This is a modern-English version of A Defence of Poetry and Other Essays, originally written by Shelley, Percy Bysshe. It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.









A DEFENCE OF POETRY AND OTHER ESSAYS

By Percy Bysshe Shelley










CONTENTS

TABLE OF CONTENTS










ON LOVE

What is love? Ask him who lives, what is life? ask him who adores, what is God?

What is love? Ask someone who is alive, what is life? Ask someone who worships, what is God?

I know not the internal constitution of other men, nor even thine, whom I now address. I see that in some external attributes they resemble me, but when, misled by that appearance, I have thought to appeal to something in common, and unburthen my inmost soul to them, I have found my language misunderstood, like one in a distant and savage land. The more opportunities they have afforded me for experience, the wider has appeared the interval between us, and to a greater distance have the points of sympathy been withdrawn. With a spirit ill fitted to sustain such proof, trembling and feeble through its tenderness, I have everywhere sought sympathy and have found only repulse and disappointment.

I don't know the inner workings of other people, or even yours, to whom I now speak. I see that in some outward traits they are like me, but when I’ve mistakenly thought that we shared something in common and tried to open up my deepest feelings to them, I've discovered that they misunderstand me, like someone in a remote and wild place. The more chances they’ve given me to experience this, the greater the gap between us seems, and the points of connection have moved further away. With a spirit that isn’t strong enough to handle such trials, trembling and weak because of its sensitivity, I’ve sought understanding everywhere and have only found rejection and disappointment.

Thou demandest what is love? It is that powerful attraction towards all that we conceive, or fear, or hope beyond ourselves, when we find within our own thoughts the chasm of an insufficient void, and seek to awaken in all things that are, a community with what we experience within ourselves. If we reason, we would be understood; if we imagine, we would that the airy children of our brain were born anew within another's; if we feel, we would that another's nerves should vibrate to our own, that the beams of their eyes should kindle at once and mix and melt into our own, that lips of motionless ice should not reply to lips quivering and burning with the heart's best blood. This is Love. This is the bond and the sanction which connects not only man with man, but with everything which exists. We are born into the world, and there is something within us which, from the instant that we live, more and more thirsts after its likeness. It is probably in correspondence with this law that the infant drains milk from the bosom of its mother; this propensity develops itself with the development of our nature. We dimly see within our intellectual nature a miniature as it were of our entire self, yet deprived of all that we condemn or despise, the ideal prototype of everything excellent or lovely that we are capable of conceiving as belonging to the nature of man. Not only the portrait of our external being, but an assemblage of the minutest particles of which our nature is composed;[Footnote: These words are ineffectual and metaphorical. Most words are so—No help!] a mirror whose surface reflects only the forms of purity and brightness; a soul within our soul that describes a circle around its proper paradise, which pain, and sorrow, and evil dare not overleap. To this we eagerly refer all sensations, thirsting that they should resemble or correspond with it. The discovery of its antitype; the meeting with an understanding capable of clearly estimating our own; an imagination which should enter into and seize upon the subtle and delicate peculiarities which we have delighted to cherish and unfold in secret; with a frame whose nerves, like the chords of two exquisite lyres, strung to the accompaniment of one delightful voice, vibrate with the vibrations of our own; and of a combination of all these in such proportion as the type within demands; this is the invisible and unattainable point to which Love tends; and to attain which, it urges forth the powers of man to arrest the faintest shadow of that, without the possession of which there is no rest nor respite to the heart over which it rules. Hence in solitude, or in that deserted state when we are surrounded by human beings, and yet they sympathize not with us, we love the flowers, the grass, and the waters, and the sky. In the motion of the very leaves of spring, in the blue air, there is then found a secret correspondence with our heart. There is eloquence in the tongueless wind, and a melody in the flowing brooks and the rustling of the reeds beside them, which by their inconceivable relation to something within the soul, awaken the spirits to a dance of breathless rapture, and bring tears of mysterious tenderness to the eyes, like the enthusiasm of patriotic success, or the voice of one beloved singing to you alone. Sterne says that, if he were in a desert, he would love some cypress. So soon as this want or power is dead, man becomes the living sepulchre of himself, and what yet survives is the mere husk of what once he was.

What is love, you ask? It's that powerful pull towards everything we imagine, fear, or hope for that goes beyond ourselves. When we feel the emptiness within our thoughts, we seek to find a connection with everything around us that mirrors what we experience inside. If we think, we want to be understood; if we dream, we wish our thoughts could be brought to life in someone else; if we feel, we hope that another's nerves resonate with ours, that their eyes ignite and blend with ours, and that lips filled with desire respond to ours instead of staying cold and unmoving. This is love. It’s the bond that connects not just people to one another, but all of existence. We come into this world with a deep longing for what reflects ourselves. Perhaps this is why a baby instinctively seeks nourishment from its mother. This need grows as we develop. We have a fuzzy vision of a smaller version of ourselves within our minds, stripped of all we find shameful or unworthy—a perfect image of everything wonderful and beautiful we can imagine as part of human nature. It’s not just a reflection of our outer selves but a collection of the tiniest details that make us who we are; a mirror that only shows purity and light; a soul within our soul that draws a circle around its own paradise, untouched by pain, sorrow, or evil. We crave all experiences to align with this ideal. Finding its counterpart; meeting someone who can truly understand us; an imagination that captures the subtle and delicate traits we cherish in secret; a connection of souls that resonates like two beautiful lyres playing in harmony; and a combination of all of this according to our inner ideal—this is the unseen and unreachable goal of love. It drives us to seek even the slightest reflection of this ideal, without which our hearts find no rest. That’s why in moments of solitude or when we’re surrounded by people who don’t connect with us, we turn our affection to flowers, grass, water, and the sky. In the whispers of spring leaves or the blue air, we sense a secret link to our hearts. There’s expression in the wind that cannot speak, and music in the flowing streams and rustling reeds that stirs our souls into a joyful dance and brings tears of deep emotion to our eyes, much like the thrill of a victory or the voice of a loved one singing just for us. Sterne said if he were in a desert, he would love a cypress tree. But when that longing or power is gone, a person becomes a living tomb, and what remains is just the shell of who they once were.

[1815; publ. 1840]

[1815; published 1840]

ON LIFE

Life and the world, or whatever we call that which we are and feel, is an astonishing thing. The mist of familiarity obscures from us the wonder of our being. We are struck with admiration at some of its transient modifications, but it is itself the great miracle. What are changes of empires, the wreck of dynasties, with the opinions which supported them; what is the birth and the extinction of religious and of political systems to life? What are the revolutions of the globe which we inhabit, and the operations of the elements of which it is composed, compared with life? What is the universe of stars, and suns, of which this inhabited earth is one, and their motions, and their destiny, compared with life? Life, the great miracle, we admire not, because it is so miraculous. It is well that we are thus shielded by the familiarity of what is at once so certain and so unfathomable, from an astonishment which would otherwise absorb and overawe the functions of that which is its object.

Life and the world, or whatever we call our existence and feelings, is truly amazing. The haze of familiarity hides the wonder of our being from us. We admire some of its fleeting changes, but it is the essence of life itself that is the real miracle. What do the rise and fall of empires, the collapse of dynasties, and the beliefs that supported them mean in the grand scheme of life? What significance do the birth and death of religious and political systems have compared to life? What are the revolutions of the planet we live on, and the forces that shape it, next to life itself? What is the universe filled with stars and suns, of which our planet is just one, and their movements and destinies, compared to life? Life, the great miracle, often goes unappreciated because it is so miraculous. It’s a good thing we are protected by the familiarity of what is both certain and profoundly deep, shielding us from an awe that could otherwise overwhelm our understanding of it.

If any artist, I do not say had executed, but had merely conceived in his mind the system of the sun, and the stars, and planets, they not existing, and had painted to us in words, or upon canvas, the spectacle now afforded by the nightly cope of heaven, and illustrated it by the wisdom of astronomy, great would be our admiration. Or had he imagined the scenery of this earth, the mountains, the seas, and the rivers; the grass, and the flowers, and the variety of the forms and masses of the leaves of the woods, and the colours which attend the setting and the rising sun, and the hues of the atmosphere, turbid or serene, these things not before existing, truly we should have been astonished, and it would not have been a vain boast to have said of such a man, 'Non merita nome di creatore, se non Iddio ed il Poeta.' But now these things are looked on with little wonder, and to be conscious of them with intense delight is esteemed to be the distinguishing mark of a refined and extraordinary person. The multitude of men care not for them. It is thus with Life—that which includes all.

If any artist, I do not suggest he had actually created, but had only imagined in his mind the system of the sun, stars, and planets, none of which existed, and had described to us in words or depicted on canvas the spectacle we now see in the night sky, backed by the knowledge of astronomy, we would admire it greatly. Or if he had envisioned the scenery of this earth—the mountains, seas, and rivers; the grass and flowers; the various shapes and sizes of tree leaves; and the colors that come with the sunrise and sunset, along with the shades of the atmosphere, whether cloudy or clear—these things not yet in existence, we would truly be astonished, and it wouldn’t be an empty boast to say of such a man, 'He does not deserve the name of creator, except God and the Poet.' But now these things are seen with little wonder, and to experience them with deep joy is considered the mark of a refined and exceptional person. The majority of people are indifferent to them. It is the same with Life—that which encompasses everything.

What is life? Thoughts and feelings arise, with or without our will, and we employ words to express them. We are born, and our birth is unremembered, and our infancy remembered but in fragments; we live on, and in living we lose the apprehension of life. How vain is it to think that words can penetrate the mystery of our being! Rightly used they may make evident our ignorance to ourselves, and this is much. For what are we? Whence do we come? and whither do we go? Is birth the commencement, is death the conclusion of our being? What is birth and death?

What is life? Thoughts and feelings come up, whether we want them to or not, and we use words to express them. We are born, and we don't remember our birth, and our early childhood is remembered only in bits and pieces; we continue living, and in doing so, we forget the essence of life. How pointless it is to think that words can truly uncover the mystery of our existence! When used properly, they can reveal our own ignorance, and that is significant. So, who are we? Where do we come from? And where are we headed? Is birth the beginning, and is death the end of our existence? What do birth and death really mean?

The most refined abstractions of logic conduct to a view of life, which, though startling to the apprehension, is, in fact, that which the habitual sense of its repeated combinations has extinguished in us. It strips, as it were, the painted curtain from this scene of things. I confess that I am one of those who are unable to refuse my assent to the conclusions of those philosophers who assert that nothing exists but as it is perceived.

The most sophisticated ideas of logic lead to a perspective on life that, although surprising at first, is actually something our usual sense of its repeated patterns has dulled in us. It removes, in a way, the decorative curtain from the stage of reality. I admit that I am one of those who cannot disagree with the philosophers who claim that nothing exists except as it is perceived.

It is a decision against which all our persuasions struggle, and we must be long convicted before we can be convinced that the solid universe of external things is 'such stuff as dreams are made of.' The shocking absurdities of the popular philosophy of mind and matter, its fatal consequences in morals, and their violent dogmatism concerning the source of all things, had early conducted me to materialism. This materialism is a seducing system to young and superficial minds. It allows its disciples to talk, and dispenses them from thinking. But I was discontented with such a view of things as it afforded; man is a being of high aspirations, 'looking both before and after,' whose 'thoughts wander through eternity,' disclaiming alliance with transience and decay; incapable of imagining to himself annihilation; existing but in the future and the past; being, not what he is, but what he has been and shall be. Whatever may be his true and final destination, there is a spirit within him at enmity with nothingness and dissolution. This is the character of all life and being. Each is at once the centre and the circumference; the point to which all things are referred, and the line in which all things are contained. Such contemplations as these, materialism and the popular philosophy of mind and matter alike forbid; they are only consistent with the intellectual system.

Making this choice is something we struggle against, and it takes a long time to truly believe that the solid universe of external things is 'made of the same stuff as dreams.' The shocking absurdities of the common philosophy regarding mind and matter, along with its disastrous consequences for morals and its dogmatic claims about the origins of everything, initially pushed me toward materialism. This materialism is an enticing ideology for young and shallow thinkers. It lets followers talk without requiring them to think deeply. However, I was unhappy with the perspective it offered; humans are beings with great aspirations, 'looking both before and after,' whose 'thoughts wander through eternity,' rejecting any connection to fleeting existence and decay; they cannot even imagine being annihilated; they exist only in the future and the past; they are not just what they are but also what they have been and will become. Regardless of where they ultimately end up, there is a spirit within them that opposes nothingness and decay. This is the essence of all life and existence. Each one is both the center and the boundary; the point to which everything is related and the line in which everything exists. Such thoughts as these are forbidden by materialism and the common views on mind and matter; they only align with a deeper intellectual approach.

It is absurd to enter into a long recapitulation of arguments sufficiently familiar to those inquiring minds, whom alone a writer on abstruse subjects can be conceived to address. Perhaps the most clear and vigorous statement of the intellectual system is to be found in Sir William Drummond's Academical Questions.

It’s pointless to go over a long summary of arguments that are already well-known to those curious minds, who are the only audience a writer on complex topics can realistically address. The most clear and strong explanation of the intellectual system can likely be found in Sir William Drummond's Academical Questions.

After such an exposition, it would be idle to translate into other words what could only lose its energy and fitness by the change. Examined point by point, and word by word, the most discriminating intellects have been able to discern no train of thoughts in the process of reasoning, which does not conduct inevitably to the conclusion which has been stated.

After such an explanation, it would be pointless to put it into different words that would only weaken its impact and relevance. When looked at carefully, word by word, even the sharpest minds have found no line of reasoning that doesn't lead directly to the conclusion that has been presented.

What follows from the admission? It establishes no new truth, it gives us no additional insight into our hidden nature, neither its action nor itself. Philosophy, impatient as it may be to build, has much work yet remaining, as pioneer for the overgrowth of ages. It makes one step towards this object; it destroys error, and the roots of error. It leaves, what it is too often the duty of the reformer in political and ethical questions to leave, a vacancy. It reduces the mind to that freedom in which it would have acted, but for the misuse of words and signs, the instruments of its own creation. By signs, I would be understood in a wide sense, including what is properly meant by that term, and what I peculiarly mean. In this latter sense, almost all familiar objects are signs, standing, not for themselves, but for others, in their capacity of suggesting one thought which shall lead to a train of thoughts. Our whole life is thus an education of error.

What does the admission lead to? It doesn't establish any new truths or give us deeper insight into our hidden nature, nor does its action or itself. Philosophy, though it might be eager to build, still has a lot of work left to do, acting as a pioneer through the growth of ages. It takes a step toward this goal; it eliminates falsehood and the roots of falsehood. It often leaves behind what reformers in political and ethical matters have to leave—a void. It brings the mind to that freedom it would have acted upon, if not for the misuse of words and signs, the very tools of its own making. By "signs," I mean this in a broad sense, including what is generally understood by that term and what I specifically refer to. In this latter sense, nearly all familiar objects are signs, representing not themselves but others, suggesting a thought that leads to a series of thoughts. Our entire life is thus an education of error.

Let us recollect our sensations as children. What a distinct and intense apprehension had we of the world and of ourselves! Many of the circumstances of social life were then important to us which are now no longer so. But that is not the point of comparison on which I mean to insist. We less habitually distinguished all that we saw and felt, from ourselves. They seemed as it were to constitute one mass. There are some persons who, in this respect, are always children. Those who are subject to the state called reverie, feel as if their nature were dissolved into the surrounding universe, or as if the surrounding universe were absorbed into their being. They are conscious of no distinction. And these are states which precede, or accompany, or follow an unusually intense and vivid apprehension of life. As men grow up this power commonly decays, and they become mechanical and habitual agents. Thus feelings and then reasonings are the combined result of a multitude of entangled thoughts, and of a series of what are called impressions, planted by reiteration.

Let’s remember our feelings as kids. We had such a clear and strong understanding of the world and ourselves! Many aspects of social life were really important to us back then that just don’t matter anymore. But that’s not the main comparison I want to make. We didn’t often separate what we saw and felt from ourselves. They seemed, in a way, to form a single whole. Some people are always like this in this regard. Those who experience a state called reverie feel as if their essence is merged with the universe around them, or as if the universe has become part of them. They don’t sense any separation. These are states that come before, during, or after an unusually intense and vivid experience of life. As people grow older, this ability usually fades, and they start to become mechanical, routine-driven beings. So, feelings and their subsequent thoughts are the result of a tangled mix of many ideas and a series of what we call impressions, reinforced by repetition.

The view of life presented by the most refined deductions of the intellectual philosophy, is that of unity. Nothing exists but as it is perceived. The difference is merely nominal between those two classes of thought, which are vulgarly distinguished by the names of ideas and of external objects. Pursuing the same thread of reasoning, the existence of distinct individual minds, similar to that which is employed in now questioning its own nature, is likewise found to be a delusion. The words I, YOU, THEY, are not signs of any actual difference subsisting between the assemblage of thoughts thus indicated, but are merely marks employed to denote the different modifications of the one mind.

The perspective on life offered by the most sophisticated conclusions of intellectual philosophy is one of unity. Nothing exists except as it is perceived. The distinction between the two categories of thought, commonly referred to as ideas and external objects, is merely a name. Following the same line of reasoning, the existence of separate individual minds, akin to the one that is currently questioning its own nature, is also shown to be an illusion. The words I, YOU, THEY are not indicators of any real difference between the collection of thoughts they represent; they are simply labels used to denote the various changes of the one mind.

Let it not be supposed that this doctrine conducts to the monstrous presumption that I, the person who now write and think, am that one mind. I am but a portion of it. The words I, and YOU, and THEY, are grammatical devices invented simply for arrangement, and totally devoid of the intense and exclusive sense usually attached to them. It is difficult to find terms adequate to express so subtle a conception as that to which the Intellectual Philosophy has conducted us. We are on that verge where words abandon us, and what wonder if we grow dizzy to look down the dark abyss of how little we know. The relations of THINGS remain unchanged, by whatever system. By the word THINGS is to be understood any object of thought, that is any thought upon which any other thought is employed, with an apprehension of distinction.

Don't think that this idea leads to the crazy assumption that I, the one who is writing and thinking right now, am the only mind. I’m just a part of it. The words I, YOU, and THEY are just grammatical tools created to organize thoughts and don’t carry the deep and exclusive meaning we usually associate with them. It’s hard to find words that can adequately express such a subtle concept as that which Intellectual Philosophy has brought us to. We’re at the edge where words fail us, and it’s no surprise that we feel overwhelmed when we consider how little we actually know. The relationships of THINGS remain unchanged, regardless of any system. By THINGS, we mean any object of thought, or any thought that other thoughts are based on, with a clear understanding of the differences.

The relations of these remain unchanged; and such is the material of our knowledge. What is the cause of life? that is, how was it produced, or what agencies distinct from life have acted or act upon life? All recorded generations of mankind have weariedly busied themselves in inventing answers to this question; and the result has been,—Religion. Yet, that the basis of all things cannot be, as the popular philosophy alleges, mind, is sufficiently evident. Mind, as far as we have any experience of its properties, and beyond that experience how vain is argument! cannot create, it can only perceive. It is said also to be the cause. But cause is only a word expressing a certain state of the human mind with regard to the manner in which two thoughts are apprehended to be related to each other. If any one desires to know how unsatisfactorily the popular philosophy employs itself upon this great question, they need only impartially reflect upon the manner in which thoughts develop themselves in their minds. It is infinitely improbable that the cause of mind, that is, of existence, is similar to mind.

The relationships here remain the same, and this is the foundation of our knowledge. What causes life? In other words, how did it come to be, or what influences separate from life have acted or continue to act upon it? All recorded generations of humanity have tirelessly worked to come up with answers to this question, resulting in—Religion. However, it is clear that the foundation of everything cannot be, as popular philosophy suggests, the mind. Based on our limited experience with its properties—and how pointless arguments become beyond that experience—it cannot create; it can only perceive. It is also said to be the cause. But “cause” is merely a term expressing a specific state of the human mind regarding how two thoughts are perceived to be related. Anyone curious about how unfulfilling popular philosophy is in tackling this significant question need only reflect objectively on how their thoughts form in their minds. It's extremely unlikely that the cause of the mind, which means existence, is anything like the mind itself.

[1815; publ. 1840]

[1815; published 1840]










ON A FUTURE STATE

It has been the persuasion of an immense majority of human beings in all ages and nations that we continue to live after death,—that apparent termination of all the functions of sensitive and intellectual existence. Nor has mankind been contented with supposing that species of existence which some philosophers have asserted; namely, the resolution of the component parts of the mechanism of a living being into its elements, and the impossibility of the minutest particle of these sustaining the smallest diminution. They have clung to the idea that sensibility and thought, which they have distinguished from the objects of it, under the several names of spirit and matter, is, in its own nature, less susceptible of division and decay, and that, when the body is resolved into its elements, the principle which animated it will remain perpetual and unchanged. Some philosophers-and those to whom we are indebted for the most stupendous discoveries in physical science, suppose, on the other hand, that intelligence is the mere result of certain combinations among the particles of its objects; and those among them who believe that we live after death, recur to the interposition of a supernatural power, which shall overcome the tendency inherent in all material combinations, to dissipate and be absorbed into other forms.

A huge majority of people throughout history and across different cultures have believed that we continue to live after death, which seems to be the end of all our physical and intellectual functions. Humanity hasn't been satisfied with the idea of existence proposed by some philosophers, who suggest that a living being’s components break down into their basic elements and that even the smallest particle can't hold up against fading away. Instead, they've held onto the belief that our ability to feel and think, which they separate from the things we feel and think about, referred to as spirit and matter, is naturally less likely to be divided or decay. They believe that when the body breaks down into its elements, the force that gave it life will persist, unchanged and eternal. Meanwhile, some philosophers—especially those whose groundbreaking discoveries have advanced physical science—argue that intelligence is simply the product of specific combinations among its components. Among those who believe in life after death, some resort to the idea of a supernatural power that overcomes the inherent tendency of all matter to break down and merge into different forms.

Let us trace the reasonings which in one and the other have conducted to these two opinions, and endeavour to discover what we ought to think on a question of such momentous interest. Let us analyse the ideas and feelings which constitute the contending beliefs, and watchfully establish a discrimination between words and thoughts. Let us bring the question to the test of experience and fact; and ask ourselves, considering our nature in its entire extent, what light we derive from a sustained and comprehensive view of its component parts, which may enable, us to assert, with certainty, that we do or do not live after death.

Let’s explore the reasoning behind both sides of this debate and try to figure out what we should think about such an important question. Let’s break down the ideas and feelings that make up the opposing beliefs, carefully distinguishing between words and thoughts. Let’s put the question to the test using experience and facts; and ask ourselves, considering our nature as a whole, what insights we gain from a thorough and detailed look at its different aspects, which might allow us to confidently state whether or not we live on after death.

The examination of this subject requires that it should be stript of all those accessory topics which adhere to it in the common opinion of men. The existence of a God, and a future state of rewards and punishments, are totally foreign to the subject. If it be proved that the world is ruled by a Divine Power, no inference necessarily can be drawn from that circumstance in favour of a future state. It has been asserted, indeed, that as goodness and justice are to be numbered among the attributes of the Deity, He will undoubtedly compensate the virtuous who suffer during life, and that He will make every sensitive being who does not deserve punishment, happy for ever. But this view of the subject, which it would be tedious as well as superfluous to develop and expose, satisfies no person, and cuts the knot which we now seek to untie. Moreover, should it be proved, on the other hand, that the mysterious principle which regulates the proceedings of the universe, is neither intelligent nor sensitive, yet it is not an inconsistency to suppose at the same time, that the animating power survives the body which it has animated, by laws as independent of any supernatural agent as those through which it first became united with it. Nor, if a future state be clearly proved, does it follow that it will be a state of punishment or reward.

The study of this topic requires stripping away all the additional themes that people commonly associate with it. The existence of a God and an afterlife of rewards and punishments are completely unrelated to the topic. Even if it can be shown that the world is governed by a Divine Power, it doesn't automatically imply a future state. Some have claimed that since goodness and justice are attributes of the Deity, He will surely reward those who suffer virtue in life, and that He will ensure happiness forever for all beings who don't deserve punishment. However, this perspective, which it would be both tedious and unnecessary to discuss further, doesn't satisfy anyone and complicates the issue we're trying to resolve. Additionally, if it turns out that the mysterious force behind the universe is neither intelligent nor sensitive, it doesn't contradict the idea that the animating force survives beyond the body it animated, by laws independent of any supernatural influence, just as those that first connected it. Furthermore, even if we can clearly demonstrate that an afterlife exists, it doesn’t necessarily mean it will be one of punishment or reward.

By the word death, we express that condition in which natures resembling ourselves apparently cease to be that which they were. We no longer hear them speak, nor see them move. If they have sensations and apprehensions, we no longer participate in them. We know no more than that those external organs, and all that fine texture of material frame, without which we have no experience that life or thought can subsist, are dissolved and scattered abroad. The body is placed under the earth, and after a certain period there remains no vestige even of its form. This is that contemplation of inexhaustible melancholy, whose shadow eclipses the brightness of the world. The common observer is struck with dejection at the spectacle. He contends in vain against the persuasion of the grave, that the dead indeed cease to be. The corpse at his feet is prophetic of his own destiny. Those who have preceded him, and whose voice was delightful to his ear; whose touch met his like sweet and subtle fire; whose aspect spread a visionary light upon his path—these he cannot meet again. The organs of sense are destroyed, and the intellectual operations dependent on them have perished with their sources. How can a corpse see or feel? its eyes are eaten out, and its heart is black and without motion. What intercourse can two heaps of putrid clay and crumbling bones hold together? When you can discover where the fresh colours of the faded flower abide, or the music of the broken lyre, seek life among the dead. Such are the anxious and fearful contemplations of the common observer, though the popular religion often prevents him from confessing them even to himself.

By the word death, we signify that state in which beings like us seem to stop being what they were. We no longer hear them speak or see them move. Even if they have feelings and thoughts, we no longer share in them. All we know is that those physical bodies, and all the intricate structures of material existence that are essential for life or thought, are broken down and dispersed. The body lies beneath the ground, and after a while, there is no trace of its form left. This is the source of deep sadness, casting a shadow over the world's brightness. The ordinary observer feels overwhelmed by the sight. They struggle in vain against the reality of the grave, believing that the dead truly no longer exist. The corpse at their feet foreshadows their own fate. Those who came before them, whose voices were music to their ears; whose touch ignited a sweet, subtle spark; whose presence lit up their path—these loved ones they cannot meet again. The senses have vanished, and the mental activities dependent on them have died with their sources. How can a corpse see or feel? Its eyes are gone, and its heart is lifeless and still. What connection can two piles of decaying flesh and crumbling bones have? When you can find where the vibrant colors of the wilted flower remain, or the music of the broken lyre, search for life among the dead. Such are the anxious and fearful thoughts of the ordinary observer, even if popular beliefs often keep them from admitting this to themselves.

The natural philosopher, in addition to the sensations common to all men inspired by the event of death, believes that he sees with more certainty that it is attended with the annihilation of sentiment and thought. He observes the mental powers increase and fade with those of the body, and even accommodate themselves to the most transitory changes of our physical nature. Sleep suspends many of the faculties of the vital and intellectual principle; drunkenness and disease will either temporarily or permanently derange them. Madness or idiotcy may utterly extinguish the most excellent and delicate of those powers. In old age the mind gradually withers; and as it grew and was strengthened with the body, so does it together with the body sink into decrepitude. Assuredly these are convincing evidences that so soon as the organs of the body are subjected to the laws of inanimate matter, sensation, and perception, and apprehension, are at an end. It is probable that what we call thought is not an actual being, but no more than the relation between certain parts of that infinitely varied mass, of which the rest of the universe is composed, and which ceases to exist so soon as those parts change their position with regard to each other. Thus colour, and sound, and taste, and odour exist only relatively. But let thought be considered as some peculiar substance, which permeates, and is the cause of, the animation of living beings. Why should that substance be assumed to be something essentially distinct from all others, and exempt from subjection to those laws from which no other substance is exempt? It differs, indeed, from all other substances, as electricity, and light, and magnetism, and the constituent parts of air and earth, severally differ from all others. Each of these is subject to change and to decay, and to conversion into other forms. Yet the difference between light and earth is scarcely greater than that which exists between life, or thought, and fire. The difference between the two former was never alleged as an argument for the eternal permanence of either, in that form under which they first might offer themselves to our notice. Why should the difference between the two latter substances be an argument for the prolongation of the existence of one and not the other, when the existence of both has arrived at their apparent termination? To say that fire exists without manifesting any of the properties of fire, such as light, heat, etc., or that the principle of life exists without consciousness, or memory, or desire, or motive, is to resign, by an awkward distortion of language, the affirmative of the dispute. To say that the principle of life MAY exist in distribution among various forms, is to assert what cannot be proved to be either true or false, but which, were it true, annihilates all hope of existence after death, in any sense in which that event can belong to the hopes and fears of men. Suppose, however, that the intellectual and vital principle differs in the most marked and essential manner from all other known substances; that they have all some resemblance between themselves which it in no degree participates. In what manner can this concession be made an argument for its imperishability? All that we see or know perishes and is changed. Life and thought differ indeed from everything else. But that it survives that period, beyond which we have no experience of its existence, such distinction and dissimilarity affords no shadow of proof, and nothing but our own desires could have led us to conjecture or imagine. Have we existed before birth? It is difficult to conceive the possibility of this. There is, in the generative principle of each animal and plant, a power which converts the substances by which it is surrounded into a substance homogeneous with itself. That is, the relations between certain elementary particles of matter undergo a change, and submit to new combinations. For when we use the words PRINCIPLE, POWER, CAUSE, we mean to express no real being, but only to class under those terms a certain series of co-existing phenomena; but let it be supposed that this principle is a certain substance which escapes the observation of the chemist and anatomist. It certainly MAY BE; though it is sufficiently unphilosophical to allege the possibility of an opinion as a proof of its truth. Does it see, hear, feel, before its combination with those organs on which sensation depends? Does it reason, imagine, apprehend, without those ideas which sensation alone can communicate? If we have not existed before birth; if, at the period when the parts of our nature on which thought and life depend, seem to be woven together; if there are no reasons to suppose that we have existed before that period at which our existence apparently commences, then there are no grounds for supposition that we shall continue to exist after our existence has apparently ceased. So far as thought is concerned, the same will take place with regard to use, individually considered, after death, as had place before our birth.

The natural philosopher, in addition to the feelings that are common to all people regarding the event of death, believes he sees more clearly that it comes with the end of feeling and thought. He notices that mental abilities rise and fall with those of the body and even adapt to the most fleeting changes in our physical state. Sleep temporarily halts many faculties of life and intellect; intoxication and illness can either disrupt them for a while or permanently. Madness or severe disabilities can completely extinguish even the finest and most sensitive mental powers. In old age, the mind gradually declines; just as it grew and got stronger with the body, it also deteriorates alongside it. These are strong indications that as soon as the body’s organs are governed by the laws of lifeless matter, sensation, perception, and understanding come to an end. It’s likely that what we refer to as thought is not an actual entity, but rather just the relationship between certain parts of that infinitely complex mass, of which the rest of the universe is made, and which ceases to exist as soon as those parts change their arrangement concerning each other. Thus, color, sound, taste, and smell exist only relatively. But if we consider thought to be some unique substance that pervades and causes the animation of living beings, why should we assume that this substance is fundamentally different from all others and exempt from the laws that bind everything else? It does differ from other substances, just as electricity, light, magnetism, and the components of air and earth each differ. Each of these is subject to change, decay, and transformation into other forms. Yet the difference between light and earth is hardly greater than the difference between life or thought and fire. The distinction between the first two has never been used to argue for the eternal permanence of either in the form in which we first encounter them. So, why should the difference between the latter two be used as an argument for the continued existence of one but not the other when both have seemingly reached their end? To say that fire exists without showing any of its properties, like light or heat, or that the principle of life exists without awareness, memory, desire, or motivation, is to awkwardly twist the language of the debate. Claiming that the principle of life might be distributed among various forms is to assert something that can't be proven true or false, and if it were true, it would eliminate all hope of existence after death in any way that relates to human hopes and fears. However, let’s assume that the intellectual and vital principles differ in significant and essential ways from all other known substances, that all others have some similarity among themselves that these principles do not share. How can this acknowledgment be used to argue for their everlasting nature? Everything we see or know perishes and changes. Life and thought do indeed differ from everything else. But saying that they survive beyond a point, past which we have no experience of their existence, offers no proof whatsoever, and only our own desires could lead us to speculate or imagine. Did we exist before birth? It’s hard to imagine that is possible. Each animal and plant’s generative principle has a power that transforms the materials around it into a substance that matches itself. In other words, the relationships between certain basic particles of matter change and form new combinations. When we use terms like PRINCIPLE, POWER, CAUSE, we express no real entity, only categorizing a particular series of co-existing phenomena; yet let’s assume this principle is a certain substance that escapes the notice of chemists and anatomists. It certainly might exist; however, it is quite unphilosophical to use the possibility of an opinion as proof of its truth. Does it see, hear, or feel before it connects with those organs that allow sensation? Does it reason, imagine, or understand without the ideas that only sensation can provide? If we didn’t exist before birth; if at the moment when the elements of our being that support thought and life seem to come together; if there’s no reason to believe we existed before the point at which our existence apparently begins, then there’s no basis to suggest that we will continue to exist after our existence appears to end. As far as thought is concerned, the same will happen regarding usefulness, when considered individually, after death, as it did before our birth.

It is said that it, is possible that we should continue to exist in some mode totally inconceivable to us at present. This is a most unreasonable presumption. It casts on the adherents of annihilation the burthen of proving the negative of a question, the affirmative of which is not supported by a single argument, and which, by its very nature, lies beyond the experience of the human understanding. It is sufficiently easy, indeed, to form any proposition, concerning which we are ignorant, just not so absurd as not to be contradictory in itself, and defy refutation. The possibility of whatever enters into the wildest imagination to conceive is thus triumphantly vindicated. But it is enough that such assertions should be either contradictory to the known laws of nature, or exceed the limits of our experience, that their fallacy or irrelevancy to our consideration should be demonstrated. They persuade, indeed, only those who desire to be persuaded. This desire to be for ever as we are; the reluctance to a violent and unexperienced change, which is common to all the animated and inanimate combinations of the universe, is, indeed, the secret persuasion which has given birth to the opinions of a future state.

It's said that we might continue to exist in some way that's completely unimaginable to us right now. This is a highly unreasonable assumption. It places the burden on those who believe in annihilation to prove a negative claim, which doesn't have a single argument supporting it and, by its very nature, is beyond human understanding. It’s quite easy to come up with any statement about things we don't know, as long as it’s not so absurd that it contradicts itself and cannot be disproven. The possibility of whatever the wildest imagination can conceive is thus claimed as valid. However, it’s enough that such claims contradict known laws of nature or go beyond the limits of our experience to show their fallacy or irrelevance to our consideration. They only convince those who want to be convinced. This desire to stay the same; the unwillingness to undergo a drastic and unfamiliar change, which is common to all living and non-living things in the universe, is indeed the hidden belief that has led to the ideas of an afterlife.

[1815; publ. 1840]

[1815; published 1840]










ON THE PUNISHMENT OF DEATH

A FRAGMENT

The first law which it becomes a Reformer to propose and support, at the approach of a period of great political change, is the abolition of the punishment of death.

The first law that a Reformer should suggest and advocate for during a time of significant political change is the elimination of the death penalty.

It is sufficiently clear that revenge, retaliation, atonement, expiation, are rules and motives, so far from deserving a place in any enlightened system of political life, that they are the chief sources of a prodigious class of miseries in the domestic circles of society. It is clear that however the spirit of legislation may appear to frame institutions upon more philosophical maxims, it has hitherto, in those cases which are termed criminal, done little more than palliate the spirit, by gratifying a portion of it; and afforded a compromise between that which is bests—the inflicting of no evil upon a sensitive being, without a decisively beneficial result in which he should at least participates—and that which is worst; that he should be put to torture for the amusement of those whom he may have injured, or may seem to have injured.

It's pretty clear that revenge, retaliation, atonement, and expiation don't belong in any enlightened political system. In fact, they're the main sources of a huge amount of suffering in our daily lives. Even though lawmakers might try to create institutions based on more rational ideas, they've mostly just skimmed over the core issues. They've settled for a middle ground: not causing harm to someone who's sensitive unless there's a clear benefit that they can at least be part of. On the flip side, the worst option is to torture someone for the entertainment of those they've harmed or who think they've harmed them.

Omitting these remoter considerations, let us inquire what, DEATH is; that punishment which is applied as a measure of transgressions of indefinite shades of distinction, so soon as they shall have passed that degree and colour of enormity, with which it is supposed no, inferior infliction is commensurate.

Omitting these broader thoughts, let's explore what DEATH really is; that punishment given for violations of various degrees of seriousness, as soon as they cross the line into a level of wrongdoing that is believed to warrant no lesser consequence.

And first, whether death is good or evil, a punishment or a reward, or whether it be wholly indifferent, no man can take upon himself to assert. That that within us which thinks and feels, continues to think and feel after the dissolution of the body, has been the almost universal opinion of mankind, and the accurate philosophy of what I may be permitted to term the modern Academy, by showing the prodigious depth and extent of our ignorance respecting the causes and nature of sensation, renders probable the affirmative of a proposition, the negative of which it is so difficult to conceive, and the popular arguments against which, derived from what is called the atomic system, are proved to be applicable only to the relation which one object bears to another, as apprehended by the mind, and not to existence itself, or the nature of that essence which is the medium and receptacle of objects.

And first, whether death is good or bad, a punishment or a reward, or if it’s completely neutral, no one can claim to know for sure. The idea that what we think and feel continues after our body dies has been the almost universal belief among people, and the precise philosophy of what I’ll call the modern Academy, by highlighting the vast depth of our ignorance about the causes and nature of sensation, suggests that it’s likely true. It's hard to wrap our heads around the opposite of this idea, and the common arguments against it, coming from what’s known as the atomic system, only apply to the relationship between objects as understood by the mind, not to existence itself or the nature of the essence that receives and holds those objects.

The popular system of religion suggests the idea that the mind, after death, will be painfully or pleasurably affected according to its determinations during life. However ridiculous and pernicious we must admit the vulgar accessories of this creed to be, there is a certain analogy, not wholly absurd, between the consequences resulting to an individual during life from the virtuous or vicious, prudent or imprudent, conduct of his external actions, to those consequences which are conjectured to ensue from the discipline and order of his internal thoughts, as affecting his condition in a future state. They omit, indeed, to calculate upon the accidents of disease, and temperament, and organization, and circumstance, together with the multitude of independent agencies which affect the opinions, the conduct, and the happiness of individuals, and produce determinations of the will, and modify the judgement, so as to produce effects the most opposite in natures considerably similar. These are those operations in the order of the whole of nature, tending, we are prone to believe, to some definite mighty end, to which the agencies of our peculiar nature are subordinate; nor is there any reason to suppose, that in a future state they should become suddenly exempt from that subordination. The philosopher is unable to determine whether our existence in a previous state has affected our present condition, and abstains from deciding whether our present condition will affect us in that which may be future. That, if we continue to exist, the manner of our existence will be such as no inferences nor conjectures, afforded by a consideration of our earthly experience, can elucidate, is sufficiently obvious. The opinion that the vital principle within us, in whatever mode it may continue to exist, must lose that consciousness of definite and individual being which now characterizes it, and become a unit in the vast sum of action and of thought which disposes and animates the universe, and is called God, seems to belong to that class of opinion which has been designated as indifferent.

The common belief in religion suggests that the mind, after death, will experience pain or pleasure based on how it acted during life. While we might find the silly and harmful aspects of this belief hard to accept, there's a certain logic—though not entirely reasonable—connecting the outcomes of a person's virtuous or immoral actions during life to the anticipated consequences of their internal thoughts for their future state. They often ignore the impact of illness, temperament, physical makeup, and circumstances, along with countless outside influences that shape people’s opinions, actions, and happiness, leading to decisions and altering judgments in ways that can create very different results from what seems similar. These factors are part of the broader workings of nature, which we tend to believe aim towards some significant goal, of which our individual nature is merely a part; there's no reason to think that they would suddenly operate differently in a future state. Philosophers struggle to say whether our past existence influences our current situation and hesitate to claim whether our present state will affect our future existence. It's fairly clear that if we do continue to exist, the way we exist will be beyond what we can infer or guess from our earthly experiences. The belief that the vital essence within us, no matter how it continues to exist, must lose its awareness of distinct individual identity and become a part of the vast actions and thoughts that govern and energize the universe—often referred to as God—seems to be one of those opinions deemed indifferent.

To compel a person to know all that can be known by the dead concerning that which the living fear, hope, or forget; to plunge him into the pleasure or pain which there awaits him; to punish or reward him in a manner and in a degree incalculable and incomprehensible by us; to disrobe him at once from all that intertexture of good and evil with which Nature seems to have clothed every form of individual existence, is to inflict on him the doom of death.

To force someone to understand everything the dead know about what the living fear, hope for, or forget; to immerse them in the joy or sorrow that awaits them; to punish or reward them in a way that we can't measure or fully grasp; to strip away all the complexities of good and evil that seem to define every individual's existence, is to subject them to the fate of death.

A certain degree of pain and terror usually accompany the infliction of death. This degree is infinitely varied by the infinite variety in the temperament and opinions of the sufferers. As a measure of punishment, strictly so considered, and as an exhibition, which, by its known effects on the sensibility of the sufferer, is intended to intimidate the spectators from incurring a similar liability, it is singularly inadequate.

A certain level of pain and fear usually comes with death. This level varies greatly due to the endless differences in the temperaments and beliefs of those who suffer. When viewed strictly as a punishment and as a display meant to scare onlookers from facing the same fate, it is remarkably insufficient.

Firstly, Persons of energetic character, in whom, as in men who suffer for political crimes, there is a large mixture of enterprise, and fortitude, and disinterestedness, and the elements, though misguided and disarranged, by which the strength and happiness of a nation might have been cemented, die in such a manner, as to make death appear not evil, but good. The death of what is called a traitor, that is, a person who, from whatever motive, would abolish the government of the day, is as often a triumphant exhibition of suffering virtue, as the warning of a culprit. The multitude, instead of departing with a panic-stricken approbation of the laws which exhibited such a spectacle, are inspired with pity, admiration and sympathy; and the most generous among them feel an emulation to be the authors of such flattering emotions, as they experience stirring in their bosoms. Impressed by what they see and feel, they make no distinctive between the motives which incited the criminals to the action for which they suffer, or the heroic courage with which they turned into good that which their judges awarded to them as evil or the purpose itself of those actions, though that purpose may happen to be eminently pernicious. The laws in this case lose their sympathy, which it ought to be their chief object to secure, and in a participation of which consists their chief strength in maintaining those sanctions by which the parts of the social union are bound together, so as to produce, as nearly as possible, the ends for which it is instituted.

Firstly, people with strong characters, much like those who suffer for political reasons, often display a mix of boldness, resilience, and selflessness. These qualities, although misguided and disordered, could have been the foundation for a nation's strength and happiness. They die in a way that makes death seem more like a noble act than a tragedy. The death of someone labeled a traitor—someone who, for any reason, seeks to overthrow the current government—often becomes a moving testament to suffering virtue rather than just a warning sign for wrongdoers. The crowd, rather than leaving in fear of the laws that created such a scene, feels pity, admiration, and sympathy. The most noble among them are inspired to evoke the same uplifting feelings they experience within themselves. Moved by what they witness, they don’t draw lines between the motivations that drove the offenders to act or the brave way they turned what their judges deemed evil into something good, even if the intent behind those actions is undeniably harmful. In such cases, the laws lose their connection with the very sympathy they ought to cultivate, which is essential to the strength needed to uphold the rules that bind the fabric of society together and aim to achieve the purposes for which it was created.

Secondly,—Persons of energetic character, in communities not modelled with philosophical skill to turn all the energies which they contain to the purposes of common good, are prone also to fall into the temptation of undertaking, and are peculiarly fitted for despising the perils attendant upon consummating, the most enormous crimes. Murder, rapes, extensive schemes of plunder are the actions of persons belonging to this class; and death is the penalty of conviction. But the coarseness of organization, peculiar to men capable of committing acts wholly selfish, is usually found to be associated with a proportionate insensibility to fear or pain. Their sufferings communicate to those of the spectators, who may be liable to the commission of similar crimes a sense of the lightness of that event, when closely examined which, at a distance, as uneducated persons are accustomed to do, probably they regarded with horror. But a great majority of the spectators are so bound up in the interests and the habits of social union that no temptation would be sufficiently strong to induce them to a commission of the enormities to which this penalty is assigned. The more powerful, and the richer among them,—and a numerous class of little tradesmen are richer and more powerful than those who are employed by them, and the employer, in general, bears this relation to the employed,—regard their own wrongs as, in some degree, avenged, and their own rights secured by this punishment, inflicted as the penalty of whatever crime. In cases of murder or mutilation, this feeling is almost universal. In those, therefore, whom this exhibition does not awaken to the sympathy which extenuates crime and discredits the law which restrains it, it produces feelings more directly at war with the genuine purposes of political society. It excites those emotions which it is the chief object of civilization to extinguish for ever, and in the extinction of which alone there can be any hope of better institutions than those under which men now misgovern one another. Men feel that their revenge is gratified, and that their security is established by the extinction and the sufferings of beings, in most respects resembling themselves; and their daily occupations constraining them to a precise form in all their thoughts, they come to connect inseparably the idea of their own advantage with that of the death and torture of others. It is manifest that the object of sane polity is directly the reverse; and that laws founded upon reason, should accustom the gross vulgar to associate their ideas of security and of interest with the reformation, and the strict restraint, for that purpose alone, of those who might invade it.

Secondly, energetic individuals in communities that aren't structured with philosophical insight to channel their energies for the common good often fall into the trap of committing severe crimes and tend to underestimate the risks involved. Murder, rape, and large-scale theft are actions associated with this group, and death is the penalty for such convictions. However, the brutality often found in those willing to commit self-serving acts typically comes with a notable insensitivity to fear or pain. Their suffering can make onlookers—who might consider committing similar crimes—see the seriousness of the issue as less alarming, whereas from a distance, uneducated individuals might view it with horror. Yet, most spectators are so invested in social norms and interests that nothing would be strong enough to push them toward committing the crimes punishable by death. The more powerful and wealthier among them—often including many small business owners, who may be richer and more influential than their employees—see their own grievances as somewhat avenged and their rights secured by this punishment. This sentiment is nearly universal in cases of murder or mutilation. For those who are not moved by sympathy that mitigates crime and undermines the laws that prevent it, these events stir emotions that directly conflict with the true aims of a political society. They ignite feelings that civilization seeks to suppress permanently and which are essential for improving the systems by which people currently misuse power against one another. People feel that their vengeance is satisfied and their security is reinforced by the suffering and death of others who are, in many respects, just like them. Their daily lives condition them to link their own benefit closely with the death and torture of others. It is clear that the aim of a rational political system is the opposite; laws based on reason should teach the general public to connect their ideas of safety and interest with the reform and strict control of those who might threaten it.

The passion of revenge is originally nothing more than an habitual perception of the ideas of the sufferings of the person who inflicts an injury, as connected, as they are in a savage state, or in such portions of society as are yet undisciplined to civilization, with security that that injury will not be repeated in future. This feeling, engrafted upon superstition and confirmed by habit, at last loses sight of the only object for which it may be supposed to have been implanted, and becomes a passion and a duty to be pursued and fulfilled, even to the destruction of those ends to which it originally tended. The other passions, both good and evil. Avarice, Remorse, Love, Patriotism, present a similar appearance; and to this principle of the mind over-shooting the mark at which it aims, we owe all that is eminently base or excellent in human nature; in providing for the nutriment or the extinction of which, consists the true art of the legislator. [Footnote: The savage and the illiterate are but faintly aware of the distinction between the future and the past; they make actions belonging to periods so distinct, the subjects of similar feelings; they live only in the present, or in the past, as it is present. It is in this that the philosopher excels one of the many; it is this which distinguishes the doctrine of philosophic necessity from fatalism; and that determination of the will, by which it is the active source of future events, from that liberty or indifference, to which the abstract liability of irremediable actions is attached, according to the notions of the vulgar.

The urge for revenge is basically just a habitual way of seeing the pain caused by someone who has been hurt, as linked to the idea, especially in primitive societies or groups that aren't yet civilized, that this harm won't happen again in the future. This feeling, rooted in superstition and reinforced by habit, eventually loses sight of the original reason it might have developed and turns into a passion and a duty to pursue, even if it ends up destroying the very goals it was meant to achieve. Other feelings, both good and bad, like greed, guilt, love, and patriotism, have a similar nature. This tendency of the mind to miss its target leads to all that is notably bad or good in human nature; understanding how to nourish or eliminate this is the true skill of a lawmaker. [Footnote: The primitive and the uneducated have only a vague understanding of the difference between the future and the past; they tie actions from very different times to the same feelings; they exist only in the present, or in the past as it feels present. This is where a philosopher excels over the many; it is what sets the philosophy of necessity apart from fatalism and distinguishes the active will that shapes future events from the freedom or indifference associated with the abstract idea of unavoidable actions, as understood by the common people.]

This is the source of the erroneous excesses of Remorse and Revenge; the one extending itself over the future, and the other over the past; provinces in which their suggestions can only be the sources of evil. The purpose of a resolution to act more wisely and virtuously in future, and the sense of a necessity of caution in repressing an enemy, are the sources from which the enormous superstitions implied in the words cited have arisen.]

This is where the misguided extremes of Remorse and Revenge come from; one looking toward the future and the other looking back at the past. In these areas, their suggestions can only lead to harm. The intention to act more wisely and morally in the future, along with the need to be cautious in dealing with an enemy, are the roots of the intense superstitions implied in the quoted words.

Nothing is more clear than that the infliction of punishment in general, in a degree which the reformation and the restraint of those who transgress the laws does not render indispensable, and none more than death, confirms all the inhuman and unsocial impulses of men. It is almost a proverbial remark, that those nations in which the penal code has been particularly mild, have been distinguished from all others by the rarity of crime. But the example is to be admitted to be equivocal. A more decisive argument is afforded by a consideration of the universal connexion of ferocity of manners, and a contempt of social ties, with the contempt of human life. Governments which derive their institutions from the existence of circumstances of barbarism and violence, with some rare exceptions perhaps, are bloody in proportion as they are despotic, and form the manners of their subjects to a sympathy with their own spirit.

Nothing is clearer than the fact that punishment in general, especially when it goes beyond what’s necessary for reforming and restraining lawbreakers, and none more so than death, really reinforces all the cruel and antisocial instincts of people. It’s almost common knowledge that countries with more lenient penal codes tend to have lower crime rates. However, that example can be seen as ambiguous. A stronger argument comes from looking at the clear link between a cruel nature, a disregard for social connections, and a lack of respect for human life. Governments that are built on foundations of barbarism and violence, with a few rare exceptions, tend to be bloody in relation to how oppressive they are, and they shape the behavior of their people to mirror their own violent tendencies.

The spectators who feel no abhorrence at a public execution, but rather a self-applauding superiority, and a sense of gratified indignation, are surely excited to the most inauspicious emotions. The first reflection of such a one is the sense of his own internal and actual worth, as preferable to that of the victim, whom circumstances have led to destruction. The meanest wretch is impressed with a sense of his own comparative merit. He is one of those on whom the tower of Siloam fell not—he is such a one as Jesus Christ found not in all Samaria, who, in his own soul, throws the first stone at the woman taken in adultery. The popular religion of the country takes its designation from that illustrious person whose beautiful sentiment I have quoted. Any one who has stript from the doctrines of this person the veil of familiarity, will perceive how adverse their spirit is to feelings of this nature.

The spectators who feel no disgust at a public execution but instead a sense of self-satisfied superiority and a feeling of justified anger are clearly stirred by the most unfortunate emotions. Their first thought is a recognition of their own inner worth, which they believe is better than that of the victim, who has faced ruin due to circumstances. Even the lowest of individuals feels a sense of their own relative merit. They are not like those on whom the tower of Siloam fell—they are the ones whom Jesus Christ could not find in all of Samaria, who, in their own hearts, cast the first stone at the woman caught in adultery. The mainstream religion of the country is named after that great figure, whose meaningful words I've quoted. Anyone who has removed the familiar gloss from this person’s teachings will see how contrary their essence is to feelings like these.










SPECULATIONS ON METAPHYSICS

I—THE MIND

It is an axiom in mental philosophy, that we can think of nothing which we have not perceived. When I say that we can think of nothing, I mean, we can imagine nothing, we can reason of nothing, we can remember nothing, we can foresee nothing. The most astonishing combinations of poetry, the subtlest deductions of logic and mathematics, are no other than combinations which the intellect makes of sensations according to its own laws. A catalogue of all the thoughts of the mind, and of all their possible modifications, is a cyclopedic history of the universe.

It's a basic principle in psychology that we can't think of anything we haven't experienced. When I say we can't think of anything, I mean we can't imagine anything, reason about anything, remember anything, or predict anything. The most amazing blends of poetry and the finest conclusions from logic and math are just mixes of sensations that the mind creates based on its own rules. A complete list of all the thoughts in our minds and all their possible variations would be an encyclopedic history of the universe.

But, it will be objected, the inhabitants of the various planets of this and other solar systems; and the existence of a Power bearing the same relation to all that we perceive and are, as what we call a cause does to what we call effect, were never subjects of sensation, and yet the laws of mind almost universally suggest, according to the various disposition of each, a conjecture, a persuasion, or a conviction of their existence. The reply is simple; these thoughts are also to be included in the catalogue of existence; they are modes in which thoughts are combined; the objection only adds force to the conclusion, that beyond the limits of perception and thought nothing can exist.

But, some might argue, the inhabitants of different planets in this and other solar systems, and the existence of a Power that relates to everything we perceive and are, similar to how we view cause-and-effect, were never subjects of direct experience. However, the laws of the mind almost universally suggest, based on individual perspectives, a guess, a belief, or a certainty about their existence. The answer is straightforward; these thoughts also belong in the list of what exists; they are just ways that thoughts are connected. The objection only strengthens the conclusion that nothing can exist beyond the boundaries of perception and thought.

Thoughts, or ideas, or notions, call them what you will, differ from each other, not in kind, but in force. It has commonly been supposed that those distinct thoughts which affect a number of persons, at regular intervals, during the passage of a multitude of other thoughts, which are called REAL or EXTERNAL OBJECTS, are totally different in kind from those which affect only a few persons, and which recur at irregular intervals, and are usually more obscure and indistinct, such as hallucinations, dreams, and the ideas of madness. No essential distinction between any one of these ideas, or any class of them, is founded on a correct observation of the nature of things, but merely on a consideration of what thoughts are most invariably subservient to the security and happiness of life; and if nothing more were expressed by the distinction, the philosopher might safely accommodate his language to that of the vulgar. But they pretend to assert an essential difference, which has no foundation in truth, and which suggests a narrow and false conception of universal nature, the parent of the most fatal errors in speculation. A specific difference between every thought of the mind, is, indeed, a necessary consequence of that law by which it perceives diversity and number; but a generic and essential difference is wholly arbitrary. The principle of the agreement and similarity of all thoughts, is, that they are all thoughts; the principle of their disagreement consists in the variety and irregularity of the occasions on which they arise in the mind. That in which they agree, to that in which they differ, is as everything to nothing. Important distinctions, of various degrees of force, indeed, are to be established between them, if they were, as they may be, subjects of ethical and economical discussion; but that is a question altogether distinct. By considering all knowledge as bounded by perception, whose operations may be indefinitely combined, we arrive at a conception of Nature inexpressibly more magnificent, simple and true, than accords with the ordinary systems of complicated and partial consideration. Nor does a contemplation of the universe, in this comprehensive and synthetical view, exclude the subtlest analysis of its modifications and parts.

Thoughts, ideas, or notions—call them what you want—differ from one another not in type, but in intensity. It's often been assumed that those distinct thoughts that influence many people consistently over time, amidst a stream of other thoughts deemed REAL or EXTERNAL OBJECTS, are fundamentally different from those that affect only a few individuals, which appear sporadically and are usually more vague and unclear, like hallucinations, dreams, and the thoughts associated with insanity. There isn’t a real fundamental difference between these ideas or any group of them based on an accurate understanding of reality; rather, it’s just about which thoughts more consistently contribute to security and happiness in life. If that were the only point made by the distinction, a philosopher could easily adopt the language of everyday people. However, they claim there’s an essential difference that lacks truth and promotes a narrow and misleading view of universal nature, leading to some of the most serious mistakes in reasoning. A specific difference between each thought in the mind is indeed a necessary outcome of the law that allows it to perceive diversity and quantity; however, a general and essential difference is completely arbitrary. The common thread among all thoughts is that they are all thoughts; the basis for their differences lies in the variety and irregularity of when they appear in the mind. What they have in common compared to their differences is like everything versus nothing. Important distinctions with varying degrees of intensity can be made between them, especially if they serve as subjects of ethical and economic discussions; but that’s a separate issue entirely. By viewing all knowledge as limited by perception, whose processes can be indefinitely combined, we reach a much more magnificent, simple, and accurate understanding of Nature than what's usually presented in the traditional complex and partial viewpoints. Furthermore, this broad and synthetic view of the universe doesn’t dismiss the most detailed analysis of its components and modifications.

A scale might be formed, graduated according to the degrees of a combined ratio of intensity, duration, connexion, periods of recurrence, and utility, which would be the standard, according to which all ideas might be measured, and an uninterrupted chain of nicely shadowed distinctions would be observed, from the faintest impression on the senses, to the most distinct combination of those impressions; from the simplest of those combinations, to that mass of knowledge which, including our own nature, constitutes what we call the universe.

A scale could be created, marked by the levels of a combined ratio of intensity, duration, connection, frequency, and usefulness, serving as the standard by which all ideas are assessed. This would allow for a continuous spectrum of finely detailed distinctions to be noted, from the faintest sensory impressions to the clearest combinations of those impressions; from the simplest combinations to the vast body of knowledge that, including our own nature, makes up what we refer to as the universe.

We are intuitively conscious of our own existence, and of that connexion in the train of our successive ideas, which we term our identity. We are conscious also of the existence of other minds; but not intuitively. Our evidence, with respect to the existence of other minds, is founded upon a very complicated relation of ideas, which it is foreign to the purpose of this treatise to anatomize. The basis of this relation is, undoubtedly, a periodical recurrence of masses of ideas, which our voluntary determinations have, in one peculiar direction, no power to circumscribe or to arrest, and against the recurrence of which they can only imperfectly provide. The irresistible laws of thought constrain us to believe that the precise limits of our actual ideas are not the actual limits of possible ideas; the law, according to which these deductions are drawn, is called analogy; and this is the foundation of all our inferences, from one idea to another, inasmuch as they resemble each other.

We are instinctively aware of our own existence and the connection in the flow of our successive thoughts, which we call our identity. We are also aware of other minds, but not instinctively. Our understanding of the existence of other minds is based on a very complex relationship of ideas, which is beyond the scope of this discussion to break down. The foundation of this relationship is undoubtedly a recurring pattern of thoughts that our voluntary choices cannot fully control or stop, and against which we can only make imperfect preparations. The unyielding laws of thought force us to believe that the exact boundaries of our current ideas aren't the actual boundaries of possible ideas; the principle by which these conclusions are drawn is called analogy, and this is the basis for all our connections between one idea and another, as long as they share similarities.

We see trees, houses, fields, living beings in our own shape, and in shapes more or less analogous to our own. These are perpetually changing the mode of their existence relatively to us. To express the varieties of these modes, we say, WE MOVE, THEY MOVE; and as this motion is continual, though not uniform, we express our conception of the diversities of its course by—IT HAS BEEN, IT IS, IT SHALL BE. These diversities are events or objects, and are essential, considered relatively to human identity, for the existence of the human mind. For if the inequalities, produced by what has been termed the operations of the external universe, were levelled by the perception of our being, uniting and filling up their interstices, motion and mensuration, and time, and space; the elements of the human mind being thus abstracted, sensation and imagination cease. Mind cannot be considered pure.

We see trees, houses, fields, and living beings that resemble us, and some that don't. These things are always changing in relation to us. To describe the different ways they change, we say, WE MOVE, THEY MOVE; and since this motion is constant, though not always the same, we express our understanding of its variations by saying—IT HAS BEEN, IT IS, IT SHALL BE. These variations are events or objects, and they are crucial, in relation to human identity, for the existence of the human mind. If the differences caused by what’s called the workings of the external universe were flattened by our perception of being, which would unify and fill their gaps, then motion, measurement, time, and space would lose their meaning; if the elements of the human mind were taken away, sensation and imagination would stop. The mind can't be seen as pure.

II—WHAT METAPHYSICS ARE. ERRORS IN THE USUAL METHODS OF CONSIDERING THEM

II—WHAT METAPHYSICS ARE. ERRORS IN THE USUAL METHODS OF CONSIDERING THEM

We do not attend sufficiently to what passes within ourselves. We combine words, combined a thousand times before. In our minds we assume entire opinions; and in the expression of those opinions, entire phrases, when we would philosophize. Our whole style of expression and sentiment is infected with the tritest plagiarisms. Our words are dead, our thoughts are cold and borrowed.

We don’t pay enough attention to what’s going on inside us. We string together words that have been put together countless times before. In our minds, we take entire beliefs for granted, and when we try to express those beliefs, we use whole phrases that are clichéd. Our way of expressing ourselves and our feelings is filled with the most common clichés. Our words feel empty, and our thoughts are unoriginal and borrowed.

Let us contemplate facts; let us, in the great study of ourselves, resolutely compel the mind to a rigid consideration of itself. We are not content with conjecture, and inductions, and syllogisms, in sciences regarding external objects. As in these, let us also, in considering the phenomena of mind, severely collect those facts which cannot be disputed. Metaphysics will thus possess this conspicuous advantage over every other science, that each student, by attentively referring to his own mind, may ascertain the authorities upon which any assertions regarding it are supported. There can thus be no deception, we ourselves being the depositaries of the evidence of the subject which we consider.

Let's reflect on the facts; let’s, in the grand exploration of ourselves, firmly push our minds to consider themselves rigorously. We aren’t satisfied with guesses, assumptions, and logical arguments when dealing with things outside of us. Similarly, when examining the workings of the mind, let’s stringently gather those undeniable facts. Metaphysics will thus have a notable advantage over every other field of study, as each learner, by closely examining their own mind, can determine the basis for any claims made about it. There can be no deceit, since we ourselves hold the evidence of the topic we’re discussing.

Metaphysics may be defined as an inquiry concerning those things belonging to, or connected with, the internal nature of man.

Metaphysics can be defined as the study of things that relate to or are connected to the internal nature of humans.

It is said that mind produces motion; and it might as well have been said, that motion produces mind.

It’s said that the mind creates movement; it could just as easily be said that movement creates the mind.

III—DIFFICULTY OF ANALYSING THE HUMAN MIND

If it were possible that a person should give a faithful history of his being, from the earliest epochs of his recollection, a picture would be presented such as the world has never contemplated before. A mirror would be held up to all men in which they might behold their own recollections, and, in dim perspective, their shadowy hopes and fears,—all that they dare not, or that, daring and desiring, they could not expose to the open eyes of day. But thought can with difficulty visit the intricate and winding chambers which it inhabits. It is like a river whose rapid and perpetual stream flows outwards;—like one in dread who speeds through the recesses of some haunted pile, and dares not look behind. The caverns of the mind are obscure, and shadowy; or pervaded with a lustre, beautifully bright indeed, but shining not beyond their portals. If it were possible to be where we have been, vitally and indeed—if, at the moment of our presence there, we could define the results of our experience,—if the passage from sensation to reflection—from a state of passive perception to voluntary contemplation, were not so dizzying and so tumultuous, this attempt would be less difficult.

If a person could give an honest account of their life, from the earliest moments they remember, it would create a picture unlike anything the world has ever seen. It would be a mirror reflecting everyone’s memories and their faint hopes and fears—everything they either can’t or won’t reveal in broad daylight. But it’s hard for thought to navigate the complicated and twisting pathways of the mind. It’s like a river with a fast and constant current rushing outward; or like someone terrified, racing through the hallways of a haunted house, too scared to look back. The depths of the mind are dark and shadowy, or filled with a stunning light that doesn’t extend beyond their edges. If it were possible to revisit where we have been, genuinely and truly—if we could define the outcomes of our experiences in the moment we were there—if the shift from feeling to thinking—from simply observing to deep contemplation—weren't so dizzying and chaotic, this task would be much easier.

IV—HOW THE ANALYSIS SHOULD BE CARRIED ON

Most of the errors of philosophers have arisen from considering the human being in a point of view too detailed and circumscribed He is not a moral, and an intellectual,—but also, and pre-eminently, an imaginative being. His own mind is his law; his own mind is all things to him. If we would arrive at any knowledge which should be serviceable from the practical conclusions to which it leads, we ought to consider the mind of man and the universe as the great whole on which to exercise our speculations. Here, above all, verbal disputes ought to be laid aside, though this has long been their chosen field of battle. It imports little to inquire whether thought be distinct from the objects of thought. The use of the words EXTERNAL and INTERNAL, as applied to the establishment of this distinction, has been the symbol and the source of much dispute. This is merely an affair of words, and as the dispute deserves, to say, that when speaking of the objects of thought, we indeed only describe one of the forms of thought—or that, speaking of thought, we only apprehend one of the operations of the universal system of beings.

Most of the mistakes philosophers make come from looking at humans in a limited and overly detailed way. We are not just moral and intellectual beings—we're primarily imaginative ones. Our own thoughts govern us; our mind encompasses everything. To gain any useful knowledge that leads to practical conclusions, we need to view the human mind and the universe as a whole for our speculations. Above all, we should set aside verbal arguments, even though that has been a favorite battleground for a long time. It's not very important to ask whether thought is separate from the objects of thought. The terms EXTERNAL and INTERNAL, used to make this distinction, have sparked a lot of disagreement. This is just a matter of words, and as the disagreement suggests, when we talk about the objects of thought, we are really only describing one aspect of thought—similarly, when discussing thought, we are just grasping one of the functions of the entire system of existence.

V—CATALOGUE OF THE PHENOMENA OF DREAMS, AS CONNECTING SLEEPING AND WAKING

V—CATALOGUE OF THE PHENOMENA OF DREAMS, AS CONNECTING SLEEPING AND WAKING

1. Let us reflect on our infancy, and give as faithfully as possible a relation of the events of sleep.

1. Let’s think back to our early years and share, as accurately as we can, what happened during our sleep.

And first I am bound to present a faithful picture of my own peculiar nature relatively to sleep. I do not doubt that were every individual to imitate me, it would be found that among many circumstances peculiar to their individual nature, a sufficiently general resemblance would be found to prove the connexion existing between those peculiarities and the most universal phenomena. I shall employ caution, indeed, as to the facts which I state, that they contain nothing false or exaggerated. But they contain no more than certain elucidations of my own nature; concerning the degree in which it resembles, or differs from, that of others, I am by no means accurately aware. It is sufficient, however, to caution the reader against drawing general inferences from particular instances.

First, I need to give an honest description of my unique relationship with sleep. I have no doubt that if everyone were to imitate me, we would find that despite the many individual differences, there would still be enough similarities to show a connection between those differences and the most universal experiences. I will be careful about the facts I share, ensuring they are neither false nor exaggerated. However, these facts will only shed light on my own nature; I’m not entirely sure how much it resembles or differs from others. It is important for the reader to be cautious about making broad conclusions based on specific examples.

I omit the general instances of delusion in fever or delirium, as well as mere dreams considered in themselves. A delineation of this subject, however inexhaustible and interesting, is to be passed over. What is the connexion of sleeping and of waking?

I’m skipping the common cases of delusion seen in fever or delirium, along with simple dreams taken on their own. A detailed exploration of this topic, no matter how endless and intriguing, will be overlooked. What’s the link between sleeping and waking?

2. I distinctly remember dreaming three several times, between intervals of two or more years, the same precise dream. It was not so much what is ordinarily called a dream; the single image, unconnected with all other images, of a youth who was educated at the same school with myself, presented itself in sleep. Even now, after the lapse of many years, I can never hear the name of this youth, without the three places where I dreamed of him presenting themselves distinctly to my mind.

2. I clearly remember dreaming the same exact dream three times, spaced out over two or more years. It wasn't what people usually think of as a dream; it was just a single image of a young man who went to the same school as I did. Even now, after so many years, I can't hear his name without vividly recalling the three different places where I dreamed about him.

3. In dreams, images acquire associations peculiar to dreaming; so that the idea of a particular house, when it recurs a second time in dreams, will have relation with the idea of the same house, in the first time, of a nature entirely different from that which the house excites, when seen or thought of in relation to waking ideas.

3. In dreams, images take on unique associations; so when a specific house appears again in dreams, it relates to the idea of that house from the first time, in a way that’s completely different from how the house is perceived or thought of in relation to waking thoughts.

4. I have beheld scenes, with the intimate and unaccountable connexion of which with the obscure parts of my own nature, I have been irresistibly impressed. I have beheld a scene which has produced no unusual effect on my thoughts. After the lapse of many years I have dreamed of this scene. It has hung on my memory, it has haunted my thoughts, at intervals, with the pertinacity of an object connected with human affections. I have visited this scene again. Neither the dream could be dissociated from the landscape, nor the landscape from the dream, nor feelings, such as neither singly could have awakened, from both.

4. I've seen scenes that have a deep and mysterious connection to parts of myself that I can't explain, and I've been strongly affected by them. There's one scene that hasn't had an unusual impact on my thoughts. Even after many years, I've dreamed about this scene. It's stuck in my memory, lingering in my mind with the persistence of something tied to human emotions. I've returned to this scene again. The dream can't be separated from the landscape, nor can the landscape be separated from the dream, and the feelings they evoke together are something neither alone could have stirred up.

But the most remarkable event of this nature, which ever occurred to me, happened five years ago at Oxford. I was walking with a friend, in the neighbourhood of that city, engaged in earnest and interesting conversation. We suddenly turned the corner of a lane, and the view, which its high banks and hedges had concealed, presented itself. The view consisted of a wind-mill, standing in one among many plashy meadows, inclosed with stone walls; the irregular and broken ground, between the wall and the road on which we stood; a long low hill behind the windmill, and a grey covering of uniform cloud spread over the evening sky. It was that season when the last leaf had just fallen from the scant and stunted ash. The scene surely was a common scene; the season and the hour little calculated to kindle lawless thought; it was a tame uninteresting assemblage of objects, such as would drive the imagination for refuge in serious and sober talk, to the evening fireside, and the dessert of winter fruits and wine. The effect which it produced on me was not such as could have been expected. I suddenly remembered to have seen that exact scene in some dream of long—. [Footnote: Here I was obliged to leave off, overcome by thrilling horror.]

But the most remarkable event of this kind that ever happened to me took place five years ago in Oxford. I was walking with a friend in that city, having a serious and interesting conversation. Suddenly, we turned a corner, and the view hidden by the tall banks and hedges revealed itself. The view included a windmill standing among several marshy meadows, enclosed by stone walls; the uneven ground between the wall and the road we were on; a long, low hill behind the windmill; and a blanket of uniform grey clouds over the evening sky. It was that time of year when the last leaf had just fallen from the sparse and stunted ash tree. The scene was certainly ordinary; the season and hour weren’t exactly designed to spark reckless thoughts; it was a dull, uninteresting collection of objects, the kind that would drive the imagination to seek solace in serious conversations by the evening fire, along with winter fruits and wine. The effect it had on me was unexpected. I suddenly remembered having seen that exact scene in some long-ago dream. [Footnote: Here I was forced to stop, overwhelmed by chilling horror.]

[1815; publ. 1840]

[1815; published 1840]










SPECULATIONS ON MORALS

I—PLAN OF A TREATISE ON MORALS

That great science which regards nature and the operations of the human mind, is popularly divided into Morals and Metaphysics. The latter relates to a just classification, and the assignment of distinct names to its ideas; the former regards simply the determination of that arrangement of them which produces the greatest and most solid happiness. It is admitted that a virtuous or moral action, is that action which, when considered in all its accessories and consequences, is fitted to produce the highest pleasure to the greatest number of sensitive beings. The laws according to which all pleasure, since it cannot be equally felt by all sensitive beings, ought to be distributed by a voluntary agent, are reserved for a separate chapter.

That important science that looks at nature and how the human mind works is commonly divided into Ethics and Metaphysics. The latter focuses on properly categorizing and naming its concepts; the former is solely about figuring out the arrangement of those concepts that leads to the greatest and most lasting happiness. It's widely accepted that a virtuous or moral action is one that, when considered alongside its details and results, is likely to create the highest pleasure for the largest number of sentient beings. The principles that guide how pleasure, since it can't be experienced equally by all sentient beings, should be distributed by a voluntary agent will be discussed in a separate chapter.

The design of this little treatise is restricted to the development of the elementary principles of morals. As far as regards that purpose, metaphysical science will be treated merely so far as a source of negative truth; whilst morality will be considered as a science, respecting which we can arrive at positive conclusions.

The goal of this brief essay is to outline the basic principles of morals. For this purpose, we'll consider metaphysical science only to the extent that it provides negative insights; meanwhile, morality will be viewed as a science from which we can draw positive conclusions.

The misguided imaginations of men have rendered the ascertaining of what IS NOT TRUE, the principal direct service which metaphysical science can bestow upon moral science. Moral science itself is the doctrine of the voluntary actions of man, as a sentient and social being. These actions depend on the thoughts in his mind. But there is a mass of popular opinion, from which the most enlightened persons are seldom wholly free, into the truth or falsehood of which it is incumbent on us to inquire, before we can arrive at any firm conclusions as to the conduct which we ought to pursue in the regulation of our own minds, or towards our fellow beings; or before we can ascertain the elementary laws, according to which these thoughts, from which these actions flow, are originally combined.

The misguided ideas of people have made figuring out what IS NOT TRUE the main direct benefit that metaphysical science can offer to moral science. Moral science itself is about understanding the voluntary actions of humans as sentient and social beings. These actions depend on the thoughts in their minds. However, there is a lot of popular opinion that even the most enlightened people are rarely completely free from, and it's essential for us to investigate the truth or falsehood of this opinion before we can reach any solid conclusions about how we should regulate our own minds or interact with others; or before we can understand the basic laws that originally connect these thoughts, from which these actions arise.

The object of the forms according to which human society is administered, is the happiness of the individuals composing the communities which they regard, and these forms are perfect or imperfect in proportion to the degree in which they promote this end.

The purpose of the structures through which human society is organized is to ensure the happiness of the individuals within the communities they encompass, and these structures are considered perfect or imperfect based on how well they achieve this goal.

This object is not merely the quantity of happiness enjoyed by individuals as sensitive beings, but the mode in which it should be distributed among them as social beings. It is not enough, if such a coincidence can be conceived as possible, that one person or class of persons should enjoy the highest happiness, whilst another is suffering a disproportionate degree of misery. It is necessary that the happiness produced by the common efforts, and preserved by the common care, should be distributed according to the just claims of each individual; if not, although the quantity produced should be the same, the end of society would remain unfulfilled. The object is in a compound proportion to the quantity of happiness produced, and the correspondence of the mode in which it is distributed, to the elementary feelings of man as a social being.

This topic isn't just about the amount of happiness people experience as sensitive beings; it's also about how that happiness should be shared among them as social beings. It's not enough, even if we could imagine it being possible, for one person or group to have the highest happiness while another suffers an unfair amount of misery. It's essential that the happiness created through our collective efforts and maintained through our shared responsibilities is distributed fairly based on each person's rightful claims. If this doesn't happen, even if the total amount of happiness remains the same, society's purpose won't be achieved. The goal relates both to the overall happiness produced and to how well its distribution aligns with the fundamental feelings of people as social beings.

The disposition in an individual to promote this object is called virtue; and the two constituent parts of virtue, benevolence and justice, are correlative with these two great portions of the only true object of all voluntary actions of a human being. Benevolence is the desire to be the author of good, and justice the apprehension of the manner in which good ought to be done.

The tendency in a person to pursue this goal is called virtue; and the two main components of virtue, kindness and fairness, are linked to these two key aspects of the only true aim of all voluntary actions of a human being. Kindness is the wish to do good, and fairness is the understanding of how good should be done.

Justice and benevolence result from the elementary laws of the human mind.

Justice and kindness come from the basic principles of the human mind.










CHAPTER I ON THE NATURE OF VIRTUE

SECT. 1. General View of the Nature and Objects of Virtue.—2. The Origin and Basis of Virtue, as founded on the Elementary Principles of Mind.—3. The Laws which flow from the nature of Mind regulating the application of those principles to human actions;—4. Virtue, a possible attribute of man.

SECT. 1. Overview of the Nature and Purpose of Virtue.—2. The Origin and Foundation of Virtue, based on the Basic Principles of Mind.—3. The Laws that arise from the nature of Mind, governing how those principles apply to human actions;—4. Virtue as a potential characteristic of humanity.

We exist in the midst of a multitude of beings like ourselves, upon whose happiness most of our actions exert some obvious and decisive influence.

We live among many other people like us, and our actions have a clear and significant impact on their happiness.

The regulation of this influence is the object of moral science. We know that we are susceptible of receiving painful or pleasurable impressions of greater or less intensity and duration. That is called good which produces pleasure; that is called evil which produces pain. These are general names, applicable to every class of causes, from which an overbalance of pain or pleasure may result. But when a human being is the active instrument of generating or diffusing happiness, the principle through which it is most effectually instrumental to that purpose, is called virtue. And benevolence, or the desire to be the author of good, united with justice, or an apprehension of the manner in which that good is to be done, constitutes virtue.

The regulation of this influence is the focus of moral science. We know that we can experience painful or pleasurable feelings with varying intensity and duration. What we refer to as good produces pleasure, while what we call evil causes pain. These are broad terms that apply to every type of cause that can lead to either more pain or more pleasure. However, when a person actively creates or spreads happiness, the principle that most effectively helps achieve this goal is called virtue. Benevolence, or the wish to create good, combined with justice, or an understanding of how that good should be achieved, makes up virtue.

But wherefore should a man be benevolent and just? The immediate emotions of his nature, especially in its most inartificial state, prompt him to inflict pain, and to arrogate dominion. He desires to heap superfluities to his own store, although others perish with famine. He is propelled to guard against the smallest invasion of his own liberty, though he reduces others to a condition of the most pitiless servitude. He is revengeful, proud and selfish. Wherefore should he curb these propensities?

But why should a man be kind and fair? His natural instincts, especially in their rawest form, push him to cause harm and assert control. He wants to gather excess for himself, even if it means that others suffer from hunger. He feels compelled to protect even the slightest threat to his own freedom, while pushing others into extreme slavery. He is vengeful, arrogant, and self-centered. So why should he hold back these instincts?

It is inquired, for what reason a human being should engage in procuring the happiness, or refrain from producing the pain of another? When a reason is required to prove the necessity of adopting any system of conduct, what is it that the objector demands? He requires proof of that system of conduct being such as will most effectually promote the happiness of mankind. To demonstrate this, is to render a moral reason. Such is the object of virtue.

Why should a person work to create happiness or avoid causing pain for someone else? When someone asks for a reason to support a way of behaving, what are they really looking for? They want evidence that this way of behaving will best promote human happiness. Providing this evidence gives a moral justification. That’s the goal of virtue.

A common sophism, which, like many others, depends on the abuse of a metaphorical expression to a literal purpose, has produced much of the confusion which has involved the theory of morals. It is said that no person is bound to be just or kind, if, on his neglect, he should fail to incur some penalty. Duty is obligation. There can be no obligation without an obliger. Virtue is a law, to which it is the will of the lawgiver that we should conform; which will we should in no manner be bound to obey, unless some dreadful punishment were attached to disobedience. This is the philosophy of slavery and superstition.

A common fallacy, like many others, relies on misusing a metaphor and taking it literally, causing a lot of confusion in moral theory. It’s argued that no one is required to be just or kind if they don’t face any consequences for their neglect. Duty means obligation. There can't be an obligation without someone to obligate. Virtue is a law that the lawgiver wants us to follow; we wouldn’t feel any obligation to obey it unless there was some terrible punishment for not doing so. This is the mindset of slavery and superstition.

In fact, no person can be BOUND or OBLIGED, without some power preceding to bind and oblige. If I observe a man bound hand and foot, I know that some one bound him. But if I observe him returning self-satisfied from the performance of some action, by which he has been the willing author of extensive benefit, I do not infer that the anticipation of hellish agonies, or the hope of heavenly reward, has constrained him to such an act.

In fact, no one can be BOUND or OBLIGED without some power that precedes their obligation. If I see a man tied up, I know someone must have tied him. But if I see him coming back satisfied from doing something that he willingly contributed to for a greater good, I don’t assume that the fear of hell or the hope of heaven made him do it.

       .      .      .      .      .       .       .
.      .      .      .      .       .       .

It remains to be stated in what manner the sensations which constitute the basis of virtue originate in the human mind; what are the laws which it receives there; how far the principles of mind allow it to be an attribute of a human being; and, lastly, what is the probability of persuading mankind to adopt it as a universal and systematic motive of conduct.

It’s important to explain how the feelings that form the foundation of virtue arise in the human mind; what rules are accepted there; to what extent the principles of the mind enable it to be a trait of a person; and, finally, what the chances are of convincing humanity to embrace it as a universal and systematic guiding principle for behavior.

BENEVOLENCE

There is a class of emotions which we instinctively avoid. A human being, such as is man considered in his origin, a child a month old, has a very imperfect consciousness of the existence of other natures resembling itself. All the energies of its being are directed to the extinction of the pains with which it is perpetually assailed. At length it discovers that it is surrounded by natures susceptible of sensations similar to its own. It is very late before children attain to this knowledge. If a child observes, without emotion, its nurse or its mother suffering acute pain, it is attributable rather to ignorance than insensibility. So soon as the accents and gestures, significant of pain, are referred to the feelings which they express, they awaken in the mind of the beholder a desire that they should cease. Pain is thus apprehended to be evil for its own sake, without any other necessary reference to the mind by which its existence is perceived, than such as is indispensable to its perception. The tendencies of our original sensations, indeed, all have for their object the preservation of our individual being. But these are passive and unconscious. In proportion as the mind acquires an active power, the empire of these tendencies becomes limited. Thus an infant, a savage, and a solitary beast, is selfish, because its mind is incapable of receiving an accurate intimation of the nature of pain as existing in beings resembling itself. The inhabitant of a highly civilized community will more acutely sympathize with the sufferings and enjoyments of others, than the inhabitant of a society of a less degree of civilization. He who shall have cultivated his intellectual powers by familiarity with the highest specimens of poetry and philosophy, will usually sympathize more than one engaged in the less refined functions of manual labour. Every one has experience of the fact, that to sympathize with the sufferings of another, is to enjoy a transitory oblivion of his own.

There are certain emotions that we instinctively shy away from. A human being, like a man in his early days, or a one-month-old baby, has a very limited awareness of the existence of other beings similar to itself. All of its energy is focused on relieving the pains that constantly affect it. Eventually, it realizes that it is surrounded by others who can feel sensations similar to its own. It takes a long time for children to reach this understanding. If a child sees its caregiver or parent in acute pain without showing any emotion, it's more due to ignorance than a lack of sensitivity. As soon as the sounds and movements indicating pain are connected to the feelings they convey, they trigger a desire in the observer for that pain to stop. Pain is understood to be bad in itself, without requiring any additional connection to the mind that perceives its existence, aside from the basic awareness needed to recognize it. The natural tendency of our original sensations is to ensure our own survival. However, these responses are passive and unconscious. As the mind gains active power, the influence of these tendencies becomes more limited. Thus, an infant, an uncivilized person, or a solitary animal may seem selfish because their minds can't fully grasp the nature of pain as it exists in beings like themselves. Someone living in a highly developed society will empathize more with the suffering and joys of others than someone from a less advanced society. A person who has developed their intellectual abilities through exposure to the finest poetry and philosophy will typically empathize more than someone engaged in less refined manual work. Everyone has experienced that sympathizing with someone else's suffering offers a brief escape from their own.

The mind thus acquires, by exercise, a habit, as it were, of perceiving and abhorring evil, however remote from the immediate sphere of sensations with which that individual mind is conversant. Imagination or mind employed in prophetically imaging forth its objects, is that faculty of human nature on which every gradation of its progress, nay, every, the minutest, change, depends. Pain or pleasure, if subtly analysed, will be found to consist entirely in prospect. The only distinction between the selfish man and the virtuous man is, that the imagination of the former is confined within a narrow limit, whilst that of the latter embraces a comprehensive circumference. In this sense, wisdom and virtue may be said to be inseparable, and criteria of each other. Selfishness is the offspring of ignorance and mistake; it is the portion of unreflecting infancy, and savage solitude, or of those whom toil or evil occupations have blunted or rendered torpid; disinterested benevolence is the product of a cultivated imagination, and has an intimate connexion with all the arts which add ornament, or dignity, or power, or stability to the social state of man. Virtue is thus entirely a refinement of civilized life; a creation of the human mind; or, rather, a combination which it has made, according to elementary rules contained within itself, of the feelings suggested by the relations established between man and man.

The mind develops a habit of recognizing and rejecting evil through practice, even if that evil is far removed from the immediate experiences of that individual. Imagination, or the mind's ability to envision its objects, is the part of human nature that determines every aspect of its development and every tiny change. When analyzed closely, pain or pleasure turns out to be based entirely on anticipation. The only difference between a selfish person and a virtuous person is that the imagination of the former is limited, while that of the latter is expansive and inclusive. In this sense, wisdom and virtue are closely linked and serve as measures of one another. Selfishness arises from ignorance and misunderstanding; it belongs to those who are unreflective, in their early stages of development, or isolated, or to those whose hard work or negative experiences have dulled their senses; while selfless kindness comes from a well-developed imagination and is deeply connected to all the arts that enhance the dignity, strength, or stability of human society. Therefore, virtue is a refinement of civilized life, a creation of the human mind, or more accurately, a synthesis formed according to basic principles within itself, based on the feelings influenced by the relationships between individuals.

All the theories which have refined and exalted humanity, or those which have been devised as alleviations of its mistakes and evils, have been based upon the elementary emotions of disinterestedness, which we feel to constitute the majesty of our nature. Patriotism, as it existed in the ancient republics, was never, as has been supposed, a calculation of personal advantages. When Mutius Scaevola thrust his hand into the burning coals, and Regulus returned to Carthage, and Epicharis sustained the rack silently, in the torments of which she knew that she would speedily perish, rather than betray the conspirators to the tyrant [Footnote: Tacitus.]; these illustrious persons certainly made a small estimate of their private interest. If it be said that they sought posthumous fame; instances are not wanting in history which prove that men have even defied infamy for the sake of good. But there is a great error in the world with respect to the selfishness of fame. It is certainly possible that a person should seek distinction as a medium of personal gratification. But the love of fame is frequently no more than a desire that the feelings of others should confirm, illustrate, and sympathize with, our own. In this respect it is allied with all that draws us out of ourselves. It is the 'last infirmity of noble minds'. Chivalry was likewise founded on the theory of self-sacrifice. Love possesses so extraordinary a power over the human heart, only because disinterestedness is united with the natural propensities. These propensities themselves are comparatively impotent in cases where the imagination of pleasure to be given, as well as to be received, does not enter into the account. Let it not be objected that patriotism, and chivalry, and sentimental love, have been the fountains of enormous mischief. They are cited only to establish the proposition that, according to the elementary principles of mind, man is capable of desiring and pursuing good for its own sake.

All the theories that have improved and elevated humanity, or those created to ease its mistakes and wrongs, have been built on the basic emotions of selflessness, which we believe represent the greatness of our nature. Patriotism, as it was understood in ancient republics, was never really about calculating personal benefits. When Mutius Scaevola plunged his hand into the burning coals, when Regulus chose to return to Carthage, and when Epicharis endured torture in silence, knowing she would soon die rather than betray the conspirators to the tyrant [Footnote: Tacitus.]; these remarkable individuals clearly placed little value on their own interests. If it is argued that they were seeking fame after death; there are plenty of historical examples showing that people have even faced disgrace for the sake of good. However, there is a significant misunderstanding in the world regarding the selfishness of fame. It is indeed possible for someone to pursue recognition as a way of satisfying personal desires. But the desire for fame often reflects a wish for others to acknowledge, highlight, and empathize with our own feelings. In this sense, it connects to everything that draws us beyond ourselves. It is the “last weakness of noble minds.” Chivalry was also based on the idea of self-sacrifice. Love has such a remarkable power over the human heart precisely because selflessness is combined with natural inclinations. These inclinations themselves are relatively weak when the imagination of pleasure, both given and received, is not part of the equation. Let it not be said that patriotism, chivalry, and romantic love have caused great harm. They are mentioned only to support the idea that, according to the fundamental principles of the mind, humans are capable of wanting and pursuing good for its own sake.

JUSTICE

The benevolent propensities are thus inherent in the human mind. We are impelled to seek the happiness of others. We experience a satisfaction in being the authors of that happiness. Everything that lives is open to impressions or pleasure and pain. We are led by our benevolent propensities to regard every human being indifferently with whom we come in contact. They have preference only with respect to those who offer themselves most obviously to our notice. Human beings are indiscriminating and blind; they will avoid inflicting pain, though that pain should be attended with eventual benefit; they will seek to confer pleasure without calculating the mischief that may result. They benefit one at the expense of many.

Benevolent tendencies are inherent in the human mind. We're driven to seek the happiness of others and feel good about being the source of that happiness. Everything that lives is susceptible to pleasure and pain. Our benevolent tendencies lead us to regard every person we come into contact with in a neutral way, with preferences only towards those who stand out to us. People are often indiscriminate and blind; they will avoid causing pain, even if that pain could lead to eventual benefits; they seek to provide pleasure without considering the potential harm that might come from it. They often help one person at the expense of many.

There is a sentiment in the human mind that regulates benevolence in its application as a principle of action. This is the sense of justice. Justice, as well as benevolence, is an elementary law of human nature. It is through this principle that men are impelled to distribute any means of pleasure which benevolence may suggest the communication of to others, in equal portions among an equal number of applicants. If ten men are shipwrecked on a desert island, they distribute whatever subsistence may remain to them, into equal portions among themselves. If six of them conspire to deprive the remaining four of their share, their conduct is termed unjust.

There’s a feeling in the human mind that controls how kindness is applied as a guiding principle. This is the sense of justice. Justice, like kindness, is a fundamental aspect of human nature. It is through this principle that people are driven to share any means of happiness that kindness might encourage, distributing it equally among an equal number of people. For example, if ten men are shipwrecked on a deserted island, they will share any food or resources they have left in equal parts among themselves. If six of them scheme to take away the share of the remaining four, their actions are seen as unjust.

The existence of pain has been shown to be a circumstance which the human mind regards with dissatisfaction, and of which it desires the cessation. It is equally according to its nature to desire that the advantages to be enjoyed by a limited number of persons should be enjoyed equally by all. This proposition is supported by the evidence of indisputable facts. Tell some ungarbled tale of a number of persons being made the victims of the enjoyments of one, and he who would appeal in favour of any system which might produce such an evil to the primary emotions of our nature, would have nothing to reply. Let two persons, equally strangers, make application for some benefit in the possession of a third to bestow, and to which he feels that they have an equal claim. They are both sensitive beings; pleasure and pain affect them alike.

The presence of pain is something that the human mind experiences with dissatisfaction and wants to end. It’s also natural for people to wish that the benefits enjoyed by a few should be shared equally among all. This idea is backed by clear evidence. If you tell an unfiltered story of several people suffering because one person is enjoying themselves, anyone who defends a system that allows for such unfairness would have no response. If two strangers ask for some benefit that a third person has the power to grant, and they both feel they have equal rights to it, they are both sensitive beings; pleasure and pain impact them in the same way.










CHAPTER II

It is foreign to the general scope of this little treatise to encumber a simple argument by controverting any of the trite objections of habit or fanaticism. But there are two; the first, the basis of all political mistake, and the second, the prolific cause and effect of religious error, which it seems useful to refute.

It doesn't fit the purpose of this brief essay to complicate a straightforward argument by addressing any of the common objections based on tradition or extreme beliefs. However, there are two objections worth refuting: the first, the root of all political mistakes, and the second, the frequent cause and result of religious errors.

First, it is inquired, 'Wherefore should a man be benevolent and just?' The answer has been given in the preceding chapter.

First, the question is asked, 'Why should a person be kind and fair?' The answer has been provided in the previous chapter.

If a man persists to inquire why he ought to promote the happiness of mankind, he demands a mathematical or metaphysical reason for a moral action. The absurdity of this scepticism is more apparent, but not less real than the exacting a moral reason for a mathematical or metaphysical fact. If any person should refuse to admit that all the radii of a circle are of equal length, or that human actions are necessarily determined by motives, until it could be proved that these radii and these actions uniformly tended to the production of the greatest general good, who would not wonder at the unreasonable and capricious association of his ideas?

If a man keeps asking why he should promote the happiness of humanity, he's looking for a mathematical or philosophical reason for a moral action. The absurdity of this skepticism is clearer, but no less real than demanding a moral justification for a mathematical or philosophical fact. If someone were to refuse to accept that all the radii of a circle are equal, or that human actions are inevitably influenced by motives, until it could be proven that these radii and actions consistently aimed at creating the greatest overall good, who wouldn't be amazed at the unreasonable and random connections in his thinking?

The writer of a philosophical treatise may, I imagine, at this advanced era of human intellect, be held excused from entering into a controversy with those reasoners, if such there are, who would claim an exemption from its decrees in favour of any one among those diversified systems of obscure opinion respecting morals, which, under the name of religions, have in various ages and countries prevailed among mankind. Besides that if, as these reasoners have pretended, eternal torture or happiness will ensue as the consequence of certain actions, we should be no nearer the possession of a standard to determine what actions were right and wrong, even if this pretended revelation, which is by no means the case, had furnished us with a complete catalogue of them. The character of actions as virtuous or vicious would by no means be determined alone by the personal advantage or disadvantage of each moral agent individually considered. Indeed, an action is often virtuous in proportion to the greatness of the personal calamity which the author willingly draws upon himself by daring to perform it. It is because an action produces an overbalance of pleasure or pain to the greatest number of sentient beings, and not merely because its consequences are beneficial or injurious to the author of that action, that it is good or evil. Nay, this latter consideration has a tendency to pollute the purity of virtue, inasmuch as it consists in the motive rather than in the consequences of an action. A person who should labour for the happiness of mankind lest he should be tormented eternally in Hell, would, with reference to that motive, possess as little claim to the epithet of virtuous, as he who should torture, imprison, and burn them alive, a more usual and natural consequence of such principles, for the sake of the enjoyments of Heaven.

The writer of a philosophical essay might, I think, be excused in this advanced age of human thought from debating with those thinkers, if there are any, who would claim a pass from its conclusions in favor of any one of the various obscure moral belief systems that, under the name of religions, have influenced people throughout different times and cultures. Moreover, even if these thinkers are correct that eternal suffering or joy will follow from certain actions, we still wouldn’t be any closer to having a clear standard to decide which actions are right and wrong, even if this supposed revelation had actually given us a complete list of them. The nature of actions as good or bad wouldn’t be determined solely by the personal benefit or harm to each moral agent considered individually. In fact, an action is often more virtuous based on the significant personal suffering that the doer willingly takes on by choosing to do it. It’s because an action leads to a greater balance of pleasure or pain for the most people involved, and not just because its results are good or bad for the person performing it, that it is classified as good or evil. Furthermore, focusing only on the latter can corrupt the essence of virtue, since virtue lies in the intention rather than the outcomes of an action. A person who works for the happiness of others to avoid eternal damnation would, based on that motivation, have as little right to be called virtuous as someone who tortures, imprisons, and kills for the sake of enjoying Heaven, which is a more common and natural outcome of such beliefs.

My neighbour, presuming on his strength, may direct me to perform or to refrain from a particular action; indicating a certain arbitrary penalty in the event of disobedience within power to inflict. My action, if modified by his menaces, can no degree participate in virtue. He has afforded me no criterion as to what is right or wrong. A king, or an assembly of men, may publish a proclamation affixing any penalty to any particular action, but that is not immoral because such penalty is affixed. Nothing is more evident than that the epithet of virtue is inapplicable to the refraining from that action on account of the evil arbitrarily attached to it. If the action is in itself beneficial, virtue would rather consist in not refraining from it, but in firmly defying the personal consequences attached to its performance.

My neighbor, relying on his strength, might try to tell me to do or not do something, threatening a specific punishment if I don't obey, which he is capable of enforcing. If my behavior is influenced by his threats, it can't be considered virtuous at all. He hasn't given me any standards for what's right or wrong. A king or a group of people can issue a rule with some penalty attached to a certain action, but that doesn't make it immoral just because there's a penalty. It's obvious that calling something virtuous isn't applicable when someone avoids an action simply because of the arbitrary punishment tied to it. If the action itself is beneficial, true virtue would actually mean not avoiding it and instead standing firm against the personal consequences that come from doing it.

Some usurper of supernatural energy might subdue the whole globe to his power; he might possess new and unheard-of resources for enduing his punishments with the most terrible attributes or pain. The torments of his victims might be intense in their degree, and protracted to an infinite duration. Still the 'will of the lawgiver' would afford no surer criterion as to what actions were right or wrong. It would only increase the possible virtue of those who refuse to become the instruments of his tyranny.

Some usurper of supernatural energy could take control of the entire world; he might have new and unimaginable ways to make his punishments even more horrific. The suffering of his victims could be extreme and last forever. Still, the 'will of the lawmaker' wouldn't provide a clearer standard for what actions are right or wrong. It would only enhance the virtue of those who refuse to be his tools of tyranny.

II—MORAL SCIENCE CONSISTS IN CONSIDERING THE DIFFERENCE, NOT THE RESEMBLANCE, OF PERSONS

II—MORAL SCIENCE IS ABOUT EXAMINING THE DIFFERENCE, NOT THE SIMILARITY, BETWEEN PEOPLE

The internal influence, derived from the constitution of the mind from which they flow, produces that peculiar modification of actions, which makes them intrinsically good or evil.

The internal influence, coming from the nature of the mind that generates them, creates that unique change in actions that makes them inherently good or bad.

To attain an apprehension of the importance of this distinction, let us visit, in imagination, the proceedings of some metropolis. Consider the multitude of human beings who inhabit it, and survey, in thought, the actions of the several classes into which they are divided. Their obvious actions are apparently uniform: the stability of human society seems to be maintained sufficiently by the uniformity of the conduct of its members, both with regard to themselves, and with regard to others. The labourer arises at a certain hour, and applies himself to the task enjoined him. The functionaries of government and law are regularly employed in their offices and courts. The trader holds a train of conduct from which he never deviates. The ministers of religion employ an accustomed language, and maintain a decent and equable regard. The army is drawn forth, the motions of every soldier are such as they were expected to be; the general commands, and his words are echoed from troop to troop. The domestic actions of men are, for the most part, undistinguishable one from the other, at a superficial glance. The actions which are classed under the general appellation of marriage, education, friendship, &c., are perpetually going on, and to a superficial glance, are similar one to the other.

To understand the significance of this distinction, let’s imagine the activities in a major city. Think about the countless people who live there and consider the various groups they belong to. Their obvious actions seem very similar: the stability of society appears to rely on the consistent behavior of its members, both in relation to themselves and to others. The laborer gets up at a specific time and focuses on the job assigned to him. Government and legal officials are routinely engaged in their offices and courts. The trader follows a pattern of behavior that never changes. Religious leaders use familiar language and maintain a respectful and calm demeanor. The army is deployed, and every soldier acts as expected; the general gives commands, and his orders are echoed from unit to unit. Most of the daily actions of individuals look pretty much the same at first glance. The activities categorized as marriage, education, friendship, etc., continually occur and, to a casual observer, appear quite similar to one another.

But, if we would see the truth of things, they must be stripped of this fallacious appearance of uniformity. In truth, no one action has, when considered in its whole extent, any essential resemblance with any other. Each individual, who composes the vast multitude which we have been contemplating, has a peculiar frame of mind, which, whilst the features of the great mass of his actions remain uniform, impresses the minuter lineaments with its peculiar hues. Thus, whilst his life, as a whole, is like the lives of other men, in detail, it is most unlike; and the more subdivided the actions become; that is, the more they enter into that class which have a vital influence on the happiness of others and his own, so much the more are they distinct from those of other men.

But if we want to see the truth of things, we need to strip away this misleading appearance of uniformity. In reality, no single action, when looked at in its entirety, truly resembles any other. Each individual, who makes up the vast number of people we’ve been observing, has a unique mindset that, while the overall traits of his actions may seem uniform, colors the finer details with its distinctive qualities. So, while his life as a whole is similar to the lives of others, in the details, it is very different; and the more we break down the actions—specifically those that significantly affect the happiness of others and himself—the more they stand apart from those of other people.

      Those little, nameless, unremembered acts
          Of kindness and of love,
      Those small, unnamed, forgotten acts
          Of kindness and of love,

as well as those deadly outrages which are inflicted by a look, a word—or less—the very refraining from some faint and most evanescent expression of countenance; these flow from a profounder source than the series of our habitual conduct, which, it has been already said, derives its origin from without. These are the actions, and such as these, which make human life what it is, and are the fountains of all the good and evil with which its entire surface is so widely and impartially overspread; and though they are called minute, they are called so in compliance with the blindness of those who cannot estimate their importance. It is in the due appreciating the general effects of their peculiarities, and in cultivating the habit of acquiring decisive knowledge respecting the tendencies arising out of them in particular cases, that the most important part of moral science consists. The deepest abyss of these vast and multitudinous caverns, it is necessary that we should visit.

as well as those harmful acts that can be caused by a glance, a word—or even less—a simple lack of any slight, fleeting expression on our face; these stem from a deeper place than our usual behavior, which has already been mentioned as coming from external sources. These are the actions, among others, that shape human life and are the sources of all the good and bad that blanket our existence so broadly and without bias; and even though they are termed minor, it's only because of the shortsightedness of those who can’t grasp their significance. The key to moral science lies in properly recognizing the overall impact of these subtleties and developing the habit of gaining clear insights into the implications they carry in specific situations. We must explore the deepest depths of these vast and numerous caverns.

This is the difference between social and individual man. Not that this distinction is to be considered definite, or characteristic of one human being as compared with another; it denotes rather two classes of agency, common in a degree to every human being. None is exempt, indeed, from that species of influence which affects, as it were, the surface of his being, and gives the specific outline to his conduct. Almost all that is ostensible submits to that legislature created by the general representation of the past feelings of mankind—imperfect as it is from a variety of causes, as it exists in the government, the religion, and domestic habits. Those who do not nominally, yet actually, submit to the same power. The external features of their conduct, indeed, can no more escape it, than the clouds can escape from the stream of the wind; and his opinion, which he often hopes he has dispassionately secured from all contagion of prejudice and vulgarity, would be found, on examination, to be the inevitable excrescence of the very usages from which he vehemently dissents. Internally all is conducted otherwise; the efficiency, the essence, the vitality of actions, derives its colour from what is no ways contributed to from any external source. Like the plant which while it derives the accident of its size and shape from the soil in which it springs, and is cankered, or distorted, or inflated, yet retains those qualities which essentially divide it from all others; so that hemlock continues to be poison, and the violet does not cease to emit its odour in whatever soil it may grow.

This is the difference between social and individual man. This distinction shouldn’t be seen as fixed or specific to one person compared to another; it actually represents two types of influence that every human experiences to some degree. No one is free from the kind of influence that impacts the surface of their being and shapes their behavior. Almost everything that is visible conforms to the rules established by the general sentiments of humanity’s past—flawed as they are due to various reasons, found in systems of government, religion, and family traditions. Those who don’t openly submit still actually follow the same power. The outward aspects of their behavior can’t escape these influences, just like clouds can’t avoid the force of the wind; and any opinion that someone believes they’ve formed independently from biases and common views would, upon closer inspection, reveal itself to be a product of the very customs they strongly reject. Internally, everything operates differently; the effectiveness, the essence, the life of actions comes from sources not influenced by anything external. Like a plant that gets its size and shape from the soil it grows in, which may cause it to become damaged, twisted, or swollen, yet still retains the characteristics that set it apart from all others; hence, hemlock remains poison, and the violet continues to release its fragrance no matter where it grows.

We consider our own nature too superficially. We look on all that in ourselves with which we can discover a resemblance in others; and consider those resemblances as the materials of moral knowledge. It is in the differences that it actually consists.

We think about our own nature too lightly. We focus only on the aspects of ourselves that we can see reflected in others and view those similarities as the basis for moral understanding. In reality, it is the differences that truly define it.

[1815; publ. 1840]

[1815; published 1840]










ESSAY ON THE LITERATURE, THE ARTS, AND THE MANNERS OF THE ATHENIANS

A FRAGMENT

The period which intervened between the birth of Pericles and the death of Aristotle, is undoubtedly, whether considered in itself, or with reference to the effects which it has produced upon the subsequent destinies of civilized man, the most memorable in the history of the world. What was the combination of moral and political circumstances which produced so unparalleled a progress during that period in literature and the arts;—why that progress, so rapid and so sustained, so soon received a check, and became retrograde,—are problems left to the wonder and conjecture of posterity. The wrecks and fragments of those subtle and profound minds, like the ruins of a fine statue, obscurely suggest to us the grandeur and perfection of the whole. Their very language—a type of the understandings of which it was the creation and the image—in variety, in simplicity, in flexibility, and in copiousness, excels every other language of the western world. Their sculptures are such as we, in our presumption, assume to be the models of ideal truth and beauty, and to which no artist of modern times can produce forms in any degree comparable. Their paintings, according to Pliny and Pausanias, were full of delicacy and harmony; and some even were powerfully pathetic, so as to awaken, like tender music or tragic poetry, the most overwhelming emotions. We are accustomed to conceive the painters of the sixteenth century, as those who have brought their art to the highest perfection, probably because none of the ancient paintings have been preserved. For all the inventive arts maintain, as it were, a sympathetic connexion between each other, being no more than various expressions of one internal power, modified by different circumstances, either of an individual, or of society; and the paintings of that period would probably bear the same relation as is confessedly borne by the sculptures to all succeeding ones. Of their music we know little; but the effects which it is said to have produced, whether they be attributed to the skill of the composer, or the sensibility of his audience, are far more powerful than any which we experience from the music of our own times; and if, indeed, the melody of their compositions were more tender and delicate, and inspiring, than the melodies of some modern European nations, their superiority in this art must have been something wonderful, and wholly beyond conception.

The time between the birth of Pericles and the death of Aristotle is undoubtedly the most remarkable in the history of the world, both in itself and for its impact on the future of civilized humanity. What combination of moral and political factors led to such unprecedented progress in literature and the arts during that period? Why did this rapid and sustained progress soon come to a halt and start to decline? These questions remain a source of wonder and speculation for future generations. The remnants of those brilliant minds, much like the ruins of a beautiful statue, hint at the grandeur and perfection of the whole. Their language—a reflection of the intellect it shaped and mirrored—excels in variety, simplicity, flexibility, and richness compared to any other language in the Western world. Their sculptures are what we, in our arrogance, consider to be models of ideal truth and beauty, and no modern artist can create forms that come close. Their paintings, according to Pliny and Pausanias, were full of delicacy and harmony; some even evoked powerful emotions, much like soft music or tragic poetry. We tend to view the painters of the 16th century as having achieved the peak of artistic excellence, likely because none of the ancient paintings have survived. All the creative arts maintain a sympathetic connection to one another, serving as different expressions of a single internal force, shaped by various circumstances, whether of individuals or society; thus, the paintings of that period would likely hold the same significance as the sculptures do to the ones that followed. We know little about their music, but the effects it reportedly had, whether due to the composer’s skill or the audience’s sensitivity, were far more powerful than what we experience from our modern music; and if their melodies were indeed more tender, delicate, and inspiring than those of some modern European nations, their superiority in this art must have been truly remarkable and beyond our comprehension.

Their poetry seems to maintain a very high, though not so disproportionate a rank, in the comparison. Perhaps Shakespeare, from the variety and comprehension of his genius, is to be considered, on the whole, as the greatest individual mind, of which we have specimens remaining. Perhaps Dante created imaginations of greater loveliness and energy than any that are to be found in the ancient literature of Greece. Perhaps nothing has been discovered in the fragments of the Greek lyric poets equivalent to the sublime and chivalric sensibility of Petrarch.—But, as a poet. Homer must be acknowledged to excel Shakespeare in the truth, the harmony, the sustained grandeur, the satisfying completeness of his images, their exact fitness to the illustration, and to that to which they belong. Nor could Dante, deficient in conduct, plan, nature, variety, and temperance, have been brought into comparison with these men, but for those fortunate isles laden with golden fruit, which alone could tempt any one to embark in the misty ocean of his dark and extravagant fiction.

Their poetry seems to hold a very high, though not excessively disproportionate, rank in comparison. Shakespeare might be seen as the greatest individual intellect we have examples of, thanks to the range and depth of his genius. Dante possibly created visions of greater beauty and energy than anything found in the ancient literature of Greece. Perhaps nothing discovered in the remnants of the Greek lyric poets matches the sublime and noble sensibility of Petrarch. However, when it comes to poetry, Homer must be recognized as superior to Shakespeare in the truth, harmony, sustained grandeur, and satisfying completeness of his images, as well as their precise relevance to the themes they represent. Dante, lacking in structure, planning, nature, variety, and moderation, could only be compared to these greats because of those fortunate islands rich with golden fruit, which alone could entice anyone to venture into the foggy ocean of his dark and extravagant tales.

But, omitting the comparison of individual minds, which can afford no general inference, how superior was the spirit and system of their poetry to that of any other period! So that had any other genius equal in other respects to the greatest that ever enlightened the world, arisen in that age, he would have been superior to all, from this circumstance alone—that had conceptions would have assumed a more harmonious and perfect form. For it is worthy of observation, that whatever the poet of that age produced is as harmonious and perfect as possible. In a drama, for instance, were the composition of a person of inferior talent, it was still homogeneous and free from inequalities it was a whole, consistent with itself. The compositions of great minds bore throughout the sustained stamp of their greatness. In the poetry of succeeding ages the expectations are often exalted on Icarian wings, and fall, too much disappointed to give a memory and a name to the oblivious pool in which they fell.

But if we set aside the comparison of individual minds, which doesn’t lead to any broad conclusions, the spirit and structure of their poetry were far superior to any other period! So if any other genius, equal in other respects to the greatest that ever illuminated the world, had emerged during that time, he would have outshined everyone else simply because his ideas would have taken on a more harmonious and perfect form. It’s important to note that everything the poets of that time created was as harmonious and perfect as it could be. In a play, for instance, even if it was written by someone less talented, it still had a cohesive quality and was free from inconsistencies; it was a whole that made sense in itself. The works of great minds consistently carried the unmistakable mark of their greatness. In the poetry of later ages, expectations often soared high like Icarus but then fell, leaving behind too much disappointment to be remembered or named by the depths into which they fell.

In physical knowledge Aristotle and Theophrastus had already—no doubt assisted by the labours of those of their predecessor whom they criticize—made advances worthy of the maturity of science. The astonishing invention of geometry, that series of discoveries which have enabled man to command the element and foresee future events, before the subjects of his ignorant wonder, and which have opened as it were the doors of the mysteries of nature, had already been brought to great perfection. Metaphysics, the science of man's intimate nature, and logic, or the grammar and elementary principles of that science received from the latter philosophers of the Periclean age a firm basis. All our more exact philosophy is built upon the labours of these great men, and many of the words which we employ in metaphysical distinctions were invented by them to give accuracy and system to their reasonings. The science of morals, or the voluntary conduct of men in relation to themselves or others, dates from this epoch. How inexpressibly bolder and more pure were the doctrines of those great men, in comparison with the timid maxims which prevail in the writings of the most esteemed modern moralists! They were such as Phocion, and Epaminondas, and Timoleon, who formed themselves on their influence, were to the wretched heroes of our own age.

In physical knowledge, Aristotle and Theophrastus had already—no doubt aided by the efforts of their predecessors whom they critiqued—made significant advances worthy of the maturity of science. The remarkable invention of geometry, a series of discoveries that allowed people to control the elements and predict future events, previously subjects of their ignorant wonder, had already reached a high level of sophistication. Metaphysics, the study of human nature, and logic, which involves the basic principles of that study, gained a solid foundation from the latter philosophers of the Periclean era. All our more precise philosophy is built on the work of these great thinkers, and many of the terms we use in metaphysical discussions were created by them to add clarity and structure to their arguments. The study of ethics, or the voluntary actions of individuals towards themselves and others, began during this time. How infinitely bolder and more refined were the teachings of those great men compared to the cautious principles found in the writings of the most respected modern moralists! They were like Phocion, Epaminondas, and Timoleon, who shaped themselves under their influence, in stark contrast to the unfortunate heroes of our time.

Their political and religious institutions are more difficult to bring into comparison with those of other times. A summary idea may be formed of the worth of any political and religious system, by observing the comparative degree of happiness and of intellect produced under its influence. And whilst many institution and opinions, which in ancient Greece were obstacles to the improvement of the human race, have been abolished among modern nations, how many pernicious superstitions and new contrivances of misrule, and unheard-of complications of public mischief, have not been invented among them by the ever-watchful spirit of avarice and tyranny!

Their political and religious institutions are harder to compare with those from other times. You can get a general sense of the value of any political and religious system by looking at the level of happiness and intellect it produces. While many institutions and beliefs that held back humanity in ancient Greece have been eliminated in modern nations, there are still countless harmful superstitions, new forms of misrule, and unprecedented public troubles that have been created by the ever-watchful forces of greed and tyranny!

The modern nations of the civilized world owe the progress which they have made—as well in those physical sciences in which they have already excelled their masters, as in the moral and intellectual inquiries, in which, with all the advantage of the experience of the latter, it can scarcely be said that they have yet equalled them,—to what is called the revival of learning; that is, the study of the writers of the age which preceded and immediately followed the government of Pericles, or of subsequent writers, who were, so to speak, the rivers flowing from those immortal fountains. And though there seems to be a principle in the modern world, which, should circumstances analogous to those which modelled the intellectual resources of the age to which we refer, into so harmonious a proportion, again arise, would arrest and perpetuate them, and consign their results to a more equal, extensive, and lasting improvement of the condition of man—though justice and the true meaning of human society are, if not more accurately, more generally understood; though perhaps men know more, and therefore are more, as a mass, yet this principle has never been called into action, and requires indeed a universal and an almost appalling change in the system of existing things. The study of modern history is the study of kings, financiers, statesmen, and priests. The history of ancient Greece is the study of legislators, philosophers, and poets; it is the history of men, compared with the history of titles. What the Greeks were, was a reality, not a promise. And what we are and hope to be, is derived, as it were, from the influence and inspiration of these glorious generations.

The modern nations of the civilized world owe their progress—both in physical sciences where they've surpassed their predecessors and in moral and intellectual pursuits, where they haven't quite matched them yet—to what we call the revival of learning. This refers to studying the writers from the era before and just after Pericles, or other following writers who are, so to speak, the rivers flowing from those immortal fountains. Although it seems like there's a principle in the modern world that, if circumstances similar to those that shaped the intellectual resources of that era arise again, could sustain and enhance them, leading to a more equal, widespread, and lasting improvement in human conditions—although justice and the true meaning of human society are more widely understood now; and while maybe people know more and therefore are more knowledgeable as a group, this principle has never really been put into action and actually requires a universal and almost shocking change in the existing system. The study of modern history focuses on kings, financiers, statesmen, and priests. In contrast, the history of ancient Greece studies lawmakers, philosophers, and poets; it’s about real people, compared to the history of titles. What the Greeks were is a reality, not just a promise. And what we are and hope to be is rooted in the influence and inspiration of those remarkable generations.

Whatever tends to afford a further illustration of the manners and opinions of those to whom we owe so much, and who were perhaps, on the whole, the most perfect specimens of humanity of whom we have authentic record, were infinitely valuable. Let us see their errors, their weaknesses, their daily actions, their familiar conversation, and catch the tone of their society. When we discover how far the most admirable community ever framed was removed from that perfection to which human society is impelled by some active power within each bosom to aspire, how great ought to be our hopes, how resolute our struggles! For the Greeks of the Periclean age were widely different from us. It is to be lamented that no modern writer has hitherto dared to show them precisely as they were. Barthelemi cannot be denied the praise of industry and system; but he never forgets that he is a Christian and a Frenchman. Wieland, in his delightful novels, makes indeed a very tolerable Pagan, but cherishes too many political prejudices, and refrains from diminishing the interest of his romances by painting sentiments in which no European of modern times can possibly sympathize. There is no book which shows the Greeks precisely as they were; they seem all written for children with the caution that no practice or sentiment, highly inconsistent with our present manners, should be mentioned, lest those manners should receive outrage and violation. But there are many to whom the Greek language is inaccessible, who ought not to be excluded by this prudery from possessing an exact and comprehensive conception of the history of man; for there is no knowledge concerning what man has been and may be, from partaking of which a person can depart, without becoming in some degree more philosophical, tolerant, and just.

Anything that provides more insight into the customs and beliefs of those we owe so much to, and who were perhaps the best examples of humanity we have reliable records of, is extremely valuable. Let's look at their mistakes, their weaknesses, their everyday actions, their casual conversations, and really grasp the vibe of their society. When we see how far even the most remarkable community fell short of the perfect society that humanity naturally strives for, it should inspire great hopes and determined efforts! The Greeks during the age of Pericles were very different from us. It’s unfortunate that no modern writer has had the courage to portray them exactly as they were. Barthelemi deserves credit for his hard work and organization, but he never forgets he is a Christian and a Frenchman. Wieland, in his charming novels, creates a decent portrayal of a Pagan but holds on to too many political biases and avoids diminishing the appeal of his stories by depicting feelings that no modern European could fully relate to. There’s no book that depicts the Greeks just as they were; they all seem aimed at children, with a warning against mentioning any practices or beliefs that clash with today's norms, for fear of upsetting those norms. However, many people who cannot access the Greek language shouldn’t be excluded from having an accurate and thorough understanding of human history. Because there’s no knowledge about what humanity has been and can become that someone can engage with without becoming a little more philosophical, understanding, and fair.

One of the chief distinctions between the manners of ancient Greece and modern Europe, consisted in the regulations and the sentiments respecting sexual intercourse. Whether this difference arises from some imperfect influence of the doctrines of Jesus, who alleges the absolute and unconditional equality of all human beings, or from the institutions of chivalry, or from a certain fundamental difference of physical nature existing in the Celts, or from a combination of all or any of these causes acting on each other, is a question worthy of voluminous investigation. The fact is, that the modern Europeans have in this circumstance, and in the abolition of slavery, made an improvement the most decisive in the regulation of human society; and all the virtue and the wisdom of the Periclean age arose under other institutions, in spite of the diminution which personal slavery and the inferiority of women, recognized by law and opinion, must have produced in the delicacy, the strength, the comprehensiveness, and the accuracy of their conceptions, in moral, political, and metaphysical science, and perhaps in every other art and science.

One of the main differences between the customs of ancient Greece and modern Europe is how they view and regulate sexual relationships. Whether this difference comes from the incomplete influence of Jesus' teachings, which promote the absolute equality of all people, from the traditions of chivalry, from a fundamental difference in physical nature among the Celts, or a mix of all or any of these factors interacting, is a question that deserves extensive exploration. The reality is that modern Europeans have made a significant improvement in the organization of human society through this aspect and the abolition of slavery. The virtues and wisdom of the Periclean age emerged under different systems, despite the constraints that personal slavery and the societal inferiority of women, which were accepted by law and culture, likely imposed on the richness, strength, breadth, and precision of their ideas in moral, political, and metaphysical thought, and perhaps in every other art and science.

The women, thus degraded, became such as it was expected they would become. They possessed, except with extraordinary exceptions, the habits and the qualities of slaves. They were probably not extremely beautiful; at least there was no such disproportion in the attractions of the external form between the female and male sex among the Greeks, as exists among the modern Europeans. They were certainly devoid of that moral and intellectual loveliness with which the acquisition of knowledge and the cultivation of sentiment animates, as with another life of overpowering grace, the lineaments and the gestures of every form which they inhabit. Their eyes could not have been deep and intricate from the workings of the mind, and could have entangled no heart in soul-enwoven labyrinths.

The women, having been treated this way, became exactly what was expected of them. They generally had the habits and qualities of slaves, with only a few exceptions. They were probably not very beautiful; at least, there wasn't the same stark contrast in physical attractiveness between women and men among the Greeks as there is among modern Europeans. They certainly lacked the moral and intellectual beauty that comes from acquiring knowledge and nurturing feelings, which adds a powerful grace to the features and movements of anyone who embodies them. Their eyes likely weren't deep and complex from the workings of the mind, and they could not have ensnared anyone's heart in their intricate emotional webs.

Let it not be imagined that because the Greeks were deprived of its legitimate object, they were incapable of sentimental love; and that this passion is the mere child of chivalry and the literature of modern times. This object or its archetype for ever exists in the mind, which selects among those who resemble it that which most resembles it; and instinctively fills up the interstices of the imperfect image, in the same manner as the imagination moulds and completes the shapes in clouds, or in the fire, into the resemblances of whatever form, animal, building, &c., happens to be present to it. Man is in his wildest state a social being: a certain degree of civilization and refinement ever produces the want of sympathies still more intimate and complete; and the gratification of the senses is no longer all that is sought in sexual connexion. It soon becomes a very small part of that profound and complicated sentiment, which we call love, which is rather the universal thirst for a communion not only of the senses, but of our whole nature, intellectual, imaginative and sensitive, and which, when individualized, becomes an imperious necessity, only to be satisfied by the complete or partial, actual or supposed fulfilment of its claims. This want grows more powerful in proportion to the development which our nature receives from civilization, for man never ceases to be a social being. The sexual impulse, which is only one, and often a small part of those claims, serves, from its obvious and external nature, as a kind of type or expression of the rest, a common basis, an acknowledged and visible link. Still it is a claim which even derives a strength not its own from the accessory circumstances which surround it, and one which our nature thirsts to satisfy. To estimate this, observe the degree of intensity and durability of the love of the male towards the female in animals and savages and acknowledge all the duration and intensity observable in the love of civilized beings beyond that of savages to be produced from other causes. In the susceptibility of the external senses there is probably no important difference.

Let’s not think that just because the Greeks lacked its true focus, they were incapable of sentimental love, or that this feeling is merely a creation of chivalry and modern literature. This focus or its ideal always exists in the mind, which chooses from those that resemble it the one that is closest; it instinctively fills in the gaps of the imperfect image, just like the imagination shapes and completes the forms in clouds or fire into whatever shapes, animals, buildings, etc., come to mind. Humans are inherently social beings: a certain level of civilization and refinement always leads to a desire for deeper and more complete connections; the mere satisfaction of the senses is no longer all people seek in sexual relationships. It quickly becomes a minor part of that deep and complex emotion we call love, which is more about the universal desire for a connection that involves not just the senses but our entire nature—intellectual, imaginative, and sensitive—and which, when personalized, becomes a strong necessity that can only be fulfilled through the complete or partial, actual or imagined satisfaction of its demands. This desire becomes more powerful as our nature evolves through civilization, since humans remain social beings. The sexual urge, which is only one part of those demands and often a minor one, serves as a kind of symbol or representation of the rest—a common foundation, a recognized and visible connection. Still, it is a demand that gains strength from the surrounding circumstances, and one our nature longs to fulfill. To assess this, consider the intensity and duration of male love for females in animals and savages, and recognize that the depth and endurance seen in the love of civilized individuals beyond that of savages come from different causes. There is likely no significant difference in the sensitivity of our external senses.

Among the ancient Greeks the male sex, one half of the human race, received the highest cultivation and refinement: whilst the other, so far as intellect is concerned, were educated as slaves and were raised but few degrees in all that related to moral of intellectual excellence above the condition of savages. The gradations in the society of man present us with slow improvement in this respect. The Roman women held a higher consideration in society, and were esteemed almost as the equal partners with their husbands in the regulation of domestic economy and the education of their children. The practices and customs of modern Europe are essentially different from and incomparably less pernicious than either, however remote from what an enlightened mind cannot fail to desire as the future destiny of human beings.

Among the ancient Greeks, men, representing half of the human population, received the most education and refinement, while women were educated like slaves and barely elevated above the level of savages in terms of intellect and morality. The structure of society showed slow improvement in this area. Roman women were held in higher regard and were almost seen as equal partners with their husbands in managing the household and educating their children. The customs and practices of modern Europe are fundamentally different from, and far less harmful than, those of the past, although they still fall short of what an enlightened mind would envision for the future of humanity.

[1818; publ. 1840]

[1818; published 1840]










ON THE SYMPOSIUM, OR PREFACE TO THE BANQUET OF PLATO

A FRAGMENT

The dialogue entitled The Banquet was selected by the translator as the most beautiful and perfect among all the works of Plato. [Footnote: The Republic, though replete with considerable errors of speculation, is, indeed, the greatest repository of important truths of all the works of Plato. This, perhaps, is because it is the longest. He first, and perhaps last, maintained that a state ought to be governed, not by the wealthiest, or the most ambitious, or the most cunning, but by the wisest; the method of selecting such rulers, and the laws by which such a selection is made, must correspond with and arise out of the moral freedom and refinement of the people.] He despairs of having communicated to the English language any portion of the surpassing graces of the composition, or having done more than present an imperfect shadow of the language and the sentiment of this astonishing production.

The dialogue titled The Banquet was chosen by the translator as the most beautiful and perfect among all of Plato's works. [Footnote: The Republic, while filled with significant speculative errors, is indeed the greatest collection of important truths among all Plato's works. This might be because it is the longest. He was the first, and perhaps the last, to argue that a state should be led, not by the richest, the most ambitious, or the most cunning, but by the wisest; the method for selecting such leaders and the laws governing that selection must align with and emerge from the moral freedom and refinement of the people.] He feels hopeless about having conveyed any part of the exceptional beauty of the original text in English, or having done more than offer an imperfect reflection of the language and sentiment of this remarkable work.

Plato is eminently the greatest among the Greek philosophers, and from, or, rather, perhaps through him, his master Socrates, have proceeded those emanations of moral and metaphysical knowledge, on which a long series and an incalculable variety of popular superstitions have sheltered their absurdities from the slow contempt of mankind. Plato exhibits the rare union of close and subtle logic with the Pythian enthusiasm of poetry, melted by the splendour and harmony of his periods into one irresistible stream of musical impressions, which hurry the persuasions onward, as in a breathless career. His language is that of an immortal spirit, rather than a man. Lord Bacon is, perhaps, the only writer, who, in these particulars, can be compared with him: his imitator, Cicero, sinks in the comparison into an ape mocking the gestures of a man. His views into the nature of mind and existence are often obscure, only because they are profound; and though his theories respecting the government of the world, and the elementary laws of moral action, are not always correct, yet there is scarcely any of his treatises which do not, however stained by puerile sophisms, contain the most remarkable intuitions into all that can be the subject of the human mind. His excellence consists especially in intuition, and it is this faculty which raises him far above Aristotle, whose genius, though vivid and various, is obscure in comparison with that of Plato.

Plato is undoubtedly the greatest of the Greek philosophers, and through him, or rather his teacher Socrates, emerged the foundations of moral and metaphysical knowledge, which have allowed a long line of popular superstitions to hide their absurdities from the gradual disdain of humanity. Plato showcases the rare blend of sharp and nuanced logic with the passionate enthusiasm of poetry, fused by the brilliance and rhythm of his writing into an irresistible flow of musical ideas that propel his arguments forward with an almost breathless momentum. His language resonates with the voice of an immortal rather than that of a mere human. Lord Bacon might be the only writer who can be compared to him in these respects; his imitator, Cicero, pales in comparison, resembling an ape imitating human gestures. His insights into the nature of the mind and existence can often be unclear, but that's because they are so deep; and while his theories on the governance of the world and the fundamental laws of moral action aren't always accurate, almost every one of his works—despite being marred by childish arguments—contains remarkable insights into everything that can occupy the human mind. His brilliance lies primarily in his intuition, which elevates him far above Aristotle, whose genius, though bright and diverse, seems dim when compared to Plato's.

The dialogue entitled the Banquet, is called [word in Greek], or a Discussion upon Love, and is supposed to have taken place at the house of Agathon, at one of a series of festivals given by that poet, on the occasion of his gaining the prize of tragedy at the Dionysiaca. The account of the debate on this occasion is supposed to have been given by Apollodorus, a pupil of Socrates, many years after it had taken place, to a companion who was curious to hear it. This Apollodorus appears, both from the style in which he is represented in this piece, as well as from a passage in the Phaedon, to have been a person of an impassioned and enthusiastic disposition; to borrow an image from the Italian painters, he seems to have been the St. John of the Socratic group. The drama (for so the lively distinction of character and the various and well-wrought circumstances of the story almost entitle it to be called) begins by Socrates persuading Aristodemus to sup at Agathon's, uninvited. The whole of this introduction affords the most lively conception of refined Athenian manners.

The dialogue called the Banquet, or a Discussion on Love, is believed to have taken place at Agathon's house during one of his festivals, celebrating his victory in tragedy at the Dionysiac Games. The account of the debate was supposedly given by Apollodorus, a student of Socrates, many years later to a friend who wanted to know about it. Apollodorus seems to have been passionate and enthusiastic, like the St. John of the Socratic circle, based on both how he is portrayed here and a reference in the Phaedon. The drama (as the distinctive character and the various well-crafted circumstances of the story suggest it can rightly be called) starts with Socrates convincing Aristodemus to join him for dinner at Agathon's, even though they weren't invited. This introduction provides a vivid picture of refined Athenian social customs.

[1818; publ. 1840] [UNFINISHED]

[1818; pub. 1840] [UNFINISHED]










A DEFENCE OF POETRY

I

According to one mode of regarding those two classes of mental action, which are called reason and imagination, the former may be considered as mind contemplating the relations borne by one thought to another, however produced; and the latter, as mind acting upon those thoughts so as to colour them with its own light, and composing from them, as from elements, other thoughts, each containing within itself the principle of its own integrity. The one is the [word in Greek], or the principle of synthesis, and has for its objects those forms which are common to universal nature and existence itself; the other is the [word in Greek], or principle of analysis, and its action regards the relations of things, simply as relations; considering thoughts, not in their integral unity, but as the algebraical representations which conduct to certain general results. Reason is the enumeration of quantities already known; imagination is the perception of the value of those quantities, both separately and as a whole. Reason respects the differences, and imagination the similitudes of things. Reason is to the imagination as the instrument to the agent, as the body to the spirit, as the shadow to the substance.

According to one way of looking at these two types of mental processes, known as reason and imagination, reason can be seen as the mind reflecting on how one thought relates to another, regardless of how those thoughts came about. On the other hand, imagination involves the mind acting on those thoughts, adding its own perspective to them, and combining them like elements to create new thoughts, each containing its own essence. Reason is the principle of synthesis and focuses on those patterns that are universal in nature and existence. Imagination, meanwhile, is the principle of analysis and deals with the relationships between things purely as relationships, viewing thoughts not as a whole but as symbolic representations that lead to general conclusions. Reason counts known quantities, while imagination understands the significance of these quantities, both individually and collectively. Reason acknowledges differences, while imagination recognizes similarities. Reason is to imagination as a tool is to the user, as the physical body is to the spirit, as a shadow is to its source.

Poetry, in a general sense, may be defined to be 'the expression of the imagination': and poetry is connate with the origin of man. Man is an instrument over which a series of external and internal impressions are driven, like the alternations of an ever-changing wind over an Aeolian lyre, which move it by their motion to ever-changing melody. But there is a principle within the human being, and perhaps within all sentient beings, which acts otherwise than in the lyre, and produces not melody alone, but harmony, by an internal adjustment of the sounds or motions thus excited to the impressions which excite them. It is as if the lyre could accommodate its chords to the motions of that which strikes them, in a determined proportion of sound; even as the musician can accommodate his voice to the sound of the lyre. A child at play by itself will express its delight by its voice and motions; and every inflexion of tone and every gesture will bear exact relation to a corresponding antitype in the pleasurable impressions which awakened it; it will be the reflected image of that impression; and as the lyre trembles and sounds after the wind has died away, so the child seeks, by prolonging in its voice and motions the duration of the effect, to prolong also a consciousness of the cause. In relation to the objects which delight a child, these expressions are, what poetry is to higher objects. The savage (for the savage is to ages what the child is to years) expresses the emotions produced in him by surrounding objects in a similar manner; and language and gesture, together with plastic or pictorial imitation, become the image of the combined effect of those objects, and of his apprehension of them. Man in society, with all his passions and his pleasures, next becomes the object of the passions and pleasures of man; an additional class of emotions produces an augmented treasure of expressions; and language, gesture, and the imitative arts, become at once the representation and the medium, the pencil and the picture, the chisel and the statue, the chord and the harmony. The social sympathies, or those laws from which, as from its elements, society results, begin to develop themselves from the moment that two human beings coexist; the future is contained within the present, as the plant within the seed; and equality, diversity, unity, contrast, mutual dependence, become the principles alone capable of affording the motives according to which the will of a social being is determined to action, inasmuch as he is social; and constitute pleasure in sensation, virtue in sentiment, beauty in art, truth in reasoning, and love in the intercourse of kind. Hence men, even in the infancy of society, observe a certain order in their words and actions, distinct from that of the objects and the impressions represented by them, all expression being subject to the laws of that from which it proceeds. But let us dismiss those more general considerations which might involve an inquiry into the principles of society itself, and restrict our view to the manner in which the imagination is expressed upon its forms.

Poetry, broadly speaking, can be defined as 'the expression of imagination'; it's something that has been part of humanity since the beginning. Humans are like instruments that react to a range of external and internal impressions, similar to how an ever-changing wind affects an Aeolian lyre, creating diverse melodies. However, there’s a deeper mechanism within us, and likely within all sentient beings, that operates differently from the lyre, generating not just melody but harmony through an internal adjustment that connects sounds or movements to the impressions that triggered them. It’s as if the lyre could adjust its strings to the force hitting them, creating a specific sound, much like how a musician can adapt their voice to the sound of the lyre. A child playing alone will express joy through their voice and movements; each change in tone and gesture corresponds perfectly to the joyful impressions that sparked them; it's a mirror reflecting that impression. Just as the lyre vibrates and resonates even after the wind calms down, a child tries to extend the effect of their joy through their voice and actions, maintaining a sense of the cause. In relation to what pleases a child, these expressions are like poetry in response to more profound subjects. The primitive person (since the primitive is to ages what a child is to years) expresses emotions evoked by their environment in a similar way; through language, gestures, and artistic imitation, they manifest the combined impact of those objects and their understanding of them. As humans live together with their passions and pleasures, they become the focus of each other's emotions; this leads to a wider range of expressions, where language, gesture, and art serve as both representation and medium—like a pencil and a picture, a chisel and a statue, a chord and a harmony. Social connections, or those fundamental laws from which society emerges, start to form the moment two people coexist; the future is present in the now, much like a plant within a seed; principles of equality, diversity, unity, contrast, and interdependence become the motivations behind the actions of social beings, allowing for pleasure in sensation, virtue in feeling, beauty in art, truth in reasoning, and love in social interactions. Therefore, even in the early stages of society, individuals observe a certain order in their words and actions that sets them apart from the objects and impressions they represent, with all expressions governed by the laws of their origins. But let’s set aside those broader topics that might lead to an exploration of societal principles and focus on how imagination is expressed through its forms.

In the youth of the world, men dance and sing and imitate natural objects, observing in these actions, as in all others, a certain rhythm or order. And, although all men observe a similar, they observe not the same order, in the motions of the dance, in the melody of the song, in the combinations of language, in the series of their imitations of natural objects. For there is a certain order or rhythm belonging to each of these classes of mimetic representation, from which the hearer and the spectator receive an intenser and purer pleasure than from any other: the sense of an approximation to this order has been called taste by modern writers. Every man in the infancy of art observes an order which approximates more or less closely to that from which this highest delight results: but the diversity is not sufficiently marked, as that its gradations should be sensible, except in those instances where the predominance of this faculty of approximation to the beautiful (for so we may be permitted to name the relation between this highest pleasure and its cause) is very great. Those in whom it exists in excess are poets, in the most universal sense of the word; and the pleasure resulting from the manner in which they express the influence of society or nature upon their own minds, communicates itself to others, and gathers a sort or reduplication from that community. Their language is vitally metaphorical; that is, it marks the before unapprehended relations of things and perpetuates their apprehension, until the words which represent them become, through time, signs for portions or classes of thoughts instead of pictures of integral thoughts; and then if no new poets should arise to create afresh the associations which have been thus disorganized, language will be dead to all the nobler purposes of human intercourse. These similitudes or relations are finely said by Lord Bacon to be 'the same footsteps of nature impressed upon the various subjects of the world'; [Footnote: De Augment. Scient., cap. i, lib. iii.] and he considers the faculty which perceives them as the storehouse of axioms common to all knowledge. In the infancy of society every author is necessarily a poet, because language itself is poetry; and to be a poet is to apprehend the true and the beautiful, in a word, the good which exists in the relation, subsisting, first between existence and perception, and secondly between perception and expression. Every original language near to its source is in itself the chaos of a cyclic poem: the copiousness of lexicography and the distinctions of grammar are the works of a later age, and are merely the catalogue and the form of the creations of poetry.

In the early days of the world, people danced, sang, and mimicked natural objects, noticing a certain rhythm or order in these actions, just like in everything else. Although everyone sees a similar order, they don't see the same one in the movements of the dance, the melody of the song, the ways they use language, or how they imitate natural objects. Each of these forms of mimicry has its own kind of order or rhythm, from which listeners and viewers derive a deeper and purer enjoyment than from anything else: the feeling of being close to this order is what modern writers call taste. In the early stages of art, every person recognizes an order that is more or less close to the one that brings the highest joy, but the differences aren’t distinct enough for it to be easily noticeable, except in cases where this ability to appreciate beauty stands out greatly. Those who have this ability in abundance are poets, in the broadest sense of the word; the joy that comes from how they express the impact of society or nature on their own minds resonates with others and fosters a kind of shared experience. Their language is deeply metaphorical, meaning it highlights previously unrecognized relationships between things and keeps those perceptions alive until the words that symbolize them eventually become mere labels for specific thoughts instead of vivid images of complete ideas; and then, if new poets don’t emerge to revive the connections that have fallen apart, language will become useless for the deeper purposes of human communication. These similarities or relationships are elegantly described by Lord Bacon as "the same footsteps of nature impressed upon the various subjects of the world"; [Footnote: De Augment. Scient., cap. i, lib. iii.] he views the ability to see them as a repository of fundamental truths that apply to all knowledge. In the early stages of society, every writer is inherently a poet because language itself is poetry; to be a poet is to recognize the true and the beautiful, essentially the good that exists in the connection between existence and perception, and then between perception and expression. Every original language, close to its origins, is essentially like the chaos of a cyclic poem: the richness of vocabulary and grammar distinctions are the results of a later time and merely serve as a catalog and structure for the creations of poetry.

But poets, or those who imagine and express this indestructible order, are not only the authors of language and of music, of the dance, and architecture, and statuary, and painting; they are the institutors of laws, and the founders of civil society, and the inventors of the arts of life, and the teachers, who draw into a certain propinquity with the beautiful and the true, that partial apprehension of the agencies of the invisible world which is called religion. Hence all original religions are allegorical, or susceptible of allegory, and, like Janus, have a double face of false and true. Poets, according to the circumstances of the age and nation in which they appeared, were called, in the earlier epochs of the world, legislators, or prophets: a poet essentially comprises and unites both these characters. For he not only beholds intensely the present as it is, and discovers those laws according to which present things ought to be ordered, but he beholds the future in the present, and his thoughts are the germs of the flower and the fruit of latest time. Not that I assert poets to be prophets in the gross sense of the word, or that they can foretell the form as surely as they foreknow the spirit of events: such is the pretence of superstition, which would make poetry an attribute of prophecy, rather than prophecy an attribute of poetry. A poet participates in the eternal, the infinite, and the one; as far as relates to his conceptions, time and place and number are not. The grammatical forms which express the moods of time, and the difference of persons, and the distinction of place, are convertible with respect to the highest poetry without injuring it as poetry; and the choruses of Aeschylus, and the book of Job, and Dante's Paradise, would afford, more than any other writings, examples of this fact, if the limits of this essay did not forbid citation. The creations of sculpture, painting, and music, are illustrations still more decisive.

But poets, or those who imagine and express this unbreakable order, are not just the creators of language, music, dance, architecture, sculpture, and painting; they are the makers of laws, the founders of society, the inventors of life’s arts, and the teachers who bring us closer to the beautiful and the true, which is a limited understanding of the forces of the unseen world we call religion. Because of this, all original religions are allegorical or open to allegory and, like Janus, have two sides of false and true. Poets were called legislators or prophets in earlier times, depending on the age and culture in which they emerged: a poet embodies and combines both roles. They not only see the present for what it is and find the laws by which things should be arranged, but they also perceive the future within the present, and their thoughts are the seeds of future developments. I don't mean to say that poets are prophets in the general sense or that they can predict the exact form of events just as they intuit the spirit behind them: that’s the boast of superstition, which would claim that poetry is a type of prophecy rather than the other way around. A poet connects with the eternal, the infinite, and the oneness; in terms of their ideas, time, place, and numbers become irrelevant. The grammatical structures that express time, person, and location can interchangeably relate to the highest forms of poetry without compromising their poetic nature; the choruses of Aeschylus, the book of Job, and Dante's Paradise would provide, more than any other texts, clear examples of this if the scope of this essay didn’t prevent me from quoting them. The creations of sculpture, painting, and music offer even more definitive illustrations.

Language, colour, form, and religious and civil habits of action, are all the instruments and materials of poetry; they may be called poetry by that figure of speech which considers the effect as a synonym of the cause. But poetry in a more restricted sense expresses those arrangements of language, and especially metrical language, which are created by that imperial faculty; whose throne is curtained within the invisible nature of man. And this springs from the nature itself of language, which is a more direct representation of the actions and passions of our internal being, and is susceptible of more various and delicate combinations, than colour, form, or motion, and is more plastic and obedient to the control of that faculty of which it is the creation. For language is arbitrarily produced by the imagination and has relation to thoughts alone; but all other materials, instruments and conditions of art, have relations among each other, which limit and interpose between conception and expression The former is as a mirror which reflects, the latter as a cloud which enfeebles, the light of which both are mediums of communication. Hence the fame of sculptors, painters, and musicians, although the intrinsic powers of the great masters of these arts may yield in no degree to that of those who have employed language as the hieroglyphic of their thoughts, has never equalled that of poets in the restricted sense of the term, as two performers of equal skill will produce unequal effects from a guitar and a harp. The fame of legislators and founders of religions, so long as their institutions last, alone seems to exceed that of poets in the restricted sense; but it can scarcely be a question, whether, if we deduct the celebrity which their flattery of the gross opinions of the vulgar usually conciliates, together with that which belonged to them in their higher character of poets, any excess will remain.

Language, color, form, and societal and religious behaviors are all the tools and materials of poetry; they can be called poetry in a way that equates the effect with the cause. However, poetry in a more precise sense refers to the arrangements of language, especially metrical language, created by that dominant ability whose realm is hidden within the unseen nature of humanity. This ability arises from the nature of language itself, which directly represents the actions and emotions of our inner selves and can be combined in more varied and subtle ways than color, form, or movement. Language is more adaptable and responsive to the influence of that ability from which it is created. Language is generated by imagination and relates solely to thoughts; meanwhile, other materials, tools, and artistic conditions have relationships with each other that limit and mediate between conception and expression. The former is like a mirror that reflects, while the latter resembles a cloud that diminishes, with both serving as means of communication. Therefore, the renown of sculptors, painters, and musicians, even though the inherent skills of the great masters of these arts may be on par with those who express their thoughts through language, has never matched that of poets in this more specific sense. It’s similar to how two equally skilled performers can produce different effects from a guitar and a harp. The fame of lawmakers and founders of religions, as long as their institutions endure, seems to surpass that of poets in this specific sense; however, it’s debatable whether, when we discount the popularity that comes from catering to the crude opinions of the masses, along with the recognition they receive in their higher role as poets, any excess will remain.

We have thus circumscribed the word poetry within the limits of that art which is the most familiar and the most perfect expression of the faculty itself. It is necessary, however, to make the circle still narrower, and to determine the distinction between measured and unmeasured language; for the popular division into prose and verse is inadmissible in accurate philosophy.

We have therefore defined the word poetry within the boundaries of the art that serves as the most familiar and the most complete expression of the faculty itself. However, it’s essential to narrow the focus even more and to clarify the difference between structured and unstructured language; because the common division into prose and verse is not acceptable in precise philosophy.

Sounds as well as thoughts have relation both between each other and towards that which they represent, and a perception of the order of those relations has always been found connected with a perception of the order of the relations of thoughts. Hence the language of poets has ever affected a certain uniform and harmonious recurrence of sound, without which it were not poetry, and which is scarcely less indispensable to the communication of its influence, than the words themselves, without reference to that peculiar order. Hence the vanity of translation; it were as wise to cast a violet into a crucible that you might discover the formal principle of its colour and odour, as seek to transfuse from one language into another the creations of a poet. The plant must spring again from its seed, or it will bear no flower—and this is the burthen of the curse of Babel.

Sounds and thoughts are connected to each other and to what they represent, and understanding the order of those connections has always been linked to understanding the order of thoughts. This is why the language of poets has always emphasized a consistent and harmonious sound, which is essential to poetry, and just as important for conveying its impact as the actual words, regardless of their specific arrangement. This highlights the futility of translation; it would be just as sensible to place a violet in a crucible to discover the formal principle of its color and scent as it would be to try to transfer a poet's creations from one language to another. The plant must grow again from its seed, or it won’t bloom—and this is the burden of the curse of Babel.

An observation of the regular mode of the recurrence of harmony in the language of poetical minds, together with its relation to music, produced metre, or a certain system of traditional forms of harmony and language. Yet it is by no means essential that a poet should accommodate his language to this traditional form, so that the harmony, which is its spirit, be observed. The practice is indeed convenient and popular, and to be preferred, especially in such composition as includes much action: but every great poet must inevitably innovate upon the example of his predecessors in the exact structure of his peculiar versification. The distinction between poets and prose writers is a vulgar error. The distinction between philosophers and poets has been anticipated. Plato was essentially a poet—the truth and splendour of his imagery, and the melody of his language, are the most intense that it is possible to conceive. He rejected the measure of the epic, dramatic, and lyrical forms, because he sought to kindle a harmony in thoughts divested of shape and action, and he forbore to invent any regular plan of rhythm which would include, under determinate forms, the varied pauses of his style. Cicero sought to imitate the cadence of his periods, but with little success. Lord Bacon was a poet. [Footnote: See the Filum Labyrinthi, and the Essay on Death particularly]. His language has a sweet and majestic rhythm, which satisfies the sense, no less than the almost superhuman wisdom of his philosophy satisfies the intellect; it is a strain which distends, and then bursts the circumference of the reader's mind, and pours itself forth together with it into the universal element with which it has perpetual sympathy. All the authors of revolutions in opinion are not only necessarily poets as they are inventors, nor even as their words unveil the permanent analogy of things by images which participate in the life of truth; but as their periods are harmonious and rhythmical, and contain in themselves the elements of verse; being the echo of the eternal music. Nor are those supreme poets, who have employed traditional forms of rhythm on account of the form and action of their subjects, less capable of perceiving and teaching the truth of things, than those who have omitted that form. Shakespeare, Dante, and Milton (to confine ourselves to modern writers) are philosophers of the very loftiest power.

Observing how harmony regularly recurs in the language of poetic minds, along with its connection to music, led to the creation of meter, or a specific set of traditional forms for harmony and language. However, it’s not essential for a poet to stick to these traditional forms as long as the underlying harmony, which embodies the spirit of the language, is maintained. While following this practice is indeed convenient and popular, especially in works that involve a lot of action, every great poet must inevitably innovate on the examples set by their predecessors when it comes to the exact structure of their unique verse. The idea that there is a clear distinction between poets and prose writers is a common misconception. The difference between philosophers and poets has already been addressed. Plato was fundamentally a poet—the truth and beauty of his imagery, along with the musicality of his language, are beyond what can be fully imagined. He disregarded the established measures of epic, dramatic, and lyrical forms because he aimed to create harmony in thoughts that were stripped of form and action, avoiding any fixed rhythmic plan that would restrict the diverse pauses in his style. Cicero tried to mimic the rhythm of his sentences, but not with much success. Lord Bacon was a poet. [Footnote: See the Filum Labyrinthi, and the Essay on Death particularly]. His language has a sweet and grand rhythm that satisfies the senses, just as the almost superhuman wisdom of his philosophy satisfies the intellect; it is a melody that stretches and then breaks the boundaries of the reader's mind, overflowing into the universal essence with which it has a constant connection. All the pioneers of shifts in thought are not only poets by virtue of being inventors, nor just because their words reveal the enduring analogy of things through images that embody the life of truth; they are also poets because their sentences are harmonious and rhythmic, containing the elements of verse—they echo the eternal music. Those supreme poets who have used traditional rhythmic forms due to the nature and action of their subjects are just as capable of understanding and conveying the truth of things as those who have not used those forms. Shakespeare, Dante, and Milton (to focus on modern writers) are philosophers of the highest order.

A poem is the very image of life expressed in its eternal truth. There is this difference between a story and a poem, that a story is a catalogue of detached facts, which have no other connexion than time, place, circumstance, cause and effect; the other is the creation of actions according to the unchangeable forms of human nature, as existing in the mind of the Creator, which is itself the image of all other minds. The one is partial, and applies only to a definite period of time, and a certain combination of events which can never again recur; the other is universal, and contains within itself the germ of a relation to whatever motives or actions have place in the possible varieties of human nature. Time, which destroys the beauty and the use of the story of particular facts, stripped of the poetry which should invest them, augments that of poetry, and for ever develops new and wonderful applications of the eternal truth which it contains. Hence epitomes have been called the moths of just history; they eat out the poetry of it. A story of particular facts is as a mirror which obscures and distorts that which should be beautiful: poetry is a mirror which makes beautiful that which is distorted.

A poem is the true reflection of life expressed in its timeless essence. The key difference between a story and a poem is that a story is a collection of separate facts linked only by time, place, circumstances, cause, and effect; whereas a poem creates actions based on the unchanging aspects of human nature as understood by the Creator, which mirrors all other minds. One is limited and applies only to a specific time and a particular set of events that can never happen again; the other is universal and contains the potential for connections to any motives or actions found in the possible variations of human nature. Time, which diminishes the beauty and relevance of the story of specific facts, stripped of the poetry that should enhance them, actually enhances poetry and continually brings forth new and remarkable expressions of the eternal truth it holds. This is why summaries are often regarded as the destroyers of true history; they strip away its poetry. A story of specific facts acts like a mirror that obscures and distorts what should be beautiful, while poetry is a mirror that reveals beauty in what is distorted.

The parts of a composition may be poetical, without the composition as a whole being a poem. A single sentence may be a considered as a whole, though it may be found in the midst of a series of unassimilated portions: a single word even may be a spark of inextinguishable thought. And thus all the great historians, Herodotus, Plutarch, Livy, were poets; and although, the plan of these writers, especially that of Livy, restrained them; from developing this faculty in its highest degree, they made copious and ample amends for their subjection, by filling all the interstices of their subjects with living images.

The elements of a composition can be poetic, even if the entire work isn’t a poem. A single sentence can stand alone as a complete thought, even if it’s surrounded by unrelated parts; a single word can ignite an unquenchable idea. In this way, all the great historians—Herodotus, Plutarch, Livy—were poets; and although their plans, particularly Livy's, limited their ability to fully express this talent, they more than compensated for this constraint by filling the gaps in their subjects with vibrant imagery.

Having determined what is poetry, and who are poets, let us proceed to estimate its effects upon society.

Having figured out what poetry is and who the poets are, let's move on to evaluate its impact on society.

Poetry is ever accompanied with pleasure: all spirits on which it falls open themselves to receive the wisdom which is mingled with its delight. In the infancy of the world, neither poets themselves nor their auditors are fully aware of the excellence of poetry: for it acts in a divine and unapprehended manner, beyond and above consciousness; and it is reserved for future generations to contemplate and measure the mighty cause and effect in all the strength and splendour of their union. Even in modern times, no living poet ever arrived at the fullness of his fame; the jury which sits in judgement upon a poet, belonging as he does to all time, must be composed of his peers: it must be impanelled by Time from the selectest of the wise of many generations. A poet is a nightingale, who sits in darkness and sings to cheer its own solitude with sweet sounds; his auditors are as men entranced by the melody of an unseen musician, who feel that they are moved and softened, yet know not whence or why. The poems of Homer and his contemporaries were the delight of infant Greece; they were the elements of that social system which is the column upon which all succeeding civilization has reposed. Homer embodied the ideal perfection of his age in human character; nor can we doubt that those who read his verses were awakened to an ambition of becoming like to Achilles, Hector, and Ulysses the truth and beauty of friendship, patriotism, and persevering devotion to an object, were unveiled to the depths in these immortal creations: the sentiments of the auditors must have been refined and enlarged by a sympathy with such great and lovely impersonations, until from admiring they imitated, and from imitation they identified themselves with the objects of their admiration. Nor let it be objected, that these characters are remote from moral perfection, and that they can by no means be considered as edifying patterns for general imitation. Every epoch, under names more or less specious, has deified its peculiar errors; Revenge is the naked idol of the worship of a semi-barbarous age; and Self-deceit is the veiled image of unknown evil, before which luxury and satiety lie prostrate. But a poet considers the vices of his contemporaries as a temporary dress in which his creations must be arrayed, and which cover without concealing the eternal proportions of their beauty. An epic or dramatic personage is understood to wear them around his soul, as he may the ancient armour or the modern uniform around his body; whilst it is easy to conceive a dress more graceful than either. The beauty of the internal nature cannot be so far concealed by its accidental vesture, but that the spirit of its form shall communicate itself to the very disguise, and indicate the shape it hides from the manner in which it is worn. A majestic form and graceful motions will express themselves through the most barbarous and tasteless costume. Few poets of the highest class have chosen to exhibit the beauty of their conceptions in its naked truth and splendour; and it is doubtful whether the alloy of costume, habit, &c., be not necessary to temper this planetary music for mortal ears.

Poetry always brings pleasure: anyone touched by it opens up to the wisdom intertwined with its joy. In the early days of the world, neither poets nor their audiences fully recognized the greatness of poetry. It operates in a divine and unrecognized way, beyond our awareness; it’s up to future generations to understand and appreciate the profound relationship between cause and effect in all their powerful and beautiful combination. Even today, no living poet ever achieves complete fame; the jury that judges a poet, who belongs to all time, must consist of their peers, selected by Time from the wisest individuals of many generations. A poet is like a nightingale, singing in darkness to brighten its solitude with sweet sounds; listeners are like people enchanted by an unseen musician's melody, feeling moved and softened, yet unsure of the source or reason. The works of Homer and his contemporaries delighted early Greece; they formed the foundation of the social system upon which all future civilization rests. Homer captured his era's ideal perfection in human character; we can assume that those who read his lines were inspired to become like Achilles, Hector, and Ulysses—uncovering the truth and beauty of friendship, patriotism, and unwavering dedication to a cause, reflected in these timeless creations. The feelings of the audience must have been refined and expanded by their connection with such grand and beautiful representations, shifting from admiration to imitation, and ultimately identifying with what they admired. Don’t argue that these characters are far from moral perfection and shouldn’t be seen as examples for general imitation. Every era, using names that sound appealing, has glorified its unique faults; Revenge is the bare idol worshipped in a semi-barbaric age, while Self-deceit is the masked image of hidden evil before which luxury and excess bow down. But a poet views the vices of their contemporaries as merely a temporary disguise for their creations, covering but not hiding the eternal aspects of their beauty. An epic or dramatic character is seen as wearing these flaws around their soul, just as they might wear ancient armor or a modern uniform on their body, even though a more graceful outfit is easy to imagine. The beauty of internal nature can’t be completely hidden by superficial appearance; the essence of its form will communicate through the disguise, revealing the shape it conceals by how it is worn. A majestic form and graceful movements will express themselves even through the most barbaric and tasteless attire. Few poets of the highest rank choose to reveal the beauty of their ideas in their pure and bright form; and it remains uncertain whether the blend of costume, habits, etc., is necessary to adjust this musical harmony for human ears.

The whole objection, however, of the immorality of poetry rests upon a misconception of the manner in which poetry acts to produce the moral improvement of man. Ethical science arranges the elements which poetry has created, and propounds schemes and proposes examples of civil and domestic life: nor is it for want of admirable doctrines that men hate, and despise, and censure, and deceive, and subjugate one another. But poetry acts in another and diviner manner. It awakens and enlarges the mind itself by rendering it the receptacle of a thousand unapprehended combinations of thought. Poetry lifts the veil from the hidden beauty of the world, and makes familiar objects be as if they were not familiar; it reproduces all that it represents, and the impersonations clothed in its Elysian light stand thenceforward in the minds of those who have once contemplated them as memorials of that gentle and exalted content which extends itself over all thoughts and actions with which it coexists. The great secret of morals is love; or a going out of our own nature, and an identification of ourselves with the beautiful which exists in thought, action, or person, not our own. A man, to be greatly good, must imagine intensely and comprehensively; he must put himself in the place of another and of many others; the pains and pleasures of his species must become his own. The great instrument of moral good is the imagination; and poetry administers to the effect by acting upon the cause. Poetry enlarges the circumference of the imagination by replenishing it with thought of ever new delight, which have the power of attracting and assimilating to their own nature all other thoughts, and which form new intervals and interstices whose void for ever craves fresh food. Poetry strengthens the faculty which is the organ of the moral nature of man, in the same manner as exercise strengthens a limb. A poet therefore would do ill to embody his own conceptions of right and wrong, which are usually those of his place and time, in his poetical creations, which participate in neither By this assumption of the inferior office of interpreting the effect in which perhaps after all he might acquit himself but imperfectly, he would resign a glory in a participation in the cause. There was little danger that Homer, or any of the eternal poets should have so far misunderstood themselves as to have abdicated this throne of their widest dominion. Those in whom the poetical faculty, though great, is less intense, as Euripides, Lucan, Tasso, Spenser, have frequently affected a moral aim, and the effect of their poetry is diminished in exact proportion to the degree in which they compel us to advert to this purpose.

The objection to the immorality of poetry is based on a misunderstanding of how poetry contributes to the moral improvement of humanity. Ethical science organizes the elements that poetry has created, offering frameworks and examples of civic and domestic life; yet, people hate, despise, criticize, deceive, and control each other not due to a lack of admirable principles. Poetry operates differently and more divinely. It awakens and expands the mind by making it a vessel for countless unrecognized combinations of thought. Poetry reveals the hidden beauty of the world and makes ordinary things feel unfamiliar; it reproduces everything it represents, and the characters illuminated by its ethereal light remain in the minds of those who have reflected on them as reminders of the gentle and elevated content that spreads over all thoughts and actions alongside it. The key to morals is love—an outreach beyond our own nature, identifying with the beauty in thoughts, actions, or people that aren't our own. To be truly good, a person must be able to imagine deeply and widely; they must empathize not only with others but also with many people. The joys and sorrows of humanity must become their own. The primary instrument of moral goodness is imagination, and poetry contributes to this by influencing the foundational cause. Poetry expands the range of imagination by filling it with thoughts of continual new delight, which have the ability to draw in and incorporate all other ideas and create new gaps that will always crave fresh inspiration. Poetry strengthens the capacity that serves as the organ of human moral nature, just as exercise builds a muscle. Therefore, it would be a mistake for a poet to shape their own ideas of right and wrong, which usually reflect their time and place, in their poetic works, as these creations should not be limited by them. By assuming the lesser role of interpreting the effect, in which they might only succeed imperfectly, they would forfeit a glory that comes from participating in the cause itself. There was little risk that Homer or any of the timeless poets so misunderstood themselves as to give up their throne of greatest influence. Those whose poetic talent is significant but less intense, like Euripides, Lucan, Tasso, and Spenser, have often aimed for a moral message, and the effect of their poetry diminishes in exact proportion to how much they force us to focus on this intent.

Homer and the cyclic poets were followed at a certain interval by the dramatic and lyrical poets of Athens, who flourished contemporaneously with all that is most perfect in the kindred expressions of the poetical faculty; architecture, painting, music the dance, sculpture, philosophy, and, we may add, the forms of civil life. For although the scheme of Athenian society was deformed by many imperfections which the poetry existing in chivalry and Christianity has erased from the habits and institutions of modern Europe; yet never at any other period has so much energy, beauty, and virtue, been developed; never was blind strength and stubborn form so disciplined and rendered subject to the will of man, or that will less repugnant to the dictates of the beautiful and the true, as during the century which preceded the death of Socrates. Of no other epoch in the history of our species have we records and fragments stamped so visibly with the image of the divinity in man. But it is poetry alone, in form, in action, or in language, which has rendered this epoch memorable above all others, and the storehouse of examples to everlasting time. For written poetry existed at that epoch simultaneously with the other arts, and it is an idle inquiry to demand which gave and which received the light, which all, as from a common focus, have scattered over the darkest periods of succeeding time. We know no more of cause and effect than a constant conjunction of events: poetry is ever found to coexist with whatever other arts contribute to the happiness and perfection of man. I appeal to what has already been established to distinguish between the cause and the effect.

Homer and the cyclic poets were later followed by the dramatic and lyrical poets of Athens, who thrived alongside the most refined expressions of poetic talent, including architecture, painting, music, dance, sculpture, philosophy, and, we can add, the structure of civic life. Although Athenian society had many flaws that the poetry of chivalry and Christianity has since removed from the customs and institutions of modern Europe, never before or since has so much energy, beauty, and virtue emerged. Never has raw strength and rigid form been so well disciplined and brought under the control of human will, which became more aligned with the ideals of beauty and truth, as during the century leading up to Socrates' death. No other period in our history has left us with records and fragments so clearly imprinted with the divine essence in humanity. But it is poetry, whether in form, action, or language, that has made this era unforgettable and a treasure trove of examples for all time. Written poetry existed at that time alongside the other arts, and it's pointless to argue which influenced the other more, as they all emanated from a shared source and enlightened the dark times that followed. We understand no more about cause and effect than a consistent connection of events: poetry consistently appears alongside other arts that enhance human happiness and fulfillment. I refer to what has already been established to differentiate between cause and effect.

It was at the period here adverted to, that the drama had its birth; and however a succeeding writer may have equalled or surpassed those few great specimens of the Athenian drama which have been preserved to us, it is indisputable that the art itself never was understood or practised according to the true philosophy of it, as at Athens. For the Athenians employed language, action, music, painting, the dance, and religious institutions, to produce a common effect in the representation of the highest idealisms of passion and of power; each division in the art was made perfect in its kind by artists of the most consummate skill, and was disciplined into a beautiful proportion and unity one towards the other. On the modern stage a few only of the elements capable of expressing the image of the poet's conception are employed at once. We have tragedy without music and dancing; and music and dancing without the highest impersonations of which they are the fit accompaniment, and both without religion and solemnity. Religious institution has indeed been usually banished from the stage. Our system of divesting the actor's face of a mask, on which the many expressions appropriated to his dramatic character might be moulded into one permanent and unchanging expression, is favourable only to a partial and inharmonious effect; it is fit for nothing but a monologue, where all the attention may be directed to some great master of ideal mimicry. The modern practice of blending comedy with tragedy, though liable to great abuse in point of practice, is undoubtedly an extension of the dramatic circle; but the comedy should be as in KING LEAR, universal, ideal, and sublime. It is perhaps the intervention of this principle which determines the balance in favour of KING LEAR against the OEDIPUS TYRANNUS or the AGAMEMNON, or, if you will, the trilogies with which they are connected; unless the intense power of the choral poetry, especially that of the latter, should be considered as restoring the equilibrium. KING LEAR, if it can sustain this comparison, may be judged to be the most perfect specimen of the dramatic art existing in the world; in spite of the narrow conditions to which the poet was subjected by the ignorance of the philosophy of the drama which has prevailed in modern Europe. Calderon, in his religious AUTOS, has attempted to fulfil some of the high conditions of dramatic representation neglected by Shakespeare; such as the establishing a relation between the drama and religion and the accommodating them to music and dancing; but he omits the observation of conditions still more important, and more is lost than gained by the substitution of the rigidly-defined and ever-repeated idealisms of a distorted superstition for the living impersonations of the truth of human passion.

It was during the time referred to here that drama was born; and while a later writer may have matched or exceeded the few great examples of Athenian drama that have been preserved, it is clear that the art itself was never understood or practiced according to its true philosophy like it was in Athens. The Athenians used language, action, music, painting, dance, and religious institutions to create a unified effect in conveying the highest ideals of passion and power; each component of the art was perfected by highly skilled artists and harmonized beautifully with each other. On the modern stage, only a few of the elements that can express the poet’s vision are used at once. We have tragedy without music and dance, and music and dance without the profound performances that should accompany them, and both are lacking in religious depth and solemnity. Religion has typically been excluded from the stage. Our practice of removing the actor's mask, which once allowed for a range of expressions molded into one consistent and unchanging look, only leads to a fragmented and unbalanced effect; it suits nothing but a monologue where all focus can be on a great master of ideal imitation. The modern tendency to mix comedy with tragedy, though it can be misused, undeniably expands the dramatic realm; however, the comedy should be universal, ideal, and sublime, as seen in KING LEAR. This principle might tip the scale in favor of KING LEAR over OEDIPUS TYRANNUS or AGAMEMNON, or the trilogies related to them; unless we consider the intense power of choral poetry, especially from the latter, as restoring the balance. If KING LEAR can withstand this comparison, it may be regarded as the most perfect example of dramatic art in the world, despite the limited conditions imposed by the prevailing ignorance of drama’s philosophy in modern Europe. Calderon, in his religious AUTOS, has attempted to meet some of the high standards of dramatic representation overlooked by Shakespeare; such as establishing a connection between drama and religion and integrating them with music and dance; but he neglects even more critical conditions, and more is lost than gained by replacing the rigid, repeated idealisms of a warped superstition with the true expressions of human passion.

But I digress.—The connexion of scenic exhibitions with the improvement or corruption of the manners of men, has been universally recognized: in other words, the presence or absence of poetry in its most perfect and universal form, has been found to be connected with good and evil in conduct or habit. The corruption which has been imputed to the drama as an effect, begins when the poetry employed in its constitution ends: I appeal to the history of manners whether the periods of the growth of the one and the decline of the other have not corresponded with an exactness equal to any example of moral cause and effect.

But I’m getting sidetracked.—The link between theatrical performances and the improvement or decline of people's behavior has been widely acknowledged: in other words, the presence or absence of poetry in its most complete and universal form has been found to relate to good and bad conduct or habits. The corruption that has been attributed to drama as a consequence starts when the poetry used in its creation stops: I challenge the history of behavior to show whether the times of the rise of one and the fall of the other have not matched up with a precision equal to any example of moral cause and effect.

The drama at Athens, or wheresoever else it may have approached to its perfection, ever co-existed with the moral and intellectual greatness of the age. The tragedies of the Athenian poets are as mirrors in which the spectator beholds himself, under a thin disguise of circumstance, stript of all but that ideal perfection and energy which every one feels to be the internal type of all that he loves, admires, and would become. The imagination is enlarged by a sympathy with pains and passions so mighty, that they distend in their conception the capacity of that by which they are conceived; the good affections are strengthened by pity, indignation, terror, and sorrow; and an exalted calm is prolonged from the satiety of this high exercise of them into the tumult of familiar life: even crime is disarmed of half its horror and all its contagion by being represented as the fatal consequence of the unfathomable agencies of nature; error is thus divested of its wilfulness; men can no longer cherish it as the creation of their choice. In a drama of the highest order there is little food for censure or hatred; it teaches rather self-knowledge and self-respect. Neither the eye nor the mind can see itself, unless reflected upon that which it resembles. The drama, so long as it continues to express poetry, is as a prismatic and many-sided mirror, which collects the brightest rays of human nature and divides and reproduces them from the simplicity of these elementary forms, and touches them with majesty and beauty, and multiplies all that it reflects, and endows it with the power of propagating its like wherever it may fall.

The drama in Athens, or wherever it reached its peak, always went hand in hand with the moral and intellectual greatness of the time. The tragedies of Athenian poets act like mirrors in which the audience sees themselves, under a thin veil of circumstances, stripped of everything but the ideal perfection and energy that everyone feels is the true essence of what they love, admire, and aspire to be. The imagination expands through empathy with such powerful pains and emotions that they stretch the capacity of the mind that conceives them; positive feelings are intensified by pity, outrage, fear, and sadness; and a serene calm follows from this intense engagement into the chaos of everyday life: even crime loses much of its horror and contagion when depicted as the unavoidable result of the deep forces of nature; mistakes are seen without their intentionality; people can no longer hold onto them as products of their decisions. In a high-quality drama, there is little room for blame or hatred; it rather encourages self-awareness and self-respect. Neither the eye nor the mind can see itself unless reflected in something similar. As long as drama continues to express poetry, it serves as a prismatic, multifaceted mirror that gathers the brightest rays of human nature, separates and reproduces them from simple forms, touches them with grandeur and beauty, multiplies all it reflects, and gives it the power to reproduce itself wherever it may land.

But in periods of the decay of social life, the drama sympathizes with that decay. Tragedy becomes a cold imitation of the form of the great masterpieces of antiquity, divested of all harmonious accompaniment of the kindred arts; and often the very form misunderstood, or a weak attempt to teach certain doctrines, which the writer considers as moral truths; and which are usually no more than specious flatteries of some gross vice or weakness, with which the author, in common with his auditors, are infected. Hence what has been called the classical and domestic drama. Addison's CATO is a specimen of the one; and would it were not superfluous to cite examples of the other! To such purposes poetry cannot be made subservient. Poetry is a sword of lightning, ever unsheathed, which consumes the scabbard that would contain it. And thus we observe that all dramatic writings of this nature are unimaginative in a singular degree; they affect sentiment and passion, which, divested of imagination, are other names for caprice and appetite. The period in our own history of the grossest degradation of the drama is the reign of Charles II, when all forms in which poetry had been accustomed to be expressed became hymns to the triumph of kingly power over liberty and virtue. Milton stood alone illuminating an age unworthy of him. At such periods the calculating principle pervades all the forms of dramatic exhibition, and poetry ceases to be expressed upon them. Comedy loses its ideal universality: wit succeeds to humour; we laugh from self-complacency and triumph, instead of pleasure; malignity, sarcasm, and contempt, succeed to sympathetic merriment; we hardly laugh, but we Obscenity, which is ever blasphemy against the divine beauty in life, becomes, from the very veil which it assumes, more active if less disgusting: it is a monster for which the corruption of society for ever brings forth new food, which it devours in secret.

But during times when social life is falling apart, drama reflects that decay. Tragedy turns into a cold imitation of the great classic works of the past, stripped of all the beautiful support from related arts; often, it misunderstands the very form or makes a weak attempt to promote certain beliefs that the writer thinks are moral truths, which usually amount to mere flattering excuses for some blatant vice or weakness that the author shares with their audience. This led to what we now call classical and domestic drama. Addison's CATO is an example of the former; and it's a shame to think we need more examples of the latter! For such purposes, poetry can't be made to serve. Poetry is like a sword of lightning, always unsheathed, consuming the scabbard that tries to contain it. Thus, we see that all dramatic works of this type are strikingly unimaginative; they stir up feelings and emotions that, without imagination, are just other names for whim and desire. The lowest point in our own history for the drama was during the reign of Charles II, when every form of poetry became a celebration of royal power over freedom and virtue. Milton stood alone, shining a light on an age that didn't deserve him. In such times, a calculating mindset takes over all forms of dramatic expression, and poetry stops being conveyed through them. Comedy loses its ideal universality: wit replaces humor; we laugh out of self-satisfaction and triumph instead of enjoyment; malice, sarcasm, and disdain take the place of shared joy; our laughter is scarce, and when it happens, it feels empty. Obscenity, which is always an insult to the divine beauty of life, becomes, behind the mask it wears, more active if less revolting: it's a monster that the decay of society continually feeds, devouring its sustenance in secret.

The drama being that form under which a greater number of modes of expression of poetry are susceptible of being combined than any other, the connexion of poetry and social good is more observable in the drama than in whatever other form. And it is indisputable that the highest perfection of human society has ever corresponded with the highest dramatic excellence; and that the corruption or the extinction of the drama in a nation where it has once flourished, is a mark of a corruption of manners and an extinction of the energies which sustain the soul of social life. But, as Machiavelli says of political institutions, that life may be preserved and renewed, if men should arise capable of bringing back the drama to its principles. And this is true with respect to poetry in its most extended sense: all language, institution and form, require not only to be produced but to be sustained: the office and character of a poet participates in the divine nature as regards providence, no less than as regards creation.

The drama is the form that can combine more modes of poetic expression than any other, making the link between poetry and social good more evident in drama than in any other form. It's clear that the peak of human society has always aligned with the peak of dramatic excellence; when drama declines or disappears in a nation where it once thrived, it reflects a decline in moral values and a loss of the energies that support the soul of social life. However, as Machiavelli notes about political institutions, life can be preserved and renewed if people emerge who can bring drama back to its foundational principles. This holds true for poetry in its broadest sense: all language, institutions, and forms not only need to be created but also need to be sustained. The role and nature of a poet connects with the divine in terms of both providence and creation.

Civil war, the spoils of Asia, and the fatal predominance first of the Macedonian, and then of the Roman arms, were so many symbols of the extinction or suspension of the creative faculty in Greece. The bucolic writers, who found patronage under the lettered tyrants of Sicily and Egypt, were the latest representatives of its most glorious reign. Their poetry is intensely melodious, like the odour of the tuberose, it overcomes and sickens the spirit with excess of sweetness; whilst the poetry of the preceding age was as a meadow-gale of June, which mingles the fragrance all the flowers of the field, and adds a quickening and harmonizing spirit of its own, which endows the sense with a power of sustaining its extreme delight. The bucolic and erotic delicacy in written poetry is correlative with that softness in statuary, music and the kindred arts, and even in manners and institutions, which distinguished the epoch to which I now refer. Nor is it the poetical faculty itself, or any misapplication of it, to which this want of harmony is to be imputed. An equal sensibility to the influence of the senses and the affections is to be found in the writings of Homer and Sophocles: the former, especially, has clothed sensual and pathetic images with irresistible attractions. Their superiority over these succeeding writers consists in the presence of those thoughts which belong to the inner faculties of our nature, not in the absence of those which are connected with the external: their incomparable perfection consists in a harmony of the union of all. It is not what the erotic poets have, but what they have not, in which their imperfection consists. It is not inasmuch as they were poets, but inasmuch as they were not poets, that they can be considered with any plausibility as connected with the corruption of their age. Had that corruption availed so as to extinguish in them the sensibility to pleasure, passion, and natural scenery, which is imputed to them as an imperfection, the last triumph of evil would have been achieved. For the end of social corruption is to destroy all sensibility to pleasure; and, therefore, it is corruption. It begins at the imagination and the intellect as at the core, and distributes itself thence as a paralysing venom, through the affections into the very appetites, until all become a torpid mass in which hardly sense survives. At the approach of such a period, poetry ever addresses itself to those faculties which are the last to be destroyed, and its voice is heard, like the footsteps of Astraea, departing from the world. Poetry ever communicates all the pleasure which men are capable of receiving: it is ever still the light of life; the source of whatever of beautiful or generous or true can have place in an evil time. It will readily be confessed that those among the luxurious citizens of Syracuse and Alexandria, who were delighted with the poems of Theocritus, were less cold, cruel, and sensual than the remnant of their tribe. But corruption must utterly have destroyed the fabric of human society before poetry can ever cease. The sacred links of that chain have never been entirely disjoined, which descending through the minds of many men is attached to those great minds, whence as from a magnet the invisible effluence is sent forth, which at once connects, animates, and sustains the life of all. It is the faculty which contains within itself the seeds at once of its own and of social renovation. And let us not circumscribe the effects of the bucolic and erotic poetry within the limits of the sensibility of those to whom it was addressed. They may have perceived the beauty of those immortal compositions, simply as fragments and isolated portions: those who are more finely organized, or born in a happier age, may recognize them as episodes to that great poem, which all poets, like the cooperating thoughts of one great mind, have built up since the beginning of the world.

Civil war, the spoils of Asia, and the deadly dominance of first Macedonian, then Roman forces were clear signs of the loss or pause of creativity in Greece. The pastoral writers, who gained support from the educated tyrants of Sicily and Egypt, were the last representatives of its most glorious time. Their poetry is deeply melodic, overwhelming and exhausting the spirit with too much sweetness, while the poetry of the previous era was like a June breeze, blending the fragrances of all the flowers in the field and adding a refreshing and harmonizing spirit of its own, allowing the senses to fully savor their extreme pleasure. The pastoral and romantic delicacy in written poetry correlates with that gentleness found in sculpture, music, and related arts, and even in manners and institutions that characterized the era I am referencing. This lack of harmony isn’t due to the poetic ability itself or any misapplication of it. The same sensitivity to sensory influences and emotions can be found in the works of Homer and Sophocles; the former, in particular, has wrapped sensual and emotional images in irresistible appeal. Their superiority over the later writers lies in the presence of thoughts that connect to our inner nature, not in their lack of those linked to the external world: their unmatched perfection comes from the harmony in their union. It’s not what the erotic poets have that shows their flaws, but rather what they lack. It’s not because they were poets, but because they fell short as poets that we can plausibly link them to the decay of their era. If that decline had managed to extinguish their sensitivity to pleasure, passion, and nature—thought of as imperfections—the ultimate victory of corruption would have been achieved. The goal of societal corruption is to eliminate all sensitivity to pleasure; and that’s why it’s corruption. It begins at the imagination and intellect as its core and spreads like a paralyzing poison through emotions to the very appetites, until everything turns into a lifeless mass where barely any sense remains. As such a period approaches, poetry always appeals to those faculties that are the last to be destroyed, and its voice is heard like Astraea’s footsteps leaving the world. Poetry always provides all the joy that people are capable of receiving: it remains the light of life; the source of anything beautiful, generous, or true that can exist in a corrupt time. It’s easy to agree that those among the wealthy citizens of Syracuse and Alexandria, who enjoyed Theocritus’s poems, were less cold, cruel, and sensual than the rest of their group. But for poetry to ever cease, corruption must completely dismantle the structure of human society. The sacred links of that chain, which stretches through the minds of many people and connects to those great minds—where, like a magnet, an invisible influence is sent forth—has never been fully broken, connecting, animating, and sustaining the life of all. It is the faculty that holds within it the seeds of both its own and social renewal. And let’s not confine the effects of pastoral and romantic poetry to the limits of the sensitivity of those it addressed. They may have seen the beauty of those immortal works simply as fragments and isolated pieces: those who are more finely attuned or born in a better time may recognize them as episodes in that grand poem, which all poets, like the cooperating thoughts of one great mind, have been building since the dawn of time.

The same revolutions within a narrower sphere had place in ancient Rome; but the actions and forms of its social life never seem to have been perfectly saturated with the poetical element. The Romans appear to have considered the Greeks as the selectest treasuries of the selectest forms of manners and of nature, and to have abstained from creating in measured language, sculpture, music, or architecture, anything which might bear a particular relation to their own condition, whilst it should bear a general one to the universal constitution of the world. But we judge from partial evidence, and we judge perhaps partially Ennius, Varro, Pacuvius, and Accius, all great poets, have been lost. Lucretius is in the highest, and Virgil in a very high sense, a creator. The chosen delicacy of expressions of the latter, are as a mist of light which conceal from us the intense and exceeding truth of his conceptions of nature. Livy is instinct with poetry. Yet Horace, Catullus, Ovid, and generally the other great writers of the Virgilian age, saw man and nature in the mirror of Greece. The institutions also, and the religion of Rome were less poetical than those of Greece, as the shadow is less vivid than the substance. Hence poetry in Rome, seemed to follow, rather than accompany, the perfection of political and domestic society. The true poetry of Rome lived in its institutions; for whatever of beautiful, true, and majestic, they contained, could have sprung only from the faculty which creates the order in which they consist. The life of Camillus, the death of Regulus; the expectation of the senators, in their godlike state, of the victorious Gauls: the refusal of the republic to make peace with Hannibal, after the battle of Cannae, were not the consequences of a refined calculation of the probable personal advantage to result from such a rhythm and order in the shows of life, to those who were at once the poets and the actors of these immortal dramas. The imagination beholding the beauty of this order, created it out of itself according to its own idea; the consequence was empire, and the reward everliving fame. These things are not the less poetry quid carent vate sacro. They are the episodes of that cyclic poem written by Time upon the memories of men. The Past, like an inspired rhapsodist, fills the theatre of everlasting generations with their harmony.

The same revolutions within a smaller scope occurred in ancient Rome; however, the actions and forms of its social life never really seemed to be fully infused with a poetic element. The Romans seemed to view the Greeks as the ultimate source of the finest manners and aspects of nature, and they refrained from creating in structured language, sculpture, music, or architecture anything that might directly relate to their own circumstances, while still maintaining a broader connection to the universal structure of the world. But we base our views on limited evidence, and we might judge Ennius, Varro, Pacuvius, and Accius—great poets—only partially, as their works have been lost. Lucretius is a creator in the highest sense, and Virgil is too. The refined delicacy of Virgil’s expressions is like a mist of light that obscures the profound and intense truths of his ideas about nature. Livy's work is filled with poetry. Yet Horace, Catullus, Ovid, and generally the other prominent writers from the age of Virgil, saw humanity and nature reflected in the lens of Greek culture. Furthermore, the institutions and religion of Rome were less poetic than those of Greece, much like a shadow is less vivid than the substance it represents. As a result, poetry in Rome seemed to follow, rather than accompany, the achievements of political and social life. The true poetry of Rome resided in its institutions; anything beautiful, true, and majestic within them could only arise from the talent that creates the structure they embody. The life of Camillus, the death of Regulus; the anticipation of the senators in their godlike state regarding the victorious Gauls; the republic's refusal to make peace with Hannibal after the battle of Cannae—these were not results of a refined calculation of the potential personal benefits from such a rhythm and order in the displays of life for those who were both the poets and the actors in these timeless dramas. The imagination, observing the beauty of this order, created it from itself according to its own vision; the outcome was empire, and the reward was everlasting fame. These things are still poetry, even if they lack a sacred voice. They are the episodes of that cyclic poem written by Time in the memories of humanity. The Past, like an inspired performer, fills the stage of eternal generations with their harmony.

At length the ancient system of religion and manners had fulfilled the circle of its revolutions. And the world would have fallen into utter anarchy and darkness, but that there were found poets among the authors of the Christian and chivalric systems of manners and religion, who created forms of opinion and action never before conceived; which, copied into the imaginations of men, become as generals to the bewildered armies of their thoughts. It is foreign to the present purpose to touch upon the evil produced by these systems: except that we protest, on the ground of the principles already established, that no portion of it can be attributed to the poetry they contain.

Eventually, the old system of religion and customs had reached the end of its cycle. The world would have slipped into total chaos and darkness if not for the poets among the creators of the Christian and chivalric systems of belief and morals, who crafted ideas and actions that had never been imagined before. These ideas, once absorbed by people's minds, acted like generals guiding the confused armies of their thoughts. It's not the point here to delve into the harm caused by these systems, except to assert, based on previously established principles, that none of that harm can be blamed on the poetry they hold.

It is probable that the poetry of Moses, Job, David, Solomon, and Isaiah, had produced a great effect upon the mind of Jesus and his disciples. The scattered fragments preserved to us by the biographers of this extraordinary person, are all instinct with the most vivid poetry. But his doctrines seem to have been quickly distorted. At a certain period after the prevalence of a system of opinions founded upon those promulgated by him, the three forms into which Plato had distributed the faculties of mind underwent a sort of apotheosis, and became the object of the worship of the civilized world. Here it is to be confessed that 'Light seems to thicken,' and

It’s likely that the poetry of Moses, Job, David, Solomon, and Isaiah significantly influenced the thoughts of Jesus and his disciples. The scattered excerpts passed down by the biographers of this remarkable figure are full of intense poetry. However, his teachings appear to have been quickly misinterpreted. At some point after a set of beliefs based on his teachings gained traction, the three categories into which Plato categorized the mind's faculties experienced a kind of glorification, becoming objects of reverence in the civilized world. At this point, it must be acknowledged that 'Light seems to thicken,' and

       The crow makes wing to the rooky wood,
       Good things of day begin to droop and drowse,
       And night's black agents to their preys do rouze.
       The crow flies toward the dark woods,  
       Good things of the day start to fade and doze,  
       And the night's dark creatures stir to hunt.  

But mark how beautiful an order has sprung from the dust and blood of this fierce chaos! how the world, as from a resurrection, balancing itself on the golden wings of knowledge and of hope, has reassumed its yet unwearied flight into the heaven of time. Listen to the music, unheard by outward ears, which is as a ceaseless and invisible wind, nourishing its everlasting course with strength and swiftness.

But notice how beautiful an order has emerged from the dust and blood of this fierce chaos! How the world, as if from a resurrection, balancing itself on the golden wings of knowledge and hope, has taken back its relentless flight into the future. Listen to the music, unheard by our physical ears, which is like a constant and invisible wind, fueling its eternal journey with power and speed.

The poetry in the doctrines of Jesus Christ, and the mythology and institutions of the Celtic conquerors of the Roman empire, outlived the darkness and the convulsions connected with their growth and victory, and blended themselves in a new fabric of manners and opinion. It is an error to impute the ignorance of the dark ages to the Christian doctrines or the predominance of the Celtic nations. Whatever of evil their agencies may have contained sprang from the extinction of the poetical principle, connected with the progress of despotism and superstition. Men, from causes too intricate to be here discussed, had become insensible and selfish: their own will had become feeble, and yet they were its slaves, and thence the slaves of the will of others: lust, fear, avarice, cruelty, and fraud, characterized a race amongst whom no one was to be found capable of CREATING in form, language, or institution. The moral anomalies of such a state of society are not justly to be charged upon any class of events immediately connected with them, and those events are most entitled to our approbation which could dissolve it most expeditiously. It is unfortunate for those who cannot distinguish words from thoughts, that many of these anomalies have been incorporated into our popular religion.

The poetry in the teachings of Jesus Christ, along with the mythology and systems of the Celtic conquerors of the Roman Empire, survived the turmoil and challenges of their rise and triumph, blending into a new mix of customs and beliefs. It's a mistake to blame the ignorance of the dark ages on Christian doctrines or the dominance of the Celtic nations. Any negativity related to their influence came from the loss of the poetic spirit, which was tied to the rise of tyranny and superstition. People, for reasons too complex to discuss here, had become indifferent and self-absorbed: their own will became weak, and yet they became slaves to it, and thus became slaves to the will of others. Desire, fear, greed, cruelty, and deceit defined a society where no one could CREATE in form, language, or institution. The moral inconsistencies of such a society shouldn't be blamed on any specific events directly associated with it, and the events that are most deserving of our approval are those that can dissolve it the quickest. It is unfortunate for those who can't separate words from thoughts that many of these inconsistencies have been integrated into our mainstream religion.

It was not until the eleventh century that the effects of the poetry of the Christian and chivalric systems began to manifest themselves. The principle of equality had been discovered and applied by Plato in his Republic, as the theoretical rule of the mode in which the materials of pleasure and of power, produced by the common skill and labour of human beings, ought to be distributed among them. The limitations of this rule were asserted by him to be determined only by the sensibility of each, or the utility to result to all. Plato, following the doctrines of Timaeus and Pythagoras, taught also a moral and intellectual system of doctrine, comprehending at once the past, the present, and the future condition of man. Jesus Christ divulged the sacred and eternal truths contained in these views to mankind, and Christianity, in its abstract purity, became the exoteric expression of the esoteric doctrines of the poetry and wisdom of antiquity. The incorporation of the Celtic nations with the exhausted population of the south, impressed upon it the figure of the poetry existing in their mythology and institutions. The result was a sum of the action and reaction of all the causes included in it; for it may be assumed as a maxim that no nation or religion can supersede any other without incorporating into itself a portion of that which it supersedes. The abolition of personal and domestic slavery, and the emancipation of women from a great part of the degrading restraints of antiquity, were among the consequences of these events.

It wasn't until the eleventh century that the impact of Christian and chivalric poetry started to show. The idea of equality was first introduced and applied by Plato in his Republic, as the theoretical guideline for how the resources of pleasure and power, created by the collective skills and efforts of people, should be shared. He argued that the limits of this guideline were determined only by individual sensitivity or the benefits it would bring to everyone. Plato, influenced by the teachings of Timaeus and Pythagoras, also promoted a moral and intellectual system that addressed the past, present, and future of humanity. Jesus Christ revealed the sacred and eternal truths found in these ideas to humanity, and Christianity, in its purest form, became the public expression of the deeper teachings in the poetry and wisdom of the past. The merging of the Celtic nations with the declining population of the south infused it with the essence of the poetry rooted in their mythology and institutions. This resulted from the interplay of all the contributing factors; it's understood that no nation or religion can completely replace another without absorbing part of what it replaces. The end of personal and domestic slavery, along with the liberation of women from many of the oppressive constraints of the past, were among the outcomes of these developments.

The abolition of personal slavery is the basis of the highest political hope that it can enter into the mind of man to conceive. The freedom of women produced the poetry of sexual love. Love became a religion, the idols of whose worship were ever present. It was as if the statues of Apollo and the Muses had been endowed with life and motion, and had walked forth among their worshippers; so that earth became peopled by the inhabitants of a diviner world. The familiar appearance and proceedings of life became wonderful and heavenly, and a paradise was created as out of the wrecks of Eden. And as this creation itself is poetry, so its creators were poets; and language was the instrument of their art: 'Galeotto fu il libro, e chi lo scrisse.' The Provencal Trouveurs, or inventors, preceded Petrarch, whose verses are as spells, which unseal the inmost enchanted fountains of the delight which is in the grief of love. It is impossible to feel them without becoming a portion of that beauty which we contemplate: it were superfluous to explain how the gentleness and the elevation of mind connected with these sacred emotions can render men more amiable, more generous and wise, and lift them out of the dull vapours of the little world of self. Dante understood the secret things of love even more than Petrarch. His Vita Nuova is an inexhaustible fountain of purity of sentiment and language: it is the idealized history of that period, and those intervals of his life which were dedicated to love. His apotheosis of Beatrice in Paradise, and the gradations of his own love and her loveliness, by which as by steps he feigns himself to have ascended to the throne of the Supreme Cause, is the most glorious imagination of modern poetry. The acutest critics have justly reversed the judgement of the vulgar, and the order of the great acts of the 'Divine Drama', in the measure of the admiration which they accord to the Hell, Purgatory, and Paradise. The latter is a perpetual hymn of everlasting love. Love, which found a worthy poet in Plato alone of all the ancients, has been celebrated by a chorus of the greatest writers of the renovated world; and the music has penetrated the caverns of society, and its echoes still drown the dissonance of arms and superstition. At successive intervals, Ariosto, Tasso, Shakespeare, Spenser, Calderon, Rousseau, and the great writers of our own age, have celebrated the dominion of love, planting as it were trophies in the human mind of that sublimest victory over sensuality and force. The true relation borne to each other by the sexes into which human kind is distributed, has become less misunderstood; and if the error which confounded diversity with inequality of the powers of the two sexes has been partially recognized in the opinions and institutions of modern Europe, we owe this great benefit to the worship of which chivalry was the law, and poets the prophets.

The end of personal slavery is the foundation of the greatest political hope that humankind can imagine. The liberation of women inspired the poetry of romantic love. Love turned into a kind of religion, with its idols always around us. It was like the statues of Apollo and the Muses coming to life and mingling with their admirers, creating a world filled with beings from a higher realm. Everyday life transformed into something magical and divine, crafting a paradise from the remnants of Eden. And just as this creation itself is poetry, its artisans were poets; language was their artistic tool: 'Galeotto fu il libro, e chi lo scrisse.' The Provencal Trouveurs, or innovators, came before Petrarch, whose verses serve as powerful spells that unlock the deepest enchanted wells of joy found in the sorrow of love. You can't read them without becoming part of the beauty you’re witnessing: it's unnecessary to explain how the kindness and elevated mindset associated with these sacred feelings can make people more loving, generous, and wise, lifting them above the dull clouds of self-obsession. Dante understood the nuances of love even better than Petrarch. His Vita Nuova is an endless source of purity in feeling and expression: it idealizes the periods and moments of his life devoted to love. His idealization of Beatrice in Paradise and the stages of his own love and her beauty, which he describes as steps leading him to the throne of the Supreme Cause, is one of the most glorious concepts in modern poetry. The sharpest critics have rightly overturned the common opinion, adjusting the importance of the acts in the 'Divine Drama,' reflecting the admiration they have for Hell, Purgatory, and Paradise. The latter is an everlasting song of love. Love, which only found a worthy poet in Plato among the ancients, has been celebrated by a chorus of the greatest writers of the modern era; their music has permeated society's depths, and its echoes still drown out the chaos of violence and superstition. Throughout the years, Ariosto, Tasso, Shakespeare, Spenser, Calderon, Rousseau, and the prominent writers of our time have praised the power of love, like trophies planted in the human mind for that greatest victory over desire and force. The true relationship between the sexes has become clearer; and if the mistake that confused difference with inequality between the powers of the two sexes has been partially recognized in the thoughts and institutions of modern Europe, we owe this great benefit to the reverence for which chivalry was the law and poets were the prophets.

The poetry of Dante may be considered as the bridge thrown over the stream of time, which unites the modern and ancient world. The distorted notions of invisible things which Dante and his rival Milton have idealized, are merely the mask and the mantle in which these great poets walk through eternity enveloped and disguised. It is a difficult question to determine how far they were conscious of the distinction which must have subsisted in their minds between their own creeds and that of the people. Dante at least appears to wish to mark the full extent of it by placing Riphaeus, whom Virgil calls justissimns unus, in Paradise, and observing a most heretical caprice in his distribution of rewards and punishments. And Milton's poem contains within itself a philosophical refutation of that system, of which by a strange and natural antithesis, it has been a chief popular support. Nothing can exceed the energy and magnificence of the character of Satan as expressed in Paradise Lost. It is a mistake to suppose that he could ever have been intended for the popular personification of evil. Implacable hate, patient cunning, and a sleepless refinement of device to inflict the extremest anguish on an enemy, these things are evil; and, although venial in a slave are not to be forgiven in a tyrant; although redeemed by much that ennobles his defeat in one subdued, are marked by all that dishonours his conquest in the victor. Milton's Devil as a moral being is as far superior to his God, as one who perseveres in some purpose which he has conceived to be excellent in spite of adversity and torture, is to one who in the cold security of undoubted triumph inflicts the most horrible revenge upon his enemy, not from any mistaken notion of inducing him to repent of a perseverance in enmity, but with the alleged design of exasperating him to deserve new torments. Milton has so far violated the popular creed (if this shall be judged to be a violation) as to have alleged no superiority of moral virtue to his God over his Devil. And this bold neglect of a direct moral purpose is the most decisive proof of the supremacy of Milton's genius. He mingled as it were the elements of human nature as colours upon a single pallet, and arranged them in the composition of his great picture according to the laws of epic truth; that is, according to the laws of that principle by which a series of actions of the external universe and of intelligent and ethical beings is calculated to excite the sympathy of succeeding generations of mankind. The Divina Commedia and Paradise Lost have conferred upon modern mythology a systematic form; and when change and time shall have added one more superstition to the mass of those which have arisen and decayed upon the earth, commentators will be learnedly employed in elucidating the religion of ancestral Europe, only not utterly forgotten because it will have been stamped with the eternity of genius.

Dante's poetry can be seen as a bridge across the river of time, connecting the modern world to the ancient. The distorted ideas of invisible things that Dante and his rival Milton idealized are simply the disguise these great poets wear as they traverse eternity. It’s challenging to figure out how aware they were of the distinction that must have existed in their minds between their own beliefs and those of the people. Dante seems to want to highlight this difference by placing Riphaeus, whom Virgil calls the most just, in Paradise and showing a rather heretical approach in how he distributes rewards and punishments. Milton's poem, on the other hand, contains an internal philosophical rebuttal to the very system that, ironically, it has primarily supported. Nothing can match the intensity and grandeur of Satan's character as depicted in Paradise Lost. It's a mistake to think he was meant to be a popular symbol of evil. Unrelenting hatred, patient cunning, and the relentless pursuit of inflicting extreme suffering on an enemy represent evil. While such traits might be forgivable in a subordinate, they are inexcusable in a tyrant; though victory might have some redeeming qualities, it is overshadowed by the disgrace of his triumph. Milton's Devil, as a moral being, is far superior to his God. The one who perseveres in a purpose he believes to be noble despite suffering and hardship stands in stark contrast to one who, secure in his triumph, cruelly seeks to punish his enemy, not to drive him to repentance, but to provoke him into deserving further torment. Milton challenges the popular belief (if this can be considered a challenge) by claiming that his God has no greater moral virtue than his Devil. This daring disregard for a straightforward moral message is a definitive testament to Milton's genius. He blended the elements of human nature like colors on a single palette, organizing them in his grand composition according to the principles of epic truth; that is, he constructed a series of actions from the external universe and from intelligent, ethical beings designed to evoke the sympathy of future generations. The Divina Commedia and Paradise Lost have given modern mythology a structured form; and when change and time have introduced another superstition to the cycle of those that have emerged and faded on earth, scholars will be earnestly engaged in explaining the religion of ancestral Europe, remembered not entirely because it will be marked by the eternal nature of genius.

Homer was the first and Dante the second epic poet: that is, the second poet, the series of whose creations bore a defined and intelligible relation to the knowledge and sentiment and religion of the age in which he lived, and of the ages which followed it: developing itself in correspondence with their development. For Lucretius had limed the wings of his swift spirit in the dregs of the sensible world; and Virgil, with a modesty that ill became his genius, had affected the fame of an imitator, even whilst he created anew all that he copied; and none among the flock of mock-birds, though their notes were sweet, Apollonius Rhodius, Quintus Calaber, Nonnus, Lucan, Statius, or Claudian, have sought even to fulfil a single condition of epic truth. Milton was the third epic poet. For if the title of epic in its highest sense be refused to the Aeneid, still less can it be conceded to the Orlando Furioso, the Gerusalemme Liberata, the Lusiad, or the Fairy Queen.

Homer was the first epic poet, and Dante was the second. He was the second poet whose works were clearly connected to the knowledge, feelings, and beliefs of his time and the times that followed, growing alongside their development. Lucretius had grounded his brilliant ideas in the more mundane aspects of the physical world, and Virgil, with a humility that didn't match his talent, pretended to be an imitator even while he was reinventing everything he borrowed from. None of the imitators, despite their pleasant verses—Apollonius Rhodius, Quintus Calaber, Nonnus, Lucan, Statius, or Claudian—managed to meet even one standard of epic truth. Milton was the third epic poet. Even if we deny the title of epic in its truest sense to the Aeneid, it’s even harder to grant it to the Orlando Furioso, the Gerusalemme Liberata, the Lusiad, or the Fairy Queen.

Dante and Milton were both deeply penetrated with the ancient religion of the civilized world; and its spirit exists in their poetry probably in the same proportion as its forms survived in the unreformed worship of modern Europe. The one preceded and the other followed the Reformation at almost equal intervals. Dante was the first religious reformer, and Luther surpassed him rather in the rudeness and acrimony, than in the boldness of his censures of papal usurpation. Dante was the first awakener of entranced Europe; he created a language, in itself music and persuasion, out of a chaos of inharmonious barbarisms. He was the congregator of those great spirits who presided over the resurrection of learning; the Lucifer of that starry flock which in the thirteenth century shone forth from republican Italy, as from a heaven, into the darkness of the benighted world. His very words are instinct with spirit; each is as a spark, a burning atom of inextinguishable thought; and many yet lie covered in the ashes of their birth, and pregnant with a lightning which has yet found no conductor. All high poetry is infinite; it is as the first acorn, which contained all oaks potentially. Veil after veil may be undrawn, and the inmost naked beauty of the meaning never exposed. A great poem is a fountain for ever overflowing with the waters of wisdom and delight; and after one person and one age has exhausted all its divine effluence which their peculiar relations enable them to share, another and yet another succeeds, and new relations are ever developed, the source of an unforeseen and an unconceived delight.

Dante and Milton were both deeply influenced by the ancient religion of the civilized world, and its spirit is present in their poetry in about the same way that its forms remain in the outdated worship of modern Europe. Dante came before and Milton followed the Reformation by nearly the same amount of time. Dante was the first religious reformer, while Luther excelled more in his harshness and intensity than in the fearlessness of his criticisms of papal power. Dante was the first to awaken the slumbering Europe; he created a language that was both musical and persuasive from a mix of disjointed barbaric expressions. He brought together those great minds who led the resurgence of learning; he was the guiding light of those brilliant thinkers who, in the thirteenth century, emerged from republican Italy like stars shining through the darkness of a lost world. His very words are full of spirit; each one is like a spark, a burning particle of unquenchable thought, and many still lie buried under the ashes of their creation, filled with unexpressed potential. All great poetry is infinite; it’s like the first acorn that holds all oaks within it. Layer after layer can be removed, but the deepest and most beautiful meaning remains uncovered. A great poem is a fountain that constantly overflows with wisdom and joy; and after one person and one era have tapped into all its divine essence that their unique connection allows, another, and then another, follows, continually creating new connections and a source of unexpected and unimaginable joy.

The age immediately succeeding to that of Dante, Petrarch, and Boccaccio, was characterized by a revival of painting, sculpture, and architecture. Chaucer caught the sacred inspiration, and the superstructure of English literature is based upon the materials of Italian invention.

The time right after Dante, Petrarch, and Boccaccio was marked by a resurgence in painting, sculpture, and architecture. Chaucer was inspired by this and the foundation of English literature is built on the ideas of Italian creativity.

But let us not be betrayed from a defence into a critical history of poetry and its influence on society. Be it enough to have pointed out the effects of poets, in the large and true sense of the word, upon their own and all succeeding times.

But let’s not get sidetracked from a defense into a critical history of poetry and its impact on society. It’s enough to have highlighted the effects of poets, in the broad and genuine sense of the term, on their own time and all future generations.

But poets have been challenged to resign the civic crown to reasoners and mechanists, on another plea. It is admitted that the exercise of the imagination is most delightful, but it is alleged that that of reason is more useful. Let us examine as the grounds of this distinction, what is here meant by utility. Pleasure or good, in a general sense, is that which the consciousness of a sensitive and intelligent being seeks, and in which, when found, it acquiesces. There are two kinds of pleasure, one durable, universal and permanent; the other transitory and particular. Utility may either express the means of producing the former or the latter. In the former sense, whatever strengthens and purifies the affections, enlarges the imagination, and adds spirit to sense, is useful. But a narrower meaning may be assigned to the word utility, confining it to express that which banishes the importunity of the wants of our animal nature, the surrounding men with security of life, the dispersing the grosser delusions of superstition, and the conciliating such a degree of mutual forbearance among men as may consist with the motives of personal advantage.

But poets have been urged to give up the civic crown to those who focus on reason and mechanics, based on another argument. It’s recognized that using imagination is incredibly enjoyable, but it’s claimed that using reason is more beneficial. Let’s look into what is meant by utility as the basis for this distinction. Pleasure or good, in a broad sense, is what a sensitive and intelligent being seeks, and it finds satisfaction in it when discovered. There are two types of pleasure: one is lasting, universal, and permanent; the other is fleeting and specific. Utility can refer to the means of creating either type. In its broader sense, anything that strengthens and purifies our feelings, expands our imagination, and enhances our senses is useful. However, a more narrow definition of utility could focus on what alleviates the pressing needs of our physical nature, provides security for life, dispels the harsh illusions of superstition, and fosters a level of mutual tolerance among people while still considering personal advantage.

Undoubtedly the promoters of utility, in this limited sense, have their appointed office in society. They follow the footsteps of poets, and copy the sketches of their creations into the book of common life. They make space, and give time. Their exertions are of the highest value, so long as they confine their administration of the concerns of the inferior powers of our nature within the limits due to the superior ones. But whilst the sceptic destroys gross superstitions, let him spare to deface, as some of the French writers have defaced, the eternal truths charactered upon the imaginations of men. Whilst the mechanist abridges, and the political economist combines labour, let them beware that their speculations, for want of correspondence with those first principles which belong to the imagination, do not tend, as they have in modern England, to exasperate at once the extremes of luxury and want. They have exemplified the saying, 'To him that hath, more shall be given; and from him that hath not, the little that he hath shall be taken away.' The rich have become richer, and the poor have become poorer; and the vessel of the state is driven between the Scylla and Charybdis of anarchy and despotism. Such are the effects which must ever flow from an unmitigated exercise of the calculating faculty.

Without a doubt, the advocates of practical utility play an essential role in society. They follow the paths laid down by poets, translating the ideas from their creativity into the everyday lives of people. They create opportunities and allocate time. Their efforts are incredibly valuable, provided they manage the lesser aspects of our nature without overstepping the bounds set by the higher ones. However, while skeptics dismantle blatant superstitions, they should be careful not to erase, as some French writers have done, the fundamental truths etched in the minds of people. As mechanics streamline processes, and political economists organize labor, they must ensure that their theories align with the foundational principles of imagination; otherwise, as seen in modern England, they risk escalating the divide between extreme luxury and extreme poverty. They have illustrated the adage, "To those who have, more will be given; and from those who have not, even what little they have will be taken away." The wealthy have grown even wealthier, while the poor have sunk deeper into poverty; the state teeters between the dangers of anarchy and tyranny. Such are the consequences that will always arise from an unchecked use of analytical reasoning.

It is difficult to define pleasure in its highest sense; the definition involving a number of apparent paradoxes. For, from an inexplicable defect of harmony in the constitution of human nature, the pain of the inferior is frequently connected with the pleasures of the superior portions of our being. Sorrow, terror, anguish, despair itself, are often the chosen expressions of an approximation to the highest good. Our sympathy in tragic fiction depends on this principle; tragedy delights by affording a shadow of the pleasure which exists in pain. This is the source also of the melancholy which is inseparable from the sweetest melody. The pleasure that is in sorrow is sweeter than the pleasure of pleasure itself. And hence the saying, 'It is better to go to the house of mourning, than to the house of mirth.' Not that this highest species of pleasure is necessarily linked with pain. The delight of love and friendship, the ecstasy of the admiration of nature, the joy of the perception and still more of the creation of poetry, is often wholly unalloyed.

Defining pleasure in its highest form is challenging; the definition involves several apparent contradictions. Due to a strange imbalance in human nature, the suffering of some often relates to the joys of others within ourselves. Feelings like sorrow, fear, anguish, and even despair frequently serve as expressions of reaching the highest good. Our emotional connection to tragic stories is based on this idea; tragedy captivates us by offering a glimpse of the pleasure found in pain. This also explains the sadness that often accompanies the sweetest melodies. The pleasure found in sorrow is more profound than the pleasure found in happiness itself. This is why the saying goes, 'It is better to go to the house of mourning than to the house of mirth.' However, this ultimate form of pleasure isn’t always tied to pain. The joy of love and friendship, the bliss of admiring nature, and the happiness from experiencing and creating poetry can often be completely pure.

The production and assurance of pleasure in this highest sense is true utility. Those who produce and preserve this pleasure are poets or poetical philosophers.

The creation and guarantee of pleasure in its greatest sense is true utility. Those who create and maintain this pleasure are poets or poetic thinkers.

The exertions of Locke, Hume, Gibbon, Voltaire, Rousseau, [Footnote: Although Rousseau has been thus classed, he was essentially a poet. The others, even Voltaire, were mere reasoners.] and their disciples, in favour of oppressed and deluded humanity, are entitled to the gratitude of mankind. Yet it is easy to calculate the degree of moral and intellectual improvement which the world would have exhibited, had they never lived. A little more nonsense would have been talked for a century or two; and perhaps a few more men, women, and children, burnt as heretics. We might not at this moment have been congratulating each other on the abolition of the Inquisition in Spain. But it exceeds all imagination to conceive what would have been the moral condition of the world if neither Dante, Petrarch, Boccaccio, Chaucer, Shakespeare, Calderon, Lord Bacon, nor Milton, had ever existed; if Raphael and Michael Angelo had never been born; if the Hebrew poetry had never been translated; if a revival of the study of Greek literature had never taken place; if no monuments of ancient sculpture had been handed down to us; and if the poetry of the religion of the ancient world had been extinguished together with its belief. The human mind could never, except by the intervention of these excitements, have been awakened to the invention of the grosser sciences, and that application of analytical reasoning to the aberrations of society, which it is now attempted to exalt over the direct expression of the inventive and creative faculty itself.

The efforts of Locke, Hume, Gibbon, Voltaire, Rousseau, [Footnote: Although Rousseau has been thus classed, he was essentially a poet. The others, even Voltaire, were mere reasoners.] and their followers to support oppressed and misled humanity deserve the gratitude of people everywhere. However, it's easy to imagine how different the moral and intellectual progress of the world would have been if they had never existed. A bit more nonsense might have been spoken for a century or two, and possibly a few more men, women, and children would have been burned as heretics. We might not currently be congratulating each other on the abolition of the Inquisition in Spain. But it’s beyond imagination to consider the moral state of the world if figures like Dante, Petrarch, Boccaccio, Chaucer, Shakespeare, Calderon, Lord Bacon, and Milton had never come along; if Raphael and Michelangelo had never been born; if Hebrew poetry had never been translated; if there had been no revival of Greek literature; if we hadn’t inherited any monuments of ancient sculpture; and if the poetry of ancient religious beliefs had been lost along with their faith. The human mind could never, without these influences, have been stirred to develop the more practical sciences, or to apply analytical reasoning to societal issues, which is now being promoted as superior to the direct expression of creative and inventive talent itself.

We have more moral, political and historical wisdom, than we know how to reduce into practice; we have more scientific and economical knowledge than can be accommodated to the just distribution of the produce which it multiplies. The poetry in these systems of thought, is concealed by the accumulation of facts and calculating processes. There is no want of knowledge respecting what is wisest and best in morals, government, and political economy, or at least, what is wiser and better than what men now practise and endure. But we let 'I DARE NOT wait upon I WOULD, like the poor cat in the adage.' We want the creative faculty to imagine that which we know; we want the generous impulse to act that which we imagine; we want the poetry of life: our calculations have outrun conception; we have eaten more than we can digest. The cultivation of those sciences which have enlarged the limits of the empire of man over the external world, has, for want of the poetical faculty, proportionally circumscribed those of the internal world; and man, having enslaved the elements, remains himself a slave. To what but a cultivation of the mechanical arts in a degree disproportioned to the presence of the creative faculty, which is the basis of all knowledge, is to be attributed the abuse of all invention for abridging and combining labour, to the exasperation of the inequality of mankind? From what other cause has it arisen that the discoveries which should have lightened, have added a weight to the curse imposed on Adam? Poetry, and the principle of Self, of which money is the visible, incarnation, are the God and Mammon of the world.

We have more moral, political, and historical wisdom than we know how to put into practice; we have more scientific and economic knowledge than can be fitted into a fair distribution of the goods it creates. The beauty in these ways of thinking is hidden by the pile of facts and calculations. There’s no shortage of understanding about what is wise and best in morals, government, and economics, or at least what is wiser and better than what people are currently doing and putting up with. But we let 'I DARE NOT wait upon I WOULD, like the poor cat in the saying.' We need the creative ability to envision what we know; we need the generous drive to act on what we imagine; we need the poetry of life. Our calculations have gone beyond our understanding; we've taken in more than we can handle. The development of those sciences that have expanded human control over the outside world has, due to a lack of the artistic spirit, limited our internal world in equal measure; and while humanity has conquered the elements, we remain slaves. What else can we attribute the misuse of all inventions designed to shorten and combine labor, which only seems to worsen the inequality among people, to except the growth of mechanical skills without a corresponding rise in our creative spirit, which is the foundation of all knowledge? What other reason is there for the fact that discoveries meant to alleviate burdens have instead added to the curse laid upon Adam? Poetry, and the essence of Self, which money embodies, are the God and Mammon of the world.

The functions of the poetical faculty are two-fold; by one it creates new materials of knowledge and power and pleasure; by the other it engenders in the mind a desire to reproduce and arrange them according to a certain rhythm and order which may be called the beautiful and the good. The cultivation of poetry is never more to be desired than at periods when, from an excess of the selfish and calculating principle, the accumulation of the materials of external life exceed the quantity of the power of assimilating them to the internal laws of human nature. The body has then become too unwieldy for that which animates it.

The functions of the poetic mind are twofold; on one hand, it creates new sources of knowledge, power, and pleasure; on the other, it sparks a desire in people to recreate and organize these sources according to a certain rhythm and order, which can be called beautiful and good. The growth of poetry is especially important during times when, due to an overload of selfish and calculating tendencies, the amount of external life materials exceeds our ability to integrate them into the internal principles of human nature. The body then becomes too cumbersome for what drives it.

Poetry is indeed something divine. It is at once the centre and circumference of knowledge; it is that which comprehends all science, and that to which all science must be referred. It is at the same time the root and blossom of all other systems of thought; it is that from which all spring, and that which adorns all; and that which, if blighted, denies the fruit and the seed, and withholds from the barren world the nourishment and the succession of the scions of the tree of life. It is the perfect and consummate surface and bloom of all things; it is as the odour and the colour of the rose to the texture of the elements which compose it, as the form and splendour of unfaded beauty to the secrets of anatomy and corruption. What were virtue, love, patriotism, friendship—what were the scenery of this beautiful universe which we inhabit; what were our consolations on this side of the grave—and what were our aspirations beyond it, if poetry did not ascend to bring light and fire from those eternal regions where the owl-winged faculty of calculation dare not ever soar? Poetry is not like reasoning, a power to be exerted according to the determination of the will. A man cannot say, 'I will compose poetry.' The greatest poet even cannot say it; for the mind in creation is as a fading coal, which some invisible influence, like an inconstant wind, awakens to transitory brightness; this power arises from within, like the colour of a flower which fades and changes as it is developed, and the conscious portions of our natures are unprophetic either of its approach or its departure. Could this influence be durable in its original purity and force, it is impossible to predict the greatness of the results; but when composition begins, inspiration is already on the decline, and the most glorious poetry that has ever been communicated to the world is probably a feeble shadow of the original conceptions of the poet. I appeal to the greatest poets of the present day, whether it is not an error to assert that the finest passages of poetry are produced by labour and study. The toil and the delay recommended by critics, can be justly interpreted to mean no more than a careful observation of the inspired moments, and an artificial connexion of the spaces between their suggestions by the intertexture of conventional expressions; a necessity only imposed by the limitedness of the poetical faculty itself; for Milton conceived the Paradise Lost as a whole before he executed it in portions; We have his own authority also for the muse having 'dictated' to him the 'unpremeditated song'. And let this be an answer to those who would allege the fifty-six various readings of the first line of the Orlando Furioso. Compositions so produced are to poetry what mosaic is to painting. This instinct and intuition of the poetical faculty, is still more observable in the plastic and pictorial arts; a great statue or picture grows under the power of the artist as a child in the mother's womb; and the very mind which directs the hands in formation is incapable of accounting to itself for the origin, the gradations, or the media of the process.

Poetry is truly something divine. It is both the center and the edge of knowledge; it encompasses all science, and all science must reference it. It is simultaneously the root and the bloom of all other ways of thinking; it is the source from which everything springs, and it adorns all things. If it is damaged, it denies the fruit and the seed, depriving the barren world of nourishment and the continuation of life’s legacy. It represents the perfect and complete surface and beauty of all things; it’s like the fragrance and color of a rose compared to the basic elements that make it up, and like the form and brilliance of lasting beauty in contrast to the hidden truths of anatomy and decay. What would virtue, love, patriotism, and friendship mean—what would the beauty of this universe we live in look like; what would comfort look like on this side of the grave—and what would our hopes be beyond it, if poetry didn’t rise up to bring light and inspiration from those timeless realms where logical reasoning doesn’t dare to tread? Poetry isn't like reasoning; it's not a force that can be harnessed at will. A person can’t simply declare, 'I will create poetry.' Even the greatest poet can’t say that; for during the act of creation, the mind is like a dimming ember, which some unseen force, like a fickle wind, ignites briefly. This power emerges from within, like the color of a flower that fades and shifts as it blooms, and our conscious selves can't predict when it will come or go. If this influence could last in its original purity and strength, it would be impossible to foresee how great the results might be; but once the composition begins, inspiration is already fading, and the most brilliant poetry ever shared is likely just a faint reflection of the poet's original ideas. I challenge today’s greatest poets to consider whether it’s true that the best lines of poetry come from hard work and study. The effort and time that critics suggest usually mean nothing more than carefully noting the moments of inspiration and piecing together the gaps between their ideas with common expressions; a necessity only imposed by the limitations of the poetic talent itself; because Milton envisioned Paradise Lost in its entirety before writing it in parts; we also have his own words stating that the muse 'dictated' to him the 'spontaneous song.' And let this address those who mention the fifty-six different versions of the first line of Orlando Furioso. Compositions like this are to poetry what mosaic is to painting. This instinct and intuition of the poetic talent are even more evident in visual and sculptural arts; a great statue or painting develops under the artist’s influence like a child in its mother’s womb; and the very mind that guides the hands in creation cannot explain the origin, the phases, or the means of that process.

Poetry is the record of the best and happiest moments of the happiest and best minds. We are aware of evanescent visitations of thought and feeling sometimes associated with place or person, sometimes regarding our own mind alone, and always arising unforeseen and departing unbidden, but elevating and delightful beyond all expression; so that even in the desire and regret they leave, there cannot but be pleasure, participating as it does in the nature of its object. It is as it were the interpenetration of a diviner nature through our own; but its footsteps are like those of a wind over the sea, which the coming calm erases, and whose traces remain only, as on the wrinkled sand which paves it. These and corresponding conditions of being are experienced principally by those of the most delicate sensibility and the most enlarged imagination; and the state of mind produced by them is at war with every base desire. The enthusiasm of virtue, love, patriotism, and friendship, is essentially linked with such emotions; and whilst they last, self appears as what it is, an atom to a universe. Poets are not only subject to these experiences as spirits of the most refined organization, but they can colour all that they combine with the evanescent hues of this ethereal world; a word, a trait in the representation of a scene or a passion, will touch the enchanted chord, and reanimate, in those who have ever experienced these emotions, the sleeping, the cold, the buried image of the past. Poetry thus makes immortal all that is best and most beautiful in the world; it arrests the vanishing apparitions which haunt the interlunations of life, and veiling them, or in language or in form, sends them forth among mankind, bearing sweet news of kindred joy to those with whom their sisters abide—abide, because there is no portal of expression from the caverns of the spirit which they inhabit into the universe of things. Poetry redeems from decay the visitations of the divinity in man.

Poetry captures the best and happiest moments of the brightest minds. We experience fleeting moments of thought and emotion, sometimes tied to a specific place or person, sometimes reflecting only our own thoughts, always unexpected and coming and going without invitation, yet uplifting and delightful beyond words. Even in the feelings of longing and regret they leave behind, there’s still pleasure, as it connects us to what we cherish. It’s like a purer essence flowing through our own; its presence is as fleeting as a breeze over the ocean, washed away by the calm, leaving only traces like the patterns on the sand. These feelings are primarily felt by those with the most sensitive hearts and expansive imaginations, and the mindset they create conflicts with any petty desire. The passion for virtue, love, patriotism, and friendship is deeply tied to these emotions; and while they last, we see ourselves as what we truly are—tiny pieces of a vast universe. Poets not only experience these moments as some of the most refined spirits but can also infuse everything they touch with the fleeting beauty of this ethereal realm; a single word or a detail in depicting a scene or feeling can resonate with those who have felt these emotions, awakening long-buried memories of the past. Poetry immortalizes all that is wonderful and beautiful in the world; it captures the fleeting visions that appear during life's transitions and, whether through words or form, shares them with humanity, bringing joyful connections to those who share in these feelings—connections that exist because the depths of the spirit have no way to express themselves into the tangible world. Poetry saves the divine moments in human experience from fading away.

Poetry turns all things to loveliness; it exalts the beauty of that which is most beautiful, and it adds beauty to that which is most deformed; it marries exultation and horror, grief and pleasure, eternity and change; it subdues to union under its light yoke, all irreconcilable things. It transmutes all that it touches, and every form moving within the radiance of its presence is changed by wondrous sympathy to an incarnation of the spirit which it breathes: its secret alchemy turns to potable gold the poisonous waters which flow from death through life; it strips the veil of familiarity from the world, and lays bare the naked and sleeping beauty, which is the spirit of its forms.

Poetry transforms everything into beauty; it enhances the allure of what is already beautiful and adds beauty to what is flawed. It combines joy and fear, sorrow and happiness, eternity and change; it unites all opposing things under its gentle influence. It changes everything it touches, and anything that moves within its light becomes a reflection of the spirit it embodies: its hidden magic turns toxic waters flowing from death through life into something drinkable; it removes the familiar facade of the world and reveals the raw, dormant beauty, which is the essence of its forms.

All things exist as they are perceived; at least in relation to the percipient. 'The mind is its own place, and of itself can make a heaven of hell, a hell of heaven.' But poetry defeats the curse which binds us to be subjected to the accident of surrounding impressions. And whether it spreads its own figured curtain, or withdraws life's dark veil from before the scene of things, it equally creates for us a being within our being. It makes us the inhabitants of a world to which the familiar world is a chaos. It reproduces the common universe of which we are portions and percipients, and it purges from our inward sight the film of familiarity which obscures from us the wonder of our being. It compels us to feel that which we perceive, and to imagine that which we know. It creates anew the universe, after it has been annihilated in our minds by the recurrence of impressions blunted by reiteration. It justifies the bold and true words of Tasso: Non merita nome di creatore, se non Iddio ed il Poeta.

Everything exists as we perceive it, at least in relation to the observer. "The mind is its own place, and can make a heaven out of hell, or a hell out of heaven." But poetry breaks the curse that binds us to be victims of our surrounding impressions. Whether it lays out its own patterned curtain or lifts the dark veil of life from the scene, it creates for us a reality within our reality. It makes us dwell in a world that feels like chaos compared to the familiar one. It reflects the shared universe of which we are parts and observers, and it clears away the haze of familiarity that obscures the wonder of our existence. It forces us to feel what we perceive and to imagine what we know. It recreates the universe after it has been destroyed in our minds by the dulling effect of repetitive impressions. It supports the bold and accurate words of Tasso: Non merita nome di creatore, se non Iddio ed il Poeta.

A poet, as he is the author to others of the highest wisdom, pleasure, virtue and glory, so he ought personally to be the happiest, the best, the wisest, and the most illustrious of men. As to his glory, let time be challenged to declare whether the fame of any other institutor of human life be comparable to that of a poet. That he is the wisest, the happiest, and the best, inasmuch as he is a poet, is equally incontrovertible: the greatest poets have been men of the most spotless virtue, of the most consummate prudence, and, if we would look into the interior of their lives, the most fortunate of men: and the exceptions, as they regard those who possessed the poetic faculty in a high yet inferior degree, will be found on consideration to confine rather than destroy the rule. Let us for a moment stoop to the arbitration of popular breath, and usurping and uniting in our own persons the incompatible characters of accuser, witness, judge, and executioner, let us decide without trial, testimony, or form, that certain motives of those who are 'there sitting where we dare not soar', are reprehensible. Let us assume that Homer was a drunkard, that Virgil was a flatterer, that Horace was a coward, that Tasso a madman, that Lord Bacon was a peculator, that Raphael was a libertine, that Spenser was a poet laureate. It is inconsistent with this division of our subject to cite living poets, but posterity has done ample justice to the great names now referred to. Their errors have been weighed and found to have been dust in the balance; if their sins 'were as scarlet, they are now white as snow'; they have been washed in the blood of the mediator and redeemer, Time. Observe in what a ludicrous chaos the imputation of real or fictitious crime have been confused in the contemporary calumnies against poetry and poets; consider how little is, as it appears—or appears, as it is; look to your own motives, and judge not, lest ye be judged.

A poet, being the source of the highest wisdom, joy, virtue, and glory for others, should be the happiest, best, wisest, and most renowned among all. When it comes to his glory, let time reveal whether the fame of any other creator of human life compares to that of a poet. It's clear that he is the wisest, happiest, and best because he is a poet: the greatest poets have shown the highest virtue, the best judgment, and, if we examine their lives, they were the luckiest people too. Any exceptions among those with less talent in poetry will typically reinforce rather than undermine this idea. Let’s take a moment to consider what public opinion might say, and while taking on the conflicting roles of accuser, witness, judge, and executioner ourselves, let’s declare without evidence that some motives of those who have "reached heights we cannot" are shameful. Let’s assume that Homer was a drunk, Virgil was a flatterer, Horace was a coward, Tasso was insane, Lord Bacon was corrupt, Raphael was a libertine, and Spenser was just a poet laureate. While it's not fitting to bring up living poets here, history has given fair judgment to the notable figures mentioned. Their faults have been weighed and found insignificant; if their sins "were as scarlet, they are now white as snow"; they have been cleansed by the passage of time. Look at the absurd confusion created by accusations of real or imagined wrongdoing in today's criticisms of poetry and poets; understand how little is as it seems—or seems as it is; reflect on your own motives, and don’t judge others, or you might find yourself judged.

Poetry, as has been said, differs in this respect from logic, that it is not subject to the control of the active powers of the mind, and that its birth and recurrence have no necessary connexion with the consciousness or will. It is presumptuous to determine that these are the necessary conditions of all mental causation, when mental effects are experienced unsusceptible of being referred to them. The frequent recurrence of the poetical power, it is obvious to suppose, may produce in the mind a habit of order and harmony correlative with its own nature and its effects upon other minds. But in the intervals of inspiration, and they may be frequent without being durable, a poet becomes a man, and is abandoned to the sudden reflux of the influences under which others habitually live. But as he is more delicately organized than other men, and sensible to pain and pleasure, both his own and that of others, in a degree unknown to them, he will avoid the one and pursue the other with an ardour proportioned to this difference. And he renders himself obnoxious to calumny, when he neglects to observe the circumstances under which these objects of universal pursuit and flight have disguised themselves in one another's garments.

Poetry, as has been mentioned, differs from logic in that it isn't controlled by the active powers of the mind, and its creation and recurrence aren't necessarily linked to awareness or will. It's arrogant to assume that these are the essential conditions for all mental activity when we experience mental effects that can't be traced back to them. It’s reasonable to think that the frequent emergence of poetic ability might create in the mind a habit of order and harmony that aligns with its own nature and its effects on others. However, during times when inspiration is absent—these times may happen often but not last long—a poet becomes just a person and is left to the sudden return of the influences that others typically experience. But since he is more delicately tuned than most, being more attuned to both his own pain and pleasure as well as that of others to a degree they don't experience, he will try to avoid pain and pursue pleasure with an intensity that reflects this difference. And he makes himself vulnerable to criticism when he fails to recognize the circumstances under which these objects of universal desire and fear have disguised themselves in one another's clothes.

But there is nothing necessarily evil in this error, and thus cruelty, envy, revenge, avarice, and the passions purely evil, have never formed any portion of the popular imputations on the lives of poets.

But there’s nothing inherently evil in this mistake, and so cruelty, envy, revenge, greed, and purely evil passions have never been part of the common assumptions about the lives of poets.

I have thought it most favourable to the cause of truth to set down these remarks according to the order in which they were suggested to my mind, by a consideration of the subject itself, instead of observing the formality of a polemical reply; but if the view which they contain be just, they will be found to involve a refutation of the arguers against poetry, so far at least as regards the first division of the subject. I can readily conjecture what should have moved the gall of some learned and intelligent writers who quarrel with certain versifiers; I confess myself, like them, unwilling to be stunned, by the Theseids of the hoarse Codri of the day. Bavius and Maevius undoubtedly are, as they ever were, insufferable persons. But it belongs to a philosophical critic to distinguish rather than confound.

I've found it most beneficial to the truth to write down these remarks in the order they came to me, based on my thoughts about the subject, rather than following the formal structure of a debate. However, if my perspective is correct, it will provide a counterargument to those who oppose poetry, at least regarding the first part of the topic. I can easily understand what might have angered some learned and insightful writers who criticize certain poets; I too, like them, am unwilling to be overwhelmed by the uninspired works of the loud poets of today. Bavius and Maevius are still, as they have always been, unbearable figures. But it is the role of a thoughtful critic to differentiate rather than confuse.

The first part of these remarks has related to poetry in its elements and principles; and it has been shown, as well as the narrow limits assigned them would permit, that what is called poetry, in a restricted sense, has a common source with all other forms of order and of beauty, according to which the materials of human life are susceptible of being arranged, and which is poetry in a universal sense.

The first part of these remarks has focused on poetry, its elements, and principles. It has been demonstrated, as much as the limited scope would allow, that what we refer to as poetry, in a specific sense, shares a common origin with all other forms of order and beauty. This underlying principle shows how the materials of human life can be arranged, embodying poetry in a universal sense.

The second part will have for its object an application of these principles to the present state of the cultivation of poetry, and a defence of the attempt to idealize the modern forms of manners and opinions, and compel them into a subordination to the imaginative and creative faculty. For the literature of England, an energetic development of which has ever preceded or accompanied a great and free development of the national will, has arisen as it were from a new birth. In spite of the low-thoughted envy which would undervalue contemporary merit, our own will be a memorable age in intellectual achievements, and we live among such philosophers and poets as surpass beyond comparison any who have appeared since the last national struggle for civil and religious liberty. The most unfailing herald, companion, and follower of the awakening of a great people to work a beneficial change in opinion or institution, is poetry. At such periods there is an accumulation of the power of communicating and receiving intense and impassioned conceptions respecting man and nature. The persons in whom this power resides may often, as far as regards many portions of their nature, have little apparent correspondence with that spirit of good of which they are the ministers. But even whilst they deny and abjure, they are yet compelled to serve, the power which is seated on the throne of their own soul. It is impossible to read the compositions of the most celebrated writers of the present day without being startled with the electric life which burns within their words. They measure the circumference and sound the depths of human nature with a comprehensive and all-penetrating spirit, and they are themselves perhaps the most sincerely astonished at its manifestations; for it is less their spirit than the spirit of the age. Poets are the hierophants of an unapprehended inspiration; the mirrors of the gigantic shadows which futurity casts upon the present; the words which express what they understand not; the trumpets which sing to battle, and feel not what they inspire; the influence which is moved not, but moves. Poets are the unacknowledged legislators of the world.

The second part will focus on applying these principles to the current state of poetry cultivation and defending the effort to elevate modern manners and opinions, making them subordinate to the imaginative and creative spirit. The literature of England, which has always thrived alongside significant and free expressions of the national will, has emerged as if it were reborn. Despite the petty envy that undervalues contemporary talent, our era will be remembered for its intellectual achievements, and we live among philosophers and poets who far surpass anyone since the last national fight for civil and religious freedom. Poetry is the most reliable herald, companion, and follower of a people awakening to make meaningful changes in thought or institutions. During these times, there is a buildup of the ability to communicate and receive deep and passionate ideas about humanity and nature. Those who possess this ability may often seem disconnected from the spirit of good they embody. Yet even as they deny and reject it, they are compelled to serve the power that rules their own soul. It's impossible to read the works of today’s most celebrated writers without feeling the electric energy that pulses within their words. They explore both the breadth and depth of human nature with a deep and penetrating insight, and they might be just as surprised by its revelations, as it is more a reflection of the spirit of the age than their own. Poets are the interpreters of an unrecognized inspiration; they reflect the massive shadows that the future casts on the present; they articulate what they do not fully understand; they are the trumpets that call to battle, unaware of the emotions they stir; they are the force that doesn't just respond but drives change. Poets are the unacknowledged lawmakers of the world.

THE END








Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!