emotion. However, that understanding was certainly a unique and particular kind, suggesting some distance. I also thought that when a viewer examines this shape, they must inevitably journey in the opposite direction along the same path that the artist took and feel that original emotion themselves. I viewed the form and the emotion it expressed as being completely intertwined in the overall aesthetic experience.
About the time I had arrived at these conclusions the discussion of æsthetic stimulated by the appearance of Post-Impressionism began. It became evident through these discussions that some artists who{195} were peculiarly sensitive to the formal relations of works of art, and who were deeply moved by them, had almost no sense of the emotions which I had supposed them to convey. Since it was impossible in these cases to doubt the genuineness of the æsthetic reaction it became evident that I had not pushed the analysis of works of art far enough, had not disentangled the purely æsthetic elements from certain accompanying accessories.
About the time I reached these conclusions, discussions about aesthetics sparked by the emergence of Post-Impressionism began. It became clear through these conversations that some artists who{195} were particularly attuned to the formal aspects of artworks, and who were profoundly affected by them, almost completely missed the emotions I thought they conveyed. Since it was impossible to doubt the authenticity of the aesthetic response in these cases, it became clear that I hadn't analyzed artworks deeply enough and hadn't separated the purely aesthetic elements from some accompanying features.
It was, I think, the observation of these cases of reaction to pure form that led Mr. Clive Bell in his book, “Art,” to put forward the hypothesis that however much the emotions of life might appear to play a part in the work of art, the artist was really not concerned with them, but only with the expression of a special and unique kind of emotion, the æsthetic emotion. A work of art had the peculiar property of conveying the æsthetic emotion, and it did this in virtue of having “significant form.” He also declared that representation of nature was entirely irrelevant to this and that a picture might be completely non-representative.
I think it was the observation of these reactions to pure form that led Mr. Clive Bell, in his book "Art," to propose the idea that no matter how much life’s emotions seemed to influence art, the artist was really focused only on expressing a unique kind of emotion—the aesthetic emotion. A work of art has the special ability to convey this aesthetic emotion, achieved through what he called "significant form." He also stated that representing nature was completely unrelated to this, and that a painting could be entirely non-representational.
This last view seemed to me always to go too far since any, even the slightest, suggestion of the third dimension in a picture must be due to some element of representation. What I think has resulted from Mr. Clive Bell’s book, and the discussions which it has aroused on this point is that the artist is free to choose any degree of representational accuracy which suits the expression of his feeling. That no single fact, or set of facts, about nature can be held to be obligatory for artistic form. Also one might add as an empirical observation that the greatest art seems to concern itself most with the universal aspects of natural form, to be the least pre-occupied with particulars. The greatest artists appear to be most sensitive to those qualities of natural objects which are the least obvious in ordinary life precisely because, being common to all visible objects, they do not serve as marks of distinction and recognition.
This final viewpoint always seemed too extreme to me since any hint of the third dimension in an image must come from some aspect of representation. I believe Mr. Clive Bell’s book and the discussions it sparked have led to the idea that artists can choose whatever level of representational accuracy they feel expresses their emotions best. No single fact or group of facts about nature should be seen as mandatory for artistic form. Additionally, as an observation based on experience, the greatest art seems to focus more on the universal elements of natural form and less on the specifics. The most exceptional artists appear to be the most attuned to the qualities of natural objects that are least noticeable in everyday life because these qualities are common to all visible objects and don’t serve as distinguishing or recognizable traits.
With regard to the expression of emotion in works of art I think that Mr. Bell’s sharp challenge to the usually accepted view of art as expressing the emotions of life has been of great value. It has led to an attempt to isolate the purely æsthetic feeling from the whole complex of feelings which may and generally do accompany the æsthetic feeling when we regard a work of art.{196}
When it comes to expressing emotions in art, I believe Mr. Bell's strong challenge to the commonly accepted idea that art reflects life's emotions has been very valuable. It has prompted an effort to separate the purely aesthetic experience from the complex mix of feelings that often accompany it when we look at a piece of art.{196}
Let us take as an example of what I mean Raphael’s “Transfiguration,” which a hundred years ago was perhaps the most admired picture in the world, and twenty years ago was one of the most neglected. It is at once apparent that this picture makes a very complex appeal to the mind and feelings. To those who are familiar with the Gospel story of Christ it brings together in a single composition two different events which occurred simultaneously at different places, the Transfiguration of Christ and the unsuccessful attempt of the Disciples during His absence to heal the lunatic boy. This at once arouses a number of complex ideas about which the intellect and feelings may occupy themselves. Goethe’s remark on the picture is instructive from this point of view. “It is remarkable,” he says, “that any one has ever ventured to query the essential unity of such a composition. How can the upper part be separated from the lower? The two form one whole. Below the suffering and the needy, above the powerful and helpful—mutually dependent, mutually illustrative.”
Let’s look at Raphael’s “Transfiguration” as an example. A hundred years ago, it was probably the most admired painting in the world, and twenty years ago, it was largely overlooked. It’s clear that this painting appeals to both the mind and emotions in a very complex way. For those familiar with the Gospel story of Christ, it combines two events that happened at the same time but in different places: the Transfiguration of Christ and the failed attempt by the Disciples to heal the boy with a mental illness while Jesus was away. This immediately raises a variety of intricate ideas for the intellect and feelings to explore. Goethe’s observation about the painting is enlightening in this context. He states, “It is remarkable that anyone has ever dared to question the essential unity of such a composition. How can the upper part be separated from the lower? The two form one whole. Below, the suffering and the needy; above, the powerful and helpful—mutually dependent, mutually illustrative.”
It will be seen at once what an immense complex of feelings interpenetrating and mutually affecting one another such a work sets up in the mind of a Christian spectator, and all this merely by the content of the picture, its subject, the dramatic story it tells.
It’s immediately clear what a huge mix of feelings, intertwining and influencing each other, a piece like this creates in the mind of a Christian viewer, all just from what the picture shows, its subject, and the dramatic story it tells.
Now if our Christian spectator has also a knowledge of human nature he will be struck by the fact that these figures, especially in the lower group, are all extremely incongruous with any idea he is likely to have formed of the people who surrounded Christ in the Gospel narrative. And according to his prepossessions he is likely to be shocked or pleased to find instead of the poor and unsophisticated peasants and fisherfolk who followed Christ, a number of noble, dignified, and academic gentlemen in impossible garments and purely theatrical poses. Again the representation merely as representation, will set up a number of feelings and perhaps of critical thoughts dependent upon innumerable associated ideas in the spectator’s mind.
Now, if our Christian viewer has an understanding of human nature, they'll notice that these figures, especially in the lower group, don’t match at all with the image they might have of the people who were around Christ in the Gospel story. Based on their preconceived ideas, they might be surprised or pleased to see that instead of the poor, simple farmers and fishermen who followed Christ, there are a bunch of noble, dignified, and scholarly gentlemen in unrealistic outfits and overly dramatic poses. Moreover, just the act of representation will evoke various feelings and possibly critical thoughts based on countless associated ideas in the viewer’s mind.
Now all these reactions to the picture are open to any one who has enough understanding of natural form to recognise it when represented adequately. There is no need for him to have any particular sensibility to form as such.
Now, anyone who has a basic understanding of natural form can respond to the picture, as long as it is represented clearly. They don't need to have any special sensitivity to form itself.
forms as a musical person feels the intervals and relations of tones, and let us suppose him either completely ignorant of, or indifferent to, the Gospel story. Such a spectator will be likely to be immensely excited by the extraordinary power of co-ordination of many complex masses in a single inevitable whole, by the delicate equilibrium of many directions of line. He will at once feel that the apparent division into two parts is only apparent, that they are co-ordinated by a quite peculiar power of grasping the possible correlations. He will almost certainly be immensely excited and moved, but his emotion will have nothing to do with the emotions which we have discussed since in the former case, ex-hypothesi, our spectator has no clue to them.
forms as a musical person feels the intervals and relationships of tones, and let's say he is either completely unaware of or uninterested in the Gospel story. Such a viewer is likely to be incredibly excited by the remarkable ability to coordinate many complex elements into a single, inevitable whole, by the delicate balance of many different lines. He will immediately sense that the apparent division into two parts is just that—an appearance—that they are unified by a unique ability to understand possible connections. He will almost certainly be immensely excited and moved, but his feelings won’t be connected to the emotions we've talked about before, as, in this case, our viewer has no understanding of them.
It is evident then that we have the possibility of infinitely diverse reactions to a work of art. We may imagine, for instance, that our pagan spectator, though entirely unaffected by the story, is yet conscious that the figures represent men, and that their gestures are indicative of certain states of mind and, in consequence, we may suppose that according to an internal bias his emotion is either heightened or hindered by the recognition of their rhetorical insincerity. Or we may suppose him to be so absorbed in purely formal relations as to be indifferent even to this aspect of the design as representation. We may suppose him to be moved by the pure contemplation of the spatial relations of plastic volumes. It is when we have got to this point that we seem to have isolated this extremely elusive æsthetic quality which is the one constant quality of all works of art, and which seems to be independent of all the prepossessions and associations which the spectator brings with him from his past life.
It’s clear, then, that we can have an endless variety of reactions to a piece of art. For example, we can imagine that our non-religious viewer, while completely unaffected by the story, still recognizes that the figures represent people, and that their gestures reflect certain emotional states. As a result, we can assume that his feelings are either intensified or diminished by his awareness of their lack of genuine expression. Alternatively, we might picture him so focused on purely formal aspects that he remains indifferent even to this element of representation. He could be touched simply by the visual arrangement of shapes and volumes. It’s at this point that we seem to isolate this very elusive aesthetic quality, which is the one consistent aspect of all art, appearing independent of all the biases and associations that the viewer brings from their past experiences.
A person so entirely pre-occupied with the purely formal meaning of a work of art, so entirely blind to all the overtones and associations of a picture like the Transfiguration is extremely rare. Nearly every one, even if highly sensitive to purely plastic and spatial appearances, will inevitably entertain some of those thoughts and feelings which are conveyed by implication and by reference back to life. The difficulty is that we frequently give wrong explanations of our feelings. I suspect, for instance, that Goethe was deeply moved by the marvellous discovery of design, whereby the upper and lower parts cohere in a single whole, but the explanation he gave of this feeling took the form of a moral and philosophical reflection.{198}
A person who is completely focused on the literal meaning of a work of art, completely unaware of all the nuances and associations of a painting like the Transfiguration, is extremely rare. Almost everyone, even if they are very attuned to the visual and spatial aspects, will inevitably have some thoughts and feelings that are conveyed indirectly and by connecting back to real life. The challenge is that we often misinterpret our feelings. I suspect, for example, that Goethe was profoundly affected by the amazing discovery of design, where the upper and lower parts come together as a cohesive whole, but the way he explained this feeling ended up being more of a moral and philosophical reflection.{198}
It is evident also that owing to our difficulty in recognising the nature of our own feelings we are liable to have our æsthetic reaction interfered with by our reaction to the dramatic overtones and implications. I have chosen this picture of the Transfiguration precisely because its history is a striking example of this fact. In Goethe’s time rhetorical gesture was no bar to the appreciation of æsthetic unity. Later on in the nineteenth century, when the study of the Primitives had revealed to us the charm of dramatic sincerity and naturalness, these gesticulating figures appeared so false and unsympathetic that even people of æsthetic sensibility were unable to disregard them, and their dislike of the picture as illustration actually obliterated or prevented the purely æsthetic approval which they would probably otherwise have experienced. It seems to me that this attempt to isolate the elusive element of the pure æsthetic reaction from the compounds in which it occurs has been the most important advance of modern times in practical æsthetic.
It’s clear that because we struggle to understand our own feelings, our aesthetic reactions can be disrupted by our responses to dramatic elements and implications. I chose this painting of the Transfiguration specifically because its history highlights this issue. During Goethe’s time, rhetorical gestures didn’t hinder the appreciation of aesthetic unity. However, later in the nineteenth century, when studying the Primitives revealed the appeal of dramatic sincerity and naturalness, those exaggerated figures seemed false and unappealing. Even those with a strong sense of aesthetics found it hard to overlook them, and their distaste for the painting as an illustration actually overshadowed or blocked the purely aesthetic appreciation they might have otherwise felt. I believe that the effort to separate the elusive aspect of pure aesthetic reaction from the mixtures in which it appears has been the most significant advancement of modern times in practical aesthetics.
The question which this simile suggests is full of problems; are these chemical compounds in the normal æsthetically gifted spectator, or are they merely mixtures due to our confused recognition of what goes on in the complex of our emotions? The picture I have chosen is also valuable, just at the present time, from this point of view. Since it presents in vivid opposition for most of us a very strong positive (pleasurable) reaction on the purely æsthetic side, and a violently negative (painful) reaction in the realm of dramatic association.
The question raised by this comparison is filled with challenges: are these chemical reactions present in the normally aesthetically aware viewer, or are they just mixtures because of our unclear understanding of what's happening in our complex emotions? The image I’ve selected is also important right now from this perspective. It creates a strong contrast for many of us, provoking a very intense positive (pleasurable) reaction on the aesthetic side, and a deeply negative (painful) response in terms of dramatic association.
But one could easily point to pictures where the two sets of emotions seem to run so parallel that the idea that they reinforce one another is inevitably aroused. We might take, for instance, Giotto’s “Pietà.” In my description of that (p. 110), it will be seen that the two currents of feeling ran so together in my own mind that I regarded them as being completely fused. My emotion about the dramatic idea seemed to heighten my emotion about the plastic design. But at present I should be inclined to say that this fusion of two sets of emotion was only apparent and was due to my imperfect analysis of my own mental state.
But it's easy to find images where the two sets of emotions seem to run parallel, leading to the idea that they reinforce each other. Take, for example, Giotto’s “Pietà.” In my description of that (p. 110), you’ll see that the two waves of feeling felt so intertwined in my mind that I believed they were completely fused. My feelings about the dramatic concept seemed to intensify my feelings about the physical design. However, I would currently say that this fusion of the two sets of emotions was only apparent and stemmed from my incomplete understanding of my own mental state.
Probably at this point we must hand over the question to the experimental psychologist. It is for him to discover whether this fusion is possible, whether, for example, such a thing as a song really{199} exists, that is to say, a song in which neither the meaning of the words nor the meaning of the music predominates; in which music and words do not merely set up separate currents of feeling, which may agree in a general parallelism, but really fuse and become indivisible. I expect that the answer will be in the negative.
At this point, we probably need to leave the question to the experimental psychologist. It's up to them to find out if this fusion is possible, like whether something called a song really{199} exists—meaning a song where neither the words nor the music takes over; where music and words don’t just create separate emotional channels that line up in a general way, but truly blend together and become inseparable. I expect the answer will be no.
If on the other hand such a complete fusion of different kinds of emotion does take place, this would tend to substantiate the ordinary opinion that the æsthetic emotion has greater value in highly complicated compounds than in the pure state.
If, on the other hand, a complete blending of different types of emotion does occur, this would support the common belief that aesthetic emotion is more valuable in complex combinations than in its pure form.
Supposing, then, that we are able to isolate in a work of art this purely æsthetic quality to which Mr. Clive Bell gives the name of “significant form.” Of what nature is it? And what is the value of this elusive and—taking the whole mass of mankind—rather uncommon æsthetic emotion which it causes? I put these questions without much hope of answering them, since it is of the greatest importance to recognise clearly what are the questions which remain to be solved.
Supposing, then, that we can isolate in a piece of art this purely aesthetic quality that Mr. Clive Bell calls “significant form.” What is it like? And what is the value of this elusive and—considering most people—a rather uncommon aesthetic emotion it creates? I ask these questions without much hope of being able to answer them, as it is extremely important to clearly identify the questions that still need to be addressed.
I think we are all agreed that we mean by significant form something other than agreeable arrangements of form, harmonious patterns, and the like. We feel that a work which possesses it is the outcome of an endeavour to express an idea rather than to create a pleasing object. Personally, at least, I always feel that it implies the effort on the part of the artist to bend to our emotional understanding by means of his passionate conviction some intractable material which is alien to our spirit.
I think we all agree that when we talk about significant form, we mean something beyond just nice-looking arrangements and harmonious patterns. We believe that a work with significant form comes from an effort to express an idea instead of just creating something beautiful. Personally, I always feel that it represents the artist's attempt to connect with our emotions using their strong beliefs, transforming stubborn materials that don't naturally resonate with us.
I seem unable at present to get beyond this vague adumbration of the nature of significant form. Flaubert’s “expression of the idea” seems to me to correspond exactly to what I mean, but, alas! he never explained, and probably could not, what he meant by the “idea.”
I can't seem to move past this unclear outline of what significant form is right now. Flaubert's "expression of the idea" feels like it aligns perfectly with what I'm trying to say, but unfortunately, he never clarified—and probably couldn't—what he meant by "idea."
As to the value of the æsthetic emotion—it is clearly infinitely removed from those ethical values to which Tolstoy would have confined it. It seems to be as remote from actual life and its practical utilities as the most useless mathematical theorem. One can only say that those who experience it feel it to have a peculiar quality of “reality” which makes it a matter of infinite importance in their lives. Any attempt I might make to explain this would probably land me in the depths of mysticism. On the edge of that gulf I stop.
As for the value of aesthetic emotions—they're obviously far removed from the ethical values that Tolstoy would limit them to. They seem just as distant from real life and its practical uses as the most pointless mathematical theorem. All I can say is that those who experience it feel a unique sense of "reality" that makes it extremely significant in their lives. Any effort I make to explain this would likely plunge me into the depths of mysticism. I’ll stop at the edge of that abyss.
INDEX
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_2__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_3__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_4__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_5__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_6__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_7__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_8__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_9__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_10__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_11__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_12__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_13__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_14__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_15__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_16__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_17__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_18__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_19__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_20__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_21__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_22__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_23__
Albigensian crusade, 99
American and Chinese art, 74
Architecture, domestic, 183
——, styles in, 180
Art and Christianity, 87
—— and the Franciscan movement, 87, 88
—— and Poetry, 194
——, associated ideas in, 159
——, classic, 159
——, emotion and form in, 194
——, public indifference to, 168
——, Realistic, 159
——, Romantic, 159
Artist and the community, 168
——, pure, 175
Asselin, 158
Associated ideas in art, 159
Assisi, upper church at, 103
——, great church at, 87
Assyrian art, 80
“Athenæum,” 52
Author and Cézanne, 191
—— and Gauguin, 191
—— and Impressionists, 190
—— and the public, 192
—— and Old Masters, 190, 191
—— and Seurat, 191
—— and van Goch, 191
—— and Mr. Walter Sickert, 190
—— and Mr. Wilson Steer, 190
Author’s æsthetic, 188, 189
—— house, 180
Aztecs and Incas, 70
Babelon, M., 77
Babylon and Nineveh bas-reliefs, 78
Baldovinetti, 126
—— and Ucello, 126
Baldovinetti’s Madonna and Child, 126
—— portrait in Nat. Gall., 126
—— Trinity; Accademia, Florence, 126
Balfour, Mr., 60
Baroque architect, 136
—— art and Catholic reaction, 138
—— art and Poussin, 138
—— idea and El Greco, 135-139
—— idea and Michelangelo, 136, 138
—— idea and Signorelli, 138
—— in Spanish and Italian art, 138
Bartolommeo, Fra, 164
Bastien-Lepage, 17
Beardsley and Antonio Pollajuolo, 153
—— and Mantegna, 153
—— and Nature, 153
Beardsley’s art, influences on, 153
Beauty, nature of, 193, 194
Beethoven, 19
Bell, Mr. Clive, book on art, 195, 199
Bellini, Giovanni, and Dürer, 133
Berenson, Mr., 100
Bernini and El Greco, 135, 136, 137
Besnard, M., 96, 97
Blake and the Byzantine style, 142
—— and Giotto, 111, 142
—— and the Old Testament, 140, 141
—— and Michelangelo, 141
—— and Tintoretto, 141
—— on poetry, 143
Blake’s temperament, 141
Bleek, Miss, 64
Blow, Mr., 180
Bobrinsky, Prince, 79, 80
Bode, Dr., 134
Bourgeois attitude to art, 168
Bramante, 136
Braque, 158
Bridges, Robert, 147
British public, 190
Browning, 42
Brunelleschi, 4
Bumble, 42
Bushman and Assyrian art, 58
—— and Palæolithic art, 61-63
Byzantine style and Blake, 142
Cabaner, 172
Caravaggio, 5
Cézanne, 42, 158
—— and Delacroix, 173
—— and El Greco, 139
—— and Ingres, 173
—— and Marchand, 184
—— and Poussin, 173
—— and Renoir, 177, 178
—— and Rubens’ method, 173
—— and Tintoretto’s method, 173
—— and Zola, 172
——, criticism of, 156
—— misunderstood by his contemporaries, 169
——, Poussin and El Greco, 138, 139
—— the perfect type of artist, 168, 171
Cézanne’s character, 169, 170, 171
Chateaubriand, 6
Charpentier family, by Renoir, 178
Chelsea Book Club, 65
Chinese and American art, 74
—— and Negro cultures, 67
—— art and Matisse, 158
—— landscape, Claude and, 150
—— painting, 21
Chosroes relief, 78, 79
Christianity and art, 87
Cimabue and Giotto, 103, 106, 107n
Cinematograph, 13
Cinquecento art and Giotto, 114
Classic art, 159
Claude and Chinese landscape, 150
—— and Corot, 150
—— and Turner, 146
Claude and Whistler, 150
——, Ruskin on, 145, 146
—— and Leonardo da Vinci, 146
—— and Rembrandt, 146
—— “Liber Veritatis,” 149
——, influence of Virgil on, 148, 152
Claude’s articulations, 145
—— figures, 146
—— romanticism, 150
Coco style, 29
Colour, Giotto’s, 114
Conceptual art, 62, 63
Contour in painting, 160, 161
Copée, 172
Corot and Claude, 150
—— as a draughtsman, 165
Corot’s drawing of a seated woman, 165
Cosima Tura, 176
Cosmati, 99, 100, 104
Cossa, 132
Credi, Lorenzo di, and Dürer, 133
Critic’s function, 189
Cubism, 192
—— and Marchand, 186
—— and Ucello, 124
Daddi, Bernardo, and Giotto, 108n
Dante, 2, 97, 98, 108, 110, 116
David, 5
“Decorators,” 190
Degas, 20, 176, 190
—— as a draughtsman, 165
Delacroix and Cézanne, 173
Derain, 158, 159, 193
—— and Marchand, 185
Dickens, 175
Dickey Doyle, 153
Doucet, 158
Drama, Italian, beginning of, 101n
Drawing of contours, great examples, 166
—— of the figure, 164
—— of Italian Primitives, 163
—— of Renoir and Ingres compared, 178
——, Persian, 163
Druet’s, M., photographs, 158
Duccio and Giotto, 106
Dürer and the Gothic tradition, 129
—— and Leonardo da Vinci, 127
—— and Lorenzo di Credi, 133
—— and Giovanni Bellini, 133
Dürer and Jacopo de’Barbari, 133
—— and Mantegna, 131, 132
—— and Pollajuolo, 133
—— and Raphael, 127
—— and Schongauer, 132
Dürer’s “Beetle,” 164
—— letters and diary, 127
El Greco and Baroque idea, 135-139
—— and Bernini, 135, 136, 137
—— and British public, 134
—— and Cézanne, 139
——, Poussin and Cézanne, 138, 139
Emotion and form in art, 194, 197
England and French Impressionism, 190
English Art considered, 190
Fatimite textiles, 79
Figure drawing, 164
Filippino Lippi, 163
Flaubert, 199
Flemish and Florentine art, 124
—— painting and Giotto, 110
Florentine art, a characteristic of, 125
—— and Flemish art, 124
Forli, Melozzo da, 104
Form in art, 107
Francesca, Piero della, 4
Franciscan movement and art, 87, 88
Francis, St., 2, 87, 88, 112
French art classic, 158, 159, 184
French, English and Russian art compared, 158
Gamp, Mrs., 97
Gauguin, 158, 175
Germans, the, 129
Ghiberti’s commentary, 87
Giorgione, 175
Giotto and Barnardo Daddi, 108n
—— and Blake, in, 142
—— and Cimabue, 103, 106, 107n
—— and Cinquecento art, 114
—— and classical architecture, 113
—— and Duccio, 106
—— and European art, 115
—— and Flemish painting, 110
—— and Leonardo da Vinci, 116
—— and Lorenzetti, 113
—— and Masaccio, 113
—— and pre-Raphaelitism, 103
Giotto and Raphael, 115
—— and Rembrandt, 110
—— as draughtsman, 115, 116
Giotto’s colour, 114
—— figure of Joachim, 111
—— invention of Tempera, 105
—— Pietà, 110, 198
—— place as an artist, 116
Goethe, 197, 198
Gothic tradition and Dürer, 129, 130
Græco-Roman art, 76, 77, 78
Grunwedel, Dr., 76
Guatemala and Yucatan, 71
Head, Henry, F.R.S., 62
Herbin, 158
Hermitage, 79
Holmes, Mr. C. J., 134
Homer, 97
House, author’s, 180
Houses, architects’, 179
——, builders’, 179
——, dwelling, 180
Huxley, 8
Jacquemart-André collection, 123-126
“Jane Eyre,” 185
Jeremiah of Michelangelo, 23
Johnson, Dr., 65
Joyce, Mr., 69, 73, 75
Kaiser Friedrich Museum, 47, 134
——, the, 47
Karlsruhe Museum, 78
Keats, 147
Keene, Charles, as a draughtsman, 165
Kingsborough, Lord, 71
Kraft’s stonework, 129
Krell, Oswald, 130
Kunsthistorisches Akademie, Vienna, 129
Incas and Aztecs, 70
Ingres, 164
—— and Cézanne, 173
—— as a designer, 163
—— as a draughtsman, 162
——, effect of poverty on his art, 162
Ingres’ drawing, The Apotheosis of Napoleon, 163
—— painting and drawing compared, 163
Lecoq, Dr., 76
Leeche’s drawings, 28
Lehmann, Dr., 74
Leonardo da Vinci, 4, 24
—— and Claude, 146
—— and Dürer, 127
—— and Giotto, 116
L’Hote, 158
——, M., writings of, 192
“Liber Veritatis” of Claude, 149
Limoges enamels, 77
Lincoln Cathedral, 78
Line, the function of, in drawing, 160
——, qualities of, 115
——, rarity of great design expressed in, 163
Loewy, Prof., 56, 57
Lorenzetti and Giotto, 113
Malatesta, Sigismondo, 87
Mantegna and Beardsley, 153
—— and Dürer, 131, 132
—— and Rembrandt, 132
Marchand, 158
——, a classic artist, 184
—— and Cézanne, 184
—— and Cubism, 186
—— and Derain, 185
Masaccio and Giotto, 113
Matisse, 158, 193
—— and Chinese art, 158
—— as a draughtsman, 167
Maya art, 71, 72, 73
Melozzo da Forli, 105
Meredith, 28
Mesopotamian art, 79
Michelangelo, 19, 23, 24, 109
—— and Baroque idea, 136, 138
—— and Blake, 141
Middle Ages, 29
Millais’ drawing, 165
Milton, 147
Minzel as a draughtsman, 165
Modigliani as a draughtsman, 167
Monet, 17, 190
Money, Mr., 48
Music, 15
——, psychology of, 199
National Gallery, 134
Nature, 24, 25
Naturalists, 190
Navicella mosaic, 104
Negro and European sculpture, 66
Neolithic art, 63
Nuremberg school, 130
Old Testament and Blake, 140, 141
Ottley’s prints, 142
Oxford movement, 6
Pall Mall Gazette, 154
Parapluies, Les, by Renoir, 176
Patine, 38, 39
Pelliot, M., 76
Perspective, 124, 125
Picasso, 157, 158, 193
Pietà, by Giotto, 110
Pindar, 87
Pliny on painting, 160, 161
Podsnap, Mr., 179
Poetry and art, 194
——, Blake on, 143
Pollajuolo, Antonio and Beardsley, 153
——, 147
—— and Dürer, 133
Pompeii, 30, 79
Post-Impressionism, 194
Post-Impressionists at the Grafton Gallery, 191, 193
——, criticism of, 156, 157
Poussin, 159
—— and Baroque art, 138
—— and Cézanne, 173
——, El Greco, and Cézanne, 138
Pre-Raphaelite movement, 190
Primitives, study of, in England, 198
Primum Mobile in Tarocchi prints, 133
Psychologists and art, 54
Public indifference to art, 168
Racine, 147
Raphael, 19, 164
—— and Dürer, 127
Raphael’s “Transfiguration,” 196, 198
Realistic art, 159
Rembrandt, 5, 20, 147
—— and Claude, 146
—— and Giotto, 110
—— and Mantegna, 132
—— as a draughtsman, 165, 166
Rembrandt’s characteristics, 165
Renaissance, 76
Renoir and Cézanne, 177, 178, 190
—— and Titian, 178
Renoir compared to Giorgione and Titian, 175
Renoir’s “Charpentier Family,” 178
—— “Les Parapluies,” 176, 178
Robida, 153
Rodin, 38
Romans, the, 129
Romantic art, 159
Romanticism, Claude’s, 150
Ross, Dr. Denman, 21
Rossetti’s relationship to Millais, 165
Rousseau, 156
Rowlandson’s style in drawing, 165
Rubens, 164, 175
Ruskin, 14, 38
—— on Claude, 145, 146
S. Bonaventura, 87, 101, 102
S. Francis, 2, 87, 88, 112
S. Peter’s Crucifixion, by Giotto, 107
Sassanid art, 76, 77, 78, 79, 80
Schongauer and Dürer, 132
Scrovegni, 110
Sculpture, Greek, 57
Shakespeare, 147
Shaw, Mr. Bernard, 41
Shelley, 42
Sickert, Mr. Walter, 175
Sicily, 77
Siegfried, 153
Sigismondo Malatesta, 87
“Significant Form,” 199
Signorelli and Baroque idea, 138
—— and Florence, 126
—— and Ucello, 126
—— and Umbrian art, 126
Signorelli’s Holy Family, 126
Smith, Robertson, 9
Song, psychology of, 199
Spectator of a picture, psychology of, 196, 197
Spencer, Herbert, 8, 9
Stefaneschi, Cardinal, 103, 104, 105, 108n
Stein, Dr., 76
Storr’s woodwork, 129, 130
Subject picture, 53
Sung, 32
Tahiti, 175
Tarrocchi engravings, 132
Tempera, Giotto’s invention, 105
Tennyson, 24, 26
Tiepolo, 161, 162
Tintoretto and Blake, 141
Titian, 19, 175
—— and Renoir compared, 178
Tolstoy, 16, 18, 19
Tolstoy’s “What is Art?” 193, 199
Todi, Jacopone di, 87
Tondo of Michelangelo, 23
Tongue, Miss, 57, 59
Tura, Cosima, 177
Turner and Claude, 146
Tussaud, Mme., 5
Ucello, 4
—— and Baldovinetti, 126
—— and Cubism, 124
Ucello and Van Eyck, 124
—— and perspective, 124, 125
—— and Signorelli, 126
Ucello’s “St. George,” 123, 125
Vandyke, 164
Van Eyck and Ucello, 124
—— Gogh, 158
Varnish, 139
Vasari, 87, 169
—— and Ucello, 123
Victorians and art, 65
Viollet-le-Duc, 185
Virgil’s influence on Claude, 148, 152
Von Tschudi, 139
Waldus, Petrus, 99, 100
Watteau, 164
Wells, H. G., 36
“What is Art?” by Tolstoy, 18
Whistler, 7
—— and Beardsley, 154
—— and Claude, 150
—— and Ruskin, 190
Whistler’s Impressionism, 190
Whittier, 26
Young, Brigham, 74
Yucatan and Guatemala, 71
Zola, 5
—— and Cézanne, 172
Zuloaga, Señor, 155
Albigensian crusade, 99
American and Chinese art, 74
Domestic architecture, 183
——, styles in, 180
Art and Christianity, 87
—— and the Franciscan movement, 87, 88
—— and Poetry, 194
——, associated ideas in, 159
——, classic, 159
——, emotion and form in, 194
——, public indifference to, 168
——, Realistic, 159
——, Romantic, 159
Artist and the community, 168
——, pure, 175
Asselin, 158
Associated ideas in art, 159
Assisi, upper church at, 103
——, great church at, 87
Assyrian art, 80
“Athenæum,” 52
Author and Cézanne, 191
—— and Gauguin, 191
—— and Impressionists, 190
—— and the public, 192
—— and Old Masters, 190, 191
—— and Seurat, 191
—— and van Gogh, 191
—— and Mr. Walter Sickert, 190
—— and Mr. Wilson Steer, 190
Author’s aesthetic, 188, 189
—— house, 180
Aztecs and Incas, 70
Babelon, M., 77
Babylon and Nineveh bas-reliefs, 78
Baldovinetti, 126
—— and Ucello, 126
Baldovinetti’s Madonna and Child, 126
—— portrait in Nat. Gall., 126
—— Trinity; Accademia, Florence, 126
Balfour, Mr., 60
Baroque architect, 136
—— art and Catholic reaction, 138
—— art and Poussin, 138
—— idea and El Greco, 135-139
—— idea and Michelangelo, 136, 138
—— idea and Signorelli, 138
—— in Spanish and Italian art, 138
Bartolommeo, Fra, 164
Bastien-Lepage, 17
Beardsley and Antonio Pollajuolo, 153
—— and Mantegna, 153
—— and Nature, 153
Beardsley’s art, influences on, 153
Beauty, nature of, 193, 194
Beethoven, 19
Bell, Mr. Clive, book on art, 195, 199
Bellini, Giovanni, and Dürer, 133
Berenson, Mr., 100
Bernini and El Greco, 135, 136, 137
Besnard, M., 96, 97
Blake and the Byzantine style, 142
—— and Giotto, 111, 142
—— and the Old Testament, 140, 141
—— and Michelangelo, 141
—— and Tintoretto, 141
—— on poetry, 143
Blake’s temperament, 141
Bleek, Miss, 64
Blow, Mr., 180
Bobrinsky, Prince, 79, 80
Bode, Dr., 134
Bourgeois attitude to art, 168
Bramante, 136
Braque, 158
Bridges, Robert, 147
British public, 190
Browning, 42
Brunelleschi, 4
Bumble, 42
Bushman and Assyrian art, 58
—— and Paleolithic art, 61-63
Byzantine style and Blake, 142
Cabaner, 172
Caravaggio, 5
Cézanne, 42, 158
—— and Delacroix, 173
—— and El Greco, 139
—— and Ingres, 173
—— and Marchand, 184
—— and Poussin, 173
—— and Renoir, 177, 178
—— and Rubens’ method, 173
—— and Tintoretto’s method, 173
—— and Zola, 172
——, criticism of, 156
—— misunderstood by his contemporaries, 169
——, Poussin and El Greco, 138, 139
—— the perfect type of artist, 168, 171
Cézanne’s character, 169, 170, 171
Chateaubriand, 6
Charpentier family, by Renoir, 178
Chelsea Book Club, 65
Chinese and American art, 74
—— and Black cultures, 67
—— art and Matisse, 158
—— landscape, Claude and, 150
—— painting, 21
Chosroes relief, 78, 79
Christianity and art, 87
Cimabue and Giotto, 103, 106, 107n
Cinematograph, 13
Cinquecento art and Giotto, 114
Classic art, 159
Claude and Chinese landscape, 150
—— and Corot, 150
—— and Turner, 146
Claude and Whistler, 150
——, Ruskin on, 145, 146
—— and Leonardo da Vinci, 146
—— and Rembrandt, 146
—— “Liber Veritatis,” 149
——, influence of Virgil on, 148, 152
Claude’s articulations, 145
—— figures, 146
—— romanticism, 150
Coco style, 29
Color, Giotto’s, 114
Conceptual art, 62, 63
Contour in painting, 160, 161
Copée, 172
Corot and Claude, 150
—— as a draftsman, 165
Corot’s drawing of a seated woman, 165
Cosima Tura, 176
Cosmati, 99, 100, 104
Cossa, 132
Credi, Lorenzo di, and Dürer, 133
Critic’s function, 189
Cubism, 192
—— and Marchand, 186
—— and Ucello, 124
Daddy, Bernardo, and Giotto, 108n
Dante, 2, 97, 98, 108, 110, 116
David, 5
“Decorators,” 190
Degas, 20, 176, 190
—— as a draftsman, 165
Delacroix and Cézanne, 173
Derain, 158, 159, 193
—— and Marchand, 185
Dickens, 175
Dickey Doyle, 153
Doucet, 158
Drama, Italian, beginning of, 101n
Drawing of contours, great examples, 166
—— of the figure, 164
—— of Italian Primitives, 163
—— of Renoir and Ingres compared, 178
——, Persian, 163
Druet’s, M., photographs, 158
Duccio and Giotto, 106
Dürer and the Gothic tradition, 129
—— and Leonardo da Vinci, 127
—— and Lorenzo di Credi, 133
—— and Giovanni Bellini, 133
Dürer and Jacopo de’Barbari, 133
—— and Mantegna, 131, 132
—— and Pollajuolo, 133
—— and Raphael, 127
—— and Schongauer, 132
Dürer’s “Beetle,” 164
—— letters and diary, 127
El Greco and Baroque idea, 135-139
—— and Bernini, 135, 136, 137
—— and British public, 134
—— and Cézanne, 139
——, Poussin and Cézanne, 138, 139
Emotion and form in art, 194, 197
England and French Impressionism, 190
English Art considered, 190
Fatimid textiles, 79
Figure drawing, 164
Filippino Lippi, 163
Flaubert, 199
Flemish and Florentine art, 124
—— painting and Giotto, 110
Florentine art, a characteristic of, 125
—— and Flemish art, 124
Forli, Melozzo da, 104
Form in art, 107
Francesca, Piero della, 4
Franciscan movement and art, 87, 88
Francis, St., 2, 87, 88, 112
French art classic, 158, 159, 184
French, English and Russian art compared, 158
Gamp, Mrs., 97
Gauguin, 158, 175
Germans, the, 129
Ghiberti’s commentary, 87
Giorgione, 175
Giotto and Barnardo Daddi, 108n
—— and Blake, in, 142
—— and Cimabue, 103, 106, 107n
—— and Cinquecento art, 114
—— and classical architecture, 113
—— and Duccio, 106
—— and European art, 115
—— and Flemish painting, 110
—— and Leonardo da Vinci, 116
—— and Lorenzetti, 113
—— and Masaccio, 113
—— and pre-Raphaelitism, 103
Giotto and Raphael, 115
—— and Rembrandt, 110
—— as draftsman, 115, 116
Giotto’s color, 114
—— figure of Joachim, 111
—— invention of Tempera, 105
—— Pietà, 110, 198
—— place as an artist, 116
Goethe, 197, 198
Gothic tradition and Dürer, 129, 130
Greco-Roman art, 76, 77, 78
Grunwedel, Dr., 76
Guatemala and Yucatan, 71
Head, Henry, F.R.S., 62
Herbin, 158
Hermitage, 79
Holmes, Mr. C. J., 134
Homer, 97
House, author’s, 180
Houses, architects’, 179
——, builders’, 179
——, dwelling, 180
Huxley, 8
Jacquemart-André collection, 123-126
“Jane Eyre,” 185
Jeremiah of Michelangelo, 23
Johnson, Dr., 65
Joyce, Mr., 69, 73, 75
Kaiser Friedrich Museum, 47, 134
——, the, 47
Karlsruhe Museum, 78
Keats, 147
Keene, Charles, as a draftsman, 165
Kingsborough, Lord, 71
Kraft’s stonework, 129
Krell, Oswald, 130
Kunsthistorisches Akademie, Vienna, 129
Inca Empire and Aztecs, 70
Ingres, 164
—— and Cézanne, 173
—— as a designer, 163
—— as a draftsman, 162
——, effect of poverty on his art, 162
Ingres’ drawing, The Apotheosis of Napoleon, 163
—— painting and drawing compared, 163
Lecoq, Dr., 76
Leeche’s drawings, 28
Lehmann, Dr., 74
Leonardo da Vinci, 4, 24
—— and Claude, 146
—— and Dürer, 127
—— and Giotto, 116
L’Hote, 158
——, M., writings of, 192
“Liber Veritatis” of Claude, 149
Limoges enamels, 77
Lincoln Cathedral, 78
Line, the function of, in drawing, 160
——, qualities of, 115
——, rarity of great design expressed in, 163
Loewy, Prof., 56, 57
Lorenzetti and Giotto, 113
Malatesta, Sigismondo, 87
Mantegna and Beardsley, 153
—— and Dürer, 131, 132
—— and Rembrandt, 132
Marchand, 158
——, a classic artist, 184
—— and Cézanne, 184
—— and Cubism, 186
—— and Derain, 185
Masaccio and Giotto, 113
Matisse, 158, 193
—— and Chinese art, 158
—— as a draftsman, 167
Maya art, 71, 72, 73
Melozzo da Forli, 105
Meredith, 28
Mesopotamian art, 79
Michelangelo, 19, 23, 24, 109
—— and Baroque idea, 136, 138
—— and Blake, 141
Middle Ages, 29
Millais’ drawing, 165
Milton, 147
Minzel as a draftsman, 165
Modigliani as a draftsman, 167
Monet, 17, 190
Money, Mr., 48
Music, 15
——, psychology of, 199
National Gallery, 134
Nature, 24, 25
Naturalists, 190
Navicella mosaic, 104
Black and European sculpture, 66
Neolithic art, 63
Nuremberg school, 130
Old Testament and Blake, 140, 141
Ottley’s prints, 142
Oxford movement, 6
Pall Mall Gazette, 154
Parapluies, Les, by Renoir, 176
Patine, 38, 39
Pelliot, M., 76
Perspective, 124, 125
Picasso, 157, 158, 193
Pietà, by Giotto, 110
Pindar, 87
Pliny on painting, 160, 161
Podsnap, Mr., 179
Poetry and art, 194
——, Blake on, 143
Pollajuolo, Antonio and Beardsley, 153
——, 147
—— and Dürer, 133
Pompeii, 30, 79
Post-Impressionism, 194
Post-Impressionists at the Grafton Gallery, 191, 193
——, criticism of, 156, 157
Poussin, 159
—— and Baroque art, 138
—— and Cézanne, 173
——, El Greco, and Cézanne, 138
Pre-Raphaelite movement, 190
Primitives, study of, in England, 198
Primum Mobile in Tarocchi prints, 133
Psychologists and art, 54
Public indifference to art, 168
Racine, 147
Raphael, 19, 164
—— and Dürer, 127
Raphael’s “Transfiguration,” 196, 198
Realistic art, 159
Rembrandt, 5, 20, 147
—— and Claude, 146
—— and Giotto, 110
—— and Mantegna, 132
—— as a draftsman, 165, 166
Rembrandt’s characteristics, 165
Renaissance, 76
Renoir and Cézanne, 177, 178, 190
—— and Titian, 178
Renoir compared to Giorgione and Titian, 175
Renoir’s “Charpentier Family,” 178
—— “Les Parapluies,” 176, 178
Robida, 153
Rodin, 38
Romans, the, 129
Romantic art, 159
Romanticism, Claude’s, 150
Ross, Dr. Denman, 21
Rossetti’s relationship to Millais, 165
Rousseau, 156
Rowlandson’s style in drawing, 165
Rubens, 164, 175
Ruskin, 14, 38
—— on Claude, 145, 146
S. Bonaventure, 87, 101, 102
S. Francis, 2, 87, 88, 112
S. Peter’s Crucifixion, by Giotto, 107
Sassanid art, 76, 77, 78, 79, 80
Schongauer and Dürer, 132
Scrovegni, 110
Sculpture, Greek, 57
Shakespeare, 147
Shaw, Mr. Bernard, 41
Shelley, 42
Sickert, Mr. Walter, 175
Sicily, 77
Siegfried, 153
Sigismondo Malatesta, 87
“Significant Form,” 199
Signorelli and Baroque idea, 138
—— and Florence, 126
—— and Ucello, 126
—— and Umbrian art, 126
Signorelli’s Holy Family, 126
Smith, Robertson, 9
Song, psychology of, 199
Spectator of a picture, psychology of, 196, 197
Spencer, Herbert, 8, 9
Stefaneschi, Cardinal, 103, 104, 105, 108n
Stein, Dr., 76
Storr’s woodwork, 129, 130
Subject picture, 53
Sung, 32
Tahiti, 175
Tarrocchi engravings, 132
Tempera, Giotto’s invention, 105
Tennyson, 24, 26
Tiepolo, 161, 162
Tintoretto and Blake, 141
Titian, 19, 175
—— and Renoir compared, 178
Tolstoy, 16, 18, 19
Tolstoy’s “What is Art?” 193, 199
Todi, Jacopone di, 87
Tondo of Michelangelo, 23
Tongue, Miss, 57, 59
Tura, Cosima, 177
Turner and Claude, 146
Tussaud, Mme., 5
THE END
PRINTED IN ENGLAND BY WILLIAM CLOWES AND SONS, LIMITED, LONDON AND
BECCLES.
THE END
PRINTED IN ENGLAND BY WILLIAM CLOWES AND SONS, LIMITED, LONDON AND
BECCLES.
FOOTNOTES:
FOOTNOTES:
[2] New Quarterly, 1909.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ New Quarterly, 1909.
[3] Rodin is reported to have said, “A woman, a mountain, a horse—they are all the same thing; they are made on the same principles.” That is to say, their forms, when viewed with the disinterested vision of the imaginative life, have similar emotional elements.
[3] Rodin reportedly said, “A woman, a mountain, a horse—they're all the same thing; they're created on the same principles.” In other words, their shapes, when seen through the objective lens of imaginative thought, share similar emotional qualities.
[4] I do not forget that at the death of Tennyson the writer in the Daily Telegraph averred that “level beams of the setting moon streamed in upon the face of the dying bard”; but then, after all, in its way the Daily Telegraph is a work of art.
[4] I remember that when Tennyson passed away, a writer from the Daily Telegraph claimed that “even rays of the setting moon illuminated the face of the dying poet”; but, in its own way, the Daily Telegraph is a piece of art.
[5] Athenæum, 1919.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Athenæum, 1919.
[6] Athenæum, 1919.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Athenæum, 1919.
[8] Athenæum, 1919.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Athenæum, 1919.
[9] Burlington Magazine, 1910.
Burlington Magazine, 1910.
[12] This absence of decorative feeling may be due to the irregular and vague outlines of the picture space. It is when the picture must be fitted within determined limits that decoration begins. I have noticed that children’s drawings are never decorative when they have the whole surface of a sheet of paper to draw on, but they will design a frieze with well-marked rhythm when they have only a narrow strip.
[12] This lack of decorative quality might be because of the irregular and unclear shapes in the picture space. Decoration starts when the picture needs to fit into specific boundaries. I've noticed that children's drawings aren't decorative when they have a whole sheet of paper to work with, but they'll create a frieze with a clear rhythm when they have just a narrow strip.
[14] Athenæum, 1920.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Athenæum, 1920.
[15] Burlington Magazine, 1918.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Burlington Magazine, 1918.
[16] Thomas A. Joyce, (1) “South American Archæology,” London (Macmillan), 1912; (2) “Mexican Archæology,” London (Lee Warner), 1914; (3) “Central American Archæology,” London and New York (Putnam), 1916.
[16] Thomas A. Joyce, (1) “South American Archaeology,” London (Macmillan), 1912; (2) “Mexican Archaeology,” London (Lee Warner), 1914; (3) “Central American Archaeology,” London and New York (Putnam), 1916.
[18] Burlington Magazine, 1910.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Burlington Magazine, 1910.
[20] I cannot help calling attention, though without any attempt at explaining it, to the striking similarity to these Sassanid and early Mohammedan water jugs shown by an example of Sung pottery lent by Mr. Eumorfopoulos to the recent exhibition at the Burlington Fine Arts Club, Case A, No. 43. Here a very similar form of spout is modelled into a phœnix’s head.
[20] I can't help but point out, without trying to explain it, the remarkable resemblance between these Sassanid and early Islamic water jugs and an example of Sung pottery that Mr. Eumorfopoulos lent to the recent exhibition at the Burlington Fine Arts Club, Case A, No. 43. In this piece, a very similar shape for the spout is crafted into a phoenix's head.
[21] The following, from the Monthly Review, 1901, is perhaps more than any other article here reprinted, at variance with the more recent expressions of my æsthetic ideas. It will be seen that great emphasis is laid on Giotto’s expression of the dramatic idea in his pictures. I still think this is perfectly true so far as it goes, nor do I doubt that an artist like Giotto did envisage such an expression. Where I should be inclined to disagree is that there underlies this article a tacit assumption not only that the dramatic idea may have inspired the artist to the creation of his form, but that the value of the form for us is bound up without recognition of the dramatic idea. It now seems to me possible by a more searching analysis of our experience in front of a work of art to disentangle our reaction to pure form from our reaction to its implied associated ideas.
[21] The following excerpt from the Monthly Review, 1901, is probably more inconsistent with my current aesthetic ideas than any other article included here. It emphasizes Giotto’s portrayal of dramatic themes in his artwork. I still believe this is absolutely true to some extent, and I have no doubt that an artist like Giotto aimed to convey such expressions. However, I would argue that this article assumes that the dramatic theme not only inspired the artist's creative process but also that the value of the artwork for us is tied to the recognition of that dramatic theme. It now seems to me possible, through a more in-depth analysis of our experience when viewing a piece of art, to separate our response to pure form from our response to its underlying associated ideas.
[22] Cf. H. Thode: “Franz von Assisi.”
[24] One picture, however, ascribed by Vasari to Cimabue, namely, the Madonna of the National Gallery, does not bear the characteristics of this group. Dr. Richter’s argument for giving the Rucellai painting to Duccio depends largely on the likeness of this to the Maesta, but there is no reason to cling so closely to Vasari’s attributions. If we except the National Gallery Madonna, which shows the characteristics of the Siennese school, these pictures, including the Rucellai Madonna, will be found to cohere by many common peculiarities not shared by Duccio. Among these we may notice the following: The eye has the upper eyelid strongly marked; it has a peculiar languishing expression, due in part to the large elliptical iris (Duccio’s eyes have a small, bright, round iris with a keen expression); the nose is distinctly articulated into three segments; the mouth is generally slewed round from the perpendicular; the hands are curiously curved, and in all the Madonnas clutch the supports of the throne; the hair bows seen upon the halos have a constant and quite peculiar shape; the drapery is designed in rectilinear triangular folds, very different from Duccio’s more sinuous and flowing line. The folds of the drapery where they come to the contour of the figure have no effect upon the form of the outline, an error which Duccio never makes. Finally, the thrones in all these pictures have a constant form; they are made of turned wood with a high footstool, and are seen from the side; Duccio’s is of stone and seen from the front. That the Rucellai Madonna has a morbidezza which is wanting in the earlier works can hardly be considered a sufficient distinction to set against the formal characteristics. It is clearly a later work, painted probably about the year 1300, and Cimabue, like all the other artists of the time, was striving constantly in the direction of greater fusion of tones.
[24] One painting, however, attributed by Vasari to Cimabue, specifically the Madonna of the National Gallery, does not feature the traits of this group. Dr. Richter’s argument for assigning the Rucellai painting to Duccio is largely based on its similarity to the Maesta, but there’s no need to stick so closely to Vasari’s attributions. If we exclude the National Gallery Madonna, which displays the characteristics of the Siennese school, these paintings, including the Rucellai Madonna, share many common features that Duccio does not have. Some of these include: The eyes have a pronounced upper eyelid; they have a unique, dreamy expression, partly due to the large elliptical iris (Duccio’s eyes have small, bright, round irises with an intense expression); the nose is clearly divided into three sections; the mouth is usually tilted away from vertical; the hands are oddly curved, and all the Madonnas grip the throne supports; the hair bows on the halos have a consistent and quite distinctive shape; the drapery is designed in straight triangular folds, very different from Duccio’s more flowing and sinuous lines. The folds of the drapery where they meet the figure’s outline do not alter the form of the outline, a mistake that Duccio never makes. Lastly, the thrones in all these paintings have a consistent design; they are made of turned wood with a high footstool and are viewed from the side; Duccio’s is made of stone and seen from the front. The fact that the Rucellai Madonna has a softness that is lacking in the earlier works can hardly be a strong enough distinction to outweigh the formal characteristics. It is clearly a later work, painted probably around the year 1300, and Cimabue, like all other artists of that time, was constantly trying to achieve a greater blending of tones.
[25] I should speak now both with greater confidence and much greater enthusiasm of Cimabue. The attempt of certain scholars to dispose of him as a myth has broken down. The late Mr. H. P. Horne found that the documents cited by Dr. Richter to prove that Duccio executed the Rucellai Madonna referred to another picture. I had also failed in my estimate to consider fully the superb crucifix by Cimabue in the Museum of Sta. Croce, a work of supreme artistic merit. In general my defence of Cimabue, though right enough as far as it goes, appears to me too timid and my estimate of his artistic quality far too low (1920).
[25] I should now speak with more confidence and much greater enthusiasm about Cimabue. The efforts of some scholars to dismiss him as a myth have fallen short. The late Mr. H. P. Horne discovered that the documents Dr. Richter used to argue that Duccio created the Rucellai Madonna actually referred to a different painting. I also neglected to fully consider the stunning crucifix by Cimabue in the Museum of Sta. Croce, which is a masterpiece of artistic quality. Overall, my defense of Cimabue, while valid to an extent, seems too cautious, and my assessment of his artistic talent is far too low (1920).
[26] The important position here assigned to the Roman school has been confirmed by the subsequent discovery of Cavallini’s frescoes in Sta. Cecilia at Rome (1920).
[26] The significant role given to the Roman school has been validated by the later discovery of Cavallini’s frescoes in Sta. Cecilia in Rome (1920).
[27] “Drunken with the love of compassion of Christ, the blessed Francis would at times do such-like things as this; for the passing sweet melody of the spirit within him, seething over outwardly, did often find utterance in the French tongue, and the strain of the divine whisper that his ear had caught would break forth into a French song of joyous exulting.” Then pretending with two sticks to play a viol, “and making befitting gestures, (he) would sing in French of our Lord Jesus Christ.”—“The Mirror of Perfection,” edited by P. Sabatier, transl. by S. Evans.
[27] “Filled with Christ’s compassion, the blessed Francis would sometimes do things like this; the sweet melody of the spirit within him would often spill out in French, and the divine whispers he heard would break into joyful French songs.” Then, pretending to play the violin with two sticks, “and making fitting gestures, (he) would sing in French about our Lord Jesus Christ.”—“The Mirror of Perfection,” edited by P. Sabatier, transl. by S. Evans.
[29] This was the first “representation” of the kind in Italy, and is of interest as being the beginning of the Italian Drama, and also of that infinite series of allegorical pageants, sometimes sacred, sometimes secular, which for three centuries played such a prominent part in city life and affected Italian art very intimately.
[29] This was the first “representation” of its kind in Italy, and it’s significant as the start of Italian Drama, as well as the beginning of the countless allegorical pageants, sometimes religious and sometimes secular, that played a major role in city life for three centuries and deeply influenced Italian art.
[30] The Master of the Cecilia altar-piece has been the object of much research since this article was written, and a considerable number of important works are now ascribed to him with some confidence. He has been tentatively identified with Buffalonaceo by Dr. Siren. See Burl. Mag., December, 1919; January, October, 1920.
[30] The artist behind the Cecilia altar piece has been the subject of extensive study since this article was published, and many significant works are now confidently attributed to him. Dr. Siren has tentatively linked him to Buffalonaceo. See Burl. Mag., December 1919; January, October 1920.
[31] This quality is to be distinguished from that conscious naturalistic study of atmospheric envelopment which engrossed the attention of some artists of the cinquecento; it is a decorative quality which may occur at any period in the development of painting if only an artist arises gifted with a sufficiently delicate sensitiveness to the surface-quality of his work.
[31] This quality is different from the deliberate naturalistic focus on atmosphere that captured the interest of some artists during the Renaissance; it’s a decorative quality that can appear at any point in the evolution of painting, as long as an artist emerges who has the delicate sensitivity needed to appreciate the surface quality of their work.
[34] The attribution of the Stefaneschi altar-piece to Giotto is much disputed and some authorities give it to Bernardo Daddi. I still incline to the idea that it is the work of Giotto and the starting point of Bernardo Daddi’s style (1920).
[34] The assignment of the Stefaneschi altar-piece to Giotto is widely debated, with some experts attributing it to Bernardo Daddi. I still lean towards the belief that it is Giotto’s work and the foundation of Bernardo Daddi’s style (1920).
[35] His name was Bianchi. ‘Faut il se plaindre,’ says M. Maurice Denis in his Théories, ‘qu’un Bianchi, plutôt que les laisser périr, ait ajouté un peu de la froidure de Flandrin aux fresques de Giotto à Santa Croce.’
[35] His name was Bianchi. "Should we complain," says M. Maurice Denis in his Théories, "that a Bianchi, rather than letting them fade away, added a bit of Flandrin's coolness to Giotto's frescoes at Santa Croce?"
[38] Burlington Magazine, 1914.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Burlington Magazine, 1914.
[40] See Plate, where I have also added Dürer’s version of the subject. This is of course a new design and not a copy of Mantegna’s drawing, though I suspect it is based on a vague memory of it. In any case it shows admirably the distinguishing points of Dürer’s methods of conception, his love of complexity, and his accumulation of decorative detail.
[40] See Plate, where I’ve also included Dürer’s take on the subject. This is definitely a new design and not a copy of Mantegna’s drawing, although I think it’s probably based on a vague recollection of it. In any case, it beautifully highlights the key features of Dürer’s creative approach, his appreciation for complexity, and his rich decorative detail.
[41] Athenæum, 1920.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Athenæum, 1920.
[42] Burlington Magazine, 1904.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Burlington Magazine, 1904.
[44] Burlington Magazine, 1907.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Burlington Magazine, 1907.
[46] It is not impossible that Claude got the hint for such a treatment as this from the impressionist efforts of Græco-Roman painters. That he studied such works we know from a copy of one by him in the British Museum.
[46] It’s possible that Claude was inspired to create this kind of treatment by the impressionist styles of Greco-Roman painters. We know he studied these works because there’s a copy of one of his in the British Museum.
[47] Athenæum, 1904.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Athenæum, 1904.
[49] Burlington Magazine, 1912.
Burlington Magazine, 1912.
[50] I have had to paraphrase this passage, but add the original. Whether my paraphrase is correct in detail or not, I think there can be little doubt about the general meaning.
[50] I've had to rephrase this passage, but I've included the original. Regardless of whether my rephrasing is accurate in every detail, I believe there is little doubt about the overall meaning.
Plin., Nat. Hist., xxxv. 67: “Parrhasius ... confessione artificum in liniis extremis palmam adeptus. Hæc est picturæ summa sublimitas; corpora enim pingere et media rerum est quidem magni operis, sed in quo multi gloriam tulerint. Extrema corporum facere et desinentis picturæ modum includere rarum in successu artis invenitur. Ambire enim debet se extremitas ipsa, et sic desinere ut promittat alia post se ostendatque etiam quae occultat.”
Plin., Nat. Hist., xxxv. 67: “Parrhasius... through the artists' confession, became the best in the finishing touches. This is the utmost excellence of painting; for capturing the body in its entirety is indeed a great achievement, but many have earned glory in that. To depict the extremities of the body and to include the limits of the painting is a rare success in the art. The extremity itself should strive to stand out and thus conclude in a way that promises more to be shown and reveals even what it conceals.”
[54] Vogue, 1918.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Vogue, 1918.
[55] Athenæum, 1919.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Athenæum, 1919.
[56] 1920.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ 1920.
Download ePUB
If you like this ebook, consider a donation!