This is a modern-English version of Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals, originally written by Kant, Immanuel.
It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling,
and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If
you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.
Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.
FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS
By Immanuel Kant
1785
Translated by Thomas Kingsmill Abbott
CONTENTS
TABLE OF CONTENTS
PREFACE
Ancient Greek philosophy was divided into three sciences: physics, ethics, and logic. This division is perfectly suitable to the nature of the thing; and the only improvement that can be made in it is to add the principle on which it is based, so that we may both satisfy ourselves of its completeness, and also be able to determine correctly the necessary subdivisions.
Ancient Greek philosophy was divided into three areas: physics, ethics, and logic. This division fits the nature of the subject well; the only improvement we could make is to include the principle that underlies it, so we can confirm its completeness and accurately identify the necessary subdivisions.
All rational knowledge is either material or formal: the former considers some object, the latter is concerned only with the form of the understanding and of the reason itself, and with the universal laws of thought in general without distinction of its objects. Formal philosophy is called logic. Material philosophy, however, which has to do with determinate objects and the laws to which they are subject, is again twofold; for these laws are either laws of nature or of freedom. The science of the former is physics, that of the latter, ethics; they are also called natural philosophy and moral philosophy respectively.
All rational knowledge is either material or formal: the former looks at some object, while the latter focuses only on the structure of understanding and reasoning itself, as well as the universal laws of thought in general, regardless of the objects involved. Formal philosophy is known as logic. Material philosophy, on the other hand, which deals with specific objects and the laws governing them, is split into two categories; these laws are either laws of nature or laws of freedom. The study of the former is called physics, while the study of the latter is referred to as ethics; they are also known as natural philosophy and moral philosophy, respectively.
Logic cannot have any empirical part; that is, a part in which the universal and necessary laws of thought should rest on grounds taken from experience; otherwise it would not be logic, i.e., a canon for the understanding or the reason, valid for all thought, and capable of demonstration. Natural and moral philosophy, on the contrary, can each have their empirical part, since the former has to determine the laws of nature as an object of experience; the latter the laws of the human will, so far as it is affected by nature: the former, however, being laws according to which everything does happen; the latter, laws according to which everything ought to happen. Ethics, however, must also consider the conditions under which what ought to happen frequently does not.
Logic cannot have any empirical component; that is, it cannot rely on universal and necessary laws of thought based on experience. If it did, it wouldn’t be logic—meaning a standard for understanding or reasoning that applies to all thought and can be demonstrated. In contrast, natural and moral philosophy can have their empirical parts since the former seeks to define the laws of nature as a subject of experience, while the latter explores the laws of human will as influenced by nature. The laws from natural philosophy describe how things actually happen, while those from moral philosophy explain how things should happen. However, ethics must also take into account the circumstances under which what should happen often does not occur.
We may call all philosophy empirical, so far as it is based on grounds of experience: on the other hand, that which delivers its doctrines from a priori principles alone we may call pure philosophy. When the latter is merely formal it is logic; if it is restricted to definite objects of the understanding it is metaphysic.
We can refer to all philosophy as empirical when it relies on experience. Conversely, we can label anything that derives its principles solely from a priori reasoning as pure philosophy. If the latter is purely formal, it's logic; if it's focused on specific concepts understood by the mind, it's metaphysics.
In this way there arises the idea of a twofold metaphysic—a metaphysic of nature and a metaphysic of morals. Physics will thus have an empirical and also a rational part. It is the same with Ethics; but here the empirical part might have the special name of practical anthropology, the name morality being appropriated to the rational part.
In this way, the concept of a twofold metaphysics emerges—a metaphysics of nature and a metaphysics of morals. Physics will therefore have both an empirical and a rational component. The same applies to Ethics; however, in this case, the empirical aspect could specifically be called practical anthropology, with the term morality reserved for the rational component.
All trades, arts, and handiworks have gained by division of labour, namely, when, instead of one man doing everything, each confines himself to a certain kind of work distinct from others in the treatment it requires, so as to be able to perform it with greater facility and in the greatest perfection. Where the different kinds of work are not distinguished and divided, where everyone is a jack-of-all-trades, there manufactures remain still in the greatest barbarism. It might deserve to be considered whether pure philosophy in all its parts does not require a man specially devoted to it, and whether it would not be better for the whole business of science if those who, to please the tastes of the public, are wont to blend the rational and empirical elements together, mixed in all sorts of proportions unknown to themselves, and who call themselves independent thinkers, giving the name of minute philosophers to those who apply themselves to the rational part only- if these, I say, were warned not to carry on two employments together which differ widely in the treatment they demand, for each of which perhaps a special talent is required, and the combination of which in one person only produces bunglers. But I only ask here whether the nature of science does not require that we should always carefully separate the empirical from the rational part, and prefix to Physics proper (or empirical physics) a metaphysic of nature, and to practical anthropology a metaphysic of morals, which must be carefully cleared of everything empirical, so that we may know how much can be accomplished by pure reason in both cases, and from what sources it draws this its a priori teaching, and that whether the latter inquiry is conducted by all moralists (whose name is legion), or only by some who feel a calling thereto.
All trades, arts, and crafts have improved thanks to the division of labor, which means that instead of one person doing everything, each individual focuses on a specific type of work that is different from others in the skills it requires. This specialization allows them to perform their tasks more easily and with the highest quality. When different types of work aren’t distinguished and divided, and everyone tries to do a bit of everything, manufacturing remains primitive. It’s worth considering whether pure philosophy in all its aspects needs someone dedicated solely to it, and if it would benefit science as a whole if those who mix rational and empirical elements—often in random combinations they don’t fully understand—were cautioned against trying to juggle two very different types of work. Each might require a unique talent, and combining them in one person often leads to mediocrity. I just want to highlight whether the nature of science requires us to clearly separate the empirical from the rational part. We need to establish a metaphysics of nature that comes before empirical physics, and a metaphysics of morals that precedes practical anthropology, ensuring that both are free from empirical influences. This way, we can understand what pure reason can achieve in both scenarios and identify the sources of its a priori knowledge, whether that investigation is undertaken by all moralists (and there are many) or just by a few who feel called to this work.
As my concern here is with moral philosophy, I limit the question suggested to this: Whether it is not of the utmost necessity to construct a pure thing which is only empirical and which belongs to anthropology? for that such a philosophy must be possible is evident from the common idea of duty and of the moral laws. Everyone must admit that if a law is to have moral force, i.e., to be the basis of an obligation, it must carry with it absolute necessity; that, for example, the precept, "Thou shalt not lie," is not valid for men alone, as if other rational beings had no need to observe it; and so with all the other moral laws properly so called; that, therefore, the basis of obligation must not be sought in the nature of man, or in the circumstances in the world in which he is placed, but a priori simply in the conception of pure reason; and although any other precept which is founded on principles of mere experience may be in certain respects universal, yet in as far as it rests even in the least degree on an empirical basis, perhaps only as to a motive, such a precept, while it may be a practical rule, can never be called a moral law.
Since my focus here is on moral philosophy, I limit the question raised to this: Is it not absolutely essential to create a concept that is purely empirical and related to anthropology? For the possibility of such a philosophy is clear from the general idea of duty and moral laws. Everyone must agree that if a law is to have moral authority, meaning it serves as the foundation for an obligation, it must hold absolute necessity; that, for instance, the command, "You shall not lie," is not valid only for humans, as if other rational beings were exempt from it; and the same goes for all other genuine moral laws. Therefore, the basis of obligation should not be found in human nature or in the specific circumstances of the world in which one lives, but rather a priori in the concept of pure reason. Although any other rule based on mere experience might be universal in some respects, to the extent that it relies, even slightly, on an empirical basis—perhaps only as a motive—such a rule, while it may serve as a practical guideline, can never be considered a moral law.
Thus not only are moral laws with their principles essentially distinguished from every other kind of practical knowledge in which there is anything empirical, but all moral philosophy rests wholly on its pure part. When applied to man, it does not borrow the least thing from the knowledge of man himself (anthropology), but gives laws a priori to him as a rational being. No doubt these laws require a judgement sharpened by experience, in order on the one hand to distinguish in what cases they are applicable, and on the other to procure for them access to the will of the man and effectual influence on conduct; since man is acted on by so many inclinations that, though capable of the idea of a practical pure reason, he is not so easily able to make it effective in concreto in his life.
Moral laws and their principles are fundamentally different from other types of practical knowledge that involve any empirical evidence. All moral philosophy is based entirely on its pure aspect. When it comes to humans, it doesn't take anything from our understanding of humanity (anthropology) but provides laws a priori that apply to us as rational beings. These laws definitely need a judgment informed by experience to determine when they are applicable and to ensure they influence a person's will and behavior effectively. This is because people are driven by many inclinations, making it difficult for them to apply the concept of pure practical reason in their everyday lives.
A metaphysic of morals is therefore indispensably necessary, not merely for speculative reasons, in order to investigate the sources of the practical principles which are to be found a priori in our reason, but also because morals themselves are liable to all sorts of corruption, as long as we are without that clue and supreme canon by which to estimate them correctly. For in order that an action should be morally good, it is not enough that it conform to the moral law, but it must also be done for the sake of the law, otherwise that conformity is only very contingent and uncertain; since a principle which is not moral, although it may now and then produce actions conformable to the law, will also often produce actions which contradict it. Now it is only in a pure philosophy that we can look for the moral law in its purity and genuineness (and, in a practical matter, this is of the utmost consequence): we must, therefore, begin with pure philosophy (metaphysic), and without it there cannot be any moral philosophy at all. That which mingles these pure principles with the empirical does not deserve the name of philosophy (for what distinguishes philosophy from common rational knowledge is that it treats in separate sciences what the latter only comprehends confusedly); much less does it deserve that of moral philosophy, since by this confusion it even spoils the purity of morals themselves, and counteracts its own end.
A metaphysics of morals is absolutely essential, not just for theoretical reasons to explore the sources of the practical principles that exist a priori in our reasoning, but also because morals can be easily corrupted without a guiding principle and a definitive standard to assess them accurately. For an action to be morally good, it’s not enough for it to align with the moral law; it must also be performed for the sake of the law itself. Otherwise, that alignment is merely coincidental and uncertain, since a principle that isn't moral might sometimes lead to actions that adhere to the law, but will also frequently result in actions that go against it. We can only find the moral law in its true and authentic form through pure philosophy (metaphysics), which is crucial for practical matters. Thus, we must start with pure philosophy, as there can be no moral philosophy without it. Anything that mixes these pure principles with empirical elements does not deserve to be called philosophy (since what sets philosophy apart from common rational thought is its focus on distinct sciences, whereas the latter sees things in a muddled way); even less does it merit the title of moral philosophy, as this confusion tarnishes the purity of morals themselves and defeats its own purpose.
Let it not be thought, however, that what is here demanded is already extant in the propaedeutic prefixed by the celebrated Wolf to his moral philosophy, namely, his so-called general practical philosophy, and that, therefore, we have not to strike into an entirely new field. Just because it was to be a general practical philosophy, it has not taken into consideration a will of any particular kind- say one which should be determined solely from a priori principles without any empirical motives, and which we might call a pure will, but volition in general, with all the actions and conditions which belong to it in this general signification. By this it is distinguished from a metaphysic of morals, just as general logic, which treats of the acts and canons of thought in general, is distinguished from transcendental philosophy, which treats of the particular acts and canons of pure thought, i.e., that whose cognitions are altogether a priori. For the metaphysic of morals has to examine the idea and the principles of a possible pure will, and not the acts and conditions of human volition generally, which for the most part are drawn from psychology. It is true that moral laws and duty are spoken of in the general moral philosophy (contrary indeed to all fitness). But this is no objection, for in this respect also the authors of that science remain true to their idea of it; they do not distinguish the motives which are prescribed as such by reason alone altogether a priori, and which are properly moral, from the empirical motives which the understanding raises to general conceptions merely by comparison of experiences; but, without noticing the difference of their sources, and looking on them all as homogeneous, they consider only their greater or less amount. It is in this way they frame their notion of obligation, which, though anything but moral, is all that can be attained in a philosophy which passes no judgement at all on the origin of all possible practical concepts, whether they are a priori, or only a posteriori.
However, it shouldn’t be assumed that what is being asked for is already present in the introductory section added by the renowned Wolf to his moral philosophy, specifically his so-called general practical philosophy, and therefore, we don’t need to venture into entirely new territory. Just because it aims to be a general practical philosophy, it hasn’t considered a will of a specific type—one that would be determined solely by a priori principles without any empirical motives, which we might refer to as a pure will. Instead, it addresses volition in general, along with all the actions and conditions associated with it in this broader sense. This distinguishes it from a metaphysics of morals, just as general logic, which deals with the acts and rules of thought in general, is distinct from transcendental philosophy, which focuses on the specific acts and rules of pure thought, meaning that whose knowledge is entirely a priori. The metaphysics of morals is required to explore the idea and principles of a potential pure will, rather than the acts and conditions of human volition in general, which are mostly drawn from psychology. It’s true that moral laws and duties are mentioned in general moral philosophy (although this is completely inappropriate). But this is not a problem, as in this respect, the authors of that discipline stick to their original concept; they do not differentiate between the motives that are prescribed solely by reason a priori, which are truly moral, and the empirical motives that the understanding raises to general concepts merely by comparing experiences. Instead, without recognizing the difference in their origins and viewing them all as the same, they only consider their varying degrees. This is how they construct their idea of obligation, which, while far from moral, is all that can be achieved in a philosophy that makes no judgments regarding the source of all possible practical concepts, whether they are a priori or only a posteriori.
Intending to publish hereafter a metaphysic of morals, I issue in the first instance these fundamental principles. Indeed there is properly no other foundation for it than the critical examination of a pure practical reason; just as that of metaphysics is the critical examination of the pure speculative reason, already published. But in the first place the former is not so absolutely necessary as the latter, because in moral concerns human reason can easily be brought to a high degree of correctness and completeness, even in the commonest understanding, while on the contrary in its theoretic but pure use it is wholly dialectical; and in the second place if the critique of a pure practical Reason is to be complete, it must be possible at the same time to show its identity with the speculative reason in a common principle, for it can ultimately be only one and the same reason which has to be distinguished merely in its application. I could not, however, bring it to such completeness here, without introducing considerations of a wholly different kind, which would be perplexing to the reader. On this account I have adopted the title of Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals instead of that of a Critical Examination of the pure practical reason.
Planning to publish a metaphysics of morals in the future, I am presenting these fundamental principles first. In fact, there is really no other basis for it than the critical examination of pure practical reason; just as the basis of metaphysics is the critical examination of pure speculative reason, which has already been published. However, the former is not as absolutely essential as the latter because, in moral matters, human reason can easily achieve a high degree of accuracy and completeness, even in the most basic understanding, while in its theoretical yet pure use, it is entirely dialectical. Additionally, if the critique of pure practical reason is to be thorough, it must also be possible to demonstrate its connection to speculative reason through a common principle, as ultimately it can only be one and the same reason that needs to be distinguished only by its application. However, I could not achieve such thoroughness here without introducing ideas of a completely different nature, which would confuse the reader. Therefore, I have chosen the title Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Morals instead of a Critical Examination of Pure Practical Reason.
But in the third place, since a metaphysic of morals, in spite of the discouraging title, is yet capable of being presented in popular form, and one adapted to the common understanding, I find it useful to separate from it this preliminary treatise on its fundamental principles, in order that I may not hereafter have need to introduce these necessarily subtle discussions into a book of a more simple character.
But thirdly, since a metaphysics of ethics, despite its off-putting title, can still be presented in a way that's accessible and suitable for general understanding, I believe it's helpful to separate this introductory piece on its basic principles. This way, I won't have to include these complex discussions later in a simpler book.
The present treatise is, however, nothing more than the investigation and establishment of the supreme principle of morality, and this alone constitutes a study complete in itself and one which ought to be kept apart from every other moral investigation. No doubt my conclusions on this weighty question, which has hitherto been very unsatisfactorily examined, would receive much light from the application of the same principle to the whole system, and would be greatly confirmed by the adequacy which it exhibits throughout; but I must forego this advantage, which indeed would be after all more gratifying than useful, since the easy applicability of a principle and its apparent adequacy give no very certain proof of its soundness, but rather inspire a certain partiality, which prevents us from examining and estimating it strictly in itself and without regard to consequences.
This current work is basically an examination and establishment of the ultimate principle of morality, and that alone makes it a complete study that should be kept separate from any other moral inquiry. Without a doubt, my conclusions on this important issue, which has so far been inadequately explored, would gain a lot of clarity from applying the same principle to the entire system, and would be significantly supported by the consistency it shows throughout; however, I must forgo this benefit, which would ultimately be more satisfying than useful, since the straightforward application of a principle and its seemingly adequate performance do not provide any strong proof of its validity. Instead, they tend to create a bias that prevents us from thoroughly examining and assessing it on its own, without considering the outcomes.
I have adopted in this work the method which I think most suitable, proceeding analytically from common knowledge to the determination of its ultimate principle, and again descending synthetically from the examination of this principle and its sources to the common knowledge in which we find it employed. The division will, therefore, be as follows:
I have used a method in this work that I believe is the most appropriate, starting from common knowledge to determine its ultimate principle, and then moving back down from the examination of this principle and its sources to the common knowledge where we see it applied. The division will, therefore, be as follows:
1 FIRST SECTION. Transition from the common rational knowledge of morality to the philosophical.
1 FIRST SECTION. Transition from general understanding of morality to philosophical insights.
2 SECOND SECTION. Transition from popular moral philosophy to the metaphysic of morals.
2 SECOND SECTION. Transition from popular moral philosophy to the metaphysics of morals.
3 THIRD SECTION. Final step from the metaphysic of morals to the critique of the pure practical reason.
3 THIRD SECTION. Final step from the metaphysics of morals to the critique of pure practical reason.
FIRST SECTION—TRANSITION FROM THE COMMON RATIONAL KNOWLEDGE OF MORALITY TO THE PHILOSOPHICAL
Nothing can possibly be conceived in the world, or even out of it, which can be called good, without qualification, except a good will. Intelligence, wit, judgement, and the other talents of the mind, however they may be named, or courage, resolution, perseverance, as qualities of temperament, are undoubtedly good and desirable in many respects; but these gifts of nature may also become extremely bad and mischievous if the will which is to make use of them, and which, therefore, constitutes what is called character, is not good. It is the same with the gifts of fortune. Power, riches, honour, even health, and the general well-being and contentment with one's condition which is called happiness, inspire pride, and often presumption, if there is not a good will to correct the influence of these on the mind, and with this also to rectify the whole principle of acting and adapt it to its end. The sight of a being who is not adorned with a single feature of a pure and good will, enjoying unbroken prosperity, can never give pleasure to an impartial rational spectator. Thus a good will appears to constitute the indispensable condition even of being worthy of happiness.
Nothing in the world, or even beyond it, can be considered truly good without exception except for a good will. Intelligence, wit, judgment, and other mental talents—whatever you call them—along with qualities like courage, determination, and perseverance, are certainly good and desirable in many ways. However, these natural gifts can also turn out to be very harmful and negative if the will that guides their use, which is what we refer to as character, is not good. The same goes for gifts from fortune. Power, wealth, honor, even health, and the general happiness that comes from being content with one’s situation, can lead to pride and often arrogance if there isn’t a good will to balance their influence on the mind, and to also realign the entire principle of action to suit its purpose. Seeing someone without a trace of pure and good will enjoying continuous success can never be pleasing to an unbiased rational observer. Therefore, a good will seems to be essential for even deserving happiness.
There are even some qualities which are of service to this good will itself and may facilitate its action, yet which have no intrinsic unconditional value, but always presuppose a good will, and this qualifies the esteem that we justly have for them and does not permit us to regard them as absolutely good. Moderation in the affections and passions, self-control, and calm deliberation are not only good in many respects, but even seem to constitute part of the intrinsic worth of the person; but they are far from deserving to be called good without qualification, although they have been so unconditionally praised by the ancients. For without the principles of a good will, they may become extremely bad, and the coolness of a villain not only makes him far more dangerous, but also directly makes him more abominable in our eyes than he would have been without it.
There are even some qualities that benefit good will itself and can help it function, yet these qualities don’t have any absolute value and always depend on good will. This affects how much we respect them and prevents us from seeing them as purely good. Moderation in emotions and desires, self-control, and thoughtful decision-making are not just good in many ways, but they also seem to be part of a person's true worth. However, they definitely shouldn't be called good without qualification, even though the ancients praised them without reservation. Without the foundation of good will, they can become very harmful, and a villain’s calmness not only makes him much more dangerous but also makes him seem even more contemptible to us than he would without it.
A good will is good not because of what it performs or effects, not by its aptness for the attainment of some proposed end, but simply by virtue of the volition; that is, it is good in itself, and considered by itself is to be esteemed much higher than all that can be brought about by it in favour of any inclination, nay even of the sum total of all inclinations. Even if it should happen that, owing to special disfavour of fortune, or the niggardly provision of a step-motherly nature, this will should wholly lack power to accomplish its purpose, if with its greatest efforts it should yet achieve nothing, and there should remain only the good will (not, to be sure, a mere wish, but the summoning of all means in our power), then, like a jewel, it would still shine by its own light, as a thing which has its whole value in itself. Its usefulness or fruitlessness can neither add nor take away anything from this value. It would be, as it were, only the setting to enable us to handle it the more conveniently in common commerce, or to attract to it the attention of those who are not yet connoisseurs, but not to recommend it to true connoisseurs, or to determine its value.
A good will is valuable not because of what it does or achieves, not because it's suited for reaching some specific goal, but simply because of the intention behind it; that is, it is good in and of itself, and when considered on its own, it is valued much more highly than anything it could accomplish for any desire, or even for all desires combined. Even if, due to bad luck or a selfish nature, this will completely lacks the ability to fulfill its goal, if it puts forth its best effort yet still achieves nothing, and only the good will remains (not just a wish, but the active effort to use all resources available), then, like a jewel, it would still shine with its own light, as something that holds its entire value within itself. Its usefulness or lack of results can neither add nor detract from this value. It would merely serve as a setting to help us handle it more conveniently in everyday transactions or to attract the attention of those who may not be experts, but it wouldn’t change how true connoisseurs perceive its value.
There is, however, something so strange in this idea of the absolute value of the mere will, in which no account is taken of its utility, that notwithstanding the thorough assent of even common reason to the idea, yet a suspicion must arise that it may perhaps really be the product of mere high-flown fancy, and that we may have misunderstood the purpose of nature in assigning reason as the governor of our will. Therefore we will examine this idea from this point of view.
There’s something really odd about the idea of the absolute value of will alone, without considering its usefulness. Even though common sense generally agrees with this idea, we can't help but wonder if it’s just a product of overblown imagination and that we might have misunderstood nature's intention in giving reason the role of guiding our will. So, let’s take a closer look at this idea from that perspective.
In the physical constitution of an organized being, that is, a being adapted suitably to the purposes of life, we assume it as a fundamental principle that no organ for any purpose will be found but what is also the fittest and best adapted for that purpose. Now in a being which has reason and a will, if the proper object of nature were its conservation, its welfare, in a word, its happiness, then nature would have hit upon a very bad arrangement in selecting the reason of the creature to carry out this purpose. For all the actions which the creature has to perform with a view to this purpose, and the whole rule of its conduct, would be far more surely prescribed to it by instinct, and that end would have been attained thereby much more certainly than it ever can be by reason. Should reason have been communicated to this favoured creature over and above, it must only have served it to contemplate the happy constitution of its nature, to admire it, to congratulate itself thereon, and to feel thankful for it to the beneficent cause, but not that it should subject its desires to that weak and delusive guidance and meddle bunglingly with the purpose of nature. In a word, nature would have taken care that reason should not break forth into practical exercise, nor have the presumption, with its weak insight, to think out for itself the plan of happiness, and of the means of attaining it. Nature would not only have taken on herself the choice of the ends, but also of the means, and with wise foresight would have entrusted both to instinct.
In the physical makeup of an organized being, meaning a being properly suited for life’s purposes, we take it as a basic principle that no organ exists for any reason that isn't also the most effective and well-adapted for that reason. Now, in a being that has reason and will, if the main goal of nature were its preservation, its well-being, or simply its happiness, then nature would have made a poor choice by giving the creature reason to fulfill this goal. All actions the creature needs to take for this purpose, and its overall behavior, would definitely be more effectively guided by instinct, and that goal would be achieved much more reliably this way than through reason. If reason were granted to this favored creature, it should have only allowed it to appreciate the wonderful design of its own nature, to admire it, to take pride in it, and to be grateful to the benevolent source for it, rather than to constrain its desires with that weak and misleading guidance and interfere awkwardly with nature's purpose. In summary, nature would have ensured that reason wouldn’t step into practical action or presume, with its limited understanding, to determine the plan for happiness and how to achieve it. Nature would not only have chosen the ends but also the means, and wisely entrusted both to instinct.
And, in fact, we find that the more a cultivated reason applies itself with deliberate purpose to the enjoyment of life and happiness, so much the more does the man fail of true satisfaction. And from this circumstance there arises in many, if they are candid enough to confess it, a certain degree of misology, that is, hatred of reason, especially in the case of those who are most experienced in the use of it, because after calculating all the advantages they derive, I do not say from the invention of all the arts of common luxury, but even from the sciences (which seem to them to be after all only a luxury of the understanding), they find that they have, in fact, only brought more trouble on their shoulders, rather than gained in happiness; and they end by envying, rather than despising, the more common stamp of men who keep closer to the guidance of mere instinct and do not allow their reason much influence on their conduct. And this we must admit, that the judgement of those who would very much lower the lofty eulogies of the advantages which reason gives us in regard to the happiness and satisfaction of life, or who would even reduce them below zero, is by no means morose or ungrateful to the goodness with which the world is governed, but that there lies at the root of these judgements the idea that our existence has a different and far nobler end, for which, and not for happiness, reason is properly intended, and which must, therefore, be regarded as the supreme condition to which the private ends of man must, for the most part, be postponed.
And, in fact, we find that the more a cultivated mind deliberately focuses on enjoying life and finding happiness, the less true satisfaction a person actually feels. Because of this, many people, if they’re honest about it, develop a certain degree of misology, or hatred of reason, especially those who are most skilled in using it. After weighing all the benefits they receive—not just from the creation of simple luxuries, but even from sciences (which they see as just a luxury of the intellect)—they realize they’ve only taken on more burdens instead of gaining happiness. They end up envying, rather than looking down on, the more ordinary people who rely mostly on instinct and let their reason have little influence over their actions. We must acknowledge that those who significantly downplay the high praises of the benefits reason brings to happiness and life satisfaction—or even argue that those benefits are nonexistent—aren’t being bitter or ungrateful for the goodness with which our world is governed. Instead, underlying these thoughts is the belief that our existence has a different and far greater purpose, for which reason is truly intended, and that this purpose must generally take precedence over individual human goals for happiness.
For as reason is not competent to guide the will with certainty in regard to its objects and the satisfaction of all our wants (which it to some extent even multiplies), this being an end to which an implanted instinct would have led with much greater certainty; and since, nevertheless, reason is imparted to us as a practical faculty, i.e., as one which is to have influence on the will, therefore, admitting that nature generally in the distribution of her capacities has adapted the means to the end, its true destination must be to produce a will, not merely good as a means to something else, but good in itself, for which reason was absolutely necessary. This will then, though not indeed the sole and complete good, must be the supreme good and the condition of every other, even of the desire of happiness. Under these circumstances, there is nothing inconsistent with the wisdom of nature in the fact that the cultivation of the reason, which is requisite for the first and unconditional purpose, does in many ways interfere, at least in this life, with the attainment of the second, which is always conditional, namely, happiness. Nay, it may even reduce it to nothing, without nature thereby failing of her purpose. For reason recognizes the establishment of a good will as its highest practical destination, and in attaining this purpose is capable only of a satisfaction of its own proper kind, namely that from the attainment of an end, which end again is determined by reason only, notwithstanding that this may involve many a disappointment to the ends of inclination.
Since reason isn't always capable of guiding our will clearly regarding what we want and fulfilling all our desires (which it can actually complicate), an instinct would have led us to our goals with much more certainty. However, because reason is given to us as a practical tool meant to influence our will, we can assume that nature has generally arranged its capacities to fit its purposes. Therefore, its true aim must be to create a will that is not just good as a means to an end but good in itself, which is why reason is absolutely necessary. This will, while not the only ultimate good, must be considered the highest good and the foundation of everything else, including the desire for happiness. In this context, there's nothing contradictory about nature's wisdom in the fact that developing reason, which is essential for the primary and unconditional aim, often interferes with achieving the secondary, conditional aim of happiness, at least in this life. In fact, it may even nullify happiness without nature missing its goal. Reason views the establishment of a good will as its highest practical aim, and achieving this goal yields only a specific kind of satisfaction from reaching an end, which is determined solely by reason, even if this can lead to disappointment in fulfilling other desires.
We have then to develop the notion of a will which deserves to be highly esteemed for itself and is good without a view to anything further, a notion which exists already in the sound natural understanding, requiring rather to be cleared up than to be taught, and which in estimating the value of our actions always takes the first place and constitutes the condition of all the rest. In order to do this, we will take the notion of duty, which includes that of a good will, although implying certain subjective restrictions and hindrances. These, however, far from concealing it, or rendering it unrecognizable, rather bring it out by contrast and make it shine forth so much the brighter.
We need to develop the idea of a will that is worthy of high regard for its own sake and is inherently good without any ulterior motives. This idea already exists in our basic understanding and needs to be clarified rather than taught. When we evaluate the worth of our actions, this notion takes priority and serves as the foundation for everything else. To do this, we will consider the idea of duty, which includes the notion of a good will, even though it comes with certain subjective limitations and obstacles. However, these do not hide or obscure the good will; instead, they highlight it by contrast, making it stand out even more.
I omit here all actions which are already recognized as inconsistent with duty, although they may be useful for this or that purpose, for with these the question whether they are done from duty cannot arise at all, since they even conflict with it. I also set aside those actions which really conform to duty, but to which men have no direct inclination, performing them because they are impelled thereto by some other inclination. For in this case we can readily distinguish whether the action which agrees with duty is done from duty, or from a selfish view. It is much harder to make this distinction when the action accords with duty and the subject has besides a direct inclination to it. For example, it is always a matter of duty that a dealer should not over charge an inexperienced purchaser; and wherever there is much commerce the prudent tradesman does not overcharge, but keeps a fixed price for everyone, so that a child buys of him as well as any other. Men are thus honestly served; but this is not enough to make us believe that the tradesman has so acted from duty and from principles of honesty: his own advantage required it; it is out of the question in this case to suppose that he might besides have a direct inclination in favour of the buyers, so that, as it were, from love he should give no advantage to one over another. Accordingly the action was done neither from duty nor from direct inclination, but merely with a selfish view.
I leave out actions that are clearly contrary to duty, even if they might be useful for one reason or another, because in these cases, the question of whether they are performed out of duty doesn’t apply at all, as they conflict with it. I also exclude those actions that do align with duty but which people perform not because they want to, but because they are motivated by some other desire. In this situation, we can easily tell whether the action that aligns with duty is done out of duty or for selfish reasons. It becomes much more difficult to make this distinction when the action is in line with duty and the person also genuinely wants to do it. For instance, it’s always a matter of duty for a seller not to overcharge an inexperienced buyer; and in places with a lot of commerce, a sensible seller keeps a consistent price for everyone, so that a child pays the same amount as anyone else. People are honestly served this way, but that’s not enough to conclude that the seller acted out of duty and honesty; he was motivated by his own benefit. In this scenario, it’s unrealistic to think he could also have a direct inclination to help the buyers, as if out of kindness he’s giving no one an advantage over another. Thus, the action was done neither from duty nor from genuine desire, but simply out of selfish motives.
On the other hand, it is a duty to maintain one's life; and, in addition, everyone has also a direct inclination to do so. But on this account the often anxious care which most men take for it has no intrinsic worth, and their maxim has no moral import. They preserve their life as duty requires, no doubt, but not because duty requires. On the other hand, if adversity and hopeless sorrow have completely taken away the relish for life; if the unfortunate one, strong in mind, indignant at his fate rather than desponding or dejected, wishes for death, and yet preserves his life without loving it- not from inclination or fear, but from duty- then his maxim has a moral worth.
On the other hand, it's our responsibility to keep ourselves alive, and everyone naturally feels drawn to do so. However, the anxious worry that most people put into this has no real value, and their reasoning lacks moral significance. They indeed keep their lives because it's their duty, but not out of a sense of duty. Conversely, if someone faces hardship and overwhelming sorrow that completely dampens their enjoyment of life; if this person, mentally strong and angry at their circumstances rather than defeated or downcast, wishes for death yet continues to live without any love for life—not out of desire or fear, but because it's what they feel obligated to do—then their reasoning holds moral value.
To be beneficent when we can is a duty; and besides this, there are many minds so sympathetically constituted that, without any other motive of vanity or self-interest, they find a pleasure in spreading joy around them and can take delight in the satisfaction of others so far as it is their own work. But I maintain that in such a case an action of this kind, however proper, however amiable it may be, has nevertheless no true moral worth, but is on a level with other inclinations, e.g., the inclination to honour, which, if it is happily directed to that which is in fact of public utility and accordant with duty and consequently honourable, deserves praise and encouragement, but not esteem. For the maxim lacks the moral import, namely, that such actions be done from duty, not from inclination. Put the case that the mind of that philanthropist were clouded by sorrow of his own, extinguishing all sympathy with the lot of others, and that, while he still has the power to benefit others in distress, he is not touched by their trouble because he is absorbed with his own; and now suppose that he tears himself out of this dead insensibility, and performs the action without any inclination to it, but simply from duty, then first has his action its genuine moral worth. Further still; if nature has put little sympathy in the heart of this or that man; if he, supposed to be an upright man, is by temperament cold and indifferent to the sufferings of others, perhaps because in respect of his own he is provided with the special gift of patience and fortitude and supposes, or even requires, that others should have the same- and such a man would certainly not be the meanest product of nature- but if nature had not specially framed him for a philanthropist, would he not still find in himself a source from whence to give himself a far higher worth than that of a good-natured temperament could be? Unquestionably. It is just in this that the moral worth of the character is brought out which is incomparably the highest of all, namely, that he is beneficent, not from inclination, but from duty.
Being kind when we can is our responsibility; additionally, there are many people who are naturally empathetic, and without any selfish motives, they genuinely enjoy spreading happiness and take pleasure in the satisfaction of others as a result of their efforts. However, I argue that even in such cases, this kind of action, no matter how appropriate or kind it may be, lacks true moral value and is comparable to other inclinations, like the desire for honor. If that desire is positively directed toward something that is genuinely beneficial to the public and aligns with our responsibilities, it merits praise and support, but not respect. The principle is missing a moral dimension, which is that such actions should be taken out of duty, not mere inclination. Imagine if that philanthropist were overwhelmed with his own sorrow, blocking out any empathy for others' suffering, yet still had the ability to help those in need. If he pulls himself from this state of apathy and acts solely out of duty, without any personal inclination to do so, then his action holds genuine moral value. Furthermore, if nature has endowed a certain person with little empathy, and he is, by disposition, cool and indifferent to the pain of others—perhaps because he possesses remarkable patience and resilience regarding his own struggles, and believes that others should share the same qualities—such a person wouldn’t necessarily be the worst creation of nature. However, if nature didn’t specifically design him to be a philanthropist, wouldn’t he still discover within himself a deeper source of worth that surpasses that of simply being good-natured? Absolutely. This is where the moral value of character shines through, which is ultimately the highest of all: that he acts generously, not out of inclination, but out of duty.
To secure one's own happiness is a duty, at least indirectly; for discontent with one's condition, under a pressure of many anxieties and amidst unsatisfied wants, might easily become a great temptation to transgression of duty. But here again, without looking to duty, all men have already the strongest and most intimate inclination to happiness, because it is just in this idea that all inclinations are combined in one total. But the precept of happiness is often of such a sort that it greatly interferes with some inclinations, and yet a man cannot form any definite and certain conception of the sum of satisfaction of all of them which is called happiness. It is not then to be wondered at that a single inclination, definite both as to what it promises and as to the time within which it can be gratified, is often able to overcome such a fluctuating idea, and that a gouty patient, for instance, can choose to enjoy what he likes, and to suffer what he may, since, according to his calculation, on this occasion at least, he has not sacrificed the enjoyment of the present moment to a possibly mistaken expectation of a happiness which is supposed to be found in health. But even in this case, if the general desire for happiness did not influence his will, and supposing that in his particular case health was not a necessary element in this calculation, there yet remains in this, as in all other cases, this law, namely, that he should promote his happiness not from inclination but from duty, and by this would his conduct first acquire true moral worth.
Securing your own happiness is a responsibility, even if it's indirect; being unhappy with your situation, loaded with worries and unfulfilled desires, can easily lead to a temptation to neglect your duties. But again, without focusing on duty, everyone already has a strong and deep desire for happiness, as all desires come together in this single idea. However, the idea of happiness often clashes with certain desires, and it's hard for someone to have a clear understanding of what all their satisfaction, summed up as happiness, actually is. It's no surprise that a specific desire, clear about what it offers and when it can be fulfilled, can often overshadow such a vague concept. For example, a person suffering from gout might choose to indulge in what they enjoy and endure the pain, believing that, at least in that moment, they haven’t sacrificed their present enjoyment for an uncertain expectation of happiness linked to good health. Yet, even in this scenario, if the overall desire for happiness didn't guide their choices, and assuming that, in their case, health wasn't crucial to their happiness, there still exists a principle that they should seek their happiness not out of personal desire but from a sense of duty. By doing this, their actions would gain true moral value.
It is in this manner, undoubtedly, that we are to understand those passages of Scripture also in which we are commanded to love our neighbour, even our enemy. For love, as an affection, cannot be commanded, but beneficence for duty's sake may; even though we are not impelled to it by any inclination- nay, are even repelled by a natural and unconquerable aversion. This is practical love and not pathological- a love which is seated in the will, and not in the propensions of sense- in principles of action and not of tender sympathy; and it is this love alone which can be commanded.
It is in this way, for sure, that we should understand those passages in the Bible that tell us to love our neighbor, even our enemy. Love, as a feeling, can’t be commanded, but doing good for the sake of duty can be; even if we aren't driven to it by any desire—indeed, we might even feel a strong, unshakeable dislike. This is practical love and not emotional—it's a love that comes from the will, not from feelings; based on principles of action rather than just tender emotions; and it's this kind of love that can truly be commanded.
The second proposition is: That an action done from duty derives its moral worth, not from the purpose which is to be attained by it, but from the maxim by which it is determined, and therefore does not depend on the realization of the object of the action, but merely on the principle of volition by which the action has taken place, without regard to any object of desire. It is clear from what precedes that the purposes which we may have in view in our actions, or their effects regarded as ends and springs of the will, cannot give to actions any unconditional or moral worth. In what, then, can their worth lie, if it is not to consist in the will and in reference to its expected effect? It cannot lie anywhere but in the principle of the will without regard to the ends which can be attained by the action. For the will stands between its a priori principle, which is formal, and its a posteriori spring, which is material, as between two roads, and as it must be determined by something, it follows that it must be determined by the formal principle of volition when an action is done from duty, in which case every material principle has been withdrawn from it.
The second proposition is that an action motivated by duty gains its moral value not from the outcome it aims to achieve but from the principle guiding it. This means that the worth of an action doesn't depend on the successful realization of its objective, but simply on the intention behind the action, without considering any personal desires. It’s clear from what has been said earlier that the goals we pursue in our actions, or their outcomes viewed as purposes driving our will, cannot bestow any unconditional or moral worth on those actions. So, where does their worth come from if it isn't linked to the will or its anticipated effects? It must come solely from the will's principle, independent of the goals that can be achieved through the action. The will sits between its formal principle, which is a priori, and its material motivation, which is a posteriori, like two paths. Since it must be determined by something, it follows that it should be guided by the formal principle of intention when acting out of duty, in which case all material principles are set aside.
The third proposition, which is a consequence of the two preceding, I would express thus: Duty is the necessity of acting from respect for the law. I may have inclination for an object as the effect of my proposed action, but I cannot have respect for it, just for this reason, that it is an effect and not an energy of will. Similarly I cannot have respect for inclination, whether my own or another's; I can at most, if my own, approve it; if another's, sometimes even love it; i.e., look on it as favourable to my own interest. It is only what is connected with my will as a principle, by no means as an effect- what does not subserve my inclination, but overpowers it, or at least in case of choice excludes it from its calculation- in other words, simply the law of itself, which can be an object of respect, and hence a command. Now an action done from duty must wholly exclude the influence of inclination and with it every object of the will, so that nothing remains which can determine the will except objectively the law, and subjectively pure respect for this practical law, and consequently the maxim * that I should follow this law even to the thwarting of all my inclinations.
The third proposition, which follows from the two before it, can be stated this way: Duty is the requirement to act out of respect for the law. I might have a desire for something because of the outcome of my planned action, but I can’t respect it for that reason, since it’s an outcome and not a willful action. Similarly, I can’t respect desires, whether they are my own or someone else's; I can at most approve of my own desire, and with someone else's, I might even love it, meaning I see it as beneficial to my own interests. Only what is connected to my will as a principle—not as an outcome—what doesn’t serve my desires, but instead takes precedence over them, or at least excludes them in the case of making a choice— in other words, just the law itself—can be respected and thus can command me. Therefore, an action done out of duty must completely eliminate the influence of desire and any objective of the will, so that nothing is left to determine my will except the law itself, and a pure respect for this practical law, and therefore the principle that I should adhere to this law even if it means going against all my desires.
* A maxim is the subjective principle of volition. The objective principle (i.e., that which would also serve subjectively as a practical principle to all rational beings if reason had full power over the faculty of desire) is the practical law.
* A maxim is a personal guideline for making choices. The objective principle (that which would also work as a practical principle for all rational beings if reason had complete control over desire) is the practical law.
Thus the moral worth of an action does not lie in the effect expected from it, nor in any principle of action which requires to borrow its motive from this expected effect. For all these effects- agreeableness of one's condition and even the promotion of the happiness of others- could have been also brought about by other causes, so that for this there would have been no need of the will of a rational being; whereas it is in this alone that the supreme and unconditional good can be found. The pre-eminent good which we call moral can therefore consist in nothing else than the conception of law in itself, which certainly is only possible in a rational being, in so far as this conception, and not the expected effect, determines the will. This is a good which is already present in the person who acts accordingly, and we have not to wait for it to appear first in the result. *
The moral value of an action doesn’t come from the outcome we expect from it, nor from any principle of action that needs to rely on this expected outcome for its motivation. All these outcomes—like improving one’s situation or even contributing to the happiness of others—could have been achieved through other means, so there’s no requirement for the will of a rational being in that case. Rather, the ultimate and unconditional good can only be found in the rational will itself. The highest form of good, which we call moral, can only come from the understanding of law in itself, which is possible only in a rational being, where this understanding, not the expected outcome, drives the will. This is a good that already exists in the person acting in this way, and we don’t need to wait for it to show up in the results.
* It might be here objected to me that I take refuge behind the word respect in an obscure feeling, instead of giving a distinct solution of the question by a concept of the reason. But although respect is a feeling, it is not a feeling received through influence, but is self-wrought by a rational concept, and, therefore, is specifically distinct from all feelings of the former kind, which may be referred either to inclination or fear, What I recognise immediately as a law for me, I recognise with respect. This merely signifies the consciousness that my will is subordinate to a law, without the intervention of other influences on my sense. The immediate determination of the will by the law, and the consciousness of this, is called respect, so that this is regarded as an effect of the law on the subject, and not as the cause of it. Respect is properly the conception of a worth which thwarts my self-love. Accordingly it is something which is considered neither as an object of inclination nor of fear, although it has something analogous to both. The object of respect is the law only, and that the law which we impose on ourselves and yet recognise as necessary in itself. As a law, we are subjected too it without consulting self-love; as imposed by us on ourselves, it is a result of our will. In the former aspect it has an analogy to fear, in the latter to inclination. Respect for a person is properly only respect for the law (of honesty, etc.) of which he gives us an example. Since we also look on the improvement of our talents as a duty, we consider that we see in a person of talents, as it were, the example of a law (viz., to become like him in this by exercise), and this constitutes our respect. All so-called moral interest consists simply in respect for the law.
* It might be argued that I'm hiding behind the term respect and relying on an unclear feeling, rather than providing a clear answer to the question through a rational concept. However, even though respect is a feeling, it isn't one shaped by external influences; it's generated by a rational concept. Therefore, it is fundamentally different from the feelings that come from inclination or fear. What I immediately recognize as a law for myself, I recognize with respect. This simply means I’m aware that my will is subject to a law, independent of any other influences on my feelings. The direct influence of the law on my will, along with my awareness of this, is called respect. This is seen as an effect of the law on the individual, rather than its cause. Respect reflects an understanding of a value that contradicts my self-interest. Thus, it’s considered neither an object of desire nor of fear, although it has similarities to both. The only object of respect is the law, specifically the law we impose on ourselves, which we also recognize as inherently necessary. As a law, we are subject to it without consulting our self-interest, while when we impose it on ourselves, it results from our will. In the former sense, it resembles fear; in the latter, it resembles inclination. Respect for a person is essentially respect for the law (like honesty, etc.) that they exemplify. Since we also view the development of our abilities as a duty, we see someone talented as a kind of example of a law (that is, to emulate them through practice), and that forms our respect. All so-called moral interest is fundamentally based on respect for the law.
But what sort of law can that be, the conception of which must determine the will, even without paying any regard to the effect expected from it, in order that this will may be called good absolutely and without qualification? As I have deprived the will of every impulse which could arise to it from obedience to any law, there remains nothing but the universal conformity of its actions to law in general, which alone is to serve the will as a principle, i.e., I am never to act otherwise than so that I could also will that my maxim should become a universal law. Here, now, it is the simple conformity to law in general, without assuming any particular law applicable to certain actions, that serves the will as its principle and must so serve it, if duty is not to be a vain delusion and a chimerical notion. The common reason of men in its practical judgements perfectly coincides with this and always has in view the principle here suggested. Let the question be, for example: May I when in distress make a promise with the intention not to keep it? I readily distinguish here between the two significations which the question may have: Whether it is prudent, or whether it is right, to make a false promise? The former may undoubtedly often be the case. I see clearly indeed that it is not enough to extricate myself from a present difficulty by means of this subterfuge, but it must be well considered whether there may not hereafter spring from this lie much greater inconvenience than that from which I now free myself, and as, with all my supposed cunning, the consequences cannot be so easily foreseen but that credit once lost may be much more injurious to me than any mischief which I seek to avoid at present, it should be considered whether it would not be more prudent to act herein according to a universal maxim and to make it a habit to promise nothing except with the intention of keeping it. But it is soon clear to me that such a maxim will still only be based on the fear of consequences. Now it is a wholly different thing to be truthful from duty and to be so from apprehension of injurious consequences. In the first case, the very notion of the action already implies a law for me; in the second case, I must first look about elsewhere to see what results may be combined with it which would affect myself. For to deviate from the principle of duty is beyond all doubt wicked; but to be unfaithful to my maxim of prudence may often be very advantageous to me, although to abide by it is certainly safer. The shortest way, however, and an unerring one, to discover the answer to this question whether a lying promise is consistent with duty, is to ask myself, "Should I be content that my maxim (to extricate myself from difficulty by a false promise) should hold good as a universal law, for myself as well as for others?" and should I be able to say to myself, "Every one may make a deceitful promise when he finds himself in a difficulty from which he cannot otherwise extricate himself?" Then I presently become aware that while I can will the lie, I can by no means will that lying should be a universal law. For with such a law there would be no promises at all, since it would be in vain to allege my intention in regard to my future actions to those who would not believe this allegation, or if they over hastily did so would pay me back in my own coin. Hence my maxim, as soon as it should be made a universal law, would necessarily destroy itself.
But what kind of law can it be that requires a person's will to act, without considering the expected outcome, in order for that will to be called absolutely good? Since I have removed any motivation that might come from obeying any law, what remains is just a general alignment of actions with the law, which must guide the will as a principle. In other words, I should never act in a way that I couldn’t also will for my action to become a universal law. Here, it’s the simple adherence to law in general—without needing to refer to any specific law for particular actions—that serves as the principle for the will and must do so if duty is to be meaningful and not just an illusion. Common sense in practical judgments naturally aligns with this principle. For example, let’s consider the question: Can I, when in trouble, make a promise with no intention to keep it? Here, I can easily see two meanings the question might have: Is it wise or is it moral to make a false promise? The first scenario could definitely occur. I can clearly see that just getting out of a current bind with this trick isn’t enough; I must think carefully about whether this lie might lead to greater problems later than the difficulty I'm currently avoiding. Moreover, despite my cleverness, I can’t predict consequences well enough. Once lost, trust can be far more damaging to me than the trouble I'm trying to escape right now. Therefore, it might be smarter to adhere to a universal principle and make it a habit to only promise what I truly intend to keep. But I soon realize that this principle would still be based on fear of consequences. It is fundamentally different to be truthful out of duty than to do so out of fear of negative outcomes. In the first case, the concept of the action itself implies a law for me; in the second, I must first look for potential results that may affect me. Deviating from the principle of duty is undoubtedly wrong, while being unfaithful to my own wisdom may often benefit me, even though sticking to it is certainly safer. The quickest and most reliable way to find out if a false promise aligns with duty is to ask myself, “Would I be okay with my principle (to get out of trouble by making a false promise) being a universal law for everyone, including myself?” If I can say to myself, “Everyone can make a deceptive promise when they’re in a bind they can’t get out of,” then I realize that while I can accept the lie, I can’t accept that lying should be a universal law. With such a law, there would be no promises at all since it would be pointless to claim my intentions about future actions to people who wouldn’t believe me, or those who might too quickly believe me would just turn around and deceive me in return. Therefore, as soon as my principle becomes a universal law, it effectively negates itself.
I do not, therefore, need any far-reaching penetration to discern what I have to do in order that my will may be morally good. Inexperienced in the course of the world, incapable of being prepared for all its contingencies, I only ask myself: Canst thou also will that thy maxim should be a universal law? If not, then it must be rejected, and that not because of a disadvantage accruing from it to myself or even to others, but because it cannot enter as a principle into a possible universal legislation, and reason extorts from me immediate respect for such legislation. I do not indeed as yet discern on what this respect is based (this the philosopher may inquire), but at least I understand this, that it is an estimation of the worth which far outweighs all worth of what is recommended by inclination, and that the necessity of acting from pure respect for the practical law is what constitutes duty, to which every other motive must give place, because it is the condition of a will being good in itself, and the worth of such a will is above everything.
I don't need to dig deep to figure out how to make my choices morally right. I'm inexperienced in the ways of the world and can’t be ready for every situation, so I simply ask myself: Can you will that your principle should be a universal law? If not, then I have to reject it, not because it might disadvantage me or others, but because it can't be a guiding principle for universal law. My reason demands that I respect such a law. I might not yet understand why I have this respect (that's for philosophers to explore), but I do realize that it represents a value that far exceeds any personal desires. Acting out of pure respect for the practical law is what defines my duty, and every other motive must come after that because it's essential for a will to be good in itself, and the value of such a will is the highest of all.
Thus, then, without quitting the moral knowledge of common human reason, we have arrived at its principle. And although, no doubt, common men do not conceive it in such an abstract and universal form, yet they always have it really before their eyes and use it as the standard of their decision. Here it would be easy to show how, with this compass in hand, men are well able to distinguish, in every case that occurs, what is good, what bad, conformably to duty or inconsistent with it, if, without in the least teaching them anything new, we only, like Socrates, direct their attention to the principle they themselves employ; and that, therefore, we do not need science and philosophy to know what we should do to be honest and good, yea, even wise and virtuous. Indeed we might well have conjectured beforehand that the knowledge of what every man is bound to do, and therefore also to know, would be within the reach of every man, even the commonest. Here we cannot forbear admiration when we see how great an advantage the practical judgement has over the theoretical in the common understanding of men. In the latter, if common reason ventures to depart from the laws of experience and from the perceptions of the senses, it falls into mere inconceivabilities and self-contradictions, at least into a chaos of uncertainty, obscurity, and instability. But in the practical sphere it is just when the common understanding excludes all sensible springs from practical laws that its power of judgement begins to show itself to advantage. It then becomes even subtle, whether it be that it chicanes with its own conscience or with other claims respecting what is to be called right, or whether it desires for its own instruction to determine honestly the worth of actions; and, in the latter case, it may even have as good a hope of hitting the mark as any philosopher whatever can promise himself. Nay, it is almost more sure of doing so, because the philosopher cannot have any other principle, while he may easily perplex his judgement by a multitude of considerations foreign to the matter, and so turn aside from the right way. Would it not therefore be wiser in moral concerns to acquiesce in the judgement of common reason, or at most only to call in philosophy for the purpose of rendering the system of morals more complete and intelligible, and its rules more convenient for use (especially for disputation), but not so as to draw off the common understanding from its happy simplicity, or to bring it by means of philosophy into a new path of inquiry and instruction?
So, without leaving behind the moral knowledge that comes from common human reason, we have reached its core principle. And while ordinary people might not see it in such an abstract and universal way, they always have it right in front of them and use it as the basis for their decisions. It's easy to show that, with this guideline in hand, people can clearly differentiate in every situation what is good and what is bad, whether it aligns with duty or not. If we simply direct their attention to the principle they already use, just like Socrates did, they don’t need to learn anything new. We don't require science and philosophy to figure out how to be honest, good, wise, and virtuous. In fact, we could have guessed that the knowledge of what everyone is obligated to do—and therefore to understand—would be accessible to every person, even the most ordinary. It's fascinating to see how much more effective practical judgment is compared to theoretical judgment in the common understanding of people. In the latter, if common reason strays from the laws of experience and sensory perceptions, it falls into confusion and contradictions, leading to uncertainty and instability. However, in practical matters, when common understanding ignores all sensory elements from practical laws, its judgment shines through. It becomes quite nuanced, whether it's wrestling with its own conscience, addressing other claims about what is considered right, or trying to honestly evaluate the worth of actions. In the last scenario, it might actually be just as likely to be correct as any philosopher could hope to be. In fact, it might be more likely because philosophers don't have any other guiding principle and can easily complicate their judgment with irrelevant factors, leading them off course. Wouldn't it be wiser in moral matters to trust the judgment of common reason, or at most, only bring in philosophy to make the moral system more complete and understandable and its rules easier to use (especially in debates), without taking the common understanding away from its straightforward simplicity, or leading it into a new route of inquiry and learning through philosophy?
Innocence is indeed a glorious thing; only, on the other hand, it is very sad that it cannot well maintain itself and is easily seduced. On this account even wisdom- which otherwise consists more in conduct than in knowledge- yet has need of science, not in order to learn from it, but to secure for its precepts admission and permanence. Against all the commands of duty which reason represents to man as so deserving of respect, he feels in himself a powerful counterpoise in his wants and inclinations, the entire satisfaction of which he sums up under the name of happiness. Now reason issues its commands unyieldingly, without promising anything to the inclinations, and, as it were, with disregard and contempt for these claims, which are so impetuous, and at the same time so plausible, and which will not allow themselves to be suppressed by any command. Hence there arises a natural dialectic, i.e., a disposition, to argue against these strict laws of duty and to question their validity, or at least their purity and strictness; and, if possible, to make them more accordant with our wishes and inclinations, that is to say, to corrupt them at their very source, and entirely to destroy their worth- a thing which even common practical reason cannot ultimately call good.
Innocence is truly a beautiful thing; however, it's also quite sad that it struggles to stay intact and can be easily tempted. Because of this, even wisdom—which typically relies more on actions than on knowledge—still needs education, not to learn from it, but to ensure its principles are accepted and endured. Against all the demands of duty that reason presents to people as deserving of great respect, they feel a strong counterbalance in their needs and desires, which they sum up as happiness. Reason gives its commands unwaveringly, without offering anything to these desires, almost ignoring and dismissing these powerful and convincing claims, which refuse to be silenced by any command. This creates a natural tendency to challenge the rigid laws of duty and to question their validity, or at least their purity and severity; and, if possible, to align them more with our desires, which means to undermine their very foundation and completely destroy their value—a situation that even common practical reason ultimately cannot deem good.
Thus is the common reason of man compelled to go out of its sphere, and to take a step into the field of a practical philosophy, not to satisfy any speculative want (which never occurs to it as long as it is content to be mere sound reason), but even on practical grounds, in order to attain in it information and clear instruction respecting the source of its principle, and the correct determination of it in opposition to the maxims which are based on wants and inclinations, so that it may escape from the perplexity of opposite claims and not run the risk of losing all genuine moral principles through the equivocation into which it easily falls. Thus, when practical reason cultivates itself, there insensibly arises in it a dialetic which forces it to seek aid in philosophy, just as happens to it in its theoretic use; and in this case, therefore, as well as in the other, it will find rest nowhere but in a thorough critical examination of our reason.
Thus, the common reasoning of humans is pushed to step outside its usual limits and explore practical philosophy, not to fulfill any theoretical desire (which doesn’t come up as long as it’s satisfied being straightforward reasoning), but for practical reasons, to gain information and clear guidance about the source of its principles and how to accurately define them against maxims based on needs and desires. This way, it can avoid the confusion of conflicting claims and the risk of losing all true moral principles due to the misunderstandings it might easily fall into. So, when practical reasoning develops, a dialectic naturally arises that compels it to seek help in philosophy, just like it does in its theoretical application; and in this case, just as in the other, it finds no peace except through a thorough critical examination of our reasoning.
SECOND SECTION—TRANSITION FROM POPULAR MORAL PHILOSOPHY TO THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS
If we have hitherto drawn our notion of duty from the common use of our practical reason, it is by no means to be inferred that we have treated it as an empirical notion. On the contrary, if we attend to the experience of men's conduct, we meet frequent and, as we ourselves allow, just complaints that one cannot find a single certain example of the disposition to act from pure duty. Although many things are done in conformity with what duty prescribes, it is nevertheless always doubtful whether they are done strictly from duty, so as to have a moral worth. Hence there have at all times been philosophers who have altogether denied that this disposition actually exists at all in human actions, and have ascribed everything to a more or less refined self-love. Not that they have on that account questioned the soundness of the conception of morality; on the contrary, they spoke with sincere regret of the frailty and corruption of human nature, which, though noble enough to take its rule an idea so worthy of respect, is yet weak to follow it and employs reason which ought to give it the law only for the purpose of providing for the interest of the inclinations, whether singly or at the best in the greatest possible harmony with one another.
If we've gotten our idea of duty so far from the common use of our practical reason, it doesn't mean that we've treated it as just an empirical concept. On the contrary, when we look at how people behave, we often see, and even admit ourselves, that there are valid complaints that we can't find a single clear example of someone acting purely out of duty. While many actions align with what duty demands, it's always unclear if they are truly done out of duty in a way that has moral value. Because of this, there have always been philosophers who completely denied that such a disposition exists in human actions, attributing everything to a more or less refined self-interest. This doesn’t mean they doubted the integrity of the idea of morality; rather, they expressed genuine regret over the shortcomings and corruption of human nature, which, despite being noble enough to adhere to such a respected ideal, is still too weak to follow it. Instead, it uses reason—meant to provide laws for itself—to serve the interests of its desires, whether individually or, at best, in the greatest possible harmony.
In fact, it is absolutely impossible to make out by experience with complete certainty a single case in which the maxim of an action, however right in itself, rested simply on moral grounds and on the conception of duty. Sometimes it happens that with the sharpest self-examination we can find nothing beside the moral principle of duty which could have been powerful enough to move us to this or that action and to so great a sacrifice; yet we cannot from this infer with certainty that it was not really some secret impulse of self-love, under the false appearance of duty, that was the actual determining cause of the will. We like them to flatter ourselves by falsely taking credit for a more noble motive; whereas in fact we can never, even by the strictest examination, get completely behind the secret springs of action; since, when the question is of moral worth, it is not with the actions which we see that we are concerned, but with those inward principles of them which we do not see.
Actually, it's completely impossible to definitively identify a single instance where the motivation behind an action, no matter how right it may be, is solely based on moral grounds or the idea of duty. Sometimes, even after the most thorough self-reflection, we can find nothing but the moral principle of duty that seems strong enough to drive us to take a particular action and make significant sacrifices; yet we can't conclude with certainty that there wasn't actually some hidden impulse of self-love disguised as duty that was the true reason behind our decision. We like to deceive ourselves by taking credit for a nobler intention; however, in reality, we can never fully uncover the hidden motivations behind our actions because, when it comes to moral worth, we aren't focused on the actions we see, but on the internal principles behind them that we don't.
Moreover, we cannot better serve the wishes of those who ridicule all morality as a mere chimera of human imagination over stepping itself from vanity, than by conceding to them that notions of duty must be drawn only from experience (as from indolence, people are ready to think is also the case with all other notions); for or is to prepare for them a certain triumph. I am willing to admit out of love of humanity that even most of our actions are correct, but if we look closer at them we everywhere come upon the dear self which is always prominent, and it is this they have in view and not the strict command of duty which would often require self-denial. Without being an enemy of virtue, a cool observer, one that does not mistake the wish for good, however lively, for its reality, may sometimes doubt whether true virtue is actually found anywhere in the world, and this especially as years increase and the judgement is partly made wiser by experience and partly, also, more acute in observation. This being so, nothing can secure us from falling away altogether from our ideas of duty, or maintain in the soul a well-grounded respect for its law, but the clear conviction that although there should never have been actions which really sprang from such pure sources, yet whether this or that takes place is not at all the question; but that reason of itself, independent on all experience, ordains what ought to take place, that accordingly actions of which perhaps the world has hitherto never given an example, the feasibility even of which might be very much doubted by one who founds everything on experience, are nevertheless inflexibly commanded by reason; that, e.g., even though there might never yet have been a sincere friend, yet not a whit the less is pure sincerity in friendship required of every man, because, prior to all experience, this duty is involved as duty in the idea of a reason determining the will by a priori principles.
Moreover, we cannot better address the desires of those who mock all morality as a mere illusion of human imagination driven by vanity than by conceding to them that ideas of duty must be based solely on experience (just as, due to laziness, people are ready to believe applies to all other ideas); for this would prepare them for a certain victory. I am willing to acknowledge, out of a love for humanity, that many of our actions are correct, but if we examine them closely, we always encounter the self, which is always at the forefront, and it is this self-centeredness that they are considering, not the true command of duty that often requires self-denial. Without being an enemy of virtue, a detached observer who does not confuse the desire for good, no matter how intense, with its actual presence, may sometimes doubt whether true virtue exists anywhere in the world, especially as the years pass and judgment becomes partly wiser through experience and partly sharper in observation. Given this, nothing can prevent us from completely drifting away from our concepts of duty or maintain a genuine respect for its laws in our souls, except for the clear conviction that although there may never have been actions that truly came from such pure sources, the question is not whether this or that occurs; rather, it is that reason, on its own, independent of all experience, dictates what should happen. Consequently, actions which the world may never have witnessed, and whose feasibility might be doubted by someone who bases everything on experience, are nonetheless unyieldingly mandated by reason; for example, even if there has never been a genuinely sincere friend, pure sincerity in friendship is still required from every person, because, prior to all experience, this duty is inherent as a duty in the idea of reason guiding the will through a priori principles.
When we add further that, unless we deny that the notion of morality has any truth or reference to any possible object, we must admit that its law must be valid, not merely for men but for all rational creatures generally, not merely under certain contingent conditions or with exceptions but with absolute necessity, then it is clear that no experience could enable us to infer even the possibility of such apodeictic laws. For with what right could we bring into unbounded respect as a universal precept for every rational nature that which perhaps holds only under the contingent conditions of humanity? Or how could laws of the determination of our will be regarded as laws of the determination of the will of rational beings generally, and for us only as such, if they were merely empirical and did not take their origin wholly a priori from pure but practical reason?
When we add that if we don't deny that the concept of morality has any truth or connects to any possible object, we have to accept that its law must be valid not just for humans but for all rational beings in general, not just under certain situations or with exceptions but with absolute necessity, then it's clear that no experience could allow us to suggest even the possibility of such certain laws. For what right would we have to hold something in universal respect as a guideline for every rational being if it only applies under the specific conditions of humanity? Or how could the laws that guide our will be seen as laws that guide the will of rational beings in general, only for us, if they were simply based on experience and didn't originate entirely from pure but practical reason?
Nor could anything be more fatal to morality than that we should wish to derive it from examples. For every example of it that is set before me must be first itself tested by principles of morality, whether it is worthy to serve as an original example, i.e., as a pattern; but by no means can it authoritatively furnish the conception of morality. Even the Holy One of the Gospels must first be compared with our ideal of moral perfection before we can recognise Him as such; and so He says of Himself, "Why call ye Me (whom you see) good; none is good (the model of good) but God only (whom ye do not see)?" But whence have we the conception of God as the supreme good? Simply from the idea of moral perfection, which reason frames a priori and connects inseparably with the notion of a free will. Imitation finds no place at all in morality, and examples serve only for encouragement, i.e., they put beyond doubt the feasibility of what the law commands, they make visible that which the practical rule expresses more generally, but they can never authorize us to set aside the true original which lies in reason and to guide ourselves by examples.
Nothing could be more damaging to morality than thinking we can derive it from examples. Every example presented to me must first be evaluated against moral principles to determine if it can be considered a worthy model. It cannot, however, give us an authoritative definition of morality. Even the figure of Jesus in the Gospels must be measured against our ideal of moral perfection for us to recognize Him as such. He Himself says, "Why do you call Me good? No one is good but God alone." But where do we get the idea of God as the highest good? It comes from our concept of moral perfection, which reason creates beforehand and links to the idea of free will. Imitation has no role in morality; examples can only provide encouragement. They confirm that what the law commands is doable and clarify what the practical rule expresses in broader terms, but they can never legitimize dismissing the true original source, which lies within reason, in favor of examples.
If then there is no genuine supreme principle of morality but what must rest simply on pure reason, independent of all experience, I think it is not necessary even to put the question whether it is good to exhibit these concepts in their generality (in abstracto) as they are established a priori along with the principles belonging to them, if our knowledge is to be distinguished from the vulgar and to be called philosophical.
If there is no real ultimate principle of morality that relies solely on pure reason, independent of any experience, I don’t think it’s even worth asking whether it’s good to present these ideas in their general form (in abstracto) as they are established a priori along with the principles that go with them, if we want our knowledge to stand out from common understanding and be considered philosophical.
In our times indeed this might perhaps be necessary; for if we collected votes whether pure rational knowledge separated from everything empirical, that is to say, metaphysic of morals, or whether popular practical philosophy is to be preferred, it is easy to guess which side would preponderate.
In our time, this might be necessary; because if we gathered votes on whether pure rational knowledge, separated from any empirical evidence—basically, the metaphysics of morals—or if we should prefer popular practical philosophy, it’s easy to see which side would win.
This descending to popular notions is certainly very commendable, if the ascent to the principles of pure reason has first taken place and been satisfactorily accomplished. This implies that we first found ethics on metaphysics, and then, when it is firmly established, procure a hearing for it by giving it a popular character. But it is quite absurd to try to be popular in the first inquiry, on which the soundness of the principles depends. It is not only that this proceeding can never lay claim to the very rare merit of a true philosophical popularity, since there is no art in being intelligible if one renounces all thoroughness of insight; but also it produces a disgusting medley of compiled observations and half-reasoned principles. Shallow pates enjoy this because it can be used for every-day chat, but the sagacious find in it only confusion, and being unsatisfied and unable to help themselves, they turn away their eyes, while philosophers, who see quite well through this delusion, are little listened to when they call men off for a time from this pretended popularity, in order that they might be rightfully popular after they have attained a definite insight.
This shift towards popular ideas is definitely admirable, but only if the foundation of pure reason has been established properly first. This means we should build ethics on metaphysics and, once that foundation is solid, make it accessible to everyone. However, it’s completely ridiculous to aim for popularity in the initial inquiry that determines the validity of the principles. Not only does this approach fail to achieve the rare quality of true philosophical popularity—since there’s no skill in being understandable if one overlooks the depth of insight—it also results in a messy collection of observations and poorly thought-out principles. Superficial thinkers enjoy this because it works for casual conversation, but wise individuals find only confusion in it. Feeling unsatisfied and helpless, they turn away, while philosophers, who see through this illusion, are rarely heard when they try to steer people away from this false popularity, so that they can achieve genuine popularity after gaining true understanding.
We need only look at the attempts of moralists in that favourite fashion, and we shall find at one time the special constitution of human nature (including, however, the idea of a rational nature generally), at one time perfection, at another happiness, here moral sense, there fear of God. a little of this, and a little of that, in marvellous mixture, without its occurring to them to ask whether the principles of morality are to be sought in the knowledge of human nature at all (which we can have only from experience); or, if this is not so, if these principles are to be found altogether a priori, free from everything empirical, in pure rational concepts only and nowhere else, not even in the smallest degree; then rather to adopt the method of making this a separate inquiry, as pure practical philosophy, or (if one may use a name so decried) as metaphysic of morals, * to bring it by itself to completeness, and to require the public, which wishes for popular treatment, to await the issue of this undertaking.
We only need to look at the efforts of moralists in that popular way, and we'll find them sometimes focusing on the specific makeup of human nature (which includes the general idea of rational nature), sometimes on perfection, at other times on happiness, and sometimes on moral sense or fear of God. A little of this and a little of that, mixed together in a remarkable way, without considering whether the foundations of morality should be based on understanding human nature at all (which we can only gain through experience); or, if that's not the case, whether these foundations can be found purely a priori, completely free from any empirical influences, existing only in pure rational concepts and nowhere else, not even to the slightest extent. In that case, it would be better to take on this as a separate inquiry, as pure practical philosophy, or (if one can use a term that is often criticized) as the metaphysics of morals, to develop it fully on its own, and to ask the public, who desires a more accessible discussion, to be patient while we see the outcome of this endeavor.
* Just as pure mathematics are distinguished from applied, pure logic from applied, so if we choose we may also distinguish pure philosophy of morals (metaphysic) from applied (viz., applied to human nature). By this designation we are also at once reminded that moral principles are not based on properties of human nature, but must subsist a priori of themselves, while from such principles practical rules must be capable of being deduced for every rational nature, and accordingly for that of man.
* Just as pure mathematics is different from applied mathematics, and pure logic from applied logic, we can also distinguish between pure moral philosophy (metaphysics) and applied moral philosophy (specifically, applied to human nature). This distinction reminds us that moral principles aren't based on the characteristics of human nature; they must exist independently. From these principles, we should be able to derive practical rules for every rational being, including humans.
Such a metaphysic of morals, completely isolated, not mixed with any anthropology, theology, physics, or hyperphysics, and still less with occult qualities (which we might call hypophysical), is not only an indispensable substratum of all sound theoretical knowledge of duties, but is at the same time a desideratum of the highest importance to the actual fulfilment of their precepts. For the pure conception of duty, unmixed with any foreign addition of empirical attractions, and, in a word, the conception of the moral law, exercises on the human heart, by way of reason alone (which first becomes aware with this that it can of itself be practical), an influence so much more powerful than all other springs * which may be derived from the field of experience, that, in the consciousness of its worth, it despises the latter, and can by degrees become their master; whereas a mixed ethics, compounded partly of motives drawn from feelings and inclinations, and partly also of conceptions of reason, must make the mind waver between motives which cannot be brought under any principle, which lead to good only by mere accident and very often also to evil.
A metaphysics of ethics that is completely separate and not mixed with any anthropology, theology, physics, or metaphysics—and even less with hidden qualities (which we might call metaphysical)—is not only a necessary foundation for all solid theoretical understanding of duties, but also a crucial requirement for actually following those duties. The pure idea of duty, free from any additional empirical motivations, and in short, the idea of the moral law, has a much stronger influence on the human heart through reason alone (which first realizes that it can be practical) than all other influences that come from experience. In realizing its value, it looks down on the latter and can gradually become its master. On the other hand, a mixed ethics, made up of motivations drawn from feelings and inclinations as well as reasoning, causes the mind to waver between motivations that cannot be unified under any principle, leading to good only by chance and often to evil.
* I have a letter from the late excellent Sulzer, in which he asks me what can be the reason that moral instruction, although containing much that is convincing for the reason, yet accomplishes so little? My answer was postponed in order that I might make it complete. But it is simply this: that the teachers themselves have not got their own notions clear, and when they endeavour to make up for this by raking up motives of moral goodness from every quarter, trying to make their physic right strong, they spoil it. For the commonest understanding shows that if we imagine, on the one hand, an act of honesty done with steadfast mind, apart from every view to advantage of any kind in this world or another, and even under the greatest temptations of necessity or allurement, and, on the other hand, a similar act which was affected, in however low a degree, by a foreign motive, the former leaves far behind and eclipses the second; it elevates the soul and inspires the wish to be able to act in like manner oneself. Even moderately young children feel this impression, ana one should never represent duties to them in any other light.
* I have a letter from the late great Sulzer, asking me why moral teaching, despite having many compelling points, is still so ineffective. I postponed my response to ensure I could give a thorough answer. But the answer is simple: the teachers themselves aren't clear on their own beliefs, and when they try to compensate for this by pulling moral motivations from every direction, they end up ruining it. It's clear that if we consider, on one hand, an honest act done with determination, without any thought of personal gain in this life or the next—even under the strongest temptations of need or temptation—and, on the other hand, a similar act that is influenced, even slightly, by an outside motive, the first far surpasses and outshines the second; it uplifts the soul and inspires the desire to act in the same way. Even very young children can sense this difference, and we should never present their responsibilities in any other way.
From what has been said, it is clear that all moral conceptions have their seat and origin completely a priori in the reason, and that, moreover, in the commonest reason just as truly as in that which is in the highest degree speculative; that they cannot be obtained by abstraction from any empirical, and therefore merely contingent, knowledge; that it is just this purity of their origin that makes them worthy to serve as our supreme practical principle, and that just in proportion as we add anything empirical, we detract from their genuine influence and from the absolute value of actions; that it is not only of the greatest necessity, in a purely speculative point of view, but is also of the greatest practical importance, to derive these notions and laws from pure reason, to present them pure and unmixed, and even to determine the compass of this practical or pure rational knowledge, i.e., to determine the whole faculty of pure practical reason; and, in doing so, we must not make its principles dependent on the particular nature of human reason, though in speculative philosophy this may be permitted, or may even at times be necessary; but since moral laws ought to hold good for every rational creature, we must derive them from the general concept of a rational being. In this way, although for its application to man morality has need of anthropology, yet, in the first instance, we must treat it independently as pure philosophy, i.e., as metaphysic, complete in itself (a thing which in such distinct branches of science is easily done); knowing well that unless we are in possession of this, it would not only be vain to determine the moral element of duty in right actions for purposes of speculative criticism, but it would be impossible to base morals on their genuine principles, even for common practical purposes, especially of moral instruction, so as to produce pure moral dispositions, and to engraft them on men's minds to the promotion of the greatest possible good in the world.
From what has been discussed, it's clear that all moral ideas originate entirely from reason, without any prior experience, and that this holds true for both regular and highly theoretical reasoning. These ideas cannot be extracted from any empirical or merely contingent knowledge. It’s this purity of origin that qualifies them to be our ultimate practical principle, and the more we add empirical elements, the more we diminish their true influence and the absolute value of our actions. It is crucial, from a theoretical standpoint, as well as practically, to derive these concepts and laws from pure reason, to present them untainted, and even to define the scope of this practical or pure rational knowledge, which means determining the entire faculty of pure practical reason. In doing this, we shouldn't base its principles on the specific nature of human reason, even though that may be acceptable or sometimes necessary in speculative philosophy. Since moral laws should be valid for all rational beings, we must derive them from the general idea of a rational being. Thus, while morality needs anthropology for its application to humans, we must initially treat it as an independent field of pure philosophy, or metaphysics, self-contained (this is easily achievable in clearly defined branches of science). It's important to recognize that without this foundation, it would not only be pointless to identify the moral aspects of duty in righteous actions for speculative analysis, but it would also be impossible to ground morals in their true principles, even for basic practical purposes, especially in moral education, aimed at fostering pure moral attitudes and instilling them in people's minds to achieve the greatest possible good in the world.
But in order that in this study we may not merely advance by the natural steps from the common moral judgement (in this case very worthy of respect) to the philosophical, as has been already done, but also from a popular philosophy, which goes no further than it can reach by groping with the help of examples, to metaphysic (which does allow itself to be checked by anything empirical and, as it must measure the whole extent of this kind of rational knowledge, goes as far as ideal conceptions, where even examples fail us), we must follow and clearly describe the practical faculty of reason, from the general rules of its determination to the point where the notion of duty springs from it.
But to ensure that in this study we don't just progress naturally from common moral judgments (which are quite worthy of respect in this case) to philosophical ones, as has already been done, but also move from a popular philosophy that only goes as far as it can through examples, to metaphysics (which can indeed be evaluated by empirical means and, since it has to encompass all aspects of this type of rational knowledge, reaches ideal concepts where even examples fall short), we need to examine and describe the practical aspects of reason, starting from the general guidelines that shape it to the point where the idea of duty emerges.
Everything in nature works according to laws. Rational beings alone have the faculty of acting according to the conception of laws, that is according to principles, i.e., have a will. Since the deduction of actions from principles requires reason, the will is nothing but practical reason. If reason infallibly determines the will, then the actions of such a being which are recognised as objectively necessary are subjectively necessary also, i.e., the will is a faculty to choose that only which reason independent of inclination recognises as practically necessary, i.e., as good. But if reason of itself does not sufficiently determine the will, if the latter is subject also to subjective conditions (particular impulses) which do not always coincide with the objective conditions; in a word, if the will does not in itself completely accord with reason (which is actually the case with men), then the actions which objectively are recognised as necessary are subjectively contingent, and the determination of such a will according to objective laws is obligation, that is to say, the relation of the objective laws to a will that is not thoroughly good is conceived as the determination of the will of a rational being by principles of reason, but which the will from its nature does not of necessity follow.
Everything in nature operates according to laws. Only rational beings have the ability to act based on the understanding of laws, meaning they have a will. Since deriving actions from principles requires reason, the will is essentially practical reason. If reason always determines the will, then the actions of such a being that are seen as objectively necessary are also subjectively necessary; in other words, the will can only choose what reason, independent of desire, recognizes as practically necessary, or good. However, if reason alone doesn't fully determine the will, if the will is also influenced by subjective conditions (specific impulses) that don’t always align with objective conditions; in short, if the will does not fully align with reason (which is actually the case with humans), then the actions that are objectively recognized as necessary are subjectively contingent. The determination of such a will according to objective laws is called obligation. This means that the relationship between objective laws and a will that is not entirely good is seen as the determination of the will of a rational being by principles of reason, but the will does not necessarily follow these principles because of its nature.
The conception of an objective principle, in so far as it is obligatory for a will, is called a command (of reason), and the formula of the command is called an imperative.
The idea of an objective principle, as far as it is binding for a will, is referred to as a command (of reason), and the wording of the command is known as an imperative.
All imperatives are expressed by the word ought [or shall], and thereby indicate the relation of an objective law of reason to a will, which from its subjective constitution is not necessarily determined by it (an obligation). They say that something would be good to do or to forbear, but they say it to a will which does not always do a thing because it is conceived to be good to do it. That is practically good, however, which determines the will by means of the conceptions of reason, and consequently not from subjective causes, but objectively, that is on principles which are valid for every rational being as such. It is distinguished from the pleasant, as that which influences the will only by means of sensation from merely subjective causes, valid only for the sense of this or that one, and not as a principle of reason, which holds for every one. *
All commands are expressed with the word "ought" [or "shall"], which highlights the connection between an objective law of reason and a will that, due to its subjective nature, isn’t always influenced by it (an obligation). They suggest that something would be good to do or to avoid, but they direct this to a will that doesn’t always act simply because it’s seen as the right thing to do. What is practically good, however, is what guides the will through the ideas of reason, and thus not from personal motives, but objectively, based on principles that are valid for all rational beings. It is different from what is enjoyable, as that influences the will only through sensation from purely subjective causes, which are only relevant to an individual’s perception, and not as a universal principle of reason that applies to everyone.
* The dependence of the desires on sensations is called inclination, and this accordingly always indicates a want. The dependence of a contingently determinable will on principles of reason is called an interest. This therefore, is found only in the case of a dependent will which does not always of itself conform to reason; in the Divine will we cannot conceive any interest. But the human will can also take an interest in a thing without therefore acting from interest. The former signifies the practical interest in the action, the latter the pathological in the object of the action. The former indicates only dependence of the will on principles of reason in themselves; the second, dependence on principles of reason for the sake of inclination, reason supplying only the practical rules how the requirement of the inclination may be satisfied. In the first case the action interests me; in the second the object of the action (because it is pleasant to me). We have seen in the first section that in an action done from duty we must look not to the interest in the object, but only to that in the action itself, and in its rational principle (viz., the law).
* The reliance of desires on sensations is called inclination, and this always points to a need. The reliance of a will that can be determined in certain situations on principles of reason is called an interest. This is only found in the case of a dependent will, which does not always align with reason on its own; in the Divine will, we can't think of any interest. However, a human will can also take an interest in something without acting out of that interest. The former refers to practical interest in the action, while the latter refers to pathological interest in the object of the action. The former indicates only the dependence of the will on principles of reason themselves; the latter indicates dependence on principles of reason for the sake of inclination, with reason providing only practical guidelines on how to satisfy the requirement of that inclination. In the first case, the action interests me; in the second, the object of the action does (because it is enjoyable for me). We saw in the first section that in an action done from duty, we must focus not on the interest in the object, but solely on the interest in the action itself and its rational principle (i.e., the law).
A perfectly good will would therefore be equally subject to objective laws (viz., laws of good), but could not be conceived as obliged thereby to act lawfully, because of itself from its subjective constitution it can only be determined by the conception of good. Therefore no imperatives hold for the Divine will, or in general for a holy will; ought is here out of place, because the volition is already of itself necessarily in unison with the law. Therefore imperatives are only formulae to express the relation of objective laws of all volition to the subjective imperfection of the will of this or that rational being, e.g., the human will.
A perfectly good will is likewise subject to objective laws (like the laws of good), but it can't be seen as required to act lawfully because, by its very nature, it can only be shaped by the idea of what is good. Therefore, no imperatives apply to the Divine will, or to any holy will; the notion of obligation doesn't fit here since the will is already inherently in harmony with the law. Thus, imperatives are just ways to express the relationship between the objective laws governing all volition and the subjective shortcomings of the will of various rational beings, such as the human will.
Now all imperatives command either hypothetically or categorically. The former represent the practical necessity of a possible action as means to something else that is willed (or at least which one might possibly will). The categorical imperative would be that which represented an action as necessary of itself without reference to another end, i.e., as objectively necessary.
Now all imperatives command either hypothetically or categorically. The former represents the practical necessity of a possible action as a means to something else that is desired (or at least something one might desire). The categorical imperative represents an action as necessary in itself, without referring to another goal, meaning it is objectively necessary.
Since every practical law represents a possible action as good and, on this account, for a subject who is practically determinable by reason, necessary, all imperatives are formulae determining an action which is necessary according to the principle of a will good in some respects. If now the action is good only as a means to something else, then the imperative is hypothetical; if it is conceived as good in itself and consequently as being necessarily the principle of a will which of itself conforms to reason, then it is categorical.
Since every practical law presents a possible action as good and, for someone who can be guided by reason, necessary, all imperatives serve as formulas that define an action deemed necessary according to the principle of a good will in certain respects. If the action is considered good only as a means to achieve something else, then the imperative is hypothetical; if it is viewed as good in itself and therefore as necessarily aligning with a will that naturally conforms to reason, then it is categorical.
Thus the imperative declares what action possible by me would be good and presents the practical rule in relation to a will which does not forthwith perform an action simply because it is good, whether because the subject does not always know that it is good, or because, even if it know this, yet its maxims might be opposed to the objective principles of practical reason.
Thus, the imperative states what action I could take that would be good and presents the practical rule regarding a will that doesn't immediately act just because it is good. This is true either because the person doesn't always recognize that it is good, or because, even if they do, their personal beliefs may conflict with the objective principles of practical reason.
Accordingly the hypothetical imperative only says that the action is good for some purpose, possible or actual. In the first case it is a problematical, in the second an assertorial practical principle. The categorical imperative which declares an action to be objectively necessary in itself without reference to any purpose, i.e., without any other end, is valid as an apodeictic (practical) principle.
The hypothetical imperative simply states that an action is good for a specific purpose, whether that purpose is possible or actual. In the first scenario, it is a conditional statement, and in the second, it is a definitive practical principle. The categorical imperative, which states that an action is objectively necessary on its own, without reference to any purpose or external goal, is considered a universally valid (practical) principle.
Whatever is possible only by the power of some rational being may also be conceived as a possible purpose of some will; and therefore the principles of action as regards the means necessary to attain some possible purpose are in fact infinitely numerous. All sciences have a practical part, consisting of problems expressing that some end is possible for us and of imperatives directing how it may be attained. These may, therefore, be called in general imperatives of skill. Here there is no question whether the end is rational and good, but only what one must do in order to attain it. The precepts for the physician to make his patient thoroughly healthy, and for a poisoner to ensure certain death, are of equal value in this respect, that each serves to effect its purpose perfectly. Since in early youth it cannot be known what ends are likely to occur to us in the course of life, parents seek to have their children taught a great many things, and provide for their skill in the use of means for all sorts of arbitrary ends, of none of which can they determine whether it may not perhaps hereafter be an object to their pupil, but which it is at all events possible that he might aim at; and this anxiety is so great that they commonly neglect to form and correct their judgement on the value of the things which may be chosen as ends.
Anything that can only happen through the power of a rational being can also be thought of as a possible goal of someone's will; therefore, the principles guiding actions regarding the means necessary to achieve these possible goals are actually countless. All fields of study have a practical side, which includes problems that show some kind of goal is achievable for us and guidelines on how to reach it. These can generally be called skills-based guidelines. Here, the focus isn’t on whether the goal is rational and good, but rather on what one needs to do to achieve it. The guidelines for a doctor to make a patient completely healthy and for a poisoner to guarantee death hold equal importance in this context, as each effectively fulfills its intended purpose. Since it's impossible to know early in life what goals we may adopt as we grow, parents tend to have their children learn a wide range of subjects and equip them with skills to pursue various arbitrary ends, none of which they can definitively say will be relevant to their child later on, but which it is certainly possible that the child might aim for. This concern is so strong that parents often overlook the need to shape and refine their judgment on the value of the things that could be chosen as goals.
There is one end, however, which may be assumed to be actually such to all rational beings (so far as imperatives apply to them, viz., as dependent beings), and, therefore, one purpose which they not merely may have, but which we may with certainty assume that they all actually have by a natural necessity, and this is happiness. The hypothetical imperative which expresses the practical necessity of an action as means to the advancement of happiness is assertorial. We are not to present it as necessary for an uncertain and merely possible purpose, but for a purpose which we may presuppose with certainty and a priori in every man, because it belongs to his being. Now skill in the choice of means to his own greatest well-being may be called prudence, * in the narrowest sense. And thus the imperative which refers to the choice of means to one's own happiness, i.e., the precept of prudence, is still always hypothetical; the action is not commanded absolutely, but only as means to another purpose.
There is one end that can be seen as truly relevant to all rational beings (insofar as imperatives apply to them, meaning as beings who depend on something), and therefore, one purpose that they not only might have, but which we can confidently assume they all actually possess by a natural necessity, and that is happiness. The hypothetical imperative that conveys the practical necessity of an action as a means to achieve happiness is assertive. We shouldn’t present it as necessary for an uncertain and merely possible goal, but for a purpose we can assume with certainty and a priori in every person, because it’s part of their existence. Now, the ability to choose the means to their own greatest well-being can be called prudence, in the strictest sense. Thus, the imperative that relates to the selection of means for one's own happiness, i.e., the principle of prudence, remains hypothetical; the action is not mandated absolutely, but only as a means to another end.
* The word prudence is taken in two senses: in the one it may bear the name of knowledge of the world, in the other that of private prudence. The former is a man's ability to influence others so as to use them for his own purposes. The latter is the sagacity to combine all these purposes for his own lasting benefit. This latter is properly that to which the value even of the former is reduced, and when a man is prudent in the former sense, but not in the latter, we might better say of him that he is clever and cunning, but, on the whole, imprudent.
* The word prudence is understood in two ways: one refers to a person's understanding of the world, while the other relates to personal wisdom. The first is about a person’s ability to manipulate others for their own goals. The second is the insight to align all these goals for their long-term advantage. The second meaning is essentially what gives value to the first, and when someone is prudent in the first sense but not in the second, it would be more accurate to describe them as clever and crafty, but ultimately imprudent.
Finally, there is an imperative which commands a certain conduct immediately, without having as its condition any other purpose to be attained by it. This imperative is categorical. It concerns not the matter of the action, or its intended result, but its form and the principle of which it is itself a result; and what is essentially good in it consists in the mental disposition, let the consequence be what it may. This imperative may be called that of morality.
Finally, there is a command that requires a specific action right away, without needing any other goal to justify it. This command is categorical. It doesn’t focus on what you’re doing or the outcome you hope to achieve, but rather on the way you do it and the principle that leads to it. What is fundamentally good about it lies in the mindset behind the action, regardless of the outcome. This command can be referred to as the command of morality.
There is a marked distinction also between the volitions on these three sorts of principles in the dissimilarity of the obligation of the will. In order to mark this difference more clearly, I think they would be most suitably named in their order if we said they are either rules of skill, or counsels of prudence, or commands (laws) of morality. For it is law only that involves the conception of an unconditional and objective necessity, which is consequently universally valid; and commands are laws which must be obeyed, that is, must be followed, even in opposition to inclination. Counsels, indeed, involve necessity, but one which can only hold under a contingent subjective condition, viz., they depend on whether this or that man reckons this or that as part of his happiness; the categorical imperative, on the contrary, is not limited by any condition, and as being absolutely, although practically, necessary, may be quite properly called a command. We might also call the first kind of imperatives technical (belonging to art), the second pragmatic * (to welfare), the third moral (belonging to free conduct generally, that is, to morals).
There’s a clear difference between the motivations behind these three types of principles based on the obligation of the will. To clarify this difference, we could refer to them as rules of skill, counsels of prudence, and commands (laws) of morality. Only laws involve the idea of an unconditional and objective necessity, which makes them universally valid; commands are laws that must be followed, even against one's inclinations. Counsels involve necessity too, but it’s contingent on whether a person considers something as part of their happiness; in contrast, the categorical imperative is unconditional, making it appropriately called a command. We could also categorize the first type of imperatives as technical (related to skill), the second as pragmatic (related to well-being), and the third as moral (related to general free conduct or ethics).
* It seems to me that the proper signification of the word pragmatic may be most accurately defined in this way. For sanctions are called pragmatic which flow properly not from the law of the states as necessary enactments, but from precaution for the general welfare. A history is composed pragmatically when it teaches prudence, i.e., instructs the world how it can provide for its interests better, or at least as well as, the men of former time.
* I think the best way to define the word pragmatic is like this. Sanctions are considered pragmatic when they come from a concern for the general welfare, rather than being strictly necessary laws of the state. A history is written pragmatically when it teaches prudence, meaning it shows people how to better care for their interests, or at least as well as people did in the past.
Now arises the question, how are all these imperatives possible? This question does not seek to know how we can conceive the accomplishment of the action which the imperative ordains, but merely how we can conceive the obligation of the will which the imperative expresses. No special explanation is needed to show how an imperative of skill is possible. Whoever wills the end, wills also (so far as reason decides his conduct) the means in his power which are indispensably necessary thereto. This proposition is, as regards the volition, analytical; for, in willing an object as my effect, there is already thought the causality of myself as an acting cause, that is to say, the use of the means; and the imperative educes from the conception of volition of an end the conception of actions necessary to this end. Synthetical propositions must no doubt be employed in defining the means to a proposed end; but they do not concern the principle, the act of the will, but the object and its realization. E.g., that in order to bisect a line on an unerring principle I must draw from its extremities two intersecting arcs; this no doubt is taught by mathematics only in synthetical propositions; but if I know that it is only by this process that the intended operation can be performed, then to say that, if I fully will the operation, I also will the action required for it, is an analytical proposition; for it is one and the same thing to conceive something as an effect which I can produce in a certain way, and to conceive myself as acting in this way.
Now the question arises: how are all these demands possible? This question doesn't aim to understand how we can imagine completing the action that the demand specifies, but simply how we can conceptualize the obligation of will that the demand indicates. No special explanation is needed to show how a skill demand is possible. Whoever desires the outcome also desires (as far as reason guides their behavior) the means within their ability that are absolutely necessary for that outcome. This statement is analytical regarding the intention, because when wanting an object as my result, I already think of my own causality as an acting cause, meaning the use of means; and the demand draws from the conception of wanting an end the idea of actions necessary to achieve that end. Synthetic statements will definitely be needed in defining the means to a desired end; but they don't pertain to the principle, the act of will, but rather to the object and its realization. For example, to divide a line based on an infallible method, I must draw two intersecting arcs from its ends; this is undoubtedly taught by mathematics only through synthetic statements; but if I understand that it is only through this process that the desired operation can be completed, then stating that if I fully desire the operation, I also desire the action required for it is an analytical statement; because it is essentially the same to imagine something as an effect that I can produce in a specific way, and to envision myself acting in that way.
If it were only equally easy to give a definite conception of happiness, the imperatives of prudence would correspond exactly with those of skill, and would likewise be analytical. For in this case as in that, it could be said: "Whoever wills the end, wills also (according to the dictate of reason necessarily) the indispensable means thereto which are in his power." But, unfortunately, the notion of happiness is so indefinite that although every man wishes to attain it, yet he never can say definitely and consistently what it is that he really wishes and wills. The reason of this is that all the elements which belong to the notion of happiness are altogether empirical, i.e., they must be borrowed from experience, and nevertheless the idea of happiness requires an absolute whole, a maximum of welfare in my present and all future circumstances. Now it is impossible that the most clear-sighted and at the same time most powerful being (supposed finite) should frame to himself a definite conception of what he really wills in this. Does he will riches, how much anxiety, envy, and snares might he not thereby draw upon his shoulders? Does he will knowledge and discernment, perhaps it might prove to be only an eye so much the sharper to show him so much the more fearfully the evils that are now concealed from him, and that cannot be avoided, or to impose more wants on his desires, which already give him concern enough. Would he have long life? who guarantees to him that it would not be a long misery? would he at least have health? how often has uneasiness of the body restrained from excesses into which perfect health would have allowed one to fall? and so on. In short, he is unable, on any principle, to determine with certainty what would make him truly happy; because to do so he would need to be omniscient. We cannot therefore act on any definite principles to secure happiness, but only on empirical counsels, e.g. of regimen, frugality, courtesy, reserve, etc., which experience teaches do, on the average, most promote well-being. Hence it follows that the imperatives of prudence do not, strictly speaking, command at all, that is, they cannot present actions objectively as practically necessary; that they are rather to be regarded as counsels (consilia) than precepts precepts of reason, that the problem to determine certainly and universally what action would promote the happiness of a rational being is completely insoluble, and consequently no imperative respecting it is possible which should, in the strict sense, command to do what makes happy; because happiness is not an ideal of reason but of imagination, resting solely on empirical grounds, and it is vain to expect that these should define an action by which one could attain the totality of a series of consequences which is really endless. This imperative of prudence would however be an analytical proposition if we assume that the means to happiness could be certainly assigned; for it is distinguished from the imperative of skill only by this, that in the latter the end is merely possible, in the former it is given; as however both only ordain the means to that which we suppose to be willed as an end, it follows that the imperative which ordains the willing of the means to him who wills the end is in both cases analytical. Thus there is no difficulty in regard to the possibility of an imperative of this kind either.
If it were just as easy to define happiness, the rules of caution would perfectly match those of expertise, and would also be straightforward. In both cases, one could say: "Whoever wants the end also necessarily wants (based on reason) the essential means available to them." Unfortunately, the idea of happiness is so unclear that although everyone wants to achieve it, they can never clearly and consistently say what they truly desire. This is because all the aspects that make up happiness are entirely based on experience; they must be drawn from what we’ve encountered. Yet, the concept of happiness demands a complete picture—a maximum level of well-being in the present and all future situations. It’s impossible for even the most insightful and powerful being (assuming they’re finite) to clearly define what they truly want in this regard. If someone desires wealth, they might also invite anxiety, jealousy, and traps upon themselves. If they seek knowledge and understanding, it might just sharpen their awareness of the many hidden misfortunes they can’t escape or increase their desires, which already trouble them. If they want a long life, who can assure them it wouldn't just be a prolonged misery? If they want health, how often does physical discomfort prevent someone from overindulging in ways that perfect health would allow? And so on. In short, they cannot definitively determine what would truly make them happy because doing so would require them to be all-knowing. Therefore, we cannot act on any definite principles to achieve happiness, but only on practical advice, like managing our health, being frugal, courteous, or reserved, which experience suggests generally promote well-being. This leads to the conclusion that the guidelines of caution do not strictly command anything; they can't present actions as objectively necessary. They are better regarded as recommendations than as rules of reason. The challenge of definitively and universally identifying what action would benefit the happiness of a rational being is completely unsolvable, and thus no command regarding such actions is possible that would strictly require doing what leads to happiness; because happiness is not a rational ideal but a product of imagination, based entirely on empirical foundations. It's futile to expect that these experiences would pinpoint an action that leads to a complete series of outcomes that are essentially endless. However, the guidelines of caution would be an analytical statement if we could reliably identify the means to happiness; it differs from the guidelines of expertise only in that the latter considers the end to be merely possible, while the former accepts it as given. Since both only prescribe the means to what we believe to be desired as an end, it follows that the guideline directing the means to someone who wants the end is analytical in both instances. Thus, there’s also no difficulty regarding the possibility of such a guideline.
On the other hand, the question how the imperative of morality is possible, is undoubtedly one, the only one, demanding a solution, as this is not at all hypothetical, and the objective necessity which it presents cannot rest on any hypothesis, as is the case with the hypothetical imperatives. Only here we must never leave out of consideration that we cannot make out by any example, in other words empirically, whether there is such an imperative at all, but it is rather to be feared that all those which seem to be categorical may yet be at bottom hypothetical. For instance, when the precept is: "Thou shalt not promise deceitfully"; and it is assumed that the necessity of this is not a mere counsel to avoid some other evil, so that it should mean: "Thou shalt not make a lying promise, lest if it become known thou shouldst destroy thy credit," but that an action of this kind must be regarded as evil in itself, so that the imperative of the prohibition is categorical; then we cannot show with certainty in any example that the will was determined merely by the law, without any other spring of action, although it may appear to be so. For it is always possible that fear of disgrace, perhaps also obscure dread of other dangers, may have a secret influence on the will. Who can prove by experience the non-existence of a cause when all that experience tells us is that we do not perceive it? But in such a case the so-called moral imperative, which as such appears to be categorical and unconditional, would in reality be only a pragmatic precept, drawing our attention to our own interests and merely teaching us to take these into consideration.
On a different note, the question of how the imperative of morality is possible is undeniably crucial and the only one that truly needs an answer, as it isn’t hypothetical, and the objective necessity it presents can't be based on any assumption, unlike hypothetical imperatives. However, we must always keep in mind that we can't definitively determine, through examples or empirically, whether such an imperative even exists. It's quite possible that those which seem categorical might actually be hypothetical at their core. For example, when we say: "You shall not make a deceitful promise," if we assume that the necessity here isn’t just advice to avoid some other harm—meaning it's not just "Don’t make a false promise, or you might ruin your reputation"—but rather that this action is inherently bad, making the imperative of the prohibition categorical; we still can’t confidently demonstrate through an example that the will was solely motivated by the law, without any other motivations at play, even if it appears that way. It’s always possible that fear of shame or perhaps some vague anxiety about other dangers might be influencing the will on a subconscious level. Who can prove, through experience, that a cause doesn’t exist when all experience tells us is that we don’t perceive it? In this case, the so-called moral imperative, which seems categorical and unconditional, could actually just be a pragmatic guideline, directing us toward our own interests and simply teaching us to consider them.
We shall therefore have to investigate a priori the possibility of a categorical imperative, as we have not in this case the advantage of its reality being given in experience, so that [the elucidation of] its possibility should be requisite only for its explanation, not for its establishment. In the meantime it may be discerned beforehand that the categorical imperative alone has the purport of a practical law; all the rest may indeed be called principles of the will but not laws, since whatever is only necessary for the attainment of some arbitrary purpose may be considered as in itself contingent, and we can at any time be free from the precept if we give up the purpose; on the contrary, the unconditional command leaves the will no liberty to choose the opposite; consequently it alone carries with it that necessity which we require in a law.
We need to explore in advance the possibility of a categorical imperative, since we don’t have the benefit of its reality being evident from experience. Therefore, understanding its possibility is necessary for clarifying it, not for proving it. In the meantime, it’s clear that the categorical imperative is the only thing that functions as a practical law; everything else can be considered principles of the will but not true laws. This is because anything that is just necessary to achieve a specific goal can be seen as contingent, and we can disregard that requirement any time we abandon the goal. In contrast, an unconditional command does not allow the will the freedom to choose otherwise; thus, it is the only one that has the necessary force we expect from a law.
Secondly, in the case of this categorical imperative or law of morality, the difficulty (of discerning its possibility) is a very profound one. It is an a priori synthetical practical proposition; * and as there is so much difficulty in discerning the possibility of speculative propositions of this kind, it may readily be supposed that the difficulty will be no less with the practical.
Secondly, when it comes to this categorical imperative or moral law, the challenge of figuring out its possibility is quite significant. It is an a priori synthetic practical proposition; and since there is so much trouble in determining the possibility of speculative propositions like this, it’s reasonable to assume that the difficulty will be just as great with the practical ones.
* I connect the act with the will without presupposing any condition resulting from any inclination, but a priori, and therefore necessarily (though only objectively, i.e., assuming the idea of a reason possessing full power over all subjective motives). This is accordingly a practical proposition which does not deduce the willing of an action by mere analysis from another already presupposed (for we have not such a perfect will), but connects it immediately with the conception of the will of a rational being, as something not contained in it.
* I link the act to the will without assuming any conditions that come from any inclination, but rather from the outset, and therefore necessarily (though only objectively, meaning assuming the idea of a reason that has complete control over all subjective motives). This is thus a practical proposition that does not derive the desire to act merely through analysis from another already assumed (since we do not have such a perfect will), but instead connects it directly to the idea of the will of a rational being as something not included within it.
In this problem we will first inquire whether the mere conception of a categorical imperative may not perhaps supply us also with the formula of it, containing the proposition which alone can be a categorical imperative; for even if we know the tenor of such an absolute command, yet how it is possible will require further special and laborious study, which we postpone to the last section.
In this problem, we will first explore whether the simple idea of a categorical imperative might also provide us with its formula, which includes the statement that can truly be a categorical imperative. Even if we understand the nature of such an absolute command, figuring out how it works will need more detailed and challenging study, which we will reserve for the final section.
When I conceive a hypothetical imperative, in general I do not know beforehand what it will contain until I am given the condition. But when I conceive a categorical imperative, I know at once what it contains. For as the imperative contains besides the law only the necessity that the maxims * shall conform to this law, while the law contains no conditions restricting it, there remains nothing but the general statement that the maxim of the action should conform to a universal law, and it is this conformity alone that the imperative properly represents as necessary.
When I think about a hypothetical imperative, I usually don't know what it will involve until I get the condition. But when I think about a categorical imperative, I immediately understand what it means. This is because the imperative includes not just the law, but also the need for the maxims to align with this law, whereas the law doesn't have any conditions that limit it. So, all that’s left is the general idea that the maxim of the action should align with a universal law, and it’s this alignment that the imperative clearly indicates as necessary.
* A maxim is a subjective principle of action, and must be distinguished from the objective principle, namely, practical law. The former contains the practical rule set by reason according to the conditions of the subject (often its ignorance or its inclinations), so that it is the principle on which the subject acts; but the law is the objective principle valid for every rational being, and is the principle on which it ought to act that is an imperative.
* A maxim is a personal principle of action and should be differentiated from the objective principle, which is practical law. The former includes the practical guideline established by reason based on the individual's circumstances (often their ignorance or desires), making it the principle that the individual follows; however, the law is the objective principle that applies to all rational beings and is the principle that they should follow, which is imperative.
There is therefore but one categorical imperative, namely, this: Act only on that maxim whereby thou canst at the same time will that it should become a universal law.
There is only one absolute rule, which is this: Act only according to that principle that you would want to become a universal law.
Now if all imperatives of duty can be deduced from this one imperative as from their principle, then, although it should remain undecided what is called duty is not merely a vain notion, yet at least we shall be able to show what we understand by it and what this notion means.
Now, if all the demands of duty can be derived from this one principle, then, although we may not agree on what duty truly is, we can at least clarify our understanding of it and what this concept really means.
Since the universality of the law according to which effects are produced constitutes what is properly called nature in the most general sense (as to form), that is the existence of things so far as it is determined by general laws, the imperative of duty may be expressed thus: Act as if the maxim of thy action were to become by thy will a universal law of nature.
Since the universal law that produces effects defines what we call nature in the broadest sense (in terms of form), meaning the existence of things as it is shaped by general laws, the principle of duty can be stated like this: Act as if the guiding principle of your action were to become a universal law of nature through your own will.
We will now enumerate a few duties, adopting the usual division of them into duties to ourselves and ourselves and to others, and into perfect and imperfect duties. *
We will now list a few responsibilities, following the common division of them into duties to ourselves and to others, and into perfect and imperfect duties. *
* It must be noted here that I reserve the division of duties for a future metaphysic of morals; so that I give it here only as an arbitrary one (in order to arrange my examples). For the rest, I understand by a perfect duty one that admits no exception in favour of inclination and then I have not merely external but also internal perfect duties. This is contrary to the use of the word adopted in the schools; but I do not intend to justify there, as it is all one for my purpose whether it is admitted or not.
* It should be noted that I'm setting aside the division of duties for a future discussion on moral philosophy; I'm mentioning it here just as a way to organize my examples. Furthermore, I define a perfect duty as one that allows no exceptions based on personal desires, and I recognize not only external but also internal perfect duties. This goes against the typical usage of the term adopted in academic circles; however, I don’t feel the need to justify it here, as it doesn’t matter for my purposes whether it's accepted or not.
1. A man reduced to despair by a series of misfortunes feels wearied of life, but is still so far in possession of his reason that he can ask himself whether it would not be contrary to his duty to himself to take his own life. Now he inquires whether the maxim of his action could become a universal law of nature. His maxim is: "From self-love I adopt it as a principle to shorten my life when its longer duration is likely to bring more evil than satisfaction." It is asked then simply whether this principle founded on self-love can become a universal law of nature. Now we see at once that a system of nature of which it should be a law to destroy life by means of the very feeling whose special nature it is to impel to the improvement of life would contradict itself and, therefore, could not exist as a system of nature; hence that maxim cannot possibly exist as a universal law of nature and, consequently, would be wholly inconsistent with the supreme principle of all duty.
1. A man brought to despair by a series of bad luck feels exhausted by life, but he is still rational enough to question whether it would be against his duty to himself to take his own life. He then considers whether the principle of his actions could be a universal law of nature. His principle is: "Out of self-love, I adopt the idea of ending my life when living longer is likely to bring more pain than happiness." The question here is whether this principle based on self-love can become a universal law of nature. It quickly becomes clear that a natural system in which it would be a law to destroy life through the very feeling that is meant to drive the improvement of life would contradict itself and, therefore, could not function as a natural system; thus, that principle cannot possibly be a universal law of nature and would, therefore, be completely inconsistent with the fundamental principle of all duty.
2. Another finds himself forced by necessity to borrow money. He knows that he will not be able to repay it, but sees also that nothing will be lent to him unless he promises stoutly to repay it in a definite time. He desires to make this promise, but he has still so much conscience as to ask himself: "Is it not unlawful and inconsistent with duty to get out of a difficulty in this way?" Suppose however that he resolves to do so: then the maxim of his action would be expressed thus: "When I think myself in want of money, I will borrow money and promise to repay it, although I know that I never can do so." Now this principle of self-love or of one's own advantage may perhaps be consistent with my whole future welfare; but the question now is, "Is it right?" I change then the suggestion of self-love into a universal law, and state the question thus: "How would it be if my maxim were a universal law?" Then I see at once that it could never hold as a universal law of nature, but would necessarily contradict itself. For supposing it to be a universal law that everyone when he thinks himself in a difficulty should be able to promise whatever he pleases, with the purpose of not keeping his promise, the promise itself would become impossible, as well as the end that one might have in view in it, since no one would consider that anything was promised to him, but would ridicule all such statements as vain pretences.
2. Someone finds himself in a situation where he has to borrow money. He knows he won’t be able to pay it back, but he realizes that no one will lend to him unless he confidently promises to repay it by a specific date. He wants to make this promise, but he still has enough conscience to question himself: “Is it wrong and against my duty to get out of a tough spot like this?” Suppose he decides to go through with it: then his guiding principle would be stated like this: “When I feel I need money, I will borrow it and promise to pay it back, even though I know I can’t.” Now, this principle of self-interest might seem okay for my overall well-being; but the real question is, “Is it right?” I then turn this idea of self-interest into a universal law and ask: “What if my principle were a universal law?” I quickly see that it could never serve as a universal law of nature and would end up contradicting itself. If everyone were allowed to promise anything they wanted in a moment of struggle, with the intention of not keeping that promise, the concept of a promise would lose its meaning, and the goal one might have in making that promise would also fail, since no one would believe that any promise was truly made, but would mock such claims as empty words.
3. A third finds in himself a talent which with the help of some culture might make him a useful man in many respects. But he finds himself in comfortable circumstances and prefers to indulge in pleasure rather than to take pains in enlarging and improving his happy natural capacities. He asks, however, whether his maxim of neglect of his natural gifts, besides agreeing with his inclination to indulgence, agrees also with what is called duty. He sees then that a system of nature could indeed subsist with such a universal law although men (like the South Sea islanders) should let their talents rest and resolve to devote their lives merely to idleness, amusement, and propagation of their species- in a word, to enjoyment; but he cannot possibly will that this should be a universal law of nature, or be implanted in us as such by a natural instinct. For, as a rational being, he necessarily wills that his faculties be developed, since they serve him and have been given him, for all sorts of possible purposes.
3. A third person discovers he has a talent that, with some development, could make him useful in many ways. However, he finds himself in comfortable circumstances and prefers to enjoy life rather than put in the effort to grow and enhance his natural abilities. He questions whether his choice to neglect his gifts, aligned with his desire for pleasure, is also in line with what is considered duty. He realizes that a system of nature could indeed exist with such a universal law, even if people (like the South Sea islanders) chose to let their talents go to waste and commit their lives solely to idleness, fun, and reproduction—in short, to enjoyment. However, he cannot truly will for this to be a universal law of nature or for it to be instinctively embedded in us. As a rational being, he inherently wants his abilities to be developed, since they serve him and have been given to him for a variety of potential purposes.
4. A fourth, who is in prosperity, while he sees that others have to contend with great wretchedness and that he could help them, thinks: "What concern is it of mine? Let everyone be as happy as Heaven pleases, or as he can make himself; I will take nothing from him nor even envy him, only I do not wish to contribute anything to his welfare or to his assistance in distress!" Now no doubt if such a mode of thinking were a universal law, the human race might very well subsist and doubtless even better than in a state in which everyone talks of sympathy and good-will, or even takes care occasionally to put it into practice, but, on the other side, also cheats when he can, betrays the rights of men, or otherwise violates them. But although it is possible that a universal law of nature might exist in accordance with that maxim, it is impossible to will that such a principle should have the universal validity of a law of nature. For a will which resolved this would contradict itself, inasmuch as many cases might occur in which one would have need of the love and sympathy of others, and in which, by such a law of nature, sprung from his own will, he would deprive himself of all hope of the aid he desires.
4. A fourth person, who is doing well, sees that others are struggling and that he could help them, thinks: "What’s it to me? Let everyone be as happy as they can, or as life allows; I won’t take anything from them or even envy them, I just don’t want to help with their well-being or assist them in tough times!" There’s no doubt that if everyone thought this way, humanity might actually survive and maybe even thrive better than in a situation where everyone talks about kindness and goodwill, or sometimes even tries to act on it, while also taking advantage when they can and ignoring people's rights or violating them. However, even if there could be a natural law that supports that idea, it’s impossible to wish for such a principle to have the universal strength of a natural law. Because a will that chose this would contradict itself, since there would be many situations where someone would need the love and support of others, and by such a law of nature, which comes from their own will, they would be robbing themselves of any hope for the help they seek.
These are a few of the many actual duties, or at least what we regard as such, which obviously fall into two classes on the one principle that we have laid down. We must be able to will that a maxim of our action should be a universal law. This is the canon of the moral appreciation of the action generally. Some actions are of such a character that their maxim cannot without contradiction be even conceived as a universal law of nature, far from it being possible that we should will that it should be so. In others this intrinsic impossibility is not found, but still it is impossible to will that their maxim should be raised to the universality of a law of nature, since such a will would contradict itself It is easily seen that the former violate strict or rigorous (inflexible) duty; the latter only laxer (meritorious) duty. Thus it has been completely shown how all duties depend as regards the nature of the obligation (not the object of the action) on the same principle.
These are just a few of the many real responsibilities, or at least what we consider them to be, which clearly fall into two categories based on the principle we've established. We must be able to will that a principle of our actions could be a universal law. This serves as the standard for the moral evaluation of actions in general. Some actions are such that their principle cannot even be conceived as a universal law of nature without contradiction, let alone that we should will for it to be so. In other cases, this inherent impossibility isn't present, but it remains impossible to will that their principle be elevated to the universality of a natural law, as that would contradict itself. It's clear that the former violate strict or rigid duty, while the latter only violate more flexible (meritorious) duty. Thus, it has been thoroughly demonstrated how all duties depend, concerning the nature of the obligation (not the nature of the action), on the same principle.
If now we attend to ourselves on occasion of any transgression of duty, we shall find that we in fact do not will that our maxim should be a universal law, for that is impossible for us; on the contrary, we will that the opposite should remain a universal law, only we assume the liberty of making an exception in our own favour or (just for this time only) in favour of our inclination. Consequently if we considered all cases from one and the same point of view, namely, that of reason, we should find a contradiction in our own will, namely, that a certain principle should be objectively necessary as a universal law, and yet subjectively should not be universal, but admit of exceptions. As however we at one moment regard our action from the point of view of a will wholly conformed to reason, and then again look at the same action from the point of view of a will affected by inclination, there is not really any contradiction, but an antagonism of inclination to the precept of reason, whereby the universality of the principle is changed into a mere generality, so that the practical principle of reason shall meet the maxim half way. Now, although this cannot be justified in our own impartial judgement, yet it proves that we do really recognise the validity of the categorical imperative and (with all respect for it) only allow ourselves a few exceptions, which we think unimportant and forced from us.
If we take a moment to reflect on any time we’ve failed in our duties, we'll realize that we don’t actually want our rule to be a universal law, because that’s impossible for us. Instead, we wish for the opposite to remain a universal law but allow ourselves the freedom to make exceptions for our own benefit or just this one time in favor of our desires. So, if we considered all situations from the same perspective, specifically that of reason, we would see a contradiction in our own will: that a specific principle should be objectively necessary as a universal law, but subjectively should not be universal and allow for exceptions. However, since we sometimes view our actions from the standpoint of a will fully aligned with reason and other times view the same action from a will influenced by desire, there isn’t actually a contradiction, but rather a conflict between desire and the dictates of reason. This causes the universality of the principle to shift to a mere generality, allowing the practical principle of reason to meet the rule halfway. Now, while we can’t justify this in our own unbiased judgment, it shows that we do recognize the validity of the categorical imperative and, with all due respect to it, we only permit ourselves a few exceptions, which we believe to be minor and unavoidable.
We have thus established at least this much, that if duty is a conception which is to have any import and real legislative authority for our actions, it can only be expressed in categorical and not at all in hypothetical imperatives. We have also, which is of great importance, exhibited clearly and definitely for every practical application the content of the categorical imperative, which must contain the principle of all duty if there is such a thing at all. We have not yet, however, advanced so far as to prove a priori that there actually is such an imperative, that there is a practical law which commands absolutely of itself and without any other impulse, and that the following of this law is duty.
We have established at least this much: if duty is a concept that holds any significance and real authority over our actions, it can only be expressed in categorical terms and never in hypothetical ones. Additionally, we have clearly and definitively laid out the content of the categorical imperative for every practical application, which must contain the principle of all duty, assuming such a thing exists. However, we have not yet proven a priori that such an imperative does exist, that there is a practical law that commands on its own without any other motivation, and that following this law constitutes duty.
With the view of attaining to this, it is of extreme importance to remember that we must not allow ourselves to think of deducing the reality of this principle from the particular attributes of human nature. For duty is to be a practical, unconditional necessity of action; it must therefore hold for all rational beings (to whom an imperative can apply at all), and for this reason only be also a law for all human wills. On the contrary, whatever is deduced from the particular natural characteristics of humanity, from certain feelings and propensions, nay, even, if possible, from any particular tendency proper to human reason, and which need not necessarily hold for the will of every rational being; this may indeed supply us with a maxim, but not with a law; with a subjective principle on which we may have a propension and inclination to act, but not with an objective principle on which we should be enjoined to act, even though all our propensions, inclinations, and natural dispositions were opposed to it. In fact, the sublimity and intrinsic dignity of the command in duty are so much the more evident, the less the subjective impulses favour it and the more they oppose it, without being able in the slightest degree to weaken the obligation of the law or to diminish its validity.
To achieve this, it's crucial to remember that we cannot rely on the specific traits of human nature to determine the reality of this principle. Duty is a practical, unconditional necessity for action; it must apply to all rational beings (to whom an imperative can be relevant) and thus should also be a law for all human wills. On the flip side, anything that comes from the specific natural traits of humanity, from particular feelings and tendencies, or even from any specific inclination tied to human reason—which may not necessarily apply to the will of every rational being—can provide us with a guideline but not a law. It gives us a subjective principle that may inspire us to act, but not an objective principle that requires us to act, even if all our inclinations and natural dispositions oppose it. In fact, the greatness and inherent worth of the command in duty become even more apparent when subjective impulses do not support it and instead stand against it, without in any way diminishing the obligation of the law or reducing its validity.
Here then we see philosophy brought to a critical position, since it has to be firmly fixed, notwithstanding that it has nothing to support it in heaven or earth. Here it must show its purity as absolute director of its own laws, not the herald of those which are whispered to it by an implanted sense or who knows what tutelary nature. Although these may be better than nothing, yet they can never afford principles dictated by reason, which must have their source wholly a priori and thence their commanding authority, expecting everything from the supremacy of the law and the due respect for it, nothing from inclination, or else condemning the man to self-contempt and inward abhorrence.
Here we see philosophy in a crucial position, as it needs to be firmly established, despite having no support from heaven or earth. Here it must demonstrate its purity as the ultimate guide of its own rules, rather than acting as a messenger for ideas whispered to it by an innate sense or some protective nature. While those might be better than nothing, they can never provide principles dictated by reason, which must originate entirely a priori, thus possessing their commanding authority, relying entirely on the supremacy of the law and proper respect for it, and not on personal inclinations; otherwise, it condemns the individual to self-contempt and inner disgust.
Thus every empirical element is not only quite incapable of being an aid to the principle of morality, but is even highly prejudicial to the purity of morals, for the proper and inestimable worth of an absolutely good will consists just in this, that the principle of action is free from all influence of contingent grounds, which alone experience can furnish. We cannot too much or too often repeat our warning against this lax and even mean habit of thought which seeks for its principle amongst empirical motives and laws; for human reason in its weariness is glad to rest on this pillow, and in a dream of sweet illusions (in which, instead of Juno, it embraces a cloud) it substitutes for morality a bastard patched up from limbs of various derivation, which looks like anything one chooses to see in it, only not like virtue to one who has once beheld her in her true form. *
Every empirical element is not just ineffective in supporting the principle of morality; it can actually harm the integrity of morals. The true and invaluable worth of an absolutely good will lies in the fact that the principle of action is free from any influence of contingent factors that only experience can provide. We cannot stress enough the importance of caution against this lax and even petty way of thinking that looks for its principle in empirical motives and laws. Human reason, when exhausted, is eager to rest on this comfortable but misleading notion, creating a fantasy where it trades true morality for a fake version cobbled together from various sources—something that can resemble anything one wishes to see, but is definitely not virtue for someone who has seen her in her true form.
* To behold virtue in her proper form is nothing else but to contemplate morality stripped of all admixture of sensible things and of every spurious ornament of reward or self- love. How much she then eclipses everything else that appears charming to the affections, every one may readily perceive with the least exertion of his reason, if it be not wholly spoiled for abstraction.
* To see virtue in its true form is simply to think about morality without any influence from material things or any false decorations of reward or selfishness. It's clear to anyone that with just a little use of their reasoning, they can easily see how much it outshines everything else that seems appealing to our feelings, unless their ability to think abstractly is completely lost.
The question then is this: "Is it a necessary law for all rational beings that they should always judge of their actions by maxims of which they can themselves will that they should serve as universal laws?" If it is so, then it must be connected (altogether a priori) with the very conception of the will of a rational being generally. But in order to discover this connexion we must, however reluctantly, take a step into metaphysic, although into a domain of it which is distinct from speculative philosophy, namely, the metaphysic of morals. In a practical philosophy, where it is not the reasons of what happens that we have to ascertain, but the laws of what ought to happen, even although it never does, i.e., objective practical laws, there it is not necessary to inquire into the reasons why anything pleases or displeases, how the pleasure of mere sensation differs from taste, and whether the latter is distinct from a general satisfaction of reason; on what the feeling of pleasure or pain rests, and how from it desires and inclinations arise, and from these again maxims by the co-operation of reason: for all this belongs to an empirical psychology, which would constitute the second part of physics, if we regard physics as the philosophy of nature, so far as it is based on empirical laws. But here we are concerned with objective practical laws and, consequently, with the relation of the will to itself so far as it is determined by reason alone, in which case whatever has reference to anything empirical is necessarily excluded; since if reason of itself alone determines the conduct (and it is the possibility of this that we are now investigating), it must necessarily do so a priori.
The question then is this: "Is it a necessary law for all rational beings that they should always evaluate their actions based on principles that they can will to become universal laws?" If that’s the case, it must be fundamentally linked (altogether a priori) to the very concept of the will of a rational being. However, to uncover this connection, we must, albeit reluctantly, delve into metaphysics, specifically the metaphysics of morals, which is distinct from speculative philosophy. In practical philosophy, where we are not looking to understand the reasons behind what happens but rather the laws of what should happen—even if it never actually does, meaning objective practical laws—we don't need to explore why something is pleasurable or displeasurable, how sensory pleasure differs from taste, or whether taste is separate from a general satisfaction of reason; we don't need to examine what the feeling of pleasure or pain is based on, how desires and inclinations arise from it, or how these then lead to principles through the cooperation of reason. All of this falls under empirical psychology, which could form the second part of physics if we view physics as the philosophy of nature based on empirical laws. Here, we are focused on objective practical laws and, thus, on the relationship of the will to itself as determined solely by reason, meaning anything empirical must be excluded; because if reason alone determines conduct (and that’s what we’re investigating), it must do so a priori.
The will is conceived as a faculty of determining oneself to action in accordance with the conception of certain laws. And such a faculty can be found only in rational beings. Now that which serves the will as the objective ground of its self-determination is the end, and, if this is assigned by reason alone, it must hold for all rational beings. On the other hand, that which merely contains the ground of possibility of the action of which the effect is the end, this is called the means. The subjective ground of the desire is the spring, the objective ground of the volition is the motive; hence the distinction between subjective ends which rest on springs, and objective ends which depend on motives valid for every rational being. Practical principles are formal when they abstract from all subjective ends; they are material when they assume these, and therefore particular springs of action. The ends which a rational being proposes to himself at pleasure as effects of his actions (material ends) are all only relative, for it is only their relation to the particular desires of the subject that gives them their worth, which therefore cannot furnish principles universal and necessary for all rational beings and for every volition, that is to say practical laws. Hence all these relative ends can give rise only to hypothetical imperatives.
The will is seen as the ability to make decisions and take actions based on certain laws. This ability is found only in rational beings. The goal that guides the will in its decision-making is the end, and if this end is determined by reason alone, it must apply to all rational beings. On the other hand, anything that provides the foundation for the possibility of an action leading to that end is called the means. The personal reason for the desire is the spring, while the objective reason for the will is the motive; thus, we differentiate between subjective ends based on springs and objective ends based on motives that apply to every rational being. Practical principles are formal when they ignore all subjective ends; they become material when they include these specific desires and thus particular motivations for action. The ends that a rational being chooses for their actions (material ends) are all relative because their value comes only from their connection to the individual’s particular desires, which means they can't provide universally valid and necessary principles for all rational beings and all decisions, in other words, practical laws. Therefore, all these relative ends can only lead to hypothetical imperatives.
Supposing, however, that there were something whose existence has in itself an absolute worth, something which, being an end in itself, could be a source of definite laws; then in this and this alone would lie the source of a possible categorical imperative, i.e., a practical law.
Supposing, however, that there is something whose existence has absolute value, something that, as an end in itself, could serve as the foundation for definite laws; then in this and only this would lie the source of a possible categorical imperative, i.e., a practical law.
Now I say: man and generally any rational being exists as an end in himself, not merely as a means to be arbitrarily used by this or that will, but in all his actions, whether they concern himself or other rational beings, must be always regarded at the same time as an end. All objects of the inclinations have only a conditional worth, for if the inclinations and the wants founded on them did not exist, then their object would be without value. But the inclinations, themselves being sources of want, are so far from having an absolute worth for which they should be desired that on the contrary it must be the universal wish of every rational being to be wholly free from them. Thus the worth of any object which is to be acquired by our action is always conditional. Beings whose existence depends not on our will but on nature's, have nevertheless, if they are irrational beings, only a relative value as means, and are therefore called things; rational beings, on the contrary, are called persons, because their very nature points them out as ends in themselves, that is as something which must not be used merely as means, and so far therefore restricts freedom of action (and is an object of respect). These, therefore, are not merely subjective ends whose existence has a worth for us as an effect of our action, but objective ends, that is, things whose existence is an end in itself; an end moreover for which no other can be substituted, which they should subserve merely as means, for otherwise nothing whatever would possess absolute worth; but if all worth were conditioned and therefore contingent, then there would be no supreme practical principle of reason whatever.
Now I say: a person and generally any rational being exists as an end in themselves, not just as a means to be used by someone else's will. In all their actions, whether relating to themselves or other rational beings, they must always be regarded as an end. All objects of desires have only conditional worth; if the desires and wants based on them didn’t exist, then their objects would have no value. However, since desires are sources of wants, they are far from having absolute worth that one should desire; on the contrary, it should be the universal wish of every rational being to be completely free from them. Thus, the worth of any object that we seek through our actions is always conditional. Beings whose existence depends on nature rather than our will have only relative value as means and are therefore called things; rational beings, on the other hand, are referred to as persons because their very nature identifies them as ends in themselves, meaning they must not be used merely as means, which thus limits freedom of action (and deserves respect). These are not merely subjective ends whose existence has worth for us as a result of our actions, but objective ends, meaning things whose existence is an end in itself; an end for which no other can take their place, which they should not simply serve as means, because otherwise nothing would have absolute worth; but if all worth were conditional and therefore contingent, there would be no ultimate practical principle of reason at all.
If then there is a supreme practical principle or, in respect of the human will, a categorical imperative, it must be one which, being drawn from the conception of that which is necessarily an end for everyone because it is an end in itself, constitutes an objective principle of will, and can therefore serve as a universal practical law. The foundation of this principle is: rational nature exists as an end in itself. Man necessarily conceives his own existence as being so; so far then this is a subjective principle of human actions. But every other rational being regards its existence similarly, just on the same rational principle that holds for me: * so that it is at the same time an objective principle, from which as a supreme practical law all laws of the will must be capable of being deduced. Accordingly the practical imperative will be as follows: So act as to treat humanity, whether in thine own person or in that of any other, in every case as an end withal, never as means only. We will now inquire whether this can be practically carried out.
If there is a supreme practical principle or, in terms of the human will, a categorical imperative, it must be one that, based on the idea of what is necessarily an end for everyone because it is an end in itself, serves as an objective principle of will and can therefore function as a universal practical law. The foundation of this principle is: rational nature exists as an end in itself. A person necessarily sees their own existence like this; thus, it is a subjective principle for human actions. However, every other rational being views its existence in the same way, based on the same rational principle that applies to me: so it is also an objective principle from which a supreme practical law can be derived for all laws of the will. Hence, the practical imperative will be: Act in a way that treats humanity, whether in your own person or in that of anyone else, always as an end in itself, never merely as a means. We will now explore whether this can be practically realized.
* This proposition is here stated as a postulate. The ground of it will be found in the concluding section.
* This idea is presented here as a fundamental principle. The reasoning behind it will be explained in the final section.
To abide by the previous examples:
Understood. Please provide the text you'd like me to modernize.
Firstly, under the head of necessary duty to oneself: He who contemplates suicide should ask himself whether his action can be consistent with the idea of humanity as an end in itself. If he destroys himself in order to escape from painful circumstances, he uses a person merely as a mean to maintain a tolerable condition up to the end of life. But a man is not a thing, that is to say, something which can be used merely as means, but must in all his actions be always considered as an end in himself. I cannot, therefore, dispose in any way of a man in my own person so as to mutilate him, to damage or kill him. (It belongs to ethics proper to define this principle more precisely, so as to avoid all misunderstanding, e. g., as to the amputation of the limbs in order to preserve myself, as to exposing my life to danger with a view to preserve it, etc. This question is therefore omitted here.)
Firstly, regarding the essential duty to oneself: Anyone who is thinking about suicide should ask themselves if their action aligns with the idea of humanity as an end in itself. If they choose to end their life to escape painful circumstances, they are treating themselves merely as a means to maintain a bearable existence until the end. However, a person is not an object, meaning something that can be used only as a means, but must always be regarded in all actions as an end in themselves. Therefore, I cannot treat myself in any way that would mutilate, harm, or kill me. (It is the role of ethics to define this principle more clearly to avoid any misunderstanding, for example, regarding the amputation of limbs to save myself or putting my life in danger to preserve it, etc. This question is therefore set aside here.)
Secondly, as regards necessary duties, or those of strict obligation, towards others: He who is thinking of making a lying promise to others will see at once that he would be using another man merely as a mean, without the latter containing at the same time the end in himself. For he whom I propose by such a promise to use for my own purposes cannot possibly assent to my mode of acting towards him and, therefore, cannot himself contain the end of this action. This violation of the principle of humanity in other men is more obvious if we take in examples of attacks on the freedom and property of others. For then it is clear that he who transgresses the rights of men intends to use the person of others merely as a means, without considering that as rational beings they ought always to be esteemed also as ends, that is, as beings who must be capable of containing in themselves the end of the very same action. *
Secondly, regarding necessary duties, or those that are a strict obligation to others: Anyone thinking of making a dishonest promise to others will quickly realize that they would be using another person merely as a means to an end, without that person also being treated as an end in themselves. The person I intend to manipulate with such a promise cannot possibly agree to how I am treating them and, therefore, cannot themselves represent the end of that action. This violation of the principle of humanity towards others becomes even clearer when we consider examples of attacks on others' freedom and property. In these cases, it's obvious that anyone who infringes on others' rights intends to use others merely as a means, failing to recognize that, as rational beings, they should always be valued as ends in themselves, that is, as beings capable of containing the purpose of the very same action.
* Let it not be thought that the common "quod tibi non vis fieri, etc." could serve here as the rule or principle. For it is only a deduction from the former, though with several limitations; it cannot be a universal law, for it does not contain the principle of duties to oneself, nor of the duties of benevolence to others (for many a one would gladly consent that others should not benefit him, provided only that he might be excused from showing benevolence to them), nor finally that of duties of strict obligation to one another, for on this principle the criminal might argue against the judge who punishes him, and so on.
* It's important not to think that the common saying "treat others as you want to be treated" can be used as the rule or principle here. It's only a conclusion from the previous idea, but it has many limitations; it can't be a universal law because it doesn't include the principle of duties to oneself or the duties of kindness to others (since many people would happily agree not to benefit from others as long as they don't have to show kindness to them), nor does it cover the duties of strict obligation to one another, because by this principle, a criminal could argue against the judge who punishes him, and so on.
Thirdly, as regards contingent (meritorious) duties to oneself: It is not enough that the action does not violate humanity in our own person as an end in itself, it must also harmonize with it. Now there are in humanity capacities of greater perfection, which belong to the end that nature has in view in regard to humanity in ourselves as the subject: to neglect these might perhaps be consistent with the maintenance of humanity as an end in itself, but not with the advancement of this end.
Thirdly, regarding the duties we owe ourselves: it's not enough that our actions don't harm our own humanity as an end in itself; they also need to support it. There are aspects of human nature that reflect higher levels of perfection, which align with the purpose that nature has for humanity in ourselves as individuals. Ignoring these aspects might maintain humanity as an end in itself, but it doesn't contribute to the progress of that end.
Fourthly, as regards meritorious duties towards others: The natural end which all men have is their own happiness. Now humanity might indeed subsist, although no one should contribute anything to the happiness of others, provided he did not intentionally withdraw anything from it; but after all this would only harmonize negatively not positively with humanity as an end in itself, if every one does not also endeavour, as far as in him lies, to forward the ends of others. For the ends of any subject which is an end in himself ought as far as possible to be my ends also, if that conception is to have its full effect with me.
Fourthly, regarding our responsibilities to others: The basic goal that everyone has is their own happiness. Humanity could still exist even if no one actively contributed to another person’s happiness, as long as they didn’t purposely take away from it. However, this would only create a negative balance, not a positive one, for humanity as an end in itself. Each person should also strive, as much as they can, to support the goals of others. The goals of any individual, who is an end in themselves, should, as much as possible, align with my own goals if that idea is to truly resonate with me.
This principle, that humanity and generally every rational nature is an end in itself (which is the supreme limiting condition of every man's freedom of action), is not borrowed from experience, firstly, because it is universal, applying as it does to all rational beings whatever, and experience is not capable of determining anything about them; secondly, because it does not present humanity as an end to men (subjectively), that is as an object which men do of themselves actually adopt as an end; but as an objective end, which must as a law constitute the supreme limiting condition of all our subjective ends, let them be what we will; it must therefore spring from pure reason. In fact the objective principle of all practical legislation lies (according to the first principle) in the rule and its form of universality which makes it capable of being a law (say, e. g., a law of nature); but the subjective principle is in the end; now by the second principle the subject of all ends is each rational being, inasmuch as it is an end in itself. Hence follows the third practical principle of the will, which is the ultimate condition of its harmony with universal practical reason, viz.: the idea of the will of every rational being as a universally legislative will.
This principle, that humanity and generally every rational being is an end in itself (which is the ultimate limit to everyone’s freedom to act), isn’t derived from experience. First, it’s universal, applying to all rational beings, and experience can’t determine anything about them. Second, it doesn’t present humanity as an end for people (subjectively), meaning it’s not something that individuals inherently choose as an end; rather, it presents humanity as an objective end that must, as a law, represent the ultimate limitation of all our subjective ends, regardless of what they are. Therefore, it must come from pure reason. In fact, the objective principle of all practical legislation lies (according to the first principle) in the rule and its form of universality, which makes it capable of being a law (for example, a law of nature); however, the subjective principle is in the end goal. According to the second principle, the subject of all ends is each rational being, as it is an end in itself. This leads to the third practical principle of the will, which is the ultimate condition for its alignment with universal practical reason: the concept of the will of every rational being as a will that legislates universally.
On this principle all maxims are rejected which are inconsistent with the will being itself universal legislator. Thus the will is not subject simply to the law, but so subject that it must be regarded as itself giving the law and, on this ground only, subject to the law (of which it can regard itself as the author).
On this principle, all maxims that don't align with the will being a universal legislator are dismissed. Therefore, the will isn't just bound by the law; it's bound in a way that it must be seen as creating the law and, for this reason only, is subject to the law (which it can see itself as the author of).
In the previous imperatives, namely, that based on the conception of the conformity of actions to general laws, as in a physical system of nature, and that based on the universal prerogative of rational beings as ends in themselves- these imperatives, just because they were conceived as categorical, excluded from any share in their authority all admixture of any interest as a spring of action; they were, however, only assumed to be categorical, because such an assumption was necessary to explain the conception of duty. But we could not prove independently that there are practical propositions which command categorically, nor can it be proved in this section; one thing, however, could be done, namely, to indicate in the imperative itself, by some determinate expression, that in the case of volition from duty all interest is renounced, which is the specific criterion of categorical as distinguished from hypothetical imperatives. This is done in the present (third) formula of the principle, namely, in the idea of the will of every rational being as a universally legislating will.
In the previous imperatives, which are based on the idea of actions aligning with general laws, similar to a natural physical system, and those based on the universal right of rational beings to be treated as ends in themselves—these imperatives, since they were thought of as categorical, excluded any personal interests as a motive for action. However, they were only considered categorical because that assumption was necessary to explain the concept of duty. Yet, we couldn't independently prove that there are practical statements that command categorically, nor can it be demonstrated in this section. One thing we can do, though, is indicate in the imperative itself, through a clear expression, that when acting out of duty, all personal interests are set aside. This is the specific criterion that defines categorical imperatives compared to hypothetical ones. This is established in the current (third) version of the principle, which presents the idea of the will of every rational being as a universally legislating will.
For although a will which is subject to laws may be attached to this law by means of an interest, yet a will which is itself a supreme lawgiver so far as it is such cannot possibly depend on any interest, since a will so dependent would itself still need another law restricting the interest of its self-love by the condition that it should be valid as universal law.
For even though a will that is subject to laws can be linked to this law through an interest, a will that is a supreme lawmaker, as it stands, cannot rely on any interest. A will that depends on such interests would itself require another law to limit its self-interest by the condition that it must be valid as a universal law.
Thus the principle that every human will is a will which in all its maxims gives universal laws, * provided it be otherwise justified, would be very well adapted to be the categorical imperative, in this respect, namely, that just because of the idea of universal legislation it is not based on interest, and therefore it alone among all possible imperatives can be unconditional. Or still better, converting the proposition, if there is a categorical imperative (i.e., a law for the will of every rational being), it can only command that everything be done from maxims of one's will regarded as a will which could at the same time will that it should itself give universal laws, for in that case only the practical principle and the imperative which it obeys are unconditional, since they cannot be based on any interest.
So, the idea that every human will is a will that, in all its maxims, creates universal laws—provided it is justified—fits perfectly as the categorical imperative. This is because, due to the concept of universal legislation, it isn't based on self-interest, making it the only unconditional imperative. Even better, rephrasing the statement: if there is a categorical imperative (meaning a law for the will of every rational being), it can only require that everything is done from maxims of one's will regarded as a will that could simultaneously wish to establish universal laws. In that case, only the practical principle and the imperative it follows are unconditional since they can't be grounded in any self-interest.
* I may be excused from adducing examples to elucidate this principle, as those which have already been used to elucidate the categorical imperative and its formula would all serve for the like purpose here.
* I can skip giving examples to explain this principle, since the ones I've already used to clarify the categorical imperative and its formula would work just as well here.
Looking back now on all previous attempts to discover the principle of morality, we need not wonder why they all failed. It was seen that man was bound to laws by duty, but it was not observed that the laws to which he is subject are only those of his own giving, though at the same time they are universal, and that he is only bound to act in conformity with his own will; a will, however, which is designed by nature to give universal laws. For when one has conceived man only as subject to a law (no matter what), then this law required some interest, either by way of attraction or constraint, since it did not originate as a law from his own will, but this will was according to a law obliged by something else to act in a certain manner. Now by this necessary consequence all the labour spent in finding a supreme principle of duty was irrevocably lost. For men never elicited duty, but only a necessity of acting from a certain interest. Whether this interest was private or otherwise, in any case the imperative must be conditional and could not by any means be capable of being a moral command. I will therefore call this the principle of autonomy of the will, in contrast with every other which I accordingly reckon as heteronomy.
Looking back at all the previous attempts to figure out the principle of morality, we shouldn't be surprised that they all failed. It was clear that humans were bound by duty to laws, but it wasn't recognized that the laws they follow are those they create themselves, even though they are universal, and that they are only required to act according to their own will; a will that nature intends to produce universal laws. When one only sees humans as subjects to a law (regardless of what it is), that law then needs some sort of interest, either from attraction or pressure, since it didn’t originate as a law from their own will, but instead, this will was obliged by something external to act in a specific way. Consequently, all the effort spent trying to find a supreme principle of duty was ultimately wasted. Because people never identified duty, but rather a need to act based on a particular interest. Whether that interest was private or anything else, in any case, the imperative must be conditional and could never truly be a moral command. Therefore, I will refer to this as the principle of autonomy of the will, in contrast to all others which I consider as heteronomy.
The conception of the will of every rational being as one which must consider itself as giving in all the maxims of its will universal laws, so as to judge itself and its actions from this point of view- this conception leads to another which depends on it and is very fruitful, namely that of a kingdom of ends.
The idea that every rational being's will should see itself as creating universal laws through its maxims, allowing it to evaluate itself and its actions from this perspective, leads to another important and productive concept, which is the idea of a kingdom of ends.
By a kingdom I understand the union of different rational beings in a system by common laws. Now since it is by laws that ends are determined as regards their universal validity, hence, if we abstract from the personal differences of rational beings and likewise from all the content of their private ends, we shall be able to conceive all ends combined in a systematic whole (including both rational beings as ends in themselves, and also the special ends which each may propose to himself), that is to say, we can conceive a kingdom of ends, which on the preceding principles is possible.
By a kingdom, I mean the joining together of different rational beings within a system governed by common laws. Since it's through laws that goals are defined in terms of their universal validity, if we put aside the personal differences of rational beings and the specific details of their individual goals, we can envision all goals working together in a systematic whole (including both rational beings as ends in themselves, and the specific goals each may set for themselves). In other words, we can imagine a kingdom of ends, which, based on the earlier principles, is possible.
For all rational beings come under the law that each of them must treat itself and all others never merely as means, but in every case at the same time as ends in themselves. Hence results a systematic union of rational being by common objective laws, i.e., a kingdom which may be called a kingdom of ends, since what these laws have in view is just the relation of these beings to one another as ends and means. It is certainly only an ideal.
For all rational beings are subject to the principle that they must treat themselves and others not just as tools to an end, but always as ends in themselves. This leads to a systematic connection among rational beings through common objective laws, forming what can be called a kingdom of ends, because these laws focus on the relationships between these beings as ends and means. It is certainly only an ideal.
A rational being belongs as a member to the kingdom of ends when, although giving universal laws in it, he is also himself subject to these laws. He belongs to it as sovereign when, while giving laws, he is not subject to the will of any other.
A rational being is part of the kingdom of ends when, while establishing universal laws, they are also subject to those laws themselves. They are part of it as a sovereign when, while creating laws, they are not subject to anyone else's will.
A rational being must always regard himself as giving laws either as member or as sovereign in a kingdom of ends which is rendered possible by the freedom of will. He cannot, however, maintain the latter position merely by the maxims of his will, but only in case he is a completely independent being without wants and with unrestricted power adequate to his will.
A rational person must always see themselves as either a member or a ruler in a community of goals that becomes possible through free will. However, they can't truly take on the latter role just by following their own principles; they can only do so if they are completely independent, without desires, and possess total power that matches their will.
Morality consists then in the reference of all action to the legislation which alone can render a kingdom of ends possible. This legislation must be capable of existing in every rational being and of emanating from his will, so that the principle of this will is never to act on any maxim which could not without contradiction be also a universal law and, accordingly, always so to act that the will could at the same time regard itself as giving in its maxims universal laws. If now the maxims of rational beings are not by their own nature coincident with this objective principle, then the necessity of acting on it is called practical necessitation, i.e., duty. Duty does not apply to the sovereign in the kingdom of ends, but it does to every member of it and to all in the same degree.
Morality is about relating all actions to the laws that can create a community of rational beings. These laws must be applicable to every rational person and come from their own will, meaning the guiding principle is to never act according to any rule that couldn't logically be a universal law. Therefore, one must act in a way that their will can see its own rules as universal laws. If the rules of rational beings do not naturally align with this objective principle, then the obligation to follow it is called practical necessity, or duty. Duty doesn't apply to the sovereign in the community of rational beings, but it does apply to every individual within it and equally to all.
The practical necessity of acting on this principle, i.e., duty, does not rest at all on feelings, impulses, or inclinations, but solely on the relation of rational beings to one another, a relation in which the will of a rational being must always be regarded as legislative, since otherwise it could not be conceived as an end in itself. Reason then refers every maxim of the will, regarding it as legislating universally, to every other will and also to every action towards oneself; and this not on account of any other practical motive or any future advantage, but from the idea of the dignity of a rational being, obeying no law but that which he himself also gives.
The practical need to act on this principle, that is, duty, doesn’t come from feelings, impulses, or desires, but entirely from how rational beings relate to each other. In this relation, the will of a rational being must always be seen as setting laws, because otherwise it wouldn’t make sense as an end in itself. Reason, then, assesses every principle of the will as if it were creating universal laws, applying it to every other will and also to every action towards oneself; and this is not because of any other practical motive or future gain, but due to the concept of the dignity of a rational being, who follows no law other than the one he also establishes for himself.
In the kingdom of ends everything has either value or dignity. Whatever has a value can be replaced by something else which is equivalent; whatever, on the other hand, is above all value, and therefore admits of no equivalent, has a dignity.
In the kingdom of ends, everything holds either value or dignity. Anything with value can be swapped out for something else of equal worth; however, anything that is above all value, and therefore doesn’t have an equivalent, has dignity.
Whatever has reference to the general inclinations and wants of mankind has a market value; whatever, without presupposing a want, corresponds to a certain taste, that is to a satisfaction in the mere purposeless play of our faculties, has a fancy value; but that which constitutes the condition under which alone anything can be an end in itself, this has not merely a relative worth, i.e., value, but an intrinsic worth, that is, dignity.
Anything related to the general desires and needs of people has market value; anything that satisfies a certain taste, without assuming a specific need, has a fancy value, which is just enjoyment in the pointless exercise of our abilities. However, what establishes the condition that allows something to be an end in itself holds not just relative worth, or value, but also intrinsic worth, which means dignity.
Now morality is the condition under which alone a rational being can be an end in himself, since by this alone is it possible that he should be a legislating member in the kingdom of ends. Thus morality, and humanity as capable of it, is that which alone has dignity. Skill and diligence in labour have a market value; wit, lively imagination, and humour, have fancy value; on the other hand, fidelity to promises, benevolence from principle (not from instinct), have an intrinsic worth. Neither nature nor art contains anything which in default of these it could put in their place, for their worth consists not in the effects which spring from them, not in the use and advantage which they secure, but in the disposition of mind, that is, the maxims of the will which are ready to manifest themselves in such actions, even though they should not have the desired effect. These actions also need no recommendation from any subjective taste or sentiment, that they may be looked on with immediate favour and satisfaction: they need no immediate propension or feeling for them; they exhibit the will that performs them as an object of an immediate respect, and nothing but reason is required to impose them on the will; not to flatter it into them, which, in the case of duties, would be a contradiction. This estimation therefore shows that the worth of such a disposition is dignity, and places it infinitely above all value, with which it cannot for a moment be brought into comparison or competition without as it were violating its sanctity.
Now morality is the condition under which a rational being can truly be an end in themselves, as it is what enables them to be a legislating member in the kingdom of ends. Therefore, morality, and humanity as capable of it, is the only thing that has true dignity. Skills and hard work have market value; wit, lively imagination, and humor have aesthetic value; however, fidelity to promises and benevolence based on principle (not instinct) have intrinsic worth. Neither nature nor art offers anything that can replace these, as their value lies not in the results they produce or the benefits they provide, but in the state of mind—specifically, the maxims of the will that are ready to manifest in such actions, even if they don’t achieve the desired outcome. These actions don't need any endorsement from personal taste or feeling to be viewed with immediate favor and satisfaction; they don’t require an immediate inclination or feeling towards them; they present the will that performs them as deserving of immediate respect, and only reason is necessary to direct the will towards them—not to flatter it into action, which would contradict the nature of duties. This understanding therefore shows that the worth of such a disposition is dignity, elevating it infinitely above all other values, to which it cannot be compared or competed without violating its sanctity.
What then is it which justifies virtue or the morally good disposition, in making such lofty claims? It is nothing less than the privilege it secures to the rational being of participating in the giving of universal laws, by which it qualifies him to be a member of a possible kingdom of ends, a privilege to which he was already destined by his own nature as being an end in himself and, on that account, legislating in the kingdom of ends; free as regards all laws of physical nature, and obeying those only which he himself gives, and by which his maxims can belong to a system of universal law, to which at the same time he submits himself. For nothing has any worth except what the law assigns it. Now the legislation itself which assigns the worth of everything must for that very reason possess dignity, that is an unconditional incomparable worth; and the word respect alone supplies a becoming expression for the esteem which a rational being must have for it. Autonomy then is the basis of the dignity of human and of every rational nature.
What justifies virtue or a morally good attitude in making such high claims? It is simply the privilege it grants to rational beings to participate in creating universal laws, qualifying them to be members of a possible community of ends. This privilege is inherent to their nature as beings who are ends in themselves, allowing them to legislate within this community of ends. They are free from all physical laws and only follow the laws they create, which means their principles can be part of a universal legal system to which they also submit. Nothing has value except what the law assigns to it. The legislation itself, which determines the value of everything, must therefore carry dignity, meaning it has unconditional and incomparable worth; and the term respect appropriately conveys the esteem that a rational being must hold for it. Autonomy is the foundation of the dignity of humans and every rational nature.
The three modes of presenting the principle of morality that have been adduced are at bottom only so many formulae of the very same law, and each of itself involves the other two. There is, however, a difference in them, but it is rather subjectively than objectively practical, intended namely to bring an idea of the reason nearer to intuition (by means of a certain analogy) and thereby nearer to feeling. All maxims, in fact, have:
The three ways of expressing the principle of morality that have been mentioned are essentially just different versions of the same law, and each one includes the other two. There is, however, a difference among them, but it's more about subjective practicality than objective practicality. It's meant to make a rational idea easier to grasp through a certain analogy, and as a result, more accessible to feelings. In fact, all maxims have:
1. A form, consisting in universality; and in this view the formula of the moral imperative is expressed thus, that the maxims must be so chosen as if they were to serve as universal laws of nature.
1. A form that represents universality; from this perspective, the moral imperative is expressed in such a way that the maxims should be chosen as if they were meant to be universal laws of nature.
2. A matter, namely, an end, and here the formula says that the rational being, as it is an end by its own nature and therefore an end in itself, must in every maxim serve as the condition limiting all merely relative and arbitrary ends.
2. A matter, specifically an end, and here the formula states that a rational being, by its very nature as an end in itself, must serve in every principle as the condition that limits all purely relative and arbitrary ends.
3. A complete characterization of all maxims by means of that formula, namely, that all maxims ought by their own legislation to harmonize with a possible kingdom of ends as with a kingdom of nature. * There is a progress here in the order of the categories of unity of the form of the will (its universality), plurality of the matter (the objects, i.e., the ends), and totality of the system of these. In forming our moral judgement of actions, it is better to proceed always on the strict method and start from the general formula of the categorical imperative: Act according to a maxim which can at the same time make itself a universal law. If, however, we wish to gain an entrance for the moral law, it is very useful to bring one and the same action under the three specified conceptions, and thereby as far as possible to bring it nearer to intuition.
3. A complete description of all maxims using that formula, which states that all maxims should, by their own rules, align with a possible kingdom of ends just like a kingdom of nature. * There is a development here in the arrangement of the categories of unity of the will's form (its universality), diversity of the matter (the objects, i.e., the ends), and the completeness of the system of these. When forming our moral judgment of actions, it's best to always follow the strict method and begin with the general formula of the categorical imperative: Act according to a maxim that can also become a universal law. However, if we want to open the door for the moral law, it is very helpful to apply one action to the three specified concepts, thereby getting it as close to intuition as possible.
* Teleology considers nature as a kingdom of ends; ethics regards a possible kingdom of ends as a kingdom nature. In the first case, the kingdom of ends is a theoretical idea, adopted to explain what actually is. In the latter it is a practical idea, adopted to bring about that which is not yet, but which can be realized by our conduct, namely, if it conforms to this idea.
* Teleology views nature as a realm of purposes; ethics sees a potential realm of purposes as a natural kingdom. In the first instance, the realm of purposes is a theoretical concept used to explain what exists. In the second, it’s a practical idea intended to create what doesn’t exist yet but can be achieved through our actions if they align with this idea.
We can now end where we started at the beginning, namely, with the conception of a will unconditionally good. That will is absolutely good which cannot be evil- in other words, whose maxim, if made a universal law, could never contradict itself. This principle, then, is its supreme law: "Act always on such a maxim as thou canst at the same time will to be a universal law"; this is the sole condition under which a will can never contradict itself; and such an imperative is categorical. Since the validity of the will as a universal law for possible actions is analogous to the universal connexion of the existence of things by general laws, which is the formal notion of nature in general, the categorical imperative can also be expressed thus: Act on maxims which can at the same time have for their object themselves as universal laws of nature. Such then is the formula of an absolutely good will.
We can now return to where we started, specifically the idea of a will that is unconditionally good. A will is absolutely good if it cannot be evil—in other words, if its principle, when turned into a universal law, would never contradict itself. This principle is its highest law: "Always act according to a principle that you can will to become a universal law." This is the only condition in which a will can never contradict itself, and such a command is categorical. Since the validity of the will as a universal law for possible actions is similar to the universal connection of the existence of things governed by general laws, which represents the basic idea of nature as a whole, the categorical imperative can also be stated this way: Act according to principles that can also serve as universal laws of nature. This is the formula of an absolutely good will.
Rational nature is distinguished from the rest of nature by this, that it sets before itself an end. This end would be the matter of every good will. But since in the idea of a will that is absolutely good without being limited by any condition (of attaining this or that end) we must abstract wholly from every end to be effected (since this would make every will only relatively good), it follows that in this case the end must be conceived, not as an end to be effected, but as an independently existing end. Consequently it is conceived only negatively, i.e., as that which we must never act against and which, therefore, must never be regarded merely as means, but must in every volition be esteemed as an end likewise. Now this end can be nothing but the subject of all possible ends, since this is also the subject of a possible absolutely good will; for such a will cannot without contradiction be postponed to any other object. The principle: "So act in regard to every rational being (thyself and others), that he may always have place in thy maxim as an end in himself," is accordingly essentially identical with this other: "Act upon a maxim which, at the same time, involves its own universal validity for every rational being." For that in using means for every end I should limit my maxim by the condition of its holding good as a law for every subject, this comes to the same thing as that the fundamental principle of all maxims of action must be that the subject of all ends, i.e., the rational being himself, be never employed merely as means, but as the supreme condition restricting the use of all means, that is in every case as an end likewise.
Rational nature is different from the rest of nature because it sets a goal for itself. This goal would be the basis of every good will. However, since a will that is completely good without being limited by attaining a specific goal must be understood without any goal to achieve (because that would make the will only relatively good), it follows that in this case, the goal must be seen not as something to achieve but as an end that exists independently. Therefore, it is understood negatively, meaning it is something we should never act against and, as a result, should never be viewed merely as a means but must always be valued as an end in every intention. This end can only be the subject of all possible ends since it is also the subject of a possible absolutely good will; for such a will cannot be subordinated to any other object without contradicting itself. The principle: "Act in such a way that every rational being (including yourself and others) is always treated as an end in themselves," is essentially the same as this: "Act according to a principle that can be universally applied to every rational being." If I am using means to achieve any goal, I must ensure my principles hold true as a law for everyone; this means that the fundamental principle of all actions must be that no rational being is used merely as a means, but always as the ultimate condition that limits the use of all means, treating them as ends as well.
It follows incontestably that, to whatever laws any rational being may be subject, he being an end in himself must be able to regard himself as also legislating universally in respect of these same laws, since it is just this fitness of his maxims for universal legislation that distinguishes him as an end in himself; also it follows that this implies his dignity (prerogative) above all mere physical beings, that he must always take his maxims from the point of view which regards himself and, likewise, every other rational being as law-giving beings (on which account they are called persons). In this way a world of rational beings (mundus intelligibilis) is possible as a kingdom of ends, and this by virtue of the legislation proper to all persons as members. Therefore every rational being must so act as if he were by his maxims in every case a legislating member in the universal kingdom of ends. The formal principle of these maxims is: "So act as if thy maxim were to serve likewise as the universal law (of all rational beings)." A kingdom of ends is thus only possible on the analogy of a kingdom of nature, the former however only by maxims, that is self-imposed rules, the latter only by the laws of efficient causes acting under necessitation from without. Nevertheless, although the system of nature is looked upon as a machine, yet so far as it has reference to rational beings as its ends, it is given on this account the name of a kingdom of nature. Now such a kingdom of ends would be actually realized by means of maxims conforming to the canon which the categorical imperative prescribes to all rational beings, if they were universally followed. But although a rational being, even if he punctually follows this maxim himself, cannot reckon upon all others being therefore true to the same, nor expect that the kingdom of nature and its orderly arrangements shall be in harmony with him as a fitting member, so as to form a kingdom of ends to which he himself contributes, that is to say, that it shall favour his expectation of happiness, still that law: "Act according to the maxims of a member of a merely possible kingdom of ends legislating in it universally," remains in its full force, inasmuch as it commands categorically. And it is just in this that the paradox lies; that the mere dignity of man as a rational creature, without any other end or advantage to be attained thereby, in other words, respect for a mere idea, should yet serve as an inflexible precept of the will, and that it is precisely in this independence of the maxim on all such springs of action that its sublimity consists; and it is this that makes every rational subject worthy to be a legislative member in the kingdom of ends: for otherwise he would have to be conceived only as subject to the physical law of his wants. And although we should suppose the kingdom of nature and the kingdom of ends to be united under one sovereign, so that the latter kingdom thereby ceased to be a mere idea and acquired true reality, then it would no doubt gain the accession of a strong spring, but by no means any increase of its intrinsic worth. For this sole absolute lawgiver must, notwithstanding this, be always conceived as estimating the worth of rational beings only by their disinterested behaviour, as prescribed to themselves from that idea [the dignity of man] alone. The essence of things is not altered by their external relations, and that which, abstracting from these, alone constitutes the absolute worth of man, is also that by which he must be judged, whoever the judge may be, and even by the Supreme Being. Morality, then, is the relation of actions to the relation of actions will, that is, to the autonomy of potential universal legislation by its maxims. An action that is consistent with the autonomy of the will is permitted; one that does not agree therewith is forbidden. A will whose maxims necessarily coincide with the laws of autonomy is a holy will, good absolutely. The dependence of a will not absolutely good on the principle of autonomy (moral necessitation) is obligation. This, then, cannot be applied to a holy being. The objective necessity of actions from obligation is called duty.
It’s clear that, no matter what laws any rational being might follow, since each person is an end in themselves, they must also see themselves as able to create universal laws regarding those same laws. This ability to align their principles with universal legislation distinguishes them as ends in themselves. It also means that their dignity puts them above all mere physical beings. Therefore, they must take their principles from a perspective that sees both themselves and other rational beings as law-giving individuals, which is why they are called persons. This idea makes a world of rational beings into a kingdom of ends possible, based on the laws shared by all persons as members. Consequently, every rational being must act as if, through their principles, they are a legislating member of this universal kingdom of ends. The formal principle of these guidelines is: "Act as if your principle should also be a universal law for all rational beings." A kingdom of ends can only exist in a way similar to a kingdom of nature, though the former relies on self-imposed rules (maxims) while the latter operates based on external laws of efficient causes. Still, even if nature is viewed as a machine, it is referred to as a kingdom of nature because it relates to rational beings as its ends. This kingdom of ends would become a reality through maxims that align with the rules set out by the categorical imperative if they were universally followed. However, even if a rational being strictly follows this principle, they cannot assume that others will do the same, nor can they expect nature and its orderly systems to align with them as a fitting member to create a kingdom of ends that supports their pursuit of happiness. Nevertheless, the law to "Act according to the principles of a member of a potentially existing kingdom of ends legislating universally" remains fully valid, as it is a categorical command. The paradox lies in that the simple dignity of humans as rational beings, independent of any other goals or benefits, should serve as an unyielding principle for will. This independence from all other motivations is what gives the principle its greatness, making every rational being deserving of being a legislative member in the kingdom of ends; otherwise, they would be regarded only as subjects of their physical desires. Even if we assume that the kingdom of nature and the kingdom of ends could be united under one sovereign, transforming the latter from mere idea into true reality, it would gain a powerful force but not an increase in intrinsic value. This absolute lawgiver must always be thought of as valuing rational beings solely based on their selfless actions, guided by the idea of human dignity alone. The essence of things does not change based on their external relationships, and it is that which constitutes the absolute worth of a person, regardless of who the judge is, even including the Supreme Being. Morality, then, pertains to the relationship between actions and the will, specifically to the autonomy of potential universal legislation through maxims. An action that aligns with the autonomy of the will is allowed; one that does not is prohibited. A will whose principles necessarily aligns with the laws of autonomy is a holy will, completely good. The dependence of a will that is not wholly good on the principle of autonomy (moral necessitation) is what we call obligation, which cannot apply to a holy being. The objective necessity of actions stemming from obligation is referred to as duty.
From what has just been said, it is easy to see how it happens that, although the conception of duty implies subjection to the law, we yet ascribe a certain dignity and sublimity to the person who fulfils all his duties. There is not, indeed, any sublimity in him, so far as he is subject to the moral law; but inasmuch as in regard to that very law he is likewise a legislator, and on that account alone subject to it, he has sublimity. We have also shown above that neither fear nor inclination, but simply respect for the law, is the spring which can give actions a moral worth. Our own will, so far as we suppose it to act only under the condition that its maxims are potentially universal laws, this ideal will which is possible to us is the proper object of respect; and the dignity of humanity consists just in this capacity of being universally legislative, though with the condition that it is itself subject to this same legislation.
From what has just been said, it's clear how it happens that, even though the idea of duty means being bound by the law, we still give a certain dignity and greatness to the person who meets all their obligations. There isn't really any greatness in them, as far as they are bound by the moral law; however, in that very context, they are also a legislator and, for that reason alone, subject to it, which gives them greatness. We've also shown earlier that it's not fear or desire, but simply respect for the law that can give actions their moral value. Our own will, as long as we assume it acts only under the condition that its principles could be universal laws, this ideal will which we are capable of is what deserves respect; and the dignity of humanity is exactly in this ability to be universally legislative, even while being subject to the same laws.
The Autonomy of the Will as the Supreme Principle of Morality
Autonomy of the will is that property of it by which it is a law to itself (independently of any property of the objects of volition). The principle of autonomy then is: "Always so to choose that the same volition shall comprehend the maxims of our choice as a universal law." We cannot prove that this practical rule is an imperative, i.e., that the will of every rational being is necessarily bound to it as a condition, by a mere analysis of the conceptions which occur in it, since it is a synthetical proposition; we must advance beyond the cognition of the objects to a critical examination of the subject, that is, of the pure practical reason, for this synthetic proposition which commands apodeictically must be capable of being cognized wholly a priori. This matter, however, does not belong to the present section. But that the principle of autonomy in question is the sole principle of morals can be readily shown by mere analysis of the conceptions of morality. For by this analysis we find that its principle must be a categorical imperative and that what this commands is neither more nor less than this very autonomy.
Autonomy of the will is the characteristic of it that allows it to be a law to itself (regardless of any properties of the things we want). The principle of autonomy is: "Always choose in a way that your choice can be a universal law." We can't prove that this practical rule is an imperative, meaning that the will of every rational being is necessarily bound by it, just by analyzing the concepts involved, since it's a synthetic proposition; we need to move beyond just understanding the objects to critically examining the subject, which is the pure practical reason, because this synthetic proposition that commands must be able to be understood completely a priori. However, this topic doesn't belong in the current section. Still, we can easily show that the principle of autonomy in question is the only principle of morals just by analyzing the concepts of morality. This analysis reveals that its principle must be a categorical imperative and that what it commands is simply this very autonomy.
Heteronomy of the Will as the Source of all spurious Principles of Morality
If the will seeks the law which is to determine it anywhere else than in the fitness of its maxims to be universal laws of its own dictation, consequently if it goes out of itself and seeks this law in the character of any of its objects, there always results heteronomy. The will in that case does not give itself the law, but it is given by the object through its relation to the will. This relation, whether it rests on inclination or on conceptions of reason, only admits of hypothetical imperatives: "I ought to do something because I wish for something else." On the contrary, the moral, and therefore categorical, imperative says: "I ought to do so and so, even though I should not wish for anything else." E.g., the former says: "I ought not to lie, if I would retain my reputation"; the latter says: "I ought not to lie, although it should not bring me the least discredit." The latter therefore must so far abstract from all objects that they shall have no influence on the will, in order that practical reason (will) may not be restricted to administering an interest not belonging to it, but may simply show its own commanding authority as the supreme legislation. Thus, e.g., I ought to endeavour to promote the happiness of others, not as if its realization involved any concern of mine (whether by immediate inclination or by any satisfaction indirectly gained through reason), but simply because a maxim which excludes it cannot be comprehended as a universal law in one and the same volition.
If the will looks for the law that governs it anywhere other than in the suitability of its principles to be universal laws created by itself, then it ends up seeking this law in the nature of its objects, leading to heteronomy. In that case, the will does not create the law for itself, but rather it is imposed by the object based on its relationship to the will. This relationship, whether based on desire or logical reasoning, only allows for hypothetical imperatives: "I should do something because I want something else." In contrast, the moral, and thus categorical, imperative states: "I must do this and that, even if I don't want anything else." For example, the former says: "I shouldn't lie if I want to keep my reputation"; the latter says: "I shouldn't lie, even if it does not damage my reputation at all." The latter must therefore ignore all objects so that they do not influence the will, allowing practical reason (the will) to act without being limited to pursuing an interest not inherent to it, but to display its own authoritative command as the highest legislation. Thus, for instance, I should strive to promote the happiness of others, not because achieving it concerns me (whether through immediate desire or any satisfaction indirectly gained through reason), but simply because a principle that excludes it cannot be understood as a universal law in a single consistent decision.
Classification of all Principles of Morality which can be founded on the Conception of Heteronomy
Here as elsewhere human reason in its pure use, so long as it was not critically examined, has first tried all possible wrong ways before it succeeded in finding the one true way.
Here and in other places, human reason, in its pure form and without critical examination, initially explored all possible wrong paths before finally discovering the one true path.
All principles which can be taken from this point of view are either empirical or rational. The former, drawn from the principle of happiness, are built on physical or moral feelings; the latter, drawn from the principle of perfection, are built either on the rational conception of perfection as a possible effect, or on that of an independent perfection (the will of God) as the determining cause of our will.
All principles that can be viewed this way are either empirical or rational. The empirical ones, based on the principle of happiness, rely on physical or moral feelings; the rational ones, based on the principle of perfection, depend either on the rational idea of perfection as a possible outcome or on the notion of an independent perfection (God's will) as the determining cause of our will.
Empirical principles are wholly incapable of serving as a foundation for moral laws. For the universality with which these should hold for all rational beings without distinction, the unconditional practical necessity which is thereby imposed on them, is lost when their foundation is taken from the particular constitution of human nature, or the accidental circumstances in which it is placed. The principle of private happiness, however, is the most objectionable, not merely because it is false, and experience contradicts the supposition that prosperity is always proportioned to good conduct, nor yet merely because it contributes nothing to the establishment of morality- since it is quite a different thing to make a prosperous man and a good man, or to make one prudent and sharp-sighted for his own interests and to make him virtuous- but because the springs it provides for morality are such as rather undermine it and destroy its sublimity, since they put the motives to virtue and to vice in the same class and only teach us to make a better calculation, the specific difference between virtue and vice being entirely extinguished. On the other hand, as to moral feeling, this supposed special sense, * the appeal to it is indeed superficial when those who cannot think believe that feeling will help them out, even in what concerns general laws: and besides, feelings, which naturally differ infinitely in degree, cannot furnish a uniform standard of good and evil, nor has anyone a right to form judgements for others by his own feelings: nevertheless this moral feeling is nearer to morality and its dignity in this respect, that it pays virtue the honour of ascribing to her immediately the satisfaction and esteem we have for her and does not, as it were, tell her to her face that we are not attached to her by her beauty but by profit.
Empirical principles can’t really serve as a foundation for moral laws. The universality that these laws should have for all rational beings, without exception, is lost when they’re based on the specific nature of human beings or the random circumstances they find themselves in. The idea of private happiness is particularly problematic, not just because it’s incorrect—experience shows that success isn’t always tied to good behavior—but also because it doesn’t help establish what morality is. It’s one thing to create a successful person and another to create a good person. Being smart and skilled for one’s own benefit is different from being virtuous. The motivations it provides for morality actually weaken it and diminish its greatness, since it groups the reasons for virtue and vice together and only teaches us to calculate better, erasing the clear distinction between the two. In terms of moral feeling, this supposed unique sense is really superficial when those who can’t think believe that feelings will guide them, even regarding general laws. Moreover, feelings, which vary greatly in intensity, can’t provide a consistent standard for good and evil, and no one has the right to judge others based on their own feelings. Still, this moral feeling is closer to morality and its value because it honors virtue by directly associating it with the satisfaction and respect we have for it, rather than suggesting that our attachment is based on its benefits.
* I class the principle of moral feeling under that of happiness, because every empirical interest promises to contribute to our well-being by the agreeableness that a thing affords, whether it be immediately and without a view to profit, or whether profit be regarded. We must likewise, with Hutcheson, class the principle of sympathy with the happiness of others under his assumed moral sense.
* I consider the principle of moral feelings to fall under the idea of happiness, because every personal interest claims to enhance our well-being by the pleasure something brings us, whether it provides immediate enjoyment without aiming for gain or if it includes a profit motive. We should also, like Hutcheson, categorize the principle of sympathy with the happiness of others under his proposed moral sense.
Amongst the rational principles of morality, the ontological conception of perfection, notwithstanding its defects, is better than the theological conception which derives morality from a Divine absolutely perfect will. The former is, no doubt, empty and indefinite and consequently useless for finding in the boundless field of possible reality the greatest amount suitable for us; moreover, in attempting to distinguish specifically the reality of which we are now speaking from every other, it inevitably tends to turn in a circle and cannot avoid tacitly presupposing the morality which it is to explain; it is nevertheless preferable to the theological view, first, because we have no intuition of the divine perfection and can only deduce it from our own conceptions, the most important of which is that of morality, and our explanation would thus be involved in a gross circle; and, in the next place, if we avoid this, the only notion of the Divine will remaining to us is a conception made up of the attributes of desire of glory and dominion, combined with the awful conceptions of might and vengeance, and any system of morals erected on this foundation would be directly opposed to morality.
Among the rational principles of morality, the idea of perfection, despite its flaws, is better than the theological idea that morality comes from a completely perfect Divine will. The former is undoubtedly vague and undefined, making it unhelpful for identifying the best possible outcomes for us in the endless possibilities of reality. Additionally, when trying to specifically differentiate the reality we're discussing from all others, it tends to loop back on itself and cannot help but assume the morality it's meant to explain. Nevertheless, it is preferable to the theological perspective for two reasons: first, we don't have a direct understanding of divine perfection and can only deduce it from our own concepts, the most important being morality. This leads us into a problematic circular reasoning. Second, if we set aside this issue, the only idea of the Divine will left to us is a mix of qualities like the desire for glory and power, along with terrifying notions of strength and vengeance, and any moral system built on that would completely contradict morality.
However, if I had to choose between the notion of the moral sense and that of perfection in general (two systems which at least do not weaken morality, although they are totally incapable of serving as its foundation), then I should decide for the latter, because it at least withdraws the decision of the question from the sensibility and brings it to the court of pure reason; and although even here it decides nothing, it at all events preserves the indefinite idea (of a will good in itself free from corruption, until it shall be more precisely defined.
However, if I had to choose between the idea of moral sense and the idea of perfection in general (two concepts that don’t undermine morality, even though they can't really serve as its foundation), I would go with the latter. This is because it takes the decision out of emotions and brings it to the realm of pure reason; and even though it doesn’t actually resolve anything, it at least keeps the vague concept of a will that is good in itself and free from corruption, until we can define it more clearly.
For the rest I think I may be excused here from a detailed refutation of all these doctrines; that would only be superfluous labour, since it is so easy, and is probably so well seen even by those whose office requires them to decide for one of these theories (because their hearers would not tolerate suspension of judgement). But what interests us more here is to know that the prime foundation of morality laid down by all these principles is nothing but heteronomy of the will, and for this reason they must necessarily miss their aim.
For the rest, I think I can skip a detailed rebuttal of all these beliefs; that would just be unnecessary effort since it’s so straightforward, and probably clear even to those whose job requires them to choose one of these theories (because their audience wouldn't accept indecision). What we’re more interested in here is to understand that the core foundation of morality established by all these principles is simply the heteronomy of will, and for this reason, they will inevitably fall short of their goal.
In every case where an object of the will has to be supposed, in order that the rule may be prescribed which is to determine the will, there the rule is simply heteronomy; the imperative is conditional, namely, if or because one wishes for this object, one should act so and so: hence it can never command morally, that is, categorically. Whether the object determines the will by means of inclination, as in the principle of private happiness, or by means of reason directed to objects of our possible volition generally, as in the principle of perfection, in either case the will never determines itself immediately by the conception of the action, but only by the influence which the foreseen effect of the action has on the will; I ought to do something, on this account, because I wish for something else; and here there must be yet another law assumed in me as its subject, by which I necessarily will this other thing, and this law again requires an imperative to restrict this maxim. For the influence which the conception of an object within the reach of our faculties can exercise on the will of the subject, in consequence of its natural properties, depends on the nature of the subject, either the sensibility (inclination and taste), or the understanding and reason, the employment of which is by the peculiar constitution of their nature attended with satisfaction. It follows that the law would be, properly speaking, given by nature, and, as such, it must be known and proved by experience and would consequently be contingent and therefore incapable of being an apodeictic practical rule, such as the moral rule must be. Not only so, but it is inevitably only heteronomy; the will does not give itself the law, but is given by a foreign impulse by means of a particular natural constitution of the subject adapted to receive it. An absolutely good will, then, the principle of which must be a categorical imperative, will be indeterminate as regards all objects and will contain merely the form of volition generally, and that as autonomy, that is to say, the capability of the maxims of every good will to make themselves a universal law, is itself the only law which the will of every rational being imposes on itself, without needing to assume any spring or interest as a foundation.
In every situation where we have to assume a goal for our desires in order to set a rule for how to act, that rule is simply heteronomy; the directive is conditional, meaning if or because someone wants that goal, they should act a certain way: thus, it can never be a true moral command, which is categorical. Whether the goal influences the will through desire, as in the idea of personal happiness, or through reason aimed at what we can generally will, as in the idea of perfection, in either case the will does not determine itself purely by the idea of the action, but rather by the effect the anticipated outcome has on the will; I feel I should do something because I want something else; and here there must be another rule assumed within me that compels me to want that other thing, and this rule again requires an imperative to limit this guiding principle. The effect that the idea of an achievable goal can have on a person's will, due to its natural qualities, depends on the nature of the person, whether it's sensitivity (desire and taste) or reasoning, which, because of how they are naturally constructed, tends to bring satisfaction. This suggests that the law would, in true terms, be given by nature, and, therefore, would need to be understood and verified through experience, making it contingent and thus unable to be a definitive practical rule, as moral law must be. Furthermore, it is inevitably just heteronomy; the will doesn’t create its own law but is influenced by an external impulse due to a specific natural makeup that can receive it. An absolutely good will, then, whose principle must be a categorical imperative, would be undefined regarding all goals and would only contain the general form of willing, and that, as autonomy, meaning the ability of the maxims of every good will to establish themselves as a universal law, is the only law that every rational individual imposes on themselves, without needing to assume any underlying motivation or interest.
How such a synthetical practical a priori proposition is possible, and why it is necessary, is a problem whose solution does not lie within the bounds of the metaphysic of morals; and we have not here affirmed its truth, much less professed to have a proof of it in our power. We simply showed by the development of the universally received notion of morality that an autonomy of the will is inevitably connected with it, or rather is its foundation. Whoever then holds morality to be anything real, and not a chimerical idea without any truth, must likewise admit the principle of it that is here assigned. This section then, like the first, was merely analytical. Now to prove that morality is no creation of the brain, which it cannot be if the categorical imperative and with it the autonomy of the will is true, and as an a priori principle absolutely necessary, this supposes the possibility of a synthetic use of pure practical reason, which however we cannot venture on without first giving a critical examination of this faculty of reason. In the concluding section we shall give the principal outlines of this critical examination as far as is sufficient for our purpose.
How it's possible for a synthetic practical a priori proposition to exist, and why it's necessary, is a problem that doesn't fall within the realm of moral metaphysics. We haven't claimed its truth here, much less asserted that we can prove it. We merely demonstrated through the exploration of the widely accepted idea of morality that autonomy of the will is inevitably linked to it, or rather, is its foundation. Anyone who considers morality to be something real, rather than just a fanciful notion without any truth, must also accept the principle we've outlined here. This section, like the first, is simply analytical. Now to show that morality isn't just a product of the mind—something it can't be if the categorical imperative and the autonomy of the will are true, and as an a priori principle, absolutely necessary—this requires that we explore the possibility of a synthetic use of pure practical reason, which we can't attempt without first conducting a critical examination of this capacity of reason. In the concluding section, we'll outline the main points of this critical examination as far as is necessary for our purpose.
THIRD SECTION—TRANSITION FROM THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS TO THE CRITIQUE OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON
The Concept of Freedom is the Key that explains the Autonomy of the Will
The will is a kind of causality belonging to living beings in so far as they are rational, and freedom would be this property of such causality that it can be efficient, independently of foreign causes determining it; just as physical necessity is the property that the causality of all irrational beings has of being determined to activity by the influence of foreign causes.
The will is a type of cause that applies to living beings as long as they are rational, and freedom is the characteristic of that type of cause that allows it to act independently of external influences; just as physical necessity is the characteristic of the cause in all irrational beings that makes them act under the influence of external factors.
The preceding definition of freedom is negative and therefore unfruitful for the discovery of its essence, but it leads to a positive conception which is so much the more full and fruitful.
The earlier definition of freedom is limiting and doesn't really help us understand its true nature, but it points us toward a more comprehensive and valuable understanding.
Since the conception of causality involves that of laws, according to which, by something that we call cause, something else, namely the effect, must be produced; hence, although freedom is not a property of the will depending on physical laws, yet it is not for that reason lawless; on the contrary it must be a causality acting according to immutable laws, but of a peculiar kind; otherwise a free will would be an absurdity. Physical necessity is a heteronomy of the efficient causes, for every effect is possible only according to this law, that something else determines the efficient cause to exert its causality. What else then can freedom of the will be but autonomy, that is, the property of the will to be a law to itself? But the proposition: "The will is in every action a law to itself," only expresses the principle: "To act on no other maxim than that which can also have as an object itself as a universal law." Now this is precisely the formula of the categorical imperative and is the principle of morality, so that a free will and a will subject to moral laws are one and the same.
Since the idea of causality involves laws that state that something we call a cause must produce something else, namely an effect; therefore, even though freedom is not a characteristic of the will governed by physical laws, it’s not lawless for that reason. On the contrary, it should be a form of causality that operates according to unchanging laws, but of a specific type; otherwise, a free will would be nonsensical. Physical necessity is a form of external control over the causes, as every effect can only occur according to the law that something else determines the efficient cause to act. So what can freedom of the will be other than autonomy, meaning the will's ability to be a law unto itself? However, the statement: "The will is a law to itself in every action," simply conveys the principle: "To act only according to a maxim that can also be a universal law." This is precisely the formula of the categorical imperative and represents the principle of morality, which means a free will and a will that is subject to moral laws are essentially the same.
On the hypothesis, then, of freedom of the will, morality together with its principle follows from it by mere analysis of the conception. However, the latter is a synthetic proposition; viz., an absolutely good will is that whose maxim can always include itself regarded as a universal law; for this property of its maxim can never be discovered by analysing the conception of an absolutely good will. Now such synthetic propositions are only possible in this way: that the two cognitions are connected together by their union with a third in which they are both to be found. The positive concept of freedom furnishes this third cognition, which cannot, as with physical causes, be the nature of the sensible world (in the concept of which we find conjoined the concept of something in relation as cause to something else as effect). We cannot now at once show what this third is to which freedom points us and of which we have an idea a priori, nor can we make intelligible how the concept of freedom is shown to be legitimate from principles of pure practical reason and with it the possibility of a categorical imperative; but some further preparation is required.
Based on the assumption of free will, morality and its principles can be derived simply by analyzing the concept. However, this is a synthetic statement; specifically, an absolutely good will is one whose guiding principle can always be viewed as a universal law. This characteristic of its guiding principle cannot be found just by analyzing the idea of an absolutely good will. Synthetic statements are only possible when two ideas are linked through a third idea in which both are present. The positive concept of freedom provides this third idea, which, unlike physical causes, cannot be defined by the nature of the sensible world (where we find the concept of cause linked to the concept of effect). We cannot immediately clarify what this third idea, to which freedom refers, is or how the concept of freedom is justified by the principles of pure practical reason, along with the possibility of a categorical imperative; further preparation is necessary.
Freedom must be presupposed as a Property of the Will of all Rational Beings
It is not enough to predicate freedom of our own will, from Whatever reason, if we have not sufficient grounds for predicating the same of all rational beings. For as morality serves as a law for us only because we are rational beings, it must also hold for all rational beings; and as it must be deduced simply from the property of freedom, it must be shown that freedom also is a property of all rational beings. It is not enough, then, to prove it from certain supposed experiences of human nature (which indeed is quite impossible, and it can only be shown a priori), but we must show that it belongs to the activity of all rational beings endowed with a will. Now I say every being that cannot act except under the idea of freedom is just for that reason in a practical point of view really free, that is to say, all laws which are inseparably connected with freedom have the same force for him as if his will had been shown to be free in itself by a proof theoretically conclusive. * Now I affirm that we must attribute to every rational being which has a will that it has also the idea of freedom and acts entirely under this idea. For in such a being we conceive a reason that is practical, that is, has causality in reference to its objects. Now we cannot possibly conceive a reason consciously receiving a bias from any other quarter with respect to its judgements, for then the subject would ascribe the determination of its judgement not to its own reason, but to an impulse. It must regard itself as the author of its principles independent of foreign influences. Consequently as practical reason or as the will of a rational being it must regard itself as free, that is to say, the will of such a being cannot be a will of its own except under the idea of freedom. This idea must therefore in a practical point of view be ascribed to every rational being.
It’s not enough to claim freedom of our own will, for any reason, if we don’t have solid grounds to claim the same for all rational beings. Since morality acts as a law for us only because we are rational beings, it must also apply to all rational beings; and since it must be derived simply from the property of freedom, we must show that freedom is also a trait of all rational beings. So, it’s insufficient to prove this from certain assumed experiences of human nature (which is actually quite impossible, and it can only be shown a priori), but we need to demonstrate that it belongs to the actions of all rational beings equipped with a will. I say that every being that can only act under the concept of freedom is, from a practical standpoint, genuinely free. This means all laws that are inseparably connected with freedom have the same force for them as if their will had been demonstrated to be free in itself by a conclusive theoretical proof. Now, I assert that we must attribute to every rational being with a will the idea of freedom and that they act entirely under this idea. In such a being, we imagine a reason that is practical, meaning it has causality concerning its objectives. We cannot conceive of a reason consciously influenced by any external factors regarding its judgments, because then the subject would attribute the determination of its judgment not to its own reason but to an impulse. It must see itself as the author of its principles, independent of outside influences. Therefore, as practical reason or as the will of a rational being, it must see itself as free; in other words, the will of such a being cannot be its own will except under the idea of freedom. This idea must, therefore, be ascribed to every rational being from a practical standpoint.
* I adopt this method of assuming freedom merely as an idea which rational beings suppose in their actions, in order to avoid the necessity of proving it in its theoretical aspect also. The former is sufficient for my purpose; for even though the speculative proof should not be made out, yet a being that cannot act except with the idea of freedom is bound by the same laws that would oblige a being who was actually free. Thus we can escape here from the onus which presses on the theory.
* I'm taking this approach of treating freedom as just an idea that rational beings believe in when they act, to skip the need to prove it in a theoretical way as well. The first point is enough for what I need; because even if the theoretical proof doesn't hold up, a being that can only act with the idea of freedom is still subject to the same laws that would apply to a being who is truly free. So, we can avoid the burden that weighs on the theory here.
Of the Interest attaching to the Ideas of Morality
We have finally reduced the definite conception of morality to the idea of freedom. This latter, however, we could not prove to be actually a property of ourselves or of human nature; only we saw that it must be presupposed if we would conceive a being as rational and conscious of its causality in respect of its actions, i.e., as endowed with a will; and so we find that on just the same grounds we must ascribe to every being endowed with reason and will this attribute of determining itself to action under the idea of its freedom.
We have finally boiled down the clear concept of morality to the idea of freedom. However, we were unable to show that this is actually a trait of ourselves or human nature; we only realized that it has to be assumed if we want to understand a being as rational and aware of its ability to cause its actions, that is, as having a will. Therefore, we conclude that for every being with reason and will, we must attribute the ability to determine itself to act based on the idea of its freedom.
Now it resulted also from the presupposition of these ideas that we became aware of a law that the subjective principles of action, i.e., maxims, must always be so assumed that they can also hold as objective, that is, universal principles, and so serve as universal laws of our own dictation. But why then should I subject myself to this principle and that simply as a rational being, thus also subjecting to it all other being endowed with reason? I will allow that no interest urges me to this, for that would not give a categorical imperative, but I must take an interest in it and discern how this comes to pass; for this properly an "I ought" is properly an "I would," valid for every rational being, provided only that reason determined his actions without any hindrance. But for beings that are in addition affected as we are by springs of a different kind, namely, sensibility, and in whose case that is not always done which reason alone would do, for these that necessity is expressed only as an "ought," and the subjective necessity is different from the objective.
As a result of these ideas, we realized a law: the subjective principles of action, or maxims, must always be considered as if they could also be objective, meaning universal principles, and thus serve as universal laws that we create ourselves. But why should I adhere to this principle simply because I am a rational being, and in doing so apply it to all other rational beings? I can acknowledge that no personal interest compels me to do so, as that wouldn't create a categorical imperative. However, I need to take an interest in understanding how this works; for what I "ought" to do is essentially what I "would" want to do, valid for every rational being, provided that reason guides their actions without interference. Yet, for beings who, like us, are also influenced by different factors, namely our senses, the situations in which we act aren’t always dictated by reason alone. For these beings, necessity is only expressed as an "ought," and the subjective necessity differs from the objective necessity.
It seems then as if the moral law, that is, the principle of autonomy of the will, were properly speaking only presupposed in the idea of freedom, and as if we could not prove its reality and objective necessity independently. In that case we should still have gained something considerable by at least determining the true principle more exactly than had previously been done; but as regards its validity and the practical necessity of subjecting oneself to it, we should not have advanced a step. For if we were asked why the universal validity of our maxim as a law must be the condition restricting our actions, and on what we ground the worth which we assign to this manner of acting- a worth so great that there cannot be any higher interest; and if we were asked further how it happens that it is by this alone a man believes he feels his own personal worth, in comparison with which that of an agreeable or disagreeable condition is to be regarded as nothing, to these questions we could give no satisfactory answer.
It seems that the moral law, or the principle of autonomy of the will, is really only assumed in the idea of freedom, and we can’t demonstrate its reality and objective necessity on its own. Even in that case, we would still have made significant progress by clarifying the true principle more accurately than before; however, when it comes to its validity and the practical necessity of following it, we wouldn’t have moved forward at all. If we were asked why the universal validity of our principle as a law must limit our actions, and what justifies the importance we place on this way of acting — an importance so great that nothing could be of higher value — and if we were also asked how it is that this alone makes a person feel their own worth, which is far more significant than any agreeable or disagreeable situation, we wouldn’t be able to provide a satisfying answer to these questions.
We find indeed sometimes that we can take an interest in a personal quality which does not involve any interest of external condition, provided this quality makes us capable of participating in the condition in case reason were to effect the allotment; that is to say, the mere being worthy of happiness can interest of itself even without the motive of participating in this happiness. This judgement, however, is in fact only the effect of the importance of the moral law which we before presupposed (when by the idea of freedom we detach ourselves from every empirical interest); but that we ought to detach ourselves from these interests, i.e., to consider ourselves as free in action and yet as subject to certain laws, so as to find a worth simply in our own person which can compensate us for the loss of everything that gives worth to our condition; this we are not yet able to discern in this way, nor do we see how it is possible so to act- in other words, whence the moral law derives its obligation.
Sometimes, we realize that we can take an interest in a personal quality that doesn't involve any outside factors, as long as this quality allows us to engage in that situation if reason were to dictate the distribution; in other words, just being deserving of happiness can be interesting on its own, even without the motivation of sharing in that happiness. However, this judgment is really just a reflection of the significance of the moral law that we initially assumed (when we separate ourselves from any empirical interests through the idea of freedom); but we should separate ourselves from these interests, meaning we should view ourselves as free in our actions while also being subject to certain laws, so we can find worth simply in who we are, which can make up for losing everything that gives worth to our situation; this is something we still struggle to see clearly, nor do we understand how it’s possible to act this way—in other words, where the moral law gets its authority from.
It must be freely admitted that there is a sort of circle here from which it seems impossible to escape. In the order of efficient causes we assume ourselves free, in order that in the order of ends we may conceive ourselves as subject to moral laws: and we afterwards conceive ourselves as subject to these laws, because we have attributed to ourselves freedom of will: for freedom and self-legislation of will are both autonomy and, therefore, are reciprocal conceptions, and for this very reason one must not be used to explain the other or give the reason of it, but at most only logical purposes to reduce apparently different notions of the same object to one single concept (as we reduce different fractions of the same value to the lowest terms).
It must be acknowledged that there's a kind of loop here that feels impossible to break. We think of ourselves as free in terms of causes so that we can see ourselves as following moral laws when it comes to our goals. We then see ourselves as bound by these laws because we believe we have free will. Freedom and self-regulation of will are both forms of autonomy, and for that reason, they are interrelated concepts. Therefore, we shouldn't use one to explain the other or justify it; rather, we should, at most, aim to logically unify seemingly different ideas about the same thing into one single concept (just like we simplify different fractions that represent the same value to their lowest terms).
One resource remains to us, namely, to inquire whether we do not occupy different points of view when by means of freedom we think ourselves as causes efficient a priori, and when we form our conception of ourselves from our actions as effects which we see before our eyes.
One resource we have left is to ask whether we have different perspectives when, through freedom, we consider ourselves as causes that are effective a priori, and when we form our self-conception from our actions as effects that are visible to us.
It is a remark which needs no subtle reflection to make, but which we may assume that even the commonest understanding can make, although it be after its fashion by an obscure discernment of judgement which it calls feeling, that all the "ideas" that come to us involuntarily (as those of the senses) do not enable us to know objects otherwise than as they affect us; so that what they may be in themselves remains unknown to us, and consequently that as regards "ideas" of this kind even with the closest attention and clearness that the understanding can apply to them, we can by them only attain to the knowledge of appearances, never to that of things in themselves. As soon as this distinction has once been made (perhaps merely in consequence of the difference observed between the ideas given us from without, and in which we are passive, and those that we produce simply from ourselves, and in which we show our own activity), then it follows of itself that we must admit and assume behind the appearance something else that is not an appearance, namely, the things in themselves; although we must admit that as they can never be known to us except as they affect us, we can come no nearer to them, nor can we ever know what they are in themselves. This must furnish a distinction, however crude, between a world of sense and the world of understanding, of which the former may be different according to the difference of the sensuous impressions in various observers, while the second which is its basis always remains the same, Even as to himself, a man cannot pretend to know what he is in himself from the knowledge he has by internal sensation. For as he does not as it were create himself, and does not come by the conception of himself a priori but empirically, it naturally follows that he can obtain his knowledge even of himself only by the inner sense and, consequently, only through the appearances of his nature and the way in which his consciousness is affected. At the same time beyond these characteristics of his own subject, made up of mere appearances, he must necessarily suppose something else as their basis, namely, his ego, whatever its characteristics in itself may be. Thus in respect to mere perception and receptivity of sensations he must reckon himself as belonging to the world of sense; but in respect of whatever there may be of pure activity in him (that which reaches consciousness immediately and not through affecting the senses), he must reckon himself as belonging to the intellectual world, of which, however, he has no further knowledge. To such a conclusion the reflecting man must come with respect to all the things which can be presented to him: it is probably to be met with even in persons of the commonest understanding, who, as is well known, are very much inclined to suppose behind the objects of the senses something else invisible and acting of itself. They spoil it, however, by presently sensualizing this invisible again; that is to say, wanting to make it an object of intuition, so that they do not become a whit the wiser.
It's a straightforward point that doesn’t require deep thought to recognize, but we can assume that even a basic understanding can grasp it, albeit in a vague way through what it calls feelings: all the "ideas" that come to us involuntarily (like those from our senses) only allow us to know objects as they impact us; thus, their true nature remains unknown to us. Consequently, regarding these kinds of "ideas," even with the best effort and clarity our understanding can muster, we can only achieve knowledge of appearances, never of things as they truly are. Once we recognize this distinction—perhaps due to the difference noted between externally provided ideas, where we simply react, and those we create ourselves, where we exercise our own initiative—it becomes apparent that we must accept that behind appearances, there’s something else that is not just an appearance: namely, the things in themselves; although we must also recognize that we can never know them except through how they affect us, and therefore we cannot get any closer to understanding their true essence. This creates a basic distinction between a world of sense and a world of understanding; the former may differ based on varying sensory impressions among different observers, while the latter, which is its foundation, always remains constant. Even regarding oneself, a person can’t claim to know what they are in essence just through internal sensations. Since one does not essentially create oneself, and doesn’t conceive of oneself a priori but rather through experience, it follows that one's knowledge of oneself is also acquired solely through inner senses, and therefore only through the manifestations of one's nature and how their consciousness is affected. At the same time, beyond these aspects of their own being, which consist solely of appearances, one must assume that there is something else underlying them, namely, one's ego, regardless of what its intrinsic characteristics may be. Thus, in terms of pure perception and receptivity to sensations, one must consider oneself as belonging to the world of sense; but regarding any element of pure activity (that which reaches consciousness directly and not through sensory influence), one must regard oneself as belonging to the intellectual world, of which, however, they have no further knowledge. A reflective person must arrive at this conclusion about all things that can be presented to them. This idea likely resonates even with those of the simplest understanding, who are famously inclined to assume there’s something invisible and self-acting behind sensory objects. However, they often complicate it by wanting to turn this invisible essence into something tangible, leaving them no wiser.
Now man really finds in himself a faculty by which he distinguishes himself from everything else, even from himself as affected by objects, and that is reason. This being pure spontaneity is even elevated above the understanding. For although the latter is a spontaneity and does not, like sense, merely contain intuitions that arise when we are affected by things (and are therefore passive), yet it cannot produce from its activity any other conceptions than those which merely serve to bring the intuitions of sense under rules and, thereby, to unite them in one consciousness, and without this use of the sensibility it could not think at all; whereas, on the contrary, reason shows so pure a spontaneity in the case of what I call ideas [ideal conceptions] that it thereby far transcends everything that the sensibility can give it, and exhibits its most important function in distinguishing the world of sense from that of understanding, and thereby prescribing the limits of the understanding itself.
Now, a person truly discovers within themselves an ability that separates them from everything else, even from their own experiences influenced by objects, and that is reason. This is a pure form of spontaneity that is even higher than understanding. While understanding is also spontaneous and doesn’t just contain perceptions that occur when we are affected by things (and thus are passive), it can only generate concepts that help to organize sensory perceptions under rules, bringing them together in a single awareness; without this sensory input, it couldn't think at all. In contrast, reason demonstrates such pure spontaneity when it comes to what I refer to as ideas (ideal concepts) that it far surpasses anything that sensory perception can provide. It plays a crucial role in differentiating between the realm of sensory experience and that of understanding, and in that way, it establishes the boundaries of understanding itself.
For this reason a rational being must regard himself qua intelligence (not from the side of his lower faculties) as belonging not to the world of sense, but to that of understanding; hence he has two points of view from which he can regard himself, and recognise laws of the exercise of his faculties, and consequently of all his actions: first, so far as he belongs to the world of sense, he finds himself subject to laws of nature (heteronomy); secondly, as belonging to the intelligible world, under laws which being independent of nature have their foundation not in experience but in reason alone.
For this reason, a rational being should see himself as an intellectual being (not just from the perspective of his lower faculties) as belonging to the realm of understanding rather than the world of sensory experience. Thus, he has two viewpoints to consider himself and recognize the rules guiding his faculties, and, consequently, all his actions: first, as he pertains to the sensory world, he is subject to the laws of nature (heteronomy); second, as part of the intelligible world, he operates under principles that are independent of nature, rooted not in experience but solely in reason.
As a rational being, and consequently belonging to the intelligible world, man can never conceive the causality of his own will otherwise than on condition of the idea of freedom, for independence of the determinate causes of the sensible world (an independence which reason must always ascribe to itself) is freedom. Now the idea of freedom is inseparably connected with the conception of autonomy, and this again with the universal principle of morality which is ideally the foundation of all actions of rational beings, just as the law of nature is of all phenomena.
As a rational being, and therefore part of the intelligible world, people can only understand the causality of their own will if they consider the idea of freedom. This means being independent from the specific causes of the sensible world (a type of independence that reason must always attribute to itself), which is what freedom is. The idea of freedom is closely linked to the concept of autonomy, which is in turn connected to the universal principle of morality that ideally underpins all actions of rational beings, just like the law of nature underlies all phenomena.
Now the suspicion is removed which we raised above, that there was a latent circle involved in our reasoning from freedom to autonomy, and from this to the moral law, viz.: that we laid down the idea of freedom because of the moral law only that we might afterwards in turn infer the latter from freedom, and that consequently we could assign no reason at all for this law, but could only [present] it as a petitio principii which well disposed minds would gladly concede to us, but which we could never put forward as a provable proposition. For now we see that, when we conceive ourselves as free, we transfer ourselves into the world of understanding as members of it and recognise the autonomy of the will with its consequence, morality; whereas, if we conceive ourselves as under obligation, we consider ourselves as belonging to the world of sense and at the same time to the world of understanding.
Now the earlier suspicion is cleared up, which suggested that there was an unspoken circular reasoning in our argument from freedom to autonomy, and from that to the moral law. Specifically, that we proposed the idea of freedom solely because of the moral law, so that we could then infer the moral law from freedom, and therefore we couldn't provide any real justification for this law. Instead, we could only present it as a circular argument that well-intentioned people might accept, but that we could never put forward as something proven. Now we see that when we think of ourselves as free, we place ourselves in the realm of understanding as part of it and recognize the autonomy of the will along with its result, morality. On the other hand, if we think of ourselves as obligated, we see ourselves as belonging to the sensory world while also being part of the world of understanding.
How is a Categorical Imperative Possible?
Every rational being reckons himself qua intelligence as belonging to the world of understanding, and it is simply as an efficient cause belonging to that world that he calls his causality a will. On the other side he is also conscious of himself as a part of the world of sense in which his actions, which are mere appearances [phenomena] of that causality, are displayed; we cannot, however, discern how they are possible from this causality which we do not know; but instead of that, these actions as belonging to the sensible world must be viewed as determined by other phenomena, namely, desires and inclinations. If therefore I were only a member of the world of understanding, then all my actions would perfectly conform to the principle of autonomy of the pure will; if I were only a part of the world of sense, they would necessarily be assumed to conform wholly to the natural law of desires and inclinations, in other words, to the heteronomy of nature. (The former would rest on morality as the supreme principle, the latter on happiness.) Since, however, the world of understanding contains the foundation of the world of sense, and consequently of its laws also, and accordingly gives the law to my will (which belongs wholly to the world of understanding) directly, and must be conceived as doing so, it follows that, although on the one side I must regard myself as a being belonging to the world of sense, yet on the other side I must recognize myself as subject as an intelligence to the law of the world of understanding, i.e., to reason, which contains this law in the idea of freedom, and therefore as subject to the autonomy of the will: consequently I must regard the laws of the world of understanding as imperatives for me and the actions which conform to them as duties.
Every rational person sees themselves as part of the realm of understanding through their intelligence, and it's specifically as an active cause within that realm that they refer to their ability to act as will. At the same time, they are aware of themselves as part of the sensory world where their actions, which are just manifestations of that will, take place. However, we can't understand how these actions stem from this causality that we don’t fully grasp; instead, we have to view these actions in the sensory world as being influenced by other factors, specifically desires and inclinations. If I were solely a member of the realm of understanding, all my actions would perfectly align with the principle of self-governance of a pure will; if I were just part of the sensory world, they would inevitably align with the natural laws of desires and inclinations, which means I would be governed by the nature around me. (The former relies on morality as the highest principle, the latter on happiness.) Since the realm of understanding underlies the sensory world and its laws, it directly governs my will (which belongs entirely to the realm of understanding) and must be seen as doing so. Thus, while I need to consider myself as part of the sensory world, I also have to acknowledge that, as an intelligent being, I am subject to the laws of the realm of understanding, meaning I must adhere to reason, which embodies these laws through the concept of freedom. Therefore, I must see the laws of the realm of understanding as commands for me, and the actions that align with them as my responsibilities.
And thus what makes categorical imperatives possible is this, that the idea of freedom makes me a member of an intelligible world, in consequence of which, if I were nothing else, all my actions would always conform to the autonomy of the will; but as I at the same time intuite myself as a member of the world of sense, they ought so to conform, and this categorical "ought" implies a synthetic a priori proposition, inasmuch as besides my will as affected by sensible desires there is added further the idea of the same will but as belonging to the world of the understanding, pure and practical of itself, which contains the supreme condition according to reason of the former will; precisely as to the intuitions of sense there are added concepts of the understanding which of themselves signify nothing but regular form in general and in this way synthetic a priori propositions become possible, on which all knowledge of physical nature rests.
What makes categorical imperatives possible is that the idea of freedom identifies me as part of an intelligible world. Therefore, if I were nothing else, all my actions would always align with the autonomy of the will. However, since I also see myself as part of the sensory world, my actions should align with this as well. This categorical "ought" suggests a synthetic a priori proposition, because in addition to my will being influenced by sensory desires, there is also the idea of that same will as part of the world of understanding, which is pure and practical by itself. This understanding contains the ultimate condition according to reason for the former will. Just as concepts of understanding add to sensory intuitions, signifying nothing more than a general regular form, synthetic a priori propositions become possible, forming the basis for all knowledge of physical nature.
The practical use of common human reason confirms this reasoning. There is no one, not even the most consummate villain, provided only that he is otherwise accustomed to the use of reason, who, when we set before him examples of honesty of purpose, of steadfastness in following good maxims, of sympathy and general benevolence (even combined with great sacrifices of advantages and comfort), does not wish that he might also possess these qualities. Only on account of his inclinations and impulses he cannot attain this in himself, but at the same time he wishes to be free from such inclinations which are burdensome to himself. He proves by this that he transfers himself in thought with a will free from the impulses of the sensibility into an order of things wholly different from that of his desires in the field of the sensibility; since he cannot expect to obtain by that wish any gratification of his desires, nor any position which would satisfy any of his actual or supposable inclinations (for this would destroy the pre-eminence of the very idea which wrests that wish from him): he can only expect a greater intrinsic worth of his own person. This better person, however, he imagines himself to be when be transfers himself to the point of view of a member of the world of the understanding, to which he is involuntarily forced by the idea of freedom, i.e., of independence on determining causes of the world of sense; and from this point of view he is conscious of a good will, which by his own confession constitutes the law for the bad will that he possesses as a member of the world of sense- a law whose authority he recognizes while transgressing it. What he morally "ought" is then what he necessarily "would," as a member of the world of the understanding, and is conceived by him as an "ought" only inasmuch as he likewise considers himself as a member of the world of sense.
The practical use of common human reason confirms this thinking. There’s no one, not even the worst villain, who, when we present them with examples of honesty, commitment to good principles, compassion, and overall kindness (even when it involves significant sacrifices of personal gain and comfort), doesn’t wish to have these qualities too. It’s just that due to their own tendencies and impulses, they can’t achieve this within themselves, yet at the same time, they want to be free from these burdensome inclinations. This shows that they mentally place themselves, with a will free from the impulses of their feelings, into a completely different situation from that of their desires rooted in sensation; since they can’t hope to satisfy their desires or find a situation that would fulfill any of their actual or imagined inclinations (because that would undermine the very ideal that inspires this wish), they can only expect to gain a greater inherent worth in themselves. This better version of themselves, however, is what they imagine when they view things from the perspective of a member of the realm of understanding, to which they are involuntarily drawn by the idea of freedom, meaning independence from the determining factors of the sensory world; and from this perspective, they recognize a good will, which, by their own admission, serves as a law against the bad will they possess as part of the sensory world—a law whose authority they acknowledge even while breaking it. What they morally "ought" to do is then what they necessarily "would" do as a member of the realm of understanding, and they only perceive it as an "ought" because they also see themselves as part of the sensory world.
Of the Extreme Limits of all Practical Philosophy.
All men attribute to themselves freedom of will. Hence come all judgements upon actions as being such as ought to have been done, although they have not been done. However, this freedom is not a conception of experience, nor can it be so, since it still remains, even though experience shows the contrary of what on supposition of freedom are conceived as its necessary consequences. On the other side it is equally necessary that everything that takes place should be fixedly determined according to laws of nature. This necessity of nature is likewise not an empirical conception, just for this reason, that it involves the motion of necessity and consequently of a priori cognition. But this conception of a system of nature is confirmed by experience; and it must even be inevitably presupposed if experience itself is to be possible, that is, a connected knowledge of the objects of sense resting on general laws. Therefore freedom is only an idea of reason, and its objective reality in itself is doubtful; while nature is a concept of the understanding which proves, and must necessarily prove, its reality in examples of experience.
All people believe they have free will. This belief leads to all judgments about actions as if they should have happened, even when they didn't. However, this freedom isn't something we gain through experience, nor can it be, since it still exists even when experience contradicts what we understand as its necessary outcomes based on the idea of freedom. On the other hand, it’s just as essential that everything that happens is strictly determined by the laws of nature. This necessity of nature is also not something we come to know through experience, because it involves the concept of necessity and, consequently, a priori knowledge. Yet, this idea of a natural system is supported by experience, and it must be assumed for experience itself to be possible, meaning a coherent understanding of sensory objects based on general laws. Therefore, freedom is merely an idea of reason, and its objective reality is uncertain; while nature is a concept of understanding that proves, and must necessarily prove, its reality through examples of experience.
There arises from this a dialectic of reason, since the freedom attributed to the will appears to contradict the necessity of nature, and placed between these two ways reason for speculative purposes finds the road of physical necessity much more beaten and more appropriate than that of freedom; yet for practical purposes the narrow footpath of freedom is the only one on which it is possible to make use of reason in our conduct; hence it is just as impossible for the subtlest philosophy as for the commonest reason of men to argue away freedom. Philosophy must then assume that no real contradiction will be found between freedom and physical necessity of the same human actions, for it cannot give up the conception of nature any more than that of freedom.
This creates a conflict of reason, as the freedom assigned to the will seems to clash with the necessity of nature. In this struggle between the two, reason often finds that the path of physical necessity is more established and fitting than that of freedom. However, for practical purposes, the narrow path of freedom is the only one where we can apply reason to our actions. Therefore, it's impossible for even the most complex philosophy or the simplest reasoning of everyday people to dismiss freedom. Philosophy must assume that there is no real contradiction between freedom and the physical necessity of human actions, as it cannot abandon the concept of nature any more than it can of freedom.
Nevertheless, even though we should never be able to comprehend how freedom is possible, we must at least remove this apparent contradiction in a convincing manner. For if the thought of freedom contradicts either itself or nature, which is equally necessary, it must in competition with physical necessity be entirely given up.
Nevertheless, even though we may never fully understand how freedom is possible, we need to resolve this apparent contradiction in a persuasive way. If the idea of freedom conflicts with itself or with nature, which is equally essential, then it must ultimately be abandoned in the face of physical necessity.
It would, however, be impossible to escape this contradiction if the thinking subject, which seems to itself free, conceived itself in the same sense or in the very same relation when it calls itself free as when in respect of the same action it assumes itself to be subject to the law of nature. Hence it is an indispensable problem of speculative philosophy to show that its illusion respecting the contradiction rests on this, that we think of man in a different sense and relation when we call him free and when we regard him as subject to the laws of nature as being part and parcel of nature. It must therefore show that not only can both these very well co-exist, but that both must be thought as necessarily united in the same subject, since otherwise no reason could be given why we should burden reason with an idea which, though it may possibly without contradiction be reconciled with another that is sufficiently established, yet entangles us in a perplexity which sorely embarrasses reason in its theoretic employment. This duty, however, belongs only to speculative philosophy. The philosopher then has no option whether he will remove the apparent contradiction or leave it untouched; for in the latter case the theory respecting this would be bonum vacans, into the possession of which the fatalist would have a right to enter and chase all morality out of its supposed domain as occupying it without title.
It would, however, be impossible to escape this contradiction if the thinking individual, who feels free, understands their freedom in the same way when they call themselves free as they do when, regarding the same action, they see themselves as subject to the laws of nature. Therefore, it's crucial for speculative philosophy to demonstrate that the illusion concerning this contradiction comes from the fact that we think of a person in different ways when we call them free and when we consider them as subject to the laws of nature, as part of nature itself. It must show that not only can both coexist, but they must be understood as necessarily connected in the same individual; otherwise, there would be no reason to burden reason with an idea that, although it might be reconciled with another well-established idea, leads us into confusion that severely complicates reason's theoretical use. This task, however, belongs solely to speculative philosophy. The philosopher has no choice about whether to resolve the apparent contradiction or leave it unresolved; because if they leave it unresolved, the theory would be abandoned, allowing the fatalist to claim it and drive all morality out of its supposed domain as if it had no valid claim to be there.
We cannot however as yet say that we are touching the bounds of practical philosophy. For the settlement of that controversy does not belong to it; it only demands from speculative reason that it should put an end to the discord in which it entangles itself in theoretical questions, so that practical reason may have rest and security from external attacks which might make the ground debatable on which it desires to build.
We can’t really say that we are reaching the limits of practical philosophy yet. The resolution of that debate isn’t part of it; it only requires speculative reason to resolve the conflicts it creates in theoretical questions, allowing practical reason to have peace and protection from outside challenges that could make the foundation it wants to build on questionable.
The claims to freedom of will made even by common reason are founded on the consciousness and the admitted supposition that reason is independent of merely subjectively determined causes which together constitute what belongs to sensation only and which consequently come under the general designation of sensibility. Man considering himself in this way as an intelligence places himself thereby in a different order of things and in a relation to determining grounds of a wholly different kind when on the one hand he thinks of himself as an intelligence endowed with a will, and consequently with causality, and when on the other he perceives himself as a phenomenon in the world of sense (as he really is also), and affirms that his causality is subject to external determination according to laws of nature. Now he soon becomes aware that both can hold good, nay, must hold good at the same time. For there is not the smallest contradiction in saying that a thing in appearance (belonging to the world of sense) is subject to certain laws, of which the very same as a thing or being in itself is independent, and that he must conceive and think of himself in this twofold way, rests as to the first on the consciousness of himself as an object affected through the senses, and as to the second on the consciousness of himself as an intelligence, i.e., as independent on sensible impressions in the employment of his reason (in other words as belonging to the world of understanding).
The claims to free will that even common reasoning makes are based on the awareness and accepted idea that reason is separate from purely subjective influences that make up what is related to sensation alone, and which are generally categorized as sensibility. When a person sees themselves this way as an intelligent being, they place themselves in a different context and relate to determining factors of a completely different nature. On one hand, they consider themselves as an intelligence with a will, and thus with causality; on the other hand, they recognize themselves as a phenomenon in the sensory world (which is indeed true), affirming that their causality is influenced by external factors according to the laws of nature. Soon enough, they realize that both perspectives can be true, and in fact, must coexist. There is no contradiction in saying that something appearing (belonging to the sensory world) is subject to certain laws, while the very same thing, as a thing or being in itself, is independent. The need to understand themselves in this dual way stems, firstly, from the awareness of themselves as an object influenced by the senses, and secondly, from the awareness of themselves as an intelligence, that is, as independent of sensory impressions in their reasoning (in other words, as belonging to the world of understanding).
Hence it comes to pass that man claims the possession of a will which takes no account of anything that comes under the head of desires and inclinations and, on the contrary, conceives actions as possible to him, nay, even as necessary which can only be done by disregarding all desires and sensible inclinations. The causality of such actions lies in him as an intelligence and in the laws of effects and actions [which depend] on the principles of an intelligible world, of which indeed he knows nothing more than that in it pure reason alone independent of sensibility gives the law; moreover since it is only in that world, as an intelligence, that he is his proper self (being as man only the appearance of himself), those laws apply to him directly and categorically, so that the incitements of inclinations and appetites (in other words the whole nature of the world of sense) cannot impair the laws of his volition as an intelligence. Nay, he does not even hold himself responsible for the former or ascribe them to his proper self, i.e., his will: he only ascribes to his will any indulgence which he might yield them if he allowed them to influence his maxims to the prejudice of the rational laws of the will.
So it turns out that people believe they have a will that ignores everything related to desires and inclinations, and instead sees actions as possible, or even necessary, only by disregarding all desires and sensory urges. The cause of these actions is found within them as intelligences and in the laws of effects and actions, which depend on the principles of a world beyond understanding. They only know that in that world, pure reason, independent of emotions, sets the laws. Furthermore, it's only in that world, as intelligences, that they are their true selves—since as humans, they are just appearances of themselves. These laws apply directly and unequivocally to them, meaning that the prompts from inclinations and urges, or basically everything about the sensory world, cannot affect the laws governing their will as intelligences. In fact, they don’t even hold themselves accountable for those inclinations or attribute them to their true selves, meaning their will. They only attribute to their will any indulgence they might give in to if they let these inclinations influence their principles at the expense of the rational laws of the will.
When practical reason thinks itself into a world of understanding, it does not thereby transcend its own limits, as it would if it tried to enter it by intuition or sensation. The former is only a negative thought in respect of the world of sense, which does not give any laws to reason in determining the will and is positive only in this single point that this freedom as a negative characteristic is at the same time conjoined with a (positive) faculty and even with a causality of reason, which we designate a will, namely a faculty of so acting that the principle of the actions shall conform to the essential character of a rational motive, i.e., the condition that the maxim have universal validity as a law. But were it to borrow an object of will, that is, a motive, from the world of understanding, then it would overstep its bounds and pretend to be acquainted with something of which it knows nothing. The conception of a world of the understanding is then only a point of view which reason finds itself compelled to take outside the appearances in order to conceive itself as practical, which would not be possible if the influences of the sensibility had a determining power on man, but which is necessary unless he is to be denied the consciousness of himself as an intelligence and, consequently, as a rational cause, energizing by reason, that is, operating freely. This thought certainly involves the idea of an order and a system of laws different from that of the mechanism of nature which belongs to the sensible world; and it makes the conception of an intelligible world necessary (that is to say, the whole system of rational beings as things in themselves). But it does not in the least authorize us to think of it further than as to its formal condition only, that is, the universality of the maxims of the will as laws, and consequently the autonomy of the latter, which alone is consistent with its freedom; whereas, on the contrary, all laws that refer to a definite object give heteronomy, which only belongs to laws of nature and can only apply to the sensible world.
When practical reason considers itself in a world of understanding, it doesn’t go beyond its own limits, which would happen if it tried to access it through intuition or sensation. The former is merely a negative thought concerning the world of senses, which doesn’t provide any laws for reason in guiding the will and is positive only in the sense that this freedom, as a negative characteristic, is also linked to a positive faculty and even to a causality of reason, which we call a will. This will is the ability to act in a way that aligns the principle of actions with the essential nature of a rational motive, meaning the condition that the maxim has universal validity as a law. However, if it were to take a motive from the world of understanding as an object of will, it would overstep its boundaries and claim to know something it does not. The idea of a world of understanding is simply a perspective that reason feels compelled to adopt beyond appearances to view itself as practical. This wouldn’t be possible if the influences of sensibility had a determining power over humans, but it’s essential unless we deny them the awareness of themselves as intelligences and, therefore, as rational causes acting out of reason and operating freely. This thought involves the concept of an order and a system of laws that differs from the mechanisms of nature belonging to the sensible world. It makes the idea of an intelligible world necessary—that is, the entire system of rational beings as things in themselves. However, it doesn’t allow us to think of it beyond its formal condition, which is the universality of the maxims of the will as laws, and thus the autonomy of the will, which is the only thing consistent with its freedom. In contrast, all laws referring to a specific object create heteronomy, which pertains only to the laws of nature and applies solely to the sensible world.
But reason would overstep all its bounds if it undertook to explain how pure reason can be practical, which would be exactly the same problem as to explain how freedom is possible.
But reason would go beyond its limits if it tried to explain how pure reason can be practical, which is exactly the same issue as explaining how freedom is possible.
For we can explain nothing but that which we can reduce to laws, the object of which can be given in some possible experience. But freedom is a mere idea, the objective reality of which can in no wise be shown according to laws of nature, and consequently not in any possible experience; and for this reason it can never be comprehended or understood, because we cannot support it by any sort of example or analogy. It holds good only as a necessary hypothesis of reason in a being that believes itself conscious of a will, that is, of a faculty distinct from mere desire (namely, a faculty of determining itself to action as an intelligence, in other words, by laws of reason independently on natural instincts). Now where determination according to laws of nature ceases, there all explanation ceases also, and nothing remains but defence, i.e., the removal of the objections of those who pretend to have seen deeper into the nature of things, and thereupon boldly declare freedom impossible. We can only point out to them that the supposed contradiction that they have discovered in it arises only from this, that in order to be able to apply the law of nature to human actions, they must necessarily consider man as an appearance: then when we demand of them that they should also think of him qua intelligence as a thing in itself, they still persist in considering him in this respect also as an appearance. In this view it would no doubt be a contradiction to suppose the causality of the same subject (that is, his will) to be withdrawn from all the natural laws of the sensible world. But this contradiction disappears, if they would only bethink themselves and admit, as is reasonable, that behind the appearances there must also lie at their root (although hidden) the things in themselves, and that we cannot expect the laws of these to be the same as those that govern their appearances.
We can only explain things that can be reduced to laws, which can be described in some possible experience. However, freedom is just an idea, and its objective reality cannot be demonstrated according to natural laws, and therefore, not in any possible experience. For this reason, it can never be fully grasped or understood, as we can't support it with any examples or analogies. It only stands as a necessary hypothesis of reason in a being that feels it's conscious of a will, meaning a faculty distinct from mere desire (specifically, a faculty that allows it to decide on actions as an intelligence, or in other words, by reason independent of natural instincts). Once the determination according to laws of nature stops, all explanation halts too, leaving only defense, which means addressing the concerns of those who claim to have a deeper understanding of reality and boldly assert that freedom is impossible. We can only point out that the supposed contradiction they find arises from their need to treat humans as appearances to apply natural laws to human actions. When we ask them to consider humans as intelligences in themselves, they continue to view them merely as appearances. In this context, it would indeed seem contradictory to suppose that the same subject's causality (that is, their will) is exempt from all natural laws of the sensible world. However, this contradiction vanishes if they would just reflect and accept that behind appearances there must also be hidden things in themselves, and we shouldn't expect the laws governing these to be the same as those that apply to their appearances.
The subjective impossibility of explaining the freedom of the will is identical with the impossibility of discovering and explaining an interest * which man can take in the moral law. Nevertheless he does actually take an interest in it, the basis of which in us we call the moral feeling, which some have falsely assigned as the standard of our moral judgement, whereas it must rather be viewed as the subjective effect that the law exercises on the will, the objective principle of which is furnished by reason alone.
The difficulty in explaining the freedom of will is the same as the challenge of identifying and explaining any interest a person can have in the moral law. However, people do have an interest in it, which we refer to as moral feeling. Some have mistakenly viewed this as the standard for our moral judgment, whereas it should be seen as the subjective impact that the law has on the will, with the objective principle provided solely by reason.
* Interest is that by which reason becomes practical, i.e., a cause determining the will. Hence we say of rational beings only that they take an interest in a thing; irrational beings only feel sensual appetites. Reason takes a direct interest in action then only when the universal validity of its maxims is alone sufficient to determine the will. Such an interest alone is pure. But if it can determine the will only by means of another object of desire or on the suggestion of a particular feeling of the subject, then reason takes only an indirect interest in the action, and, as reason by itself without experience cannot discover either objects of the will or a special feeling actuating it, this latter interest would only be empirical and not a pure rational interest. The logical interest of reason (namely, to extend its insight) is never direct, but presupposes purposes for which reason is employed.
* Interest is what makes reason practical, meaning it is a cause that influences our will. That's why we say only rational beings take an interest in things; irrational beings only experience basic desires. Reason directly engages with action only when the universal validity of its principles is enough to influence the will. This type of interest is purely rational. However, if reason can influence the will only through another object of desire or based on a specific feeling of the individual, then it is engaging with the action indirectly. Since reason alone, without experience, cannot identify what the will wants or a specific feeling driving it, this kind of interest is empirical rather than purely rational. The logical interest of reason (which is to enhance its understanding) is never direct; it assumes goals for which reason is used.
In order indeed that a rational being who is also affected through the senses should will what reason alone directs such beings that they ought to will, it is no doubt requisite that reason should have a power to infuse a feeling of pleasure or satisfaction in the fulfilment of duty, that is to say, that it should have a causality by which it determines the sensibility according to its own principles. But it is quite impossible to discern, i.e., to make it intelligible a priori, how a mere thought, which itself contains nothing sensible, can itself produce a sensation of pleasure or pain; for this is a particular kind of causality of which as of every other causality we can determine nothing whatever a priori; we must only consult experience about it. But as this cannot supply us with any relation of cause and effect except between two objects of experience, whereas in this case, although indeed the effect produced lies within experience, yet the cause is supposed to be pure reason acting through mere ideas which offer no object to experience, it follows that for us men it is quite impossible to explain how and why the universality of the maxim as a law, that is, morality, interests. This only is certain, that it is not because it interests us that it has validity for us (for that would be heteronomy and dependence of practical reason on sensibility, namely, on a feeling as its principle, in which case it could never give moral laws), but that it interests us because it is valid for us as men, inasmuch as it had its source in our will as intelligences, in other words, in our proper self, and what belongs to mere appearance is necessarily subordinated by reason to the nature of the thing in itself.
To ensure that a rational being, who is also influenced by their senses, is motivated to act according to what reason dictates, it's essential that reason has the ability to create a sense of pleasure or satisfaction when fulfilling a duty. This means that reason must have a way of influencing our feelings based on its own principles. However, it's impossible to understand a priori how a simple thought, which lacks any sensory content, can produce a feeling of pleasure or pain. This is a specific kind of causality that we cannot determine without experience. Yet, experience can only provide us with cause-and-effect relationships between two objects we can observe, while in this scenario, the effect may be within our experience, but the cause is pure reason acting through abstract ideas, which do not present any observable object. Therefore, it becomes clear that for us humans, it's impossible to explain how and why the universality of a moral maxim, as a law, is compelling. What is certain is that it does not compel us because it interests us (which would imply that our practical reason is dependent on our senses—essentially, that a feeling is its principle—leading to the inability to establish moral laws), but rather, it interests us because it is valid for us as humans. This validity has its origin in our will as rational beings—essentially, in our true selves—while what pertains to mere appearances is necessarily subordinate to the nature of things as they are in themselves.
The question then, "How a categorical imperative is possible," can be answered to this extent, that we can assign the only hypothesis on which it is possible, namely, the idea of freedom; and we can also discern the necessity of this hypothesis, and this is sufficient for the practical exercise of reason, that is, for the conviction of the validity of this imperative, and hence of the moral law; but how this hypothesis itself is possible can never be discerned by any human reason. On the hypothesis, however, that the will of an intelligence is free, its autonomy, as the essential formal condition of its determination, is a necessary consequence. Moreover, this freedom of will is not merely quite possible as a hypothesis (not involving any contradiction to the principle of physical necessity in the connexion of the phenomena of the sensible world) as speculative philosophy can show: but further, a rational being who is conscious of causality through reason, that is to say, of a will (distinct from desires), must of necessity make it practically, that is, in idea, the condition of all his voluntary actions. But to explain how pure reason can be of itself practical without the aid of any spring of action that could be derived from any other source, i.e., how the mere principle of the universal validity of all its maxims as laws (which would certainly be the form of a pure practical reason) can of itself supply a spring, without any matter (object) of the will in which one could antecedently take any interest; and how it can produce an interest which would be called purely moral; or in other words, how pure reason can be practical- to explain this is beyond the power of human reason, and all the labour and pains of seeking an explanation of it are lost.
The question, "How is a categorical imperative possible?" can be answered to some extent by identifying the only hypothesis that makes it possible: the idea of freedom. We can recognize the necessity of this hypothesis, and that's enough for the practical exercise of reason, meaning, for believing in the validity of this imperative and, consequently, the moral law. However, how this hypothesis itself is possible can never be understood by human reason. On the hypothesis that an intelligent will is free, its autonomy, which is the essential formal condition for its determination, is a necessary outcome. Furthermore, this freedom of will is not just a possible hypothesis (not contradicting the principle of physical necessity in the connection of the phenomena of the sensible world), as speculative philosophy can demonstrate. Additionally, a rational being who is aware of causality through reason—that is, of a will distinct from desires—must necessarily regard it as the practical condition, in principle, for all of their voluntary actions. But explaining how pure reason can be practical on its own, without relying on any external motivation, is beyond human capability. It involves understanding how the mere principle of the universal validity of its maxims as laws could independently provide a motive, without any object of the will that one might naturally care about, and how it can generate an interest described as purely moral. In other words, explaining how pure reason can be practical is beyond the reach of human reason, and all efforts to seek such an explanation are in vain.
It is just the same as if I sought to find out how freedom itself is possible as the causality of a will. For then I quit the ground of philosophical explanation, and I have no other to go upon. I might indeed revel in the world of intelligences which still remains to me, but although I have an idea of it which is well founded, yet I have not the least knowledge of it, nor an I ever attain to such knowledge with all the efforts of my natural faculty of reason. It signifies only a something that remains over when I have eliminated everything belonging to the world of sense from the actuating principles of my will, serving merely to keep in bounds the principle of motives taken from the field of sensibility; fixing its limits and showing that it does not contain all in all within itself, but that there is more beyond it; but this something more I know no further. Of pure reason which frames this ideal, there remains after the abstraction of all matter, i.e., knowledge of objects, nothing but the form, namely, the practical law of the universality of the maxims, and in conformity with this conception of reason in reference to a pure world of understanding as a possible efficient cause, that is a cause determining the will. There must here be a total absence of springs; unless this idea of an intelligible world is itself the spring, or that in which reason primarily takes an interest; but to make this intelligible is precisely the problem that we cannot solve.
It's just like trying to understand how freedom can exist as the cause of a will. When I do this, I step away from the foundation of philosophical explanation, and I have no other basis to rely on. I could immerse myself in the realm of intelligences that is still accessible to me, but even though I have a well-founded idea of it, I lack any true knowledge of it, and I can never gain such knowledge despite all my efforts with my natural capacity for reason. It only represents something that remains after I’ve removed everything related to the sensory world from the driving principles of my will, which only serves to contain the motivations drawn from the realm of sensations; it defines its limits and shows that there is more beyond it, yet I don’t know anything more about this "something more." From pure reason, which constructs this ideal, all that’s left after stripping away all matter—i.e., knowledge of objects—is the form, specifically, the practical law of the universality of maxims. In line with this concept of reason concerning a pure world of understanding as a possible efficient cause, meaning a cause that influences the will, there must be a complete absence of motivations. Unless this idea of an intelligible world itself serves as the motivation, or is what reason is primarily concerned with; but making this intelligible is exactly the challenge we cannot resolve.
Here now is the extreme limit of all moral inquiry, and it is of great importance to determine it even on this account, in order that reason may not on the one hand, to the prejudice of morals, seek about in the world of sense for the supreme motive and an interest comprehensible but empirical; and on the other hand, that it may not impotently flap its wings without being able to move in the (for it) empty space of transcendent concepts which we call the intelligible world, and so lose itself amidst chimeras. For the rest, the idea of a pure world of understanding as a system of all intelligences, and to which we ourselves as rational beings belong (although we are likewise on the other side members of the sensible world), this remains always a useful and legitimate idea for the purposes of rational belief, although all knowledge stops at its threshold, useful, namely, to produce in us a lively interest in the moral law by means of the noble ideal of a universal kingdom of ends in themselves (rational beings), to which we can belong as members then only when we carefully conduct ourselves according to the maxims of freedom as if they were laws of nature.
Here is the ultimate boundary of all moral exploration, and it's crucial to define it for several reasons. First, so that reason doesn't, to the detriment of morality, search in the sensory world for the highest motive and a comprehensible but empirical interest. Second, to prevent it from flailing without direction in the void of transcendent concepts we call the intelligible world, losing itself in illusions. Additionally, the idea of a pure realm of understanding as a system of all intelligences, which includes us as rational beings (even though we are also part of the sensory world), remains a valuable and valid concept for rational belief. However, all knowledge stops at its threshold. This idea inspires us with a strong interest in the moral law through the noble ideal of a universal kingdom of ends in themselves (rational beings), a kingdom we can only join if we conduct ourselves according to the principles of freedom as if they were natural laws.
CONCLUDING REMARK
The speculative employment of reason with respect to nature leads to the absolute necessity of some supreme cause of the world: the practical employment of reason with a view to freedom leads also to absolute necessity, but only of the laws of the actions of a rational being as such. Now it is an essential principle of reason, however employed, to push its knowledge to a consciousness of its necessity (without which it would not be rational knowledge). It is, however, an equally essential restriction of the same reason that it can neither discern the necessity of what is or what happens, nor of what ought to happen, unless a condition is supposed on which it is or happens or ought to happen. In this way, however, by the constant inquiry for the condition, the satisfaction of reason is only further and further postponed. Hence it unceasingly seeks the unconditionally necessary and finds itself forced to assume it, although without any means of making it comprehensible to itself, happy enough if only it can discover a conception which agrees with this assumption. It is therefore no fault in our deduction of the supreme principle of morality, but an objection that should be made to human reason in general, that it cannot enable us to conceive the absolute necessity of an unconditional practical law (such as the categorical imperative must be). It cannot be blamed for refusing to explain this necessity by a condition, that is to say, by means of some interest assumed as a basis, since the law would then cease to be a supreme law of reason. And thus while we do not comprehend the practical unconditional necessity of the moral imperative, we yet comprehend its incomprehensibility, and this is all that can be fairly demanded of a philosophy which strives to carry its principles up to the very limit of human reason.
The speculative use of reason concerning nature leads to the absolute necessity of a supreme cause for the world. The practical use of reason aimed at freedom also leads to absolute necessity, but only in terms of the laws governing the actions of a rational being. It’s a fundamental principle of reason, no matter how it's used, to push its understanding toward a recognition of its necessity (without which it wouldn't count as rational knowledge). However, it's equally a crucial limitation of reason that it can't grasp the necessity of what is, what happens, or what should happen unless there's a condition thought to underlie what is, happens, or should happen. Therefore, through the continuous search for this condition, the satisfaction of reason is only postponed further and further. As a result, it constantly seeks the unconditionally necessary and finds itself compelled to assume it, even though it lacks a means to understand it, content if it can just discover a concept that aligns with this assumption. So, it’s not a failing in our deduction of the supreme principle of morality, but rather a shortcoming of human reason in general, that it can't help us conceive the absolute necessity of an unconditional practical law (like the categorical imperative must be). It can't be faulted for rejecting an explanation of this necessity based on some assumed interest, since doing so would mean that the law is no longer a supreme law of reason. Thus, while we don’t grasp the practical unconditional necessity of the moral imperative, we do understand its incomprehensibility, and that’s all that can reasonably be asked of a philosophy that aims to push its principles to the very limit of human reason.
THE END
Download ePUB
If you like this ebook, consider a donation!