This is a modern-English version of The Prince, originally written by Machiavelli, Niccolò.
It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling,
and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If
you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.
Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.

THE PRINCE
BY
NICCOLÒ MACHIAVELLI
TRANSLATED INTO ENGLISH BY
LUIGI RICCI
HUMPHREY MILFORD
OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS
LONDON EDINBURGH GLASGOW
NEW YORK TORONTO MELBOURNE CAPETOWN
BOMBAY CALCUTTA AND MADRAS
1909
PREFACE
Of all Machiavelli's works The Prince is undoubtedly the greatest; and a new English edition of it is likely to be welcome to all those who have not the advantage of reading it in the classical Italian original.
Of all of Machiavelli's works, The Prince is definitely the best; and a new English edition is probably going to be appreciated by anyone who can't read it in the original classical Italian.
For a true appreciation of Machiavelli, impossible in a brief Preface, I must refer the English reader to Macaulay's Essay on the Italian historian and statesman.[1] In it he will see how our Author's ideas and work were wrongfully and wilfully misinterpreted by the very men who, while profiting by his wisdom, have with great ingratitude criticised the statesman and defamed his name, as that of the inventor of the worst political system ever imagined. Yet, as his whole life was an indefatigable and unremitting endeavour to secure for his native Florence a good and popular government, and as he lost his great office of Secretary to the Florentine Republic on account of his avowed liberal opinions, it is not only unjust but ridiculous to accuse him of helping tyrants to enslave the people. What he did was to show in the most deliberate and in the plainest way the arts by which free peoples were made slaves; and, had his words of advice been always heeded, no tyrant in Italy or elsewhere could have been successful in his policy. That he was not listened to, and his advice scorned and spurned, was not Machiavelli's fault.
To truly appreciate Machiavelli, which is impossible in a brief Preface, I have to point the English reader to Macaulay's Essay on the Italian historian and statesman.[1] In it, you’ll see how our author’s ideas and work were wrongly and deliberately misinterpreted by the very people who, while benefiting from his wisdom, have ingratitude criticized the statesman and tarnished his name, as if he were the creator of the worst political system imaginable. However, since his entire life was a tireless effort to secure a good and popular government for his hometown of Florence, and since he lost his significant role as Secretary to the Florentine Republic because of his openly liberal views, it’s not just unfair but absurd to accuse him of helping tyrants oppress the people. What he did was clearly demonstrate the tactics that turn free people into slaves; and if his advice had always been followed, no tyrant in Italy or anywhere else would have succeeded in their policies. The fact that he wasn’t listened to, and his advice was dismissed and rejected, was not Machiavelli's fault.
Those who still share the opinion of his interested detractors should read his private correspondence with the leaders of liberal ideas in Italy—many of his letters being still left unpublished in the MS. Collection of Giuliano Ricci in the National Library, in the Riccardiana Library (No. 2467), in the Government Archives (Strozzi, Nos. 133 and 1028) of Florence, in the Barberini Library, and in the Collezione Gonnelli of the Palatine Library in Rome.
Those who still agree with his self-serving critics should read his private letters with the leaders of progressive thought in Italy—many of his letters are still unpublished in the MS. Collection of Giuliano Ricci at the National Library, in the Riccardiana Library (No. 2467), in the Government Archives (Strozzi, Nos. 133 and 1028) of Florence, in the Barberini Library, and in the Gonnelli Collection of the Palatine Library in Rome.
LUIGI RICCI.
LUIGI RICCI.
22 ALBEMARLE STREET,
LONDON, W.
22 Albemarle St,
London, W.
CONTENTS
NICCOLÒ MACHIAVELLI TO LORENZO THE MAGNIFICENT
Chapter
1. The various kinds of Government and the ways by which they are established.
2. Of Hereditary Monarchies.
3. Of Mixed Monarchies.
4. Why the Kingdom of Darius, occupied by Alexander, did not rebel against the successors of the latter after his death.
5. The way to govern Cities or Dominions that, previous to being occupied, lived under their own Laws.
6. Of New Dominions which have been acquired by one's own Arms and Powers.
7. Of New Dominions acquired by the Power of others or by Fortune.
8. Of those who have attained the position of Prince by villainy.
9. Of the Civic Principality.
10. How the strength of all States should be measured.
11. Of Ecclesiastical Principalities.
12. The different kinds of Militia and Mercenary Soldiers.
13. Of Auxiliary, Mixed, and Native Troops
14. What the duties of a Prince are with regard to the Militia.
15. Of the things for which Men, and especially Princes, are praised or blamed.
16. Of Liberality and Niggardliness.
17. Of Cruelty and Clemency, and whether it is better to be loved or feared.
18. In what way Princes must keep faith.
19. That we must avoid being despised and hated.
20. Whether Fortresses and other things which Princes often make are useful or injurious.
21. How a Prince must act in order to gain reputation.
22. Of the Secretaries of Princes.
23. How Flatterers must be shunned.
24. Why the Princes of Italy have lost their States.
25. How much Fortune can do in human affairs, and how it may be opposed.
26. Exhortation to liberate Italy from the Barbarians.
NICCOLÒ MACHIAVELLI TO LORENZO THE MAGNIFICENT
Chapter
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__. The various forms of government and how they are established.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__. On Hereditary Monarchies.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_2__. On Mixed Monarchies.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_3__. Why the Kingdom of Darius, conquered by Alexander, did not revolt against his successors after his death.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_4__. The approach to governing cities or regions that were self-governing before they were taken over.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_5__. Regarding new territories acquired through one’s own strength and capabilities.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_6__. Regarding new territories gained through the influence of others or by chance.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_7__. On those who have become Prince through deception.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_8__. On the Civic Principality.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_9__. How to assess the strength of all states.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_10__. On Ecclesiastical Principalities.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_11__. The different kinds of militias and mercenary forces.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_12__. On Auxiliaries, Mixed Forces, and Native Troops.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_13__. What a Prince's obligations are to the military.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_14__. For the qualities for which people, especially rulers, are praised or criticized.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_15__. On Generosity and Stinginess.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_16__. On cruelty and compassion, and whether it’s better to be loved or feared.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_17__. How Princes should honor their promises.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_18__. The importance of avoiding being looked down upon or disliked.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_19__. Whether fortresses and similar structures that princes often build are beneficial or detrimental.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_20__. How a Prince should conduct himself to enhance his reputation.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_21__. On the Secretaries of Princes.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_22__. How to steer clear of flatterers.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_23__. Why the Princes of Italy have lost their lands.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_24__. The extent of luck's influence in our lives and how it can be countered.
__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_25__. A call to liberate Italy from the Barbarians.
NICCOLÒ MACHIAVELLI
TO
LORENZO THE MAGNIFICENT
SON OF PIERO DI MEDICI
It is customary for those who wish to gain the favour of a prince to endeavour to do so by offering him gifts of those things which they hold most precious, or in which they know him to take especial delight. In this way princes are often presented with horses, arms, cloth of gold, gems, and such-like ornaments worthy of their grandeur. In my desire, however, to offer to Your Highness some humble testimony of my devotion, I have been unable to find among my possessions anything which I hold so dear or esteem so highly as that knowledge of the deeds of great men which I have acquired through a long experience of modern events and a constant study of the past.
It’s common for people who want to win a prince’s favor to try to do so by giving him gifts of their most valued possessions or things they know he especially enjoys. Because of this, princes often receive horses, weapons, fine fabrics, jewels, and other splendid items that match their status. However, in my wish to present Your Highness with a simple sign of my loyalty, I haven’t found anything in my belongings that I cherish as much or value as highly as the knowledge I've gained about the actions of great men through years of observing modern events and studying history.
The results of my long observations and reflections are recorded in the little volume which I now offer to Your Highness: and although I deem this work unworthy of Your Highness's notice, yet my confidence in your humanity assures me that you will accept it, knowing that it is not in my power to offer you a greater gift than that of enabling you to understand in the shortest possible time all those things which I have learnt through danger and suffering in the course of many years. I have not sought to adorn my work with long phrases or high-sounding words or any of those allurements and ornaments with which many writers seek to embellish their books, as I desire no honour for my work but such as its truth and the gravity of its subject may justly deserve. Nor will it, I trust, be deemed presumptuous on the part of a man of humble and obscure condition to attempt to discuss and criticise the government of princes; for in the same way that landscape painters station themselves in the valleys in order to draw mountains or elevated ground, and ascend an eminence in order to get a good view of the plains, so it is necessary to be a prince to be able to know thoroughly the nature of a people, and to know the nature of princes one must be one of the populace.
The results of my long observations and reflections are recorded in the little book I'm presenting to Your Highness. While I consider this work unworthy of your attention, I trust in your kindness and believe you will accept it, understanding that I can offer you no greater gift than helping you quickly grasp all the insights I've gained through years of danger and suffering. I haven’t tried to embellish my work with fancy phrases or elaborate words, as I seek no acclaim for my efforts beyond what the truth and seriousness of the topic deserve. I hope it won’t seem arrogant for someone of humble and modest standing to attempt to discuss and critique the governance of princes; just as landscape painters position themselves in valleys to capture mountains or elevated land and climb high to view the plains, one must be a prince to fully understand the nature of a people, and to understand princes, one must be part of the populace.
May I trust, therefore, that Your Highness will accept this little gift in the spirit in which it is offered; and if Your Highness will deign to peruse it, you will recognise in it my ardent desire that you may attain to that grandeur which fortune and your own merits presage for you.
May I trust that Your Highness will accept this small gift in the spirit it’s given; and if Your Highness takes the time to read it, you will see my sincere wish for you to achieve the greatness that both luck and your own talents promise for you.
And should Your Highness gaze down from the summit of that eminence towards this humble spot, you will recognise the great and unmerited sufferings inflicted on me by a cruel fate.
And if Your Highness looks down from the top of that hill toward this modest place, you will see the great and undeserved hardships that a cruel fate has caused me.
THE PRINCE
CHAPTER I
THE VARIOUS KINDS OF GOVERNMENT AND THE WAYS BY WHICH THEY ARE ESTABLISHED
All states and dominions which hold or have held sway over mankind are either republics or monarchies. Monarchies are either hereditary ones, in which the rulers have been for many years of the same family, or else they are those of recent foundation. The newly founded ones are either entirely new, as was Milan to Francesco Sforza, or else they are, as it were, new members grafted on to the hereditary possessions of the prince that annexes them, as is the kingdom of Naples to the King of Spain. The dominions thus acquired have either been previously accustomed to the rule of another prince, or else have been free states, and they are annexed either by force of arms of the prince, or of others, or else fall to him by good fortune or merit.
All states and territories that have ruled or currently rule over people are either republics or monarchies. Monarchies can be hereditary, where the rulers have belonged to the same family for many years, or they can be newly established. The newly established ones are either completely new, like Milan to Francesco Sforza, or they are new territories added to the hereditary lands of the prince who annexes them, like the kingdom of Naples to the King of Spain. The territories gained this way have either been under the rule of another prince before or have been free states, and they are annexed either by the prince's military force, the force of others, or they come to him through luck or merit.
CHAPTER II
OF HEREDITARY MONARCHIES
I will not here speak of republics, having already treated of them fully in another place. I will deal only with monarchies, and will show how the various kinds described above can be governed and maintained. In the first place, in hereditary states accustomed to the reigning family the difficulty of maintaining them is far less than in new monarchies; for it is sufficient not to exceed the ancestral usages, and to accommodate one's self to accidental circumstances; in this way such a prince, if of ordinary ability, will always be able to maintain his position, unless some very exceptional and excessive force deprives him of it; and even if he be thus deprived of it, on the slightest misfortune happening to the new occupier, he will be able to regain it.
I won’t talk about republics here, since I’ve already covered them in another place. I’ll focus on monarchies and explain how the different types described above can be governed and maintained. First, in hereditary states where the ruling family is established, it’s much easier to keep control than in new monarchies. It’s enough not to stray too far from traditional practices and to adapt to unexpected situations. In this way, a prince of average skill can usually hold onto his position, unless an extraordinary and overwhelming force takes it away. Even if he does lose it, he can regain it at the first sign of trouble for the new occupant.
We have in Italy the example of the Duke of Ferrara, who was able to withstand the assaults of the Venetians in the year '84, and of Pope Julius in the year '10, for no other reason than because of the antiquity of his family in that dominion. In as much as the legitimate prince has less cause and less necessity to give offence, it is only natural that he should be more loved; and, if no extraordinary vices make him hated, it is only reasonable for his subjects to be naturally attached to him, the memories and causes of innovations being forgotten in the long period over which his rule has existed; whereas one change always leaves the way prepared for the introduction of another.
We see in Italy the example of the Duke of Ferrara, who was able to resist the attacks from the Venetians in the year '84 and from Pope Julius in the year '10, simply because of his family's long-standing presence in that region. Since a legitimate ruler has less reason and less need to cause offense, it’s only natural that he should be more loved; and if he doesn’t have any major flaws that make him disliked, it makes sense for his subjects to feel a strong loyalty to him, as the memories and reasons for past changes fade over time. On the other hand, every change tends to pave the way for another.
CHAPTER III
OF MIXED MONARCHIES
But it is in the new monarchy that difficulties really exist. Firstly, if it is not entirely new, but a member as it were of a mixed state, its disorders spring at first from a natural difficulty which exists in all new dominions, because men change masters willingly, hoping to better themselves; and this belief makes them take arms against their rulers, in which they are deceived, as experience shows them that they have gone from bad to worse. This is the result of another very natural cause, which is the necessary harm inflicted on those over whom the prince obtains dominion, both by his soldiers and by an infinite number of other injuries unavoidably caused by his occupation.
But this is where the real problems arise in a new monarchy. First, if it’s not entirely new but part of a mixed state, its troubles stem from a common challenge seen in all new territories: people tend to switch rulers, hoping for a better situation. This expectation leads them to take up arms against their leaders, but they soon realize, as experience teaches, that their situation often worsens. This happens due to another natural cause: the unavoidable harm inflicted on the people under the prince's control, both from his soldiers and from countless other injuries that result from his rule.
Thus you find enemies in all those whom you have injured by occupying that dominion, and you cannot maintain the friendship of those who have helped you to obtain this possession, as you will not be able to fulfil their expectations, nor can you use strong measures with them, being under an obligation to them; for which reason, however strong your armies may be, you will always need the favour of the inhabitants to take possession of a province. It was from these causes that Louis XII. of France, though able to occupy Milan without trouble, immediately lost it, and the forces of Ludovico alone were sufficient to take it from him the first time, for the inhabitants who had willingly opened their gates to him, finding themselves deluded in the hopes they had cherished and not obtaining those benefits that they had anticipated, could not bear the vexatious rule of their new prince.
So, you find enemies in everyone you've hurt by taking over that territory, and you can't keep the friendship of those who helped you gain this possession, because you won't meet their expectations. You also can't act harshly towards them since you owe them something. For this reason, no matter how strong your armies are, you’ll always need the support of the locals to hold onto a province. This is why Louis XII of France, although he could take Milan easily, lost it right away. Ludovico's forces alone were enough to reclaim it from him the first time, because the locals, who had eagerly opened their gates to him, felt deceived by the hopes they had and didn't receive the benefits they expected. They simply couldn't tolerate the irritating leadership of their new ruler.
It is indeed true that, after reconquering the rebel territories they are not so easily lost again, for the ruler is now, by the fact of the rebellion, less averse to secure his position by punishing offenders, investigating any suspicious circumstances, and strengthening himself in weak places. So that although the mere appearance of such a person as Duke Ludovico on the frontier was sufficient to cause France to lose Milan the first time, to make her lose her grip of it the second time was only possible when all the world was against her, and after her enemies had been defeated and driven out of Italy; which was the result of the causes above mentioned. Nevertheless it was taken from her both the first and the second time. The general causes of the first loss have been already discussed; it remains now to be seen what were the causes of the second loss and by what means France could have avoided it, or what measures might have been taken by another ruler in that position which were not taken by the King of France. Be it observed, therefore, that those states which on annexation are united to a previously existing state may or may not be of the same nationality and language. If they are, it is very easy to hold them, especially if they are not accustomed to freedom; and to possess them securely it suffices that the family of the princes which formerly governed them be extinct. For the rest, their old condition not being disturbed, and there being no dissimilarity of customs, the people settle down quietly under their new rulers, as is seen in the case of Burgundy, Brittany, Gascony, and Normandy, which have been so long united to France; and although there may be some slight differences of language, the customs of the people are nevertheless similar, and they can get along well together, and whoever obtains possession of them and wishes to retain them must bear in mind two things: the one, that the blood of their old rulers is extinct; the other, to make no alteration either in their laws or in their taxes; in this way they will in a very short space of time become united with their old possessions and form one state. But when dominions are acquired in a province differing in language, laws, and customs, the difficulties to be overcome are great, and it requires good fortune as well as great industry to retain them; one of the best and most certain means of doing so would be for the new ruler to take up his residence in them. This would render their possession more secure and durable, it is what the Turk has done in Greece; in spite of all the other measures taken by him to hold that state, it would not have been possible to retain it had he not gone to live there. Being on the spot, disorders can be seen as they arise and can quickly be remedied, but living at a distance, they are only heard of when they get beyond remedy. Besides which, the province is not despoiled by your officials, the subjects are pleased with the easy accessibility of their prince; and wishing to be loyal they have more reason to love him, and should they be otherwise they will have greater cause to fear him.
It’s true that once rebel territories are taken back, they’re not easily lost again. The ruler, having faced the rebellion, is now more inclined to secure their position by punishing wrongdoers, checking for any suspicious activities, and reinforcing their weak areas. So while the mere presence of someone like Duke Ludovico on the border was enough to make France lose Milan the first time, the second loss was only possible when everyone was against her, and after her enemies had been defeated and pushed out of Italy; this resulted from the factors mentioned earlier. Still, both times, it was taken from her. The general reasons for the first loss have already been discussed; now we need to look at the reasons for the second loss and how France could have avoided it, or what actions another ruler in that position might have taken that the King of France did not. It's important to note that states which become part of an existing state might share the same nationality and language or not. If they do, it’s easy to hold onto those territories, especially if the people aren’t used to freedom. To securely possess these regions, it’s enough for the ruling family that once governed them to be extinct. With the old way of life left undisturbed and no significant differences in customs, the people will settle down under their new rulers, as seen with Burgundy, Brittany, Gascony, and Normandy, which have long been part of France. Even if there are slight language differences, their customs are similar enough for them to coexist peacefully. Whoever takes control of these areas and wishes to keep them must remember two things: first, that the bloodline of their former rulers is gone; and second, not to change their laws or taxes. This way, they will quickly become integrated with their old possessions and form one state. However, when territories are taken in a region that differs in language, laws, and customs, the challenges are significant, and retaining them requires both luck and hard work. One of the best and most reliable ways to succeed is for the new ruler to live there. This would make their claim more secure and lasting, as the Turk has done in Greece; despite all his other efforts to maintain control, it wouldn’t have been possible without relocating there. Being present allows for issues to be seen as they come up and fixed quickly, whereas living far away means problems are only noticed when they’re too serious. Additionally, the province isn’t plundered by officials, the people appreciate having easy access to their prince, and they’re likely to be loyal out of love for him; if they feel otherwise, they’ll have more reason to fear him.
Any external Power who wishes to assail that state will be less disposed to do so; so that as long as he resides there he will be very hard to dispossess. The other and better remedy is to plant colonies in one or two of those places which form as it were the keys of the land, for it is necessary either to do this or to maintain a large force of armed men. The colonies will cost the prince little; with little or no expense on his part, he can send and maintain them; he only injures those whose lands and houses are taken to give to the new inhabitants, and these form but a small proportion of the state, and those who are injured, remaining poor and scattered, can never do any harm to him, and all the others are, on the one hand, not injured and therefore easily pacified; and, on the other, are fearful of offending lest they should be treated like those who have been dispossessed of their property. To conclude, these colonies cost nothing, are more faithful, and give less offence; and the injured parties being poor and scattered are unable to do mischief, as I have shown. For it must be noted, that men must either be caressed or else annihilated; they will revenge themselves for small injuries, but cannot do so for great ones; the injury therefore that we do to a man must be such that we need not fear his vengeance. But by maintaining a garrison instead of colonists, one will spend much more, and consume in guarding it all the revenues of that state, so that the acquisition will result in a loss, besides giving much greater offence, since it injures every one in that state with the quartering of the army on it; which being an inconvenience felt** by all, every one becomes an enemy, and these are enemies which can do mischief, as, though beaten, they remain in their own homes. In every way, therefore, a garrison is as useless as colonies are useful. Further, the ruler of a foreign province as described, should make himself the leader and defender of his less powerful neighbours, and endeavour to weaken the stronger ones, and take care that his possessions are not entered by some foreigner not less powerful than himself, who will always intervene at the request of those who are discontented either through ambition or fear, as was seen when the Ætoli invited the Romans into Greece; and in whatever province they entered, it was always at the request of the inhabitants. And the rule is that when a powerful foreigner enters a province, all the less powerful inhabitants become his adherents, moved by the envy they bear to those ruling over them; so much so that with regard to these minor potentates he has no trouble whatever in winning them over, for they willingly join forces with the state that he has acquired. He has merely to be careful that they do not assume too much power and authority, and he can easily with his own forces and their favour put down those that are powerful and remain in everything the arbiter of that province. And he who does not govern well in this way will soon lose what he has acquired, and while he holds it will meet with infinite difficulty and trouble.
Any external power that wants to attack that state will be less inclined to do so; as long as he stays there, it will be very difficult to remove him. A better solution is to establish colonies in one or two strategic locations that essentially control the land, because it’s necessary to either do this or maintain a large military presence. The colonies won’t cost the prince much; with little to no expense from him, he can send and support them. He only harms those whose land and homes are taken for the new settlers, and they only make up a small part of the state. Those affected will remain poor and scattered, unable to cause any trouble, while the rest are not harmed and can be easily pacified; they fear offending him, worried they might be treated like those who lost their property. Overall, these colonies cost nothing, are more loyal, and create less resentment; those who are harmed are poor and scattered, making it hard for them to create disruptions, as I've explained. It’s important to understand that people must either be treated well or eliminated; they might seek revenge for small slights, but not for major ones. Thus, any injury we inflict must be small enough that we don't fear retaliation. However, relying on a garrison instead of colonies will be much more expensive and will consume all the state's revenue in its upkeep, turning the acquisition into a loss, while also causing greater offense since it disrupts everyone in the state due to the military presence. This is a burden felt by all, making everyone an enemy, and these enemies can cause harm because, though defeated, they remain in their homes. Therefore, in every way, a garrison is as ineffective as colonies are beneficial. Additionally, a ruler of a foreign province should position himself as the leader and protector of his weaker neighbors and work to weaken the stronger ones. He needs to ensure that his territory is not invaded by someone equally powerful who will always step in at the behest of discontented locals, driven by ambition or fear, as seen when the Aetolians invited the Romans into Greece. Whenever the Romans entered a province, it was always at the request of its people. The rule is that when a strong foreign power enters a province, all the weaker inhabitants align with him, driven by envy toward their current rulers; so much so that he has no trouble gaining their support against these lesser rulers, who will willingly join forces with the new state he has acquired. He just needs to be cautious not to let them gain too much power and authority, and with his own strength and their backing, he can easily subdue the powerful ones, remaining the dominant force in that province. If someone fails to govern effectively in this way, they will soon lose what they have gained, and even while holding on to it, they will face immense challenges and troubles.
The Romans in the provinces they took, always followed this policy; they established colonies, flattered the less powerful without increasing their strength, put down the most powerful and did not allow foreign rulers to obtain influence in them. I will let the single province of Greece suffice as an example. They made friends with the Achæi and the Ætoli, the kingdom of Macedonia was cast down, and Antiochus driven out, nor did they allow the merits of the Achæi or the Ætoli to gain them any increase of territory, nor did the persuasions of Philip induce them to befriend him without lowering him, nor could the power of Antiochus make them consent to allow him to hold any state in that province.
The Romans, in the provinces they conquered, consistently followed this strategy: they set up colonies, won over the less powerful without boosting their strength, subdued the strongest, and prevented foreign rulers from gaining influence. The province of Greece serves as a clear example. They allied with the Achæi and the Ætoli, brought down the kingdom of Macedonia, and expelled Antiochus. They did not let the achievements of the Achæi or the Ætoli earn them any new territory, nor did Philip's appeals convince them to support him at his expense, nor could Antiochus's power persuade them to let him maintain any authority in that province.
For the Romans did in this case what all wise princes should do, who look not only at present dangers but also at future ones and diligently guard against them; for being foreseen they can easily be remedied, but if one waits till they are at hand, the medicine is no longer in time as the malady has become incurable; it happening with this as with those hectic fevers spoken of by doctors, which at their beginning are easy to cure but difficult to recognise, but in course of time when they have not at first been recognised and treated, become easy to recognise and difficult to cure. Thus it happens in matters of state; for knowing afar off (which it is only given to a prudent man to do) the evils that are brewing, they are easily cured. But when, for want of such knowledge, they are allowed to grow so that every one can recognise them, there is no longer any remedy to be found. However, the Romans, observing these disorders while yet remote, were always able to find a remedy, and never allowed them to proceed in order to avoid a war; for they knew that war was not to be avoided, and could be deferred only to the advantage of the other side; they therefore declared war against Philip and Antiochus in Greece, so as not to have to fight them in Italy, though they might at the time have avoided either; this they did not choose to do, never caring to do that which is now every day to be heard in the mouths of our wise men, to enjoy the benefits of time, but preferring those of their own virtue and prudence, for time brings with it all things, and may produce indifferently either good or evil. But let us return to France and examine whether she did any of these things; and I will speak not of Charles, but of Louis as the one whose proceedings can be better seen, as he held possession in Italy for a longer time; you will then see that he did the opposite of all those things which must be done to keep possession of a foreign state. King Louis was called into Italy by the ambition of the Venetians, who wished by his coming to gain half of Lombardy. I will not blame the king for coming nor for the part he took, because wishing to plant his foot in Italy, and not having friends in the country, on the contrary the conduct of King Charles having caused all doors to be closed to him, he was forced to accept what friendships he could find, and his schemes would have quickly been successful if he had made no mistakes in his other proceedings.
For the Romans did in this case what all wise leaders should do, who look not only at current threats but also at future ones and work hard to guard against them; because if they are anticipated, they can be easily fixed, but if one waits until they are upon us, the solution is no longer timely as the problem has become incurable. This is similar to those fevers mentioned by doctors, which at their onset are easy to cure but hard to spot; but over time, if they go unrecognized and untreated, they become easy to recognize and hard to cure. This is true for political matters as well; a wise person can foresee the problems that are brewing and address them easily. However, if these issues are allowed to escalate without such foresight, making them obvious to everyone, then a remedy is no longer available. The Romans, spotting these issues while they were still far off, were always able to find a solution and never let them escalate to avoid war; they understood that war couldn't be avoided and could only be postponed to the other side's advantage. Thus, they declared war on Philip and Antiochus in Greece to avoid fighting them in Italy, even though they could have chosen not to fight at that moment; they didn’t opt for that solution, unlike what we often hear from our contemporary thinkers about making the most of time. Instead, they preferred to rely on their own virtue and wisdom, knowing that time brings both good and bad. But let's turn our focus to France and see if she did any of these things; I will speak not about Charles but Louis, as his actions can be analyzed more clearly since he held power in Italy for a longer period. You will then see that he did the opposite of what was necessary to maintain control over a foreign territory. King Louis was drawn into Italy by the ambitions of the Venetians, who hoped his arrival would help them gain half of Lombardy. I won’t criticize the king for his decision to come or for the role he played, because, wanting to establish his presence in Italy and lacking local allies—due to King Charles's actions closing all doors to him—he had to accept whatever friendships he could find. His plans might have succeeded quickly if he hadn't made errors in his other actions.
The king then having acquired Lombardy regained immediately the reputation lost by Charles. Genoa yielded, the Florentines became his friends, the Marquis of Mantua, the Dukes of Ferrara and Bentivogli, the Lady of Furlì, the Lords of Faenza, Pesaro, Rimini, Camerino, and Piombino, the inhabitants of Lucca, of Pisa, and of Sienna, all approached him with offers of friendship. The Venetians might then have seen the effects of their temerity, how to gain a few lands in Lombardy they had made the king ruler over two-thirds of Italy. Consider how little difficulty the king would have had in maintaining his reputation in Italy if he had observed the rules above given, and kept a firm and sure hold over all those friends of his, who being many in number, and weak, and fearful one of the Church, another of the Venetians, were always obliged to hold fast to him, and by whose aid he could easily make sure of any who were still great. But he was hardly in Milan before he did exactly the opposite, by giving aid to Pope Alexander to occupy the Romagna. Nor did he perceive that, in taking this course, he weakened himself, by casting off his friends and those who had placed themselves at his disposal, and strengthened the Church by adding to the spiritual power, which gives it such authority, further temporal powers. And having made the first mistake, he was obliged to follow it up, whilst, to put a stop to the ambition of Alexander and prevent him becoming ruler of Tuscany, he was forced to come to Italy. And not content with having increased the power of the Church and lost his friends, he now desiring the kingdom of Naples, divided it with the king of Spain; and where he alone was the arbiter of Italy, he now brought in a companion, so that the ambitious of that province who were dissatisfied with him might have some one else to appeal to; and where he might have left in that kingdom a king tributary to him, he dispossessed him in order to bring in another who was capable of driving him out. The desire to acquire possessions is a very natural and ordinary thing, and when those men do it who can do so successfully, they are always praised and not blamed, but when they cannot and yet want to do so at all costs, they make a mistake deserving of great blame. If France, therefore, with her own forces could have taken Naples, she ought to have done so; if she could not she ought not to have divided it. And if the partition of Lombardy with the Venetians is to be excused, as having been the means of allowing the French king to set foot in Italy, this other partition deserves blame, not having the excuse of necessity. Louis had thus made these five mistakes: he had crushed the smaller Powers, increased the power in Italy of one ruler, brought into the land a very powerful foreigner, and he had not come to live there himself, nor had he established any colonies. Still these mistakes might, if he had lived, not have injured him, had he not made the sixth, that of taking the state from the Venetians; for, if he had not strengthened the Church and brought the Spaniards into Italy, it would have been right and necessary to humble them; having once taken those measures, he ought never to have consented to their ruin; because, had the Venetians been strong, it would have kept the others from making attempts on Lombardy, partly because the Venetians would not have consented to any measures by which they did not get it for themselves, and partly because the others would not have wanted to take it from France to give it to Venice, and would not have had the courage to attack both.
The king, after taking Lombardy, quickly regained the reputation that Charles had lost. Genoa gave in, the Florentines became his allies, and the Marquis of Mantua, the Dukes of Ferrara and Bentivogli, the Lady of Furlì, the Lords of Faenza, Pesaro, Rimini, Camerino, and Piombino, along with the people of Lucca, Pisa, and Sienna, all approached him with offers of friendship. The Venetians should have realized the consequences of their boldness; in their quest for a few territories in Lombardy, they made the king the ruler of two-thirds of Italy. Imagine how easy it would have been for the king to maintain his reputation in Italy if he had followed the earlier mentioned rules and kept a strong grip on all his many, weak, and fearful allies—who were scared of the Church and the Venetians—because they were always reliant on him, and through their support, he could easily secure the loyalty of any remaining powerful figures. But as soon as he arrived in Milan, he did the exact opposite by assisting Pope Alexander in taking over the Romagna. He failed to see that this move weakened his position by alienating his allies and those who had supported him, while simultaneously strengthening the Church by granting it additional worldly powers alongside its spiritual authority. Once he made that initial mistake, he had to follow it up; to curb Alexander’s ambition and prevent him from dominating Tuscany, he felt compelled to return to Italy. Not satisfied with bolstering the Church’s power and losing his friends, he aimed for the kingdom of Naples and decided to split it with the king of Spain; instead of being the sole power in Italy, he brought in a partner, allowing any ambitious figures in that region who were unhappy with him an alternative to consult; he also replaced a king who owed allegiance to him with another who could potentially oust him. The desire to acquire property is entirely natural, and those who can do so effectively are usually praised, not criticized. However, when someone tries to acquire territory at all costs and fails, they make a significant error deserving of blame. If France could have seized Naples with its own forces, it should have done so; if it couldn’t, it should not have divided it. The division of Lombardy with the Venetians might be excused since it allowed the French king to enter Italy, but this other division deserves criticism as it lacks the justification of necessity. Louis made five major mistakes: he had crushed smaller powers, heightened the power of a single ruler in Italy, invited a strong foreign power into the region, and he didn’t reside there himself nor established any colonies. Still, these mistakes might not have harmed him if he hadn't made the sixth mistake of taking the state from the Venetians. If he had not bolstered the Church and brought the Spaniards into Italy, it would have been right and necessary to humble them; once he took those actions, he should not have allowed their destruction. If the Venetians had been strong, it would have deterred others from attempting to seize Lombardy, partly because the Venetians wouldn't agree to any arrangements that didn't benefit them, and partly because others wouldn’t have wanted to take it from France just to hand it over to Venice and would have lacked the courage to confront both powers.
If any one urges that King Louis yielded the Romagna to Alexander and the kingdom to Spain in order to avoid war, I reply, with the reasons already given, that one ought never to allow a disorder to take place in order to avoid war, for war is not thereby avoided, but only deferred to your disadvantage. And if others allege the promise given by the king to the pope to undertake that enterprise for him, in return for the dissolution of his marriage and for the cardinalship of Rohan, I reply with what I shall say later on about the faith of princes and how it is to be observed. Thus King Louis lost Lombardy through not observing any of those conditions which have been observed by others who have taken provinces and wished to retain them. Nor is this any miracle, but very reasonable and natural. I spoke of this matter with Cardinal Rohan at Nantes when Valentine, as Cesare Borgia, son of Pope Alexander, was commonly called, was occupying the Romagna, for on Cardinal Rohan saying to me that the Italians did not understand war, I replied that the French did not understand politics, for if they did they would never allow the Church to become so great. And experience shows us that the greatness in Italy of the Church and also of Spain have been caused by France, and her ruin has proceeded from them. From which may be drawn a general rule, which never or very rarely fails, that whoever is the cause of another becoming powerful, is ruined himself; for that power is produced by him either through craft or force; and both of these are suspected by the one that has become powerful.
If anyone argues that King Louis gave up Romagna to Alexander and the kingdom to Spain to avoid war, I respond, based on the reasons I've already provided, that one should never let chaos happen just to avoid conflict, because war doesn't really get avoided, it just gets postponed to your disadvantage. If others point out the promise made by the king to the pope to carry out that mission for him in exchange for the annulment of his marriage and the cardinalship for Rohan, I'll address this later regarding the trustworthiness of princes and how it should be upheld. Thus, King Louis lost Lombardy because he didn't follow any of the conditions that others have adhered to when they seized territories and wanted to keep them. This isn’t surprising but rather reasonable and natural. I discussed this with Cardinal Rohan in Nantes when Valentine, commonly referred to as Cesare Borgia, son of Pope Alexander, was taking control of Romagna. When Cardinal Rohan mentioned that Italians didn’t understand war, I replied that the French didn’t understand politics, because if they did, they would never let the Church gain so much power. Experience shows us that the Church's rise in Italy, as well as Spain’s, has been due to France, and their downfall has come from that. From this, we can derive a general rule that almost always holds true: whoever is responsible for making another powerful ends up ruined themselves; that power arises from them either through cunning or force; and both of these are mistrusted by the one who has gained power.
CHAPTER IV
WHY THE KINGDOM OF DARIUS, OCCUPIED BY ALEXANDER, DID NOT REBEL AGAINST THE SUCCESSORS OF THE LATTER AFTER HIS DEATH.
Considering the difficulties there are in holding a newly acquired state, some may wonder how it came to pass that Alexander the Great became master of Asia in a few years, and had hardly occupied it when he died, from which it might be supposed that the whole state would have rebelled. However, his successors maintained themselves in possession, and had no further difficulty in doing so than those which arose among themselves from their own ambitions.
Considering the challenges of maintaining a newly acquired territory, some might question how Alexander the Great managed to become the ruler of Asia in just a few years and had barely taken control when he died, leading to the assumption that the entire territory would have revolted. However, his successors managed to keep their hold on power and faced no more challenges than those that came from their own ambitions.
I reply that the kingdoms known to history have been governed in two ways: either by a prince and his servants, who, as ministers by his grace and permission, assist in governing the realm; or by a prince and by barons, who hold their positions not by favour of the ruler but by antiquity of blood. Such barons have states and subjects of their own, who recognise them as their lords, and are naturally attached to them. In those states which are governed by a prince and his servants, the prince possesses more authority, because there is no one in the state regarded as a superior besides himself, and if others are obeyed it is merely as ministers and officials of the prince, and no one regards them with any special affection. Examples of these two kinds of government in our own time are the Turk and the King of France. All the Turkish monarchy is governed by one ruler, the others are his servants, and dividing his kingdom into "sangiacates," he sends to them various administrators, and changes or recalls them at his pleasure. But the King of France is surrounded by a large number of ancient nobles, recognised as such by their subjects, and loved by them; they have their prerogatives, which the king cannot deprive them of without danger to himself. Whoever now considers these two states will see that it would be difficult to acquire the state of the Turk; but having conquered it, it would be very easy to hold it.
I respond that the kingdoms known in history have been governed in two ways: either by a prince and his servants, who, as officials by his grace and permission, help govern the realm; or by a prince and barons, who hold their positions not due to the ruler's favor but because of noble lineage. These barons have their own estates and subjects, who recognize them as their lords and are naturally loyal to them. In states governed by a prince and his servants, the prince has more authority because there is no one else in the state seen as superior to him, and if others are obeyed, it is merely as representatives and officials of the prince, with no special loyalty toward them. Examples of these two types of government today are the Turk and the King of France. The Turkish monarchy is ruled by one leader, while others are his servants; he divides his kingdom into "sangiacates," appointing various administrators whom he can change or recall at will. In contrast, the King of France is surrounded by many noble families with ancient titles, recognized and loved by their subjects; they have rights that the king cannot take away without putting himself in danger. Anyone who considers these two states will see that while it would be challenging to acquire the Turkish state, once conquered, it would be much easier to maintain.
The causes of the difficulty of occupying the Turkish kingdom are, that the invader could not be invited by princes of that kingdom, nor hope to facilitate his enterprise by the rebellion of those around him, as will be evident from reasons given above. Because, being all slaves, and bound, it will be more difficult to corrupt them, and even if they were corrupted, little effect could be hoped for, as they would not be able to carry the people with them for the reasons mentioned. Therefore, whoever assaults the Turk must be prepared to meet his united forces, and must rely more on his own strength than on the disorders of others; but having once conquered him, and beaten him in battle so that he can no longer raise armies, nothing else is to be feared except the family of the prince, and if this is extinguished, there is no longer any one to be feared, the others having no credit with the people; and as the victor before the victory could place no hope in them, so he need not fear them afterwards. The contrary is the case in kingdoms governed like that of France, because it is easy to enter them by winning over some baron of the kingdom, there being always some malcontents, and those desiring innovations. These can, for the reasons stated, open the way to you and facilitate victory; but afterwards, if you wish to keep possession, infinite difficulties arise, both from those who have aided you and from those you have oppressed. Nor is it sufficient to extinguish the family of the prince, for there remain those nobles who will make themselves the head of new changes, and being neither able to content them nor exterminate them, you will lose the state whenever an occasion arises. Now if you will consider what was the nature of the government of Darius you will find it similar to the kingdom of the Turk, and therefore Alexander had first to completely overthrow it and seize the country, after which victory, Darius being dead, the state remained secure to Alexander, for the reasons discussed above. And his successors, had they remained united, might have enjoyed it in peace, nor did any tumults arise in the kingdom except those fomented by themselves. But it is impossible to possess with such ease countries constituted like France.
The reasons it's tough to take over the Turkish kingdom are that the invader can't be invited by the princes of that kingdom, nor can he count on a rebellion to help his cause, as explained earlier. Since everyone is enslaved and bound, it’s harder to corrupt them, and even if they are, they wouldn’t have much influence because they can’t rally the people for the same reasons. So, anyone who attacks the Turks needs to be ready to face their united forces and rely more on their own strength than on the chaos among others. However, once they defeat him in battle so that he can no longer raise armies, the only thing left to worry about is the prince’s family, and if that line is extinguished, there’s nobody left to fear, since the rest have no standing with the people. Just as the victor had no hope in them before victory, there’s no reason to fear them afterward. On the other hand, it’s different in kingdoms like France because it’s easy to invade by winning over some of the barons since there are always some discontented people looking for change. These individuals could help pave the way for victory, but once you want to keep control, countless problems arise from both those who supported you and those you oppressed. It’s not enough to eliminate the prince’s family because other nobles will rise to lead new changes, and since you can neither satisfy nor wipe them out, you will lose the state whenever the opportunity arises. If you think about the nature of Darius's government, it resembles the Turkish kingdom, which is why Alexander first had to completely destroy it and seize the land. After that victory, once Darius was dead, the state remained secure for Alexander, for the reasons discussed. If his successors had stayed united, they might have enjoyed peace, and no unrest would have occurred in the kingdom except what they instigated themselves. But possessing territories like France is far from that easy.
Hence arose the frequent rebellions of Spain, France, and Greece against the Romans, owing to the numerous principalities which existed in those states; for, as long as the memory of these lasted, the Romans were always uncertain of their possessions; but when the memory of these principalities had been extinguished they became, with the power and duration of the empire, secure possessions.
Thus, there were frequent rebellions in Spain, France, and Greece against the Romans because of the many principalities that existed in those regions. As long as the memory of these principalities persisted, the Romans were always unsure about their control. However, once the memory of these principalities faded away, these territories became secure holdings due to the strength and longevity of the empire.
And afterwards the latter could, when fighting among themselves, draw each one with him a portion of these provinces, according to the authority he had established there, and these provinces, when the family of their ancient princes was extinct, recognised no other rulers but the Romans. Considering these things, therefore, let no one be surprised at the facility with which Alexander could hold Asia, and at the difficulties that others have had in holding acquired possessions, like Pyrrhus and many others; as this was not caused by the greater or smaller ability of the conqueror, but depended on the dissimilarity of the conditions.
And later, when those factions fought among themselves, each could claim a portion of these regions based on the authority they had established there. Once the original royal family died out, these regions recognized no rulers except the Romans. Given this, it’s no wonder that Alexander was able to maintain control over Asia easily, while others, like Pyrrhus and many others, struggled to keep their territories. This wasn't due to the conqueror's greater or lesser skill, but rather the different circumstances they faced.
CHAPTER V
THE WAY TO GOVERN CITIES OR DOMINIONS THAT, PREVIOUS TO BEING OCCUPIED, LIVED UNDER THEIR OWN LAWS.
When those states which have been acquired are accustomed to live at liberty under their own laws, there are three ways of holding them. The first is to ruin them; the second is to go and live there in person; the third is to allow them to live under their own laws, taking tribute of them, and creating there within the country a state composed of a few who will keep it friendly to you. Because this state, being created by the prince, knows that it cannot exist without his friendship and protection, and will do all it can to keep them, and a city used to liberty can be more easily held by means of its citizens than in any other way, if you wish to preserve it. There is the example of the Spartans and the Romans. The Spartans held Athens and Thebes by creating within them a state of a few people; nevertheless they lost them. The Romans, in order to hold Capua, Carthage, and Numantia, destroyed them, but did not lose them. They wanted to hold Greece in almost the same way as the Spartans held it, leaving it free and under its own laws, but they did not succeed; so that they were compelled to destroy many cities in that province in order to keep it, because in truth there is no sure method of holding them except by ruining them. And whoever becomes the ruler of a free city and does not destroy it, can expect to be destroyed by it, for it can always find a motive for rebellion in the name of liberty and of its ancient usages, which are forgotten neither by lapse of time nor by benefits received, and whatever one does or provides, so long as the inhabitants are not separated or dispersed, they do not forget that name and those usages, but appeal to them at once in every emergency, as did Pisa after being so many years held in servitude by the Florentines. But when cities or provinces have been accustomed to live under a prince, and the family of that prince is extinguished, being on the one hand used to obey, and on the other not having their old prince, they cannot unite in choosing one from among themselves, and they do not know how to live in freedom, so that they are slower to take arms, and a prince can win them over with greater facility and establish himself securely. But in republics there is greater life, greater hatred, and more desire for vengeance; they do not and cannot cast aside the memory of their ancient liberty, so that the surest way is either to destroy them or reside in them.
When territories that have been taken over are used to living freely under their own laws, there are three ways to control them. The first is to destroy them; the second is to live there personally; the third is to let them follow their own laws, collecting taxes from them, and establishing a small group within the country that will remain loyal to you. This group, created by the ruler, understands that it cannot exist without his support and protection, and will do everything it can to maintain that relationship. A city that is used to freedom can be more easily controlled by its own citizens than in any other way if you want to keep it. The Spartans and Romans serve as examples. The Spartans held Athens and Thebes by forming a small loyal state within them; however, they still lost them. The Romans, to retain Capua, Carthage, and Numantia, chose to destroy them but did not lose control. They aimed to hold Greece in a similar manner to how the Spartans did, allowing it to remain free and under its own laws, but they did not succeed; therefore, they were forced to destroy many cities in that area to maintain control, because in reality, the only sure way to hold them is by ruining them. Anyone who takes charge of a free city and does not destroy it can expect to be destroyed by it, as it can always find reasons to rebel in the name of freedom and its historical practices, which are not forgotten by the passage of time or even by favors received. Regardless of what one does or provides, as long as the residents remain together and not scattered, they will not forget that name and those practices, turning to them in any crisis, as Pisa did after many years under Florentine control. However, when cities or regions are accustomed to obeying a prince, and that prince’s family comes to an end, they, having learned to obey and lacking their former ruler, cannot agree on selecting one among themselves and do not know how to live freely. This makes them slower to take up arms, allowing a prince to win them over more easily and establish himself safely. In republics, on the other hand, there is more energy, more resentment, and a greater thirst for revenge; they cannot forget their past freedom, so the safest option is either to destroy them or to live among them.
CHAPTER VI
OF NEW DOMINIONS WHICH HAVE BEEN ACQUIRED BY ONE'S OWN ARMS AND POWERS
Let no one marvel if in speaking of new dominions both as to prince and state, I bring forward very exalted instances, for as men walk almost always in the paths trodden by others, proceeding in their actions by imitation, and not being always able to follow others exactly, nor attain to the excellence of those they imitate, a prudent man should always follow in the path trodden by great men and imitate those who are most excellent, so that if he does not attain to their greatness, at any rate he will get some tinge of it. He will do like prudent archers, who when the place they wish to hit is too far off, knowing how far their bow will carry, aim at a spot much higher than the one they wish to hit, not in order to reach this height with their arrow, but by help of this high aim to hit the spot they wish to. I say then that in new dominions, where there is a new prince, it is more or less easy to hold them according to the greater or lesser ability of him who acquires them. And as the fact of a private individual becoming a prince presupposes either great ability or good fortune, it would appear that either of these things would mitigate in part many difficulties. Nevertheless those who have been wanting as regards good fortune have maintained themselves best. The matter is also facilitated by the prince being obliged to reside personally in his territory, having no others. But to come to those who have become princes through their own merits and not by fortune, I regard as the greatest, Moses, Cyrus, Romulus, Theseus, and such like. And although one should not speak of Moses, he having merely carried out what was ordered him by God, still he deserves admiration, if only for that grace which made him worthy to speak with God. But regarding Cyrus and others who have acquired or founded kingdoms, they will all be found worthy of admiration; and if their particular actions and methods are examined they will not appear very different from those of Moses, although he had so great a Master. And in examining their life and deeds it will be seen that they owed nothing to fortune but the opportunity which gave them matter to be shaped into the form that they thought fit; and without that opportunity their powers would have been wasted, and without their powers the opportunity would have come in vain. It was thus necessary that Moses should find the people of Israel slaves in Egypt and oppressed by the Egyptians, so that they were disposed to follow him in order to escape from their servitude. It was necessary that Romulus should be unable to remain in Alba, and should have been exposed at his birth, in order that he might become King of Rome and founder of that nation. It was necessary that Cyrus should find the Persians discontented with the empire of the Medes, and the Medes weak and effeminate through long peace. Theseus could not have showed his abilities if he had not found the Athenians dispersed.
Let no one be surprised if I mention very high examples when talking about new territories, both in terms of the ruler and the state. People often follow the paths laid out by others, acting by imitation. Since they can't always perfectly emulate those they look up to or reach their level of excellence, a wise person should always follow in the footsteps of great individuals and imitate the best, so even if they don’t achieve the same greatness, they’ll at least gain some of it. It’s like careful archers who, when their target is far away, know how far their bow can shoot and aim for a higher spot than their target—not to hit that spot directly, but to help them hit the target they want. So, in new territories where there’s a new ruler, it’s relatively easy to maintain control depending on the skills of the one who gains power. A private individual becoming a prince requires either significant talent or good fortune, and either of these can help ease some challenges. However, those who lack good fortune often end up sustaining their power the best. This is also easier when the prince has to personally reside in his territory without others to manage it. Now, when it comes to those who became rulers through their own merits rather than luck, I consider the greatest to be Moses, Cyrus, Romulus, Theseus, and others like them. Although we shouldn’t overly praise Moses since he only did what God commanded him, he still deserves respect for the grace that allowed him to speak with God. As for Cyrus and others who gained or founded kingdoms, they are all admirable figures; if we look closely at their actions and methods, they won’t seem very different from Moses, despite his having such a great mentor. When we examine their lives and deeds, we see that they didn’t owe their success to luck, but rather to the opportunities that allowed them to shape their circumstances as they saw fit. Without those opportunities, their abilities would have been wasted, and without those abilities, the opportunities would have meant nothing. For instance, it was necessary for Moses to find the Israelites as slaves in Egypt, oppressed by the Egyptians, making them willing to follow him to escape their bondage. Similarly, Romulus had to be unable to stay in Alba and must have been abandoned at birth to become King of Rome and the founder of that nation. Cyrus needed to find the Persians unhappy with the rule of the Medes, who were weakened by prolonged peace. Theseus couldn’t have shown his capabilities if he hadn’t found the Athenians scattered.
These opportunities, therefore, gave these men their chance, and their own great qualities enabled them to profit by them, so as to ennoble their country and augment its fortunes. Those who by heroic means such as these become princes, obtain their dominions with difficulty but retain them easily, and the difficulties which they have in acquiring their dominions arise in part from the new rules and regulations that they have to introduce in order to establish their position securely. It must be considered that there is nothing more difficult to carry out, nor more doubtful of success, nor more dangerous to handle, than to initiate a new order of things. For the reformer has enemies in all those who profit by the old order, and only lukewarm defenders in all those who would profit by the new order, this lukewarmness arising partly from fear of their adversaries, who have the laws in their favour; and partly from the incredulity of mankind, who do not truly believe in anything new until they have had actual experience of it. Thus it arises that on every opportunity for attacking the reformer, his opponents do so with the zeal of partisans, the others only defend him half-heartedly, so that between them he runs great danger. It is necessary, however, in order to investigate thoroughly this question, to examine whether these innovators are independent, or whether they depend upon others, that is to say, whether in order to carry out their designs they have to entreat or are able to force. In the first case they invariably succeed ill, and accomplish nothing; but when they can depend on their own strength and are able to use force, they rarely fail. Thus it comes about that all armed prophets have conquered and unarmed ones failed; for besides what has been already said, the character of people varies, and it is easy to persuade them of a thing, but difficult to keep them in that persuasion. And so it is necessary to order things so that when they no longer believe, they can be made to believe by force. Moses, Cyrus, Theseus, and Romulus would not have been able to make their institutions observed for so long had they been disarmed, as happened in our own time to Fra Girolamo Savonarola, who failed entirely in his new rules when the multitude began to disbelieve in him, and he had no means of holding fast those who had believed nor of compelling the unbelievers to believe. Therefore such men as these have great difficulty in making their way, and all their dangers are met on the road and must be overcome by their own abilities; but when once they have overcome them and have begun to be held in veneration, and have suppressed those who envied them, they remain powerful and secure, honoured and happy. To the high examples given I will add a lesser one, which, however, is to be compared in some measure with them and will serve as an instance of all such cases, that of Jerone of Syracuse, who from a private individual became Prince of Siracusa, without other aid from fortune beyond the opportunity; for the Siracusans being oppressed elected him as their captain, from which by merit he was made prince; while still in private life his virtues were such that it was written of him, that he lacked nothing to reign but the kingdom. He abolished the old militia, raised a new one, abandoned his old friendships and formed new ones; and as he had thus friends and soldiers of his own, he was able on this foundation to build securely, so that while he had great trouble in acquiring his position he had little in maintaining it.
These opportunities gave these men a chance, and their own remarkable qualities allowed them to take advantage of them, which helped elevate their country and improve its fortunes. Those who become leaders through heroic actions face challenges in gaining their territories but often find it easier to keep them. The challenges they face in establishing their rule partly come from the new rules and regulations they need to implement to secure their position. It’s important to note that initiating a new order of things is one of the hardest, most uncertain, and most perilous tasks. Reformers have enemies among those who benefit from the old order and only half-hearted supporters from those who would benefit from the new one. This lukewarm support often stems from fear of their opponents, who have the laws on their side, and from the skepticism of people, who generally don’t believe in anything new until they've experienced it themselves. Consequently, whenever there's a chance to attack the reformer, their opponents go after them with passion, while the others support them only half-heartedly, putting the reformer in significant danger. However, to thoroughly investigate this issue, we must consider whether these innovators are independent or reliant on others, meaning whether they need to seek favor to carry out their plans or can force their will. In the former case, they usually struggle and achieve little; in the latter, when they can rely on their own strength, they seldom fail. Hence, all armed leaders have succeeded while unarmed ones have not. Additionally, people’s character varies; it's easy to convince them of something, but hard to keep them convinced. Therefore, it is necessary to arrange things so that if people stop believing, they can be made to believe through force. Moses, Cyrus, Theseus, and Romulus wouldn’t have had such lasting influence if they had been disarmed, like Fra Girolamo Savonarola in our time, who completely failed in his new rules when the people began to doubt him and he had no means to hold on to his supporters or compel the skeptics to believe. Thus, figures like these face significant challenges, and all their obstacles must be overcome through their own skills. But once they navigate these challenges and gain respect, and if they suppress their envious rivals, they can remain powerful, secure, honored, and happy. Alongside the grand examples already mentioned, I’ll add a lesser one that is still somewhat comparable: Jerone of Syracuse, who went from being an ordinary citizen to the Prince of Siracusa, with no other fortune assisting him beyond the chance he was given. The people of Syracuse, feeling oppressed, elected him as their leader, and through his merit, he became prince. Even in private life, his qualities were such that it was said he lacked only a kingdom to rule. He dismantled the old army, created a new one, let go of old friendships, and formed new alliances. With friends and soldiers of his own, he was able to build a solid foundation, so while he faced significant trouble in gaining his position, he had little difficulty in keeping it.
CHAPTER VII
OF NEW DOMINIONS ACQUIRED BY THE POWER OF OTHERS OR BY FORTUNE
Those who rise from private citizens to be princes merely by fortune have little trouble in rising but very much in maintaining their position. They meet with no difficulties on the way as they fly over them, but all their difficulties arise when they are established. Such are they who are granted a state either for money, or by favour of him who grants it, as happened to many in Greece, in the cities of Ionia and of the Hellespont, who were created princes by Darius in order to hold these places for his security and glory; such were also those emperors who from private citizens became emperors by bribing the army. Such as these depend absolutely on the good will and fortune of those who have raised them, both of which are extremely inconstant and unstable. They neither know how to, nor are in a position to maintain their rank, for unless he be a man of great genius it is not likely that one who has always lived in a private position should know how to command, and they are unable to command because they possess no forces which will be friendly and faithful to them. Moreover, states quickly founded, like all other things which are born and grow rapidly, cannot have deep roots, so that the first storm destroys them, unless, as already said, the man who thus becomes a prince is of such great genius as to be able to take immediate steps for maintaining what fortune has thrown into his lap, and lay afterwards those foundations which others make before becoming princes. With regard to these two methods of becoming a prince,—by ability or by good fortune, I will here adduce two examples which have taken place within our memory, those of Francesco Sforza and Cesare Borgia.
Those who go from being private citizens to becoming princes just by luck have an easy time rising but struggle a lot to keep their position. They face no challenges on their way up as they soar above them, but all their struggles start once they’re established. This is true for those granted a state either through money or by the favor of the one who gives it, like many in Greece, in the cities of Ionia and the Hellespont, who were made princes by Darius to maintain these locations for his security and glory; this also applied to those emperors who went from private citizens to emperors by bribing the army. Such individuals rely completely on the goodwill and luck of those who elevated them, both of which are extremely fickle and unreliable. They neither know how to maintain their status, nor are they positioned to do so. Unless someone is exceptionally talented, it’s unlikely that a person who has always lived a private life will know how to lead, and they can't lead because they lack forces that are loyal and supportive. Furthermore, states that are rapidly established, like all things that are born and grow quickly, can’t have deep roots, so the first storm can wipe them out unless, as previously mentioned, the person who becomes a prince has the exceptional talent to take immediate measures to maintain what luck has brought them, and later lay the groundwork that others establish before becoming princes. Regarding these two ways of becoming a prince—through skill or by good fortune—I will now provide two examples from our own time: Francesco Sforza and Cesare Borgia.
Francesco, by appropriate means and through great abilities, from citizen became Duke of Milan, and what he had attained after a thousand difficulties he maintained with little trouble. On the other hand, Cesare Borgia, commonly called Duke Valentine, acquired the state through the fortune of his father and by the same means lost it, and that although every measure was adopted by him and everything done that a prudent and capable man could do to establish himself firmly in that state that the arms and the favours of others had given him. For, as we have said, he who does not lay his foundations beforehand may by great abilities do so afterwards, although with great trouble to the architect and danger to the building. If, then, one considers the progress made by the duke, it will be seen how firm were the foundations he had laid to his future power, which I do not think it superfluous to examine, as I know of no better precepts for a new prince to follow than the example of his actions; and if his measures were not successful, it was through no fault of his own but only by the most extraordinary malignity of fortune. In wishing to aggrandise the duke his son, Alexander VI. had to meet very great difficulties both present and future. In the first place, he saw no way of making him ruler of any state that was not a possession of the Church. And in attempting to take that of the Church, he knew that the Duke of Milan and the Venetians would not consent, because Faenza and Rimini were already under the protection of the Venetians. He saw, moreover, that the arms of Italy, especially of those who might have served him, were in the hands of those who would fear the greatness of the pope, and therefore he could not depend upon them, being all under the Orsinis and Colonnas and their adherents. It was, therefore, necessary to disturb the existing condition and bring about disorders in the states of Italy in order to obtain secure mastery over a part of them; this was easy, for he found the Venetians, who, actuated by other motives, had invited the French into Italy, which he not only did not oppose, but facilitated by dissolving the marriage of King Louis. The king came thus into Italy with the aid of the Venetians and the consent of Alexander, and had hardly arrived at Milan before the pope obtained troops from him for his enterprise in the Romagna, which he carried out by means of the reputation of the king. The duke having thus obtained the Romagna and defeated the Colonnas, was hindered in maintaining it and proceeding further by two things: the one, his forces, of which he doubted the fidelity; the other the will of France, that is to say, he feared lest the arms of the Orsini of which he had availed himself should fail him, and not only hinder him in obtaining more but take from him what he had already conquered, and he also feared that the king might do the same. He had evidence of this as regards the Orsini when, after taking Faenza, he assaulted Bologna and observed their backwardness in the assault. And as regards the king, he perceived his designs when, after taking the dukedom of Urbino, he attacked Tuscany, and the king made him desist from that enterprise; whereupon the duke decided to depend no longer on the fortunes and arms of others. The first thing he did was to weaken the parties of the Orsinis and Colonnas in Rome by gaining all their adherents who were gentlemen and making them followers of himself, by granting them large pensions, and appointing them to commands and offices according to their rank, so that their attachment to their parties was extinguished in a few months, and entirely concentrated on the duke. After this he awaited an opportunity for crushing the Orsinis, having dispersed the adherents of the Colonna family, and when the opportunity arrived he made good use of it, for the Orsini seeing at length that the greatness of the duke and of the Church meant their own ruin, convoked a diet at Magione in the Perugino. Hence sprang the rebellion of Urbino and the tumults in Romagna and infinite dangers to the duke, who overcame them all with the help of the French; and having regained his reputation, neither trusting France nor other foreign forces in order not to have to oppose them, he had recourse to stratagem. He dissembled his aims so well that the Orsini, through the mediation of Signor Pavolo, made their peace with him, which the duke spared no efforts to make secure, presenting them with robes, money, and horses, so that in their simplicity they were induced to come to Sinigaglia and fell into his hands. Having thus suppressed these leaders and made their partisans his friends, the duke had laid a very good foundation to his power, having all the Romagna with the duchy of Urbino, and having gained the favour of the inhabitants, who began to feel the benefit of his rule. And as this part is worthy of note and of imitation by others, I will not omit mention of it. When he took the Romagna, it had previously been governed by weak rulers, who had rather despoiled their subjects than governed them, and given them more cause for disunion than for union, so that the province was a prey to robbery, assaults, and every kind of disorder. He, therefore, judged it necessary to give them a good government in order to make them peaceful and obedient to his rule. For this purpose he appointed Messer Remiro d' Orco, a cruel and able man, to whom he gave the fullest authority. This man, in a short time, was highly successful in rendering the country orderly and united, whereupon the duke, not deeming such excessive authority expedient, lest it should become hateful, appointed a civil court of justice in the middle of the province under an excellent president, to which each city appointed its own advocate. And as he knew that the harshness of the past had engendered some amount of hatred, in order to purge the minds of the people and to win them over completely, he resolved to show that if any cruelty had taken place it was not by his orders, but through the harsh disposition of his minister. And taking him on some pretext, he had him placed one morning in the public square at Cesena, cut in half, with a piece of wood and blood-stained knife by his side. The ferocity of this spectacle caused the people both satisfaction and amazement. But to return to where we left off.
Francesco, through the right strategies and great skills, rose from being a citizen to become Duke of Milan, and what he achieved after many challenges he kept with little effort. In contrast, Cesare Borgia, known as Duke Valentino, gained his territory through his father's fortunate legacy and lost it by the same means, despite taking every possible action a wise and capable person could to secure himself in the land that arms and favors of others had provided him. As we mentioned, anyone who doesn’t lay their foundations in advance may, despite great talent, manage to do so later, but with significant effort for the architect and risk to the structure. If we look at how the duke progressed, we can see how solid the foundations he laid for his future power were, which I believe is worth examining, as I know of no better guidance for a new prince to follow than the example of his actions. If his plans didn’t work out, it wasn’t due to any failure on his part, but solely because of the extraordinary malice of fate. In trying to elevate his son, Alexander VI had to confront considerable challenges, both immediate and long-term. First, he saw no way to make him the ruler of any state not owned by the Church. And in trying to take from the Church, he recognized that the Duke of Milan and the Venetians wouldn’t agree, as Faenza and Rimini were already under Venetian protection. Furthermore, he realized that the military power in Italy, especially among those who could have supported him, was held by those who would fear the pope's rising power, leaving him unable to rely on them, as they were all aligned with the Orsinis and Colonnas and their followers. Thus, it became necessary to disrupt the existing order and create chaos in the Italian states to gain secure control over part of them; this was straightforward since he discovered that the Venetians had invited the French into Italy for their own reasons, which he not only didn’t oppose but actively supported by dissolving King Louis's marriage. Hence, the king entered Italy with the Venetians' backing and Alexander's consent, and before long, the pope secured troops from him for his campaign in Romagna, which he carried out leveraging the king's reputation. Having gained Romagna and defeated the Colonnas, the duke faced two main obstacles in keeping his new territory and advancing: first, he had doubts about the loyalty of his forces; second, he was concerned about France's intentions—he feared that the Orsini, whose support he relied on, would turn against him, preventing him from gaining further territories or taking back those he had already conquered, and he was also wary that the king might do the same. He had seen evidence of this concerning the Orsini when, after seizing Faenza, he attacked Bologna and noticed their lack of enthusiasm for the assault. Regarding the king, he recognized his intentions when, after capturing the dukedom of Urbino, he attempted to invade Tuscany and was forced to back down due to the king’s intervention. Consequently, the duke resolved to stop relying on the fortunes and military powers of others. The first step he took was to weaken the Orsini and Colonna factions in Rome by winning over their noble supporters, granting them generous pensions and appointing them to positions and offices based on their rank, rendering their loyalty to their factions obsolete within months and shifting it entirely to the duke. Following this, he waited for the right moment to crush the Orsini after having dispersed the Colonna supporters, and when the opportunity arose, he seized it effectively. The Orsini, realizing that the duke's and the Church's ascent meant their own downfall, called a meeting at Magione in Perugia. This led to the rebellion in Urbino, protests in Romagna, and countless threats to the duke, who managed to overcome them all with French support. Having regained his reputation and no longer trusting France or other foreign forces to avoid conflict with them, he resorted to cunning. He cleverly concealed his true intentions so well that the Orsini, with the help of Signor Pavolo, negotiated peace with him, which the duke went to great lengths to secure, offering them robes, money, and horses. In their naïveté, they were lured to Sinigaglia, falling right into his trap. By eliminating these leaders and turning their followers into his allies, the duke established a strong foundation for his power, gaining all of Romagna along with the dukedom of Urbino, winning the favor of the people who began to appreciate his governance. This aspect is notable and worth emulating, so I must mention it. When he took over Romagna, it had been managed by weak leaders who exploited their subjects instead of governing them, creating more grounds for division than unity, resulting in a region plagued by theft, violence, and every manner of disarray. Thus, he realized it was essential to provide them with effective governance to foster peace and obedience to his rule. For this, he appointed Messer Remiro d’Orco, a ruthless yet competent man, granting him full authority. This man quickly succeeded in restoring order and unity to the region, after which the duke, feeling such excessive power was no longer wise—fearing it might become disliked—established a civil court of justice at the center of the province under an excellent president, with each city selecting its own lawyer. Understanding that the harshness of the past had created some resentment, he decided to absolve the people's minds and win them over completely by demonstrating that if any brutality had occurred, it was not at his command, but due to his minister's cruel nature. One morning, under some pretext, he had Remiro displayed in the public square at Cesena, cut in half, with a piece of wood and a bloody knife beside him. The brutality of this sight both satisfied and shocked the people. But let’s return to where we left off.
The duke being now powerful and partly secured against present perils, being armed himself, and having in a great measure put down those neighbouring forces which might injure him, had now to get the respect of France, if he wished to proceed with his acquisitions, for he knew that the king, who had lately discovered his error, would not give him any help. He began therefore to seek fresh alliances and to vacillate with France in the expedition that the French made towards the kingdom of Naples against the Spaniards, who were besieging Gaeta. His intention was to assure himself of them, which he would soon have succeeded in doing if Alexander had lived. These were the measures taken by him with regard to the present. As to the future, he feared that a new successor to the Church might not be friendly to him and might seek to deprive him of what Alexander had given him, and he sought to provide against this in four ways. Firstly, by destroying all who were of the blood of those ruling families which he had despoiled, in order to deprive the pope of any opportunity. Secondly, by gaining the friendship of the Roman nobles, so that he might through them hold as it were the pope in check. Thirdly, by obtaining as great a hold on the College as he could. Fourthly, by acquiring such power before the pope died as to be able to resist alone the first onslaught. Of these four things he had at the death of Alexander accomplished three, and the fourth he had almost accomplished.
The duke, now powerful and somewhat protected from immediate dangers, armed himself and significantly subdued the neighboring forces that could harm him. He needed to earn the respect of France if he wanted to continue with his gains, as he knew that the king, who had recently realized his mistake, would not offer him any support. Therefore, he began to seek new alliances and play both sides in the French expedition towards the kingdom of Naples against the Spaniards, who were besieging Gaeta. His goal was to secure their support, which he would have succeeded in if Alexander had lived. These were his actions regarding the present. For the future, he worried that a new pope might not be on his side and might try to take away what Alexander had given him, so he planned to guard against this in four ways. First, by eliminating all members of the royal families he had robbed to cut off any chance for the pope to retaliate. Second, by winning the loyalty of the Roman nobles, allowing him to keep the pope in check through them. Third, by gaining as much influence over the College as possible. Fourth, by accumulating enough power before the pope's death to be able to withstand the initial attack alone. At the time of Alexander’s death, he had achieved three of these four objectives, and he was very close to completing the fourth.
For of the dispossessed rulers he killed as many as he could lay hands on, and very few escaped; he had gained to his party the Roman nobles; and he had a great share in the College. As to new possessions, he designed to become lord of Tuscany, and already possessed Perugia and Piombino, and had assumed the protectorate over Pisa; and as he had no longer to fear the French (for the French had been deprived of the kingdom of Naples by the Spaniards in such a way that both parties were obliged to buy his friendship) he seized Pisa. After this, Lucca and Siena at once yielded, partly through envy of the Florentines and partly through fear; the Florentines had no resources, so that, had he succeeded as he had done before, in the very year that Alexander died he would have gained such strength and renown as to be able to maintain himself without depending on the fortunes or strength of others, but solely by his own power and ability. But Alexander died five years after he had first drawn his sword. He left him with the state of Romagna only firmly established, and all the other schemes in mid-air, between two very powerful and hostile armies, and suffering from a fatal illness. But the valour and ability of the duke were such, and he knew so well how to win over men or vanquish them, and so strong were the foundations that he had laid in this short time, that if he had not had those two armies upon him, or else had been in good health, he would have survived every difficulty. And that his foundations were good is seen from the fact that the Romagna waited for him more than a month; in Rome, although half dead, he remained secure, and although the Baglioni, Vitelli, and Orsini entered Rome they found no followers against him. He was able, if not to make pope whom he wished, at any rate to prevent a pope being created whom he did not wish. But if at the death of Alexander he had been well everything would have been easy. And he told me on the day that Pope Julius II. was created, that he had thought of everything which might happen on the death of his father, and provided against everything, except that he had never thought that at his father's death he would be dying himself. Reviewing thus all the actions of the duke, I find nothing to blame, on the contrary, I feel bound, as I have done, to hold him up as an example to be imitated by all who by fortune and with the arms of others have risen to power. For with his great courage and high ambition he could not have acted otherwise, and his designs were only frustrated by the short life of Alexander and his own illness.
He killed as many of the deposed rulers as he could get his hands on, and very few escaped. He had won over the Roman nobles to his side and held a significant position in the College. He aimed to become the lord of Tuscany and already controlled Perugia and Piombino, having also taken on the protectorate over Pisa. With the French no longer a threat—since they had lost the Kingdom of Naples to the Spaniards, both sides needed to secure his friendship—he took Pisa. After that, Lucca and Siena quickly surrendered, partly out of envy for the Florentines and partly out of fear. The Florentines were low on resources, so had he succeeded as he had before, in the very year Alexander died, he would have gained enough strength and fame to stand on his own without relying on the fortunes or strength of others, just his own power and ability. But Alexander died five years after he first unsheathed his sword. He left the state of Romagna firmly established, but all his other plans were left hanging, caught between two very powerful and hostile armies, while he battled a severe illness. However, the duke's courage and skills were remarkable; he knew how to win people over or defeat them, and the foundations he had built in such a short time were strong enough that if he hadn't had those two armies against him, or if he had been in good health, he would have overcome every obstacle. The strength of his foundations is shown by the fact that Romagna waited for him for over a month; in Rome, despite being half dead, he remained secure, and even when the Baglioni, Vitelli, and Orsini entered Rome, they found no one to support them against him. He could have prevented a pope from being elected whom he didn’t want, if not directly chosen one himself. But if he had been well during Alexander's death, everything would have been easy. He told me on the day Pope Julius II was elected that he had thought of everything that might happen after his father's death and had planned for every possibility, except that he never expected to be dying himself at the same time. After reviewing all the duke's actions, I find nothing to criticize; on the contrary, I feel compelled, as I have done, to hold him up as a model for anyone who has risen to power through fortune and the resources of others. With his immense courage and high aspirations, he couldn't have acted any differently, and his plans were only thwarted by the untimely death of Alexander and his own illness.
Whoever, therefore, deems it necessary in his new principality to secure himself against enemies, to gain friends, to conquer by force or fraud, to make himself beloved and feared by the people, followed and reverenced by the soldiers, to destroy those who can and may injure him, introduce innovations into old customs, to be severe and kind, magnanimous and liberal, suppress the old militia, create a new one, maintain the friendship of kings and princes in such a way that they are glad to benefit him and fear to injure him, such a one can find no better example than the actions of this man. The only thing he can be accused of is that in the creation of Julius II. he made a bad choice; for, as has been said, not being able to choose his own pope, he could still prevent any one being made pope, and he ought never to have permitted any of those cardinals to be raised to the papacy whom he had injured, or who when pope would stand in fear of him. For men commit injuries either through fear or through hate.
Whoever thinks it's necessary in his new principality to protect himself from enemies, gain friends, conquer by force or trickery, make himself loved and feared by the people, followed and respected by the soldiers, eliminate those who might harm him, introduce changes to old customs, be both strict and kind, generous and open-handed, disband the old militia, create a new one, and maintain the goodwill of kings and princes so that they are happy to assist him and afraid to harm him, has no better example than this man’s actions. The only criticism he might face is that he made a poor choice in selecting Julius II; as mentioned earlier, while he couldn’t choose his own pope, he could still prevent anyone from becoming pope, and he should never have allowed any of those cardinals he had wronged, or who would fear him as pope, to ascend to that position. Because people act out of fear or hate.
Those whom he had injured were, among others, San Pietro ad Vincula, Colonna, San Giorgio, and Ascanio. All the others, if assumed to the pontificate, would have had to fear him except Rohan and the Spaniards; the latter through their relationship and obligations to him, the former from his great power, being related to the King of France. For these reasons the duke ought above all things to have created a Spaniard pope; and if unable to, then he should have consented to Rohan being appointed and not San Pietro ad Vincula. And whoever thinks that in high personages new benefits cause old offences to be forgotten, makes a great mistake. The duke, therefore, erred in this choice, and it was the cause of his ultimate ruin.
Those he had wronged included, among others, San Pietro ad Vincula, Colonna, San Giorgio, and Ascanio. Everyone else who might take on the papacy would have had to be wary of him, except for Rohan and the Spaniards; the latter due to their ties and responsibilities to him, and the former because of his significant influence, being connected to the King of France. For these reasons, the duke should have prioritized making a Spaniard pope; and if that wasn't possible, he should have accepted Rohan for the position instead of San Pietro ad Vincula. Anyone who believes that powerful people can overlook past offenses due to new benefits is seriously mistaken. Therefore, the duke made a mistake in this choice, and it led to his eventual downfall.
CHAPTER VIII
OF THOSE WHO HAVE ATTAINED THE POSITION OF PRINCE BY VILLAINY
But as there are still two ways of becoming prince which cannot be attributed entirely either to fortune or to ability, they must not be passed over, although one of them could be more fully discussed if we were treating of republics. These are when one becomes prince by some nefarious or villainous means, or when a private citizen becomes the prince of his country through the favour of his fellow-citizens. And in speaking of the former means, I will give two examples, one ancient, the other modern, without entering further into the merits of this method, as I judge them to be sufficient for any one obliged to imitate them. Agathocles the Sicilian rose not only from private life but from the lowest and most abject position to be King of Syracuse. The son of a potter, he led a life of the utmost wickedness through all the stages of his fortune. Nevertheless, his wickedness was accompanied by such vigour of mind and body that, having joined the militia, he rose through all its grades to be prætor of Syracuse. Having been appointed to this position, and having decided to become prince, and to hold with violence and without the support of others that which had been granted him; and having imparted his design to Hamilcar the Carthaginian, who with his armies was fighting in Sicily, he called together one morning the people and senate of Syracuse, as if he had to deliberate on matters of importance to the republic, and at a given signal had all the senators and the richest men of the people killed by his soldiers; after their death he occupied and held rule over the city without any civil disorders. And although he was twice beaten by the Carthaginians and ultimately besieged, he was able not only to defend the city, but leaving a portion of his forces for its defence, with the remainder he invaded Africa, and in a short time liberated Syracuse from the siege and brought the Carthaginians to great extremities, so that they were obliged to come to terms with him, and remain contented with the possession of Africa, leaving Sicily to Agathocles. Whoever considers, therefore, the actions and qualities of this man, will see few if any things which can be attributed to fortune; for, as above stated, it was not by the favour of any person, but through the grades of the militia, which he had gained with a thousand hardships and perils, that he arrived at the position of prince, which he afterwards maintained by so many courageous and perilous expedients. It cannot be called a virtue to kill one's fellow-citizens, betray one's friends, be without faith, without pity, and without religion, by which methods one may indeed gain an empire, but not glory. For if the virtues of Agathocles in braving and overcoming perils, and his greatness of soul in supporting and surmounting obstacles be considered, one sees no reason for holding him inferior to any of the most renowned captains. Nevertheless his barbarous cruelty and inhumanity, together with his countless atrocities, do not permit of his being named among the most famous men. We cannot attribute to fortune or merit that which he achieved without either. In our own times, during the reign of Alexander VI., Oliverotto du Fermo had been left a young boy under the care of his maternal uncle, Giovanni Fogliani, who brought him up, and sent him in early youth to fight under Paolo Vitelli, in order that he might, under that discipline, obtain a good military position. On the death of Paolo he fought under his brother Vitellozzo, and in a very short time, being of great intelligence, and active in mind and body, he became one of the leaders of his troops. But deeming it servile to be under others, he resolved, with the help of some citizens of Fermo, who preferred servitude to the liberty of their country, and with the favour of the Vitellis, to occupy Fermo; he therefore wrote to Giovanni Fogliani, how, having been for many years away from home, he wished to come to see him and his city, and in some measure to revisit his estates. And as he had only laboured to gain honour, in order that his fellow-citizens might see that he had not spent his time in vain, he wished to come honourably accompanied by one hundred horsemen, his friends and followers, and prayed him that he would be pleased to order that he should be received with honour by the citizens of Fermo, by which he would honour not only him, Oliverotto, but also himself, as he had been his pupil. Giovanni did not fail in any duty towards his nephew; he caused him to be honourably received by the people of Fermo, and lodged him in his own houses. After waiting some days to arrange all that was necessary to his villainous projects, Oliverotto invited Giovanni Fogliani and all the principal men of Fermo to a grand banquet. After the dinner and the entertainments usual at such feasts, Oliverotto artfully introduced certain important matters of discussion, speaking of the greatness of Pope Alexander, and of his son Cesare, and of their enterprises. To which discourses Giovanni and others having replied, he all at once rose, saying that these matters should be spoken of in a more secret place, and withdrew into a room where Giovanni and the other citizens followed him. They were no sooner seated than soldiers rushed out of hiding-places and killed Giovanni and all the others. After which massacre Oliverotto mounted his horse, rode through the town and besieged the chief magistrate in his palace, so that through fear they were obliged to obey him and form a government, of which he made himself prince. And all those being dead who, if discontented, could injure him, he fortified himself with new orders, civil and military, in such a way that within the year that he held the principality he was not only safe himself in the city of Fermo, but had become formidable to all his neighbours. And his overthrow would have been difficult, like that of Agathocles, if he had not allowed himself to be deceived by Cesare Borgia, when he besieged the Orsinis and Vitellis at Sinigaglia, as already related, where he also was taken, one year after the parricide he had committed, and strangled, together with Vitellozzo, who had been his teacher in ability and atrocity. Some may wonder how it came about that Agathocles, and others like him, could, after infinite treachery and cruelty, live secure for many years in their country and defend themselves from external enemies without being conspired against by their subjects; although many others have, through their cruelty, been unable to maintain their position in times of peace, not to speak of the uncertain times of war.
But since there are still two ways to become a prince that can't be completely attributed to luck or skill, they shouldn't be overlooked, although one would require more discussion if we were talking about republics. These ways are when someone becomes a prince through shady or villainous means, or when a private citizen becomes the prince of their country through the support of their fellow citizens. When discussing the first method, I'll provide two examples: one from ancient times and another from modern times, without going into detail about the merits of this approach, as I believe they are sufficient for anyone who has to follow them. Agathocles the Sicilian rose from a completely humble and lowly background to become the King of Syracuse. The son of a potter, he lived a life of extreme wickedness through all stages of his fortune. Nevertheless, his wickedness was paired with such strength of mind and body that, after joining the military, he moved up through the ranks to become the praetor of Syracuse. Once he was in that position and decided to claim the title of prince by force, without depending on others, and after sharing his plan with Hamilcar the Carthaginian, who was fighting in Sicily with his armies, he called the people and the Senate of Syracuse together one morning, as if to discuss important matters for the republic. At a signal, he had all the senators and the wealthiest citizens killed by his soldiers; after their deaths, he took control of the city without any civil unrest. Although he was twice defeated by the Carthaginians and ultimately besieged, he was able not only to defend the city but, leaving part of his forces for its defense, he invaded Africa with the rest and quickly freed Syracuse from the siege, putting the Carthaginians in a difficult position where they had to negotiate with him, settling for keeping Africa and allowing Agathocles to have Sicily. Therefore, anyone who considers the actions and qualities of this man will see few, if any, things that can be attributed to luck; for, as stated above, it wasn't due to anyone's favor but through the ranks of the military, which he earned through countless hardships and dangers, that he reached the position of prince, which he later maintained through many courageous and perilous actions. It can't be called a virtue to kill one's fellow citizens, betray friends, be untrustworthy, show no mercy, and possess no religion, as these methods may indeed lead to an empire but not to glory. If one considers the virtues of Agathocles in facing and overcoming dangers, and his strength in bearing and overcoming obstacles, one sees no reason to regard him as inferior to any of the most famous captains. Nevertheless, his barbaric cruelty and inhumanity, along with his countless atrocities, prevent him from being mentioned among the most celebrated men. We can't attribute what he achieved to luck or merit since he did it without either. In our own time, during the reign of Alexander VI, Oliverotto du Fermo was left a young boy under the care of his maternal uncle, Giovanni Fogliani, who raised him and sent him off to fight under Paolo Vitelli at a young age, hoping he would gain a good military position through that training. After Paolo's death, he served under his brother Vitellozzo, and very quickly, being smart and physically capable, he became one of the leaders of his troops. However, thinking it beneath him to serve under others, he made up his mind to take over Fermo with the help of some citizens who preferred servitude to their country's freedom, and with the support of the Vitellis. He therefore wrote to Giovanni Fogliani, saying that after many years away from home, he wished to visit him and his city, and to some extent, see his estates again. Since he had worked hard to gain honor, wanting his fellow citizens to see that he hadn’t wasted his time, he planned to return with one hundred horsemen—his friends and followers—and asked Giovanni to ensure he was received with honor by the citizens of Fermo, which would honor not only him, Oliverotto, but also himself as his mentor. Giovanni didn’t fail in any duty towards his nephew; he arranged for him to be honorably received by the people of Fermo and housed him in his own home. After waiting a few days to set up everything needed for his villainous plans, Oliverotto invited Giovanni Fogliani and all the prominent men of Fermo to a grand banquet. Following the dinner and the usual entertainment of such feasts, Oliverotto cleverly brought up important discussions, talking about the greatness of Pope Alexander and his son Cesare, and their ambitions. When Giovanni and the others responded to these discussions, he suddenly rose, saying that these matters should be discussed in a more private place, and he led them into a room where Giovanni and the other citizens followed him. No sooner had they sat down than soldiers burst from hiding and killed Giovanni and all the others. After this massacre, Oliverotto mounted his horse, rode through the town, and besieged the chief magistrate in his palace, forcing them to obey him and set up a government in which he declared himself prince. And with all those dead who could harm him if they were unhappy, he secured his position with new civil and military orders, so that within a year of holding the principality, he was not only safe in the city of Fermo but had also become a threat to all his neighbors. His downfall would have been difficult, much like Agathocles, if he hadn’t allowed himself to be tricked by Cesare Borgia when he besieged the Orsinis and Vitellis at Sinigaglia, as mentioned earlier, where he was also captured, a year after the murder he committed, and strangled alongside Vitellozzo, who had taught him in skill and atrocity. Some may wonder how Agathocles and others like him could live securely in their own country for many years after endless treachery and cruelty, defending themselves against external enemies without being conspired against by their subjects; while many others, through their cruelty, have been unable to maintain their positions in times of peace, let alone during the uncertain times of war.
I believe this arises from the cruelties being used well or badly. Well used may be called those (if it is permissible to use the word well of evil) which are committed once for the need of securing one's self, and which afterwards are not persisted in, but are exchanged for measures as useful to the subjects as possible. Cruelties ill used are those which, although at first few, increase rather than diminish with time. Those who follow the former method may remedy in some measure their condition, both with God and man; as did Agathocles. As to the others, it is impossible for them to maintain themselves. Whence it is to be noted, that in taking a state the conqueror must arrange to commit all his cruelties at once, so as not to have to recur to them every day, and so as to be able, by not making fresh changes, to reassure people and win them over by benefiting them. Whoever acts otherwise, either through timidity or bad counsels, is always obliged to stand with knife in hand, and can never depend on his subjects, because they, through continually fresh injuries, are unable to depend upon him. For injuries should be done all together, so that being less tasted, they will give less offence. Benefits should be granted little by little, so that they may be better enjoyed. And above all, a prince must live with his subjects in such a way that no accident should make him change it, for good or evil; for necessity arising in adverse times, you are not in time with severity, and the good that you do does not profit you, as it is judged to be forced, and you will derive no benefit whatever from it.
I believe this comes from how cruelties are used, whether well or badly. Well-used cruelties might be considered those (if it's acceptable to call something evil "well used") that are committed once to secure one's safety, and then not continued, but replaced with measures that are as beneficial to the subjects as possible. Badly used cruelties are those that, although few at first, increase rather than decrease over time. Those who follow the first approach can somewhat improve their situation, both with God and people, like Agathocles did. As for the others, it becomes impossible for them to maintain their power. Therefore, it's important for a conqueror to arrange all their cruelties at once when taking control of a state, so they don’t have to resort to them every day and can instead reassure people and win them over by providing benefits without making new changes. Anyone who acts differently, either out of fear or bad advice, is always left on edge and can never fully rely on their subjects because the continuous injuries prevent any trust. Injuries should be done all at once to be less impactful, while benefits should be given gradually so they can be enjoyed more. Most importantly, a ruler must maintain a stable relationship with their subjects, ensuring nothing—good or bad—forces a change in that relationship. If necessary actions arise in difficult times, being too harsh won't help, and any good you do will seem forced and won’t benefit you at all.
CHAPTER IX
OF THE CIVIC PRINCIPALITY
But we now come to the case where a citizen becomes prince not through crime or intolerable violence, but by the favour of his fellow-citizens, which may be called a civic principality. To arrive at this position depends not entirely on worth or entirely on fortune, but rather on cunning assisted by fortune. One attains it by help of popular favour or by the favour of the aristocracy. For in every city these two opposite parties are to be found, arising from the desire of the populace to avoid the oppression of the great, and the desire of the great to command and oppress the people. And from these two opposing interests arises in the city one of three effects: either absolute government, liberty, or license. The former is created either by the populace or the nobility depending on the relative opportunities of the two parties; for when the nobility see that they are unable to resist the people they unite in creating one of their number prince, so as to be able to carry out their own designs under the shadow of his authority. The populace, on the other hand, when unable to resist the nobility, endeavour to create a prince in order to be protected by his authority. He who becomes prince by help of the nobility has greater difficulty in maintaining his power than he who is raised by the populace, for he is surrounded by those who think themselves his equals, and is thus unable to direct or command as he pleases. But one who is raised to the leadership by popular favour finds himself alone, and has no one or very few who are not ready to obey him. Besides which, it is impossible to satisfy the nobility by fair dealing and without inflicting injury on others, whereas it is very easy to satisfy the mass of the people in this way. For the aim of the people is more honest than that of the nobility, the latter desiring to oppress, and the former merely to avoid oppression. It must also be added that the prince can never insure himself against a hostile populace on account of their number, but he can against the hostility of the great, as they are but few. The worst that a prince has to expect from a hostile people is to be abandoned, but from hostile nobles he has to fear not only abandonment but their active opposition, and as they are more farseeing and more cunning, they are always in time to save themselves and take sides with the one who they expect will conquer. The prince is, moreover, obliged to live always with the same people, but he can easily do without the same nobility, being able to make and unmake them at any time, and increase their position or deprive them of it as he pleases. And to throw further light on this part, I would say, that the nobles are to be considered in two different manners; that is, they are either to be ruled so as to make them entirely depend on your fortunes, or else not. Those that are thus bound to you and are not rapacious, must be honoured and loved; those who are not bound must be considered in two ways, they either do this through pusillanimity and natural want of courage, and in this case you ought to make use of them, and especially such as are of good counsel, so that they may honour you in prosperity and in adversity you have not to fear them. But when they are not bound to you of set purpose and for ambitious ends, it is a sign that they think more of themselves than of you; and from such men the prince must guard himself and look upon them as secret enemies, who will help to ruin him when in adversity. One, however, who becomes prince by favour of the populace, must maintain its friendship, which he will find easy, the people asking nothing but not to be oppressed. But one who against the people's wishes becomes prince by favour of the nobles, should above all endeavour to gain the favour of the people; this will be easy to him if he protects them. And as men, who receive good from those they expected evil from, feel under a greater obligation to their benefactor, so the subject populace will become even better disposed towards him than if he had become prince through their favour. The prince can win their favour in many ways, which vary according to circumstances, for which no certain rule can be given, and will therefore be passed over.
But now we come to the situation where a citizen becomes prince not through wrongdoing or extreme violence, but with the support of his fellow citizens, which we can call a civic principality. Achieving this position relies not solely on talent or luck but rather on skill boosted by fortune. One gains it through popular support or by the backing of the aristocracy. In every city, there are these two opposing factions stemming from the people's desire to escape the oppression of the powerful and the powerful's desire to dominate and subjugate the citizens. From these conflicting interests emerge one of three outcomes in the city: absolute rule, freedom, or chaos. The former is established either by the people or the nobility, depending on the power dynamics between the two groups; when the nobility realize they cannot resist the populace, they come together to appoint one of their own as prince to pursue their own agendas under his shield of authority. Conversely, when the people are unable to stand up against the nobility, they push to create a prince to gain protection through his authority. A prince supported by the nobility faces more challenges in keeping his power than one who rises through popular support, as he is surrounded by those who consider themselves his equals and thus struggles to lead or command freely. Meanwhile, someone who gains leadership through public backing often finds himself alone, with few who are not ready to obey him. Furthermore, it's impossible to satisfy the nobility without doing harm to others, but it’s quite easy to meet the needs of the general populace this way. The people's goals are generally more straightforward than those of the nobility, who seek to oppress, while the populace simply aims to avoid oppression. It’s also important to note that a prince can never fully protect himself from a hostile public because of their sheer numbers, while he can defend against the fewer noble opponents. The worst outcome a prince might face from an angry populace is being abandoned, but from hostile nobles, he risks not just abandonment but their active resistance, as they tend to be more strategic and clever, often ready to side with whoever they believe is likely to win. Additionally, the prince is compelled to consistently associate with the same people, but he can easily distance himself from the nobility, creating and dismantling their roles whenever he chooses and altering their position as he sees fit. To clarify this aspect further, nobles can generally be viewed in two ways: they can either be ruled in such a way that they depend entirely on your fortunes or not. Those who are tied to you and aren’t greedy should be honored and loved; those who aren’t tied can be perceived in two ways: either they do so out of cowardice and a natural lack of bravery, and in this case, you should engage with them, especially those who provide good advice, so they will honor you in good times, and you won't have to fear them in bad times. But if they’re not tied to you intentionally and out of ambition, it’s a sign they value themselves more than you; thus, the prince must protect himself from them and view them as hidden enemies, ready to betray him in difficult times. However, a prince who rises through the people's favor must maintain their friendship, which is relatively easy since the people only ask not to be oppressed. A prince who gains power against the people's will through noble support must strive above all to win the people's favor; this will be straightforward if he protects them. Just as those who receive good from someone they expected harm from feel more indebted to their benefactor, the subject population will be even more inclined to support him than if he had come to power through their favor. The prince can win their support through various means, which change depending on the situation, and there are no definitive rules for this, so it will be set aside.
I will only say, in conclusion, that it is necessary for a prince to possess the friendship of the people; otherwise he has no resource in times of adversity. Nabis, prince of the Spartans, sustained a siege by the whole of Greece and a victorious Roman army, and defended against them his country and maintained his own position. It sufficed when the danger arose for him to make sure of a few, which would not have been enough if the populace had been hostile to him. And let no one oppose my opinion in this by quoting the trite proverb, "He who builds on the people, builds on mud"; because that is true when a private citizen relies upon the people and persuades himself that they will liberate him if he is oppressed by enemies or by the magistrates; in this case he might often find himself deceived, as happened in Rome to the Gracchi and in Florence to Messer Georgio Scali.
I’ll just say, in conclusion, that it’s essential for a leader to have the support of the people; otherwise, they have no help during tough times. Nabis, the prince of the Spartans, endured a siege from all of Greece and a victorious Roman army, defending his country and holding onto his position. When the threat came, it was enough for him to secure a few allies, which wouldn’t have been sufficient if the public had turned against him. And no one should challenge my view by quoting the old saying, "He who builds on the people, builds on mud"; that’s true when a private citizen depends on the people and believes they will help him if he’s oppressed by enemies or officials; in such cases, he might often find himself let down, as happened in Rome with the Gracchi and in Florence with Messer Georgio Scali.
But when it is a prince who founds himself on this basis, one who can command and is a man of courage, and does not get frightened in adversity, and does not neglect other preparations, and one who by his own courage and measures animates the mass of the people, he will not find himself deceived by them, and he will find that he has laid his foundations well. Usually these principalities are in danger when the prince from the position of a civil ruler changes to an absolute one, for these princes either command themselves or by means of magistrates. In the latter case their position is weaker and more dangerous, for they are at the mercy of those citizens who are appointed magistrates, who can, especially in times of adversity, with great facility deprive them of their position, either by acting against them or by not obeying them. The prince is not in time, in such dangers, to assume absolute authority, for the citizens and subjects who are accustomed to take their orders from the magistrates are not ready in these emergencies to obey his, and he will always in doubtful times lack men whom he can rely on. Such a prince cannot base himself on what he sees in quiet times, when the citizens have need of the state; for then every one is full of promises and each one is ready to die for him when death is far off; but in adversity, when the state has need of citizens, then he will find but few. And this experience is the more dangerous, in that it can only be had once. Therefore a wise prince will seek means by which his subjects will always and in every possible condition of things have need of his government, and then they will always be faithful to him.
But when a prince builds his rule on this foundation, one who can lead and is brave, who doesn’t get scared in tough times and doesn’t neglect other preparations, and who inspires the people through his own courage and actions, he won’t be fooled by them, and he’ll see that he has established solid foundations. Typically, these principalities are at risk when the prince shifts from being a civil ruler to an absolute one, since these princes either lead themselves or through magistrates. In the latter situation, their position is weaker and more precarious, as they depend on appointed magistrates, who can, especially in tough times, easily strip them of their power by either opposing them or ignoring their commands. The prince can’t just suddenly take absolute control in such crises because the citizens and subjects who are used to taking orders from magistrates won’t be ready to obey him in emergencies, and he will always lack trustworthy supporters in uncertain times. A prince cannot rely on the behavior of citizens in peaceful situations, when they depend on the state; during those times, everyone is full of promises and ready to die for him when death seems distant; but in challenging times, when the state needs citizens, he will find very few. This lesson is even more dangerous because it can only be learned once. So, a wise prince will find ways to ensure that his subjects always need his leadership, and then they will remain loyal to him.
CHAPTER X
HOW THE STRENGTH OF ALL STATES SHOULD BE MEASURED
In examining the character of these principalities it is necessary to consider another point, namely, whether the prince has such a position as to be able in case of need to maintain himself alone, or whether he has always need of the protection of others. The better to explain this I would say, that I consider those capable of maintaining themselves alone who can, through abundance of men or money, put together a sufficient army, and hold the field against any one who assails them; and I consider to have need of others, those who cannot take the field against their enemies, but are obliged to take refuge within their walls and stand on the defensive. We have already discussed the former case and will speak in future of it as occasion arises. In the second case there is nothing to be said except to encourage such a prince to provision and fortify his own town, and not to trouble about the country. And whoever has strongly fortified his town and, as regards the government of his subjects, has proceeded as we have already described and will further relate, will be attacked with great reluctance, for men are always averse to enterprises in which they foresee difficulties, and it can never appear easy to attack one who has his town well guarded and is not hated by the people. The cities of Germany are extremely liberal, have little surrounding country, and obey the emperor when they choose, and they do not fear him or any other potentate that they have about them. They are fortified in such a manner that every one thinks that to reduce them would be tedious and difficult, for they all have the necessary moats and bastions, sufficient artillery, and always keep in the public storehouses food and drink and fuel for one year. Beyond which, to keep the lower classes satisfied, and without loss to the public, they have always enough means to give them work for one year in these employments which form the nerve and life of the town, and in the industries by which the lower classes live; military exercises are still held in reputation, and many regulations are in force for maintaining them. A prince, therefore, who possesses a strong city and does not make himself hated, cannot be assaulted; and if he were to be so, the assailant would be obliged to retire shamefully; for so many things change, that it is almost impossible for any one to hold the field for a year with his armies idle. And to those who urge that the people, having their possessions outside and seeing them burnt, will not have patience, and the long siege and self-interest will make them forget their prince, I reply that a powerful and courageous prince will always overcome those difficulties by now raising the hopes of his subjects that the evils will not last long, now impressing them with fear of the enemy's cruelty, now by dextrously assuring himself of those who appear too bold. Besides which, the enemy would naturally burn and ruin the country on first arriving and in the time when men's minds are still hot and eager to defend themselves, and therefore the prince has still less to fear, for after some days, when people have cooled down, the damage is done, the evil has been suffered, and there is no remedy, so that they are the more ready to unite with their prince, as it appears that he is under an obligation to them, their houses having been burnt and their possessions ruined in his defence.
When looking at the character of these principalities, it’s important to consider whether the prince is in a position to stand alone when necessary or if he always relies on others for protection. To clarify, I believe those who can maintain themselves alone are capable of assembling enough men or resources to form a strong army and defend against any attackers. In contrast, those who rely on others are unable to confront their enemies directly and must take refuge within their walls, focusing on defense. We’ve already discussed the former situation and will cover it again as needed. In the latter case, there’s not much to say other than to advise such a prince to stock up and strengthen his city instead of worrying about the surrounding area. A prince who has fortified his town and governs his subjects as we’ve already described—and will further elaborate on—will be attacked with great reluctance. People generally shy away from ventures where they anticipate difficulties, and it’s never easy to attack someone who has a well-defended city and is not disliked by the populace. German cities, for example, are very liberal, have little surrounding land, and obey the emperor when it suits them, showing no fear of him or any other local powers. They are fortified in such a way that many believe subduing them would be a long and challenging process, as they all have necessary moats and bastions, adequate artillery, and always keep enough food, drink, and fuel in public storage to last a year. Additionally, to keep the lower classes satisfied and avoid public unrest, they ensure there are enough jobs for them for a year in the essential trades that sustain the city. Military drills are still valued, and various regulations are in place to maintain them. Therefore, a prince with a strong city who isn’t hated cannot be easily attacked. If he were to face an assault, the attacker would likely retreat in embarrassment. Since circumstances change so much, it's nearly impossible for anyone to maintain a military presence for a year while their armies sit idle. To those who argue that people will grow impatient when their possessions are outside and being destroyed, I respond that a strong and courageous prince can always overcome these challenges by raising his subjects’ hopes that the suffering won’t last long, instilling fear of the enemies’ cruelty, and cleverly securing the loyalty of those who appear overly bold. Moreover, the enemy would typically devastate the countryside upon arrival, especially when people are still eager to defend themselves. This means the prince has even less to worry about because, after a few days, once emotions have settled, the damage is done and cannot be undone. At that point, people are likely to unite with their prince, feeling grateful that he has endured the destruction of their homes and possessions in his defense.
It is the nature of men to be as much bound by the benefits that they confer as by those they receive. From which it follows that, everything considered, a prudent prince will not find it difficult to uphold the courage of his subjects both at the commencement and during a state of siege, if he possesses provisions and means to defend himself.
It’s human nature for people to feel just as tied to the benefits they give as to those they receive. Therefore, a wise leader will find it easy to maintain the courage of his people at the start and throughout a siege, as long as he has enough supplies and resources to defend himself.
CHAPTER XI
OF ECCLESIASTICAL PRINCIPALITIES
It now remains to us only to speak of ecclesiastical principalities, with regard to which the difficulties lie wholly before they are possessed. They are acquired either by ability or by fortune; but are maintained without either, for they are sustained by the ancient religious customs, which are so powerful and of such quality, that they keep their princes in power in whatever manner they proceed and live. These alone have a state without defending it, have subjects without governing them, and the states, not being defended, are not taken from them; the subjects not being governed do not disturb themselves, and neither think of nor are capable of alienating themselves from them. Only these principalities, therefore, are secure and happy. But as they are upheld by higher causes, which the human mind cannot attain to, I will abstain from speaking of them; for being exalted and maintained by God, it would be the work of a presumptuous and foolish man to discuss them.
It now only remains for us to talk about ecclesiastical principalities, where the challenges arise entirely before they are acquired. They are gained either through skill or luck, but once obtained, they don’t require either to be maintained, as they are supported by longstanding religious traditions. These traditions are so strong and significant that they keep their rulers in power regardless of how they act or live. These principalities have a status without needing to defend it, have subjects without having to govern them, and since the states are not defended, they are not taken away from them. The subjects, not being governed, do not trouble themselves and neither think about nor are capable of distancing themselves from their rulers. Therefore, these principalities are truly secure and prosperous. However, since they are supported by higher powers that the human mind cannot grasp, I will refrain from discussing them; as they are elevated and sustained by God, it would be the work of a presumptuous and foolish person to delve into them.
However, I might be asked how it has come about that the Church has reached such great temporal power, when, previous to Alexander VI., the Italian potentates,—and not merely the really powerful ones, but every lord or baron, however insignificant, held it in slight esteem as regards temporal power; whereas now it is dreaded by a king of France, whom it has been able to drive out of Italy, and has also been able to ruin the Venetians. Therefore, although this is well known, I do not think it superfluous to call it to mind. Before Charles, King of France, came into Italy, this country was under the rule of the pope, the Venetians, the King of Naples, the Duke of Milan, and the Florentines. These potentates had to have two chief cares: one, that no foreigner should enter Italy by force of arms, the other that none of the existing governments should extend its dominions. Those chiefly to be watched were the pope and the Venetians. To keep back the Venetians required the ruin of all the others, as in the defence of Ferrara, and to keep down the pope they made use of the Roman barons. These were divided into two factions, the Orsinis and the Colonnas, and as there was constant quarrelling between them, and they were constantly under arms, before the eyes of the pope, they kept the papacy weak and infirm. And although there arose now and then a resolute pope like Sextus, yet his fortune or ability was never able to liberate him from these evils. The shortness of their life was the reason of this, for in the course of ten years which, as a general rule, a pope lived, he had great difficulty in suppressing even one of the factions, and if, for example, a pope had almost put down the Colonnas, a new pope would succeed who was hostile to the Orsinis, which caused the Colonnas to spring up again, and he was not in time to suppress them. This caused the temporal power of the pope to be of little esteem in Italy.
However, I might be asked how it came to be that the Church gained such significant temporal power, when, before Alexander VI, the Italian rulers—not just the most powerful ones but every lord or baron, no matter how minor—held it in low regard regarding temporal authority; whereas now it is feared by a king of France, whom it has managed to drive out of Italy and has also succeeded in ruining the Venetians. Therefore, even though this is well known, I don’t think it’s unnecessary to point it out. Before Charles, King of France, came into Italy, the country was ruled by the pope, the Venetians, the King of Naples, the Duke of Milan, and the Florentines. These rulers had two main concerns: one, preventing any foreign invasion into Italy by force, and the other, ensuring that none of the existing governments expanded their territories. The main ones to watch were the pope and the Venetians. Keeping the Venetians at bay required undermining all the others, as seen in the defense of Ferrara, and to keep the pope in check, they relied on the Roman barons. These barons were split into two factions, the Orsinis and the Colonnas, and since they were always quarreling and constantly armed in the presence of the pope, they kept the papacy weak and vulnerable. And although strong popes like Sextus would occasionally arise, his luck or skill never managed to free him from these troubles. The brevity of their lives contributed to this, because during the typical ten-year lifespan of a pope, he struggled to even suppress one of the factions, and if, for example, a pope nearly subdued the Colonnas, a new pope would take over who was opposed to the Orsinis, causing the Colonnas to rise again, and he wouldn’t be able to act quickly enough to suppress them. This led to the temporal power of the pope being held in little regard in Italy.
Then arose Alexander VI. who of all the pontiffs who have ever reigned, best showed how a pope might prevail both by money and by force. With Duke Valentine as his instrument, and on the occasion of the French invasion, he did all that I have previously described in speaking of the actions of the duke. And although his object was to aggrandise not the Church but the duke, what he did resulted in the aggrandisement of the Church, which after the death of the duke became the heir of his labours. Then came Pope Julius, who found the Church powerful, possessing all Romagna, all the Roman barons suppressed, and the factions destroyed by the severity of Alexander. He also found the way open for accumulating wealth in ways never used before the time of Alexander. These measures were not only followed by Julius, but increased; he resolved to gain Bologna, put down the Venetians and drive the French from Italy, in all which enterprises he was successful. He merits the greater praise, as he did everything to increase the power of the Church and not of any private person. He also kept the Orsini and Colonna parties in the conditions in which he found them, and although there were some leaders among them who might have made changes, there were two things that kept them steady: one, the greatness of the Church, which they dreaded; the other, the fact that they had no cardinals, who are the origin of the tumults among them. For these parties are never at rest when they have cardinals, for these stir up the parties both within Rome and outside, and the barons are forced to defend them. Thus from the ambitions of prelates arise the discords and tumults among the barons. His holiness, Pope Leo X., therefore, has found the pontificate in a very powerful condition, from which it is hoped, that as those popes made it great by force of armies, so he through his goodness and infinite other virtues will make it both great and venerated.
Then came Alexander VI, who showed better than any other pope how one could succeed with both money and power. Using Duke Valentine as his tool during the French invasion, he carried out everything I described earlier regarding the duke's actions. While his goal was to elevate not the Church but the duke, his actions ultimately benefited the Church, which inherited the duke's efforts after his death. Then came Pope Julius, who found the Church strong, having control over all of Romagna, with all the Roman barons subdued and factions wiped out thanks to Alexander's harshness. He also discovered new ways to accumulate wealth that hadn't been utilized prior to Alexander. Julius not only followed these strategies but expanded upon them; he aimed to take Bologna, suppress the Venetians, and drive the French out of Italy, achieving success in all these efforts. He deserves more praise because everything he did was to enhance the Church's power, not that of any individual. He also maintained the Orsini and Colonna factions in their original state, and despite having some leaders among them who might have instigated change, two things kept them stable: first, the Church's power, which they feared; second, the absence of cardinals, who often spark conflicts among them. These factions are never calm when they have cardinals, as they provoke disputes both within Rome and beyond, forcing the barons to protect them. Therefore, the ambitions of church leaders breed discord among the barons. Pope Leo X, has thus inherited a deeply powerful papacy, from which we hope that, just as those popes strengthened it through military might, he will enhance it through his kindness and numerous other virtues, making it both great and revered.
CHAPTER XII
THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF MILITIA AND MERCENARY SOLDIERS
Having now discussed fully the qualities of these principalities of which I proposed to treat, and partially considered the causes of their prosperity or failure, and having also showed the methods by which many have sought to obtain such states, it now remains for me to treat generally of the methods of attack and defence that can be used in each of them. We have said already how necessary it is for a prince to have his foundations good, otherwise he is certain to be ruined. The chief foundations of all states, whether new, old, or mixed, are good laws and good arms. And as there cannot be good laws where there are not good arms, and where there are good arms there should be good laws, I will not now discuss the laws, but will speak of the arms. I say, therefore, that the arms by which a prince defends his possessions are either his own, or else mercenaries, or auxiliaries, or mixed. The mercenaries and auxiliaries are useless and dangerous, and if any one keeps his state based on the arms of mercenaries, he will never stand firm or sure, as they are disunited, ambitious, without discipline, faithless, bold amongst friends, cowardly amongst enemies, they have no fear of God, and keep no faith with men. Ruin is only deferred as long as the assault is postponed; in peace you are despoiled by them, and in war by the enemy. The cause of this is that they have no love or other motive to keep them in the field beyond a trifling wage, which is not enough to make them ready to die for you. They are quite willing to be your soldiers so long as you do not make war, but when war comes, it is either fly or be off. I ought to have little trouble in proving this, since the ruin of Italy is now caused by nothing else but through her having relied for many years on mercenary arms. These were somewhat improved in a few cases, and appeared courageous among themselves, but when the foreigner came they showed their worthlessness. Thus it came about that King Charles of France was allowed to take Italy without the slightest trouble, and those who said that it was owing to our sins, spoke the truth, but it was not the sins that they believed but those that I have related. And as it was the sins of princes, they too have suffered the punishment. I will explain more fully the defects of these arms. Mercenary captains are either very capable men or not; if they are, you cannot rely upon them, for they will always aspire to their own greatness, either by oppressing you, their master, or by oppressing others against your intentions; but if the captain is not an able man, he will generally ruin you. And if it is replied to this, that whoever has armed forces will do the same, whether these are mercenary or not, I would reply that as armies are to be used either by a prince or by a republic, the prince must go in person to take the position of captain, and the republic must send its own citizens. If the one sent turns out incompetent, it must change him; and if capable, keep him by law from going beyond the proper limits. And it is seen by experience that only princes and armed republics make very great progress, whereas mercenary forces do nothing but damage, and also an armed republic submits less easily to the rule of one of its citizens than a republic armed by foreign forces. Rome and Sparta were for many centuries well armed and free. The Swiss are well armed and enjoy great freedom. As an example of mercenary armies in antiquity there are the Carthaginians, who were oppressed by their mercenary soldiers, after the termination of the first war with the Romans, even while they still had their own citizens as captains. Philip of Macedon was made captain of their forces by the Thebans after the death of Epaminondas, and after gaining the victory he deprived them of liberty. The Milanese, on the death of Duke Philip, hired Francesco Sforza against the Venetians, who having overcome the enemy at Caravaggio, allied himself with them to oppress the Milanese his employers. The father of this Sforza, being a soldier in the service of the Queen Giovanna of Naples, left her suddenly unarmed, by which she was compelled, in order not to lose the kingdom, to throw herself into the arms of the King of Aragon. And if the Venetians and Florentines have in times past increased their dominions by means of such forces, and their captains have not made themselves princes but have defended them, I reply that the Florentines in this case have been favoured by chance, for of the capable leaders whom they might have feared, some did not conquer, some met with opposition, and others directed their ambition elsewhere. The one who did not conquer was Sir John Hawkwood, whose fidelity could not be known as he was not victorious, but every one will admit that, had he conquered, the Florentines would have been at his mercy. Sforza had always the Bracceschi against him, they being constantly at enmity. Francesco directed his ambition towards Lombardy; Braccio against the Church and the kingdom of Naples. But let us look at what followed a short time ago. The Florentines appointed Paolo Vitelli their captain, a man of great prudence, who had risen from a private station to the highest reputation. If he had taken Pisa no one can deny that it was highly important for the Florentines to retain his friendship, because had he become the soldier of their enemies they would have had no means of opposing him; and in order to retain him they would have been obliged to obey him. As to the Venetians, if one considers the progress they made, it will be seen that they acted surely and gloriously so long as they made war with their own forces; that it was before they commenced their enterprises on land that they fought courageously with their own gentlemen and armed populace, but when they began to fight on land they abandoned this virtue, and began to follow the Italian custom. And at the commencement of their land conquests they had not much to fear from their captains, their land possessions not being very large, and their reputation being great, but as their possessions increased, as they did under Carmagnola, they had an example of their mistake. For seeing that he was very powerful, after he had defeated the Duke of Milan, and knowing, on the other hand, that he was not enterprising in warfare, they considered that they would not make any more conquests with him, and they neither would nor could dismiss him, for fear of losing what they had already gained. They were therefore obliged, in order to make sure of him, to have him killed. They then had for captains Bartolommeo da Bergamo, Roberto da San Severino, Count di Pitigliano, and such like, from whom they had to fear loss instead of gain, as happened subsequently at Vailà, where in one day they lost what they had laboriously gained in eight hundred years; for with these forces, only slow and trifling acquisitions are made, but sudden and miraculous losses. And as I have cited these examples from Italy, which has now for many years been governed by mercenary forces, I will now deal more largely with them, so that having seen their origin and progress, they can be better remedied. You must understand that in these latter times, as soon as the empire began to be repudiated in Italy and the pope to gain greater reputation in temporal matters, Italy was divided into many states; many of the principal cities took up arms against their nobles, who, favoured by the emperor, had held them in subjection, and the Church encouraged this in order to increase its temporal power. In many other cities one of the inhabitants became prince. Thus Italy having fallen almost entirely into the hands of the Church and a few republics, and the priests and other citizens not being accustomed to bear arms, they began to hire foreigners as soldiers. The first to bring reputation for this kind of militia was Alberigo da Como, a native of Romagna. The discipline of this man produced, among others, Braccio and Sforza, who were in their day the arbiters of Italy. After these came all those others who up to the present day have commanded the armies of Italy, and the result of their prowess has been that Italy has been overrun by Charles, preyed on by Louis, tyrannised over by Ferrando, and insulted by the Swiss. The system adopted by them was, in the first place, to increase their own reputation by discrediting the infantry. They did this because, as they had no country and lived on their earnings, a few foot soldiers did not augment their reputation, and they could not maintain a large number and therefore they restricted themselves almost entirely to cavalry, by which with a smaller number they were well paid and honoured. They reduced things to such a state that in an army of 20,000 soldiers there were not 2000 foot. They had also used every means to spare themselves and the soldiers any hardship or fear by not killing each other in their encounters, but taking prisoners without a blow. They made no attacks on fortifications by night; and those in the fortifications did not attack the tents at night, they made no stockades on ditches round their camps, and did not take the field in winter. All these things were permitted by their military rules, and adopted, as we have said, to avoid trouble and danger, so that they have reduced Italy to slavery and degradation.
Having fully discussed the qualities of the principalities that I intended to cover, and having partially considered the reasons for their success or failure, I will now address the general methods of attack and defense applicable to each of them. We have already established how essential it is for a prince to have a strong foundation; otherwise, he is bound to fail. The main foundations of all states, whether new, old, or mixed, are good laws and good military forces. Since there cannot be good laws without good military forces, and where there are good military forces there should also be good laws, I won’t delve into the laws now but will focus on military forces. Therefore, the military forces a prince uses to defend his territory can be his own, or they can be mercenaries, auxiliaries, or a mix of both. Mercenaries and auxiliaries are ineffective and risky. If anyone relies on mercenaries to maintain their state, they will never be stable or secure because those forces are disorganized, ambitious, undisciplined, untrustworthy, brave only when in friendly company, and cowardly when facing the enemy; they fear neither God nor man. Their downfall is only postponed until conflict arises. In peacetime, they can rob you; in wartime, they turn against you. The reason for this is simple: they have no loyalty or reason to stay other than a meager paycheck, too little to motivate them to fight for you. They are happy to serve as long as there’s no war, but when war does break out, they will either flee or abandon you. It should be easy to prove this point since Italy’s current downfall is solely due to its long-standing dependence on mercenary forces. In some instances, those forces might seem improved, displaying courage among themselves, but when faced with foreign foes, they reveal their true worthlessness. This is how King Charles of France managed to take Italy with hardly any resistance. Those who attributed this to our sins spoke a truth, but it was not the sins they thought; it was those I have recounted. Since it was the sins committed by princes, they too have faced the consequences. I will elaborate on the flaws of these military forces. Mercenary leaders can either be very capable or not; if they are capable, you can’t trust them, as they will always aspire to their own power by either oppressing you, their master, or acting against your interests; but if the leader is incompetent, they will usually lead to your downfall. If someone argues that anyone wielding armed forces would do the same, whether mercenary or otherwise, I would counter that armies must be used either by a prince or a republic. A prince must personally assume the role of captain, while a republic must send its own citizens. If the person sent is incompetent, he must be replaced; if capable, he must be legally restrained to prevent overreach. Experience shows that only princes and armed republics make significant progress, while mercenary forces cause nothing but harm. Additionally, an armed republic is less likely to submit to a citizen's authority than one empowered by mercenaries. Rome and Sparta enjoyed centuries of armament and freedom. The Swiss are well armed and enjoy considerable liberty. Historical examples of mercenary armies include the Carthaginians, who were oppressed by their mercenary soldiers following the end of the first war with Rome, even while still having their own citizens as commanders. Philip of Macedon became captain of their forces through the Thebans after Epaminondas’ death, and after he secured victory, he stripped them of their liberty. The Milanese, upon Duke Philip's death, hired Francesco Sforza against the Venetians; after defeating the enemy at Caravaggio, he allied with them to oppress the Milanese who had originally employed him. Sforza’s father, a soldier serving Queen Giovanna of Naples, abandoned her unexpectedly, forcing her to seek refuge with the King of Aragon to preserve her kingdom. If the Venetians and Florentines have expanded their territories using such forces in the past and their commanders have not crowned themselves princes but have defended them, I would argue that the Florentines benefitted from luck. Many potential capable leaders either did not conquer, faced resistance, or pursued their ambitions elsewhere. The one who failed to conquer was Sir John Hawkwood; his loyalty could not be gauged as he didn’t achieve victory, but everyone agrees that had he succeeded, the Florentines would have been at his mercy. Sforza always faced opposition from the Bracceschi, who were perpetual rivals. Francesco focused his ambitions on Lombardy; Braccio was concentrated on the Church and the Kingdom of Naples. But let’s examine recent events. The Florentines appointed Paolo Vitelli as their captain; he was a man of great wisdom who rose from humble beginnings to prominence. If he had taken Pisa, it’s undeniable that it was crucial for the Florentines to keep him in their favor because if he had turned into a soldier for their enemies, they would have had no way to counter him; to avoid this, they would have had to bow to his demands. As for the Venetians, if we look at their progression, we see that they performed admirably and with honor while fighting with their own forces. Before they started their land campaigns, they fought bravely alongside their own gentry and armed citizens; however, when they shifted their focus to land battles, they relinquished this virtue and adopted Italian practices. At the onset of their territorial conquests, they had little to fear from their commanders due to their limited land holdings and strong reputation, but as their territory expanded, especially under Carmagnola, they faced the repercussions of their missteps. Recognizing his strength after he defeated the Duke of Milan—and knowing he wasn’t proactive in warfare—they concluded that they would not gain any more territory with him at the helm. They couldn’t dismiss him without risking their existing gains, leaving them with no choice but to have him killed. Following this, they relied on captains like Bartolommeo da Bergamo, Roberto da San Severino, Count di Pitigliano, and others, from whom they had to fear losses instead of advantages. This became clear later at Vailà, where they lost, in one day, what they had laboriously built over eight hundred years; with such forces, progress comes slowly and is insignificant, while losses can be rapid and devastating. Since I've provided these examples from Italy, which has suffered for many years under mercenary forces, I will now explore them further, so we can better understand their origins and progression for effective remedies. You should note that in recent times, as soon as the empire began to lose its influence in Italy and the pope gained more temporal power, Italy was fragmented into various states; many of the major cities revolted against their nobles, who had maintained control under the emperor, with the Church encouraging this to bolster its own power. In many other cities, one local man established himself as the prince. Consequently, Italy almost entirely fell under the Church's dominion and a few republics, with clergymen and other citizens unaccustomed to military life turning to hire foreign soldiers. The first to bring recognition to this type of militia was Alberigo da Como, a Romagna native. His discipline led to the emergence of figures like Braccio and Sforza, who were the arbiters of Italy in their time. Following them, many others have commanded Italy’s armies, resulting in Italy being ravaged by Charles, exploited by Louis, ruled oppressively by Ferrando, and humiliated by the Swiss. Initially, their strategy was to elevate their own reputation by disparaging infantry. They did this because, lacking a homeland and relying on their earnings, a few foot soldiers didn’t enhance their standing, so they could not maintain a large number and essentially limited themselves to cavalry, allowing them to be well-compensated and respected with fewer troops. They brought things to a point where, in an army of 20,000, there were fewer than 2,000 foot soldiers. They also took every measure to avoid inflicting hardship or danger on themselves or their soldiers by forgoing deadly encounters, instead opting to take prisoners easily. They refrained from night assaults on fortifications; those within the fortifications also refrained from attacking tents at night. They didn’t create stockades or ditches around their camps or take the field in winter. All these practices, allowed by their military code, were established to prevent trouble and risk, leading to Italy’s degradation and enslavement.
CHAPTER XIII
OF AUXILIARY, MIXED, AND NATIVE TROOPS
Auxiliary forces, which are the other kind of useless forces, are when one calls on a potentate to come and aid one with his troops, as was done in recent times by Julius, who seeing the wretched failure of his mercenary forces, in his Ferrara enterprise, had recourse to auxiliaries, and arranged with Ferrando, King of Spain, that he should help him with his armies. These forces may be good in themselves, but they are always dangerous for those who borrow them, for if they lose you are defeated, and if they conquer you remain their prisoner. And although ancient history is full of examples of this, I will not depart from the example of Pope Julius II., which is still fresh. Nothing could be less prudent than the course he adopted; for, wishing to take Ferrara, he put himself entirely into the power of a foreigner. But by good fortune there arose a third cause which prevented him reaping the effects of his bad choice; for when his auxiliaries were beaten at Ravenna, the Swiss rose up and drove back the victors, against all expectation of himself or others, so that he was not taken prisoner by the enemy which had fled, nor by his own auxiliaries, having conquered by other arms than theirs. The Florentines, being totally disarmed, hired 10,000 Frenchmen to attack Pisa, by which measure they ran greater risk than at any period of their struggles. The emperor of Constantinople, to oppose his neighbours, put 10,000 Turks into Greece, who after the war would not go away again, which was the beginning of the servitude of Greece to the infidels. Any one, therefore, who wishes not to conquer, would do well to use these forces, which are much more dangerous than mercenaries, as with them ruin is complete, for they are all united, and owe obedience to others, whereas with mercenaries, when they have conquered, it requires more time and a good opportunity for them to injure you, as they do not form a single body and have been engaged and paid by you, therefore a third party that you have made leader cannot at once acquire enough authority to be able to injure you. In a word, the greatest dangers with mercenaries lies in their cowardice and reluctance to fight, but with auxiliaries the danger lies in their courage. A wise prince, therefore, always avoids these forces and has recourse to his own, and would prefer rather to lose with his own men than conquer with the forces of others, not deeming it a true victory which is gained by foreign arms. I never hesitate to cite the example of Cesare Borgia and his actions. This duke entered Romagna with auxiliary troops, leading forces composed entirely of French soldiers, and with these he took Imola and Forli; but as they seemed unsafe, he had recourse to mercenaries, and hired the Orsini and Vitelli; afterwards finding these uncertain to handle, unfaithful and dangerous, he suppressed them, and relied upon his own men. And the difference between these forces can be easily seen if one considers the difference between the reputation of the duke when he had only the French, when he had the Orsini and Vitelli, and when he had to rely on himself and his own soldiers. His reputation will be found to have constantly increased, and he was never so highly esteemed as when every one saw that he was the sole master of his forces.
Auxiliary forces, which are another type of useless troops, involve calling on a ruler to assist you with their soldiers. This happened recently with Julius, who, after witnessing the terrible failure of his mercenary forces in his Ferrara campaign, sought help from Ferrando, the King of Spain, to bolster his armies. While these forces might be capable on their own, they are always risky for those who borrow them: if they lose, you are defeated; if they win, you become their captive. Historical examples abound, but I will stick to the more recent case of Pope Julius II., which is still relevant. His choice was anything but wise; wanting to take Ferrara, he completely put himself at the mercy of a foreign power. Luckily, a third factor emerged that prevented him from suffering the consequences of his poor decision. When his auxiliary troops were defeated at Ravenna, the Swiss rallied and pushed back the victors, surprising everyone, including Julius himself, meaning he was not captured by the fleeing enemy or his own auxiliaries, as he had been saved by forces other than theirs. The Florentines, who were completely disarmed, hired 10,000 French troops to attack Pisa, which exposed them to greater risk than at any other time during their conflicts. The emperor of Constantinople, to counter his neighbors, sent 10,000 Turks into Greece, who, after the war, wouldn’t leave, marking the start of Greece’s servitude to the infidels. Therefore, anyone who does not truly wish to dominate should avoid using these forces, as they are far more dangerous than mercenaries. With auxiliaries, the risk is total ruin because they act in unison and owe allegiance to others, while mercenaries, after a victory, require more time and favorable circumstances to turn against you. They are not a cohesive unit and have been hired and paid by you; thus, a third party, whom you’ve appointed as a leader, cannot immediately gain enough authority to harm you. In summary, the greatest danger with mercenaries lies in their cowardice and unwillingness to fight, whereas, with auxiliaries, the risk arises from their bravery. A wise prince should, therefore, avoid these forces and rely on his own troops, preferring to lose with his men rather than win with others, not considering a victory achieved by foreign forces to be a true one. I often refer to Cesare Borgia’s example. This duke entered Romagna with auxiliary troops, leading forces made up entirely of French soldiers. With them, he captured Imola and Forli; but feeling insecure, he turned to mercenaries and hired the Orsini and Vitelli. Later, finding them unreliable, untrustworthy, and dangerous, he got rid of them and depended on his own men. The differences between these forces are clear, considering the variations in the duke's reputation when he only had the French, when he had the Orsini and Vitelli, and when he had to rely solely on himself and his own soldiers. His reputation only grew, and he was never more respected than when everyone realized he was the true master of his forces.
I do not wish to go away from recent Italian instances, but I cannot omit Hiero of Syracuse, whom I have already mentioned. This man being, as I said, made head of the army by the Syracusans, immediately recognised the uselessness of that mercenary militia which was composed like our Italian mercenary troops, and as he thought it unsafe either to retain them or dismiss them, he had them cut in pieces and thenceforward made war with his own arms and not those of others. I would also call to mind a figure out of the Old Testament which well illustrates this point. When David offered to Saul to go and fight with the Philistine champion Goliath, Saul, to encourage him, armed him with his own arms, which when David had tried on he refused saying, that with them he could not fight so well; he preferred, therefore, to face the enemy with his own sling and knife. In short, the arms of others either fall away from you, or overburden you, or else impede you. Charles VIII., father of King Louis XL, having through good fortune and bravery liberated France from the English, recognised this necessity of being armed with his own forces, and established in his kingdom a system of men-at-arms and infantry. Afterwards King Louis his son abolished the infantry and began to hire Swiss, which mistake being followed by others is, as may now be seen, a cause of danger to that kingdom. For by giving such reputation to the Swiss, France has disheartened all her own troops, the infantry having been abolished and the men-at-arms being obliged to foreigners for assistance; for being accustomed to fight with Swiss troops, they think they cannot conquer without them. Whence it comes that the French are insufficiently strong to oppose the Swiss, and without the aid of the Swiss they will not venture against others. The armies of the French are thus of a mixed kind, partly mercenary and partly her own; taken together they are much better than troops entirely composed of mercenaries or auxiliaries, but much inferior to national forces.
I don’t want to stray from recent Italian examples, but I can’t overlook Hiero of Syracuse, whom I’ve already mentioned. As I said, this man was put in charge of the army by the Syracusans and immediately recognized the uselessness of the mercenary troops, which were similar to our Italian mercenaries. He thought it was unsafe to keep them or to get rid of them, so he had them executed and then fought with his own soldiers instead of relying on others. I’d also like to mention a story from the Old Testament that illustrates this point well. When David offered to fight the Philistine giant Goliath for Saul, Saul, wanting to encourage him, gave David his own armor. After trying it on, David refused, saying he couldn't fight well with it; he preferred to face the enemy with just his sling and dagger. Basically, using someone else’s armor either doesn’t suit you, weighs you down, or gets in the way. Charles VIII, the father of King Louis XI, successfully liberated France from the English through luck and bravery, recognizing the need to rely on his own forces and established a system of knights and infantry. Later, his son King Louis abolished the infantry and started hiring Swiss soldiers, which, as history shows, was a mistake that put the kingdom in a precarious position. By giving the Swiss such a great reputation, France has discouraged its own troops; the infantry was disbanded, and the knights became dependent on foreigners for help. Accustomed to fighting alongside the Swiss, they believe they can’t win without them. As a result, the French are not strong enough to oppose the Swiss, and without Swiss support, they hesitate to confront others. Therefore, the French army is a mix, partly mercenary and partly their own; overall, they are better than armies made entirely of mercenaries or auxiliaries but still much weaker than national forces.
CHAPTER XIV
WHAT THE DUTIES OF A PRINCE ARE WITH REGARD TO THE MILITIA
A Prince should therefore have no other aim or thought, nor take up any other thing for his study, but war and its order and discipline, for that is the only art that is necessary to one who commands, and it is of such virtue that it not only maintains those who are born princes, but often enables men of private fortune to attain to that rank. And one sees, on the other hand, that when princes think more of luxury than of arms, they lose their state. The chief cause which makes any one lose it, is the contempt of this art, and the way to acquire it is to be well versed in the same. Francesco Sforza, through being well armed, became, from a private position, Duke of Milan; his sons, through wishing to avoid the fatigue and hardship of war, from dukes became private persons. For among other evils caused by being disarmed, it renders you contemptible; which is one of those disgraceful things which a prince must guard against, as will be explained later. Because there is no comparison whatever between an armed man and a disarmed one; it is not reasonable to suppose that one who is armed will obey willingly one who is unarmed; or that any unarmed man will remain safe among armed servants. For one being disdainful and the other suspicious, it is not possible for them to act well together. And yet a prince who is ignorant of military matters, besides the other misfortunes already mentioned, cannot be esteemed by his soldiers, nor have confidence in them. He ought, therefore, never to let his thoughts stray from the exercise of war; and in peace he ought to practise it more than in war, which he can do in two ways: both by action and by study. As to action, he must, besides keeping his men well disciplined and exercised, engage continually in hunting, and thus accustom his body to hardships; and on the other hand learn the nature of the land, how the mountains rise, how the valleys are disposed, where the plains lie, and understand the nature of the rivers and swamps, and to this he should devote great attention. This knowledge is useful in two ways. In the first place, one learns to know one's country, and can the better see how to defend it. Then by means of the knowledge and experience gained in one locality, one can easily understand any other that it may be necessary to venture on, for the hills and valleys, plains and rivers of Tuscany, for instance, have a certain resemblance to those of other provinces, so that from a knowledge of the country in one province one can easily arrive at a knowledge of others. And that prince who is lacking in this skill is wanting in the first essentials of a leader; for it is this which teaches how to find the enemy, take up quarters, lead armies, arrange marches and occupy positions with advantage. Philopœmen, prince of the Achæi, among other praises bestowed on him by writers, is lauded because in times of peace he thought of nothing but the methods of warfare, and when he was in the country with his friends, he often stopped and asked them: If the enemy were on that hill and we found ourselves here with our army, which of us would have the advantage? How could we safely approach him maintaining our order? If we wished to retire, what ought we to do? If they retired, how should we follow them? And he put before them as they went along all the cases that might happen to an army, heard their opinion, gave his own, fortifying it by argument; so that through these continued cogitations there could never happen any incident when leading his armies for which he was not prepared. But as to exercise for the mind, the prince ought to read history and study the actions of eminent men, see how they acted in warfare, examine the causes of their victories and losses in order to imitate the former and avoid the latter, and above all, do as some eminent men have done in the past, who have imitated some one, who has been much praised and glorified, and have always kept their deeds and actions before them, as they say Alexander the Great imitated Achilles, Cæsar Alexander, and Scipio Cyrus. And whoever reads the life of Cyrus written by Xenophon, will perceive in the life of Scipio how gloriously he imitated him, and how, in chastity, affability, humanity, and liberality Scipio conformed to those qualities of Cyrus described by Xenophon.
A prince should have no other goals or thoughts, nor focus on anything else for his studies, except for war and its organization and discipline. That’s the only essential skill for someone in command, and it's so valuable that it not only keeps those born as princes in power but also allows wealthy individuals to rise to that level. On the flip side, when princes focus more on luxury than on military strength, they lose their states. The main reason anyone loses power is the disregard for this skill, and the way to gain it is to be well-informed in military matters. Francesco Sforza became the Duke of Milan from a private position because he was well-armed; his sons, however, wanting to avoid the difficulties of war, fell from dukes to private citizens. Among the many problems caused by weakness, being unarmed makes you contemptible, which is one of the disgraceful things a prince must avoid, as will be discussed later. There’s no comparison between an armed person and an unarmed one; it’s unreasonable to think that an armed individual would willingly obey an unarmed one, or that an unarmed person would feel safe among armed attendants. With one being disdainful and the other suspicious, they cannot work well together. Moreover, a prince who knows nothing about military matters, besides the other misfortunes already mentioned, will lack respect from his soldiers and won’t have their confidence. Therefore, he should never lose focus on military practice; in times of peace, he should actually practice it more than in warfare, which he can do in two ways: through action and study. In terms of action, he must keep his men well-disciplined and exercised, participate in hunting to toughen his body, and also learn about the geography—how the mountains rise, how the valleys are laid out, where the plains are, and understand the characteristics of the rivers and swamps, giving this his full attention. This knowledge is valuable in two ways. First, it helps him know his own country better, which allows for more effective defense. Second, the skills and experiences gained in one area can easily transfer to others that he might have to engage with since the hills, valleys, plains, and rivers in Tuscany, for example, resemble those in other regions. A prince lacking this skill misses a critical quality of a leader; it teaches how to scout for the enemy, establish camp, lead armies, organize marches, and secure advantageous positions. Philopomen, leader of the Achaeans, was praised by writers for thinking only about military tactics in peaceful times. When he was in the countryside with friends, he would often pause to ask them: If the enemy were on that hill while we were here with our army, who would have the upper hand? How could we approach safely while keeping our formation? If we had to retreat, what should we do? If they retreated, how should we pursue them? He would discuss various scenarios that might arise for an army, listen to their thoughts, share his own, and back it up with reasoning, ensuring he was prepared for any event while leading his forces. For mental training, a prince should read history and study the actions of great leaders, observing how they conducted themselves in war, examining the reasons behind their victories and defeats to replicate the former and avoid the latter. Above all, he should follow the example of renowned men who imitated those highly praised, keeping their successes in mind just like Alexander the Great emulated Achilles, Julius Caesar emulated Alexander, and Scipio emulated Cyrus. Those who read Xenophon’s account of Cyrus will clearly see how gloriously Scipio followed his lead and how, in integrity, kindness, humanity, and generosity, Scipio mirrored Cyrus's attributes as described by Xenophon.
A wise prince should follow similar methods and never remain idle in peaceful times, but by industry make such good use of the time as may serve him in adversity, so that when fortune changes she may find him prepared to resist her blows.
A smart prince should use similar strategies and never stay lazy during peaceful times. Instead, he should work hard so that he can take advantage of the time for when tough times hit, ensuring that when fortune shifts, he is ready to face the challenges.
CHAPTER XV
OF THE THINGS FOR WHICH MEN, AND ESPECIALLY PRINCES, ARE PRAISED OR BLAMED
It remains now to be seen what are the methods and rules for a prince as regards his subjects and friends. And as I know that many have written of this, I fear that my writing about it may be deemed presumptuous, differing as I do, especially in this matter, from the opinions of others. But my intention being to write something of use to those who understand it, it appears to me more proper to go to the real truth of the matter than to its imagination; and many have imagined republics and principalities which have never been seen or known to exist in reality; for how we live is so far removed from how we ought to live, that he who abandons what is done for what ought to be done, will rather learn to bring about his own ruin than his preservation. A man who wishes to make a profession of goodness in everything must necessarily come to grief among so many who are not good. Therefore it is necessary for a prince, who wishes to maintain himself, to learn how not to be good, and to use it and not use it according to the necessity of the case. Leaving on one side then those things which concern only an imaginary prince, and speaking of those that are real, I state that all men, when spoken of, and especially princes, who are placed at a greater height, are noted for some of those qualities which bring them either praise or blame. Thus one is considered liberal, another miserly; one a free giver, another rapacious; one cruel, another merciful; one a breaker of his word, another faithful; one effeminate and pusillanimous, another fierce and high-spirited; one humane, another proud; one lascivious, another chaste; one frank, another astute; one hard, another easy; one serious, another frivolous; one religious, another incredulous, and so on. I know that every one will admit that it would be highly praiseworthy in a prince to possess all the above-named qualities that are reputed good, but as they cannot all be possessed or observed, human conditions not permitting of it, it is necessary that he should be prudent enough to avoid the disgrace of those vices which would lose him the state, and guard himself against those which will not lose it him, if possible, but if not able to, he can indulge them with less scruple. And yet he must not mind incurring the disgrace of those vices, without which it would be difficult to save the state, for if one considers well, it will be found that some things which seem virtues would, if followed, lead to one's ruin, and some others which appear vices result, if followed, in one's greater security and well being.
Now we need to explore the methods and rules a prince should follow concerning his subjects and friends. I realize many have written about this topic, and I worry that my perspective might come off as bold, especially since I differ from others on this subject. However, my goal is to provide something useful for those who truly understand it, so I believe it’s better to focus on the real truth rather than just imaginary ideas. Many have envisioned republics and principalities that have never really existed, and the way we live is often far removed from how we should live. A person who disregards reality for idealism is more likely to bring about their own downfall than their survival. If someone aims to always be good, they will likely fail amidst so many who are not. Therefore, a prince who wants to maintain his power must learn how to be bad when necessary and to navigate goodness as required by the situation. Focusing on real concerns rather than an imaginary prince, I assert that all people, especially princes who hold higher status, are recognized for certain traits that earn them either praise or criticism. For example, one may be seen as generous, another as stingy; one may give freely, another may be greedy; one may be cruel, another kind; one may break promises, another may keep them; one may be weak and timid, another strong and spirited; one may be compassionate, another arrogant; one may be lustful, another chaste; one may be straightforward, another clever; one may be harsh, another easygoing; one may be serious, another carefree; one may be religious, another skeptical, and so on. I think everyone can agree that it would be admirable for a prince to possess all the good qualities mentioned above, but since one cannot have or maintain them all due to human limitations, it is essential for him to be wise enough to avoid the disgrace that comes with vices that could cost him his state. He should protect himself from those vices that won’t lead to his loss, and if he must indulge in some, he can do so with less concern. Moreover, he should be willing to take on the disgrace of certain vices if it means he can save the state, as some things that seem virtuous may actually lead to ruin, while others that appear to be faults could, if embraced, foster greater security and well-being.
CHAPTER XVI
OF LIBERALITY AND NIGGARDLINESS
Beginning now with the first qualities above named, I say that it would be well to be considered liberal; nevertheless liberality used in such a way that you are not feared will injure you, because if used virtuously and in the proper way, it will not be known, and you will not incur the disgrace of the contrary vice. But one who wishes to obtain the reputation of liberality among men, must not omit every kind of sumptuous display, and to such an extent that a prince of this character will consume by such means all his resources, and will be at last compelled, if he wishes to maintain his name for liberality, to impose heavy charges on his people, become an extortioner, and do everything possible to obtain money. This will make his subjects begin to hate him and he will be little esteemed being poor, so that having by this liberality injured many and benefited but few, he will feel the first little disturbance and be endangered by every accident. If he recognises this and wishes to change his system, he incurs at once the charge of niggardliness; a prince, therefore, not being able to exercise this virtue of liberality without risk if it is known, must not, if he is prudent, object to be called miserly. In course of time he will be thought more liberal, when it is seen that by his parsimony his revenue is sufficient, that he can defend himself against those who make war on him, and undertake enterprises without burdening his people, so that he is really liberal to all those from whom he does not take, who are infinite in number, and niggardly to all to whom he does not give, who are few.
Starting with the first qualities mentioned above, I say it would be good to be seen as generous; however, being generous in a way that doesn't instill fear can harm you because, if done virtuously and correctly, it won't be obvious, and you won't face the disgrace of the opposite vice. But someone who wants to earn a reputation for generosity among people must not skip any kind of extravagant display. This can lead to a leader consuming all his resources, and eventually, if he wants to keep his reputation for generosity, he will have to burden his people with heavy taxes, become greedy, and do everything possible to get money. This will cause his subjects to begin to resent him, and he will be held in low regard for being poor, so having caused harm to many through this generosity while benefiting few, he will feel the first little disturbance and be at risk from any mishap. If he realizes this and wants to change his approach, he will immediately be accused of being stingy; therefore, a leader, unable to practice this virtue of generosity without risk if it's known, should not, if he is wise, object to being called miserly. Over time, he will be seen as more generous when it becomes evident that his frugality allows his revenue to be sufficient, enabling him to defend himself against those who wage war on him, and undertake ventures without burdening his people, so that he is truly generous to all from whom he does not take, who are countless, and stingy to those to whom he does not give, who are few.
In our times we have seen nothing great done except by those who have been esteemed niggardly; the others have all been ruined. Pope Julius II., although he had made use of a reputation for liberality in order to attain the papacy, did not seek to retain it afterwards, so that he might be able to make war on the King of France, and he earned on so many wars without imposing an extraordinary tax, because his extra expenses were covered by the parsimony he had so long practised. The present King of Spain, if he had been thought liberal, would not have engaged in and won so many enterprises. For these reasons a prince must care little for the reputation of being a miser, if he wishes to avoid robbing his subjects, if he wishes to be able to defend himself, to not become poor and contemptible, and not to be forced to become rapacious; this vice of niggardliness is one of those vices which enable him to reign. If it is said that Cæsar attained the empire through liberality, and that many others have reached the highest positions through being liberal or being thought so, I would reply that you are either a prince already or else on the way to become one. In the first case, this liberality is harmful; in the second, it is certainly necessary to be considered liberal, and Cæsar was one of those who wished to attain the mastery over Rome, but if after attaining it he had lived and had not moderated his expenses, he would have destroyed that empire. And should any one reply that there have been many princes, who have done great things with their armies, who have been thought extremely liberal, I would answer by saying that the prince may either spend his own wealth and that of his subjects or the wealth of others. In the first case he must be sparing, but in the second he must not neglect to be very liberal. This liberality is very necessary to a prince who marches with his armies, and lives by plunder, sacking and extorting, and is dealing with the wealth of others, for without it he would not be followed by his soldiers. And you may be very generous indeed with what is not the property of yourself or your subjects, as were Cyrus, Cæsar, and Alexander; for spending the wealth of others will not diminish your reputation, but increase it, only spending your own resources will injure you. There is nothing which destroys itself so much as liberality, for by using it you lose the power of using it, and become either poor and despicable, or, to escape poverty, rapacious and hated. And of all things that a prince must guard against, the most important are being despicable or hated, and liberality will lead you to one or other of these conditions. It is, therefore, wiser to have the name of a miser, which produces disgrace without hatred, than to incur of necessity the name of being rapacious, which produces both disgrace and hatred.
In our time, we haven't seen anything significant accomplished except by those who are considered greedy; everyone else has failed. Pope Julius II, who initially used his reputation for generosity to become pope, didn’t try to keep it after that so he could go to war with the King of France. He funded many wars without imposing heavy taxes because he had saved up for a long time. The current King of Spain would not have taken on and succeeded in so many ventures if he had been seen as generous. For these reasons, a ruler shouldn't care much about being seen as stingy if he wants to avoid draining his subjects, protect himself, stay wealthy and respectable, and not be forced into greed; this trait of being frugal is one of those vices that helps him rule. If someone claims that Caesar gained the empire through generosity, and that many others have reached the highest positions by being generous or being perceived as such, I would respond that you are either already a prince or on your way to becoming one. In the first case, that generosity is harmful; in the second, it is definitely necessary to be seen as generous. Caesar was one of those who wanted to dominate Rome, but if after achieving that he had lived extravagantly and not moderated his expenses, he would have destroyed that empire. And if anyone argues that there have been many princes who have accomplished great things with their armies and have been seen as very generous, I would say that a prince can either spend his own wealth and that of his subjects or the wealth of others. In the first scenario, he needs to be careful with spending, but in the second, he shouldn't forget to be quite generous. This generosity is vital for a prince who leads his armies, survives by looting, and is handling the wealth of others, because without it he wouldn’t be followed by his soldiers. You can be very generous with what doesn’t belong to you or your subjects, like Cyrus, Caesar, and Alexander did; spending other people’s wealth won’t hurt your reputation, but using your own will. There’s nothing that undermines itself more than generosity, because by using it you lose the ability to use it and become either poor and contemptible or, to avoid poverty, greedy and disliked. Of all the things a prince should avoid, the most critical are being despised or hated, and generosity will lead you to one of those outcomes. Therefore, it’s wiser to be seen as a miser, which brings embarrassment without hatred, than to inevitably be known as greedy, which brings both disgrace and hatred.
CHAPTER XVII
OF CRUELTY AND CLEMENCY, AND WHETHER IT IS BETTER TO BE LOVED OR FEARED
Proceeding to the other qualities before named, I say that every prince must desire to be considered merciful and not cruel. He must, however, take care not to misuse this mercifulness. Cesare Borgia was considered cruel, but his cruelty had settled the Romagna, united it, and brought it peace and confidence. If this is considered a benefit, it will be seen that he was really much more merciful than the Florentine people, who, to avoid the name of cruelty, allowed Pistoia to be destroyed. A prince, therefore, must not mind incurring the charge of cruelty for the purpose of keeping his subjects united and confident; for, with a very few examples, he will be more merciful than those who, from excess of tenderness, allow disorders to arise, from whence spring murders and rapine; for these as a rule injure the whole community, while the executions carried out by the prince injure only one individual. And of all princes, it is impossible for a new prince to escape the name of cruel, new states being always full of dangers. Wherefore Virgil makes Dido excuse the inhumanity of her rule by its being new, where she says:
Moving on to the other qualities mentioned earlier, I say that every prince must want to be seen as merciful rather than cruel. However, he must be careful not to misuse this mercy. Cesare Borgia was viewed as cruel, but his harshness brought order to the Romagna, uniting it and providing peace and stability. If this is seen as a positive, it shows that he was actually much more merciful than the Florentine people, who, to avoid being called cruel, let Pistoia be destroyed. Therefore, a prince shouldn’t worry about being labeled cruel if it means keeping his subjects united and confident; in fact, with just a few exceptions, he will be more merciful than those who, out of excessive kindness, allow chaos to unfold, leading to murder and theft. This generally harms the entire community, while the punishments enforced by the prince only affect one individual. Among all princes, it’s particularly difficult for a new prince to escape the label of cruelty, as new states are always filled with risks. That's why Virgil has Dido justify the brutality of her reign as a result of its novelty, saying:
Res dura, et regni novitas me talia cogunt
Moliri, et late fines custode tueri.
Res dura, and the newness of power compel me
To undertake such things and protect your borders widely.
Nevertheless, he must be cautious in believing and acting, and must not inspire fear of his own accord, and must proceed in a temperate manner with prudence and humanity, so that too much confidence does not render him incautious, and too much diffidence does not render him intolerant.
Nevertheless, he needs to be careful in what he believes and does, and he shouldn’t create fear on his own. He should act with moderation, using good judgment and kindness, so that being too confident doesn’t make him reckless, and being too unsure doesn’t make him intolerant.
From this arises the question whether it is better to be loved more than feared, or feared more than loved. The reply is, that one ought to be both feared and loved, but as it is difficult for the two to go together, it is much safer to be feared than loved, if one of the two has to be wanting. For it may be said of men in general that they are ungrateful, voluble, dissemblers, anxious to avoid danger, and covetous of gain; as long as you benefit them, they are entirely yours; they offer you their blood, their goods, their life, and their children, as I have before said, when the necessity is remote; but when it approaches, they revolt. And the prince who has relied solely on their words, without making other preparations, is ruined, for the friendship which is gained by purchase and not through grandeur and nobility of spirit is merited but is not secured, and at times is not to be had. And men have less scruple in offending one who makes himself loved than one who makes himself feared; for love is held by a chain of obligation which, men being selfish, is broken whenever it serves their purpose; but fear is maintained by a dread of punishment which never fails. Still, a prince should make himself feared in such a way that if he does not gain love, he at any rate avoids hatred; for fear, and the absence of hatred may well go together, and will be always attained by one who abstains from interfering with the property of his citizens and subjects or with their women. And when he is obliged to take the life of any one, to do so when there is a proper justification and manifest reason for it; but above all he must abstain from taking the property of others, for men forget more easily the death of their father than the loss of their patrimony. Then also pretexts for seizing property are never wanting, and one who begins to live by rapine will always find some reason for taking the goods of others, whereas causes for taking life are rarer and more quickly destroyed. But when the prince is with his army and has a large number of soldiers under his control, then it is extremely necessary that he should not mind being thought cruel; for without this reputation he could not keep an army united, or disposed to any duty.
This raises the question of whether it’s better to be loved more than feared, or feared more than loved. The answer is that one should be both feared and loved, but since it’s hard for both to coexist, it’s much safer to be feared than loved if you have to choose one. Generally speaking, people are ungrateful, fickle, deceitful, eager to avoid danger, and greedy for gain; as long as you benefit them, they are completely devoted to you; they offer you their blood, their resources, their lives, and their children, as I mentioned before, when the need is distant; but when it’s imminent, they turn against you. A leader who relies only on their words, without making other preparations, will be ruined, because friendship that is bought is not secured and can sometimes be impossible to maintain. People are less hesitant to offend someone who seeks to be loved than someone who seeks to be feared; love is based on obligation, which selfish people break whenever it suits them; but fear is sustained by the threat of punishment, which is always effective. However, a leader should be feared in such a way that if he doesn’t gain love, he at least avoids hatred; because fear and the absence of hatred can coexist, and this can be achieved by not interfering with the property of his citizens or their women. And when he has to take someone’s life, he should only do so when there's a good reason for it; but above all, he must avoid taking others' property, because people forget their father’s death more easily than the loss of their inheritance. There are always justifications for seizing property, and someone who starts living by theft will always find a reason to take from others, while reasons to take a life are rarer and fade quickly. But when the leader is with his army and has a large number of soldiers under his command, it’s very important that he doesn’t mind being seen as cruel; because without this reputation, he couldn’t keep an army united or ready for any duty.
Among the noteworthy actions of Hannibal is numbered this, that although he had an enormous army, composed of men of all nations and fighting in foreign countries, there never arose any dissension either among them or against the prince, either in good fortune or in bad. This could not be due to anything but his inhuman cruelty, which together with his infinite other virtues, made him always venerated and terrible in the sight of his soldiers, and without it his other virtues would not have sufficed to produce that effect. Thoughtless writers admire on the one hand his actions, and on the other blame the principal cause of them. And that it is true that his other virtues would not have sufficed may be seen from the case of Scipio (very rare not only in his own times, but in all times of which memory remains), whose armies rebelled against him in Spain, which arose from nothing but his excessive kindness, which allowed more license to the soldiers than was consonant with military discipline. He was reproached with this in the senate by Fabius Maximus, who called him a corrupter of the Roman militia.
One of the remarkable things about Hannibal is that even though he had a massive army made up of men from all over the world and fighting in foreign lands, there was never any conflict among them or against their leader, whether in good times or bad. This must have been because of his brutal cruelty, which, along with his many other strengths, made him both respected and feared by his soldiers; without this, his other qualities wouldn’t have had the same impact. Some careless writers admire his achievements but criticize the main reason behind them. The fact that his other strengths alone wouldn’t have been enough is evident when looking at Scipio (who is very rare not only in his own time but throughout all history), whose soldiers turned against him in Spain due to his excessive kindness, which gave them more freedom than what was proper in military discipline. He was criticized for this by Fabius Maximus in the senate, who accused him of corrupting the Roman army.
The Locri having been destroyed by one of Scipio's officers were not revenged by him, nor was the insolence of that officer punished, simply by reason of his easy nature; so much so, that some one wishing to excuse him in the senate, said that there were many men who knew rather how not to err, than how to correct the errors of others. This disposition would in time have tarnished the fame and glory of Scipio had he persevered in it under the empire, but living under the rule of the senate this harmful quality was not only concealed but became a glory to him. I conclude, therefore, with regard to being feared and loved, that men love at their own free will, but fear at the will of the prince, and that a wise prince must rely on what is in his power and not on what is in the power of others, and he must only trouble himself to avoid incurring hatred, as has been explained.
The Locri were destroyed by one of Scipio's officers, but Scipio did not seek revenge, nor did he punish the officer's arrogance, simply because of his easygoing nature. In fact, someone in the senate tried to defend him by saying that many people know how to avoid making mistakes rather than how to fix the mistakes of others. This attitude could have eventually damaged Scipio's reputation and glory if he had continued it while in power, but while living under the senate's rule, this flaw not only went unnoticed but even became a source of pride for him. Therefore, I conclude that when it comes to being feared and loved, people love willingly, but they fear based on the will of the leader. A wise leader must rely on what he can control and not on what others control, and he should only focus on avoiding hatred, as previously explained.
CHAPTER XVIII
IN WHAT WAY PRINCES MUST KEEP FAITH
How laudable it is for a prince to keep good faith and live with integrity, and not with astuteness, every one knows. Still the experience of our times shows those princes to have done great things who have had little regard for good faith, and have been able by astuteness to confuse men's brains, and who have ultimately overcome those who have made loyalty their foundation. You must know, then, that there are two methods of fighting, the one by law, the other by force: the first method is that of men, the second of beasts; but as the first method is often insufficient, one must have recourse to the second. It is therefore necessary to know well how to use both the beast and the man. This was covertly taught to princes by ancient writers, who relate how Achilles and many others of those princes were given to Chiron the centaur to be brought up, who kept them under his discipline; this system of having for teacher one who was half beast and half man is meant to indicate that a prince must know how to use both natures, and that the one without the other is not durable. A prince being thus obliged to know well how to act as a beast must imitate the fox and the lion, for the lion cannot protect himself from snares, and the fox cannot defend himself from wolves. One must therefore be a fox to recognise snares, and a lion to frighten wolves. Those that wish to be only lions do not understand this. Therefore, a prudent ruler ought not to keep faith when by so doing it would be against his interest, and when the reasons which made him bind himself no longer exist. If men were all good, this precept would not be a good one; but as they are bad, and would not observe their faith with you, so you are not bound to keep faith with them. Nor are legitimate grounds ever wanting to a prince to give colour to the non-fulfilment of his promise. Of this one could furnish an infinite number of modern examples, and show how many times peace has been broken, and how many promises rendered worthless, by the faithlessness of princes, and those that have been best able to imitate the fox have succeeded best. But it is necessary to be able to disguise this character well, and to be a great feigner and dissembler; and men are so simple and so ready to obey present necessities, that one who deceives will always find those who allow themselves to be deceived. I will only mention one modern instance. Alexander VI. did nothing else but deceive men, he thought of nothing else, and found the way to do it; no man was ever more able to give assurances, or affirmed things with stronger oaths, and no man observed them less; however, he always succeeded in his deceptions, as he knew well this side of the world. It is not, therefore, necessary for a prince to have all the above-named qualities, but it is very necessary to seem to have them. I would even be bold to say that to possess them and to always observe them is dangerous, but to appear to possess them is useful. Thus it is well to seem pious, faithful, humane, religious, sincere, and also to be so; but you must have the mind so watchful that when it is needful to be otherwise you may be able to change to the opposite qualities. And it must be understood that a prince, and especially a new prince, cannot observe all those things which are considered good in men, being often obliged, in order to maintain the state, to act against faith, against charity, against humanity, and against religion. And, therefore, he must have a mind disposed to adapt itself according to the wind, and as the variations of fortune dictate, and, as I said before, not deviate from what is good, if possible, but be able to do evil if necessitated. A prince must take great care that nothing goes out of his mouth which is not full of the above-named five qualities, and, to see and hear him, he should seem to be all faith, all integrity, all humanity, and all religion. And nothing is more necessary than to seem to have this last quality, for men in general judge more by the eyes than by the hands, for every one can see, but very few have to feel. Everybody sees what you appear to be, few feel what you are, and those few will not dare to oppose themselves to the many, who have the majesty of the state to defend them; and in the actions of men, and especially of princes, from which there is no appeal, the end is everything.
It's widely known how admirable it is for a ruler to be honest and act with integrity instead of being shrewd. However, recent experiences show that many successful rulers have cared little about being honest and have skillfully deceived people, ultimately defeating those who prioritize loyalty. You should understand that there are two ways to fight: one is through law, the other through force. The first approach is human, while the second is animalistic; but since the first is often inadequate, sometimes you must resort to the second. Therefore, it's essential to know how to wield both the animal and the human aspects. Ancient writers have subtly taught this to rulers, telling stories of how Achilles and others were raised by Chiron the centaur, who taught them under his unique discipline. This idea of having a teacher who is part beast and part man suggests that a ruler must master both natures, as one without the other is not sustainable. Thus, a ruler must learn to act like both a fox and a lion, since a lion can't protect itself from traps and a fox can't fend off wolves. You need to be a fox to recognize traps and a lion to intimidate wolves. Those who only want to be lions fail to understand this. A wise ruler shouldn't keep promises if it goes against their interests, especially when the reasons for making those promises no longer exist. If people were inherently good, this principle wouldn’t apply; but since they're not, and they wouldn't keep promises with you, you're not obligated to keep promises with them either. There are always legitimate reasons for a ruler to justify breaking a promise. One could provide countless modern examples illustrating how often peace has been disrupted and promises broken due to the dishonesty of rulers, and those who have best emulated the fox have been the most successful. However, it’s crucial to disguise this character well and to be an expert deceiver, as people are generally naive and quick to adjust to present needs; those who deceive will always find willing victims. A modern example is Alexander VI, who was nothing but a deceiver, always thinking of deceit and knowing how to execute it. No one was better at making promises or swearing oaths while keeping them less, yet he was always successful in his schemes because he understood how the world worked. Therefore, it's not necessary for a ruler to possess all the qualities mentioned above, but it’s essential to appear as if they do. I would even venture to say that truly possessing and consistently demonstrating these qualities can be risky; appearing to possess them is much more beneficial. Thus, it is important to seem religious, faithful, compassionate, and sincere, and to genuinely be so; but you must remain so vigilant that when the situation demands it, you can switch to the opposite qualities. It’s important to note that a ruler, especially a new one, cannot uphold all the virtues that society values, often needing to act against honesty, kindness, humanity, and even religion to maintain power. Therefore, they must be adaptable, responding to the winds of change and the ups and downs of fortune, and, as I mentioned earlier, strive to do good whenever possible but be prepared to do wrong if absolutely necessary. A ruler must ensure that nothing they say is devoid of those five qualities, and when people observe them, they should seem entirely honest, kind, humane, and religious. Nothing is more crucial than appearing to possess that last quality, as people generally judge based on appearances rather than actions. Everyone can see what you present, but very few can truly grasp what you are, and those few are unlikely to oppose the many who have the authority of the state backing them. In the actions of people, especially rulers, where there's no recourse, the outcome is everything.
Let a prince therefore aim at living and maintaining state the state, the means will always be judged honourable and praised by every one, for the vulgar is always taken by appearances and the result of things; and the world consists only of the vulgar, and the few find a place when the many have nothing to rest upon. A certain prince of the present time, whom it is well not to name, never does anything but preach peace and good faith, but he is really a great enemy to both, and either of them, had he observed them, would have lost him both state and reputation on many occasions.
Let a prince, therefore, focus on living and maintaining his state; the methods will always be seen as honorable and praised by everyone, because the masses are easily swayed by appearances and outcomes. The world is made up mostly of the masses, and only a few find their place when the majority has nothing solid to rely on. A certain current prince, who shall remain unnamed, only talks about peace and good faith, but in reality, he is a major threat to both. If he had truly followed either, he would have lost both his state and his reputation on many occasions.
CHAPTER XIX
THAT WE MUST AVOID BEING DESPISED AND HATED
But as I have now spoken of the most important of the qualities in question, I will now deal briefly with the rest on the general principle, that the prince must, as already stated, avoid those things which will make him hated or despised; and whenever he succeeds in this, he will have done his part, and will find no danger in other vices.
But now that I’ve discussed the most important qualities, I’ll briefly touch on the others, based on the general idea that a prince must, as mentioned earlier, steer clear of anything that could make him hated or looked down upon; and as long as he manages this, he will have fulfilled his role and won’t face any risks from other faults.
He will chiefly become hated, as I said, by being rapacious, and usurping the property and women of his subjects, which he must abstain from doing, and whenever one does not attack the property or honour of the generality of men, they will live contented; and one will only have to combat the ambition of a few, who can be easily held in check in many ways. He is rendered despicable by being thought changeable, frivolous, effeminate, timid, and irresolute; which a prince must guard against as a rock of danger, and manage so that his actions show grandeur, high courage, seriousness, and strength; and as to the government of his subjects, let his sentence be irrevocable, and let him adhere to his decisions so that no one may think of deceiving him or making him change. The prince who creates such an opinion of himself gets a great reputation, and it is very difficult to conspire against one who has a great reputation, and he will not easily be attacked, so long as it is known that he is esteemed and reverenced by his subjects. For a prince must have two kinds of fear: one internal as regards his subjects, one external as regards foreign powers. From the latter he can defend himself with good arms and good friends, and he will always have good friends if he has good arms; and internal matters will always remain quiet, if they are not perturbed by conspiracy; and even if external powers sought to foment one, if he has ruled and lived as I have described, he will always if he stands firm be able to sustain every shock, as I have shown that Nabis the Spartan did. But with regard to the subjects, if not acted on from outside, it is still to be feared lest they conspire in secret, from which the prince may guard himself well by avoiding hatred and contempt, and keeping the people satisfied with him, which it is necessary to accomplish, as has been related at length. And one of the most potent remedies that a prince has against conspiracies, is that of not being hated or despised by the mass of the people; for whoever conspires always believes that he will satisfy the people by the death of their prince; but if he thought to offend them by doing this, he would fear to engage in such an undertaking, for the difficulties that conspirators have to meet are infinite. Experience shows that there have been very many conspiracies, but few have turned out well, for whoever conspires cannot act alone, and cannot find companions except among those who are discontented; and as soon as you have disclosed your intention to a malcontent, you give him the means of satisfying himself, for by revealing it he can hope to secure everything he wants; to such an extent that seeing a certain gain by doing this, and seeing on the other hand only a doubtful one and full of danger, he must either be a rare friend to you or else a very bitter enemy to the prince if he keeps faith with you. And to reduce the matter to narrow limits, I say, that on the side of the conspirator there is nothing but fear, jealousy, suspicion, and dread of punishment which frightens him; and on the side of the prince there is the majesty of government, the laws, the protection of friends and of the state which guard him. When to these things are added the goodwill of the people, it is impossible that any one should have the temerity to conspire. For whereas generally a conspirator has to fear before the execution of his plot, in this case he must also fear afterwards, having the people for an enemy, when his crime is accomplished, and thus not being able to hope for any refuge. Numberless instances might be given of this, but I will content myself with one which took place within the memory of our fathers. Messer Annibale Bentivogli, Prince of Bologna, ancestor of the present Messer Annibale, was killed by the Canneschi, who conspired against him. He left no relations but Messer Giovanni, who was then an infant, but after the murder the people rose up and killed all the Canneschi. This arose from the popular goodwill that the house of Bentivogli enjoyed at that time in Bologna, which was so great that, as there was nobody left after the death of Annibale who could govern the state, the Bolognese hearing that there was one of the Bentivogli family in Florence, who had till then been thought the son of a blacksmith, came to fetch him and gave him the government of the city, and it was governed by him until Messer Giovanni was old enough to assume the government.
He will mainly become disliked, as I mentioned, by being greedy and taking the property and women of his people, which he must avoid. When a ruler doesn't threaten the property or honor of most people, they will live happily; then, he will only need to deal with the ambition of a few, who can be easily managed in various ways. He is seen as contemptible if he is thought to be fickle, superficial, weak, timid, and indecisive; a ruler must be wary of these traits as they pose significant danger and should act in a way that demonstrates grandeur, courage, seriousness, and strength. Regarding the governance of his subjects, his decisions should be final, and he should stick to them so that no one thinks they can deceive him or persuade him to change. A prince who cultivates such an image gains a strong reputation, and it becomes very difficult to plot against someone with a great reputation; they won't be easily targeted as long as it's clear they are respected and admired by their subjects. A prince must inspire two kinds of fear: one from within, concerning his subjects, and one from external threats, concerning foreign powers. He can protect himself against the latter with good weapons and loyal allies, and he will always have solid allies if he has strong defenses. Internal issues will remain stable unless disturbed by conspiracies; even if outside forces attempt to instigate one, if he governs and lives as I described, he will be able to withstand any challenges, as I have shown that Nabis the Spartan did. However, regarding his subjects, if there’s no external influence, there's still the risk they might secretly plot against him. The prince can guard against this by avoiding hatred and contempt and ensuring the people are satisfied with him, which, as previously discussed, is essential. One of the strongest defenses a prince has against conspiracies is not being hated or despised by the general public. Those who plot often think they will win the people over by eliminating their prince, but if they believed they would upset the public by doing so, they would hesitate to go through with their plans because the obstacles conspirators face are numerous. History shows there have been many conspiracies, but few have succeeded, as conspirators cannot act alone and can only find companions among the dissatisfied. Once you reveal your intentions to a discontented person, you give them a way to fulfill their desires; by exposing your plan, they can hope for all they want. Realizing there’s a certain benefit to betrayal and, on the other hand, only the uncertain and dangerous prospects of remaining loyal, they must either be an exceptionally good friend to you or a very bitter enemy of the prince if they keep their word. To simplify it, on the conspirator's side, there’s only fear, jealousy, suspicion, and the threat of punishment that intimidates them; on the prince’s side, there’s the authority of the government, the laws, and the protection of friends and the state surrounding him. When these factors are combined with the goodwill of the people, it becomes impossible for anyone to have the audacity to conspire. Generally, a conspirator has to fear not just before the execution of their plot but also afterwards; having the people as an enemy once their crime is committed means they can't hope for any refuge. Many examples could be given, but I'll stick to one that occurred within the memory of our parents. Messer Annibale Bentivogli, Prince of Bologna, an ancestor of the current Messer Annibale, was killed by the Canneschi, who plotted against him. He left no relatives except Messer Giovanni, who was an infant at the time, but after the murder, the people rose up and killed all the Canneschi. This happened because of the strong support the Bentivogli family had at that time in Bologna; it was so significant that, with no one left to govern after Annibale's death, the Bolognese, upon hearing there was a member of the Bentivogli family in Florence, who had until then been thought to be the son of a blacksmith, went to bring him back and made him the governor of the city, and he governed until Messer Giovanni was old enough to take over.
I conclude, therefore, that a prince need trouble little about conspiracies when the people are well disposed, but when they are hostile and hold him in hatred, then he must fear everything and everybody. Well-ordered states and wise princes have studied diligently not to drive the nobles to desperation, and to satisfy the populace and keep it contented, for this is one of the most important matters that a prince has to deal with. Among the kingdoms that are well ordered and governed in our time is France, and there we find numberless good institutions on which depend the liberty and security of the king; of these the chief is the parliament and its authority, because he who established that kingdom, knowing the ambition and insolence of the great nobles, and deeming it necessary to have a bit in their mouths to check them; and knowing on the other hand the hatred of the mass of the people to the great, based on fear, and wishing to secure them, did not wish to make this the special care of the king, to relieve him of the dissatisfaction that he might incur among the nobles by favouring the people, and among the people by favouring the nobles. He therefore established a third judge that, without direct charge of the king, kept in check the great and favoured the lesser people. Nor could any better or more prudent measure have been adopted, nor better precaution for the safety of the king and the kingdom. From which another notable rule can be drawn, that princes should let the carrying out of unpopular duties devolve on others, and bestow favours themselves. I conclude again by saying that a prince must esteem his nobles, but not make himself hated by the populace. It may perhaps seem to some, that considering the life and death of many Roman emperors that they are instances contrary to my opinion, finding that some who lived always nobly and showed great strength of character, nevertheless lost the empire, or were killed by their subjects who conspired against them. Wishing to answer these objections, I will discuss the qualities of some emperors, showing the cause of their ruin not to be at variance with what I have stated, and I will also partly consider the things to be noted by whoever reads the deeds of these times. I will content myself with taking all those emperors who succeeded to the empire from Marcus the philosopher to Maximinus; these were Marcus, Commodus his son, Pertinax, Heliogabalus, Alexander, and Maximinus. And the first thing to note is, that whereas other princes have only to contend against the ambition of the great and the insolence of the people, the Roman emperors had a third difficulty, that of having to support the cruelty and avarice of the soldiers, which was such a difficulty that it was the cause of the ruin of many, it being difficult to satisfy both the soldiers and the people. For the people love tranquillity, and therefore like princes who are pacific, but the soldiers prefer a prince of military spirit, who is insolent, cruel, and rapacious. They wish him to exercise these qualities on the people so that they may get double pay and give vent to their avarice and cruelty. Thus it came about that those emperors who, by nature or art, had not such a reputation as could keep both parties in check, invariably were ruined, and the greater number of them who were raised to the empire being new men, knowing the difficulties of these two opposite dispositions, confined themselves to satisfying the soldiers, and thought little of injuring the people. This choice was necessary, princes not being able to avoid being hated by some one. They must first try not to be hated by the mass of the people; if they cannot accomplish this they must use every means to escape the hatred of the most powerful parties. And therefore these emperors, who being new men had need of extraordinary favours, adhered to the soldiers more willingly than to the people; whether this, however, was of use to them or not, depended on whether the prince knew how to maintain his reputation with them.
I conclude that a prince doesn't need to worry much about conspiracies when the people are supportive, but when they are resentful and hate him, then he has to fear everything and everyone. Well-governed states and wise princes have worked hard not to push the nobles to the brink and to keep the populace satisfied and happy, as this is one of the most crucial issues a prince faces. Among the well-ordered and well-governed kingdoms today is France, which has countless good institutions that ensure the king's freedom and security. The most important of these is the parliament and its authority because the founder of that kingdom recognized the ambition and arrogance of powerful nobles and deemed it necessary to put them in check; at the same time, he understood the people's fear and hatred of the elite and wanted to ensure their loyalty. He didn't want this task to weigh solely on the king, which could lead to discontent among the nobles for favoring the people and vice versa. Therefore, he established a third authority that, without directly answering to the king, regulated the nobles and supported the common people. No better or wiser strategy could have been implemented, nor better safeguards for the king and his kingdom. From this, we can derive another important principle: princes should delegate unpopular tasks to others while reserving favors for themselves. I reiterate that a prince should value his nobles but must avoid being hated by the common people. Some may argue that the lives and deaths of several Roman emperors contradict my point, noting that those who lived nobly and showed strong character still lost their empires or were killed by conspirators among their subjects. In addressing these objections, I will analyze the qualities of certain emperors, demonstrating that the reasons for their downfall align with my argument. I'll examine emperors who came to power from Marcus the philosopher to Maximinus, including Marcus, Commodus (his son), Pertinax, Heliogabalus, Alexander, and Maximinus. The first thing to note is that, unlike other princes who only face the ambition of the elite and the arrogance of the populace, Roman emperors also had to deal with the cruelty and greed of the soldiers, which was such a challenge that it led to many downfalls, as it was tough to satisfy both soldiers and the general public. The people crave peace and prefer peaceful rulers, while soldiers want a militaristic prince who is ruthless, cruel, and greedy. They hope he will express these traits toward the common people so they can get higher pay and indulge their own greed and brutality. Thus, emperors who couldn't establish a strong enough reputation by nature or skill to control both groups were inevitably doomed, and most of those who ascended to the throne were newcomers who understood the challenges posed by these conflicting interests. They focused on appeasing the soldiers and often ignored the harm done to the people. This choice was necessary, as princes cannot avoid being disliked by someone. They should first aim not to be hated by the populace; if that's not possible, they should take every measure to avoid the hatred of the most powerful factions. Consequently, these emperors, being newcomers in need of exceptional favors, aligned themselves more closely with the soldiers than the common people; whether this strategy benefited them depended on whether the prince could maintain his standing with them.
From these causes it resulted that Marcus, Pertinax, and Alexander, being all of modest life, lovers of justice, enemies of cruelty, humane and benign, had all a sad ending except Marcus. Marcus alone lived and died in honour, because he succeeded to the empire by hereditary right and did not owe it either to the soldiers or to the people; besides which, possessing many virtues which made him revered, he kept both parties in their place as long as he lived and was never either hated or despised. But Pertinax was created emperor against the will of the soldiers, who being accustomed to live licentiously under Commodus, could not put up with the honest life to which Pertinax wished to limit them, so that having made himself hated, and to this contempt being added because he was old, he was ruined at the very beginning of his administration. Whence it may be seen that hatred is gained as much by good works as by evil, and therefore, as I said before, a prince who wishes to maintain the state is often forced to do evil, for when that party, whether populace, soldiery, or nobles, whichever it be that you consider necessary to you for keeping your position, is corrupt, you must follow its humour and satisfy it, and in that case good works will be inimical to you. But let us come to Alexander, who was of such goodness, that among other things for which he is praised, it is said that in the fourteen years that he reigned no one was put to death by him without a fair trial. Nevertheless, being considered effeminate, and a man who allowed himself to be ruled by his mother, and having thus fallen into contempt, the army conspired against him and killed him. Looking, on the other hand, at the qualities of Commodus, Severus, Antoninus, extremely cruel and rapacious; to satisfy the soldiers there was no injury which they would not inflict on the people, and all except Severus ended badly. Severus, however, had such abilities that by maintaining the soldiers friendly to him, he was able to reign happily, although he oppressed the people, for his virtues made him so admirable in the sight both of the soldiers and the people that the latter were, as it were, astonished and stupefied, while the former were respectful and contented. As the deeds of this ruler were great for a new prince, I will briefly show how well he could use the qualities of the fox and the lion, whose natures, as I said before, it is necessary for a prince to imitate. Knowing the sloth of the Emperor Julian, Severus, who was leader of the army in Slavonia, persuaded the troops that it would be well to go to Rome to avenge the death of Pertinax, who had been slain by the Imperial guard, and under this pretext, without revealing his aspirations to the throne, marched with his army to Rome and was in Italy before his design was known. On his arrival in Rome the senate elected him emperor through fear, and Julian died. There remained after this beginning two difficulties to be faced by Severus before he could obtain the whole control of the empire: one in Asia, where Nigrinus, head of the Asiatic armies, had declared himself emperor; the other in the west from Albinus, who also aspired to the empire. And as he judged it dangerous to show himself hostile to both, he decided to attack Nigrinus and deceive Albinus, to whom he wrote that having been elected emperor by the senate he wished to share that dignity with him; he sent him the title of Cæsar and, by deliberation of the senate, he was declared his colleague; all of which was accepted as true by Albinus. But when Severus had defeated and killed Nigrinus, and pacified things in the East, he returned to Rome and charged Albinus in the senate with having, unmindful of the benefits received from him, traitorously sought to assassinate him, and stated that he was therefore obliged to go and punish his ingratitude. He then went to France to meet him, and there deprived him of both his position and his life. Whoever examines in detail the actions of Severus, will find him to have been a very ferocious lion and an extremely astute fox, and will see him to have been feared and respected by all and not hated by the army; and will not be surprised that he, a new man, should have been able to hold the empire so well, since his great reputation defended him always from that hatred that his rapacity might have produced in the people. But Antoninus his son was also a man of great ability, and possessed qualities that rendered him admirable in the sight of the people and also made him popular with the soldiers, for he was a military man, capable of enduring the most extreme hardships, disdainful of delicate food, and every other luxury, which made him loved by all the armies. However, his ferocity and cruelty were so great and unheard of, through his having, after executing many private individuals, caused a large part of the population of Rome and all that of Alexandria to be killed, that he became hated by all the world and began to be feared by those about him to such an extent that he was finally killed by a centurion in the midst of his army. Whence it is to be noted that this kind of death, which proceeds from the deliberate action of a determined man, cannot be avoided by princes, since any one who does not fear death himself can inflict it, but a prince need not fear much on this account, as such actions are extremely rare. He must only guard against committing any grave injury to any one he makes use of, or has about him for his service, like Antoninus had done, having caused the death with contumely of the brother of that centurion, and also threatened him every day, although he still retained him in his bodyguard, which was a foolish and dangerous thing to do, as the fact proved. But let us come to Commodus, who might easily have kept the empire, having succeeded to it by heredity, being the son of Marcus, and it would have sufficed for him to follow in the steps of his father to have satisfied both the people and the soldiers. But being of a cruel and bestial disposition, in order to be able to exercise his rapacity on the people, he sought to amuse the soldiers and render them licentious; on the other hand, by not maintaining his dignity, by often descending into the theatre to fight with gladiators and committing other contemptible actions, little worthy of the imperial dignity, he became despicable in the eyes of the soldiers, and being hated on the one hand and despised on the other, he was conspired against and killed. There remains to be described the character of Maximinus. He was an extremely warlike man, and as the armies were annoyed with the effeminacy of Alexander, which we have already spoken of, he was after the death of the latter elected emperor. He did not enjoy it for long, as two things made him hated and despised: the one his base origin, as he had been a shepherd in Thrace, which was generally known and caused great disdain on all sides; the other, because he had at the commencement of his rule deferred going to Rome to take possession of the Imperial seat, and had obtained a reputation for great cruelty, having through his prefects in Rome and other parts of the empire committed many acts of cruelty. The whole world being thus moved by indignation for the baseness of his blood, and also by the hatred caused by fear of his ferocity, he was conspired against first by Africa and afterwards by the senate and all the people of Rome and Italy. His own army also joined them, for besieging Aquileia and finding it difficult to take, they became enraged at his cruelty, and seeing that he had so many enemies, they feared him less and put him to death. I will not speak of Heliogabalus, of Macrinus, or Julian, who being entirely contemptible were immediately suppressed, but I will come to the conclusion of this discourse by saying that the princes of our time have less difficulty than these of being obliged to satisfy in an extraordinary degree their soldiers in their states; for although they must have a certain consideration for them, yet it is soon settled, for none of these princes have armies that are inextricably bound up with the administration of the government and the rule of their provinces as were the armies of the Roman empire; and therefore if it was then necessary to satisfy the soldiers rather than the people, it was because the soldiers could do more than the people; now, it is more necessary to all princes, except the Turk and the Soldan, to satisfy the people than the soldiers, for the people can do more than the soldiers. I except the Turk, because he always keeps about him twelve thousand infantry and fifteen thousand cavalry, on which depend the security and strength of his kingdom; and it is necessary for him to postpone every other consideration of the people to keep them friendly. It is the same with the kingdom of the Soldan, which being entirely in the hands of the soldiers, he is bound to keep their friendship regardless of the people. And it is to be noted that this state of the Soldan is different from that of all other princes, being similar to the Christian pontificate, which cannot be called either a hereditary kingdom or a new one, for the sons of the dead prince are not his heirs, but he who is elected to that position by those who have authority. And as this order is ancient it cannot be called a new kingdom, there being none of these difficulties which exist in new ones; as although the prince is new, the rules of that state are old and arranged to receive him as if he were their hereditary lord. But returning to our matter, I say that whoever studies the preceding argument will see that either hatred or contempt were the causes of the ruin of the emperors named, and will also observe how it came about that, some of them acting in one way and some in another, in both ways there were some who had a fortunate and others an unfortunate ending. As Pertinax and Alexander were both new rulers, it was useless and injurious for them to try and imitate Marcus, who was a hereditary prince; and similarly with Caracalla, Commodus, and Maximinus it was pernicious for them to imitate Severus, as they had not sufficient ability to follow in his footsteps. Thus a new prince cannot imitate the actions of Marcus, in his dominions, nor is it necessary for him to imitate those of Severus; but he must take from Severus those portions that are necessary to found his state, and from Marcus those that are useful and glorious for conserving a state that is already established and secure.
From these reasons, it turned out that Marcus, Pertinax, and Alexander, all of them living modestly, valuing justice, opposing cruelty, and being humane and kind, all met tragic ends except Marcus. Marcus alone lived and died with honor because he inherited the empire, and didn’t owe it to the soldiers or the people. Moreover, he had many virtues that made him respected, keeping both factions in line during his life, and he was neither hated nor despised. However, Pertinax became emperor against the will of the soldiers, who, used to a reckless lifestyle under Commodus, couldn't tolerate the honest life Pertinax wanted to impose. Thus, he became hated, and being perceived as old and contemptible, he was doomed from the start of his reign. This shows that you can earn hatred through both good actions and bad ones. As I pointed out earlier, a ruler who wants to maintain their state is often forced to do wrong. When the group you rely on for your position—whether it’s the populace, soldiers, or nobles—is corrupt, you must cater to their whims, and doing good can work against you. Now let’s talk about Alexander, who was so virtuous that among the many praises for him, it was noted that during his fourteen-year reign, no one was executed without a fair trial. Nevertheless, he was seen as weak and dominated by his mother, which led to his downfall
CHAPTER XX
WHETHER FORTRESSES AND OTHER THINGS WHICH PRINCES OFTEN MAKE ARE USEFUL OR INJURIOUS
Some princes, in order to securely hold their possessions, have disarmed their subjects, some others have kept their subject lands divided into parts, others have fomented enmities against themselves, others have endeavoured to win over those whom they suspected at the commencement of their rule: some have constructed fortresses, others have ruined and destroyed them. And although one cannot pronounce a definite judgment as to these things without going into the particulars of the state to which such a deliberation is to be applied, still I will speak in such a broad way as the matter will permit of.
Some princes, to keep their territories safe, have disarmed their subjects; others have divided their lands into smaller parts. Some have stirred up conflicts against themselves, while others have tried to win over those they suspected at the beginning of their reign. Some have built fortresses, and others have torn them down. Although it’s hard to make a definite judgment about these actions without looking closely at the specific situation, I will speak as generally as the topic allows.
A new prince has never been known to disarm his subjects, on the contrary, when he has found them disarmed he has always armed them, for by arming them these arms become your own, those that you suspected become faithful and those that were faithful remain so, and from being merely subjects become your partisans. And since all the subjects cannot be armed, when you benefit those that you arm, you can deal more safely with the others; and this different treatment that they notice renders your men more obliged to you, the others will excuse you, judging that those have necessarily greater merit who have greater danger and heavier duties. But when you disarm them, you commence to offend them and show that you distrust them either through cowardice or lack of confidence, and both of these opinions generate hatred against you. And as you cannot remain unarmed, you are obliged to resort to a mercenary militia, of which we have already stated the value; and even if it were good it cannot be sufficient in number to defend you against powerful enemies and suspected subjects. But, as I have said, a new prince in a new dominion always has his subjects armed. History is full of such examples. But when a prince acquires a new state as an addition to his old one, then it is necessary to disarm that state, except those who in acquiring it have sided with you; and even these one must, when time and opportunity serve, render weak and effeminate, and arrange things so that all the arms of the new state are in the hands of your own soldiers who in your old state live near you.
A new prince has never been known to disarm his subjects; rather, when he finds them disarmed, he always arms them. By doing so, those arms become his own, turning those he suspects into loyal supporters, while those who were already loyal remain so. They transform from mere subjects into allies. Since not all subjects can be armed, by benefiting the ones you do arm, you can deal with the others more safely. This different treatment makes your men feel more obligated to you, and the others will understand, believing that those with greater danger and heavier responsibilities deserve more merit. However, when you disarm them, you start to offend them and show a lack of trust due to either cowardice or insecurity, and both of these views create animosity towards you. Since you can't remain unarmed, you are forced to rely on a mercenary army, which we have already discussed is not very reliable. Even if it were good, it wouldn't have enough numbers to protect you against powerful foes and dubious subjects. As I've mentioned, a new prince in a new territory always has his subjects armed. History provides many examples of this. But when a prince takes over a new state as an addition to his existing realm, he must disarm that state, except for those who sided with him during the acquisition. Even those must, when the time and opportunity permit, be made weak and ineffective, ensuring that all the arms in the new state are held by your own soldiers who live close by in your original state.
Our forefathers and those who were esteemed wise used to say that it was necessary to hold Pistoia by means of factious and Pisa with fortresses, and for this purpose they fomented differences among their subjects in some town in order to possess it more easily. This, in those days when Italy was fairly divided, was doubtless well done, but does not seem to me to be a good precept for the present time, for I do not believe that the divisions thus created ever do any good; on the contrary it is certain that when the enemy approaches, the cities thus divided will be at once lost, for the weaker faction will always side with the enemy and the other will not be able to stand. The Venetians, actuated, I believe, by the aforesaid motives, cherished the Guelf and Ghibelline factions in the cities subject to them, and although they never allowed them to come to bloodshed, they yet encouraged these differences among them, so that the citizens, being occupied in their own quarrels, might not act against them. This, however, did not avail them anything, as was seen when, after the defeat of Vaila, a part of those subjects immediately took courage and took from them the whole state. Such methods, besides, argue weakness in a prince, for in a strong government such dissensions will never be permitted. They are profitable only in time of peace, as by means of them it is easy to manage one's subjects, but when it comes to war, the fallacy of such a policy is at once shown. Without doubt, princes become great when they overcome difficulties and opposition, and therefore fortune, especially when it wants to render a new prince great, who has greater need of gaining a great reputation than a hereditary prince, raises up enemies and compels him to undertake wars against them, so that he may have cause to overcome them, and thus raise himself higher by means of that ladder which his enemies have brought him. There are many who think therefore that a wise prince ought, when he has the chance, to foment astutely some enmity, so that by suppressing it he will augment his greatness. Princes, and especially new ones, have found more faith and more usefulness in those men, whom at the beginning of their power they regarded with suspicion, than in those they at first confided in. Pandolfo Petrucci, Prince of Siena, governed his state more by those whom he suspected than by others. But of this we cannot speak at large, as it varies according to the subject; I will merely say that these men who at the beginning of a new government were enemies, if they are of a kind to need support to maintain their position, can be very easily gained by the prince, and they are the more compelled to serve him faithfully as they know they must by their deeds cancel the bad opinion previously held of them, and thus the prince will always derive greater help from them than from those who, serving him with greater security, neglect his interest. And as the matter requires it, I will not omit to remind a prince who has newly taken a state with the secret help of its inhabitants, that he must consider well the motives that have induced those who have favoured him to do so, and if it is not natural affection for him, but only because they were not contented with the state as it was, he will have great trouble and difficulty in maintaining their friendship, because it will be impossible for him to content them. And on well examining the cause of this in the examples drawn from ancient and modern times it will be seen that it is much easier to gain the friendship, of those men who were contented with the previous condition and were therefore at first enemies, than that of those who not being contented, became his friends and helped him to occupy it. It has been the custom of princes in order to be able to hold securely their state, to erect fortresses, as a bridle and bit to those who have designs against them, and in order to have a secure refuge against a sudden assault. I approve this method, because it was anciently used. Nevertheless, Messer Niccolo Vitelli has been seen in our own time to destroy two fortresses in Città di Castello in order to keep that state. Guid' Ubaldo, Duke of Urbino, on returning to his dominions from which he had been driven by Cesare Borgia, razed to their foundations all the fortresses of that province, and considered that without them it would be more difficult for him to lose again the state. The Bentivogli, in returning to Bologna, used similar measures. Therefore fortresses may or may not be useful according to the times; if they do good in one way, they do harm in another.
Our ancestors and those considered wise used to say that it was important to control Pistoia through factions and Pisa with fortresses. They stirred up conflicts among their subjects in certain towns to make domination easier. This strategy worked back in the days when Italy was fairly divided, but I don't think it’s a good approach for today. I believe these divisions never really help; in fact, when an enemy comes close, divided cities will quickly fall. The weaker group will side with the enemy, while the stronger one won’t be able to withstand the attack. The Venetians, motivated by this thinking, supported the Guelf and Ghibelline factions in the cities under their control. Even though they avoided letting these rivalries turn violent, they encouraged the disputes to keep the citizens busy and distracted from opposing them. However, this tactic did not benefit them, as shown when part of their subjects gained confidence after the defeat of Vaila and took away their entire state. Such methods reflect weakness in a leader; a strong government won’t allow such disagreements. They might be useful during peacetime, making it easier to manage subjects, but their flaws become clear during war. Leaders gain greatness by overcoming challenges and opposition. Fortune, especially when trying to elevate a new leader who needs to establish a strong reputation more than a hereditary one, often creates enemies for them, forcing them into wars that provide opportunities for triumph. This can elevate them on the very ladder their enemies provide. Many believe that a wise prince, when possible, should stir up some kind of enmity so that by resolving it, he can grow in stature. Princes, particularly newcomers, have often found more loyalty and utility in those they initially regarded with suspicion than in those they first trusted. For instance, Pandolfo Petrucci, the Prince of Siena, governed more effectively with those he doubted than with others. However, the dynamics vary, and I’ll just note that those who started as enemies in a new regime, if they seek support to maintain their positions, can be easily won over. They are likely to serve the prince faithfully, knowing they need to counter the poor opinions held about them, thereby providing greater support than those who feel secure in their service and may overlook the prince's interests. Additionally, it’s crucial for a prince who has taken power with the secret help of locals to carefully consider the true reasons behind their support. If it’s not genuine loyalty but merely discontent with the previous state, maintaining their friendship will be challenging, as it will be impossible to satisfy them completely. Looking at historical examples, it's much easier to win over those who were initially content and became enemies than to rely on those who, dissatisfied, became friends and helped him take control. Historically, princes have built fortresses to secure their states, acting as a deterrent against designs against them and serving as a safe haven during sudden attacks. I support this strategy since it's been used for ages. Yet, we’ve seen modern examples, like Messer Niccolo Vitelli, who destroyed two fortresses in Città di Castello to maintain his state. Guid' Ubaldo, the Duke of Urbino, upon returning to his lands after being driven out by Cesare Borgia, razed all the fortresses in that province, believing that without them, it would be harder to lose the state again. The Bentivogli did the same when returning to Bologna. Thus, fortresses can either be helpful or harmful, depending on the time; they provide benefits in one way but drawbacks in another.
The question may be discussed thus: a prince who fears his own people more than foreigners ought to build fortresses, but he who has greater fear of foreigners than of his own people ought to do without them. The castle of Milan built by Francesco Sforza has given and will give more trouble to the house of Sforza than any other disorder in that state. Therefore the best fortress is to be found in the love of the people, for although you may have fortresses they will not save you if you are hated by the people. When once the people have taken arms against you, there will never be lacking foreigners to assist them. In our times we do not see that they have profited any ruler, except the Countess of Forli on the death of her consort Count Girolamo, for she was thus enabled to escape the popular rising and await help from Milan and recover the state; the circumstances being then such that no foreigner could assist the people. But afterwards they were of little use to her when Cesare Borgia attacked her and the people being hostile to her allied themselves with the foreigner. So that then and before it would have been safer for her not to be hated by the people than to have the fortresses. Having considered these things I would therefore praise the one who erects fortresses and the one who does not, and would blame any one who, trusting in them, thinks little of being hated by his people.
The question can be discussed like this: a prince who fears his own people more than outsiders should build fortresses, but one who fears outsiders more than his own citizens should skip them. The castle of Milan, built by Francesco Sforza, has caused and will cause more trouble for the Sforza family than any other issue in the state. Thus, the best fortress is the love of the people, because even if you have fortresses, they won't save you if you are disliked by the people. Once the people take up arms against you, there will always be outsiders ready to support them. In our time, we haven't seen fortresses help any ruler, except for the Countess of Forli after the death of her husband, Count Girolamo, which allowed her to escape the popular uprising and wait for help from Milan to regain her state; the situation was such that no outsider could aid the people at that moment. However, later on, they were of little use to her when Cesare Borgia attacked, and the people, being against her, joined forces with the outsider. So in that case, and previously, it would have been safer for her to not be hated by the people rather than have the fortresses. After considering these points, I would commend both the one who builds fortresses and the one who doesn’t, while criticizing anyone who, relying on them, underestimates the importance of not being hated by their people.
CHAPTER XXI
HOW A PRINCE MUST ACT IN ORDER TO GAIN REPUTATION
Nothing causes a prince to be so much esteemed as great enterprises and setting a rare example. We have in our own day Ferdinand, King of Aragon, at present King of Spain. He may almost be termed a new prince, because from a weak king he has become for fame and glory the first king in Christendom, and if you regard his actions you will find them all very great and some of them extraordinary. At the beginning of his reign he assailed Granada, and that enterprise was the foundation of his state. At first he did it leisurely and without fear of being interfered with; he kept the minds of the barons of Castile occupied in this enterprise, so that thinking only of that war they did not think of making innovations, and he thus acquired reputation and power over them without their being aware of it. He was able with the money of the Church and the people to maintain his armies, and by that long war lay the foundations of his military power, which afterwards has made him famous. Besides this, to be able to undertake greater enterprises, and always under the pretext of religion, he had recourse to a pious cruelty, driving out the Moors from his kingdom and despoiling them. No more admirable or rare example can be found. He also attacked under the same pretext Africa, undertook his Italian enterprise, and has lately attacked France; so that he has continually contrived great things, which have kept his subjects' minds uncertain and astonished, and occupied in watching their result.
Nothing earns a prince more respect than ambitious projects and setting a unique example. In our time, we have Ferdinand, King of Aragon, now King of Spain. He could almost be seen as a new prince, because he transformed from being a weak king to the most renowned and celebrated king in Christendom. If you look at his actions, you’ll see they are all significant, with some of them being exceptional. At the start of his reign, he attacked Granada, and that campaign was the foundation of his rule. Initially, he approached it slowly and without fear of interference; he kept the nobility of Castile focused on this conflict, ensuring they were too occupied with the war to consider making any changes, thus gaining their respect and power without them noticing. He was able to finance his armies with the resources from the Church and the people, and through that prolonged war, he built the military strength that later brought him fame. Furthermore, to undertake even larger projects, always under the guise of religion, he resorted to a devout cruelty by driving the Moors out of his kingdom and seizing their wealth. There's no more admirable or unique example than this. He also launched attacks on Africa under the same pretext, embarked on his Italian campaign, and recently attacked France, continuously devising significant actions that kept his subjects uncertain and amazed, occupied with the outcomes.
And these actions have arisen one out of the other, so that they have left no time for men to settle down and act against him. It is also very profitable for a prince to give some rare examples of himself in the internal administration, like those related of Messer Bernabò of Milan, when it happens that some one does something extraordinary, either good or evil, in civil life, and to take a means of rewarding or punishing him which will be much talked about. And above all a prince must endeavour in every action to obtain fame for being great and excellent. A prince is further esteemed when he is a true friend or a true enemy, when, that is, he declares himself without reserve in favour of some one against another.
And these actions have resulted one after another, leaving no time for people to settle down and oppose him. It's also very beneficial for a prince to showcase some unique qualities in his governance, like those attributed to Messer Bernabò of Milan, especially when someone does something remarkable, whether good or bad, in public life. The prince should find a way to reward or punish them that sparks conversation. Most importantly, a prince should aim to achieve a reputation for being great and outstanding in everything he does. A prince gains even more respect when he is a true friend or a true enemy, meaning he openly takes sides in favor of one person against another.
This policy is always more useful than remaining neutral. For if two neighbouring powers come to blows, they are either such that if one wins, you will have to fear the victor, or else not. In either of these two cases it will be better for you to declare yourself openly and make war, because in the first case if you do not declare yourself, you will fall a prey to the victor, to the pleasure and satisfaction of the one who has been defeated, and you will have no reason nor anything to defend you and nobody to receive you. For, whoever wins will not desire friends whom he suspects and who do not help him when in trouble, and whoever loses will not receive you as you did not take up arms to assist his cause. Antiochus went to Greece, being sent by the Ætoli to expel the Romans. He sent orators to the Achæi who were friends of the Romans to encourage them to remain neutral, on the other hand the Romans persuaded them to take up arms on their side. The matter was brought before the council of the Achæi for deliberation, where the ambassador of Antiochus sought to persuade them to remain neutral, to which the Roman ambassador replied: "As to what is said that it is best and most useful for your state not to meddle in our war, nothing is further from the truth; for if you do not meddle in it you will become, without any favour or any reputation, the prize of the victor." And it will always happen that the one who is not your friend will want you to remain neutral, and the one who is your friend will require you to declare yourself by taking arms. Irresolute princes, to avoid present dangers, usually follow the way of neutrality and are mostly ruined by it. But when the prince declares himself frankly in favour of one side, if the one to whom you adhere conquers, even if he is powerful and you remain at his discretion, he is under an obligation to you and friendship has been established, and men are never so dishonest as to oppress you with such ingratitude.
This policy is always more effective than staying neutral. If two neighboring powers end up in conflict, you either have to fear the winner or you don’t. In both situations, it’s better for you to take a stand and join the fight. If you don’t take a side in the first situation, you’ll end up as a victim of the winner, pleasing the defeated party, and you won’t have any allies or reasons to protect you. The victor will not want friends he can’t trust and who didn’t help him when things got tough, and the loser won’t welcome you since you didn’t fight for him. Antiochus went to Greece at the request of the Ætolians to drive out the Romans. He sent envoys to the Achæans, who were friends of the Romans, urging them to stay neutral, while the Romans convinced them to take up arms with them. The issue was brought before the Achæans' council for discussion, where Antiochus' ambassador tried to persuade them to remain neutral. The Roman ambassador responded, "What you've heard about it being best for your state to stay out of our war is completely wrong; if you don’t get involved, you’ll end up being just a prize for the victor, without any favor or reputation." The truth is, those who aren’t your allies want you to stay neutral, while your allies will expect you to choose a side and fight. Indecisive leaders often choose neutrality to avoid immediate risks, but this usually leads to their downfall. However, when a leader openly supports one side, even if that side is powerful and you’re at their mercy, they will owe you a debt of gratitude, and a friendship will form, as people are generally not so ungrateful as to mistreat you after that.
Moreover, victories are never so prosperous that the victor does not need to have some scruples, especially as to justice. But if he to whom you adhere loses, you are sheltered by him, and so long as he can, he will assist you; you become the companion of a fortune which may rise again. In the second case, when those who fight are such that you have nothing to fear from the victor, it is still more prudent on your part to adhere to one; for you go to the ruin of one with the help of him who ought to save him if he were wise, and if he conquers he rests at your discretion, and it is impossible that he should not conquer with your help. And here it should be noted that a prince ought never to make common cause with one more powerful than himself to injure another, unless necessity forces him to it, as before said; for if he wins you rest at his discretion, and princes must avoid as much as possible being at the discretion of others. The Venetians united with France against the Duke of Milan, although they could have avoided that union, and from it resulted their own ruin. But when one cannot avoid it, as happened to the Florentines when the pope and Spain went with their armies to attack Lombardy, then the prince ought to join for the above reasons. Let no state believe that it can follow a secure policy, rather let it think that all are doubtful. This is found in the nature of things, that one never tries to avoid one difficulty without running into another, but prudence consists in being able to know the nature of the difficulties, and taking the least harmful as good. A prince must also show himself a lover of merit, and honour those who excel in every art. Moreover he must encourage his citizens to follow their callings quietly, whether in commerce, or agriculture, or any other trade that men follow, so that this one shall not refrain from improving his possessions through fear that they may be taken from him, and that one from starting a trade for fear of taxes; but he should offer rewards to whoever does these things, and to whoever seeks in any way to improve his city or state. Besides this, he ought, at convenient seasons of the year, to keep the people occupied with festivals and spectacles; and as every city is divided either into trades or into classes, he ought to pay attention to all these things, mingle with them from time to time, and give them an example of his humanity and magnificence, always holding firm, however, the majesty of his dignity, which must never be allowed to fan in anything whatever.
Moreover, victories are never so complete that the winner doesn’t need to have some qualms, especially regarding justice. But if the person you support loses, you are protected by them, and as long as they can, they will help you; you become associated with a fortune that may rise again. In the second situation, when those fighting are such that you have nothing to fear from the winner, it's even more sensible for you to align with one; because you risk the downfall of one with the help of the person who should save him if he were wise, and if he wins, he will rely on you, and it's unlikely that he wouldn’t win with your support. It should also be noted that a prince should never align with someone more powerful than himself to harm another, unless necessity compels it, as mentioned earlier; because if he wins, you depend on his will, and princes should avoid being at the mercy of others as much as possible. The Venetians allied with France against the Duke of Milan, even though they could have avoided that alliance, which led to their own downfall. But when one cannot avoid it, like the Florentines when the pope and Spain sent their armies to attack Lombardy, then the prince should align for the reasons stated above. No state should think it can pursue a secure policy; rather, it should understand that all situations are uncertain. It's part of the nature of things that one never manages to avoid one problem without encountering another, but wisdom lies in recognizing the nature of these difficulties and choosing the least harmful option as the best. A prince must also show himself as a supporter of merit and honor those who excel in every field. In addition, he must encourage his citizens to pursue their trades peacefully, whether in commerce, farming, or any other occupation, so that one person doesn't shy away from improving their assets for fear they might be taken away, and another doesn’t hesitate to start a business out of fear of taxes; instead, he should reward those who engage in these activities and those who seek to improve their city or state in any way. Furthermore, he should, during favorable times of the year, keep the people engaged with festivals and events; and since every city is divided either into trades or classes, he should pay attention to all these aspects, interact with them occasionally, and set an example of his generosity and greatness, while always upholding the dignity of his position, which must never waver in any respect.
CHAPTER XXII
OF THE SECRETARIES OF PRINCES
The choice of a prince's ministers is a matter of no little importance; they are either good or not according to the prudence of the prince. The first impression that one gets of a ruler and of his brains is from seeing the men that he has about him. When they are competent and faithful one can always consider him wise, as he has been able to recognise their ability and keep them faithful. But when they are the reverse, one can always form an unfavourable opinion of him, because the first mistake that he makes is in making this choice. There was nobody who knew Messer Antonio da Venafro as the minister of Pandolfo Petrucci, Prince of Siena, who did not consider Pandolfo to be a very prudent man, having him for his minister. There are three different kinds of brains, the one understands things unassisted, the other understands things when shown by others, the third understands neither alone nor with the explanations of others. The first kind is most excellent, the second also excellent, but the third useless. It is therefore evident that if Pandolfo was not of the first kind, he was at any rate of the second. For every time that one has the judgment to know the good and evil that any one does or says, even if he has no invention, yet he recognises the bad and good works of his minister and corrects the one and supports the other; and the minister cannot hope to deceive him and therefore remains good. For a prince to be able to know a minister there is this method which never fails. When you see the minister think more of himself than of you, and in all his actions seek his own profit, such a man will never be a good minister, and you can never rely on him; for whoever has in hand the state of another must never think of himself but of the prince, and not call to mind anything but what relates to him. And, on the other hand, the prince, in order to retain his fidelity ought to think of his minister, honouring and enriching him, doing him kindnesses, and conferring on him honours and giving him responsible tasks, so that the great honours and riches bestowed on him cause him not to desire other honours and riches, and the tasks he has to fulfil make him fearful of changes, knowing that he could not execute them without the prince. When princes and their ministers stand in this relation to each other, they can rely the one upon the other; when it is otherwise, the end is always injurious either for one or the other of them.
The choice of a prince’s ministers is really important; they are either good or bad depending on the prince’s judgment. The first impression you get of a ruler and their intelligence comes from the people they surround themselves with. If those people are capable and loyal, you can assume the ruler is wise for recognizing their talent and keeping them loyal. But if they aren't, people will form a negative opinion of the ruler because the first mistake is in choosing them. Anyone who knew Messer Antonio da Venafro, the minister of Pandolfo Petrucci, Prince of Siena, thought Pandolfo was very prudent for having him as a minister. There are three types of intelligence: one type understands things independently, the second understands things when explained by others, and the third understands neither alone nor with assistance. The first type is the best, the second is also good, but the third is useless. It’s clear that if Pandolfo wasn’t of the first type, he was at least of the second. Whenever someone has the judgment to recognize the good and bad actions or words of others, even without original ideas, they can identify their minister’s shortcomings and strengths; they can correct the bad and support the good, which means the minister can’t deceive them and has to remain competent. For a prince to evaluate a minister, there’s a method that never fails. When you see a minister who cares more about himself than about you and seeks his own benefit in all his actions, he will never be a good minister, and you can’t trust him. Anyone who manages someone else's state must think only of the prince and not focus on their own interests. Conversely, to maintain a minister’s loyalty, the prince must think of his minister, honor and reward him, show him kindness, and assign him important responsibilities. The significant honors and wealth given to the minister should satisfy him to the point that he doesn’t seek more, and the tasks he’s assigned should make him wary of changes since he wouldn't be able to handle them without the prince. When princes and their ministers have this kind of relationship, they can trust each other; when it’s not like this, the outcome is usually harmful to one or the other.
CHAPTER XXIII
HOW FLATTERERS MUST BE SHUNNED
I must not omit an important subject, and a mistake which princes can with difficulty avoid, if they are not very prudent, or if they do not make a good choice. And this is with regard to flatterers, of which courts are full, because men take such pleasure in their own things and deceive themselves about them that they can with difficulty guard against this plague; and by wishing to guard against it they run the risk of becoming contemptible. Because there is no other way of guarding one's self against flattery than by letting men understand that they will not offend you by speaking the truth; but when every one can tell you the truth, you lose their respect. A prudent prince must therefore take a third course, by choosing in his state wise men, and giving these alone full liberty to speak the truth to him, but only of those things that he asks and of nothing else; but he must ask them about everything and hear their opinion, and afterwards deliberate by himself in his own way, and in these councils and with each of these men comport himself so that every one may see that the more freely he speaks, the more he will be acceptable. Outside these he should listen to no one, go about the matter deliberately, and be determined in his decisions. Whoever acts otherwise either acts precipitately through flattery or else changes often through the variety of opinions, from which it happens that he is little esteemed. I will give a modern instance of this. Pre' Luca, a follower of Maximilian, the present emperor, speaking of his majesty said that he never took counsel with anybody, and yet that he never did anything as he wished; this arose from his following the contrary method to the aforesaid. As the emperor is a secret man he does not communicate his designs to any one or take any one's advice, but as on putting them into effect they begin to be known and discovered, they begin to be opposed by those he has about him, and he is easily diverted from his purpose. Hence it comes to pass that what he does one day he undoes the next, no one ever understands what he wishes or intends to do, and no reliance is to be placed on his deliberations. A prince, therefore, ought always to take counsel, but only when he wishes, not when others wish; on the contrary he ought to discourage absolutely attempts to advise him unless he asks it, but he ought to be a great asker, and a patient hearer of the truth about those things which he has inquired of; indeed, if he finds that any one has scruples in telling him the truth he should be angry. And since some think that a prince who gains the reputation of being prudent is so considered, not by his nature but by the good councillors he has about him, they are undoubtedly deceived. It is an infallible rule that a prince who is not wise himself cannot be well advised, unless by chance he left himself entirely in the hands of one man who ruled him in everything, and happened to be a very prudent man. In this case he may doubtless be well governed, but it would not last long, for that governor would in a short time deprive him of the state; but by taking counsel with many, a prince who is not wise will never have united councils and will not be able to unite them for himself. The councillors will all think of their own interests, and he will be unable either to correct or to understand them. And it cannot be otherwise, for men will always be false to you unless they are compelled by necessity to be true.
I can't overlook an important topic, which is a mistake that rulers often struggle to avoid unless they're very careful or make good choices. This topic concerns flatterers, who are everywhere in courts. People get so caught up in their own interests and are often self-deceived that it's hard for them to defend against this issue; trying to protect themselves from it can even make them look foolish. The only way to shield oneself from flattery is to let people know that speaking the truth won’t upset you. However, if everyone feels free to tell you the truth, you risk losing their respect. A wise ruler should take a third approach by surrounding himself with wise individuals in his realm and permitting only them to speak the truth, but only about the things he specifically asks about and nothing more. He must ask them everything, hear their opinions, and then think about it himself. In these discussions, he should act in a way that shows everyone that the more openly they speak, the more appreciated they are. Outside of this circle, he shouldn’t listen to anyone else, should think carefully about matters, and be resolute in his decisions. Anyone who doesn’t do this may act rashly from flattery or will frequently change his mind due to the variety of opinions, leading him to be held in low regard. A modern example is Pre' Luca, a follower of the current emperor Maximilian, who commented that the emperor never consulted anyone, yet he also never managed to do as he pleased. This occurred because he followed the opposite method of what was mentioned earlier. Since the emperor is secretive, he doesn’t share his plans with anyone or seek anyone's advice, but as soon as he tries to put those plans into action, they become known and are opposed by those around him, easily distracting him from his goals. As a result, what he decides one day he often reverses the next. No one truly knows what he wants to do, and his decisions can't be relied upon. Therefore, a prince should always seek counsel, but only when he chooses to, not when others want him to. He should firmly discourage attempts to advise him unless he asks for it, but he should be eager to ask questions and be patient in hearing the truth about the matters he inquires about; in fact, if he realizes someone hesitates to tell him the truth, he should be angry. Some believe that a prince who is seen as wise owes this to the good advisors around him, but this is a misconception. It’s a foolproof rule that a prince who isn't wise on his own won't get good advice, unless he completely relies on one person who governs him entirely and happens to be very wise. In that case, he might be well led, but it wouldn’t last long; that advisor would soon take control of the state. However, a prince who consults many people will never be able to unify those councils if he isn’t wise, and he won't be able to unify his own views. His advisors will act in their own interests, and he will find it impossible to correct or understand them. This will inevitably happen, since people will always be dishonest with you unless they're forced by necessity to be truthful.
Therefore it must be concluded that wise counsels, from whoever they come, must necessarily be due to the prudence of the prince, and not the prudence of the prince to the good counsels received.
Therefore, it must be concluded that wise advice, no matter who it comes from, is ultimately the result of the prince's own wisdom, and not the other way around, where the prince’s wisdom comes from the good advice he receives.
CHAPTER XXIV
WHY THE PRINCES OF ITALY HAVE LOST THEIR STATES
The before-mentioned things, if prudently observed, make a new prince seem ancient, and render him at once more secure and firmer in the state than if he had been established there of old. For a new prince is much more observed in his actions than a hereditary one, and when these are recognised as virtuous, he gains men more and they are more bound to him than if he were of the ancient blood. For men are much more taken by present than by past things, and when they find themselves well off in the present, they enjoy it and seek nothing more; on the contrary, they will do all they can to defend him, so long as the prince is not in other things wanting to himself. And thus he will have the double glory of having founded a new realm and adorned it and fortified it with good laws, good arms, good friends and good examples; as he will have double shame who is born a prince and through want of prudence has lost it.
The things mentioned earlier, if wisely followed, make a new prince appear established and provide him with more security and stability in his position than if he were a long-time ruler. A new prince's actions are scrutinized more closely than those of a hereditary prince, and when his actions are seen as virtuous, he gains more loyalty from his subjects, who feel more connected to him than to someone of noble lineage. People tend to be more influenced by what’s happening now rather than what happened in the past. When they find themselves doing well in the present, they appreciate it and don’t desire anything else; on the contrary, they will do everything they can to support him, as long as the prince remains consistent in other matters. This way, he will receive the dual honor of having founded a new kingdom and strengthened it with good laws, strong defenses, loyal allies, and positive examples; while he who inherits the throne and fails due to a lack of wisdom will face double disgrace.
And if one considers those rulers who have lost their position in Italy in our days, such as the King of Naples, the Dukè of Milan and others, one will find in them first a common defect as to their arms, for the reasons discussed at length, then we observe that some of them either had the people hostile to them, or that if the people were friendly they were not able to make sure of the nobility, for without these defects, states are not lost that have enough strength to be able to keep an army in the field. Philip of Macedon, not the father of Alexander the Great, but the one who was conquered by Titus Quinteus, did not possess a great state compared to the greatness of Rome and Greece which assailed him, but being a military man and one who knew how to divert the people and make sure of the great, he was able to sustain the war against them for many years; and if at length he lost his power over several cities, he was still able to keep his kingdom. Therefore, those of our princes who had held their possessions for many years must not accuse fortune for having lost them, but rather their own negligence; for having never in quiet times considered that things might change (as it is a common fault of men not to reckon on storms, in fair weather) when adverse times came, they only thought of fleeing from them, instead of defending themselves; and hoped that the people, enraged by the insolence of the conquerors, would recall them. This measure, when others are wanting, is good; but it is very bad to have neglected the other remedies for that one, for nobody would desire to fall because he believed that he would then find some one to pick him up. This may or may not take place, and if it does, it is not with safety to you, as that defence is known to be cowardly and not to be depended on; and only those defences are good, certain and durable, which depend only on yourself and your own ability.
And if you look at the rulers in Italy today who have lost their positions, like the King of Naples, the Duke of Milan, and others, you’ll notice they share a common flaw regarding their military strength, as we've discussed in detail. Some faced hostility from the people, while others had the people's support but couldn't secure the loyalty of the nobility. Without addressing these issues, states that have enough power to maintain an army don’t typically fall. Philip of Macedon, not the father of Alexander the Great but the one defeated by Titus Quinctius, didn’t have a large kingdom compared to the might of Rome and Greece that attacked him. However, being a military leader who knew how to manage the populace and win over the elite, he managed to sustain the war against them for many years; even though he eventually lost control of several cities, he was still able to hold onto his kingdom. Therefore, our princes who had maintained their territories for many years shouldn't blame fate for their losses but instead their own negligence. They failed to consider during peaceful times that circumstances could change (as it's common for people to overlook potential troubles during good times). When difficult times came, they only thought about fleeing instead of defending themselves, hoping that the people, angered by the conquerors’ arrogance, would want them back. While this strategy might work when other options are lacking, it's foolish to rely solely on it. Nobody should expect to fall and then count on someone to rescue them. This may or may not happen, and if it does, it’s not a reliable safety net, as depending on this kind of defense is seen as cowardly. The best, most dependable forms of defense come from your own strength and abilities.
CHAPTER XXV
HOW MUCH FORTUNE CAN DO IN HUMAN AFFAIRS AND HOW IT MAY BE OPPOSED
It is not unknown to me how many have been and are of opinion that worldly events are so governed by fortune and by God, that men cannot by their prudence change them, and that on the contrary there is no remedy whatever, and for this they may judge it to be useless to toil much about them, but let things be ruled by chance. This opinion has been more believed in in our day, from the great changes that have been seen, and are daily seen, beyond every human conjecture.
I'm aware that many people believe that worldly events are controlled by luck and divine will, to the point that individuals can't change them through their own wisdom. They think there's no way to fix things and therefore see it as pointless to put in a lot of effort, letting random chance take charge instead. This belief has become even more common today due to the significant changes we've witnessed, which surpass anything we could have predicted.
When I think about them at times, I am partly inclined to share this opinion. Nevertheless, that our freewill may not be altogether extinguished, I think it may be true that fortune is the ruler of half our actions, but that she allows the other half or a little less to be governed by us. I would compare her to an impetuous river that, when turbulent, inundates the plains, ruins trees and buildings, removes earth from this side and places it on the other; every one flies before it, and everything yields to its fury without being able to oppose it; and yet though it is of such a kind, still when it is quiet, men can make provision against it by dams and banks, so that when it rises it will either go into a canal or its rush will not be so wild and dangerous. It happens similarly with fortune, which shows her power where no measures have been taken to resist her, and turns her fury where she knows that no dams or barriers have been made to hold her. And if you regard Italy, which has been the seat of these changes, and who has given the impulse to them, you will see her to be a country without dams or barriers of any kind. If she had been protected by proper measures, like Germany, Spain, and France, this inundation would not have caused the great changes that it has, or would not have happened at all. This must suffice as regards opposition to fortune in general. But limiting myself more to particular cases, I would point out how one sees a certain prince to-day fortunate and to-morrow ruined, without seeing that he has changed in character or otherwise. I believe this arises in the first place from the causes that we have already discussed at length; that is to say, because the prince who bases himself entirely on fortune is ruined when fortune varies. I also believe that he is happy whose mode of proceeding accords with the needs of the times, and similarly he is unfortunate whose mode of proceeding is opposed to the times. For one sees that men in those things which lead them to the aim that each one has in view, namely, glory and riches, proceed in various ways; one with circumspection, another with impetuosity, one by violence, another by cunning, one with patience, another with the reverse; and each by these diverse ways may arrive at his aim. One sees also two cautious men, one of whom succeeds in his designs, and the other not, and in the same way two men succeed equally by different methods, one being cautious, the other impetuous, which arises only from the nature of the times, which does or does not conform to their method of proceeding. From this results, as I have said, that two men, acting differently, attain the same effect, and of two others acting in the same way, one arrives at his good and not the other. From this depend also the changes in fortune, for if it happens that time and circumstances are favourable to one who acts with caution and prudence he will be successful, but if time and circumstances change he will be ruined, because he does not change his mode of proceeding. No man is found able to adapt himself to this, either because he cannot deviate from that to which his nature disposes him, or else because having always prospered by walking in one path, he cannot persuade himself that it is well to leave it; and therefore the cautious man, when it is time to act suddenly, does not know how to do so and is consequently ruined; for if one could change one's nature with time and circumstances, fortune would never change. Pope Julius II. acted impetuously in everything he did and found the times and conditions so in conformity with that mode of proceeding, that he always obtained a good result. Consider the first war that he made against Bologna while Messer Giovanni Bentivogli was still living. The Venetians were not pleased with it, the King of Spain and likewise France had objections to this enterprise, notwithstanding which with his fierce and impetuous disposition he engaged personally in the expedition. This move caused both Spain and the Venetians to halt and hesitate, the latter through fear, the former through the desire to regain the entire kingdom of Naples. On the other hand, he engaged with him the King of France, because seeing him make this move and desiring his friendship in order to put down the Venetians, that king judged that he could not refuse him his troops without manifest injury. Thus Julius by his impetuous move achieved what no other pontiff with the utmost human prudence would have succeeded in doing, because, if he had waited till all arrangements had been made and everything settled before leaving Rome, as any other pontiff would have done, it would never have taken place. For the king of France would have found a thousand excuses, and the others would have inspired him with a thousand fears. I will omit his other actions, which were all of this kind and which all succeeded well, and the shortness of his life did not suffer him to experience the contrary, for had times succeeded in which it was necessary to act with caution, his ruin would have resulted, for he would never have deviated from these methods to which his nature disposed him. I conclude then that fortune varying and men remaining fixed in their ways, they are successful so long as these ways conform to each other, but when they are opposed to each other then they are unsuccessful. I certainly think that it is better to be impetuous than cautious, for fortune is a woman, and it is necessary, if you wish to master her, to conquer her by force; and it can be seen that she lets herself be overcome by these rather than by those who proceed coldly. And therefore, like a woman, she is a friend to the young, because they are less cautious, fiercer, and master her with greater audacity.
When I think about them sometimes, I kind of agree with this view. However, I believe it’s true that our free will isn’t completely lost; fortune rules over about half of our actions, but she allows us to control the other half, or maybe just a bit less. I would compare her to a raging river that, when it’s rough, floods the fields, destroys trees and buildings, moves soil from one side to the other; everyone runs from it, and everything surrenders to its wrath without being able to fight back. Yet, even though it can be that way, when the river is calm, people can prepare against it with dams and levees, so that when it swells, it either flows into a channel or its current isn’t as wild and dangerous. Fortune is similar; she shows her strength where no defenses have been set up to resist her and unleashes her fury where she knows there are no barriers. If you look at Italy, which has experienced these changes and has been the source of them, you’ll see it’s a country without any defenses. If it had been shielded by appropriate measures, like Germany, Spain, and France, this flooding wouldn’t have led to the significant changes it has, or it might not have happened at all. This should suffice in general about opposing fortune. But if I focus on specific instances, I want to point out how you can see a certain prince today enjoying good fortune and tomorrow facing ruin, without any apparent change in his character. I believe this happens mainly because we’ve already discussed that a prince who relies entirely on fortune will fall when fortune shifts. I also believe that the person who adapts to the needs of the times is fortunate, while the one whose approach conflicts with the times is unfortunate. People pursue various paths toward their goals, which typically are glory and wealth; some are cautious, others impulsive, some use force, others are clever, some are patient, while others are not; and each of these different approaches can lead them to their goals. Additionally, you can see two careful individuals, one succeeds in his plans, while the other does not, and likewise, two people can achieve the same success through different methods; one might be cautious, the other impulsive. This difference comes only from the nature of the times, which may or may not align with their approach. Therefore, as I’ve mentioned, two people acting differently can achieve the same outcome, while two others acting similarly may have one succeed and the other fail. Changes in fortune depend on this, too, because if circumstances and timing favor a cautious and prudent person, he will succeed, but if timing and circumstances change, he will be ruined if he doesn't adjust his approach. No person can easily adapt to this because he either cannot stray from his natural inclinations or because, having always succeeded by following one path, he struggles to believe it’s wise to abandon it. Consequently, a cautious person, when it’s time to act quickly, doesn’t know how to do so and ends up failing; for if one could change his nature with time and circumstances, fortune would never change. Pope Julius II acted impulsively in everything he did, and the times and conditions aligned with that approach, leading him to consistently achieve positive results. Consider his first war against Bologna while Messer Giovanni Bentivogli was still alive. The Venetians disapproved, and both the King of Spain and France had concerns about his venture; nonetheless, his fierce and impulsive nature led him to take part in the expedition. This decision caused Spain and the Venetians to pause, the latter out of fear, and the former to regain the entire kingdom of Naples. At the same time, he enlisted the support of the King of France, who, seeing Julius’s bold move and wanting to befriend him to counter the Venetians, felt he couldn’t refuse his troops without significant fallout. In this way, Julius accomplished what no other pope, however prudent, could have achieved, because if he had waited until all was arranged and settled before leaving Rome, as any other pope would have, it never would have happened. The King of France would have found a thousand excuses, and others would have instilled a thousand fears in him. I’ll skip over his other similar successful endeavors, and the shortness of his life didn’t allow him to face the opposite situation; for had times required a more cautious approach, he would have met his downfall, for he would never have deviated from the tactics his nature favored. I conclude, then, that as fortune shifts and men remain fixed in their approaches, they succeed as long as their methods are compatible, but they fail when those methods conflict. I definitely believe it’s better to be impulsive than cautious, for fortune is a woman, and if you want to dominate her, you have to conquer her by force; it’s apparent that she allows herself to be subdued by those who are bold rather than those who move hesitantly. Therefore, like a woman, she favors the young, because they are less cautious, more passionate, and confront her with greater daring.
CHAPTER XXVI
EXHORTATION TO LIBERATE ITALY FROM THE BARBARIANS
Having now considered all the things we have spoken of, and thought within myself whether at present the time was not propitious in Italy for a new prince, and if there was not a state of things which offered an opportunity to a prudent and capable man to introduce a new system that would do honour to himself and good to the mass of the people, it seems to me that so many things concur to favour a new ruler that I do not know of any time more fitting for such an enterprise. And if, as I said, it was necessary in order that the power of Moses should be displayed that the people of Israel should be slaves in Egypt, and to give scope for the greatness and courage of Cyrus that the Persians should be oppressed by the Medes, and to illustrate the pre-eminence of Theseus that the Athenians should be dispersed, so at the present time, in order that the might of an Italian genius might be recognised, it was necessary that Italy should be reduced to her present condition, and that she should be more enslaved than the Hebrews, more oppressed than the Persians, and more scattered than the Athenians; without a head, without order, beaten, despoiled, lacerated, and overrun, and that she should have suffered ruin of every kind. And although before now a spirit has been shown by some which gave hope that he might be appointed by God for her redemption, yet at the highest summit of his career he was thrown aside by fortune, so that now, almost lifeless, she awaits one who may heal her wounds and put a stop to the rapine and pillaging of Lombardy, to the rapacity and extortion in the kingdom and in Tuscany, and cure her of those sores which have long been festering. Behold how she prays God to send some one to redeem her from this barbarous cruelty and insolence. Behold her ready and willing to follow any standard if only there be some one to raise it. There is nothing now she can hope for but that your illustrious house may place itself at the head of this redemption, being by its power and fortune so exalted, and being favoured by God and the Church, whose leadership it now occupies. Nor will this be very difficult to you, if you call to mind the actions and lives of the men I have named. And although those men were rare and marvellous, they were none the less men, and had each of them less occasion than the present, for their enterprise was not juster than this, nor easier, nor was God more their friend than He is yours. Here is a just cause; for that war is just which is necessary; and those arms are merciful where no hope exists save in them. Here is the greatest willingness, nor can there be great difficulty where there is great willingness, provided that the measures are adopted of those whom I have set before you as examples. Besides this, unexampled wonders have been seen here performed by God, the sea has been opened, a cloud has shown you the road, the rock has given forth water, manna has rained, and everything has contributed to your greatness, the remainder must be done by you. God will not do everything, in order not to deprive us of freewill and the portion of the glory that falls to our lot. It is no marvel that none of the before-mentioned Italians have done that which it is to be hoped your illustrious house may do; and if in so many revolutions in Italy and so many warlike operations, it always seems as if the military capacity were extinct, this is because the ancient methods were not good, and no one has arisen who knew how to discover new ones. Nothing does so much honour to a newly-risen man than the new laws and measures which he introduces. These things, when they are well based and have greatness in them, render him revered and admired, and there is not lacking scope in Italy for the introduction of every kind. Here there is great virtue in the members, if it were not wanting in the heads. Look how in duels and in councils of a few the Italians are superior in strength, dexterity, and intelligence. But when it comes to armies they make a poor show; which proceeds entirely from the weakness of the leaders, for those that know are not obedient, and every one thinks that he knows, there being hitherto nobody who has raised himself so high both by valour and fortune as to make the others yield. Hence it comes about that in all this time, in all the wars waged during the last twenty years, whenever there has been an army entirely Italian it has always been a failure, as witness first Taro, then Alexandria, Capua, Genoa, Vaila, Bologna, and Mestri. If your illustrious house, therefore, wishes to follow those great men who redeemed their countries, it is before all things necessary, as the true foundation of every undertaking, to provide yourself with your own forces, for you cannot have more faithful, or truer and better soldiers. And although each one of them may be good, they will together become better when they see themselves commanded by their prince, and honoured and supported by him. It is therefore necessary to prepare such forces in order to be able with Italian prowess to defend the country from foreigners. And although both the Swiss and Spanish infantry are deemed terrible, none the less they each have their defects, so that a third order might not only oppose them, but be confident of overcoming them. For the Spaniards cannot sustain the attack of cavalry, and the Swiss have to fear infantry which meets them with resolution equal to their own. From which it has resulted, as will be seen by experience, that the Spaniards cannot sustain the attack of French cavalry, and the Swiss are overthrown by Spanish infantry. And although a complete example of the latter has not been seen, yet an instance was furnished in the battle of Ravenna, where the Spanish infantry attacked the German battalions, which observe the same order as the Swiss. The Spaniards, through their bodily agility and aided by their bucklers, had entered between and under their pikes and were in a position to attack them safely without the Germans being able to defend themselves; and if the cavalry had not charged them they would have utterly destroyed them. Knowing therefore the defects of both these kinds of infantry, a third kind can be created which can resist cavalry and need not fear infantry, and this will be done not by the creation of armies but by a change of system. And these are the things which, when newly introduced, give reputation and grandeur to a new prince. This opportunity must not, therefore, be allowed to pass, for letting Italy at length see her liberator. I cannot express the love with which he would be received in all those provinces which have suffered under these foreign invasions, with what thirst for vengeance, with what steadfast faith, with what love, with what grateful tears. What doors would be closed against him? What people would refuse him obedience? What envy could oppose him? What Italian would rebel against him? This barbarous domination stinks in the nostrils of every one. May your illustrious house therefore assume this task with that courage and those hopes which are inspired by a just cause, so that under its banner our fatherland may be raised up, and under its auspices be verified that saying of Petrarch:
Having considered everything we've discussed, I’ve thought about whether this is a good time in Italy for a new prince and if there’s a situation that allows a wise and capable person to introduce a system that would honor them and benefit the people. It seems to me that there are so many factors favoring a new ruler that I can’t think of a better time for such an undertaking. Just as it was necessary for the Israelites to be slaves in Egypt to showcase Moses's power, for the Persians to be oppressed by the Medes to highlight Cyrus's greatness, and for the Athenians to be dispersed to illustrate Theseus's preeminence, similarly, for the strength of an Italian genius to be recognized, it was necessary for Italy to be brought to its current state. Italy must be more enslaved than the Hebrews, more oppressed than the Persians, and more scattered than the Athenians—without a leader, without order, defeated, stripped, torn apart, and overrun, having suffered all kinds of ruin. Although there was once a spirit in Italy that sparked hope for redemption, at the height of that individual's success, fortune cast him aside, leaving Italy—almost lifeless—waiting for someone to heal her wounds and put an end to the plundering in Lombardy, the greed and exploitation in the kingdom and Tuscany, and to remedy the long-festering sores. Look how she prays to God for someone to save her from this brutal cruelty and arrogance. See how she is ready and willing to follow any banner if someone will only raise it. There is nothing left for her to hope for except that your illustrious house will take the lead in this redemption, as you are in a powerful and fortunate position and favored by God and the Church, which you currently lead. This won't be too difficult for you if you reflect on the actions and lives of the men I mentioned. Even though those men were exceptional, they too were just men, and each had fewer reasons than you do now; their ventures were neither just nor easier than yours, nor was God more aligned with them than He is with you. Here is a just cause, as a war is just if it is necessary, and those arms are merciful when there's no hope beyond them. Here is great willingness, and great willingness can overcome difficulties if you apply the strategies of those whom I’ve proposed as examples. Furthermore, unprecedented wonders have been witnessed, the sea has parted, a cloud has shown you the way, water has flowed from a rock, manna has rained down, and all these things have contributed to your greatness; the rest is up to you. God won’t do everything to avoid depriving us of free will and the glory that our efforts deserve. It’s no wonder that none of the aforementioned Italians have managed what your illustrious house may achieve; and if, amidst all the upheaval in Italy and military operations, it appears that military strength has faded, it’s because the old methods were flawed and no one has emerged who knew how to innovate. Nothing adds more honor to a newly risen individual than the new laws and measures they enact. When these are well-founded and significant, they make him revered and admired, and there’s plenty of opportunity in Italy for all kinds of innovations. There is great potential among the people if it were not lacking in their leaders. Look at how Italians excel in duels and small councils in strength, skill, and intelligence. But when it comes to armies, they perform poorly; this is entirely due to the leaders' weakness, as knowledgeable individuals are not obedient and everyone thinks they know better, with no one having risen high enough by valor and fortune to make the others submit. Thus, throughout this time, in all the wars fought over the last twenty years, whenever there has been a wholly Italian army, it has always failed, as seen in Taro, then Alexandria, Capua, Genoa, Vaila, Bologna, and Mestri. Therefore, if your illustrious house wants to follow the path of those great men who redeemed their countries, it is crucial, as the true foundation of any endeavor, to create your own forces, for you cannot find more loyal or better soldiers. And although each one of them may be good, together they will become even better when they see themselves led by their prince, honored, and supported by him. It is, therefore, necessary to prepare such forces to defend the country from foreign aggression with Italian prowess. Although both the Swiss and Spanish infantry are considered formidable, each has its weaknesses, allowing for a third force that could not only resist them but have confidence in overcoming them. The Spaniards can’t withstand cavalry charges, and the Swiss need to fear infantry that meets them with equal resolve. This has been evidenced in the past; the Spaniards have struggled against French cavalry, and the Swiss have been overrun by Spanish infantry. While a full demonstration of this hasn’t been seen yet, an example occurred during the battle of Ravenna, where Spanish infantry confronted German battalions, which follow the same formation as the Swiss. The Spaniards, thanks to their agility and shield support, managed to slip between and beneath the Germans' pikes, putting them in a position to attack safely while the Germans couldn't defend themselves; had cavalry not intervened, they would have been utterly destroyed. Knowing, therefore, the weaknesses of these types of infantry, a third kind could be developed capable of withstanding cavalry while not fearing infantry, which will come not through the establishment of armies but through a change in strategy. These innovations are what will give a new prince reputation and grand stature. Thus, this opportunity must not be wasted—not letting Italy finally see her liberator. I can't express the love with which he would be received in all those provinces that have suffered under foreign invasions, with what eagerness for revenge, steadfast faith, love, and grateful tears. What doors would remain closed to him? What people would deny him their loyalty? What envy could stand in his way? What Italian would rebel against him? This barbaric rule is contemptible to all. Therefore, may your illustrious house take on this challenge with the courage and hopes inspired by a just cause, so that under its banner our homeland may be restored, and under its guidance, that saying of Petrarch may be fulfilled:
Valour against fell wrath
Will take up arms; and be the combat quickly sped!
For, sure, the ancient worth,
That in Italians stirs the heart, is not yet dead.
Courage against fierce anger
Will pick up arms; and let the battle be swift!
For, surely, the noble spirit,
That inspires the hearts of Italians, is not yet gone.
THE END
Download ePUB
If you like this ebook, consider a donation!